The Yoruba Ethics
The Yoruba Ethics
The Yoruba Ethics
Different cultures of the world have their different systems of ethics. This does not necessarily
support the position of the ethical relativists because, as it were, certain ethical practices are
accepted on a global scale. No culture approves of theft, robbery, cruelty to fellow humans,
murder, breaking of promises, and other forms of immoral acts. On the other hand, all cultures of
the world approve of acts such as honesty, hard-work, love, marital faithfulness, promise-
keeping, truth-telling, among others. Neither does this advance the position of the ethical
1
Universalists. This is due to the fact that, whereas there is a global repulsion of the former set of
acts, and a global acceptance of the latter, different cultures have different justifications for either
accepting or rejecting these acts. Whatever justification a culture finds in either case, there is a
unified end in view, namely, the need to make human societies conducive for human co-
In keeping with the above backdrop, the current paper attempts an exposé of the Yorùbá
ethics as a system of morality undergirding the Yorùbá social behavioural pattern. The paper is
essentially expository; hence, it strives only to highlight some of the features of Yorùbá ethics as
a variant of the African ethical system generally, with its own peculiar nature. There are six
sections in all, sections one and six being the introduction and conclusion. Section two outlines
what it calls ‘the seven pillars of Yorùbá ethical system’. These pillars, although not strictly
unique to the Yorùbá, as the section purports to show, play major roles in the understanding of
Yorùbá ethics. The third section describes the roles of the gods and their deputies in the
determination of punitive measures for offenders of moral laws. In section four, Ifá oracle is
revealed as the custodian of Yorùbá ethical vision while section five reviews Yorùbá ethics
Every system of ethics has its peculiarities. These are features that define the essence of a
particular ethical system. In the current context, there are certain fundamental features which
give substance to the ethical reasoning of an average Yorùbá person. It is apposite to restate here
that these pillars are not really peculiar to the Yorùbá alone. Yorùbá system of morality is a
subset of the African ethical thoughts generally; and as a subset, it bears some overlapping
2
relations to the ethical thoughts of some other African groups, especially those to which it is
territorially proximate. It must also be stated that these seven pillars do not exhaust all there are
to Yorùbá ethical system; there may be others that future researches on the Yorùbá have the
mandate to unearth. However, those discussed below are ones that literature has since
established. I shall now proceed to discuss these pillars of the Yorùbá ethical system: humanism,
Humanism
Yorùbá have a human-based system of ethics, that is, a system of ethics in which everything
revolves around the wellness of human beings. Theirs is not an abstract notion of good that bears
no practical relation to human concerns. All ethical considerations have human beings as the
centre of attraction. In other words, the strongest motivation to act morally is to preserve the
sanctity of humanity either in one’s own case or in others. If, as Gyekye (2010) notes, ‘the ethics
of a society is embedded in the ideas or beliefs about what is right or wrong, what is good or bad
character, etc.’ then, it would be correct to say of the Yorùbá that their standard for arriving at
these moral judgements is whether or not a piece of action so adjudged advances the cause of
humanity, promotes human welfare, or produces other unspecified beneficial outcomes for
human flourishing. As it were for African morality generally, therefore, Yorùbá ethics reflects
the logic that ‘actions that promote human welfare and interests are good, while those that
It is remarkable to point out how the humanistic character of Yorùbá ethics derives from
the metaphysical status of the human person. The Yorùbá word for a person is ènìyàn. According
to Maulana Karenga (2009), ‘in the Ifá spiritual and ethical tradition, ènìyàn is a fundamental
concept that speaks to the moral status and moral considerability of the human person’.
3
Etymologically, the term ènìyàn derives from the Yorùbá phrase ẹni tí a yàn (literally: chosen
one(s)). This shows the peculiar status of the human person as an object of moral consideration.
To be chosen in this context ‘has profound significance in moral anthropology for both the
conception and treatment of human beings’ (Karenga 2009). In addition to the uniqueness
conferred on the human person, the element of human chosenness presents the highest level of
humanism in its inclusion of all humans as chosen. This, as a basis for human equality, equity
and fairness, makes it morally binding on the Yorùbá, to treat all human beings with equal
respect and dignity (see Balogun 2013, 2017). A corollary moral principle inferable from this is
that, given that all human beings are morally equal – based on equal chosen status – it would be
immoral for anyone to discriminate against another on the basis of race, gender, religion, or any
such standards that divide humans into different social categories. Also, as members of the same
chosen family, it is morally obligatory for those who have the means (to do so) to come to the aid
of the less privileged ones1 to enable them cope with the vagaries of life. Hence, the Yorùbá
ethics is not only humanistic, it is also humanitarian. Failure to show a genuine concern to fellow
human beings, when it is required and the resources are available, is considered a moral
omission.
Also, the humanistic approach of the Yorùbá ethics reveals some level of flexibility in
terms of how quickly a praise-worthy action can change to a blameworthy one, if adequate
attention is not paid to its deprecating effect on human agency. It means what appears a morally
right line of action may degenerate into a socially unacceptable act if caution fails to apply (see
Lawuyi 1988).
