Tyranny - A New Interpretation - Waller Newell
Tyranny - A New Interpretation - Waller Newell
Tyranny - A New Interpretation - Waller Newell
WALLER R. NEWELL
Carleton University
cambridge university press
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town,
Singapore, São Paulo, Delhi, Mexico City
Cambridge University Press
32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, ny 10013-2473, usa
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107610736
C Waller R. Newell 2013
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls
for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication and does not
guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
contents
Acknowledgments page ix
v
contents
vi
contents
vii
acknowledgments
As I was nearing the completion of this book, the world was being
inspired by the struggle for freedom unfolding across the Arab lands.
During that same period and for some time preceding it, according
to Freedom House, the world’s democracies had been in retreat while
tyrannical forces were on the rise. We seem to be living through an era
in which expectations for freedom and the proliferation of tyranny are
intensifying simultaneously. More than ever, then, it is incumbent on us
to study tyranny, attempt to identify its varieties, and try to anticipate its
emergence and hostility to the forces of freedom. Tyranny is generally
an unpleasant subject, but one does not think about tyranny because
one wants to think about unpleasant things. Rather, if one wants to
think, it must be about both pleasant and unpleasant things.
This book grew out of many years of reflection, and some of the
chapters (1, 3, 4, 5, and a portion of 6) contain greatly transformed
and lengthened versions of earlier articles. The Introduction, Chapters
2 and 7, and the Conclusion are entirely new. None of the chapters,
however, simply duplicates the content of the earlier articles, because I
only arrived at the central thesis of this book through writing them. They
have now been reshaped in light of that thesis, which I set forth in the
Introduction. This book can be read entirely on its own, independent
of my other writings. At the same time, it does draw on, and is the
scholarly culmination of, my earlier books on Plato, the manly virtues,
and political leadership.
Earlier versions of some of the chapters were presented at Peterhouse
College Cambridge, Yale University, and the University of Toronto. I
gratefully acknowledge the stimulation and the hospitality I received
ix
acknowledgments
on those occasions. I also have the pleasure and the honor of acknowl-
edging the critical insight and support that I have received from many
colleagues over the years. Although they share no responsibility for
the book’s shortcomings, they have contributed to whatever of value
readers may find in it. They include, in no special order, the follow-
ing: Charles H. Fairbanks, Thomas L. Pangle, Lorraine Pangle, Clifford
Orwin, Ryan Balot, Nalin Ranasinghe, Stanley Rosen, Catherine Zuck-
ert, Barry Strauss, Paul Rahe, Robert Sibley, Steven Smith, Travis Smith,
Graham Howell, Jarrett Carty, Geoffrey Kellow, Peter Ahrensdorf,
Harvey C. Mansfield, Lynette Mitchell, Jeff Sikkenga, Norman Doidge,
Kenneth Green, Michael Zuckert, Gregory MacIsaac, Peter Emberley,
Tom Darby, Samuel Abraham, H. D. Forbes, Edward Andrew, and
Gary McDowell. I also have the especially gratifying obligation to
acknowledge the insights I derived from discussing the political philoso-
phies examined in this book with students past and present, some of
whom are now embarked on their own careers. Finally, I owe special
thanks to my editor at Cambridge University Press, Robert Dreesen, and
to the anonymous reviewers for the original proposal, who prompted
me to address many important issues in advance that I had neglected.
This book is dedicated to my best friend and collaborator, my wife
Jacqueline Etherington Newell.
x
introduction
The Conquest of Eros
1
tyranny
a tyrant was often a “new man,” someone who seized or usurped exclu-
sive power, whether over a formerly free people or by taking the place
of a lawful king. Sometimes their rule was violent or began in violence,
but tyrants could also be recognized as benevolent, better at the art of
ruling than a legitimate king, and so successful that their position might
become hereditary for a time. However, they never entirely escaped the
taint of illegitimacy. Hence Max Weber derived his famous category
of “charisma” from Sophocles’ Oedipus the Tyrant. Because he came
to power by ridding Thebes of the sphinx and labors under mutterings
about how the legitimate king Laius had been murdered, a crime that he
must also solve to remove a famine, Oedipus must compensate for his
lack of hereditary royal authority and sanctity by proving his intellec-
tual prowess and boldness, which of course leads to his undoing as he is
exposed as his father’s murderer and in an incestuous relationship with
his mother. Throughout the play, one senses the uneasiness of Oedipus’
hold on the throne, how even in the opening lines, the priests seem
unwilling to recognize his claim to authority (30–35), and his vexation
with his behind-the-scenes power-sharing deal with Kreon, the repre-
sentative of the nobility from which a legitimate king would normally
be drawn (575–584). In another variation of the problem posed by
absolute rule, for the Romans, a king (rex) was himself tantamount to
a tyrant, hence the Latin translation of Sophocles’ title as Oedipus Rex.
The Romans’ hatred of their original Etruscan kings was so intense that
even men who later wielded what amounted to royal power such as
Julius Caesar and, above all, his serpentine successor Augustus dared
not claim this title openly but had to sheath it in the constitutional garb
of “first citizen” or “commander” (imperator), even though Augustus
was openly hailed in the Greek provinces as a monarch.2
There are so many ways we can use this term “tyranny” that it is
difficult to isolate a common definition. At a minimum, we could define
it as the use of coercive or violent force to treat others unjustly through
the exercise of political supremacy. But is this not a matter of perspec-
tive? As Hobbes sourly observed, if someone does us good, we praise
him; if someone harms our interests, we call him a tyrant.3 There is
2 For the classic account of how the usurper Octavian sheathed himself in the outward
garb of the restorer of the Republic, see Syme (2002).
3 Hobbes (1971) p. 722.
2
introduction
3
tyranny
more lavish villas for the elite, headed by a canny old mafioso survivor.
Even religiously fanatical regimes such as the rule of the Ayatollahs in
Iran can combine their zealotry with old-fashioned greed and graft of
this kind: the mullahs are said to have stolen millions in public funds
for their personal fortunes. Dictatorships like the former Soviet Union
claiming to be bent on modernization also created a nomenklatura sys-
tem of special privilege and purloined wealth for the party elite. When
the regime fell, they simply stole the state’s property and thereby became
“entrepreneurs,” a feat imitated more successfully and without a full-
blown regime change by China, a mercantilist oligarchy still claiming
to be Marxist. The list goes on and on.
The psychology of tyranny is also a rich vein for speculation. We all
sense that there are different psychological types among tyrants – the
voluptuary, the sadist, the puritan, the coldly efficient manager. Hitler
was a vegetarian and teetotaler as he ordered the deaths of millions.
Stalin issued similar orders while indulging in a gluttonous appetite for
food and booze. Indeed, as we see at length in this study, Aristotle’s
identification in the Politics of despotism with a form of “household”
authority, in which the ruler treats the country as an extension of his
own property, has endured throughout history. In addition to the exam-
ple of Franco, both Hitler and Stalin conducted their most important
state business from their private households and dinner tables, with a
blurry line at best between state official and personal retainer. Although
Hitler himself was not a gourmand, the household pattern of authority
was extended from his getaway home in the Alps to daily lunches in
Berlin where the top paladins of the regime – Speer, Goebbels, Goering,
and others – would discuss policy and monitor each other’s status while
sharing a common meal. According to Albert Speer, these daily lunches
were the heart of the Nazi government.4
Two psychological types have assumed special prominence in the
tradition coming from the classics – the erotic voluptuary and what
we might term the rational or benevolent despot. The first of these
is clearly a tyrant in a blatant way recognizable by all. Think of the
mad and depraved Caligula and Nero with their endless rounds of
cruelty and debauchery. The status of the second type, however – the
rational despot – is much more ambiguous. Everyone has this contrast
4
introduction
5
tyranny
5 Amusingly retold by Everitt (2003). For a masterful account of Julius Caesar as animated
by a love of Greek heroism, see Meier (1997).
6 Hegel (1979) sections 582–595.
6
introduction
7 Readers of Harvey Mansfield will recognize my debt to his exploration of these themes in
Machiavelli’s Virtue (1998), Machiavelli’s New Modes and Orders (2001), and Taming
the Prince (1993), although I do place more emphasis on explicitly metaphysical themes
in my readings. Mansfield’s works are discussed in the chapters to follow. For the devel-
opment of my thesis about the contrast between the personal character of ancient rule
and the impersonal character of modern authority, I am also indebted to Mansfield’s
seminal essay on Hobbes and the “science of indirect government” (1971). Other impor-
tant approaches to Machiavelli and his legacy are considered in due course, including
Rahe (1992, 2005, 2008) and Sullivan (1996, 2004). The identification of modern state
authority with the transition to impersonal authority is also a theme of the recent book
by Fukuyama (2011).
7
tyranny
8 In this sense, Weiss’s interesting book would be on a different page from mine because
she argues that Socrates in the Meno is defending the possibility of adequate moral virtue
bereft of metaphysical inquiry (2001). As Stauffer argues, Socrates in his rhetoric stresses
the tension between philosophy and the city while arguing that, at the same time and for
this very reason, philosophy is “the moral conscience of the city” (2006, p. 179).
9 This is why I cannot go all the way with Hadot (1995), interesting as his argument is,
in seeing Socratic or Platonic philosophizing as “spiritual exercises” akin to personal
therapy or mystical techniques or as if Socrates simply embodied a vague “way of life”
alongside other ways of life. The Platonic Socrates does not base his argument solely
on the best askesis for the individual but on what is objectively true and real about the
cosmos, and philosophy is not presented merely as a “way of life” but as the magisterial
guide to the truth about the cosmos, or at least the pursuit of it, and therefore as the most
suitable governor for other “ways of life” including politics and poetry. Admirable as the
postmodernist reading of Plato is in some respects as a way of freeing it from the dead
8
introduction
The studies that follow are much concerned with the problem posed
by excessive ambition spurred by an eros for glory and for possession of
the city, a problem exemplified in different ways by Sophocles’ Oedipus,
Homer’s Achilles, and Socrates’ companion Alcibiades. Plato begins a
tradition of suggesting that those aberrant erotic longings for victory
and possession might be rechanneled toward serving the common good
guided by philosophy. Unlike modern thinkers such as Hobbes, the
classics take it as given that these aberrant erotic passions cannot be
wholly suppressed or extirpated but must be reshaped and redirected
through civic paideia. As the examples of Oedipus, Achilles, and Alcibi-
ades variously illustrate, the energy and vigor of the ambitious, although
potentially dangerous, are sometimes needed by the political commu-
nity in situations of extreme peril, war, or national emergency. For the
classics, the challenge is to shape such men’s characters in a way that
will make them prefer the honor of vigorous citizenship in coopera-
tion with their fellow citizens to the excesses of tyranny. However, this
rehabilitation of eros on a psychological level to become the ally of
sound statesmanship is indivisibly connected to a view of the cosmos as
balanced and moderate so as to ground and justify on the transhuman
level the desired human and civic therapy. If the cosmos is characterized
by violent impulse and disorder, the human soul will mirror those dan-
gerous qualities. If, however, the cosmos is harmonious and balanced,
civic education can aspire to inculcate those same virtuous qualities in
the citizenry. This link between soul and cosmos, this balance between
mind and passions, is crystalized in such famous Platonic images as the
Chariot of the Soul and Diotima’s Ladder, just as later classical state-
ments of this need for balance such as Cicero’s depiction of the Dream
of Scipio the Younger tie the correct balance of active and contempla-
tive virtues in the soul to a vision of the celestial order. That is why for
Plato, as we consider in this book, the reform of political psychology
and statesmanship is indivisible from a critical encounter with the pre-
Socratics’ and Sophists’ radically opposed understanding of nature as
motion and its concomitant endorsement of tyrannical aggression (as
in Book 10 of the Laws).10
hand of utilitarian and analytical rationality, it often leads to an even more misleading
reduction of ancient philosophy to mere personal “care of the self.”
10 Plato, the Laws 888–890. On the ontological arguments of the pre-Socratics and
Sophists, consider Newell (2000) ch. 2.
9
tyranny
10
introduction
natural world with which human nature is connected and from which
it seeks its bearings. For the ancients, both the danger of the tyrannical
soul arising and the possibility of a therapy for it emerge within the order
of nature, so that the correct treatment for aberrant erotic passions is
to redirect them toward their proper natural fulfillments – civic virtue
and the contemplative life. For the moderns, by contrast, starting with
Machiavelli, the possibility is explored that through an effort of will,
we can master Fortuna, striving to step outside of nature’s limitations
altogether. As we will see, this involves a complex dyadic movement in
which the prince achieves control over Fortuna by, paradoxically, chan-
neling “her” impulsiveness to empower his own daring. The Platonic
orientation by which eros leads the soul on a hierarchical ascent from
the outward beauties of visible reality to the imperishable beauty of the
Good is replaced in Machiavelli’s new psychology by the prince’s inte-
rior and invisible modulation of the rhythms of Fortune’s subrational
impulses within the inward reaches of his own solitude. This contrast
is explored through studies of Plato, Aristotle, Xenophon, Machiavelli,
and Hobbes treating different aspects of this overarching theme. I con-
clude with a general discussion suggesting the wider implications of
the new conception of princely rule launched by Machiavelli includ-
ing, for example, a discussion of Shakespeare’s history plays. I also try
to show how the sometimes bewilderingly various interpretations of
Machiavelli, as well as his multidimensional influence on the various
streams of modern political thought, all derive from his fundamental
project for the mastery of fortune.
Let us dwell for a moment more specifically on why eros can be con-
sidered the prism for clarifying some important aspects of the general
shift away from the classical emphasis on our reconciliation with nature
to the modern project for subduing it. For Plato, eros, if left unguided,
can be the source of spontaneous tyrannical ambition. However, as
he presents it, eros also contains the potential for its own redirection
toward a love of the beautiful and the good, entailing the rehabilitation
and sublimation of those aggressive passions in the service of philoso-
phy and a devotion to the common good. That is to say, erotic longing
can be rehabilitated by being directed toward a love of the balance and
harmony that are superordinate over chance and impulse in the cosmos
as a whole. Eros, in other words, is the key to an orientation toward
the beneficence of the natural order. That is why, for Machiavelli, eros
11
tyranny
must be extirpated from the heart of the prince. The kind of erotic
longing for the beautiful and the good set forth in Plato’s Symposium
is, as we will see, the most dangerous psychological example of what
Machiavelli means by “relying on Fortuna,” that is to say, entertaining
a deluded hopefulness about nature’s friendliness toward our needs,
aspirations, and desire for an honorable life. Therefore, Machiavelli is
not merely endorsing tyranny of the kind that Plato opposed. On the
contrary: he is arguing that the entire Platonic starting point, which
sees eros both as the source of aberrant tyrannical passions and as the
source of their rehabilitation, must be abandoned. Instead, the prince
must aspire to step outside of nature altogether, face the harsh truth that
Fortuna is entirely indifferent to if not outright hostile to human hopes,
and, emboldened by that sense of alienation, turn back on nature and
master it. The key to this revaluation of values is that, before the prince
can master Fortuna outwardly, he must first conquer within himself the
allure of eros and its vision of a beautiful cosmos. The first victory of the
prince must be over his own latently Platonic soul. In this book’s inter-
pretation, then, modern tyranny is launched on the premise that eros
can be extirpated and that nature, thereby reduced to sheer hostile and
purposeless happenstance, can be mastered by an act of cold-minded
will.
14 Popper (1971).
12
introduction
13
tyranny
18 Voegelin’s review of On Tyranny first appeared in The Review of Politics (1949), and
Strauss’s response appeared in later editions of On Tyranny.
14
introduction
15
tyranny
16
introduction
Mark Lilla, in his interesting book, has tried to locate in eros a way
of exploring a continuity between the ancient and modern understand-
ing and experience of tyranny.24 In this view, Heidegger’s notorious
commitment to National Socialism would be a variation on Plato’s flir-
tation with educating the tyrant Dionysius, both stemming from an
immoderation born of excessive eros. Attractive as this thesis may be to
establish a link between ancients and moderns that might validate the
classical starting point and typologies, I argue in this book that eros is
not a constant psychological or ontological category throughout these
ancient and modern examples of philosophic immoderation on behalf
of tyranny. Although one might concede that, broadly speaking, Hei-
degger and Plato were both under the sway of passion, as were their
respective tyrants of choice, it is not the same passion of eros in the
original classical meaning. To put it briefly but not misleadingly, Plato
believed that tyranny might be cured by moving the soul away from
spontaneous impulse toward what is metaphysically highest – and mis-
took Dionysius for an eligible candidate – whereas Heidegger chose as
his “hero” the leader whose “resolve” he believed would shatter the
grip of metaphysics over the sheer spontaneity of existence. The Leader
was, indeed, the candidate of Being.25
As this book argues, the depiction and evaluation of eros changes
between the classical and modern approaches to statesmanship, as does
the role of nature. For the ancients, eros lies within the order of nature,
and the therapy for its spontaneous natural proneness to immoderation
lies in its redirection through education toward its naturally highest ful-
fillments, civic virtue and the contemplative life – an ascent that entails
moderation. In sharp contrast, for the moderns beginning with Machi-
avelli, the erotic link between human nature and the cosmos is shattered
by our fundamental experience of alienation from the “malignity of For-
tuna.” We must step outside of nature to master it, which entails purging
ourselves of our own erotic hopes for cosmically grounded repose. To
reiterate an earlier point: For Machiavelli, it is not simply a matter
of endorsing the kind of tyranny that the classics condemned, but of
24 Lilla (2001).
25 On the intrinsic connections between Heidegger’s philosophy of the 1920s and 1930s
and his commitment to National Socialism, consider Newell (1984, 1988a, 1988b,
1988c).
17
tyranny
18
introduction
19
tyranny
roots are in the tradition of the zoon politikon going back to Aristo-
tle, although I also maintain that Machiavelli almost entirely subverts
and transvaluates their meaning. What we might term the Promethean
vision of the prince as the potential master of Fortune is more sharply
etched in The Prince, whereas the approach of the Discourses is both
more communal and more explicitly reflective about the existential lim-
its placed by external reality and human psychology on our exercise of
will.29 Nevertheless, as we will see, the Promethean vigor of the ideal
prince is, according to Machiavelli, also an important element in the
founding and institutional makeup of republics. Altogether, then, in
focusing on that strain of modernity pursuing the conquest of nature,
I am abstracting what Max Horkheimer termed the “dark” dimension
of the modern project (typified in his view by Machiavelli and Hobbes)
from modernity as a whole, an undertow that weaves in and out of its
more benign enterprise typified by such thinkers as Spinoza and Locke
for the establishment of communities of rights bearing, tolerant, free,
and fulfilled individuals. How and to what extent this darker current
vitiates the more benign dimensions of liberalism is a question to which I
hope my focus on extracting this more strictly Promethean strain might
contribute. In other words, is Heidegger right to claim that, in our age,
the benign face of the Enlightenment has been unmasked to reveal
nothing but this underlying darker project for global technological
mastery?
remarks on method
Because the word “ontology” can be used in different ways, my particu-
lar use of it in the studies that follow should be clarified. An ontology is
a characterization of the fundamental status of all reality, beyond which
or behind which there is no further basis or ground. Accordingly, all the
29 The Prince and the Discourses deserve pride of place among Machiavelli’s writings
because they are the only books in which he claims to have presented everything he
knows (Mansfield [2001] p. 9. I hope I will be forgiven, as a political theorist, for
not engaging the crowded field of Machiavelli biographers. Among many fine entries, I
lean to Sebastian de Grazia (1994). The burden of his biography, to me convincing, is
that Machiavelli, in inventing Realpolitik, was recommending the use of conventionally
immoral means to bring about arguably sound political ends – greater stability and
prosperity for the state and its inhabitants.
20
introduction
21
tyranny
22
introduction
23
tyranny
33 Kennington (2005). Consider Manent’s subtle yet trenchant defense of the need to
recognize in the ideas of modern political philosophy the animating spirit of modern
liberal civilization as a whole (1995).
34 Consider Newell (2009a, 2006).
35 Gadamer (1975) p. 273.
24
introduction
25
I
is there an ontology
of tyranny?
In this chapter, I set forth the main premise of this book – that the
classical understanding of tyranny viewed it as a deformed and excessive
version of eros, the cure for which lay in the proper redirection of
eros toward civic virtue and philosophy. In contrast, I argue, modern
political thought, beginning with Machiavelli, understands statecraft as
originating in an act of will that attempts to master nature, and above
all to master the passions expressed through eros. Thus, whereas for
the ancients, both the problem of and the therapy for tyranny take
place within the natural order and man’s place in it, for the moderns,
tyranny is assimilated to a project for the rational conquest and control
of nature, including and especially human nature, starting with the
prince’s own.
Because I am proceeding at a certain level of abstraction, let me
furnish some preliminary content by beginning with a specific set of
contrasts between Machiavelli and his closest point of contact among
the ancients, Xenophon, a linkage to which we return a number of
times throughout the studies that follow. The most important differ-
ence between them is the extent to which Xenophon’s writings on
princely rule (culminating in the Education of Cyrus) explore a kind
of high political hedonism. Cyrus’s motivation as Xenophon depicts
him in the Education of Cyrus is not only the pursuit of honor but also
the pursuit of pleasure from the successful arrangement of his life and
tastes. More importantly, he is consumed by an eros to gratify “all men”
(1.1.5) without their being in a position to gratify him in return. In this
respect, Xenophon’s presentation of his rise to empire is a riposte to
the Aristotelian contention that liberality could be confined within the
boundaries of the polis and republican self-government. The perfection
26
is there an ontology of tyranny?
27
tyranny
28
is there an ontology of tyranny?
29
tyranny
between him and Machiavelli. A telling sign of this is that in the Hiero,
the work of Xenophon’s that is most candid about transforming a tyrant
into a benevolent “leader,” it is not a philosopher who dispenses the
advice but a poet (literally a “maker”). Evidently Xenophon wishes to
separate the philosopher from the teaching that suggests nature (in this
case, a human nature) can be transformed or refabricated. Machiavelli,
by contrast, simply merges himself as thinker with the poet, assum-
ing the same transformative role with respect to the addressee of The
Prince that Xenophon has Simonides assume with respect to Hiero. We
explore these nuances at length in Chapters 4 and 5.
Now, to be sure, as Chapters 6 and 7 show in detail, Machiavelli also
believes there are limits on our capacity to master Fortuna, providing a
philosophical point of contact with the classics. Still, Machiavelli’s opti-
mism about the extent of our capacity to master Fortuna far exceeds,
I argue, anything to be found even in Xenophon, the classical thinker
most open to a politics of imperialism, individualism, and acquisition.
One need only mention the contention in chapter 6 of The Prince that
the most outstanding exemplars of virtue were able to “introduce into
matter whatever form they pleased.” This is a familiar scholastic for-
mula for describing God’s power to transform nature ex nihilo.1 That
Machiavelli appears to transfer this capacity for open-ended transfor-
mation to a human ruler speaks for itself – its radicalism can hardly be
exaggerated. It goes together with the assertion that Fortuna provides
such men with nothing more than the “opportunity” to test themselves,
in the form of dismally unpromising, obscure, dangerous, and hostile
origins and circumstances. By contrast, as we see in Chapters 4 and 5,
Xenophon’s Cyrus was highly favored by nature and circumstance –
his innate character and talents, the civic education he receives under
the Persian Republic, and his grandfather’s preference for Cyrus as his
heir to the throne of Media. For Machiavelli, by contrast, the only
favor nature does us is to goad us to strike back and make a stand.
Understanding Fortuna leads to radical alienation and dissociation from
nature, an experience that equips us with the strength of will to turn
back against nature so as to subdue and transform it.
30
is there an ontology of tyranny?
31
tyranny
32
is there an ontology of tyranny?
33
tyranny
As Socrates prods him into seeing the chasm between his longing for
nobility and the putatively pandering character of his relationships in
both private and public life, his eros collapses into his thumos. Before
that, his mood is one of sublime confidence in his own capacities and
of admiration for the even greater “natural master” who tramples over
all convention (Gorgias 482–486). After Socrates deflates his eros, his
generosity and good humor give way to sullen resentment. As we will
consider in Chapter 2, the most potent figure in political life, capable
of either the noblest or the basest actions, is the man whose thumos is
absorbed into his eros, who sails above anxiety in his urge to consum-
mate his union with the city, his “beloved.” This is the type of nature
Socrates most hopes to save for philosophy, and his closest embodiment
in the dialogues is Alcibiades. For Plato, the root psychological motiva-
tion behind tyranny is an erotic longing to possess the city in the same
way that ordinary men would long to possess another human being. In
such a deformed soul, the zeal and aggressiveness of thumos become
the allies of an eros for tyrannical possession of the city. The aim of
Platonic civic pedagogy is to reorient eros toward the love of the Good
glimpsed through philosophizing, so that thumos can act instead as the
ally of wisdom and the civic virtues.3
Thus, in my view, and as I argue throughout this book, of these
two fundamental passions that can lead us either toward tyranny or
toward an openness to the eternal Good, eros entails and has primacy
over thumos. In its spontaneous emergence, prior to philosophic and
pedagogical shaping, eros strikes out for whatever it desires, summoning
forth the aggressive energy of thumos as its ally. Left on its own, thumos
by itself, without the leadership of eros, wallows in gloomy ruminations,
fear or anger – only erotic longing gives it a purpose. The same holds
after these passions are sublimated in the service of philosophy and the
common good: eros unifies the soul in the pursuit of the Good, assigning
thumos its subordinate role as ally.4 To see how Platonic civic pedagogy
tries to effect this sublimation, let us consider some of Plato’s famous
images of the soul.
34
is there an ontology of tyranny?
5 To a degree, then, I differ from the emphasis of Zuckert (2009), whose study of the
dialogues has rightly been termed “magisterial.” Zuckert’s approach, similar to another
recent book by Lampert (2010), argues that we should arrive at the order of the dialogues
by examining the internal biography of Socrates that they present. Although I agree that
this is a fruitful approach, in my own view, the internal biography of Socrates presented by
Plato is only one among a number of useful perspectives one might take on the dialogues.
Another is to group them thematically as dealing with a) the short question-and-answer
“protreptic” approach of the Socratic elenchus characteristic of, say, the Euthyphro;
b) Socrates’ extensive use of myths, images, and rhetoric as ways of appealing to the
intellect through the affects typified by the Symposium and Republic; c) a concern with
more purely metaphysical issues characteristic of the Theaetetus and Sophist. To be sure,
one could assent to this thematic division into three groups without necessarily buying
into any theory about the order in which the dialogues were composed – for example, the
fact that the Euthyphro is more of a protreptic dialogue does not in itself entitle one to
conclude that it was composed at an earlier date than, say, the Symposium. Still, against
the exclusive reliance on the internal biography, I maintain that Plato viewed his teacher
from these three different although not unrelated perspectives as his own meditation on
the life of Socrates unfolded over time. In his edition of the Gorgias, Dodds claims that
Plato deliberately blurs the internal chronology of the dialogues, juxtaposing events and
personalities that could not have been together at the same time, to prevent us from
viewing the dialogues, even internally, as unfolding in unilinear time according to the
stages of Socrates’ life. There is a sense, Dodds remarks, in which they take place “any
time” because Platonic philosophy itself is concerned with truths that are not time bound.
Dodds in Plato (1979) pp. 17–18.
35
tyranny
6 Blondell (2002) has persuasively argued for the need to reconcile the dramatic or psy-
chological reading of the Platonic dialogues with the analytical, to see how seemingly
impersonal metaphysical speculations emerge from psychological portraits of literary
genius, in such a way that the dramatic reading should only further illuminate the analyt-
ical. Annas (1981) also argues that, for Plato, making the right intellectual choice about
just action is inseparable from the character development required for embracing that
choice. I make a similar argument, against a Kantian approach to Plato, that Plato cannot
be understood exclusively in terms of either moral duty or perfectionism (Newell 2000,
ch. 3). Arguing specifically with respect to shame and Socrates’ employment of certain
varieties of it to bolster civic virtue, Tarnopolsky (2010) also argues that there can be no
strict dichotomy between emotion and reason in Platonic political psychology.