1
Including the poor, the weak, the sick, persons with disabilities, elders, and all the vulnerable in general.
4
The concern for human beings as the centre for ethical considerations among the Yorùbá
plays a pivotal role in the way they see and relate to other (non-human) components of the
universe. In other words, the Yorùbá moral attitudes towards non-human animals, trees, rocks,
water, land, etc. are regulated and sometimes moderated by possible implications they bear on
human welfare and interests. Strictly speaking, even though these environmental components of
nature do not constitute direct objects of moral concern (as humans are), human attitude towards
them may advance or disrupt human welfare or interests. The reason for this can be found in the
the ecological confinement called the world (see Balogun 2018). Invariably, since human beings
are part of the environment, whatever affects the environment equally affects them. Hence, the
need to treat the environment as an ally that must be accorded some high level of respect in order
to allow for the fulfilment of human earthly destiny. A good world is a necessary condition for a
Communality
There seems to be a great consensus among scholars that Africans practice a communalistic
social system (Idowu 1962; Mbiti 1969, Makinde 1988, Gbadegesin 2005). Their moral world is
defined by collective concerns rather than individual concerns. This central feature of Africa
social relation finds an illustrative expression in Yorùbá moral system. Joseph Omoregbe (2005)
clarifies what it means when African ethics is said to be communalistic by averring that in such
ethics, what one does affects all the others, and to this, one should add, what all others do affect
one. Further, it ‘means to say that one is there for the community just as the community is what
5
The communal outlook of the traditional Yorùbá ethics is forcefully brought out by their
based. The indigenous Yorùbá lived in towns and villages which were further broken down into
extended families. This social structure plays a pivotal role in the acculturation of moral ideals
into an individual, right from birth. Gbadegesin (2005) explains how a newly born child is
welcome into the waiting hands of older members of the family, amidst cheerfulness, joy and
prayers. At the appropriate time, usually the eighth day, the child is given names, determined
from circumstances predating its birth. The community assists the individual as he/she climbs the
ladder of personhood. In the traditional Yorùbá society, the task of morally molding a child is not
an exclusive responsibility of the parents alone; rather, it is a joint task of all older members of
the community. This point is supported by the saying ojú kan níí bímọ, igba ojú níí tọ (it takes a
single person to bear a child, but several persons to bring him/her up). Hence, the individual is
imbued with the sense of communal living from childhood, which naturally conditions him/her
to see self as a part of a whole, and not a whole all by himself or herself. Gbadegesin (2005) sees
Not that the community forces itself on an unyielding individual; rather the
individual, through socialization and the love and concerns which the household
and the community have extended to him/her cannot now see himself or herself as
anything apart from his/her community. Interest in his/her success is shown by
members of the extended family who regard him/her as their blood and the
community are (sic) also able to trace their origin to a common even if mythical
ancestor. There is, therefore, a feeling of solidarity among its members and this is
neither forced nor solicited (2005: 131).
Although the feeling of solidarity is neither forced nor solicited, it serves as a motivation for
acting or refusing to act in certain ways. In other words, solidarity with other members of the
community, forms part of what determines the rightness or wrongness of an action within
Yorùbá moral system. For instance, it is morally imperative that one rejoices with members of
6
one’s community whenever there is a thing of joy such as the arrival of a new baby, the occasion
of the roofing of a new house, conferment of a chieftaincy title, and the likes. On the other hand,
it is expected that one be soberly when calamities strike any member of the community. In fact,
sometimes major celebrations are cancelled because of the tragedies that befall members of
families. Here, there is no personal mood; each person’s mood is determined by the general
mood of the community. Any individual who is not attuned to the prevalent mood of the
The socio-ethical picture painted above has a great impact on the lives of the Yorùbá
person living outside his/her immediate community. In the first place, it helps to form social
bonding with other members of the immediate community both of whom now live in a foreign
land. Abroad, all Yorùbá persons are brothers and sisters because of their common ancestral
source. Such moral outlook helps to foster the culture of cooperation, unity and nationalist
consciousness among the Yorùbá. Yorùbá detest loneliness so much as a trait that they consider
it an evil worthy of being prayed against. 2 One of their proverbs says Àgbájọ ọwọ laa fi sàn’yà
(In unity we fight a common cause). Also, the emotional attachment to the feeling of solidarity
makes it morally obligatory for members of a community resident outside to always give back to
their communities if they have means to do so. Giving back here may mean different things
ranging from owning a house in one’s community, helping in training other people’s children, to
contributing to the general welfare of the community in some other unspecified ways. It is
immoral for any individual to have the means to give back to his/her community but refuses to
do it.
2
The Yoruba have a folksong that goes thus:
A da nikan je; a da nikan mu - he/she eats alone; he/she drinks alone
A da nikan gbenu palo bi eranko - he/she lives in the parlour like an animal
Ori mi ma je n s’ada nikan gbele o! - May my Ori not make me live in the house alone.
7
Religiosity
It has always been tempting for scholars to describe African moral system as religious. This
temptation is real, and the urge very strong. Some (Wiredu 1983, Oluwole 1984-85, Omoregbe
1989, 2005) have resisted the urge, and found alternative foundations for African ethics.