36
is there an ontology of tyranny?
37
tyranny
7 For the background of Socrates’ relationship to tragedy, consider Eliade (1978) pp. 259–
264 and Dodds (1984) pp. 29–50.
8 Socrates on the dangers of poetry: “For my dear Adeimantus, if our young should seriously
hear such things and not laugh scornfully at them as unworthy speeches, it’s not very
likely that any one of them would believe these things to be unworthy of himself, and
would reproach himself if it should enter into his head to say or do any such thing.
Rather, with neither shame nor endurance, he would chant many dirges and laments at
the slightest sufferings . . . We’ll beg Homer and the other poets not to be harsh if we
strike out these and all similar things. It’s not that they are not poetic and sweet for the
many to hear, but the more poetic they are, the less should they be heard by boys and
men who must be free and accustomed to fearing slavery more than death” (Republic
388d, 387b).
38
is there an ontology of tyranny?
and moderation are super-ordinate over motion and strife both in the
world and in a properly attuned soul (Laws 892).
Viewed in this light, Socratic philosophizing can be seen as an alterna-
tion between refutation and integration – between elenchus and image.
On one level, the Republic as a whole can be seen as Socrates’ explo-
ration of a new, reasoned poetry that would replace the manipulators of
the “images” carried along the ramp at the rear of the Cave, the unseen
source of the shadow play that the prisoners chained below mistake for
reality. Socrates’ new images will still be only a reflection of the truth,
but they will contain a kernel of philosophic transcendence that might
induce their viewers to turn around and look for the light of true being,
the Idea of the Good, in which those partial truths participate – not
mere seeming, but “correct” seeming or opinion. The elenchus is the
rough handling that Socrates says the prisoner in the cave first needs to
force him to turn around and look up toward the light (515d–516a). Its
negative refutation serves to dissect and expose as inadequate the opin-
ions of Socrates’ interlocutors about the virtues they profess to know
about and seek, while Socrates’ images gather the fragments of this
negative dialectic and re-integrate them into a more satisfying account
on the basis of what has been learned. For instance, the image of the
Ship of State (488) beautifully integrates the proposition that there is an
art of ruling properly informed by the philosopher’s desire for know-
ledge of the Good, and that the nonphilosophic will benefit, like the
passengers of a well-steered ship, if political life is guided by this true
pilot. Yet the actual content of this art, and of the philosophic life itself,
as well as its precise benefits for the city, are merely sketched rather than
filled out in the image. For up to this point in the Republic, Socrates
has merely asserted that there is an art of ruling analogous to the other
crafts, and that it is synonymous with philosophy, but the content of
which has not yet been filled in, merely assigned a place to hold in
the tri-partite hierarchy of the city and the soul.9 It is no more than a
supposition at this point that there is an art of ruling comparable to
9 Socrates’ introduction of the philosophic Guardians rests on the most flimsy of analogies
conceivable, that between the loyal guard-dog Auxillaries’ knowledge of how to distin-
guish between citizen and non-citizen and the philosopher’s search for the distinction
between knowledge and lack of knowledge in general: “Does the man who will be a fit
guardian need, in addition to spiritedness, also to be a philosopher in his nature? . . . since
(this soul) defines what’s its own and what’s alien by knowledge and ignorance . . . So
39
tyranny
the other crafts in the precision of its knowledge and its criterion for
the distribution of a solid benefit to a specific clientele. We know what
those other arts are – we do not yet know what justice is.10 The assim-
ilation of statesmanship to philosophy is lent a solidity by the Ship of
State image that is not actually manifest in the discussion itself at that
point in the Republic, but whose very ambivalence and incompleteness
invites further reflection while outwardly preserving the vision of a poli-
tics guided by selfless moderation grounded in a knowledge of the starry
cosmos.
Socrates depicts his intellectual autobiography in the Phaedo as turn-
ing away from the attempt to give the direct speech about being – the
pre-Socratics’ tendency to identify nature with one force such as motion,
strife, or a simple dyadic alternation between love and strife as principles
regnant throughout the cosmos – and toward conversing about different
opinions regarding the virtues (95a–107d). As Aristotle was later to put
it, the only approach to what is “first by nature” – that is, metaphysical
truth – is by way of what is “first for us” – political life and moral-
ity (Nicomachean Ethics 1095a17–b6). For Socrates, the debate about
what justice, moderation, piety, and so on might mean pointed to the
fact that there must be an “idea” or “form” of each virtue that solicited
the debate and disagreement. Since the form was entirely consistent with
itself, stable and permanent, then by considering how an opinion held
about a virtue failed to be free of contradiction or instability, we would
know in the case of each such opinion what virtue was not, and thereby
make progress, through excluding mere seeming, toward what virtue
truly is. If opinions about a virtue could be sifted through, retained,
or cast aside to the extent that they were consistent or inconsistent
with the “form” of virtue “in itself,” then progress toward the truth
could be made, not through the direct characterization of being, but
intermediately through the clarification of these heterogeneous human
qualities. Thus, when Socrates asks Euthyprho to define the holy, and
Euthyprho proceeds to give a series of examples of pious behavior,
Socrates tells him that he does not want a mere list of arguably pious
shall we be bold and assert that . . . the man who’s going to be a fine and good guardian
of the city will in his nature be philosophic, spirited, swift and strong” (375d–376c).
10 As Zeigler notes, we need a skilled craftsman to pursue the good because it is not a
matter of subjective preference, but instead is grounded in the objective ordering of the
whole (1979) pp. 124–125.
40
is there an ontology of tyranny?
actions, but to know what the form of the pious is unchangingly “in
itself” (6e).
The focus on the Ideas as the beginning of the Socratic “turn” com-
ports with Socrates’ famous claim in the Apology, another attempt at an
intellectual autobiography, that he knows that he knows nothing (21d;
Republic 354c).11 While Socrates’ claim is ostensibly humbly advanced,
the ability to know in the case of every important human endeavor what
the limits of our knowledge are amounts to a powerful theoretical claim.
For the clarification of the virtues guided by the search for, in each case,
a permanent, unvarying and universally valid Idea, amounts to parsing
opinion to show in each case how justice is not this, is not that, is not
this either, until one has demolished most conventional and authorita-
tive opinions and is left with mere fragments.12 For instance, in the very
first pages of the Republic, by considering the customary opinion that
justice is paying what is owed, and comparing that with the question
of whether it would be good to return a borrowed weapon to someone
of unsound mind, Socrates’ companions learn that justice is not nec-
essarily synonymous with property rights, a powerful negative insight
that almost requires in itself, then and there, that a just regime will be
communistic, though the implications are not spelled out for several
more books.13 Knowing that we know nothing amounts to knowing
how any given opinion or phenomenon falls short of the consistency
and non-contradictory permanence of the Idea in which it participates.
Socrates’ myths and images, accordingly, are ways of restoring a sense
of the wholeness that our opinions about the virtues seemingly possess
before they are deflated by the elenchus, re-integrating what refutation
has shattered by fashioning an emotionally appealing symbol of the
progress in knowledge that has been made. Hence, the growing aware-
ness in the middle dialogues of Socrates’ need to enlist allies in making
11 For a discussion of the Delphic Quest in the Apology as another version of the Socratic
“turn,” consider Strauss (1983).
12 In his elegantly argued discussion of Socrates and his successors, Villa (2001) stresses
the skeptical, questioning side of the Socratic dialectic, more intent on exposing the
inadequate conceptions of his fellow citizens than in bolstering their moral attachments.
In this sense, Villa argues, he was a “bad” citizen. As Annas observes of the Republic,
it is “meant to startle and shock” (1981) p. 2.
13 As Blitz observes about this passage, “legal force” in the defense of property right is
valid only to the degree to which it is guided by a knowledge of what is truly good for
the individual and for the common good (2010) p. 167.
41
tyranny
14 Callicles uses language akin to a religious revelation when he proclaims that “nature
herself” manifests the “shining” truth that it is “just” and a “law of nature” for the
better and more powerful to rule over the worse and weaker and to “get the better” of
them, building up to a crescendo of anti-egalitarianism: “I think these men are acting in
accordance with natural justice when they do such things, and, by God, in accordance
with the law, too, the law of nature – though not, indeed, the laws we frame. For we
mold the natures of the best and strongest among us, raising them from infancy by the
incantation of a charmed voice, as men do lion cubs. We enslave them by saying that
they must be equal and that only this is noble and justice. Yet I think that if a real man
appears, of capacity sufficient to shake off and break through our mass of written rules,
spells and charms – all against nature – our erstwhile slave will stand forth revealed as
the master, and thus natural justice will shine forth!” On the character of the Greek,
see Dodds in Plato (1979) p. 267.
42
is there an ontology of tyranny?
15 On how Socrates enlists Callicles’ passions in order to play on his longing for wholeness
to turn him away from tyranny, and not by an appeal to reason alone, consider Klosko
(1983).
43
tyranny
16 Eros is a “demon” between the divine and the human, an intermediary that “binds
together the whole” (202e–203a). As for the Beautiful itself, Diotima says: “(It) is
always being and neither comes into being nor passes away . . . It is by itself and with
itself, always being of a single form . . . For this is what it is to proceed correctly in
erotics, or to be led by another – beginning with the beautiful things around us, always
to proceed on up for the sake of beauty itself, ending at that study which is the study of
nothing other than the beautiful itself” (211a–c).
44
is there an ontology of tyranny?
they are affected by their love of renown . . . for the sake of immortal-
ity, virtue and an illustrious reputation” (208c–d). His initiation by her
into the rites of eros constitutes another version of the Socratic “turn”
from cosmology and natural science to the human things variously
depicted in the Apology (through the Delphic Quest) and the Phaedo
(the turn from the direct speech about being to the clarification of polit-
ical and moral opinions through the Ideas). While initially unwilling
to examine the eros of humans for honor because it was “irrational,”
Socrates’ “wonder” at this eros at length incentivized him to “reflect” on
the honor-seekers’ psychology, just as Diotima adjured him to do. The
Gorgias, Symposium, and Republic, taken together, explore the reaches
of this eros for honor, including the attraction to tyranny, and try to
re-direct this energy away from such excess to a robust service of the
common good, hopefully accompanied by at least a respect for philos-
ophy if not an outright pursuit of it. All of the most famous images
are therefore aimed at enlisting while moderating a love of honor that
is potentially tyrannical, using visual symbolism to extol a life guided
by reason in which the erotic and spirited passions would achieve their
greatest emotional satisfaction precisely through being sublimated by
an orientation toward the eternal truth.
Let us look more closely at how these images are fashioned to sublimate
and re-direct the eros for political honor away from tyranny toward
civic virtue and philosophy. I want to begin with the general observation
that even most contemporary exponents of artificial intelligence would
concede that there is something about the soul or the self that cannot be
expressed in propositional terms; that even if all human knowledge and
experience could be digitalized or expressed algorithmically, it would
not constitute a self-conscious personality. In other words, the super-
computer Big Blue may be able to defeat a Grand Master at chess,
but Big Blue is not playing chess – it is merely solving a problem, and
could as well be operating a desalination plant or the space shuttle.
A computer can simulate Bach by sampling all information about his
music to a degree that might fool all but a seasoned musicologist –
but would it occur to a computer to compose music of its own? The
motivation to create is strictly human.
What cannot be expressed logically about the soul and its relationship
to the world might be expressed symbolically as a myth, such as Freud’s
45
tyranny
17 As Euben notes, at the beginning of the play, Oedipus thinks he is the child of tuche or
fortune, independent of nomos or convention (1990) p. 98, n.8. On the greater affinity
of the Republic with comedy than with tragedy, consider Euben (1990) p. 241 and
Saxonhouse (1978). See also the illuminating study of Sophocles by Ahrensdorf (2009).
As against Nietzsche’s critique of Socrates for destroying the tragic age with his hyper-
trophic rationalism, Ahrensdorf argues that Sophocles does promote a role, although
not an excessive one, for reason in good government, as opposed to the hubristic reliance
on reason of Sophocles’ Oedipus. He also argues, against Nietzsche, that the political
philosophy of Plato evinces a profound awareness of the tragic dimension in life and
political life, a view with which I very much concur in my interpretation of Plato’s myths
and images, and especially in the disjunction between the erotic longing to possess the
beautiful forever and our human incapacity to do so.
46
is there an ontology of tyranny?
18 Euben makes an intriguing argument for returning to a Nietzschean view of the Greek
polis as providing a context for the rise of classical philosophy, liberating us from
intervening attempts at historical teleology (2003) ch. 2.
47
tyranny
19 See the fuller discussion in Chapter 4 and in Newell (2009) Part III.
20 On Socrates’ seduction of Alcibiades, consider Zuckert (2009) p. 230.
48
is there an ontology of tyranny?
as they embody the best republic and the best monarchy, respectively
(121–124). But by stimulating Alcibiades’ ambition to soar above the
local level to the universal so as to engage him in pursuing knowledge
about the whole, including or through the medium of politike, it is
not inconceivable that Alcibiades retained the global ambition to which
Socrates inspired him without fully cultivating the longing for univer-
sally valid knowledge which Socrates hoped would be its final aim, just
as in Diotima’s Ladder, the longing for immortality through political
honor is the way station to the philosophic life.
By enflaming Alcibiades’ eros for honor, Socrates may have been
making one of his first efforts at turning away from the direct specu-
lation about cosmology (as limned in the Phaedo) to probing the souls
of his interlocutors, responding to what he depicts in the Symposium
as Diotima’s criticism of him at some point much further back in time
when he was still the Socrates who studied nature rather than human
affairs, for failing to pay attention to the “amazing” eros of men for
honor. But if the Alcibiades 1 can be seen as a first step down this
highway from the Socrates depicted in the Clouds to the Socrates of the
Platonic dialogues, with Socrates testing his new insight into the eros for
honor on one of the city’s most promising young aspiring politicians,
the dialogue leaves it in some doubt whether the erotic diagnostician
was successful in this early attempt to use philosophy as a therapy for
the ambitious soul, or whether philosophy did not merely deepen what-
ever tendency to tyranny was present in Alcibiades in the first place, just
as in the presentation of Socrates’ effect on Pheidippides in the Clouds
behind the closed doors of the thinkery. Alcibiades’ lament decades later
in the Symposium that he wants Socrates when he courts the Demos and
wants the Demos when he is with Socrates may be in part self-serving,
presenting as an agonizing and tragically moving failure what in fact
is his own strong preference for politics over philosophy. But it may
also suggest that the universality of Athenian imperialism, whose main
exponent he was – according to Thucydides, after Sicily he planned to
conquer Carthage, telling the people that there was no natural limit on
their empire (6.18.5–16) – substituted for the universality of philoso-
phy’s search for wisdom that was only partially successfully implanted
by Socrates in his soul. If so, Socrates may have soured both alternatives
for Alcibiades, dooming him to act on his stronger impulses for political
action while cursed with knowing that life to be second rate. Was he a
49
tyranny
21 Alcibiades says that Socrates’ “philosophical speeches” are like the bites of a “painful
viper.” Further: “He conquers all human beings by speeches . . . He compels me to agree
that, although I myself am still in need of much, I neglect myself while instead I deal with
the affairs of the Athenians. I feel only shame before him. For I know within myself that
I do not have the capacity to contradict him when he says what I must do; yet, whenever
I leave him, I succumb to the honor of the many” (213e, 216a–c). While Alcibiades does
not conquer all human beings through politics, Socrates does conquer all human beings
through speeches. Alcibiades recognizes the superiority of Socrates’ empire to his own
semi-successful attempt.
50
is there an ontology of tyranny?
between the human and the divine, and between seeming and being –
unlike Aristophanes, who depicted eros solely as a human trait on a
purely anthropological level. Further, while Aristophanes had some-
what democratically recognized the existence of eros in all kinds of
people, not merely the agonistic and pederastic kaloi kagathoi, even
ordinary husbands and wives, along with homosexuals and lesbians,
Diotima preserves from Agathon’s speech the depiction of eros as hier-
archical, reserved for the best natures, the soft and cultured few, in
ascending rank. She does, however, preserve from Aristophanes the cru-
cial distinction between eros and the good for which it longs, identifying
this good, not with the forever lost bodily unity of now split genders (as
in Aristophanes’ myth), but with the over-arching and eternally present
Idea of the Beautiful. Eros is drawn upwards by this pre-eminent cosmic
orderliness and wholeness, and is not, as Agathon depicted it, a sheer
force or impulse of graciousness. Eros is not the good itself, but, in
Diotima’s phrase, “wants the Good to be one’s own forever” (206a).
As earlier observed, Diotima’s speech is another account of the
Socratic “turn,” analogous to the Delphic Quest or the Phaedo. Com-
mon to all the accounts is the implication that philosophy of the kind
Socrates practices in the Platonic dialogues emerges from a dawning
awareness of the divine in human life, the boundedness of the human
by the divine, and the search for a demonic link between the human
and the godlike.22 All the dialogues may be said to abstract from the
Idea of the Good, the superordinate reality that is unvarying throughout
Socrates’ metaphysical speculations. The dialogues are different paths
to that same end, depending on the psychological leanings and situa-
tions in life of the chief interlocutors. Socrates’ therapy for Callicles’
erotic doubleness ends up with a cosmology that abstracts from eros
altogether. The Symposium, by contrast, attempts to derive all virtue
from it, showing how thumotic aggression might be assimilated and
guided by eros itself. In further contrast, the Republic strikes a balance:
The civic virtue of the Auxillaries is purged of eros in its primordial
manifestations (the love of one’s own including wealth and the family)
51
tyranny
52
is there an ontology of tyranny?
53
tyranny
25 As Rosen comments, “the first image is primarily ontological while the second is epis-
temological. What is missing from these two images is human life. Nor does this seem
unusual, since we are discussing the most difficult abstractions of philosophy” (2006)
p. 269.
26 Both the Sophists themselves and the Platonic Socrates regarded the old poets including
Homer, Hesiod, and Pindar as the Sophists’ forbears. See, e.g., Plato Protagoras 316D–E;
Jaeger (1965) pp. 289–296; and the discussion of Machiavelli’s relationship to the
Sophists in Chapter 2.
54
is there an ontology of tyranny?
55
tyranny
56
is there an ontology of tyranny?
29 On the incompatibility of virtue and happiness, see Kant (1956) pp. 42ff. Many con-
temporary approaches to Plato are grounded in Kantian distinctions between freedom
and nature, autonomy and heteronomy, altruism and egoism, and treating others well
for their own sake as opposed to for the sake of perfecting oneself. See, for example,
the discussion in Kraut (1973) pp. 330–334 and Vlastos (1981). I share the reservations
expressed by other scholars about this Kantian approach. See, for example, Griswold
(1986), Kossman (1976), and Nussbaum (1983) pp. 4–6, 285–287. Zeigler (1979)
argues against interpreting the Platonic Socrates as a psychological egoist, pp. 123–133.
Kraut (1973) argues for attributing a much broader conception of self-interest to Plato
than is implied by the notion of egoism.
57
tyranny
58
is there an ontology of tyranny?
59
tyranny
the potential for clashing ambitions among the lovers of the city is
largely occluded. Diotima does not stress or perhaps does not realize
that too many brilliant competitors in the service of the common good
will almost unavoidably turn on each other. There cannot be a republic
full of Julius Caesars. Alcibiades’ belligerent entrance after Diotima’s
revelation provides, through the dramatic action of the dialogue, a tacit
emendation of her assimilation of eros to civic virtue in an untroubled
ascent to philosophy. The dilemma is summed up by Diotima’s own
remark, earlier mentioned, that eros is the longing to possess the beau-
tiful or noble “as one’s own forever.” The deepest problem surrounding
Platonic civic paideia is this explosive contradiction between the love
of one’s own and the eternal good.30 Diotima’s formulation expresses
the dubious paradox that a virtuous citizen could somehow “possess”
forever a truth that transcends all local political virtues, attachments,
patriotism, family ties, and the love of one’s own. The truth is own-
erless. But justice requires a commitment that says: “This is mine –
my city, my family, my god – and I will defend it.” One of the major
complexities in thinking through the connection in Platonic philosophy
between the philosopher’s direct pursuit of what is immortally last-
ing through the longing for the beautiful and the good and the citizen’s
indirect pursuit of it through virtuous citizenship is considering whether
the prospective ascent outlined by Diotima from civic virtue to philo-
sophic virtue is indeed continuous and relatively untroubled, or prob-
lematic to a degree requiring considerable rhetorical embellishment and
artistry. That complexity will loom large throughout the chapters that
follow.
In Plato, the ambiguity of the attempt to reconcile eros, whether
tyrannical or philosophic, to the city is evident to the attentive reader,
30 Like Ranasinghe (2000), with whose approach I am in broad concurrence, I am not sug-
gesting that eros is a kind of pre-established, disembodied cosmic force that antecedently
informs every thought and action in the Platonic dialogues. On the contrary, eros opens
up the inscrutable and agonizing disjunction between the longing for immortality and
our own inescapable immurement in a world of finitude and impermanence. Eros lights
up that longing, and so discloses a new envisioning of the soul in relation to the cosmos,
linked by philosophic longing. By the same token, of course, the prospect for success
in achieving union with the beautiful and the good is always present, however elusive,
fleeting, or unlikely. The longing does not, as it does for modern existentialism, condemn
us to permanent absurdity, man as “the great stupidity” to use Nietzsche’s language.
See also Nelson (1986) pp. 203–204.
60
is there an ontology of tyranny?
31 See the article by Skemp on how the psychology of thumos epitomized by Leontius in
Book 4, and especially his failure to master his desires, prefigures the rebellion of the
Auxillaries in Book 8. As Skemp puts it, “we forget Leontius” after Book 4 until the
rebellion of the thumotic class. Skemp (1982) p. 91.
61
tyranny
62
is there an ontology of tyranny?
Callicles and the Auxiliaries of the Republic. While for Aristotle the
highest moral virtue is fenced off from true happiness (the contempla-
tive life), for that very reason it can flourish on its own, unafflicted by
the unflattering contrast always manifest in Plato between the splendor
of philosophy and the rather robotic civic virtue of the best regime.
In Aristotelian political psychology, thumos becomes a mere subdivi-
sion of courage (albeit the “most natural” form of it [Nicomachean
Ethics 1116a20–1117a10]), rather than (as for Plato) the part of the
soul which is the source of this political virtue as well as of religious
revelation and theology (the theology of Books 2 and 3 of the Republic
is specifically fashioned for the thumotic part of the soul and city).
Although, as we will see, there are cryptic references in Aristotle to a
god-like ruler whose claim supersedes all others (Politics 1288a25–30),
the competition implied is not, as it is in Plato, between philosophy and
all merely political virtue, but between monarchical and aristocratic
political virtue. The philosophic life is indeed superior to both, but it
does not and should not rule. The psychology of thumos and eros fades
from view in Aristotle’s political philosophy in the same measure as
the politics of transcendence are conventionalized and fenced off from
philosophy: The code of the kalos kagathos can stand improvement,
but need not be shattered by an exposure to the highest truth. By the
same token, Aristotle’s great-souled man arguably participates more
directly in the repose for which eros longs than do Plato’s Auxillaries,
and would be a more appealing prospect for a Callicles otherwise drawn
to tyranny.
63
tyranny
32 Plato writes sympathetically about how thoughtful young men are often led by their
pride to gloomy ruminations about life’s meaning. They are aware of how often injustice
goes unpunished, how some men enjoy enormous wealth and glory at the expense of
others and die peacefully in their beds of old age. It makes them doubt whether a rational
and beneficent order governs the world. Laws 899–900. Consider Pangle (1976).
64
is there an ontology of tyranny?
65
tyranny
33 As Zeigler observes, the seat of volition in the Platonic account of the soul is boulesis,
from the verb boulomai, meaning deliberative resolve. Boulesis does not mean “will” in
the modern sense. It is more akin to a reasoned wish or a wish arising from deliberation.
It entails a particular end or counsel advantageous to the situation. Zeigler (1979)
pp. 126–127. Evidence of this is that boulesis is cognate with the word boule, a council
of citizens appointed to deliberate upon the daily affairs of the polis. For reasons such as
these, Platonic volition cannot be equated, in my view, with the modern Kantian concept
of “autonomy,” the striving to exert a pure will unmediated by empirical correlates,
which I trace to the Abrahamic conception of a God who stands outside of nature and
exerts his will to transform it. See also Hyland (1981) pp. 7ff. Of course these issues can
admittedly never be resolved through etymologies alone, but etymologies are helpful.
Along with boulomai, there are several other verbs that connote wishing, wanting
or resolving, with varying nuances of impulse, instinct, unconscious and conscious
desire, or deliberative choice, including ethelein and epithumein. I will provide here
for readers’ interest a note on the debate about their precise meanings, but stress in
advance that none of these verbs, however one assesses their bearing on volition, has
the modern connotation of the will to strive to stand outside of nature and master
it. Indeed, the very uncertainty about the precise connotation of these different words
for volition testifies to the lack of a single term possessing the clarity that the term
“will” does for us, at least philosophically. Gottlob Schrenk comments as follows on
the difference in meaning between ethelo and boulomai: “The original difference in
meaning between boulomai and ethelo is disputed in philological investigation. Two
diametrically opposing views confront one another. The one finds in ethelein impulsive
and unconscious desire and in boulomai rational and conscious choice. Ethelein thus
signifies volition by inclination or natural instinct . . . while boulomai denotes a decision
of will based on deliberate resolve . . . On the other hand, ethelein is understood to
mean the resolution of the spirit, and boulesthai as desire or inclination, as the wish
of the soul. The first view is supported by the fact that boulesthai is related to boule,
bouleuein, bouleuesthai. The second view argues amongst other things that it is often
used synonymously with epithumein. It is difficult to decide between them because at
a very early date the two groups overlap. Hence the only course is to study the usage
in different periods. The following results accrue from such historical investigation. In
Homer there are 38 instances of boulomai and 294 of ethelo. Boulomai always has here
the sense of ‘to prefer,’ ‘to choose,’ whereas ethelo is used for all the other nuances of
volition. Thus ethelo is the older and more comprehensive term. It is particularly loved
by the poets, whereas boulomai is preferred by the prose writers and predominates from
the time of Herodotus.” Quoted in Halloran (1973).
66
is there an ontology of tyranny?
67
tyranny
34 For an illuminating explanation of how ancient accounts of the soul differ from those
of Christianity, see Davis (2011). He sees in the soul of Achilles the archetypal struggle
between immortality and mortal life, a tension I trace to Diotima’s presentation of eros
68
is there an ontology of tyranny?
as the contradictory and self-vitiating longing “to possess the beautiful as one’s own
forever.” This theme is also central to the fine book by Ranasinghe (2000).
69
tyranny
35 Bruell (1977) observes that Socrates’ attraction to the beauty of Charmides enables him
to contemplate the effects of eros on the others present while not succumbing wholly to
it himself.
70
is there an ontology of tyranny?
71
tyranny
but republics are arguably more inclusive since they can accommodate
princely natures in the appropriate camouflage of dictators and leaders
who must periodically re-found the republic and extirpate its malign
“humors.” Fortuna generates “bodies” and republics and principalities
are characteristic modes in which these bodies clash, repel, and coa-
lesce. An expansionist republic whose masses are alternately unleashed
and restrained as foreign and domestic conditions require by an elite
enlightened as to the truth about Fortuna seems to anticipate all the pos-
sible manifestations of Fortuna, immanentizing them in a cosmopolitan
empire composed of “men of many nations” that is progressively per-
fected by “chance” and “the aid of events” (The Prince chapter 17;
Discourses 1.2). Since the cosmos is not ordered by nous, there can
be no Aristotelian “middle way” in the destiny of regimes or in the
moral life of individuals. Liberality, for instance, is not a mean between
parsimony and extravagance. Exposed to the clashes and reversals of
Fortuna, you must either be parsimonious so as to avoid financial ruin
or liberal with other people’s possessions.