However, it is doubtful whether such alternative foundations can be pushed to their logical
conclusion without encountering religion on the way. The observation by J. S. Mbiti (1969) that
Africans are irredeemably religious is one that is very difficult to refute in the light of the
happenings on the African continent. One argument against this position, advanced by Omoregbe
(2005), appeals to the fact that there are people with strong moral standing in Africa who do not
profess any religion. This is correct, but never inconsistent with the claim that African lives are
pervaded with religious beliefs. The claim that Africans are religious people does not mean that
every individual in Africa is a religious person. No trait ever robs on all members of a society.
Beside the fact that irreligiosity is a current orientation in Africa (Balogun 2014), imported into
its culture through contact with the ‘critical’ attitude of the western intellectual tradition; it was
almost impossible in the African traditional society to avoid religious considerations in choosing
Writing about the Yorùbá, scholars such as Idowu (1962), and Awolalu and Dopamu
(1979) have defended the religious foundation thesis. Idowu (1962) regards morality among the
Yorùbá as certainly the fruit of religion. To Awolalu and Dopamu (1979), morality is not merely
a human invention, it is an offspring of religion. The import of these scholars’ argument is that,
among Yorùbá, religion and morality, like Siamese twins, are conceptually inextricable, with the
former providing a foundation and justification for the latter. According to Bewaji (2006), the
attitude of Idowu and Awolalu and Dopamu could be attributed to the influence of their foreign
8
academic mentors such as G. E. Parrinder, R. S. Rattray, and A. B. Ellis. Makinde (1988), on his
part, does not appear to have anything against religion being the foundation of morality. For him,
In so far as reason can neither prove that God exists or not, it cannot be an offence
against reason to postulate that God, as a perfect, benevolent and the highest
good, exists and then trace the origin of our morality to His will and ideal of
moral perfection… after all, there is nothing objectionable in an obedience to the
Biblical injunction ‘love thy neighbour as thyself (1988: 8).
It is therefore reasonable to conclude that Makinde is in support of the religious foundation of
Yorùbá moral system. It should be noted that the controversy surrounding the proper relationship
between religion and morality in the Yorùbá context, has to do with whether or not the former
serves as the foundation for the latter. Taken at face value, nothing seems to be inherently wrong
in religion being a basis for morality, if by this, derogation is not intended. Religion and morality
are not mutually exclusive within the Yorùbá ethical context: religion helps individual to make
correct moral choices as a way of courting friendly relationship with the Deity and other spiritual
beings. Thus, among the Yorùbá, religion is important, but, as Bewaji (2006) notes, not
necessarily as the foundation of morals, but as an instrument of ensuring the welfare of the
individual and the society. The point then is that religion has a pivotal role in Yorùbá morality,
even if this role is not a foundational one. The roles of God and other smaller deities in the
formation, institutionalization and enforcement of moral laws will constitute the central
Existentiality
Yorùbá ethics is built on the principle of choice-based actions and responsibilities. The choices
that people make are what the essence and worth of their social standings consist in. Although
these choices are influenced, to a large extent, by the social milieu in which one finds oneself,
the choice whether on or not to be so influenced, is strictly that of the acting individual. This may
9
appear strange, and inconsistent with the communality that typifies African (Yorùbá) social
setting. In fact, some scholars have argued, sometimes with an uncut emphasis, that
individualism is strange to the African mind. On a critical look, however, there is nothing I have
said here that stands contrary to African communal existence. Against completely communalist
standpoint, scholars like Gbadegesin (2005), Ogungbemi (2007) and Famakinwa (2010) have
sought to reconcile the individual with the community by noting that the former is not crushed
under the weight of the latter. Hence, while the fact that Africans are communalistic remains
unobjectionable, the right of the individual for autonomous actions is not thereby eroded.
Although they intend the same conclusion, Gbadegesin and Ogungbemi are motivated by
different reasons for their positions. For Gbadegesin (2005), the individuals are valued in the
the existential attribute of individuality in Yorùbá moral system, Gbadegesin writes further:
Emphasis is placed on usefulness to self and the community, and not on wealth or
strength. If individual uniqueness were not recognized, how could we have such
powerful figures as Kurumi, Latoosa, Obokun, Moremi becoming charismatic
leaders? (2005: 131).