In these ways, I want to argue, Machiavelli recaptures the phe-
nomenological range of classical political philosophy but on post-
Christian principles. Viewed from within the classical horizon, thumos
becomes the chief trait of the soul for Machiavelli because the primor-
dialist view of politics entirely displaces the transcendental view oriented
through eros, which is easier to get rid of because it has already been
drained out of politics by Augustinian Christianity. Eros has already
been split into mere appetitive lust within the confines of nature and
the incorporeal love of God. But precisely because the transcendental
object of eros has disappeared – the ascent up Diotima’s Ladder from
civic virtue to the eternally beautiful – the nature of thumos is also
occluded. It is no longer understood in the complexity of its relations
with eros, philosophy, and the gods. It has become neutral “power,”
the engine for the reconstruction of nature. Even tyrannical eros, which
Plato saw as the basis for the critique of the tyrant, is too moral a cate-
gory for Machiavelli because it harbors the possibility of reformation: it
is already a part of Plato’s solution. What Machiavelli means by gloria is
something colder, subjective, self-made, and containing no intimation
of transcendence or immortality. It is reputazione, the ruler’s exter-
nal image based on the awe, fear, and gratitude of his subjects, stem-
ming from his successful mastery of Fortuna. It is at most the nimbus,
72
is there an ontology of tyranny?
the surface sheen of eros, bereft of the immanent potentiality for nature’s
development toward perfection. This diminishing of eros, and there-
fore of thumos, begins the evasion of the classical starting point for
understanding tyranny. If my argument is plausible, it follows that
Machiavelli cannot be comprehended, as Strauss would have it, solely
in terms of how his philosophy contrasts with classical thought without
regard to his engagement with Christianity. At the same time, Voegelin
arguably underestimates Machiavelli’s originality by interpreting him
as an epigone of the Joachite stream of millenarian Christianity.36 As
I will argue throughout this book, Machiavelli is after much bigger
stakes – the imposition of the eidetic quality of classical rationalism on
Fortuna through an act of will, the rational re-shaping of the natural
world, a starting point that makes his project irreducible either to the
36 See the discussion of Voegelin and Strauss in Schram (1987). It is difficult to summa-
rize the complexity of the debate between Strauss and Voegelin over the meaning of
Machiavelli. Broad strokes must suffice. Voegelin saw Machiavelli as a continuation
of the apocalyptic millenarianism of Joachim of Fiore, who preached the dawning of a
new age, a third age, based on the Book of Revelation, in which the Church would no
longer be necessary because all men would be in direct contact with God, the message
of the Gospels and universal love would reign everywhere, and Christians would unite
with Moslems. In other contexts, Voegelin saw Machiavelli as a continuation of Gnos-
ticism, the rejection of the current world in favor of a new epoch where man would be
totally liberated from the constraints of bodily and material necessity. Strauss, by con-
trast, viewed Machiavelli almost wholly within the framework of Machiavelli’s debate
with, and attempted repudiation of, classical political philosophy. Rejecting (or by-
passing) Voegelin’s suggestion of religious or pseudo-religious and millenarian motifs
in Machiavelli’s thought, Strauss believed it was more accurate to see him as being
influenced by Latin Averroism. I have a difficulty with this view because, as I discuss
in detail in Chapters 2, 6, and 7, I see Machiavelli’s focus on man’s freedom of will
to oppose and re-fashion nature to be a secularized version of the Abrahamic God,
which argues for a more intimate connection between Machiavelli and certain strains,
predominantly Augustinian, of Christian theology. At the same time, by suggesting (as
I interpret him) that man might master nature by stepping outside of it, Machiavelli
does not entirely comport with the Averroists who, as followers of Aristotle and clas-
sical thought, believed that human nature, virtue, and the soul fell within the ambit
of nature, to be clarified by philosophy. Averroism wanted to restore classical philoso-
phy and elevate it over the authority of revelation. Machiavelli, by contrast, wants to
assimilate reason to the will-power to master nature, a secularization of God’s will. The
side of Machiavelli that encourages the progressive mastery of nature does not comport
with the Averroists’ wish to restore the natural philosophy of the ancients as perma-
nently valid. For his part, Voegelin believed that Averroism itself, through its attempt
to sunder reason entirely from revelation and establish reason’s supreme authority,
bore a resemblance to Gnosticism, and paved the way for the hypertrophic rationalism
and urge to reconstruct the world in conformity with abstract reason culminating in
twentieth-century totalitarianism, aided by Joachite-Machiavellian millenarianism.
73
tyranny
74
is there an ontology of tyranny?
75
tyranny
Hobbes’s theory of the social contract and the Sovereign is the junc-
ture at which the dark and light corridors of modernity intersect before
heading in different directions – the endless reconstruction of nature
through revolutionary will versus the establishment of communities of
rights-bearing individuals living in peace and tolerance.
Just as for Machiavelli, for Hobbes man’s rationality is not given
from an objectively reasonable world, but instead dawns on him as he
struggles not to be destroyed by nature’s purposeless chaos and the grip
of that chaos on him through the passions. Hence, the criterion for
rationality is what the passions require for their own safe and efficient
pursuit. This symmetry between passion and rationality requires that
the passions move even further in the direction of abstract homogeneity
than was the case in Machiavelli. Starting as he did with the full range
of political phenomena, the same broad canvas of war, peace, honor,
and domestic faction surveyed by Aristotle, Machiavelli recognized that
glory could plausibly be more worth pursuing than self-preservation,
and in rare spirits constitutes an independent source of human moti-
vation. He in effect preserves the distinction made by Xenophon’s
Simonides – whose advice to the tyrant Hiero is one of the models,
as we will see in Chapter 4, for Machiavelli’s art of princely rule –
between the “real men” (andres) who aim for mastery and the common
run of “humans” (anthropoi) who are content with self-preservation
(Hiero 2.1; 7.3). Since, for Machiavelli, domestic politics are inevitably
connected to foreign policy – indeed, a republic that does not wish to
atrophy and die must have an expansionist dynamic – the pursuit of
glory through conquest is an irreducible necessity for healthy political
bodies. Because Hobbes, by contrast, confines himself to the internal
ordering of the polity, and begins with an a priori method – the “simili-
tude of the passions” – even these Machiavellian approximations of eros
(as the glory attendant upon successful imperialism) fade away, replaced
by the abstract and contentless summum malum of non-existence, the
fear of violent death. This reduction of the passions to the desire for self-
preservation makes it possible to make the state synonymous with what
Aristotle had called the art of household management. But for Hobbes,
unlike Aristotle, there is no distinction between good and bad, noble
and ignoble usages, for household management and property. Whereas
Aristotle had argued for an economics of sufficiency to enable citizens
to devote themselves to politics and philosophy, and for wives and
76
is there an ontology of tyranny?
77
tyranny
78
is there an ontology of tyranny?
79
tyranny
within the liberal democracies, the taming of eros and thumos is one of
the most striking indications that Hobbes may have been right to believe
that these traits, the psychological core of classical statecraft, could be
ignored, suppressed, or gradually bourgeoisified by the promulgation
of a psychology of pedestrian hedonism and appetitive self-interest “in
the universities,” successfully actualized through the rise of commercial
economies ([1971] p. 728).
However, looking at the pace of modernization in the non-Western
world (Mao, Pol Pot) or in Western regimes hostile to the West (Stalin,
Hitler), one may wonder whether the Hobbesian Sovereign has not in
fact haunted the modern project all along. In these cases, terror has
been used all too literally to reduce people to the “similitude of the
passions” and strip them of all religious, family, and national traditions
so as to convert them into human integers who are interchangeable
with one another as units of a unified and contentless compact. Perhaps
nowhere is the poverty of the liberal psychology of pedestrian power-
seeking more apparent than here. When, as in Hobbes’s theory, a tyrant
is needed to re-shape human nature through terror to make it conform
to a psychology which by definition dismisses such tyrannical natures
as impossible or absurd from the outset, then one invites the emergence
of a tyrannical project which exceeds the worst prognostications of
the classics while at the same time sacrificing the classics’ capacity for
identifying the tyrannical nature as a deformed version of the erotic
longing for immortality by contrasting it with the healthy pursuit of civic
honor and an ambition to serve the common good. When everything
is thumos, thumos disappears, becoming the ghost in the machine of
modernization.
80
II
1 “The possibility,” as the Athenian Stranger puts it, “that a divine erotic passion for
moderate and just practices should arise in some of the great and all-powerful rulers”
(711d).
81
tyranny
82
the tyrant and the statesman
83
tyranny
84
the tyrant and the statesman
the objects of religious veneration. Often they use force to such a ter-
rible degree that the constitutional arrangement they establish finds it
must bury the memory of the enormities of the founding, lest they make
it impossible to believe in the decency of the order thereby established.2
This ambiguity was encoded in the Romans’ contradictory accounts
of their own founders, the pious and heroic Aeneas versus the criminal
gang of Romulus. Yet in all the Platonic dialogues, the references to this
phenomenon of the entirely new founding are so scant as to number no
more than a few pages. There is the notorious but brief passage in the
Republic in which Socrates mentions, almost as an aside, that for the
education prescribed for the citizenry to take root from an early age, it
would be best if they could somehow start with a fresh generation of
children (541a). The reader is left to wonder momentarily what would
happen to their parents on being driven away but not encouraged to
pursue the thought. The other, more pragmatic reference – but still
only several Stephanus pages long – is the discussion we focus on in this
chapter in Book 4 of the Laws of how a young tyrant with an “eros”
for the affairs of the polis might be the best means for quickly founding
the constitution of Magnesia, setting its laws and institutions in place
all at once.
The reasons for this peculiar reticence become clear if we bear in
mind that the chief purpose of Socrates’ investigations of tyranny and
statesmanship is not to provide an agenda for actual reform but to
provoke his interlocutors to self-reflection through exploring the mean-
ing of the virtues. Before turning in detail to Book 4 of the Laws to
see how its frankness about the tyrannical founder is the exception
that proves the rule, let us pause to consider what is by all accounts
the most exhaustive defense of philosophically grounded justice against
the injustice of the tyrant, Plato’s Republic. Although it culminates in the
seemingly resounding critique of the tyrant’s life in Book 9, the grounds
on which that critique is mounted are carefully qualified and not the
entire story. For the Republic itself is very far from being a wholesale
2 This is hinted at in the Republic in the shameful indecency of Leontius’ morbid desire to
gaze into an execution pit full of corpses. At bottom, the laws and the regime presuppose
the use of deadly force, both in the founding and in continuing to enforce the law.
However, healthy-minded citizens will not dwell on this underside of political life lest it
sap their capacity for loyalty to the city’s ways and encourage them to identify with its
foes.
85
tyranny
86
the tyrant and the statesman
87
tyranny
any “wages” for the just man, because that would suggest a utilitar-
ian motive other than justice itself. In fact, Glaucon claims, the only
way we could be sure a man was being just purely for its own sake
would be if he was stripped of every ordinary benefit of conforming
to conventional morality and, furthermore, was perceived by others as
unjust, suffering horrific punishments as a consequence (361a–362b).
In answering Glaucon’s challenge to show what justice is “all alone in
the soul” and prove that it is more worth possessing than the life of the
tyrant who successfully camouflages himself as just and gains all the
benefits of a just reputation as well as enormous wealth, pleasure, and
power on top, Socrates implicitly denies that he can defend justice as an
entirely inward-directed virtue bereft of any role in relation to others.
The proposal to trace the “city writ large” implies that justice must first
be found as the ordering pattern of the city, then traced back to the
individual. Justice, according to Socrates, can be satisfying both for its
own sake and for the benefits it brings (368d–369a).
Continuing to pursue the analogy of justice to an art, Socrates pro-
poses that each nature in the city will be best suited for one job or
deed (370c–d). Those functions are then internalized as the three com-
ponents of the individual soul. Although initially the transition from
the bucolic “city of sows” based on simple survival is sparked by Glau-
con’s longing for erotic refinements, excess wealth, and luxuries, which
will require a foreign policy of imperial aggression, Socrates proposes
that a class of soldiers will be needed whose main character trait is
not erotic passion but thumotic bellicosity (372c–374a). Paradoxically,
even though the warrior class is summoned into being by the imaginary
city’s erotic excesses demanded by Glaucon, eros is driven underground
in the political psychology of the unfolding best regime in favor of the
thumotic capacity for loyalty to one’s fellow citizens and inflicting harm
on the city’s foes. On the basis of the threadbare comparison of the war-
rior’s capacity to distinguish, like a guardian dog, between friend and
enemy with the philosopher’s capacity to distinguish between what is
and what is not, a ruling class of Guardians, the future philosopher-
kings, is cemented into place in the tripartite relationship between the
city and the soul (376b–c).3
3 For a subtle consideration of the soul-city parallel and its complexities, consider Ferrari
(2003).
88
the tyrant and the statesman
Because thumos does not equate with a single job like material desire
(epthumia) and the lowly crafts that serve it but is dangerously “double”
in its capacity for both friendliness and ferocity, education is needed to
make sure it reserves its friendliness for fellow citizens. The civic edu-
cation of Books 2, 3, and 4 of the Republic fashions a cosmology that
will redirect the combative and bellicose excesses of untamed thumos
into disciplined civic-spiritedness and honorable service to the com-
mon good. The story of Leontius, who tries unsuccessfully through
self-castigation to master his morbid longing to look at the corpses of
executed criminals, proves, Socrates says, that thumos, properly reared
and habituated, could at least “sometimes” be the ally of reason in rul-
ing over aberrant impulse (440a).4 Insofar as the Republic is Socrates’
extended attempt to defend justice against injustice, as Glaucon first
demanded, Socrates appears to believe that the thumotic side of the soul
could best be rehabilitated by a devotion to public service and honor,
as if to suggest that the belligerence of thumos has a collective leaning
toward moral indignation on behalf of the “we.” But this would appear
to skirt the possibility of a supremely ambitious individual’s capacity for
thumotic rage and zeal being the fuel for a purely individual, tyrannical
claim to rule – indeed, even an aspiration to use that absolute power to
establish justice in the city. This is the possibility, to which we presently
turn, briefly explored in Book 4 of the Laws, where the ambitious young
man’s eros for the polis directs his thumotic energies toward the pur-
suit of tyranny, a drive that the Athenian Stranger suggests might be
amenable to redirection by a wise advisor so that the tyrant would find
honor from founding a city that would be just in the future. Instead of,
as in the Republic, thumos acting as the enforcer of reason on behalf
of the common good against tyranny, for these few pages of the Laws,
thumos, guided by an eros for the city, might cooperate with reason to
found a just city by tyrannical means.
This alternative is not openly discussed even briefly in the Republic,
where the argument is skewed in another direction. In Book 5, having
earlier suppressed the erotic side of human psychology in the education
of the Auxiliaries, Socrates now reintroduces it, but only to characterize
the philosophic soul. A second education ensues, that of the philosophic
4 This equivocation parallels Socrates’ earlier remark that it “is possible” that thumos
might be educated to be gentle toward friends and harsh toward enemies (375d).
89
tyranny
Guardian class per se, whose virtue is not grounded in the mere “correct
opinion” inculcated in the Auxiliaries by seemly “tales” about the gods
but by their direct, unvarnished longing to study the Idea of the Good.
Studying the Idea of the Good is now said to be the surest source of
all prudence (505a–c, 536a–b, 539c–540a, 485c–486a). This argument
precisely prepares us for Aristotle’s objection that by failing to distin-
guish between wisdom and prudence, Socrates assimilates all virtue,
including civic virtue, to the single type of the philosopher and robs the
virtue of the nonphilosophic citizens of any independent dignity or self-
sufficiency (Politics 1260a, 1261a10–22; Nicomachean Ethics 1141b).
Consequently, when Socrates finally turns to the long-anticipated show-
down in Book 9 between the philosopher and the tyrant – the ultimate
version of Glaucon’s original contrast between the truly just man reviled
for being unjust and the truly unjust but convincingly outwardly just
man – the basis for the contest is primarily erotic rather than thumotic,
philosophy (like tyranny) being chiefly erotic in its motivation, whereas
civic virtue is chiefly grounded in thumos. Moreover, by depicting the
tyrant in Book 8 as emerging from the debased hedonism of the demo-
cratic regime, Socrates makes tyrannical eros appear vulgar, low, and
contemptible in contrast with the elevated pleasure of philosophy, while
at the same time stigmatizing it by appealing to an aristocratic disdain
for the mob.
The tyrant who emerges from democracy in Book 8, setting up the
showdown in Book 9 between the tyrant and the philosopher, is a
pleasure-ridden demagogue and libertine, a Cataline or a Nero. This
derivation of tyranny from the vulgarity of democracy omits the at
least equally plausible hypothesis that another kind of tyrant – austere
and warlike – could emerge directly from timocracy, the second worst
(or best) regime type in the typology of regimes in Book 8. Only the for-
mal agreement among the interlocutors to trace the decline of the city in
speech as a decline in which each successively worse regime – timocracy,
oligarchy, and democracy – represents a widening gap between the good
of the individual and the good of the whole, which had been absolutely
harmonious in the kallipolis, allows Socrates to ignore the objection that
another kind of tyranny – zealous, austere, self-disciplined, and war-
like – could have emerged (544e–545d). For the argument pulls in the
direction of the tyrant as the most extreme instance of the contradiction
between the common good and the selfish individual, the radicalization
90
the tyrant and the statesman
91
tyranny
92
the tyrant and the statesman
5 See also the Lovers, where Socrates equates the king, tyrant, statesman, household man-
ager, master, the just man and the moderate man: all possess a single techne of ruling
(138c–d).
93
tyranny
94
the tyrant and the statesman
in describing the Idea of the Beautiful toward which all erotic longing
ought properly to be directed:
[It] is always being and neither comes into being nor passes away. . . . It is
by itself and with itself, always being of a single form. . . . For this is what
it is to proceed correctly in erotics, or to be led by another – beginning
with the beautiful things around us, always to proceed on up for the sake of
beauty itself, ending at that study which is the study of nothing other than
the beautiful itself. (211a–c)
95
tyranny
For whether or not this city is possible and whether or not it is desirable
from every plausible perspective on human happiness (given its demands
for the abolition of family life, property, and every other version of the
love of one’s own), it is the paradigm for what it would mean for politi-
cal arrangements to be naturally good. It is the only pattern of authority,
in other words, that would enable human nature to develop toward its
fullness and completion within the constraints of political convention,
to the degree that any political convention might fulfill human nature.
Indeed, when turning to the education of the philosophic Guardian
class in Book 7, Socrates argues that even the philosophers actually
existing in the world today are in some measure deformed because
they have not had the experience of an education in governing and
the experience of governing itself (539e–540a, 520d–e, 534d, 536a–d).
That there might be private pursuits, or blends of private pursuits and
civic engagement, that might as well or better fulfill the fullest range of
natural human potentialities for the good life than could an optimally
ordered city is a question that remains open, of course, throughout the
Platonic dialogues, which are not exclusively concerned with politics
even in the broad sense discussed here. The purpose of elaborating the
city in speech is, in short, as a propaedeutic for the education of the
soul, regardless of the likelihood of those arrangements coming fully
into existence. In the Republic, the soul’s erotic ascent to philosophy
proceeds by way of the question of justice. The ascent to philosophy
entails the moral virtues, just as the cosmology guiding the Auxiliaries’
education flows from the Ideas, although the ascent to philosophy ulti-
mately does not account for those moral virtues as good in themselves
but as consequences of the philosopher’s absorption in studying the
Idea of the Good. Nevertheless, the philosopher will also possess the
character traits of the Auxiliaries: moderation, steadfastness, and self-
control, even if they derive from a source other than the Auxiliaries’
civic education. So in a sense, the moral life of civic virtue will imitate
the life of the philosopher.7 In the education of the Auxiliaries, Socrates’
own quality of steadfastness (karteria, a virtue of Socrates praised by
Alcibiades in the Symposium 219d–221c) becomes a standard for the
citizenry (Republic 399a).
96
the tyrant and the statesman
“It was therefore for the sake of a pattern,” I said, “that we were seeking both
for what justice by itself is like, and for the perfectly just man, if he should
come into being, and what he would be like once he came into being; and,
in their turns, for injustice and the most unjust man. . . . We were not seeking
them for the sake of proving that it’s possible for these things to come into
being.”
“What you say is true,” he said.
“Do you suppose that a painter is any less good who draws a pattern of what
the fairest human being would be like and renders everything in this picture
adequately, but can’t prove that it’s also possible that such a man can come
into being?”
“No, by Zeus, I don’t,” he said.
“Then what about this? Weren’t we, as we assert, also making a pattern in
speech of a good city?”
“Certainly.”
“Do you suppose that what we say is any less good on account of our not
being able to prove that it is possible to found a city the same as the one in
speech?”
“Surely not,” he said.
97
tyranny
98
the tyrant and the statesman
99
tyranny
wondered at that Socrates was found guilty? We might say that it had to be so.” Hegel
(1962) pp. 388–389.
9 Syme (1982) remains the classic analysis of Octavian propaganda.
10 See the splendid study by Carcopino (1960).
100
the tyrant and the statesman
101
tyranny
102
the tyrant and the statesman
103
tyranny
two archetypal regimes, Sparta and Persia, it is in the hope that, for
Alcibiades, the universality of his ambition will be but a way station
to the universality of reason and the Idea of the Good. When Socrates
tries to moderate Callicles’ eros into friendship, that psychological ther-
apy serves a prescription for self-government that looks inward to its
own domestic affairs and avoids the external entanglements prompted
by an eros for ever-increasing wealth and glory abroad, summoning
the most ambitious and potentially tyrannical men to the forefront of
public affairs.
Plato’s circumspection about the possibility of a constructive role for
tyranny in public life is closely connected, in my view, to his emphasis
on eros as the key to the tyrannical character. For Plato, the desire for
political mastery stems from a misguided eros, and the therapy for it
lies in the redirection of this longing for wholeness and completion.
According to Socrates, Callicles is a “double” man because he is con-
fused about the objects of his erotic longing – the Athenian Demos and
the boy Demos. That the names of these objects of longing are identical
suggests that Callicles believes he can gain the same kind of satisfaction
from success in public life as he would from a personal love affair – that
he can possess the city and be loved by her just as he wants to possess
and be loved by the boy. In reality, according to Socrates, he will end
up pandering to the city just as he panders to the boy, servant rather
than master (513, 519). Socrates, by contrast, has distinct but ranked
objects of eros – Philosophy and Alcibiades (482). By keeping these two
loves distinct, with an eros for political excellence clearly subordinate
to an eros for wisdom, Socrates claims his love life is ordered in a way
that, in contrast with the divided Callicles, unifies his soul.
In considering the Platonic approach to tyranny, however, we should
beware of making too hard and fast a distinction between diagnosis
and therapy. For when we return to the political phenomena that such
a distinction helps to clarify, it may well be that the Socratic diagno-
sis of the tyrannical longings of an erotic would-be politician such as
Callicles already entails a large part of the therapy. By emphasizing
the extent to which tyranny is primarily a consequence of the aberra-
tions of eros in its spontaneous, untutored, primordial manifestations,
Socrates encourages Callicles to interpret his own experiences in this
way. Because Socrates consistently defines the art of ruling on the anal-
ogy of a selfless managerial techne, Callicles is driven to articulate his
104
the tyrant and the statesman
13 It is because he wishes to reopen the gap between nature and convention that Callicles
responds so eagerly (“Yes, by Zeus!”) when Socrates suggests that a “better” man
be defined as an intelligent and prudent man (phronimos, 490a). Prudence or practical
wisdom (phronesis) generally meant an understanding earned from a wide experience of
human and especially political affairs. In what proves to be a key move in the dialogue,
Socrates narrows the meaning of prudence to the expertise of a craftsman (technikos)
and defines rule on the analogy of craftsmanship (490b). Callicles lets this narrowing
of prudence slip by. His receptiveness to the notion of an art of skillful ruling doubtless
reflects the fact that a number of professional teachers of rhetoric, including Gorgias,
stressed the manipulative might of the techne of rhetoric that their instruction could
impart to the politically ambitious. Socrates offers a very different conception of art,
however – art as a reflection of the regularity and form that characterized nature, not
the human capacity to mold and shape nature’s formless becoming. Socrates wants
to convince Callicles (in a clear repudiation of the ontology of the motion-men) that
“excellence” of soul is “present” and “most nobly” effected by an arrangement of art,
not through chance becoming (506d–e): “Surely the virtue of each thing, whether of
an implement or a body or a soul or any living being, does not come about in the
noblest way through a mere accident, but by an order, a correctness, and an art that is
apportioned to each one specifically.”
14 As Irwin observes, “Callicles cannot both reject all restraint and advocate a way of life
which requires courage” (1977) p. 121.
105
tyranny
embody in his own love life – Socrates tries to prepare him for precisely
the sort of refutation of tyranny that he sets forth at length in Book 9
of the Republic. There, Socrates presents tyranny as a kind of eros that
is less satisfying than the eros of the philosopher. The tyrant’s pleasures
are manifestly connected with his power to plunder and ravish his sub-
jects. Yet by having the tyrant compared with the philosopher, whose
life is presented as one of superior personal happiness, the effect of
Socrates’ refutation is to present tyranny mainly as a form of personal
satisfaction and to expose its deficiencies on those grounds. Tyranny as
a form of actual political authority, let alone as the foundation of the
best regime, receives scant attention.
In other words, the chief Socratic refutation of tyranny abstracts from
the full-blown context of governance in which we ordinarily encounter
tyranny in the political world. The main treatment of tyranny as a con-
stitution occurs, as we have seen, in the typology of regimes in Book 8,
but the discussion is summary, and it too is mainly in personal terms,
concentrating on how defective the tyrant’s way of life is as opposed
to how tyrannies differ from each other and operate in practice. As
we have noted, the whole discussion of regimes in Book 8 ranks them
in descending order according to how far the individual interest strays
from the common good. The decline from one constitution to another is
depicted as a series of revolts by less worthy sons against more worthy
fathers, the sons being given over increasingly to the nonphilosophic
love of one’s own. Hence, the timocrats rebel against the philosophers
because they feel their honor as warriors has been slighted. Their sons,
in turn, find that public honor is too frail a guarantee of success and
influence and so turn to moneymaking. The sons of the oligarchs want
to spend the money earned by the diligence of their fathers on feverish
luxuries, a relaxation of standards that ushers in democracy as a society
of hedonistic laissez-aller in which even the animals are corrupted. The
tyrant emerges from the democracy as the hedonist with the biggest
appetites. By ranking the constitutions in this way, Socrates is able to
impart to timocracy, the constitution of the spirited honor seekers, a
dignity second only to that of philosophy, for the Auxiliaries are edu-
cated and habituated to practice the moderation that the philosopher’s
own overwhelming passion for wisdom automatically entails (by drain-
ing off the erotic energies that might normally expend themselves in
pleasure seeking). Because the tyrant is depicted here as a monster of
106
the tyrant and the statesman
15 See the discussion of Tocqueville’s fears regarding the “democratic despot” in Newell
(2009) Part II.
107
tyranny
108
the tyrant and the statesman
Stranger takes us, if only for a few minutes, to a place where Socrates
will not go – to the dangerous, violent underpinnings of the established
order; to the moment when the foundations were laid upon which
the normal order could grow. Readers of the Republic will recall
that Socrates will not grant the premise of Glaucon’s rehearsal of
the Sophists’ account of justice, according to which the “nature” of
politics resides in its prepolitical origins, so that law and convention
are but artificial constructs through which the pusillanimous minimize
their suffering in the competition among selfish individuals for survival
and well-being. As Socrates describes the first city, the “city of sows,”
nature comes into being already articulated according to the division
of labor among the banausic arts, and those arts simultaneously serve
a community based on the simplest needs (370d–372a). Contrary to
the Sophists’ teaching, the city precedes the individual. In Book 8, the
city “according to speech” is transported to the most distant past, both
because what is oldest and ancestral is best, and because, according
to Socrates, the natural origins of justice are not the strife, violence,
and motion ascribed to nature by the pre-Socratics and Sophists but an
already long-established harmony and community.