It may be argued that the ‘historico-heroic’ figures listed above became paradigms of moral
courage for their generations and beyond because of the personal choices they made at one point
of their lives. The case of Moremi is instructive. Oral tradition has it that she came to historical
limelight as a result of the sacrificial role she played in extricating her people from the frequent
invasions by their enemies. This choice was not without its price (responsibility), which involved
the death of her only child. She has, since then, become an epitome of courage, promise-keeping,
10
For Ogungbemi (2007), the belief in individuality spans through the entire life of the
Yorùbá person from his/her creation to death. At creation, it is the individual that is molded by
Òrìṣàńlá and given breath to by Olódừmarè, who proceeds to the house of Àjàlá to take his/her
orí. In all of these, only the individual features. Specifically on the choice of orí, Ogungbemi
identifies three key elements that betray the Yorùbá belief in individuality, namely, freedom of
choice, freedom of action and responsibility (2007: 122). While in the world, the individuality of
each person is well established. For example, Yorùbá idea of punishment for moral failures is
done on a personal, not corporate, basis. The proverbial saying, Ìka tó bá ṣẹ ni Ọba ńgé (It is the
finger that errs that the King cuts) attests to this observation. Punishment results from a choice
previously made; that is, it is a way of being responsible for one’s action or omission. It, thus,
follows that, by punishing moral offenders, the Yorùbá take individuals as responsible for their
actions. Were this not the case, the idea of punishment would have been significantly rendered
arbitrary.
If the forgoing were correct about the existential status of Yorùbá ethics, then there really
must be a problem with Wale Olajide’s (2011) submission that humans’ values are crafted for
them by God, and that they unconditionally must abide by these dictates. This submission is
informed by his position that each person has already chosen his/her essence within which
his/her scope for any other form of choice is simply stifled (ibid.). The implication of this on
human freedom is dire and unsustainable. Besides, it is not consistent with the belief that God
created each person with what the Yorùbá call Ifá àyà – roughly, Yorùbá equivalent of
conscience – a belief that Olajide seems to accept as true. My position is that, although the
Yorùbá concede to the existence of such ‘oracle of the heart’ in every person, the individual has
the freedom either or not to act in accordance with its dictates, which is the line between morally
11
good persons and their morally bad counterparts. Pace Olajide, there seems to be a sense in
which humans choose their values; the choice made naturally makes one either good or bad
person.
Rationality
Rationality is here used in the Aristotle’s sense of self-interestedness of action or inaction. For an
action to be rational, thus, means that the action follows from the human drive for self-interest.
What has been said about the Yorùbá ethical system so far shows that it is in the interest of the
acting agent to live a moral life. The interest talked about here is both personal interests and
We can say that people obey moral laws to enjoy the benefit of morality on the
one hand, and to avoid sanctions that accompany the violation of such moral
rules, on the other hand. In talking about benefits, the individual tries to be
prudent in his action. He also takes actions on an expeditious basis depending on
the situation he finds himself in. What all this points to is that human well-being
in the form of individual interest and social interest, constitutes the main rationale
for being moral (2002: 95).
Balogun (2013), thus, describes Yorùbá moral outlook as an ‘end-centric’ system. Yorùbá
consider the outcomes of their actions before embarking on them. Outcomes are what confer
moral status on actions. A good action produces a good outcome; and a bad action a bad
among the Yorùbá. These, as identified by Balogun (2013), are: good personal name, a well-
ordered relationship with others members of the human community, and a secured place among
the ancestors after death. At the base of each of these considerations lies the self-interest of the
acting agent. A good personal name is never sought for its own sake. If a good name is better
12
than silver and gold, as the Yorùbá agree, there must be something in good names that is of
higher worth than both silver and gold, to the acting agent. Also, a well-ordered relationship with
others in the human community guarantees an enabling environment that makes fulfillment of
destiny not only possible but with less social impediments. The last and the ultimate end towards
which an average Yoruba person strives is the last home, built on the religious belief and practice
of ancestors worship. Every Yorùbá elder looks to the future when they will reunite with their
departed forefathers/foremothers, and merge with the continuum of beings on the other side of
life. This is often accompanied with excitement and fear, as noted by Idowu (1962):
It is on account of After-life that we treat today hospitably, that we make good use
of the present and not abuse it. The Yorùbá aged look forward with longing or
dread in anticipation of what may be awaiting them in the new life where they are
bound to fare according to their deserts.
As an end-centric moral system, the description of Yorùbá ethics as an instance of
consequentialism, however, is not driven by the ‘end justifies the means’ motive as found in the
theories, the Yorùbá do not differentiate between the means and the end, especially when these
are found to be causally related. Within the framework of Yorùbá belief-system, a means is an
end in process; hence, when the means is wrong, the end cannot be right (Balogun 2013). A
support for this can be found in a line from Odù Ogbeate, a verse in the Yorùbá Ifá literary
corpus, which cautions that A kìí fi ìkà di ẹrừ kó gún gégé – we cannot use evil to secure good
and expect them to be anchored firmly (Karenga 1999). Hence, the means-end dichotomy that
Reciprocity
13
There seems to be a consensus among scholars that Yorùbá ethical system exemplifies what is
known in ethical discourse as the Golden Rule (Oluwole 1984-85; Makinde 1988 Omoregbe
1989). The most familiar version of the Golden Rule in moral philosophy says ‘Do unto others as
you would have them do unto you’ (Puka nd). The idea of Golden Rule, therefore, urges us to
make ourselves the measure of how we ought to act in relation to others. This describes the
reciprocity that underlies Yorùbá moral philosophy. In Ifá literary corpus, the Yorùbá moral
reciprocity is called the principle of ‘share with me that I may share with you’. Karenga (1999),
citing Odù Irosun-Obara in Ifá literary corpus, reveals the essence of this principle: ‘If we
practice the principle of share with me that I may share with you, the world will be an orderly
place’ (127). The rationale for this sense of reciprocity is found in the fact that all humans are in
the same situation, that is, the human journey, and on this journey a helping hand receives help in
return (Frisvold 2016). Fair play is here being emphasized. According to Arman, quoted in
Oladipo (Oladipo 2006: 141), reciprocity is characterized by ‘giving, but only from those from
whom we receive in equal measure. Receiving, but from only those to whom we give in
reciprocal measure’. This builds a healthy culture of mutuality of benefits and burdens, and a
community characterized by mutual trust and interdependence, wherein fear is not entertained.
The saying, ‘Ọtún wẹ òsì; òsì wẹ òtún níí mú ọwọ méjèèjì mọ’ (A complementary washing leaves
Beside its prescriptive appeal, the principle of reciprocity also describes the Yorùbá
belief in attendant cosmic justice that trails individual action, be it good or bad. Consciousness of
this cosmic justice called ẹsan is a fundamental social regulatory factor in the traditional society.
Ẹsan is that which a moral agent receives as the consequence of his/her moral deed. Hence, when
one considers that ẹsan is inevitable, one will reconsiders one’s action. Thus, Yorùbá will say:
14
‘Ẹnití ó ṣe oore, ó ṣeé fún ara rẹ, ẹnití ó ṣe ìkà, ó ṣeé fún ara rẹ. Àti oore àti ìkà,
ọkan kìí gbé. Ọjọ àtisùn l’ó ṣòro. (The person who performs good deeds does so
for himself/herself. The person who performs wicked acts does so for
himself/herself. Neither good deeds nor wicked acts will go unrewarded. The time
of death is the hard fact that should be born in mind)’ (Gbadegesin 2005: 138).
The lesson from this is that whatever one does, one will always receive in the proper measure.
Given this principle of reciprocity, humans are encouraged to take seriously moral virtues such
as hospitality to strangers, generosity to other human beings, readiness to assist others in times of
needs, forgiveness of those that offend us, and respect for people of all age-groups. Observing
these implies throwing cold water to the ground of the future so as to tread on cold ground. The
wisdom here is that, since no one is sufficient, morally or materially, it is good to sow these
virtues so as to be their recipient when one stands in need of them in the future.
Character-Based
It is rare to see any serious discussion of Yorùbá ethics without situating it within its character-
centrality. The Yorùbá word for character is ìwà. But ìwà is an ambiguous word because it can
either mean character or existence – or, according to Abimbola, ‘the fact of being, living or
existing’ (Abimbola 1975; Roland 1983; Oke 1988; Gbadegesin 2005). It should be noted,
however, that, unlike other ambiguous words, ìwà (as character) derives from ìwà (as existence).
As noted by Roland (1983), ìwà, both as character and existence, do not just have a homophone
relationship, they are also related by etymology and one appears to be a derivation of the other.
Hence, the former is not completely meaningful without the latter. Taken as the attribute of
beingness (Oke 1988), ìwà determines the essence of a person, as existence determines the
essence of things. There is, therefore, a connection between one’s personhood (as one’s essence)
and one’s ìwà. Although there are ìwà rere (good character) and ìwà búburú/burúkú (bad
character), some Yorùbá speakers just use ìwà to denote good character, for one either has ìwà or
15
lacks it. To have ìwà is to be a person; while to lack ìwà is to not be a person. Lack of ìwà leads
to the denial of one’s existence at the level of personhood. This conceptual synchronism is very
It, thus, follows that personhood is not a given. One learns to be a person by developing
or building one’s character in a socially acceptable manner. It is with one’s hand that one shapes
one’s character. Just as one can develop from a non-person to a person by developing one’s
character; one can also degenerate from a person to a non-person by losing one’s character. This
points to the indispensability of character in the search for a good life both on earth and after-life.
Karenga (2009: 346), quoting from Odù 31: 3, writes: ‘Character is all that is required. There is
no destiny that needs to be called unfortunate (bad) in Ifè City. For character is all that is
required’. Ìwà is to be nurtured and treasured because it is the key to sustaining one’s
achievements. For without ìwà, every good thing that a person has achieved, will automatically
become someone else’s. Yorùbá belief-system also connects the fulfilment of personal destiny to
possession of good character. In other words, that a person has good destiny as contained in
his/her orí is not a guarantee that such person will end up fulfilling such destiny; only good
character ensures fulfilment of destiny (Labeodan 2009). Even someone with bad destiny can
Among the Yorùbá, a morally ideal person is called Ọmọlúàbí, that is, an offspring of the
source of ìwà, ‘a person who embodies all the qualities appreciated by Yorùbá people’
(Labeodan 2009: 348). There are a number of these qualities that a morally upright person is
expected to be in possession of. Idowu (1962) refers to these qualities as ‘the main components
of good character’. Among these are: chastity in women, hospitality, unselfishness, generosity,
truth-telling, protection of women, respect for others, especially elders, as well as avoidance of
16
stealing, covenant-breaking, and hypocrisy. Others identified by Fayemi (2009) are good heart
towards others, bravery, hard-work and intelligence. An Ọmọlúàbí, must also be someone who is
properly nurtured, and who behaves accordingly (Oluwole 2007). There are also the qualities of
Ìfarabalẹ (to have control over one’s physical body and the mind), ìlutí (good listening ability)
and ìfẹràn (love towards oneself and others). A person with these qualities not only lives a
blissful life on earth, but also has the assurance of entering good heaven (Ọrun rere) after death.