Unlike Socrates (who does no more than hint at it), the Athenian
Stranger does concede that even a virtuous political order must begin
at a specific historical juncture and that the energy and ambition of a
naturally masterful individual might have a constructive role to play
in instituting it properly and all at once. In the Athenian Stranger’s
description of this personality, we encounter a variant of the relation-
ship between eros and thumos that is rather different from the variants
we encounter in the Republic, Symposium, and Gorgias. In the Sympo-
sium, well-directed eros entails civic virtue on its way to philosophizing:
The immortal fame gained through engendering virtue for the city is a
comparatively more lasting object of erotic longing than the mere physi-
cal immortality perpetuated through reproduction, and is a way station
on the ascent to the philosopher’s apprehension of the truly eternal
and imperishable Good. In the Republic, as we earlier observed, eros is
repressed within civic life on behalf of the civic virtue of the Auxiliaries,
rooted in the thumotic part of the soul, then rehabilitated as a motive
for philosophy. Common to both paths to a moderate and orderly soul
is the notion that eros cannot be thought to satisfy itself in the proper
way through political glory and mastery alone.
109
tyranny
110
the tyrant and the statesman
111
tyranny
112
the tyrant and the statesman
113
tyranny
114
the tyrant and the statesman
dialogue can the best regime be brought about by human action. After
this invocation of the god, the Laws resumes its proper topic, which is
not how an entirely new order is to be founded but how the common
good might best be ordered in normal times.
In striking contrast, Machiavelli’s main theme in The Prince and, in
a less obvious way, the Discourses is founding, which he regards as
indispensable not only to making sure that the constitution is securely
and properly ordered but to keeping it so. For at bottom, Machiavelli
argues, there is no normalcy, no “middle way,” only emergencies kept
at bay or creatively deployed against each other to generate a dynamic
equilibrium of selfish interests, “each power checking the other”
(Discourses 1.2.6). Machiavelli in effect therefore asks: Might we dis-
pense with the Platonic concerns and reservations over the tyrannical
founding in order to think through how the act of founding might unfold
and perpetuate itself in the working of the constitution? Might there be
a founder who did not require the moderate character said by the Athe-
nian Stranger to be necessary for even considering this alternative, and
so unlikely to exist among potential young tyrants as therefore to make
it unwise to consider it at length or too explicitly? Machiavelli’s answer
is that, in a sense, the founder’s possession of this moderate character
is immaterial, so long as the founding is carried out in a way that is
both methodical and in the service of the founder’s and the citizens’
interests. In making this argument, though, Machiavelli also means to
say that the whole Socratic diagnosis of tyrannical ambition and the
reticence it entails is both false as a description of the phenomenon
of rule and harmful to the prospects for stable, prosperous, and well-
governed political orders. As we will see, Machiavelli’s teaching is not
simply a negation of the Platonic one. He is not simply saying: Tyrants
and would-be tyrants, go ahead and indulge your passions to the fullest,
including your longing for mastery. What he is saying is something more
akin to the following: Do not commit the error encouraged by ancient
“writers” such as Plato of understanding yourself to be erotic – and
therefore of longing for the “offspring” of noble deeds and immortal
honor through the cultivation of justice, moderation, and humaneness;
of longing for transcendental repose in union with the beautiful and the
good through the ascent up Diotima’s Ladder. For the Platonic char-
acterization of the ruling passion as erotic, even in its spontaneous,
untutored, and therefore dangerous manifestations, already implies the
115
tyranny
116
the tyrant and the statesman
17 Strauss (1969) p. 9.
117
tyranny
118
the tyrant and the statesman
I was going to say now that man never legislates at all. Accidents and calami-
ties occur in a thousand different ways, and it is they that are the universal
legislators of the world. If it isn’t pressures of war that overturn a constitution
and re-write the laws, it’s the distress of grinding poverty, and disease too
forces us to make a great many innovations. . . . Realizing all these possibili-
ties, you may . . . say what I said just now, that . . . human affairs are almost
entirely at the mercy of chance. (709)
In these few lines, Plato anticipates and evokes the full force of the
primordialist ontology of the pre-Socratics and Sophists that the Athe-
nian Stranger summarizes later on in Book 10 and with which this
chapter concludes. Stated briefly for now, the identification of nature
with motion and strife led to the view that law and government are as
chaff before the wind compared with the awesome, underlying motions
of tuche – the power of fortune to overturn human plans both in the
obvious sense of disease and bad weather and in the subtler sense that
chance is operative on human nature through the necessity of passion,
prompting the struggle for mastery within and between nations, so that
the turmoil of class warfare, hunger, and ambition are always seething
behind the settled pattern of the laws.
But the Athenian Stranger just as quickly rejects the view that tuche is
what chiefly characterizes human nature and the world at large. Instead,
he goes on to maintain, the supreme element of control over life comes
from (the) god. As we learn elsewhere in the Laws, for the Athenian
Stranger, the god is not the interventionary deity of revealed religion
whose acts of mercy or punishment are ultimately unfathomable within
the limitations of reason. Instead, this is a god of nous – an overarch-
ing divine presence that upholds the prevalence of order and reason in
119
tyranny
the cosmos over chance and strife. By practicing virtue, human beings
can make themselves the “allies” of this god and help the Good super-
vene in human affairs progressively throughout the ages, so that justice
increasingly becomes the normal human condition rather than unbri-
dled passion (just as, by analogy, clement weather is more ordinarily
representative of the cosmos than storms or hurricanes [896–897, 903]).
As the Athenian Stranger puts it here, chance and opportunity are mere
ancillaries to the noetic rule of (the) god, temporary lapses from a more
superordinate unity. As such, they are openings in the current of events
for human beings to assist the power of nous to supervene over disorder
and licentiousness. Chance and disorder are, in other words, temporary
rifts in a more typical orderliness in the world that human beings may,
paradoxically, seize upon so as to work actively for the continuing
influence of that cosmic orderliness on human cities and affairs.18
Techne is the chief exemplar of the way in which human beings can
minimize the reversals of fortune by laying hold of and introducing
into their own affairs a portion of the orderly beneficence governing the
cosmos. Characteristically, in Plato’s use of techne, it is not aimed at a
human being’s control of nature. Instead, the arts tap into the order-
liness of the cosmos through their various aims, and, through their
bodies of knowledge and technique, introduce a degree of that order-
liness directly into human affairs. Furthermore, just as the disciplined
routine of the arts helps us in all manner of practical affairs, the Athe-
nian Stranger goes on, the same pursuit of skill in statecraft will help
found and maintain a virtuous political community:
For instance, in a storm the steersman may or may not use his skill to seize
any favourable opportunity that may offer itself. . . . So the same will apply
in the other cases too, and legislation in particular must be allowed to play
the same role.
120
the tyrant and the statesman
When a tyrant wants to change the habitual ways of a city, he doesn’t need
to exert himself very much or spend a lot of time on the job. He simply has to
be the first to set out on the road along which he wishes to urge the citizens –
whether to the practice of virtue or vice – and give them a complete model
by setting his own example; he must praise and commend some courses of
action and censure others, and in every field of conduct he must see to it that
anyone who disobeys is disgraced. (711)
On the face of it, the Athenian Stranger’s language is not unlike Machi-
avelli’s description in chapter 6 of The Prince of princes of the most
“outstanding virtue,” those who, like Cyrus or Moses, create “entirely
new modes and orders” through violence and persuasion. But there is
a crucial difference. For the Athenian Stranger, the challenge is distin-
guishing successfully ahead of time between a virtuous founding and a
vicious one. For Machiavelli, by contrast, as we see in Chapter 6, the
challenge is making the new beliefs stick, regardless of whatever specific
kind of order is created.
The “hard” part of the founding, the Athenian continues, is to ensure
that the blueprint will be in conformity with virtue rather than vice.
Here, two conditions are indispensable. The first is that the young tyrant
have a natural leaning toward moderation, the kind that “flowers early
in life . . . and in some cases succeeds in imposing a certain restraint
in the search for pleasure, but fails in others.” The other condition is
121
tyranny
that the young tyrant have the good fortune to be instructed by a wise
lawgiver. As the Athenian Stranger puts it: “When supreme power in a
man joins hands with wise judgement and moderation, there you have
the birth of the best political order with laws to match; you’ll never
achieve it otherwise. So much for my somewhat oracular fiction.” In
other words, you have to take a chance on picking the right young
man. As Socrates says in the Republic, the best natures are so delicate
that they can turn into the worst natures if they are not well reared
(491a–492d). As we see in the next chapter, Aristotle warns that what
appears to be the man best suited to rule may be a tyrant disguised as a
benefactor, or may even be a genuine benefactor who nevertheless will
display flashes of tyrannical violence and indignation over having his
opinions challenged. As Machiavelli will argue, however, if you get rid
of the requirement of a natural leaning toward moderation, you quite
simply dispense with taking that chance, because you are not dependent
on such a virtuous character arising in the first place. Mastering the
situation of the founding requires the correct method, in which both
prince and people are made secure and prosperous, not relying on hopes
that a good man will arise. Here we have a precise and revealing locus
for the contrast between the classical and modern approaches. The
classical approach is to pin one’s hopes on what Hobbes terms the
“wit” of the prince: his putative virtues of character and mind. The
modern approach, inaugurated by Machiavelli, is to avoid relying on
those hopes, to assume the worst about the nature of the prince, and
to compensate for those deficiencies with a straightforward appeal to
everyone’s self-interest and the methods needed for the aggrandizement
of both prince and people.
The Athenian Stranger began by denying that despair over fortune’s
power to thwart man’s aims is justified if we properly understand
the cosmos. He then introduced the heady prospect that a tyrannical
technikos, a craftsman of politics, could “easily” establish the sound
basis for a good constitution. Yet although this prospect is possible
according to nature and reason, it quickly transpires that the conditions
that must be met for it to unfold are extraordinarily rare to the point
of being, as he himself concedes, “oracular.” It requires a young man
whose leaning toward moderation is so strong that it innately directs
his political ambition in such a way that he fulfills his love for the polis
and exercises his ambitions by guiding the city toward virtue rather
122
the tyrant and the statesman
than using the city to gratify his passions. As the Republic makes clear,
in Socrates’ view, the most typical sort of politically ambitious per-
son will require the education fomented by an already well-established
constitution in order for this self-restraint to be inculcated. Moreover,
the innate moderation of the young founder cannot come to construc-
tive fruition unless he is guided by a wise lawgiver. The chances of
this happening are, in the end, almost as rare as the coinciding of the
philosopher and basileus in the Republic. Indeed, the Athenian’s word-
ing here (“my oracular fiction”) reminds us of Socrates’ claim that only
the extraordinarily unlikely conjunction of these two “jobs” will estab-
lish the optimal constitution and bring an end to “the ills of the cities”
(473d).
The most one can say in favor of the greater practicality of the dis-
cussion of founding in the Laws is that the coincidence of a young lover
of the city joining up with a wise advisor is somewhat less unlikely
to happen than the coincidence of wisdom and power in the Repub-
lic. For whereas Socrates maintains that the king and the philosopher
must actually be the same person, the Athenian only requires that the
city be founded by a ruler of potentially extraordinary natural moder-
ation who is closely guided by a wise lawgiver. Moreover, whereas the
philosopher-king would have to truly philosophize, the young founder
presumably need mainly be guided by the correct opinions provided by
his advisor (perhaps like the advice Cyrus receives, with mixed results,
from his Socrates-like father Cambyses in the Education of Cyrus,
an encounter we discuss in Chapter 4). Even so, the unlikelihood of
this partnership between political genius and wise statesmanship, com-
bined with the danger that a founder possessing the tyrannical power to
change everything might well choose to imbue the new city with thor-
oughgoing viciousness, quickly leads the Athenian Stranger to abandon
further reflection on the practical exigencies of the emergency situation
and return to a concern with how the citizens of a republic somehow
always already founded ought best to be educated and governed. “The
god” comes to the fore at this juncture as a symbol of Platonic cir-
cumspection as the young tyrant recedes from the discussion. “The
god,” heralded by the Athenian’s “oracular” prelude, in effect replaces
the young tyrant as the founder, obscuring the original measures in a
haze of pious custom. The tyrant’s withdrawal and replacement by the
god is evocative of the fact that it would take a partnership between
123
tyranny
19 For a discussion of this rubric in the history of political thought leading up to Abraham
Lincoln’s great Lyceum speech, see Newell (2009).
20 Did Machiavelli read Plato? Blanchard (1996) writes: “Machiavelli tells us, in his famous
letter to Francesco Vettori, that he invested in his Prince the capital accumulated from
numerous nocturnal conversations with ancient men.” More specifically, as Blanchard
notes, the first paragraph of chapter 25 of The Prince is a gloss on parts of the passage
from Book 4 of the Laws discussed earlier, although, in contrast with Blanchard, I
conclude that Machiavelli’s understanding of the connections among chance, art, and
prudence is diametrically opposed to that of Plato. Blanchard is not claiming that
Machiavelli’s engagement with Plato is necessarily conscious, but the gloss on the Laws
in The Prince is compelling evidence that it was, along with his own insightful contrast
between Machiavelli’s preference for “touch” and the Platonic epistemology of “sight,”
which I examine in Chapter 6. For a detailed treatment of the reception of Plato among
civic humanists of the Renaissance in Italy, see Hankins (1990) vol. 1: pp. 58–81. As for
Machiavelli’s specific references to Plato and Aristotle, their paucity is, I argue beginning
in Chapter 5, strategic. Plato is mentioned by name only once, and quite dismissively,
in Discourses 3.6.16 as a mentor for conspirators. Aside from alluding to an unnamed
Aristotle when discussing the regime types in Discourses I, Machiavelli mentions him by
name but once in 3.26.2, referring to his depiction of tyrants in the Politics as prompting
their own overthrow because they plunder and outrage their subjects. Is this perhaps
Aristotle’s best moment in Machiavelli’s view? He may also be alluding to Aristotle
among others, but not by name, when he mentions “philosophers who believe in the
eternity of the world” (Discourses 2.5.1).
124
the tyrant and the statesman
125
tyranny
Whence it comes to pass that all armed prophets conquer and the unarmed
ones are ruined. For . . . the nature of the people is variable, and it is easy to
persuade them of a thing, but difficult to keep them firm in that persuasion.
Therefore it is needful to order such matters in such a mode that when the
people do not believe any more, one is able to make them believe by force.
Moses, Cyrus, Theseus and Romulus, had they been unarmed, would have
been unable to make them long observe their constitutions, as in our times
happened to Fra Girolamo Savanarola. . . . Therefore such men as these have
great difficulty in the conduct, and all their perils are on the way, and they
must with their virtue surmount them; but having surmounted them, and
commencing to be held in veneration, having extinguished those who were
envious of their qualities, they remain powerful, secure, honoured, happy.
(The Prince chapter 6)
The Athenian had observed that the “easy” part of the founding
would be the young tyrant’s ability to shape the new constitution,
brushing aside Kleinias’s doubt that people would readily obey some-
one claiming such titanic authority over them. The hard part would be
that such a tyrant should be naturally moderate and fortunate enough
to have associated with a wise legislator. For Machiavelli, however, the
hard part of the prince’s path is to establish his absolute authority in the
first place, such that he is in a position to implement reforms (“all their
perils are on the way”). Although Machiavelli is thus more informative
than the Athenian Stranger about the actual dangers of becoming the
master of the state, he says nothing about what for the Athenian was
truly the hardest part: the alliance between wisdom and a naturally
moderate character. Furthermore, in discussing the greatest founders,
Machiavelli makes no distinction between the use of the founding power
for virtuous as opposed to exploitive ends. Instead, he mentions histor-
ical examples of successful princes such as Cyrus, Romulus, Theseus,
and Moses and derives from the fact that they succeeded the judgment
that they must have been outstanding in virtue. If a prince is success-
ful in founding new modes and orders on the magnitude of such great
126
the tyrant and the statesman
127
tyranny
128
the tyrant and the statesman
governing and the soul of the ruler. Socrates had defined prudence in
the Gorgias as a variant of techne – the expert (technikos) on the art of
ruling – and had argued from the structured beneficence of techne to the
geometrical proportionality of the cosmos approached through philos-
ophizing. At bottom, then, for Plato, the “prudence of the prince” must
and can only arise from the “good counsel” of the wise man – whether
through their direct association or indirectly through a civic education
that inculcates, through the twilight medium of correct opinion, those
tenets of philosophical cosmology that best ensure an orderly soul in the
citizen. Machiavelli’s way of dealing with the tension between wisdom
and rule, however, is not to attempt to subordinate rule to wise counsel
but to break down the distinction between prudence and what a prince
must do to gain and maintain his state.
To a certain extent, Machiavelli as it were takes the side of the Auxil-
iaries in the Republic in their rebellion on behalf of martial prowess and
honor against the rule of philosophy. Given that, even on Plato’s argu-
ment the Auxiliaries are incapable of grasping with theoretical clarity
the grounds for their submission to the good counsel of the Guardians,
we might view Machiavelli’s solution as a radically simple one to the
quandaries that torture the political psychology of the Republic as it
attempts to ameliorate the tension between ambition and reason. To
put it another way, Machiavelli supports Callicles’ side of the argument
with Socrates over the meaning of the art of ruling, encouraging us
to share Callicles’ indignation and amazement when Socrates tries to
separate the meaning of phronesis and statecraft from what Callicles
regarded as the concern of a sensible man of affairs with expanding the
city’s power and honor, along with his own, emulating the great impe-
rialists of the past, Themistocles and Pericles. As we will see, crucial to
this inversion is Machiavelli’s way of looking at the relation of techne
to the art of ruling. For the Athenian Stranger just as for the Platonic
Socrates, the art of ruling is, like the other arts, in conformity with an
orderliness that intimates the supervening stability of nous and eidos
over disarray and perishability – a propaedeutic for the soul’s reconcil-
iation to the larger natural order within which human nature also finds
its place. For Machiavelli, by contrast, the art of ruling is a power that
a prince achieves over natural conditions, enabling him to “introduce
any form” he pleases into the “matter” provided by the adversity that
challenges him (The Prince chapter 6).
129
tyranny
130
the tyrant and the statesman
131
tyranny
but will actually be condemned and executed for being unjust. Owing
to such parallels, not only is Machiavelli sometimes seen as the succes-
sor to the Sophists, but, conversely, the Sophists are sometimes viewed
as direct precursors of modern political rationalism and utilitarianism,
as for instance when Lessing in Laacoon describes Simonides as “the
Greek Voltaire.” Finally, one can detect a resemblance between the
view of the pre-Socratics and Sophists that nature is fundamentally to
be characterized as motion, chance, and necessity and Hobbes’s view of
nature as matter in motion, itself derived from Bacon, who attributed
this view of the external world to Machiavelli, more poetically expressed
as Fortuna.
These are valid parallels, but they are also limited in important ways.
For, in my view, there is no direct parallel among the pre-Socratics and
Sophists for Machiavelli’s radical summons to the new prince to con-
quer nature or chance and introduce into matter “whatever form he
pleases.” Moreover, when they identify nature with motion, the pre-
Socratics and Sophists do not mean precisely that nature is a field
of sheer random and empty happenstance, of clashing particles, as
in Hobbes’s version. The closest parallel among the ancient schools
to Hobbes’s Baconian physics is that of Lucretius. Even in Lucretius’
atomism, however, the atoms evolve continuously through ever more
complex concatenations into entire worlds and civilizations, whereas for
Hobbes matter in motion always stands across a barrier from artificially
constructed political convention, a secularized version of Augustine’s
categorical distinction between the City of Man and the City of God in
which the City of God is replaced by man’s own power to reshape the
chaotic realm of human and nonhuman nature. More fundamentally,
whereas for Lucretius the understanding of nature as the clash of atoms
should predispose us to eschew the irrationality of political life with its
toils and dangers and cultivate our private pleasures, for Hobbes, it is
precisely the way in which matter in motion individuates us by acting
upon us through our fear of violent death and desire for continued life
that should motivate us to join the social contract.
For the pre-Socratics and Sophists as they are depicted by Plato and
as their views survive in the fragments attributed to them, nature’s
originary power as “chance motion” has a substantial content and a
direct bearing on how we understand the human realm of politics,
justice, and morality. For “motion” is not necessarily merely atomistic
132
the tyrant and the statesman
Speech is a great power, which achieves the most divine works by means of
the smallest and least visible form. . . . The power of the incantations uniting
with the feeling in the soul soothes and persuades and transports by means of
its wizardry. [This] can be shown firstly from the arguments of the cosmol-
ogists, who by removing one opinion and implanting another, cause what is
incredible and invisible to appear before the eyes of the mind, and from legal
contests, in which a speech can sway and persuade a crowd by the skill of its
composition, not by the truth of its statements.22
21 The poets were commonly included among “the wise.” As Jaeger observes, the Sophists
“were the heirs of the educational tradition of the poets; they were the successors
of Homer and Hesiod, Solon and Theognis, Simonides and Pindar. Jaeger (1965)
pp. 289–296.
22 All references to the pre-Socratics and Sophists are from Freeman (1948).
133
tyranny
the gods are replaced by the alternation between chance and necessity.
As one of the Heracleitus fragments (30) puts it: “This cosmos, which is
the same for all, was not created by any one of the gods or of mankind,
but it was ever and is and ever shall be ever-living Fire, kindled in
measure and quenched in measure.”
The arts are “mortal” and “paltry” because they are short-lived
fabrications of man in contrast with the great primordial motions of
nature. Certain arts like “music” (tragic and lyric poetry) are utterly
paltry. (This judgment probably reflects the claim of Gorgias and other
rhetoricians to have replaced the role of the old poets in shaping opin-
ion.) Some arts, however, like medicine, farming, and gymnastic, are
relatively “serious” because they share their power “in common” with
the life forces of nature. We can tap into the potency of nature through
agriculture and through the care of the body. The realm of convention,
by contrast, is utterly artificial and opposed to nature, even more so
than the arts. Nomos adjures us to be pious, just, to seek peace and
respect the lives and property of others. However, to live naturally
is to allow the impulsive motions of nature to well up in ourselves
as the passion to maintain our lives and gratify our desires. The
“correct” life “according to nature” is to “dominate the rest,” to “get
the better” of others. The natural man’s passions will impel him to
strive spontaneously for “victory” over others, “by force” if need be,
shattering the artificial dictates of conventional morality and equality.
Echoing Callicles’ speech in the Gorgias extolling the natural master,
the pre-Socratics’ and Sophists’ view as summarized in the Laws stresses
that, although the laws say we must reject the natural life as unjust and
impious, for a real man to accept these dictates is to live like “a slave.”
It may be just and noble by convention to treat others as equals, but
it is just and noble by nature (another echo of Callicles) to tyrannize
over others whenever one can. Finally, the whole subject matter of
statecraft and legislation is held to be purely by art, and therefore
entirely unnatural – except for a “small part” of the art of ruling
which is in “partnership with nature” like the other “serious” arts of
medicine, gymnastic, and farming. That “small part” is in my view
the art of rhetoric, which for the Sophists is tantamount to everything
meaningful about statecraft, a point I will enlarge on subsequently.
Although a “small” part of art is connected to nature, according to
the Athenian Stranger’s rehearsal of the ontology of the motion-men,
134
the tyrant and the statesman
23 Anaximander: “Whence things have their origin, there they must also pass away accord-
ing to necessity; for they must pay the penalty and be judged for their injustice, according
to the ordinance of time.” Quoted in Heidegger (1984) p. 13.
24 Dodds translates nomos as “the conglomerate,” a web of interlocking social, religious,
legal, and customary prohibitions against vice and impiety. He also argues that not only
those whom we now term the Sophists but the earlier natural philosophers and cosmol-
ogists including Heracleitus had been deeply subversive of traditional and conventional
morality. Dodds (1984) pp. 21ff. For an impressive interweaving of historical, cultural,
and theoretical contexts for the emergence of the pre-Socratics and the Socratic school,
see Balot (2006), especially “Archaic Greece and the Centrality of Justice,” pp. 21ff.
Kerferd (1981) makes an insightful and detailed case for the philosophical and intellec-
tual coherence of the pre-Socratics and Sophists, rescuing the latter from the charge that
they were mere charlatans. See also Newell (2000) chapter 2.
135
tyranny
our forefathers instilled obedience into their children, so that when they
grow up they might not be overcome by any great change of fortune
(61).” Others, however, used the primordialist ontology as the basis
for a direct assault on all conventional morality in the name of selfish
individualism and, taken to its logical extreme, tyranny. According to
the Athenian Stranger, the most consistent implication of the view of
nature as motion is indeed the praise of “getting the better” of others as
the only truly natural way of life. This does not mean that the Sophists
were what we would now term moral relativists, however. They had a
definite view of natural human excellence and fulfillment that could be
defended on reasoned grounds. Because, as they would have it, nature
originates in strife and impulse, those “great and noble motions” can
well up as the ruling passion of individuals and cities, meaning that,
although treating people well and as equals may be just and noble by
convention, tyrannical mastery, whether achieved by individuals or by
cities, is just and noble by nature.25
The successful tyrant, reveling openly in his glory, is arguably the
most direct human counterpart of those great and noble motions at
the heart of becoming, a sheer spontaneous impulse to rule. There is
an echo of this implication in the Gorgias in Callicles’ professed admi-
ration for Hercules as the pattern of the natural master, a Bronze Age
cattle thief, brute, and killer who, Callicles somewhat fancifully relishes,
might return and smash through the placid and pusillanimous egalitar-
ianism of the Athenian democracy. Callicles also echoes the view just
noted, attributed by the Athenian Stranger to the pre-Socratics and
Sophists, that there is a distinction between what is just and noble
by convention (equality) and what is just and noble by nature (manly
victory) [483]). All in all, then, the motion-men do recognize certain
natural and substantive human excellences as rooted in, and flowing
from, the primordialist view of nature. Gorgias, for example, in another
fragment attributed to him, regards courage and prudence as the two
natural virtues most important to any city (8; 11.1). By “prudence”
he means the real-world sagacity of experienced and powerful leaders,
25 Heracleitus’ fragment number 80 could thus be read on both a nonhuman and a human
level: “One should know that war is universal and jurisdiction is strife, and everything
comes about by way of strife and necessity.” Freeman (1948) p. 30.
136
the tyrant and the statesman
26 As Hobbes writes in chapter 10 of the Leviathan: “Nobility is power, not in all places,
but only in those Commonwealths where it has Privileges; for in such privileges consis-
teth their power. . . . The public worth of a man, which is the value set on him by the
Commonwealth, is that which men commonly call dignity. And this value of him by the
Commonwealth is understood, by offices of Command, Judicature, public employment;
or by Names and Titles, introduced for distinction of such Value. . . . So that, of Civil
Honour, the Fountain is in the person of the Commonwealth, and dependeth on the
Will of the Sovereign, and is therefore temporary.”
27 Consider the analysis by Nussbaum (1983) p. 105.
137
tyranny
prejudice is all justice could ever mean as a phenomenon. For these rea-
sons, both the Athenian Stranger and Socrates argue that the ontology
of motion leads most consistently to tyranny as the most natural way
of life and can offer no binding argument based on its own principles of
reasoning to prefer justice to tyranny. Still, as we have observed, some
of the Sophists like Protagoras did regard themselves as the guardians
of conventional morality – only some, like Thrasymachus, assailed it
openly. Moreover, as the Gorgias fragment praising courage and pru-
dence as natural virtues suggests, the haleness and energy of nature as
great and noble motions could be seen as imparting manly vigor and
boldness to the city living in accordance with nature, and that is a
kind of moral standard or standard of excellence, if radically different
from the Socratic one. Hence, Callicles echoes Gorgias in agreeing with
Socrates that Athens needs both courage and the prudence of successful
statesman, while omitting any agreement with Socrates about the need
for justice and moderation.