Having itemized and discussed the seven pillars of Yorùbá ethical thought-system in the
foregoing manner, the current section interrogates the roles of the gods and their deputies in the
institution of morality among Yorùbá. There is no agreement among scholars as to the exact
roles played by the transcendental objects of worship in the moral system of the Yorùbá. As
earlier noted, there are two camps to this discourse. In holding that morality is founded on
religion, Idowu (1962) and others can be said to attribute a legislative role to the gods. This
would mean that God or gods is/are founder(s) of morality as a regulatory mechanism and an
instrument of control of behaviours of creatures in the created world. The Ifá-àyà (conscience)
hypothesis, for instance, shows that Olódừmarè (God in Yorùbá language) puts the
consciousness of the moral order in the heart of human beings to constantly guide them to make
right decisions in moral matters. Having created the individual with his/her conscience, a willful
disobedience to the dictate of it attracts divine punitive consequences, for anyone who knows
that a thing is wrong and still goes ahead to do it, is wicked and deserving of punishment.
The appeal to gods is born out of the epistemic limitations of human beings. So many
acts of wickedness go unpunished by human social agencies because the perpetrators are hidden
from human sight – wicked acts are carried out at nights. But this is not the case with God and
17
the gods. They see where human sight fails. E. M. Lijadu (1923: 8) cites evidence of this in one
Ifá verse:
Olódừmarè can penetrate. It (the message) is intended for a sneaking thief who
boasts that earthly kings cannot find him out. If earthly kings cannot see you, do
you not think that the eyes of the heavenly king are on you?
Deities such as Sàngó, Sànpọnná, Ayé lála, Ògún, among others, are often consulted for justice,
when a wicked act is done against a member of the community by an unknown person. It is often
part of the processes that the priests of these gods ask the suspects in the case to confess if they
know anything about the act for which justice is being sought. Where anyone fails to confess, the
priest goes ahead with the invocation of the wrath of the deity concerned, and in due course, the
perpetrator is brought to justice, most times with irrevocable consequences. This has made some
to argue that the role of the gods is that of enforcement, rather than legislators, of the moral laws
(see Oluwole 1984). This is another justification of the role of God or the gods in matters of
For the latter, reference has often been made to taboo/tabu (Yorùbá: èèwọ), which are
‘things prohibited by the Supreme Being, the divinities and the ancestors’ (Bewaji 2006). Given
this prohibitive tendency, humans are expected to avoid them in order not to incur the wrath of
the spirit being involved as the case may be. It is, therefore, clear why Yorùbá stay clear of
explanation is given as to why actions forbidden by taboo are wrong except that the gods hate
such things and anybody who does them would incur the vengeance of the gods (Omoregbe
2005). However, this attracts the problem of whether the gods hate the acts because they are
wrong or they are wrong because gods hate them. Although this problem has not been
sufficiently examined within Yorùbá moral system, it could be argued that if one affirms the
18
former, then one may conclude that moral institution is based on the inherent wrongness and
rightness of certain actions, which explain why those actions are frowned at both by the gods and
human beings. If, on the other hand, one affirms the latter, then morality becomes a matter of the
whims and caprices of the gods, wherein human inputs are neither necessary nor sought. There
Ifá literary corpus provides the epistemological source and motivational force for the Yorùbá
ethical system. Ifá literary corpus (Odù Ifá) is the sacred text of the ancient wisdom. It reveals
the profundity and beauty of Yorùbá spiritual and ethical tradition of Ifá, which is one of the
greatest sacred texts of the world and a classic of African and world literature (Karenga 2008).
Ifá wisdom is ascribed to a mythical personality called Ọrúnmìlà, reputed for having a perfect
measure of wisdom, which he reveals to human beings through the Ifá divination.
The ethical visions of Ifá are thoroughly cosmopolitan. Human being are sent to the
world saddled with the divine obligation to bring good to the world. Ifá teaches that our world is
broken, that we need to reassemble the shards of wisdom into their original unity, both on a
personal and global levels (Frisvold 2016). Karenga (2008) identifies four-tiered themes of Ifá as
all revolving around the theme of goodness of the human-populated world. They are ‘the
Goodness of and in the world, the chosen status of humans in the world; the criteria of the good
world; and the requirements for the good world’ (Karenga 2008). Hence, the chosen status of the
humans (i.e. ènìyàn) is not without its responsibility, to cure the world of its numerous evils such
as poverty, oppression, exploitation and general suffering of people; and therefore ensure a world
filled with sufficient good for human survival and convenience. One important element of the
chosen status of humans is that it is not bound by any classificatory paradigm such as nation,
19
race, gender, special religious relationship or promise. ‘And we are chosen not over and against
anyone, but chosen with everyone to bring good in the world’ (Karenga 2008, 2009). Ifá teaches
that all deserves the right to a good life, achievable only through obligation of shared
responsibility to make the world a good place for everyone. Hence, Ifá ethical vision is
Achieving a good world for all, therefore, demands that character becomes an
indispensable companion to human beings in their respective earthly spheres of existence. This
demands also permeates the length and breadth of Ifá literary corpus. As Frisvold (2016) notes,
‘Ifá is revealed ultimately to be a philosophy of character, and its diversity’. Character provides
the required light with which the individual navigates the dark terrains that the world is. Hence,
anyone without character is bound to fall into a ditch that will ultimately make the world an
unfavourable place to live in. Using Ọfún Méjì, Frisvold highlights some other ethical
requirements for peaceful co-existence among people in the world. These include possession of
inner peace, patience, love, forgiveness, compassion, generosity and charity as well as the
avoidance of greed and jealousy. At personal level, Ifá teaches ethics of cleanliness and personal
hygiene, as a force of attraction to fortunes and realization of a good destiny. It is, therefore,
plausible to surmise here that Ifá does not only provide motivations for moral living, it is also a
In contemporary times, the originality of Yorùbá ethical system has come under a heavy attack
by the forces of modernity and civilizations, especially those brought about by the introduction
of Christianity and Islam. While there is no significant conflict between Yorùbá morality and
these foreign religions in terms of rightness and wrongness, it could be observed that the focus
20
on the motivation for living morally has significantly shifted from a concern for healthy
ultimate avoidance of hell. It is not the case that these religious beliefs were totally strange to the
Yorùbá before their contact with European and Arabian missionaries. Of course there are
equivalents of heaven and hell in Yorùbá linguistic convention: Ọrun Rere (Good Heaven) and
Ọrun Àpáàdì (Heaven of Potsherds) (Fadipe 1991). As Dopamu and Alana (2004) find out,
‘there are sufficient hints to believe that the good go to the Good Heaven of the ancestors,
divinities and God, while the wicked go to the Heaven of Potsherds’. However desirous people
were of this Good Heaven, it was not taken as the primary motivation for living morally, at least,
not above the need for good life here on earth. Now, people are more concerned about making
heaven to the manifest neglect of their duties to good life on earth. Other influences of
Christianity and Islam on traditional ethic have been chronicled by Idowu (1962: 211) as
follows:
This has destroyed the communalistic fervor of Yorùbá moral values. The saying Ayé la ó ṣe ká
tó ṣ’ọrun (This world first, then heaven) is an indication that Yorùbá put a premium on healthy
humanism above anything outside here. Attentions have also been shifted from Ifá to either the
21
Yorùbá ethics has also been impacted by the force of globalization, as other aspects of
Yorùbá culture. The Cultural Revolution brought about by globalization, more than religions, has
left Yorùbá sense of morality worse than it met it. Some of the values that were held in high
esteem have lost their place. The culture of virginity, respect for elders, hard-work, good
dressing sense, among other, that used to be the hallmark of Ọmọlúàbí, have now been replaced
by their direct opposites. What used to be shameful things are now fashionable, and vice-versa.
For example, smoking of hemp used to be a shameful thing; so it was done in the bush. It was
from this that Yorùbá term for Indian hemp Igbó (bush) originated. However, in the
contemporary Yorùbá community, hemp is now smoked among people without any sense of
moral shame attached. The rat-race to become rich has made the virtue of Ọmọlúàbí a thing of
Conclusion
the Yorùbá group of Nigeria. It showed an ethic rich in considerations for the well-being of both
the individual and the community, with connecting threads spanning beyond earthly concerns to
the after-life. Both at personal and global levels, Yorùbá ethics extols human essence, which
culminates in a human-centred ethical thinking. Given the outline of the Yorùbá ethical system
attempted in this essay, it could be submitted that Yorùbá hold an optimistic view of human
nature as capable of providing solution to the world’s problems. The world’s problems are
inspired by the activities of human beings; and it takes human efforts, in terms of character, to
22
References
Abiodun, R. (1983), ‘Identity and the Artistic Process in Yorùbá Aesthetic Conception of Ìwà’,
Journal of Cultures and Ideas, 1(1): 13-30.
Abimbola, W. (1975), ‘Ìwàpẹlẹ: The Concept of Good Character in Ifá Literary Corpus’, in
Wande Abimbola (ed.) Yorùbá Oral Tradition, 387–420, Ife: Ife African Languages and
Literature Series, no. 1.
Armah. A. K. (1979), Two Thousand Seasons. London: Heinemann Educational Books Ltd.
Awolalu, J. O. and Dopamu, P. A. (1979), West African Traditional Religion. Ibadan: Onibonoje
Press and Book Industry Ltd.
Balogun, B. J. (2018), ‘A Sartrean Approach to Ayé Ṣíṣe in Yorùbá Existentialism’, Yorùbá
Studies Review, (Special Edition), 3(1): 297-314.