Now, it might be argued that the Sophists sometimes come close,
in the claims they make for the power of rhetoric, to Machiavelli’s
exhortation that fortune can be mastered. A fragment attributed to
Empedocles, the teacher of Gorgias, is apt here: “You shall check the
force of the unwearying winds which rush upon the earth and lay waste
the cultivated fields. And again, if you wish, you shall conduct the
breezes back again. And you shall bring out of Hades a dead man
restored to strength (111).” Control over nature is certainly implied.
But I would take this to mean that rhetoric cannot literally refashion
nature in the ways the fragment details but instead, as in the Gorgias
fragment about the power of rhetorical persuasion, can produce the
appearance of such transformations in the minds of the audience – not
so much create a storm as create one on stage. Yet even if we take
their claims more literally, I would argue that the Sophists thought of
controlling nature mainly in the sense of managing its shifts and eddies,
of surfing its waves, of using the protective coloration of whatever
arbitrary conventions locally obtained in order to disguise their own
pursuit of pleonexia. Even Empedocles’ fanciful talk of “summoning”
this power is more like a shamanistic incantation or a spell (to echo the
language about “wizardry” in the Gorgias fragment quoted earlier), a
way of tapping into and releasing the potent energies residing under the
surfaces of life in the primordial wellsprings of physis. Machiavelli’s
138
the tyrant and the statesman
139
tyranny
140
III
superlative virtue,
monarchy, and
political community
i n a r i s t o t l e ’ s POLITICS
In this chapter, I look at an important ambiguity in Aristotle’s political
philosophy – the issue of whether the “best regime” is a self-governing
republican aristocracy (the theme of Books 7 and 8 of the Politics) or the
much more muted claim that there may be a single ruler of superlative
virtue and prudence who might rule over many “cities and peoples”
according to the art of household management, a rational monarchy
of the kind sometimes associated with Alexander the Great but also
with Xenophon’s idealization of Cyrus the Great. I argue that Aristotle
mutes the claim because, while true, it would undermine the integrity
and claim to merit of the self-governing political community that is at
the forefront of his political philosophy. Although arguably more ratio-
nal, the monarchy of the “best man” is a regime in which citizenship
vanishes altogether under the architectonic art of household manage-
ment conducted by an all-powerful ruler. Hence, what is true, strictly
speaking, according to reason may have to retract its claims in order
that the political community of shared civic deliberation can flourish in
its own right. This, as we will see, is the context for Aristotle’s well-
known and forthright critique of what he takes to be Plato’s insistence
on excessive unity for the city, the Platonic Socrates’ failure to distin-
guish theory from prudence, and his belief in the unity of virtue. Yet
Aristotle’s own analysis of political authority cannot entirely exclude
his partiality toward precisely the kind of rational monarchy for which
he takes Plato and the Platonic Socrates to task.1
1 Although I have used the familiar translation of arete as “virtue,” one should bear in
mind that the Greek word has a broader range of meanings than its English equivalent.
Literally, it means “excellence.” Hence, it can make perfect sense in ancient Greek to
141
tyranny
speak of the “virtue” of a carpenter, doctor, orator, or general, meaning their talent for
what they do. This can strike a modern reader as odd because we usually take “virtue” to
mean something disinterested, the capacity to rise above our own desires and preferences
for the sake of the general good. We therefore might think that a general’s talent to kill
and conquer people, or an orator’s talent at persuading someone to believe that a lie is
the truth, are too prone to deceit and self-interest to be considered properly virtuous.
The Greek arete certainly can have the connotation of self-denial and a preference for the
common good above one’s own self-interest, but its meaning is not restricted to this kind
of moral purity, and virtue is never categorically defined in this way to the exclusion of
all other meanings.
2 For an interesting history of thumos, see Koziak (2000). She draws attention to the fact
that, for Aristotle, thumos represents a general capacity for all manner of emotions and
desires. To me, this means that Aristotle deliberately strips it of its Platonic status as one
of the primordial passions that open us to the question of the gods and the transcendence
of our mortal limitations.
142
superlative virtue
3 On the relationship between the Idea of the Good and the other Ideas in Plato’s meta-
physics, consider Newell (2010).
143
tyranny
144
superlative virtue
4 The political community is Aristotle’s most general term for a community of shared rule
in contrast with monarchy. The “constitution” (politeia) is the more specific ordering
of the city, and the distribution of offices and authority within it, in accordance with a
correct or deviant interpretation of justice. “Constitution” is also the name of one of the
six “constitutions.” I translate it in the familiar way as “polity” to avoid confusion.
145
tyranny
146
superlative virtue
employs are either for production (poiesis) or action (praxis). The epit-
ome of productivity is the “architectonic” rule of a master-craftsman
(architekton) over a ranked division of labor, his slaves being “tool[s]
serving tools.” Optimally, Aristotle suggests, tools would direct them-
selves automatically to fulfill their part of the master-craftsman’s plan.
The fanciful comparison of such tools to the legendary self-moving stat-
ues of Daedalus implies that, just as the most productive tools would
be animate, the most productive slaves would be inanimate, or as close
to automatons as human beings could become. Perfect productivity, in
other words, would abstract from all action. However, a slave, rightly
considered, is an instrument for action rather than production (1254a1–
10). It is like a bed, which provides nothing beyond its use, rather than
like a shuttle, which produces a commodity. A slave is thus someone
who by nature belongs to a master as an instrument of action. In this
way, Aristotle tries to prevent the identification of mastery with the
open-ended acquisition and production of wealth.
As to the question of whether the authority of master over slave can
be justified quite apart from the question of its economic consequences,
Aristotle argues that this is a matter of distinguishing natural slavery
from merely conventional or legal slavery.5 Despite the attention this
particular passage has understandably received from commentators, we
should bear in mind that Aristotle is not only or even mainly concerned
with the frequent injustice of conventional slavery (which he admits),
but to distinguish political rule over naturally equal citizens from the
rule of a master over slaves even when the latter would be just. Although
some details of the argument justifying natural slavery are drawn from
private life, in its conclusion we are reminded once again that its main
target is that error discussed during the initial distinction between polit-
ical and other kinds of authority: “all [forms of] rule are not [the same],
although some say they are” (1235b15–20).
In order to come to grips with Aristotle’s assessment of the role of
property and the economy within the political community, we must
avoid imposing on it an inappropriate set of modern distinctions.
5 The degree to which Aristotle believed that conventional slavery coincided with natural
slavery – or whether he believed such a coincidence ever occurred – is a much argued
question. See, for example, Ross (1960) pp. 241–242; Strauss (1977) pp. 22–23; Nichols
(1983); Mulgen (1977) pp. 42–45; Smith (1983); Fortenbraugh (1977).
147
tyranny
148
superlative virtue
149
tyranny
man can practice the virtue of liberality, however good may be the
intentions of the poorer man (Nicomachean Ethics 1120a4–15).
As to whether slavery or servitude is ever just, Aristotle argues that
nature as a whole is characterized by the pairing of ruling over ruled,
such as the soul over the body and the intellect over the appetites. To
be just by nature, the master’s rule over a slave would have to be as
beneficial to the slave as the rule of the soul over the body or the intellect
over the appetites within a single man (1254a17–1254b32). By impli-
cation, this natural standard, in which the slave is the chief beneficiary
of the arrangement because he could no more take care of himself than
could a body without a mind, rarely if ever coincides with the conven-
tional institution of slavery, as evidenced by the fact that those who
are masters by convention feel compelled to seek a natural justification
for what is almost inevitably their arbitrary and unmerited power over
other human beings (1254b32–1255a3, 1255a20–1255b16).
To maintain the distinction between the proper use of the art of
household management in the service of doing and its improper use
in the service of making, Aristotle argues that there are limitations on
the degree to which acquisition is natural to human beings and nec-
essary for meeting their natural needs. We need only acquire what
is sufficient for life, not luxury. Wealth should primarily be based
on agriculture and livestock, not commercial exchange and liquid
assets. Commercial exchange, when unavoidable, should be limited
to procuring the basic necessities of life, not for the sake of luxury
or surplus income (1256a1–18, 1256a40–1256b7, 1257a5–1257b40).
Of course, these parameters are imprecise, meant only as general
guidelines, because some level of surplus between the means for self-
preservation and superfluous luxury will be required to practice virtues
such as liberality that are impossible to actualize without some extra
wealth.
If, to argue the contrary, household management were synonymous
with open-ended acquisition, then all the virtues would have to be
viewed as means to moneymaking and material pleasures (1257b40–
1258a15). Someone who is unable to fulfill his desires in private life
may seek to do so “by other means” such as “courage” or “general-
ship” – that is, by political and martial daring (1258a5–15). Aristotle’s
examples of virtue in this passage remind us again that the art of house-
hold management can be employed at the regime level, and not only by
150
superlative virtue
the private family within the city. Courage and generalship are public
virtues that, properly directed, are employed by citizens in defense of the
political community’s internal way of life from external aggression. If,
however, the political community is swallowed up by a project for lim-
itless economic acquisition, then these virtues could be perverted into
means for launching imperialistic expansion and exploitation abroad.
The improper use of household management, in other words, is coeval
with tyranny, whether of a ruler tyrannizing over his own city or of a
city tyrannizing over other peoples as a conqueror. The tyrant, Aristo-
tle remarks, is in many ways like the personal owner of an enormous
household made up of his subjects, someone who disposes of an entire
city as his private property and business enterprise (1259a23–37), echo-
ing the Platonic diagnosis of this political disorder. As we recall from
the discussion of the proper end of the polis, the good life and mere
life are copresent in the city. The good life outranks mere life, just as
“being” (the mode in which the good life is) outranks “becoming” (the
mode in which mere life is [1252b28–30]). The household, as the sphere
of mere life, must be limited and circumscribed by the city, by the good
life that can only be actualized in the public deliberations of the citi-
zenry. Otherwise, it is possible that the economic aims of the household
pattern of authority may slip its bonds and absorb the city itself, so that
the polis becomes a monarchical household or even an empire.
The tenability of Aristotle’s distinction between the proper and
improper employment of oikonomia hinges, at bottom, on the onto-
logical relationship between human nature and nature as a whole. For
what if, as Machiavelli will argue, nature is in truth unremittingly hos-
tile to human efforts to survive and prosper? In order to maintain
the distinction between proper and improper oikonomia, according to
Aristotle, we need to envision nature as providing for our basic needs
without an excessive emphasis on transforming nature through human
productive techniques. Only in this way can we stress doing (praxis)
over making (poiesis) and circumscribe the latter by the former, which
is tantamount to circumscribing the household by the polis. If, on the
contrary, nature were to prove inherently too poor, sterile, or hostile to
provide for those basic needs, we would be driven to remake nature and
force it to yield the material for our survival – to “master Fortuna,” as
Machiavelli will put it, or as Bacon, following upon this fundamental
151
tyranny
shift in the meaning of politike, will argue, to convert science into the
power for “the relief of man’s estate.”
The first conclusion Aristotle draws, then, about the art of household
management is that it should not be identified with productivity. Were
this identification to be made, the inflated desires such productive arts
would serve in private life could, Aristotle observes, fuel an ambition
for power, wealth, and status in public life or even abroad through
the pursuit of empire. The productivity of the private household must
therefore be circumscribed by the requirements of the common good.
The proper use of wealth is to enable the heads of households to pursue
public affairs and philosophy within the city.
Although this argument might seem to dispose of the claim of the house-
hold as a model for good government, it is far from the whole story. For
the question remains as to whether some form of one-man authority
besides the exploitive, tyrannical kind might be more beneficial for the
city than the “political community.” This leads to the more complex
level of Aristotle’s investigation. If there are not enough people in any
given city who are sufficiently naturally talented to be able to pool their
abilities and govern their own affairs, might not a monarch who orga-
nized them into their respective functions be a superior alternative to a
self-governing community? Anticipating this objection, Aristotle argues
that “nature” will provide “human beings” fit for citizenship just as she
can be expected to provide both household managers and statesmen
with the material necessities. Statesmanship, therefore, does not have
to “make” or produce (poiein) human beings fit to live in a city, just as
weaving does not produce wool but “uses” wool already provided for
it (1258a20–30). At most, statesmanship must be able to distinguish
between the good and bad people already present. The derogation of
“making” in favor of “using” what has already been provided recalls
Aristotle’s earlier criticism of the household devoted wholly to pro-
ductivity, epitomized by the rule of a master-craftsman over a ranked
division of labor. Just as the household does not need to be wholly given
over to the “architectonic” organization of the arts, Aristotle implies,
neither does the city.
In light of what has preceded, Aristotle goes on to make the rather
startling remark that “the ruler must have complete moral virtue, for
the work [he does] is, taken absolutely, that of a master-craftsman,
152
superlative virtue
153
tyranny
154
superlative virtue
serve man’s material needs and buttress social peace? Why make up
this particular story? Why not tell the truth about nature openly, like
Machiavelli or Hobbes? At bottom, in however qualified or attenuated
a sense, Aristotle does believe that nature will provide. The closest
analogy for understanding nature, Aristotle tells us in the Physics, is a
physician who heals himself. Similarly, a statesman must employ the art
of governing to encourage the healthy flourishing of the human potential
for virtue – in which statesmen themselves share – with which nature
furnishes politike. We return to this analogy when looking at some
broader differences at the end of this chapter between the classical and
modern ontologies of tyranny.
For Aristotle, the danger posed by the art of household manage-
ment and its household paradigm of rule to the political community
is not merely the danger that the polis might be usurped by a tyrant
or a tyrant city. Although every decent person would surely agree that
the political community should not be swallowed up by the improper
use of the art of household management, what about the possibility
that it might be assimilated by the proper use of that art? The deeper
difficulty is that there is something inherently reasonable about the
division of labor itself. Human nature is fulfilled, Aristotle has told
us, by citizens employing logos to deliberate about what is just, noble,
and advantageous (1253a10–20). Yet now he tells us (to reemphasize
this arresting phrase) that “logos is an architechton” – reason itself is
a master-craftsman, the architectonic art (1260a13–18; Nicomachean
Ethics 1094a25–30). In other words, the search for reasoned clarity
about the meaning of justice, nobility, and the advantageous may lead
ineluctably away from shared deliberation toward the hierarchical dis-
tinctions uncovered by unhindered reason, because, as we recall, the cos-
mos as a whole is constituted by hierarchy (1254a17–1254b2). There is
thus a very real sense in which the political community’s shared deliber-
ations must, if left untrammeled, transcend themselves in the direction
of a rational oikonomia and the rule of “one or a few” statesman
of “superlative” prudence (1277a15–25, 1277b25–32, 1278a40–b6).
This is why Aristotle will eventually tell us that “the whole of justice”
must occasionally be sacrificed to preserve the “political justice” of the
city (as in the ostracism of the best man [1284b1–30]), and why the
best regime per se may not be a self-governing aristocracy so much as
a rational monarchy that exercises prudence and rules over “cities and
155
tyranny
156
superlative virtue
157
tyranny
158
superlative virtue
159
tyranny
160
superlative virtue
161
tyranny
8 On the difficulties of reconciling the civic friendship that ought to take place among
citizens with the conflicting claims to rule made in political deliberation, as well as the
difficulties of reconciling civic friendship with the higher claims of friendship per se, best
actualized through philosophic friendship, see the fine study by Lorraine Pangle (2000).
162
superlative virtue
9 See the detailed and probing exegesis of Aristotle with respect to economics and redis-
tributive justice by Balot (2001).
10 In Book 4, where the most inclusive constitution, polity, is discussed in detail, Aristotle
observes that not only are there many claims to virtue, but they may coexist in the same
people, making it even more difficult to decide precisely who is equal and unequal in
a politically relevant way: “the same people (may be) soldiers, farmers and artisans, as
163
tyranny
well as councillors and judges, and indeed everyone thinks they are capable of holding
most of the offices” (1291b1–10).
164
superlative virtue
to learn that virtue itself can push its claim to authority too far – that
virtue can be “overbearing,” even tyrannical, in its claims.11
But this is just what Aristotle means, and his reason for it is “politi-
cal” in the sense discussed earlier. Here we should bear in mind that the
most inclusive of the correct constitutions – most conveniently trans-
lated as “polity” – is both specifically distinguished from rule accord-
ing to virtue (aristocracy) and given as its own particular name the
name common to all six principles of rule (politeia – “constitution,”
1279a35–1279b). Although it is the least virtuous of the correct con-
stitutions, polity is evidently closer to what Aristotle takes to be the
practical aim of “constitutional” government as such – the inclusion
within the political community of as many diverse and conflicting inter-
ests and abilities as possible.12 For a city that excludes too many people
from rule will be “full of enemies,” and hence unstable, making both
mere life and the good life impossible to sustain (1281v25–35). The
derogation in this context of the politics of virtue in favor of the “con-
stitutional” politics of inclusiveness helps to explain Aristotle’s remark
that we have to consider what will happen when all six claims to rule
“are present in one city.” This appears to mean that the sixfold schema,
although useful as a heuristic device, is too abstract; that there will sel-
dom if ever be a precise fit between real cities and the six principles of
rule. Cities as we observe them in practice are more likely to be a kind
of political cauldron in which all the claims are contending for power at
once. Even in cities that do fit closely to one of the classifications, other
claims are seething beneath the surface, waiting for their opportunity.
Far from being able to stabilize the political community, therefore, each
of the constitutions (with the probable exception of polity) is likely to
be felt as a tyrannical imposition by those whom it excludes. Aristotle
underscores this deficiency by arguing that, pushed to its extreme, each
11 As Newman notes, the problem cannot be solved by assuming that “all such constitu-
tions” refers only to tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy or to ones in which authority
is claimed on the basis of something other than virtue. Aristotle is clearly referring to
the correct regimes as well as the deviant ones. Newman in Aristotle (1950) vol. 3
pp. xxii–xxiii.
12 Polity is the most inclusive and stable of constitutions because it blends the principles
of democracy and oligarchy that, between them, include the most people and are the
source of the most explosive and prevalent conflict: rich versus poor. Consider Clark
(1975) pp. 104–105; Randall (1968) pp. 263–264.
165
tyranny
166
superlative virtue
167
tyranny
168
superlative virtue
(473d), “it remains for all to obey such a man gladly, so that men of
this sort are kings in the cities forever.”
169
tyranny
170
superlative virtue
171
tyranny
claim is commensurable with all the others if only in the negative sense
that all the other claims are incommensurable with it. However, this
kind of monarchy, based on the principle of household management, is,
in accordance with the distinctions between kinds of rule made at the
beginning of the Politics, unpolitical. The one constitution that meets
the requirements of justice is not itself a political community. Thus,
although we are reminded in conclusion that to ostracize such a man
would never be in accordance with “absolute justice,” we remember
that it is in a sense “politically just” to do just that.
172
superlative virtue
tyranny – the thin edge of the wedge for Hobbes’s critique of Aristo-
tle. As Aristotle concedes, even someone who really does possess the
knowledge to govern may also be prone to a desire for a monopoly on
all honor, excessive anger, and an intolerance for even a reasonable and
well-intentioned airing of views by others.
In this respect, we might defend the Platonic Socrates against Aris-
totle’s critique of him for conflating sophia with phronesis as follows:
the philosopher-king, at least in principle, removes the danger of an
excessively honor-seeking and anger-prone statesman of genius of the
kind explored by Aristotle, because those dangerous passions would be
absorbed by the eros for wisdom. So perhaps it was not so unreason-
able after all to hold the criterion for the proper exercise of the art of
ruling to such a high standard that even the genius-statesman (but also
imperialist) Pericles did not qualify, as Socrates argued in the Gorgias.
But, in defense of Aristotle, we might observe in turn that Plato, when
he has his Athenian Stranger entertain the possibility that just such a
genius-statesman, a young tyrant with an eros for the city, might found
a just regime, is so sensitive to the danger that this tyrant’s claim to serve
justice might only be putative, or might be mixed with a desire for limit-
less honor, or end up not being reined in by a philosophic advisor, as to
abandon the prospect after only a few pages and treat the just founding
as the object of a prayer. Given that danger, Aristotle might say, why
not cooperate with the ambition for supreme honor on its own terms,
appealing to the gentleman’s own innate preference for virtuous over
disgraceful conduct and sidelining the need for philosophical mentor-
ing? At any rate, while Aristotle arguably defines the phronimos more
realistically than does Plato, both their political philosophies are depen-
dent on the coinciding of supreme political virtue and actual power in
the same leader. As we saw in the last chapter, it is this dependence on
chance, on Fortuna, as Machiavelli will put it, that takes us to the heart
of Machiavelli’s critique of the classical orientation.
In this light, we can see Hobbes as arguing that Aristotle did not
go nearly far enough in his warning that a prospective ruler claim-
ing to possess superlative prudence could turn out to be a would-be
tyrant in disguise. Hobbes’s solution, ingeniously, is to dispense with
the distinction between superlative virtue and tyranny altogether while
maximizing the total authority of the “sovereign,” now liberated from
the opprobrious comparison to a tyrant. For Hobbes, admitting even
173
tyranny
174
superlative virtue
175
tyranny
176
superlative virtue
177
tyranny
of how Plato and Aristotle understood them. For the modern Baconian,
Hobbesian, and Newtonian conception of matter in motion cannot be
precisely mapped with the primordialist ontology of the pre-Socratics
and Sophists, where the “great motions” of nature’s originary upsurges
have the substantive content of a certain view of human excellence and
one’s natural entitlement to rule (the distinction made by the unnamed
pre-Socratics in Book 10 of the Laws, echoed by Callicles, between
what is just and noble by nature and what is just and noble merely by
convention). The pre-Socratics’ ontology also has direct implications
for the city itself as a hale outgrowth of this underlying matrix of
origination (echoed in Gorgias’ endorsement of the somatic virtues of
courage and manly prudence, as against the merely conventional virtues
of justice and moderation), and even for the content of the works of
the poets, led by Homer, whom Socrates regards as the founder of the
other “motion-men,” with his whole rich psychology of manly virtue,
tragic fate, and agonistic nobility.
This whole substantive alternative account of human excellence is
excluded from the modern physics of matter in motion, which reflects
the fact that the material world has already been drained of its sub-
stantive qualities of enchantment, nobility, and glory by Augustinian
Christianity’s reduction of nature to sheer fallen matter. To reiterate
an earlier observation: if there is a close precedent for the physics of
matter in motion among the ancients, it would be the stricter atom-
ism of Lucretius, in which there are no immanent qualities of grandeur
and heroism of the kind I have attributed to the pre-Socratics’ under-
standing of nature, and for whom the visible world is generated by the
sheer, accidental “swerve” of one contentless atom into another. For
Lucretius, the hedonism stemming from his materialistic view of life
meant that a man should cultivate his pleasures in private and avoid
the pain, violence, and stupidity of politics. The genius of liberalism
beginning with Hobbes might be characterized as erecting a new theory
of the just society on the very basis of this individuating ontology of
motion. For Hobbes, nature is now conceived of as a field of forces
whose accidental clashes generate visible phenomena. Human reason
has no immanent connection with nature so conceived; it is a uniquely
human tool whereby man can reconstruct his environment so as to
tame it and secure himself from its treacherous reverses. Precisely the
empty irrationality of nature makes it malleable to the structures that
178
superlative virtue
man’s will imposes on it. For Hobbesian man as homo faber, to make
something is to know it.16
Liberal political philosophers such as Hobbes upset the Aristotelian
equipoise by reducing the understanding of nature to spontaneous self-
movement alone and asserting man’s capacity, transferred from the
Abrahamic God, to turn against nature so conceived of and reconstruct
this purposeless flux. Rousseau reacts against this purely technical mode
of statecraft by evoking the spontaneous freedom and wholeness of the
natural life, in contrast with the artificiality and alienation brought
about by the modern bourgeois project with its burgeoning economic
and scientific apparatus. This return to nature from civilization is devel-
oped by Hegel and the historical school as the return from the state as an
artificially crafted contract to society as an underlying historical com-
munity. Now nature is seen as developing in history as the immanent
mores, traditions, and contexts of agreement that precede the artificial,
alienating, and atomizing imperatives of the bourgeois era with its social
contract. On the face of it, the return to nature launched by Rousseau
as the search for an individual and communal wholeness from which
we can resist the juggernaut of materialistic modernity bears a general
resemblance to Aristotle’s preference for political community over the
unrestrained productivity of the art of household management, and
serves to recall that dimension of nature that is simply given and self-
renewing and not reducible to mere material for human technique. By
the same token, however, this return bypasses the whole dimension of
Aristotle’s account of nature stressing its resemblance to the causality
most clearly exemplified by poiesis and techne, not only in physics but in
politics. The communitarian reading of Aristotle echoes the Rousseauan
conviction that, were man to be released from the bonds of the state
and the technical reasoning that upholds it, his happiness would be free
to flower. The point, however, is that not only the Hobbesian emphasis
on technique cut adrift from its natural mooring but the Rousseauan
emphasis on spontaneity bereft of rational construction are both dis-
tortions of what Aristotle meant by the naturalness of political life.17
179
tyranny
180
superlative virtue
and the oikos as the sole preserve of economic productivity and private
individualism.19 When Aristotle famously argues that man is by nature
a political animal who fulfills himself through deliberation about the
meaning of the just, the noble and the advantageous, he says that this
teleological activity takes place “in cities and households” (my empha-
sis), a detail often overlooked in the communitarian reading (1257a17–
18). As we earlier observed, only in Aristotle’s first presentation of the
household as one of the archaic and subpolitical associations that go
to make up the fully evolved polis is its role reduced to material and
reproductive necessity. Once the household is considered as a part of
the city, it too is ennobled. In the second presentation, the relationship
between father, mother, and children is based more on deliberation than
on compulsion or the mere assertion of patrimonial authority, and the
virtues of character that the family enshrines and cultivates in children
pass straight on to the role of family members as citizens deliberating
on the common good. To be sure, Aristotle does present the second
version of the family ennobled by its membership in the city as anal-
ogous to a small community that is a blend of the republican and the
monarchical. The husband is to persuade his wife as to the correctness
of his opinions, rather than simply force her obedience, and the same is
true of the relationship between parents and children. In both cases, the
subordinate partners only need to acquire correct opinion, not rigorous
knowledge (1259a37–1260b8). Nevertheless, the husband’s persuasion
of his wife and the parents’ persuasion of their children is an appeal
to their capacity for reasoned assent, not the simple exertion of force.
The family is like a political community in which the offices do not
rotate. However, this patriarchal monarchy of the household, based on
the capacity of women and children to actualize their own potentiality
for virtue, is diametrically opposed to the bad version of household
management that is tantamount to a master’s rule over the household’s
members as if they were mere slaves. The family has its own teleology.
It is not reducible to the realm of mere life – the life of material neces-
sity – as opposed to the good life of the polis unless it is perverted by
being given over to the aim of open-ended productivity and acquisi-
tion, although Aristotle is clear that a modicum of material wealth is
181
tyranny
necessary if citizens are to have the leisure for their two highest ends of
politics and philosophy.
In addition to overlooking the teleology of the oikos, Arendt also
overlooks Aristotle’s argument that oikonomia is not merely a subpo-
litical unit – our private bourgeois or nuclear family – but, more impor-
tant, a regime-level principle whose claim to teleological primacy over
the polis is, as we have seen, no simple matter to displace in unequivocal
favor of the koinonia politike. Finally, in her excessive dichotomization
of the household and the community, Arendt imports into her vision of
the ancient polis a Heideggerian existential stance of “risk.” For Aristo-
tle, however, politics is not about seeking authenticity through making
a resolute stand amidst Being. It is, at its best, a rational conversation
about how to make the proper choices among the ranked ends of the
moral and intellectual virtues. Its primary aim is not community for
its own sake, the prediscursive being-with-one-another-in-the-world of
Heidegger’s existential anthropology of Dasein that he locates in the
archaic, prephilosophic polis. On the contrary: for Aristotle, political
deliberation is inherently controversial, always potentially divisive, and
capable of boiling over from heated argument into violence and insur-
rection. Only gregarious animals like bees (1253a) have the kind of
sheer immanent communality romantically read back into the polis by
Arendt from Heidegger.