Balogun, B. J. (2017), ‘Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights: The Yorùbá Example’,
Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions, 6(2): 1-19.
Balogun, B. J. (2014), ‘Ibi: An Examination of the Yorùbá Traditional-Existentialist Conception
of Evil’, Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya, 6(2): 55-
73.
Balogun, B. J. (2013), ‘The Consequentialist Foundations of Traditional Yorùbá Ethics: An
Exposition’, Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya, 5(2):
103-121.
Bewaji, J. A. I. (2006), ‘Ethics and Morality in Yorùbá Culture’, in Kwasi Wiredu (ed.) A
Companion to African Philosophy, 396-403, Malden: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Dopamu, P. A. and Alana, E. O. (2004), ‘Ethical System’, in Nike Lawal, Matthew Sadiku and
Ade Dopamu (eds.) Understanding Yorùbá Life and Culture, 155-157, New Jersey: African
World Press.
Fadipe, N. A. (1991), The Sociology of the Yorùbá, Ibadan: Ibadan University Press.
23
Famakinwa, J. O. (2010), ‘How Moderate is Gyekye’s Moderate Communitarianism?’, Thought
and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Society of Kenya, 2(2): 65-77.
Fayemi, A. K. (2009), ‘Human Personality and the Yorùbá Worldview: An Ethico-Sociological
Interpretation’, Journal of Pan-African Studies, 2(9):166-176.
Frisvold, N. M. (2016), Ifá: A Forest of Mystery, London: Scarlet Imprint.
Gbadegesin, S. (2005), ‘Yorùbá Philosophy: Individuality, Communality, and the Moral Order’,
in Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze (ed.) African Philosophy: An Anthology, 130-141, Malden:
Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Gyekye, K. (2010), ‘African Ethics’, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/african-ethics/. Accessed
15th January, 2020.
Idowu, E. B. (1962), Olódùmarè: God in Yorùbá Belief, London: Longman Ltd.
Karenga, M. (2009), ‘Ènìyàn’, Molefi Kete Asante and Ama Mazama (eds.) Encyclopedia of
African Religions, 239-240, California: Sage Publications, Inc.
Karenga, M. (2008), ‘Ethical Insights from Odù Ifá: Choosing to be Chosen’, Los Angeles
Sentinel (of 25th January), A-7.
Karenga, M. (1999), Odù Ifá: The Ethical Teaching, Los Angeles: University of Sankore Press.
Labeodan, K. (2009), ‘Ìwà Pẹlẹ’, in Molefi Kete Asante and Ama Mazama (eds.) Encyclopedia
of African Religions, 348-349, California: Sage Publications, Inc.
Lijadu, E. M. (1923), Ifá, Imọlẹ Rẹ, Exeter: J. Townsend & Son.
Lawuyi, O. B. (1988), ‘The Tortoise and the Snail: Animal Identities and Ethical Issues
Concerning Political Behaviours among the Yorùbá of Nigeria’, Second Order, 1(2): 29-45.
Makinde, M. A. (1988), ‘African Culture and Moral Systems: A Philosophical Study’, Second
Order, 1(2): 1-27.
Mbiti, J. S. (1969), African Religions and Philosophy, Oxford: Heinemann Educational
Publishers.
Ogungbemi, S. (2007), Philosophy and Development, Ibadan: Hope Publications.
Oke, M. (1988), ‘Self-Interest as the Ground of Moral Obligation’, Second Order, 1(2): 79-103.
Oladipo, O. (2006), ‘Challenges of African Philosophy in the Twenty-First Century’, in
Olusegun Oladipo (ed.) Core Issues in African Philosophy. Ibadan: Hope Publications.
Olajide, W. (2011), ‘Existential Reversal and Yorùbá Philosophy’, Lumina, 22: 1-15.
Oluwole, S. (1984-85), ‘The Rational Basis of Yorùbá Ethical Thinking’, The Nigerian Journal
of Philosophy, 4/5(1&2): 14-25.
24
Oluwole, S. (2007), African Philosophy on the Threshold of Modernization, First Academic
Publishers.
Omoregbe, J. (2005), ‘Ethics in Traditional African Society’, in Pantaleon Iroegbu and Anthony
Echekwebe (eds.) Kpim of Morality: Ethics, 36-42, Ibadan: Heinemann Educational Books
(Nig.) Plc.
Omoregbe, J. (1989), Ethics: A Systematic and Historical Study, 2nd Edition, Lagos: CEPCO
Communications System Ltd.
Oyeshile, A. O. (2002), ‘Morality and Its Rationale: The Yorùbá Example’, Ibadan Journal of
Humanistic Studies, nos. 11 & 12: 90-98.
Puka, Bill (n.d.), ‘Golden Rule’, in James Fraser and Bradley Dowden (eds.) Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Wiredu, K. (1983), Morality and Religion in Akan Thoug ‘ht’, in H. Odera Oruka and D. A.
Masolo (eds.), Philosophy and Cultures, Nairobi: Bookwise Limited.
25