Hobbes does indeed, on a massive level, invert Aristotle’s priority
of the city over the household and apply the art of household man-
agement to society through the construction of the social contract and
the leeway that it grants to individual self-enrichment. However, it is
not Aristotle’s art of household management that Hobbes erects – not
even Aristotle’s view of the incorrect art of household management,
which he identifies with the excesses of hedonism and which can cul-
minate in tyranny, either within a city or by a city over other cities.
For Hobbes, by contrast, the art of economic productivity entailed by
a properly constructed social contract has been totally drained of Aris-
totelian teleological content. It is a contentless method, stemming from
the priority of efficient cause over all the other causes, for the imposition
of effectuating will on the purposeless fodder of nature, inherited from
Machiavelli by way of Bacon. As for the virtues Aristotle argues might
first be nurtured in family life, they are fine with Hobbes, but politi-
cally irrelevant, mere private avocations. People may enjoy private life
182
superlative virtue
183
tyranny
184
superlative virtue
185
IV
186
tyranny and the science of ruling
187
tyranny
188
tyranny and the science of ruling
189
tyranny
forces. Cyrus punishes the young man’s father, the king of Armenia,
who had executed this sophist for alienating his son’s affections from
their household, by stripping the father of his autonomous authority.
In this way, Cyrus’s monarchy effects a reform of the tyrannical kind of
politics that allows a philosopher to be put to death (3.1.14, 3.1.23–24,
3.1.39–43). (A tyrannical action of which democracy is also capable,
because the actual Socrates was also condemned in part for alienating
sons from their fathers.) We do not know from Xenophon’s narrative,
however, whom Tigranes would have preferred between Cyrus and the
sophist if the sophist had lived. Socrates and Cyrus and the ways of life
they embody touch. They never – like the two components of the Pla-
tonic philosopher-king – coincide. Nor is it obvious whom Xenophon
himself prefers between Socrates and Cyrus.
Indeed, if there is a single premise that explains the distinctiveness
of Xenophon’s political thought, it is his doubt whether the peaks of
human achievement can coexist in a single person. In other words, he
doubts the doctrine of the unity of virtue often associated with the
Platonic Socrates.6 Like Aristotle and in contrast to Plato, Xenophon
appears to believe that the virtues – particularly political excellence –
cannot be assimilated to philosophic virtue but should be explored
and accounted for in their heterogeneity. For Aristotle, however, and
notwithstanding his tortuous acknowledgment of the claims of superla-
tive virtue that we traced in the last chapter, the heterogeneity of the
virtues has the primary political consequence of bolstering the claims of
republican communities to be able to govern themselves and resist the
assimilation of citizen virtue to the Platonic science of monarchy. For
Xenophon, by contrast, the political virtues appear to reach their fullest
development in a supremely able – but honor-loving, nonphilosophic –
monarch. Monarchy without philosophy and heterogeneity without
republicanism: this, broadly formulated, is what makes Xenophon’s
point of departure for assessing the varieties of rule so distinctive,
although, as we will see, his assessments are not inflexible.
The Education of Cyrus is Xenophon’s most sustained investigation
of princely rule, a monarchical utopia as opposed to the republican
utopias of Plato and Aristotle. It can be situated within Xenophon’s
writings by considering two other works, each of which provides a sort
190
tyranny and the science of ruling
191
tyranny
192
tyranny and the science of ruling
the laws forbid everyone equally from harming anyone else (3.3, 4.3,
6.10). As for the poor tyrant, unloved and unsafe, he might as well hang
himself.
As Simonides wryly notes, the fact that Hiero has achieved and main-
tained this, by his own argument, most dangerous of stations is con-
vincing evidence that he prizes the honor it bestows more than he fears
the dangers and difficulties it entails (7.1–2). Plainly Hiero has omitted
some compensating advantages likely to postpone his suicide indefi-
nitely. Hiero had remarked that taking something from an “unwilling”
enemy was to him “the most pleasant of all things.” Although he meant
to contrast this with the friendship of a “willing” partner, in the course
of describing the reciprocity of friendship, he admits that the “most
pleasant” moments of erotic pleasure come during the “fights and quar-
rels” on the beloved’s part (1.34–35). It is not so clear, therefore, that
Hiero would really prefer the reciprocity of friendship with his lovers
and subjects to the unqualified possession of them to do with as he
pleases or even to the struggle he may face in getting his way (1.32–33).
Moreover, the tyrant possesses additional advantages over the citizen
in pursuing erotic fulfillment. When Hiero says that “even the cities do
not fail to notice” the value of friendship, we sense that, in his view,
the life of citizenship is by no means more conductive to making friends
than the tyrant’s life, if as much so. There are two reasons for this.
First, even family ties, which Hiero considers to be the “firmest” friend-
ships, must, he says, be “compelled by law” to follow the “inclination
of nature” (3.7.9). For example, cities protect the right of husbands to
slay adulterers (3.3). If, as this suggests, even the strongest natural ties
require a degree of political – nay, tyrannical – enforcement, the tyrant
with his absolute authority is much better equipped than a private cit-
izen to keep his friends and relatives in line. The need to enforce even
private erotic and familial ties is illustrated in the Education of Cyrus
when Tigranes’ father, in justifying his execution of the Socrates-like
sophist for alienating his son’s affections, compares it to a husband
justly killing his wife’s seducer (3.1.39). If even ordinary family life in
a city where the laws provide all men with a “bodyguard” can only
be maintained through such draconian incursions, how much in accor-
dance with nature are civic and family life at all? Second and more
important, Hiero omits to mention the vastly superior resources that a
tyrant possesses compared with a citizen to gratify his friends and win
193
tyranny
their loyalty by benefits and honors. After all, his rule can draw on the
resources of an entire city to maintain his personal household. Socrates
argues in the Republic that the tyrant’s limitless power to reward his
friends and harm his enemies irrespective of their virtue, extolled by
Glaucon in his evocation of the perfectly unjust man, is one of his cen-
tral character flaws. The Education of Cyrus, however, shows that this
tyrannical power might also be used to reward merit. Cyrus’s grandfa-
ther Astyages, although the king of Media by hereditary descent, rules
as a tyrant and “master” without legal restrictions (1.3.18). He is thus
able to lavish gifts and honors on his grandson and, in his affection
for Cyrus and recognition of his talents, raises Cyrus above his own
son and legitimate heir (1.3.13–14). In this way, it would seem that
not only a political community but a tyrant can rise above the love of
one’s own – in the case of Astyages, a father’s ordinary attachment to his
son – fuelled by an appreciation of the superior merit of a youth he loves
more. Capricious? Yes. Unjust? Not necessarily. Cyrus learns from this
egregious favoritism, which would have been promptly suppressed in
his Persian homeland with its strict code of republican equality, how
to win his subjects’ friendship with a skillful mixture of a “master’s”
generosity and recognition of merit with his capacity to inspire fear.
It is not that Hiero is lying, then, when he enumerates the drawbacks
of tyranny. They certainly exist. However, in omitting the compen-
sations of tyranny and the drawbacks of citizenship, he gives a very
one-sided diagnosis. Hiero’s belief that Simonides is “jealous” specifi-
cally of his “supreme power” to benefit his friends and crush his enemies
confirms our impression of Hiero’s reluctance to expound fully these
advantages of tyranny to a potential critic or competitor (Hiero 6.12).
Notwithstanding these omissions, Simonides gives Hiero some advice
on how he “might” convert his unwilling subjects into “willing” ones
and “friends.” To clarify this advice, we should pause to note the dis-
tinctions between kinds of rule that Socrates makes in the Memora-
bilia. Monarchy is rule over willing subjects according to law, whereas
tyranny is lawless rule over unwilling subjects (Memorabilia 4.6.12–13).
However, when Socrates considers whether “knowledge” (episteme)
might not be a more efficient and beneficent title to authority than con-
formity to law, an extra category is introduced – rule over willing sub-
jects transcending the law. As Socrates presents it, knowledgeable rule
pulls away from the republican standard of a community of shared rule
194
tyranny and the science of ruling
under law and points instead toward a “household” where the monarch
rules according to his own will over a ranked division of labor, every
class doing the jobs for which its members are naturally best suited.
This is the model of rule which Simonides recommends to Hiero.7 If
Hiero follows his advice, Simonides argues, his subjects will become
loyal and happy members of a good master’s household. Relieved of
any need to concern themselves with public affairs, cared for, protected,
and rewarded by the “leader” (Simonides delicately avoids conferring
on this reformed tyrant the fully legitimate title of king [basileus]), they
will be productive workers increasing their own wealth and the city’s
(Hiero 9.6.7,8; 10.3; 11.4,11,12,14). Whereas, as we saw in the pre-
vious chapter, Aristotle oscillates between the claims of law and the
claims of knowledge because of his reluctance to endorse the monarchi-
cal art unreservedly, Xenophon has his Simonides prescribe it without
reservation.
The dialogue ends, however, with no evident success on Simonides’
part in persuading Hiero to undertake this reform. Although Hiero can
doubtless see the advantages of a plan that would bolster his authority
without constraining him with laws, we have the feeling that he does not
quite want to renounce his unqualified possession of the city even if he
would be better off doing so. Hiero’s revelation of his own psychology
and motives as a ruler suggest two explanations for this reluctance.
Hiero may enjoy his recurrent triumph over the “fights and quarrels”
of his subjects too much to allow their discontent to evaporate. He may
prefer the recurrent sensations of risk and victory to the tranquillity of
efficient political management. In this sense, his eros and thumos may
enjoy their vital bellicosity too much to curtail themselves even for the
sake of more secure power. (In a similar mood, Callicles tells Socrates
that only a corpse would be content with being moderate [Gorgias
492].) Moreover, Simonides did not claim that the “real men” would
be reconciled to the tyrant’s rule by his advice, only the “human beings”
(11.8,11,14). Since the “real men” are likely to provide, because of their
ambition, the greatest threat to Hiero’s power and, because of their
love of honor, the kind of friends he would deem most worth having,
195
tyranny
196
tyranny and the science of ruling
197
tyranny
198
tyranny and the science of ruling
in life to all its inhabitants, eventually even including the large mass of
toiling commoners hitherto excluded from any kind of civic education
or citizen participation (rather as if the Auxiliaries in Plato’s Republic
invited the Artisans to join them as comrades in the common cause of
empire). In this way, Xenophon explores the possibility that an imperial
monarchy could democratize opportunity and allow individual merit to
override any injunctions to prefer the common good to one’s own. The
lesson Cyrus has learned in Media is that the individualism characteris-
tic of the Median king and his privatized subjects can, by employing the
skill and courage of the Persian education, acquire for each Persian of all
classes “great wealth, happiness and honor” that they would otherwise
never experience (1.5.8–12). We can already anticipate Machiavelli’s
partiality toward Xenophon among the ancients: an alliance between a
prince and the common people based on material self-interest, a project
for turning republican virtue outward as the fuel for imperial expansion
and prosperity – these, as we will see, are hallmarks of The Prince and
the Discourses, and references to “Xenophon’s Cyrus” are woven by
Machiavelli throughout his exploration of them.
199
tyranny
200
tyranny and the science of ruling
201
tyranny
toward its own fullest satisfaction. The young peers shatter this assump-
tion by unhesitatingly accepting Cyrus’s proposals, overturning their
years of painstaking civic education in a trice. That Cyrus can subvert
the republican ethos with a fifteen-minute speech is Xenophon’s tacit
speculation about just how naturally choice-worthy the common good
is for its own sake.
202
tyranny and the science of ruling
possible under the republican rule of law with its restrictions on out-
standing personal achievement. The Education of Cyrus may also be
taken as Xenophon’s critique of the view he attributes to Simonides that
a tyrant can convert, well along in his career, to a more efficient and
beneficent method of governing. The influence of Cyrus’s education on
his character remedies the crucial defect in Hiero that may have pre-
vented him from profiting from Simonides’ advice. Cyrus learned about
the household form of rule in Media without losing the immunity from
hedonism acquired during his austere Persian education. As a ruler,
consequently, Cyrus has no erotic passion for the literal possession and
consumption of his household and subjects. His relations with his sub-
ordinates are untinged with the jealousy or suspicion that arise from the
competition for pleasures. Cyrus can be ruthless, as we consider more
closely in our examination of Machiavelli’s reading of him. However,
he takes no pleasure (as does Hiero) in “fights and quarrels” with his
subordinates for their own sake apart from the cold-blooded goal of
expanding his power. He is more Oliver Cromwell than Caligula.
By resisting the conflation of political authority with a lover’s jeal-
ous possessiveness, the perfect monarch is, in Xenophon’s presentation,
psychologically distinct from tyrants as we usually encounter them and
bears little if any resemblance to the tyrant excoriated in Book 9 of
the Republic. Whether he is truly a king, however, or a new kind of
tyrant cloaked as or merged with a monarch remains an open question.
Whereas Socrates says in the Republic that, in the tyrant’s disrupted
soul, eros usurps the role of reason and becomes the “factional leader”
of the desires by enflaming them (572e–573e), Xenophon presents Cyrus
as a man whose eros for limitless honor, thoroughly drained of other
erotic desires, conquers others by helping them to gratify their plea-
sures, guided by the art of architectonic management. Whereas for
Plato, reason should govern eros and thumos, in Cyrus, an eros for
honor employs both “knowledge” (the science of ruling) and thumos in
its service. Cyrus might be likened to the “noble nature” described in
Book 6 of the Republic, capable of the best and worst actions. His edu-
cation through an exposure to both Persia and Media parallels the royal
myth in Plato’s Alcibiades I, in which Socrates exposes the young man
to the two mother regimes of republic and monarchy. The difference
is that the Platonic Socrates hoped philosophy would assimilate Alcibi-
ades’ ambition. He begins by stimulating Alcibiades with the vision of
203
tyranny
world rule, then brings him back to the polis now seen in light of the
universal. By contrast, the young Cyrus receives a quasi-theological edu-
cation from his father Cambyses that is partly Socratic but not explicitly
philosophic. Meant primarily to instill political moderation, it does not
stimulate an openness to the contemplative life. In founding his world
order, Cyrus eschews philosophy per se in order to actualize a Socrati-
cally rational politics in which the execution of a “Socrates in Armenia”
is avenged.
Is Cyrus, then, an unequivocally successful example in Xenophon’s
eyes of the perfection of the gentlemanly life that citizenship under law
may reach for but cannot fully attain? Is his career meant to show a way
of transcending the perplexities of Ischomachus? It might well seem so.
Ischomachus had said that royal rule was a “divine” life (Oeconomi-
cus 21.5.11–12). At the penultimate stage of his conquests, Cyrus’s
allies present him with a captive queen as his war prize (4.6.11, 5.1.6).
Reputed to be the most beautiful woman in Asia, her name – Pantheia –
means, literally, the “wholly divine.” Her award to Cyrus thus seems to
symbolize his crowning achievement.
Yet as Xenophon presents it, the cumulative answer to these ques-
tions remains tentative. This can be illustrated with several further
observations from the Education of Cyrus. Cyrus’s rule is likened by
one of his lieutenants to that of a “king-bee” (5.1.24). We recall that
Ischomachus’ praise of his wife as the “queen-bee” raised the possibility
that the gentleman is useless to his own household. The merging of king
and queen-bee in Cyrus suggests this problem could be avoided by the
extension of household management to kingship, which requires the
exercise of political and military as well as economic skills. It requires
the hardy virtues of the “real men” to bring about a world of pleasure
and safety for the “human beings.” This remedy does not dispose alto-
gether of the possibility that royal authority is still comparable to the
rather mundane managerial skills of a housekeeper, however – espe-
cially after the period of conquests is over and there is no more glory
to be won. The air of hedonistic dissipation and laxness that overtakes
Cyrus’s government in his waning years points to this difficulty. More-
over, while a republic can replicate its way of life through its institutions,
Cyrus, being a perfect monarch, could not be replicated – his sons were
mediocre. As the Education of Cyrus draws to a close, the crisis of
the succession throws the virtuous small republic with its emphasis on
204
tyranny and the science of ruling
205
tyranny
206
tyranny and the science of ruling
Socrates, in turning away from natural philosophy and the direct speech
about being, is inspired by what he depicts as Diotima’s teaching about
eros, and he hopes that Alcibiades’ natural eros for the beautiful and
good will lead him to philosophy by way of civic virtue. However,
Alcibiades’ late and disruptive entrance in the Symposium at the height
of his political preeminence blocks that ascent and calls it into ques-
tion through his rivalry with Socrates for the possession of Agathon
(“[the] Good” [to agathon]), symbolic of a rivalry between wisdom
and power. In this case, the beauty of Pantheia (the “wholly divine”)
inspires an erotic longing for the beautiful in a young man. But it
is Cyrus himself, a ruler rather than a philosopher, who blocks the
erotic ascent in the name of a prudence guided by the art of ruling,
a prudence that disavows a love of the beautiful. The Xenophontic
debate about eros also recalls Homer’s Iliad. There, Agamemnon and
his ally Achilles vie over a captive woman, the flashpoint for Achilles’
wounded honor and insubordination toward the king who has slighted
him by seizing his war prize. In the Education of Cyrus, by contrast, a
self-controlled monarch resists the erotic battle for prestige over a cap-
tive woman with an Achillean subordinate, instead crushing his eros
through fear. Whereas for Plato the prospect for curing the Achillean
man lies in philosophically grounded eros, for Xenophon it lies in effi-
cient rule by a ruler whose eros for honor is undistracted by a love of the
beautiful.
Especially when considered in the light of his coldness and his friend-
lessness, there is something indiscriminate and egotistical about Cyrus’s
“thirst” for the gratitude and honor of millions of people whom he
never lays eyes on and not one of whom is in a position to earn his
gratitude or respect in return (5.1.1). Cyrus’s coldness (noted jokingly
by his innermost circle) toward any particular erotic attachment is not,
after all, the moderation of a citizen subordinating his desires to the
common good, but the psychological means he has devised in him-
self to devote his talents undistractedly to what could be characterized
as shameless pandering to the material needs of the “human beings.”
Whereas for the Platonic Socrates, lower erotic passions are assimilated
by an eros for the Good, for Xenophon’s Cyrus, they are assimilated
by an eros for the universal and demotic love of “all men.” As we see
in the next chapter, Machiavelli makes use of the Pantheia episode, in
ways both approving and disapproving, to develop his argument that a
207
tyranny
prince must resist the allure of eros – not only as it relates to his own
passions, but in the broader sense of longing for the love of his subjects
by believing that his eros for supreme honor is compatible with the
service of the common good. Machiavelli weaves a dense layering of
associations in which Scipio Africanus the Elder, the greatest Roman
admirer of Xenophon’s Cyrus, becomes, through his desire to enact the
erotic ascent up Diotima’s Ladder, the corrupter of the Roman repub-
lic and a wholly negative standard for either princely or republican
government, a tableau we explore in detail in Chapters 5 and 6.
Cyrus’s lack of restraint with respect to his eros for universal honor
is prefigured by his obliviousness as a young man to any sense of awe
or shame before the gods. As he tells his father Cambyses, he cheer-
fully regards the gods as “friends” who unfailingly reward ambitious
effort like his own with commensurate success (1.6.6–36, 2.3.4). By
contrast, Cambyses tries to moderate his son’s ambitions by stressing
that there is an inscrutable disjunction between human virtue and the
gods’ favor that a prudent ruler should bear in mind before undertak-
ing too ambitious an enterprise (1.6.18,23–24,26,44–46). Cambyses’
exchanges have parallels in Xenophon’s depiction of Socrates, and his
stress on the role of chance in the prospects for the success of virtue and
wise rule is, as we have seen in previous chapters, in keeping with Plato’s
presentation of Socrates as well. This private conversation between the
constitutional monarch and his son might suggest that, behind the insis-
tence of the regime on conformity to the law, there is a deeper theolog-
ical justification for the moderation it instills, one that reaches beyond
what service to the common good requires and says something about
the world at large. Cyrus, however, is confident that techne can over-
come tuche. He compares an energetic general to a productive farmer,
as if every human virtue were a means to human procurement, and as if
a general’s marshalling of force to destroy a foe were comparable to a
farmer’s cultivation of nature to yield produce while caring for the soil
(1.6.18, 2.2.24–26). Cambyses observes in reply that even an energetic
general may be thwarted by “a god,” while he greets the comparison of
generalship to farming with silence. It is as if, in Cambyses’ view, the
relation between man and the earth illustrates the disjunction between
the cultivation of virtue and the nonhuman order especially clearly, an
irreducible complex of art, nature’s potential, and the cultivation of an
208
tyranny and the science of ruling
9 See the detailed discussion in Nadon (2001) as well as Breebart (1983) p. 126 and Higgins
(1977) pp. 57–59.
209
tyranny
210
tyranny and the science of ruling
to this quandary when they pray that (the) God will protect them from
tyrants while at the same time helping the man ambitious to serve his
country. A part of the tragedy of the play is that, in their subconscious
anxiety, the Thebans are not sure which category Oedipus himself falls
into, tyrant or statesman – and neither is he. They begin:
211
tyranny
212
tyranny and the science of ruling
12 See the discussion of the Clouds in Nicholls (1983a) pp. 35 ff. As Athenian power
rose and waned during the Peloponnesian War, there was a widespread feeling that
the old religious and moral codes were melting away, leaving a vacuum filled by the
Sophists’ morality of “getting the better.” See Dodds in Plato (1979) p. 292, and Guthrie
(1983) pp. 106–107. Shorey describes Callicles, whose defense of the natural master
closely parallels that of the generals on Melos, as “the embodiment of the immoralist
tendencies of the age” (1968) pp. 141, 146–147. Friedlander sees a connection between
the debate over the two ways of life – tyranny and philosophy – in the Gorgias, Republic,
and other dialogues and this surrounding climate of moral anxiety and further observes
that Socrates’ discussion with Callicles revolves around three intertwined issues: justice
versus injustice, philosophy versus politics, and Socrates versus imperial Athens (1973)
p. 261.
213
tyranny
214
tyranny and the science of ruling
differed from more aggressive imperialists like his successors Cleon and
Alcibiades only about the means to empire, not the end itself. Therefore,
from Socrates’ viewpoint in the Gorgias, he is not fit for inclusion in the
ranks of truly prudent statesmen who would understand the need for
the city’s internal moderation to be matched by an external avoidance
of the temptations to tyrannize over other cities abroad.
Although the Athenians did foolishly underestimate the size, wealth,
and resources of Sicily before undertaking the invasion (6.18.1–3),
Thucydides observes that the main reason for its failure stemmed from
Athenian internal politics after Pericles’ death. Alcibiades began as the
leader of the invasion force, and his conduct “was as good as could
be desired.” It was his recall and replacement by Nicias that doomed
the invasion (6.18.16, 2.7.65–67, 6.19.61–62).13 Thucydides is a unique
figure in the intellectual context surrounding the emergence of the
Socratic school. He appears to share the Sophists’ view of politics as
a ceaseless struggle for individual and collective aggrandizement; that
motion is the natural condition of politics rather than rest. At the same
time, he keenly appreciates the perils that expansionism poses to the
freedom and internal ordering of regimes that are embroiled in it. In the
long run, the superpower conflict between Athens and Sparta, in part
based on self-interest (Athens’ desire for glory and wealth and Sparta’s
fear that Athens’ rising power must be nipped in the bud before it
becomes overwhelming) but also on what we might term an ideological
struggle between two different regime principles, democracy and a tim-
ocratic oligarchy, reaches into and subverts the internal politics of all the
13 For a longer discussion of the Peloponnesian War and its significance for political
philosophy, see Newell (2009), Orwin (1994), and Palmer (1992). On the relationship
between political philosophy and the historical context of Athens’ rise to empire, see
the fine study by Balot (2001), a deft and sure-footed interdisciplinary cross-hatching
of intellectual, political, and cultural history. It is part of a distinguished school of
classical and historical scholarship including Kagan (2003), Ober (1998), and Strauss
(2004) from which political theorists can learn much. On the pivotal role of Alcibiades
in Thucydides’ history, Balot writes: “Once Alcibiades is removed from a position of
leadership, the centrifugal tendencies of the democracy spiral outward in an increasing
display of civic mistrust and divisiveness. The democratic process can no longer coalesce
successfully around Alcibiades’ compelling personality and vision” (2001) p. 178. If I
am warranted in describing Thucydides’ history as a secular tragedy, Herodotus’ history
is arguably even more sui generis with a less clear connection to the pre-Socratics and
Sophists. See Thompson (1996), who argues that, for Herodotus, the transmission of
stories is crucial for the identity of a political community.
215
tyranny
216
tyranny and the science of ruling
these people were shocked by the Plague into thinking the gods were
punishing them for unjustly provoking war with Sparta and appalled
by the desecration of their ancestral villages and tombs when the rural
population was brought within the Long Walls to protect them from
the invading Spartans.
Absent an accidental monarch in disguise like Pericles, Thucydides
implies, the public and private interest in an imperialistic democracy
may be irreconcilable. This is what led to the war expanding beyond
the bounds set by Pericles . Alcibiades wanted glory and needed money
to float his many extravagances. Leading the city to fresh conquests
and plunder was the surest route. It also led to the failure of the Sicilian
expedition and Sparta’s subsequent rise to predominance, for Nicias
was not the right kind of man to place in charge of carrying out so
bold a scheme. After the death of Cleon, another bellicose leader of the
war party who had dominated Athenian politics following the demise
of Pericles’ centrist policy, the way was open for Nicias to conclude
a peace treaty with Sparta (5.15.17). Many were in favor, but others,
whipped up by Alcibiades, felt themselves taken advantage of – the war
was ending before they had a crack at the riches to come from further
expansion (5.16.43,45–46; 6.18.1,8–9).
Nicias tries to dissuade the assembly from undertaking the new war
against Sicily by detailing the enormous preparations they will have
to make to carry it off (6.18.9–15). But his very assiduousness in list-
ing these preparations convinces the demos that they have the prudent
advice they need to make the invasion a success. Alcibiades seizes the
moment to advance himself as Nicias’ junior partner – he, the young
and daring son, will carry out the invasion guided by his elder’s sober
logistical advice. In this way, he concludes, he and Nicias together, bold-
ness tempered by prudence, will make success inevitable (6.18.15–20).
Whereas Alcibiades believes in daring, innovation, and improvisation,
Nicias (broadly speaking, more like Cambyses, cautious father of the
daring Cyrus in the Education of Cyrus) relies on fortune and the ulti-
mate wisdom of the gods, who discourage overweening human ambi-
tion. In contrast with the Athenian generals on Melos, Nicias believes
that we must behave justly because the gods uphold justice. He repre-
sents a side of Athens that is attracted to the more traditional culture of
their Spartan adversaries, who live archaically as if nothing had changed
since the defeat of Persia and the rise of Athens. If one viewed the
217
tyranny
218
tyranny and the science of ruling
14 See the fine reading of the Gorgias by Ranasinghe (2009). He explores Socrates’ claim
that it is better to suffer evil than to do it, juxtaposed against the violent backdrop
of the Peloponnesian War and its incitement to demagogic violence, calling into ques-
tion the famous Socratic proposition that no one can willingly choose to do evil if he
knows what virtue is. Arguing that the rhetorical arguments of the Sophists encoun-
tered by Socrates in the Gorgias are baser and more nihilistic than those treated in the
Republic, Ranasinghe underscores the urgent need addressed by Socrates to find a noble
rhetoric of justice to defeat the interweaving of the Sophists’ and Athenian imperialism’s
demagoguery.
219
tyranny
are those “motions” that upsurge into human beings as the impulse
to master and exploit others. Regimes are local, happenstantial modal
variants of this underlying universal urge.
The Sicilian expedition and its disastrous denouement, the destruc-
tion of the fleet and of the flower of the Athenian forces, dying slowly
of starvation and exposure trapped in a marble quarry in Syracuse, fol-
lows closely on the Melian dialogue, suggesting in a massive way that
it is a deserved comeuppance for the Athenian generals’ position that
men by nature “rule wherever they can” (Peloponnesian War 7.23).
Appealing as we might find this interpretation of a historical drama
echoing the tragedic structure of hubris followed by nemesis, we should
bear in mind that the Athenian “few” – the generals on Melos – may
well not have spoken this way to the Athenian “many” back home.
(The entire dialogue takes place behind closed doors between the elites
of both sides.) Counseled by the Sophists, they likely concealed their
unvarnished impiety and pleonexia behind a more seemly deference to
convention. For, as Thucydides relates, the Athenian “silent majority”
(as we have put it) are deeply concerned at this time over a defilement of
the Hermes, a god dear to the common folk, widely suspected to have
been carried out by Alcibiades on one of his drunken carouses (6.18.28–
30). (Is it too much to wonder whether the defilement took place just
before, and making him late for, his boozy arrival in the Symposium?)
Still plagued by guilt over starting the war, these conservative Athe-
nians have been consulting oracles about the gods’ judgment (2.6.54).
The generals, on the other hand, who believe the gods, if they exist at
all (they say they “know” the truth about men but merely “believe”
it about gods), are indifferent to justice either in their own sphere or
the human sphere, represent the new Athens at its most extreme, the
side that Alcibiades belongs to as well. The generals on Melos, how-
ever, have not as yet thought through or carried out the consequences
for Athenian domestic politics of what they propose for foreign affairs:
if, as a necessary law of nature, you must “have more” wherever you
can, why not achieve this tyrannical power over your own people? The
Athenian silent majority instinctively fear that Alcibiades, on the eve of
being placed in command of an enormous armada and army, is on the
verge of connecting these dots.
The Athenians continue to want power over others and the prosper-
ity it brings. They continue to heed Pericles’ advice, in his waning days,
220
tyranny and the science of ruling
that their empire is a tiger by the tail and that, if they let it go, the peo-
ples they have oppressed will turn on them savagely. Yet although the
essence of Pericles’ utilitarian moderation was that the empire should
neither expand beyond its resources nor be abandoned, the majority
of Athenians, whatever their misgivings, cannot resist the lure of fur-
ther expansion and so launch the Sicilian expedition. At the same time,
however, they are afraid that to give the man with enough daring to
bring the invasion off the military power to do so – Alcibiades – will
simultaneously allow him to have power over them. They want to tyran-
nize over others without being tyrannized over. This is why they recall
Alcibiades from the expedition after it has embarked and place their
confidence in Nicias, even though Nicias lacks the daring to carry it off
and opposed it categorically as madly imprudent for opening another
war front when the contest with Sparta was far from resolved (6.18.9–
13). The demand for freedom from tyranny in democratic domestic
politics, Thucydides teaches, contradicts the measures that need to be
taken to achieve tyranny abroad. The expedition is a disaster because
of the nature of democratic politics in particular and of the political
community in general. Imperialistic democracy gives full flower to indi-
vidual ambition, freedom, prosperity, innovation, public magnificence,
and open-mindedness – all the things Pericles praised about Athens in
his famous funeral oration at the outset of the conflict with Sparta
(2.6.34–47). Imperialistic democracy also subverts the common good,
however, creating an irreparable tension between the individual and the
city, and gives those inclined to or tempted by the prospect of tyranny
a licit scope for their ambition.
Although Plato’s dialogues are of permanent significance, rising from
the particular context of ancient Athens to elucidate truths that are uni-
versal and lasting, they do unfold quite explicitly against the backdrop
of Athens’ extraordinary rise and fall as narrated by Thucydides, and
many events and characters from Thucydides’ narrative (Alcibiades,
Nicias, Laches) appear in Plato’s dialogues. Moreover, the Alcibiades
of history and of the Platonic dialogues do closely converge. For it was
Alcibiades, the leader of the war party in Athens, who most certainly
did think through the unspecified ramifications for internal Athenian
politics of the thesis advanced by the generals on Melos that one rules
wherever one can. He did connect the dots between empire abroad and
tyranny at home. He was impious and recognized no legal or moral
221
tyranny
222
tyranny and the science of ruling
223
tyranny
Viewed against the backdrop of this long imperial struggle, its zenith
and denouement in Athenian defeat, the backlash at home of fear
(8.24.1) and suspicion of would-be tyrants and their cronies and men-
tors (Socrates was eventually swept up in this post-Alcibiadean atmo-
sphere of populist paranoia), the classics offer two solutions for resolv-
ing the contradiction between democracy and empire. They shared
common ground with the poets in that they did not dispute the fact that
exceptional ambition is a naturally recurrent and spontaneous variation
in human psychology; that it could not be extirpated or entirely fore-
stalled, and was sometimes necessary to aid the city. But, whereas the
poets were resigned to ambition periodically arising and periodically
being crushed by an inscrutable divine necessity, the classical politi-
cal philosophers believed that this potentially tyrannical soul could be
rehabilitated into the consistent service of justice. On the other hand, in
contrast with modern Hobbesian statecraft, the aim was not to re-wire
Alcibiades through behavior modification into a clockwork orange (like
Anthony Burgess’ character Alex), but to turn him into a steadfast and
self-controlled Stoic warrior like (to take one important version) the
Auxillaries in the Republic.
The mainstream classical tradition embodied by Plato and Aristo-
tle tries as much as possible to insulate a self-governing republic from
foreign entanglements, which involves discrediting democracy itself –
with its licentiousness, individualism, love of variety, luxury and for-
eign fashion, and proneness to demagogues – in favor of an austere,
inward-looking, aristocratic republic of the best men. A concentration
on internal self-government and an avoidance of imperial ambition
through a purely defensive foreign policy, according to the classical
prescription, will prevent politics from soliciting the supremely ambi-
tious proto-tyrant who can court the many and mask his rise as the
indispensable servant of imperial expansion bringing the common peo-
ple greater riches (Republic 422a–423b; Politics 1333b26–40; 1330b-
1331a; 1324b22–41; 1325b23–33). These potential tyrants, the Alcibi-
adean men, must be forestalled from developing the erotic disorder that
is the psychological root of their tyrannical longing by an education in
civic virtue governed by philosophy. Alcibiades might have proven to
be a magnificent half-birth, but if the “pattern in the sky” (Republic
592b) of the best regime is transmitted to posterity, it may re-shape the
characters of future such men. Alcibiades will become Cicero’s Scipio,
224
tyranny and the science of ruling
subordinating the licit honor that comes from serving a republic of laws
to his higher admiration for the life of the mind, thus submitting to the
hierarchy of reason over honor in Diotima’s Ladder in a way that the
actual Alcibiades, beginning with his ribald and swaggering entrance
to the dialogue and his semi-comic, semi-serious battle with Socrates to
woo Agathon, refused to do (Symposium 212d–213e).
Thus, in the main, for Plato and Aristotle the rule of reason, to what-
ever degree practicably possible, aided by an education that sublimates
and re-directs tyrannical eros and thumos toward serving the common
good, is at its best co-terminous with republican self-government. Even
so, as we have seen at some length, Plato and Aristotle do admit the
possibility of a tyranically founded just regime and a rational monar-
chy absolute in authority and multi-national in scope. In Xenophon,
we find the fullest exploration of this alternative, whereby reason is
co-terminous with the multi-national art of household management.
It is hard not to see in Xenophon’s re-creation of the young Cyrus
a version of what Alcibiades might have become if a philosophically
grounded education had taken hold in his character from early on,
converting him, not into the citizen of a republic friendly to philosophy
envisioned by Plato and Aristotle, but into a benign, efficient, moderate,
and self-controlled universal ruler extending the pattern of the Good to
all peoples under his sway while at the same time gratifying his eros for
limitless prestige. In other words, instead of, as the Platonic Socrates
does, leading Alcibiades to the universality of thought by way of his
universal ambition so as to deliver him back to his city better equipped
to govern in it, Xenophon in effect takes him from the universality of
thought to the actualization of a universalistic government. Whereas
Plato and Aristotle try to resolve the contradiction between democracy
and empire by excluding empire and extolling the reform of republi-
can self-government in accordance with reason, Xenophon resolves it
(at least speculatively) by forsaking the polis and extolling the reform
of empire in accordance with reason. My suggested identification of
Xenophon’s Cyrus with an Alcibiades transformed into an architec-
tonically guided imperial statesman of genius is hinted at in Cyrus’s
indirect encounter with the “Armenian Socrates” whose unjust execu-
tion for allegedly alienating the sons from the fathers he posthumously
avenges. This identification is even more strikingly evoked by Cyrus’s
dialogue with his father Cambyses, a republican limited monarch
225
tyranny
16 See the very able discussion of “Cyrus’ Socratic education” in Rasmussen (2009) ch. 5.
226
tyranny and the science of ruling
227
V
machiavelli,
xenophon, and
xenophon’s cyrus
228
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
229
tyranny
230
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
art of ruling, and the Athenian Stranger in the Laws considers Cyrus’s
type of monarchy to be one of the two mother regime principles along
with democracy (Plato Laws 694–697). As we saw in Chapter 3, Aris-
totle in his Politics defines virtuous kingship as the exercise of the art
of household management over “cities and peoples” (Aristotle Politics
1285b20). Although this passage from Aristotle is sometimes taken to
allude to Alexander the Great, we have observed that it could also serve
as a brief summary of Xenophon’s monarchical utopia, the Education
of Cyrus. Among the classical writers on statecraft, Xenophon stands
out for his interest in the model provided by Cyrus’s monarchy, which
he explores in greater depth and to a far greater extent than any of
the others. As we noted earlier, according to an ancient tradition, the
Education of Cyrus was widely regarded as Xenophon’s central treatise
on politics, a multinational monarchical ideal paralleling (and perhaps
intended to rival) Plato’s idealized polis in the Republic.2
Just as the interpretation of Cyrus teaches us something about how
the Greeks evolved their own conceptions of monarchy, the way in
which that classical complex of ideas was interpreted by Machiavelli
can teach us something about how the modern conception of monarchy
and of statecraft in general differs from its classical antecedents. As we
saw in the last chapter, among the ancient thinkers, Xenophon gives
considerably more latitude, through his reflections in the Education of
Cyrus, to a rationally organized, expansionist, multinational monarchy
premised on the glory seeking and material enrichment of its individual
subjects, and correspondingly downplays the appeal of the small
homogeneous republic with its nonexpansionist foreign policy and
economic austerity. Xenophon’s idealization of Cyrus’s monarchy,
in other words, is congenial with one major rubric of Machiavelli’s
own recommendations for a more realistic art of ruling expressly
aimed at the maximization of power and economic well-being. Because
Xenophon was widely admired during classical antiquity and the
Renaissance as one of the best writers on monarchy, it is, I suggest,
rhetorically convenient for Machiavelli to wrap himself in the venerable
2 See, for example, Xenophon (1880) p. xvi. I have described these prescriptions as “ideal”
because that term is immediately accessible. However, I remind the reader to bear in mind
my earlier remarks on why the classical prescriptions for the best regime cannot strictly
speaking be considered “ideals” in the modern Kantian sense.
231
tyranny
3 Most humanists read the Education of Cyrus as presenting a paragon of kingly goodness,
although this was not always thought to be incompatible with martial prowess. See,
for example, Poggio’s dedication of his translation to Alphonso of Aragon (quoted in
Gilbert [1938] p. 131) and Vasco Fernandez’s preface to his translation (Gallet-Guerne
[1974] pp. 182–184). Montaigne, although admiring the work, was “astonished” by “the
great liberty allowed by Xenophon” in “his complete emperor” for deception. Montaigne
(1952) p. 13. Sometimes we find Xenophon being read in a more starkly Machiavellian
manner, as when, for example, James I in the Basilikon Doron refers to the Education of
Cyrus to establish the maxim that a prince needs to begin his reign by being deliberately
cruel so that he can then afford to be merciful. Gilbert (1938) p. 101.
232
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
proper balance of the intellect and the passions in pursuit of the good, a
meaning of virtue that we would readily recognize, he does not exclude
the possibility that excellence in civic life could encompass a longing for
preeminence bordering on arrogance and a disregard for the views of
others – such that his term “superlative virtue,” which describes those
few who possess prudence and are therefore best suited to govern, has a
connotation of “overbearing” or “excessive” (huperbole) talent, when
we would not ordinarily think it possible to have too much goodness of
character. These ambiguities are heightened by the Latin translation of
arete by the much narrower and specific term virtus, the root of which
means a manly man, analogous to the term aner in Greek, such that
virtus is very nearly synonymous with manly courage, especially in war.
Hence, moral thinkers such as Cicero, and later Christian theologians
such as St. Augustine, must continue to use this word originally connot-
ing martial prowess as they transpose to it gentler virtues of moderation
and an openness to philosophical or divine transcendence. While virtus
comes to include these more sublime connotations, it never loses its
original connotation of manly courage and honor in ordinary usage.
Hence, when Machiavelli discusses the “virtues” of the prince and of
statesmen, he can play upon this full range of meanings by pushing
what he means by virtu back in the pagan direction of manly honor
and victory as the basis for his even more radical assimilation of virtue
to the will to master nature. Even the morally inclined reader finds it
difficult to resist being drawn in, because even from the Christian per-
spective, it would not have been claimed that virtue had no connotation
at all of political and military strength or of civic-spiritedness, even if
faith ranked much higher. This is the thin edge of the wedge for Machi-
avelli slowly but surely divesting his use of virtu of any otherworldly
or transcendental associations at all. Among the ancients, Xenophon is
his closest ally in doing so, which is why it is so useful for Machiavelli,
writing in an atmosphere of intense respect for classical antiquity, to
invoke his venerable precedent.
Cyrus the Great is listed, along with Moses, Romulus, and The-
seus, as princes of “outstanding virtue” because of their capacity to
master fortune. Here the classical and Abrahamic codes of rule begin
to be conflated, for not only is a prophet (Moses) equated with secu-
lar rulers (Cyrus, Romulus, and Theseus), thus anticipating Spinoza’s
presentation of him as creating Judaism to achieve social cohesion
233
tyranny
234
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
It was necessary then for Moses to find the people of Israel in Egypt, enslaved
by the Egyptians, so that they would be disposed to follow him in order to
get out of their servitude. It was fitting that Romulus not be received in Alba,
that he should have been exposed at birth, if he was to become king of Rome
and founder of that fatherland. Cyrus needed to find the Persians malcontent
with the empire of the Medes, and the Medes soft and effeminate because of
a long peace.
235
tyranny
236
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
The reader must wonder just how apt this illustration is for Machi-
avelli’s own theme of rising from base to great fortune. For Xenophon’s
Cyrus was, to reiterate, never a man of base or obscure origins. In fact, as
the son of the Persian king and grandson of the Median king, he would
appear to be squarely in the category that Machiavelli has excluded
237
tyranny
In the life of Cyrus, Xenophon shows that when Cyrus was going to assault
the king of Armenia, in devising that struggle he reminded his men that this
was none other than one of those hunts that they had often undertaken with
him. He reminded those whom he sent in ambush on top of mountains that
they were like those who went to hold the nets on the ridges, and those who
rode the plains that they were like those who went to flush the beast from the
cover so that when hunted it would trip into the nets.
238
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
239
tyranny
240
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
241
tyranny
like Cyrus could shape posterity’s view of him by the choice of materials
he passes down about his exploits. It might also demonstrate the power
that a writer about princes like Xenophon has in shaping those same
materials. The reader would be left to ponder whether the seemlier
foreground account is likelier to be true – where Araspas simply exits
the narrative when his role in the story ends – or the darker version
implied by a Machiavellian reading of his fate. It is unclear whether
Machiavelli is attributing this darker sensibility to Xenophon himself
or merely inviting us to read in a darker perspective evidence amassed
by Xenophon more benignly or innocently, a perspective grounded in
Herodotus’s more realistic view of Cyrus as a man who owed nothing
to fortune or his obscure origins and had to fight for it all.
242
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
243
tyranny
vices, and thereby rose to a position of power that left him free to
remake himself and endow himself retroactively with the traditional
virtues.
Hannibal, then, is contrasted not with the real Cyrus – whom he
resembles – but with Xenophon’s Cyrus, a paragon of humanity and
kindness that is “the very opposite” course. Scipio, on the other hand,
we are told, practiced only the virtues of “humanity and benevolence”
that he had learned from the Education of Cyrus. Either Hannibal’s or
Scipio’s method is capable of success or failure, Machiavelli concedes,
depending on the “virtue” of the one who employs it, but he definitely
leans toward Hannibal’s method as the more reliable. Scipio’s generosity
to his troops, Machiavelli maintains, inflamed their desires to the point
where he could no longer satisfy them or maintain discipline. Hannibal,
however, with his “inhuman cruelty and infinite virtue” terrified his sol-
diers into reconciliation to his rule and gratitude for whatever positive
favors he chose to bestow (The Prince chapter 17). In other words, it is
not enough for a prince to rely on his subjects’ own assessment of their
self-interest. By contrasting Scipio’s failure at ruling with Hannibal’s
success, Machiavelli suggests that the imitator of the real Cyrus would
inspire fear in his subjects so as to make it always in their minimal self-
interest to obey him and to inspire their deeper gratitude for benefits
beyond the minimum of survival – an anticipatory job description for
Hobbes’s Sovereign.
Chapter 22 again stresses Xenophon’s importance in the history of
the mirror of princes. For, as Machiavelli observes, the humanity of
Cyrus praised by Xenophon “conforms very much with what Titus Livy
says of Valerius.” Nevertheless, according to Machiavelli, Livy himself
is of two minds about whether humanity or hardness is the better way,
for he “speaks honorably in the same way of Manlius, showing that his
severity in the death of his son made the army so obedient to the consul
that it was the cause of the victory that the Roman people had against
the Latins.” So, as Machiavelli concludes, “it would be difficult to
judge” which course is better. But he does offer a judgment: the severity
of Manlius is better for a republic of laws because it is impartial. As
he explains: “By showing oneself always harsh to everyone and loving
only the common good, one cannot acquire partisans; for whoever
does this does not acquire particular friends for himself, which we
call . . . partisans.” By contrast, the humane approach of Valerius,
244
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
245
tyranny
246
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
247
tyranny
248
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
6 See, for example, Aristotle On the Soul 414a30–b15, where thumos, for Plato the seat
of courage in the soul and distinct from mere bodily desire (epithumia), is demoted to
merely one variety of desire along with epithumia, and where intellect (nous) is discussed
without any reference to phronesis, the highest virtue of the statesman in the Politics and
Nicomachean Ethics.
249
tyranny
250
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
251
tyranny
252
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
subjects to his absolute authority seem to flow effortlessly from the fact
that “all men were willing to obey him.”
In chapter 17, Machiavelli debates whether a prince should practice
pity or cruelty. Pity evokes both the classical virtue of clemency toward
defeated foes practiced by great rulers like Cyrus, Alexander, and Cae-
sar and the cardinal Christian virtue of compassion. As Machiavelli
observes, it is traditionally held that a ruler who practices the virtue of
compassion will be loved by his subjects, whereas the cruel ruler will
be feared and hated. Hence, in the traditional view, compassion is both
good for its own sake and contributes to a ruler’s security. In stark con-
trast, Machiavelli argues that a ruler who is excessively compassionate
will allow civil strife and foreign foes to gain the upper hand, leading
to an increase in the violence and disorder suffered by the majority of
his subjects, which is tantamount to subjecting them to enormous cru-
elty. Again, practicing the virtue for its own sake is guaranteed to bring
about its opposite vice. Instead, Machiavelli argues, the judicious use of
force to suppress incipient insurrection or preemptively knock out a for-
eign foe will, through a short and efficiently targeted interval of cruelty,
guarantee long-term peace and prosperity for the people. Moreover, he
maintains, it is quite possible in reality to be cruel in this efficient and
utilitarian way without being hated, although one will be feared. So in
this way, too, a prince’s authority and hold on power will be more sta-
ble through his being cruel rather than compassionate. This is so long
as the cruelty is, as he puts it in chapter 8, “well-used,” which means
for the sake of maximizing security and well-being for both princes and
peoples, and not prompted by some spasm of personal lust or fury. He
concludes: “A prince . . . so as to keep his subjects united and faithful
should not care about the infamy of cruelty, because with very few
examples he will be more merciful than those who for the sake of too
much mercy allow disorders to continue” (The Prince chapter 17).8
8 See the fine exegesis by Orwin (1978), especially his emphasis on how Machiavelli lib-
erates pity from piety, and argues that “well-used” cruelty, applied judiciously and all
at once, is in the long run more compassionate than abstaining from violence, because
it saves everyone from the far worse cruelty of unrestrained civil strife, a point of con-
tact between Machiavelli and Hobbes’s unvarnished remark that the worst conceivable
tyrant, if he maintains order, is preferable to relapsing into the state of nature and the
war of all against all. On the need to use force methodically, see Wolin’s discussion of
how, for Machiavelli, politics is a “science of the controlled application of force” (2006)
p. 221.
253
tyranny
254
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
255
tyranny
(His) armies in Spain rebelled against him. This arose from nothing but his
excessive mercy, which had allowed his soldiers more license than is fitting
for military discipline. Scipio’s mercy was reproved in the Senate by Fabius
Maximus, who called him the corrupter of the Roman military.
The man who passed this test, the successful exemplar of leadership,
is Hannibal, whose methods could not have been more diametrically
opposed to the gentle approach of Scipio:
Among the admirable actions of Hannibal is numbered this one: that when
he had a very large army, mixed with infinite races of men, and had led it to
fight in alien lands, no dissension ever arose in it, neither among themselves
nor against the prince, in bad as well as in good fortune. This could not have
arisen from anything other than his inhuman cruelty which, together with his
infinite virtues, always made him venerable in the sight of his soldiers; and
without it, his other virtues would not have sufficed to bring about this effect.
And the writers, having considered little on this, on the one hand admire this
action of his but on the other condemn the principle cause of it.
256
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
might well have been supplied by the historical Cyrus himself as he,
along with Moses and the other examples of the most “outstanding
virtue,” shaped the accounts of themselves to be handed down to pos-
terity by religious, poetic, and philosophical filters. Machiavelli’s Cyrus
is the truly effective if terrifying reality, the man who rises through
force and fraud from base origins by constantly fighting the malignity
of Fortuna with his strength of will, so that he can, godlike, introduce
into matter whatever form he pleases.
257
tyranny
258
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
259
tyranny
260
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
between virtuous and vicious, noble and base, gentlemanly and unre-
strained conduct. He sees in a ruler like Cyrus a high degree of excel-
lence but also deficiencies that may be compensated for by the excel-
lences of citizenship and philosophy. Cyrus’s love of honor may be
too demotic and undiscriminating. He loves to gratify others but will
never allow himself to be put in the position of the beneficiary, which
calls into question his capacity for friendship. He is moderate but
also cold. By monopolizing all honor, he in the long run robs his
ruling elite of any serious responsibilities. His increasing reliance on
eunuchs symbolizes how his monopoly of honor has over the course
of time “effeminated,” to use Machiavelli’s term, his own once-proud
fellow aristocrats. He cannot provide a successor on his own level.
He truly benefits his peoples but is capable of ruthless violence. This
mixture of admiration for Cyrus and reservations about him makes
Xenophon unwilling to depict Cyrus either as an out-and-out tyrant or
as a paragon of virtue. For Machiavelli, as a consequence, Xenophon’s
not inconsiderable value as a source of advice for princes is under-
mined by the ancient philosopher’s ambivalence toward his own model
of princely success. Machiavelli would have us understand the unvar-
nished truth that successful princes act on their untutored impulses
for dominion, glory, and wealth. Xenophon, by contrast, holds up
the rare example of a monarch educated as far as possible like a
gentleman through the most elaborately wrought civic pedagogy – a
monarch who, although not exactly legitimate, especially beyond the
borders of Persia, is not exactly a tyrant either; who, although not
exactly noble, develops his talents and achieves many benefits for his
followers.
Xenophon’s unusual and equivocal position – less republican than
Plato and Aristotle, less “princely” than Machiavelli – explains the
double-edged relationship of his political thought to that of Machi-
avelli. Because Xenophon possesses the venerable authority of a classical
author, it is convenient for Machiavelli to be able to play up Xenophon’s
preference for princely rule and his elaboration of its advantages, and
so draw his readers’ minds away from the strictures placed on political
and military belligerence by Plato and Aristotle. Thus, as I observed at
the beginning of this chapter, Plato and Aristotle are not so much as
mentioned when the context (for example, the criticism of those who
261
tyranny
9 Consider, for example, Castiglione on the influence of the classics and their reputation
during the Renaissance. His pantheon of heroes is similar to that of Machiavelli. This
passage combines a desire for eternal glory through the love of honor from the Symposium
with the superiority of the life of the mind from Cicero’s Dream of Scipio, with the
added insight that the immortality of great writers better enables one to understand,
by analogy, the immortality of fame through noble deeds, hence the need for liberal
education: “What soul is there so abject, timid and humble, that when he reads the deeds
of Caesar, Alexander, Scipio, Hannibal and many others, is not enflamed by an ardent
desire to be like them, and does not make small account of this frail two day’s life, in
order to win the almost eternal life of fame, which in spite of death makes him live in far
262
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
is only concerned with the extent to which the classical authors focus
on this-worldly statecraft. He excludes any consideration of classical
(much less Christian) transcendentalism from his understanding of
statecraft. In contrast with many of his contemporaries who wrote
about classical philosophy as well as statecraft and the way in which
the former must provide a moral compass for the latter, there is virtu-
ally no discussion of this kind in either The Prince or the Discourses.
Machiavelli almost always wears the garb of the historian, and when he
does occasionally allude rather distantly to philosophical debates (as we
consider in Chapter 7), it is never for the sake of a purely theoretical dis-
cussion but always directly connected to a concern with political prac-
tice. At all turns, he embraces the this-worldly “fatherland” (Discourses
2.2) to the exclusion of the otherworldliness of both the classical and
Christian traditions, the “imagined republics,” as he dismissively terms
this joint conglomerate, without naming names, in chapter 15 of The
Prince – a reference, we can be certain, not only to Plato’s Republic but
surely also to St. Augustine’s Civitas Dei. Among the classical sources,
Xenophon comes closest to matching not only Machiavelli’s pragma-
tism, partiality to imperial expansionism, endorsement of economic
prosperity, and high regard for political honor, but also his aversion
for metaphysical transcendence. Not unreasonably, Xenophon’s depic-
tion of Socrates has been characterized as philosophy stripped of the
Ideas.
To look preliminarily into the religious implications of Machiavelli’s
political philosophy that will bulk large in the remaining chapters of
this book, let us recall that chapters 15 to 19 of The Prince are a cri-
tique not only of the classical catalogue of the virtues but also of their
adaptations by Christian theologians and humanists. For instance, the
question as to whether princes should “keep faith” – that is, be hon-
est – can also be read as the extent to which they should “keep the
faith.” Similarly, the discussion of “compassion” refers both to the
classical conception of clementia, a civic virtue famously invoked by
Julius Caesar, and the cardinal Christian virtue of pity that is to some
extent built on its classical antecedent, while ultimately pointing to the
greater glory than before? But he who does not feel the delight of letters, cannot either
know how great is the glory they so long preserve, and measures it by the life of one man
or two, because his memory runs no further.” Quoted in Newell (2001) pp. 140–141.
263
tyranny
very different basis of a compassion for man through one’s pity for
Christ crucified. Indeed, the very term “pity” (pietas) reminds us that
so important was this virtue to Christian revelation that the word for
“piety” in general was appropriated for its specific designation. To pity
man for the sake of God was the sum and total of what it meant to be
pious. The undercurrent of religious motifs in Machiavelli’s discussion
of virtue is also evident in the contrast made in chapter 6 of The Prince
between “armed prophets” such as Cyrus, Moses, Romulus, and The-
seus and rulers who are “unarmed” owing to Christianity and ancient
moral philosophy. The description of pagan rulers as “prophets” would
appear to invest them with an authority at least akin to that of religious
revelation itself. Moreover, the equation of the prince with the prophet
in chapter 6 reminds us that when Machiavelli later contrasts the real
Cyrus on the one hand with Xenophon’s Cyrus and Scipio on the other,
he is still tacitly discussing different kinds of princely “prophets,” with
Scipio’s excessive compassion as a pagan ruler doubling as an excess of
proto-Christian mercy.10
In assessing Machiavelli’s joint critique of pagan and Christian
statecraft, it is well to remember that Christianity’s assimilation of
ancient moral philosophy had never been smooth or complete. Christian
10 On Machiavelli’s blurring of the distinction between prince and prophet, consider the
fine formulation by Ruffo-Fiore (1985) p. 2: “Machiavelli’s new Prince is unquestion-
ably an ideal hero, an exceptional military and political role-model with remarkable
capacities of intelligence, will, and character. He is a hero-leader who has mastered the
techniques of virtu and understands the inevitability of fortuna. Although Machiavelli
utilizes such classical sources as Theseus, Cyrus, and Romulus for the mold of his ideal
leader and seems deliberately to exclude the relevance of traditional Christian virtues to
his character and actions, the Prince does reflect a disciplined selflessness and dedication
in his pursuit of national identity, stability, and glory. The persistent interest in the
prince suggests that something in Machiavelli’s treatment captures the human imagi-
nation and fulfills a universal need. In studying this problem for a number of years, I
have concluded that much of this fascination with the prince derives from Machiavelli’s
allusive, pervading vision of the sacral nature of the national patriarch. As a leader the
new prince embodies the biblical idea of the prophet-king who has received a special
divine call, a covenant from God to guide the destiny of the nation toward an appointed
goal. The force and authenticity of this princely image, at once supremely attractive and
frightening, results from how Machiavelli metaphorically parodies the religious theme
of divine election and applies it in a purely secular context. His intent is to show the
redeeming, communal function of a trustworthy leader who will liberate the people
from captivity, define their national and ethnic identity, and reinstitute political order
in a time of crisis.” This is strong corroboration for the thesis formulated by Voegelin
according to which Joachite millenarianism is immanentized in the secular prince.
264
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
orthodoxy could not abide the more full-blooded evocations of civic and
martial achievement found in the classics, but instead emphasized the
classics’ concern with transcending worldly politics in the direction of
the eternal truth. Thus, Petrarch, for example, as a good Augustinian,
abhorred Cicero’s pragmatic advice on statesmanship while admiring
his devotion to philosophy. Machiavelli’s aim of criticizing Christianity
in tandem with his criticism of the ancient philosophers is clear when
we bear in mind that his critique of Scipio the Elder for his reliance on
Xenophon’s Education of Cyrus glides easily into a critique of Cicero,
whose account of Scipio the Younger in the Dream of Scipio entered the
mirror of princes genre alongside the elder Scipio’s guide. In Cicero’s
depiction, the younger Scipio prefers the life of the mind and the fate
of his eternal soul to the world of political action, although virtuous
action in the civic sphere is the route to those higher kinds of fulfill-
ment. In the Dream of Scipio, it is his adoptive grandfather, the elder
Scipio who was the devotee of the Education of Cyrus, who imparts to
his descendant the eternal truth about the order of the cosmos. Thus,
the younger Scipio’s subordination of political ambition to the life of
the mind, admired by Cicero and enshrined in his dialogue, flows from
an ancestor who was decisively shaped by the writings of the Socratic
Xenophon. In the Discourses, as we will see, Machiavelli witheringly
criticizes Cicero’s crashing failure in real life to bring the ambitious
young Octavian Caesar under his guidance, attempting to practice that
sublimation of ambition by wise counsel idealized in his own portrait
of the younger Scipio and its antecedents including the prescription in
Book 4 of the Laws for the lover of the city to be governed by a wise
counsellor. When we read of Machiavelli’s critique of Scipio the Elder
in The Prince and Discourses, therefore, we are permitted subliminally
to think of the younger Scipio as well (especially given Machiavelli’s
penchant, earlier remarked upon, for treating two identically named
men as one). Both Scipios, elder and younger, compass the deleteri-
ous effects of Greek philosophy, in its unworldliness, on Roman vigor,
including on Cicero himself.
Machiavelli’s critique of Cicero is the reverse of Petrarch’s: whereas
Petrarch criticized Cicero for allowing his philosophical interest in the
eternal truth to be undermined by his preoccupation with political
life, Machiavelli’s implicit critique is that Cicero allows his grasp of
statesmanship to be undermined by his respect for philosophy. Cicero’s
265
tyranny
11 Coby (1999) makes a persuasive case that Machiavelli’s debt to classical Roman thought,
especially that of Livy, has sometimes been overlooked by those eager to enshrine him
as the founder of modernity and modern political science. He argues that Machiavelli is
both returning to ancient Rome and anticipating the Enlightenment, which I certainly
agree with. I would be more inclined, however, to make a sharp distinction between
Machiavelli’s endorsement of Roman practices and the content of Roman history and
his repudiation of classical political philosophy, including its influence on Livy. Whereas,
for instance, Livy is equivocal about whether harshness or gentleness are the best modes
of republican statesmanship, Machiavelli, as I argue in this chapter, although initially
echoing Livy’s balanced assessment, upon consideration is shown to definitely endorse
harshness within republics, reserving gentleness for monarchy, and implying that the
misapplication of gentleness by, for example, Scipio within a republic tends to subvert
its moral vigor.
266
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
267
tyranny
a bad ruler into a good one than is the philosopher’s concern with what
things permanently are. That is, Socrates may be reluctant to admit that
nature is so plastic or given to becoming that a ruler can supersede his
crimes and transform himself into what he was not before. By contrast,
Machiavelli simply merges himself as the author of The Prince with
this advisor. Ending the book with a poetic appeal to Italy’s prospec-
tive liberator, Machiavelli conflates the roles of philosopher, poet, and
advisor. Machiavelli also rejects the idea of nature as regular, orderly,
and placing limitations on human ambition for the “poetic” idea that
corrupt political “bodies” can be re-made into healthy ones by vigorous
princely action.
Xenophon’s reservations about committing philosophy to the reform
of tyranny might be thought to enable him to identify tyranny more
clearly for what it is than can Machiavelli. Still, Machiavelli is able to
adapt Xenophon’s writings to his own purposes by radicalizing their
character in a way that Plato’s and Aristotle’s works do not permit.
Whereas Xenophon divides the spheres of politics and philosophy so
as not to confound their respective excellences, Machiavelli simply lops
away the sphere of philosophy by adapting Xenophon’s political writ-
ings without making any reference to the Socratic ones. He thus takes
advantage of the greater latitude Xenophon offers for the separation of
politics and philosophy to argue that philosophy as traditionally con-
ceived has nothing to do with “effectual” government. Furthermore,
as we begin to explore in the next chapter, Machiavelli’s strongest ally
in this bifurcation between political primordialism and banished tran-
scendentalism is, strangely enough, the author of one of the greatest
“imagined republics” of them all, St. Augustine with his City of God.
Still, in characterizing the originality of Machiavelli’s new science of
politics, it would not go far enough to say that Machiavelli is liberat-
ing from Xenophon’s prudent reservations the capacity for poiesis that
Xenophon himself admits, through his depiction of Simonides, might
transform a tyrant into something he was not before. For, as I have
argued in earlier chapters, the classical Greek notion of “making” is
not tantamount to the Abrahamic notion of creation ex nihilo. As we
observed in Chapter 2, for the pre-Socratics and Sophists, remaking
nature has more the connotation of tapping into its vital rhythms and,
equipped with the insight that there is no distinction between seeming
268
machiavelli, xenophon, and xenophon’s cyrus
269
tyranny
270
VI
271
tyranny
272
glory and reputation
273
tyranny
1 Skinner (1980). Consider also Tarcov (1982, 2000) and Zuckert (2002).
274
glory and reputation
275
tyranny
virtue and fortune have a view of fortune that is also hard to recon-
cile with the creative one. Instead, they counsel a kind of forbearance
against the reverses of fortune by accommodating oneself to the divine
order of the universe, a blend of Christian precepts with the classical
understanding.
Skinner does not wish to drive too large a wedge between Chris-
tianity and humanism and assures the reader that Petrarch and his
successors among the humanists were “unequivocally Christian” – as
well as classical – in their espousal of such traditional virtues as jus-
tice, liberality, faith, and love. He does, however, wish to distinguish
their variant of Christian faith, which he believes made room for the
“creative” view of virtue, from “conventional” or “orthodox” writers
who shared the Augustinian assumption that man should not attempt
to resist the dictates of providence. Unquestionably there were many
variants and shadings in Christian belief and in humanism during this
period. On the particular theme of virtue and fortune, however, I do
not believe that Skinner adduces sufficient evidence for his way of dis-
tinguishing the conventional outlook from the “new attitude” he finds
in Petrarch, Salutati, and their followers.3 If I am correct in my reading
of the classical, Christian, and humanist conceptions of virtue and for-
tune, for the humanists to conceive of virtue as man’s creative power
to “mould his own fate,” they must already have parted ways with any
attachment to the traditional virtues, whether classical or Christian.
For the traditional virtues presuppose man’s subordination to a natural
or divine hierarchy of ends that prescribe his substantive duties and
fulfillment. In this view, the world external to man cannot be seen as
“capricious,” and it is neither possible nor desirable to conceive of man
as being able to stand apart from the world and impose his own “will”
on it. The creative view of virtue cannot, in my view, be added to the
traditional one, which it contradicts at every level. I would argue that
the humanists in general accepted both the traditional account of virtue
and the traditional view of man’s place in the world, suitably adapted
to Christianity. Whereas Skinner tends to range the humanists along-
side the classics in opposition to orthodox, Augustinian Christianity, I
would suggest that the humanists he sees as bearers of the “new atti-
tude” about virtue were in fact much closer to the conventional view of
276
glory and reputation
4 Hulliung trenchantly formulates the distance between Machiavelli and the Stoic and
Christian political morality of his predecessors. He sees the humanists as being “Christian
despite their admiration of pagan antiquity.” Hulliung (1983) x–xi, pp. 216–217.
5 Consider Guthrie (1984) pp. 139–142.
277
tyranny
278
glory and reputation
to their own talent and effort (Cicero [1907] p. 137). The Stoic Balbus
declines to refute Cotta’s lengthy dissection of his philosophy, but sim-
ply observes that the falsity of Stoicism would mean the falsity of all
religion and piety, which “defend Rome better than she is defended by
her ramparts.” Although the Epicurean Velleius is won over by Cotta’s
demolition of both positions, Cicero depicts himself in the dialogue
as deciding that Stoicism possesses “the greater probability” (Cicero
[1907] p. 140).
St. Augustine’s interpretation of this dialogue in The City of God
is of great interest for understanding how the terms of the classical
debate about freedom and necessity were absorbed and altered by
Christianity. If, as Skinner maintains, Augustinian Christianity was the
main opponent of the humanist revival of the classical conception of
virtue and fortune, it should help to clarify the relationships among
all three bodies of belief. Not surprisingly, St. Augustine prefers Stoi-
cism among the ancient schools to the Epicurean principle of pleasure.
The Stoics believed the world to be governed by the rationality of the
supreme being. Man brings himself more closely into accordance with
this divine rationality by living virtuously. In interpreting Cicero’s place
in the debate, St. Augustine reasons as follows: if, as the Stoics correctly
believed, God is “the Cause of all causes,” he must also have foreknowl-
edge of the future. Cicero, however, believed that man cannot be free
if God has this foreknowledge. For if everything we do it predestined,
there is no point in holding people responsible for choosing virtue over
vice. The laws, education, and political morality meant to encourage
this choice would all be in vain. According to Augustine, this is why
Cicero, in his treatise On Divination, denies that there can be knowl-
edge of the future. For St. Augustine, this is tantamount to atheism:
“Thus, to make men free, he made them give up God.” Why, then, does
Cicero incline toward the Stoic view in On the Nature of the Gods? For
Augustine, this can only be explained as Cicero’s fear of being seen too
openly to embrace the impious view he actually holds (rather as Cotta
says of the Epicureans in the dialogue). Instead, St. Augustine argues,
Cicero places his real views in the mouth of Cotta (Augustine [1958]
pp. 102–105).
Augustine’s interpretation is arresting, but it assumes that Cicero
shared Augustine’s view that the “order of causes” necessarily implies
the foreknowledge of an interventionary supreme deity. Cicero did not
279
tyranny
280
glory and reputation
281
tyranny
6 Compare St. Thomas, who represents Aristotelian causality not in its original sense
as perspectives on a thing but as successive stages of the divine artisan’s operations
on material reality. Whereas Aristotle treats natural causality as analogous to art – in
other words, like art in some respects, unlike it in others – Thomas is confident in his
commentary on Aristotle’s Physics that “nature is nothing but a certain kind of art, that
is, the divine art, impressed upon things, by which these things are moved to a determinate
end.” Thomas (1963) p. 124; my emphasis.
282
glory and reputation
eternal order of rational causality, but it does not fully determine every
human thought and action. The play of nature’s self-movement – and,
therefore, of accident and contingency – leaves a wide latitude for sen-
sible improvisation, as Aristotle had already argued with respect to
prudence. There may be gods which provide an objective grounding for
virtue, but this does not mean they constantly and reliably intervene in
human affairs on behalf of the good, at least not without a matching
effort by man (as Plato’s Timaeus puts it, the god of the cosmos is
“apathetic,” without impulse or feeling, while according to the Repub-
lic, the gods do not change shape or assume human form; Timaeus
28–34; Republic 379a–381e). In sum, the classical thinkers try to find a
place for fortune (albeit a severely circumscribed one) within the order
of causes. For St. Augustine, on the other hand, fortune simply vanishes
into the will of the Creator, or, expressed passively as His dispensation,
into Providence. (As we consider at greater length subsequently, the
fundamental theological conundrum as to whether God ought primar-
ily to be understood as “making” or as “revealing” will prove central
to Machiavelli’s revaluation of virtue and fortune.)
However, if the classical understanding of the relation between virtue
and fortune is different from the Christian one, still less does it resemble
the idea of virtue described by Skinner as man’s creative will exerting
itself over a capricious fortune so as to shape it to human desires, a
concept that, I am arguing, is distinctively modern and inaugurated by
Machiavelli. For the Greek and Roman thinkers, virtue is a conditioning
of the soul that brings one into closer proximity to eternal being. Cicero
never questions that the objects of the virtues are prescribed for man by a
rationally ordered cosmos; he works within this assumption even while
resisting its more deterministic interpretation. Accordingly, the classical
notion of virtue has no connotation of mastering fortune in the external
world. Rather, by cultivating the virtues, one lessens one’s desires, and
therefore one’s dependence on external goods. Because to be a slave of
external goods is to be a slave of what is perishable, accidental, or less
real, in this sense virtue can make one less vulnerable to the reverses
of fortune. But this way of coping with unpredictable or unmerited
suffering is more passive than masterful, grounded in our reconciliation
to our natural place within the Great Chain of Being. If the reverses
occur anyway, so the reasoning went, one can draw on the steadfastness,
dignity, and self-control achieved through the cultivation of virtue to
283
tyranny
284
glory and reputation
the world surrounding man may be entirely too rational, orderly, and
good.
285
tyranny
8 Skinner (1980) pp. 87, 94, 98. Baron takes a different view. Although Petrarch admired
Cicero as a philosopher, Baron argues, “Cicero’s civic spirit was to him nothing but
an offense against all the traditions of the Middle Ages.” Baron (1938) pp. 72–97. As
described by Hulliung, Machiavelli’s opinion of Cicero is the precise opposite of this.
Hulliung (1983) p. 132.
9 Skinner (1980) p. 97.
286
glory and reputation
287
tyranny
288
glory and reputation
between the human and the divine where passion is sublimated by rea-
son through the eros for honor, is utterly jettisoned, exposed as cheap
tinsel, and stripped of its allure as it is “dissolved by unstable time.”
Although they can draw on more Greek and Roman texts for illustra-
tions and arguments, the quattrocento humanists do not appear to be
any closer than Petrarch to advancing the conception of virtue described
by Skinner as man’s power to reshape the world. In Manetti, Albertus,
and Pico della Mirandola – three figures whom Skinner links with the
Petrarchan view of virtue – we encounter the same mixture of Christian
theology with classical moral philosophy and metaphysics. For exam-
ple, Manetti’s On the Dignity and Excellence of Man does not suggest,
as Skinner argues, a commendation of man’s creative powers to grap-
ple with the world and subdue it to his needs.12 Instead, according to
Manetti, the dignity and happiness proper to men are conferred on those
who fully understand that the soul is immortal and of divine origin. By
pursuing virtue, Manetti argues, we can approximate that transmun-
dane purity more closely in our earthly lives. Kings and princes, far
from being urged to use their talents for worldly success, prestige, and
stability, are adjured to submit themselves to the divine order: “Your
duties, as regards understanding and acting, you have in common with
omnipotent God; consequently, by acquiring and cultivating virtue, you
may attain the beatitude of a tranquil immortality” (Manetti [1967]
pp. 83–84, 100).
Similarly, Pico della Mirandola’s Oration on the Dignity of Man
cannot really be said, as Skinner would have it, to posses as “a central
theme . . . the individual’s free and creative powers.”13 The teleology
that Pico describes is incompatible with the primacy and freedom of the
individual. According to it, God endows human beings with a hierarchy
of “potentialities.” At the bottom are those who live for their appetites
and so resemble “plants” and “brutes.” At the top is the philosopher – a
this respect particularly under the spell of his great model Augustine.” Nachod (1948)
p. 241. See also Kristeller, who points out that Augustinian Christianity was very much
a part of Petrarch’s rediscovery of classical literature – not, as Skinner implies, a foil
for it. Kristeller (1969) pp. 361–363. On the general importance for the humanists of
neo-Platonism as it was filtered through Augustinian theology, see Cassirer, Kristeller,
and Randall (1948) pp. 6–7.
12 Skinner (1980) p. 97.
13 Skinner (1980) p. 97.
289
tyranny
14 Pocock regards Pico’s Oration as an example of neo-Platonism that forsook the virtu
needed for civic community in favor of “an illumined communion with the cosmos.”
Pico’s failure to find a bridge between philosophy and the requirements of political life
helps to explain, in Pocock’s view, his attraction to the “holy community” preached by
Savanarola. Pocock (1975) pp. 98–99.
15 Skinner (1980) p. 96.
290
glory and reputation
safety the most virtuous people of all. These are the “just, wise (and)
honest,” who “never cease thinking worthy thoughts.” They “do good
to others by offering a helping hand to those who are in difficulty.”
Moreover, “(n)one among men who are struggling in the river is more
welcome by the immortal gods than those who, in the little boats, look
to faith, to simplicity and to virtue” (Alberti [1967] p. 36). There is no
elevation here of Skinner’s interpretation of virtue as the Promethean
capacity of man to “control his own destiny.” Although the energetic
and self-reliant people are given their fair due of commendation, they
are clearly depicted as dependent on, and morally inferior to, those sur-
passingly good people in their modest little boats. On no level of the
allegory does Albertus suggest that the mighty power of the river could
be tamed and rechanneled to serve man’s needs, as in chapter 25 of
The Prince. Everyone must submit to its current, perhaps as to Provi-
dence, but the virtuous are able to make safe boats for themselves to
avoid its dangers as they are borne along.
Turning to the other humanists cited by Skinner, we find further
variations on the conception of virtue as a conditioning of the soul that
brings one into closer proximity to eternal truth and being. Castiglione
maintains that virtue can overcome fortune – but by virtue he means the
moderation of the Golden Mean and insists that power should never
be pursued for its own sake or for selfish and merely practical ends
(Castiglione [1959] pp. 14–15, 323–324).16 Valla illustrates especially
clearly how close the humanists often were to orthodox Christian for-
mulations of virtue and fortune when he observes that Fortune or “the
divine will . . . condemns some and saves others” without our knowing
why (Valla [1967] pp. 63–64). In contrast to Skinner’s view of how the
humanists understood virtue, Valla argues that the appropriate response
to this dilemma is not to rebel and assert our wills against fortune but
to submit even more thoroughly to its dictates. We should not “request
a guarantee” from Christ but hold onto “faith, hope and love.” Here,
the classical notion of virtue as a source of dignity and strength of soul
amidst fortune’s reverses is radicalized into the Christian’s total faith
in providence and disavowal of any need to account for God’s ways.
Aristotle’s ambition for comprehensive knowledge of the order of the
universe is accordingly dismissed as “proud and foolish,” echoing an
291
tyranny
17 Valla was highly skeptical of prospects for the synthesis of classical learning with Chris-
tian revelation. See Trinkaus (1948) p. 149.
292
glory and reputation
18 “The deeds of famous men fire the minds of noble youths, but the opinions with which
they become imbued is a matter of greater importance. . . . A prince who is about to
293
tyranny
assume control of the state must be advised at once that the main hope of a state lies
in the proper education of its youth. This Xenophon wisely taught in his Cyropaedia.
Pliable youth is amenable to any system of training.” Erasmus, The Education of a
Christian Prince, quoted in Newell (2001) pp. 212–214.
19 By contrast, Felix Gilbert observes: “Machiavelli did not merely refute the idealist
enterprise in politics in general but . . . wrote with the conscious aim of discrediting the
idealized conception of the prince as contained in the (humanists’) catalogue of the
virtues” (1939) pp. 478–480. In Hulliung’s view, Machiavelli inhabits the form of
the humanistic mirror of princes genre the more effectively to undermine its Christian
and Stoic substance (1983) pp. 11–19, 24–25, 245.
294
glory and reputation
not supply man with his rationality and end. Instead, princely men
impose “new modes and orders” on the world. In this way, the terms of
the debate about the relation of virtue to fortune undergo a profound
ontological alteration. The classical view had been that the cultivation
of virtue, by aiming at the rational and eternal, enabled man to over-
come the power of chance. Pedagogically, psychologically, and morally
this meant that overcoming tyrannical desires made a human being less
dependent on perishable and external things. Machiavelli, however,
wishes to expose the belief in an ordered universe, with its reflections
in the utopian “republics” of Greek and Roman thought, along with
Augustine’s Republic of God, as a delusion. After reducing these (what
he takes to be) imaginary standards to random chance, he opposes to
it a conception of virtue as anthropocentric will that has no transcen-
dental relation to the nonhuman world. Virtue can overcome fortune
not by transcending chance through transcending desire, a prescription
common to classics, Christians, and humanists alike. On the contrary,
by yielding to our desires for glory, wealth, and power, as princes or as
citizens of vigorous expansionist republics, we orient ourselves by the
vital disorder that is at the heart of all existence.
I have been arguing in this book that Machiavelli’s originality lies
in this paradoxical reliance on disorder. He is not merely arguing that
fortune is unreliable, but that fortune’s hindrances are in a strange way
actually to be welcomed and are constitutive of sound psychology and
statecraft. Machiavelli’s use, for example, of the Polybian cycle of the
rise and decline of states in the Discourses, which we consider at length
in the next chapter, omits Polybius’s concern with transcending this
temporal cycle in the direction of the eternal.20 As Machiavelli puts
it, “chance” and “the aid of events” can “perfect” republics without
any assistance from such transcendental sources. Because there is no
nunc stans or eternality of true being – because “everything is in per-
petual movement” – “disunity” is a more reliable source of a republic’s
power and freedom than a unity that is doomed by the flow of events.21
295
tyranny
296
glory and reputation
principalities that have never been seen or known to exist in truth; for it is
so far from how one lives to how one should live that he who lets go what
is done for what should be done learns his ruin rather than his preservation.
(The Prince chapter 15)
I broadly agree with these interpretations, and my main purpose in
this book has been to use my readings of Plato, Aristotle, and Xenophon
as foils for illuminating some of the original tenets of Machiavelli’s state-
craft. However, I am also arguing that more attention should be paid
to Machiavelli’s relationship to Christianity – not simply as an obsta-
cle to combat but as an opponent whose categories influence Machi-
avelli’s thinking even as he attempts to repudiate them. I am trying to
show that Machiavelli owes a kind of negative debt to Christianity that
helps us to understand why his thought cannot be viewed simply as
a return to the greater latitude for worldly statesmanship afforded by
pagan philosophy in comparison with Christianity. There are two main
facets to this negative debt. I will sketch them schematically, and then
show how they come together in the discussion of the prince’s relation-
ship to Fortuna, famously (and notoriously) personified in chapter 25
of The Prince. In the next and final chapter, I try to show, through a
reading of the discussion of the origins of republics in the Discourses,
how Machiavelli’s departure from the classical approach to the theme
of the founding weaves together with his negative debt to certain tenets
of Christianity to establish an entirely novel synthesis and a dynamic
new prescription for political freedom.
The first element in Machiavelli’s debt to Christianity concerns the
altered meaning of causality effected by Christian theology. For Plato,
causality is chiefly a matter of solicitation, not effectuation. In Aris-
totelian terms, final cause takes ontological priority over efficient cause.
Phenomena are summoned toward their respective completions by the
Good. The Good causes the fullness and fruition of their growth toward
the stable form that perfects each class of beings. The Image of the Sun
in Book 6 of the Republic best conveys this solicitative causality (506–
509). As the Sun summons each natural being toward its growth, this
solicitation sets in motion its natural power and energy for develop-
ment. In other words, the form toward which each being naturally
tends entails effectuation and structure. The same is true of the soul.
For Plato the soul is naturally drawn toward the repose and stability
offered by the prospect of union with the Good. Diotima’s Ladder in the
297
tyranny
298
glory and reputation
which things are shaped, and whose creations are not constrained by a
preexisting – or, depending on the theology, even a posterior – pattern
of natural order and regularity. This difference is underscored by the
fact that, because every noun in Attic Greek has an article, one can-
not unambiguously express the concept of God – it is always the god
(ho theos), which indicates the supervening whole within which we find
it, including the possible existence of gods other than this one. The
Platonic god of the Timaeus creates things in accordance with already
established patterns of rationality and coherence. The demiurge is an
agent of a cosmic rationality already present for him to actualize. There
is a very great difficulty in reconciling this subordination of effectua-
tion to an eternally preexistent cosmology with the God of revealed
religion. Socrates depicts the gods as disembodied paradigms of objec-
tive clarity that do not intervene in human affairs, do not perform
miracles or answer prayers, but uphold the eidetic stability of the world
and thereby support human efforts to inculcate that repose within the
soul through the cultivation of the virtues, even and including the best
regime itself, a “pattern in the sky” that can be housed in an indi-
vidual’s soul as a moral compass for the inferior regime in which he
lives. As Book 2 of the Republic puts it, the gods do not change their
respective eide like wizards; they have no personal qualities whatsoever
(380d).
By contrast, the Christian God as depicted in Thomistic, and even
more clearly in Augustinian theology, conflates final cause with the
efficient cause of an interventionary deity whose will creates and sus-
tains all things. As St. Augustine puts it in criticizing Cicero and other
pagan philosophers for identifying the highest being with an imper-
sonal, objective rationality, “the only efficient causes of all things are
voluntary causes, that is to say, causes of the same nature as the spirit
or breath of life. . . . The Spirit of Life, which gives life to all and is the
Creator of all matter and of every created spirit is God, a Spirit indeed,
but uncreated.” The difficulty of reconciling the Platonic, or more gen-
erally the classical account of causality with the Christian doctrine of
creation is clear, to take but one example, from the objections made
to Thomism by Christian critics who believed that even it too greatly
constrained the creative power of God with the causal categories of
pagan metaphysics, despite the fact that Thomas is quite clear that the
299
tyranny
latter are merely the means through which God effects his creative will
and are entirely subsequent to God’s creation of the world. Even mat-
ter, according to Thomas, not only the form imposed on it, must be
seen as created out of nothing by God, lest even in its inert preexisting
condition it somehow latently conditioned or shaped what God could
fashion from it. Thomas argued that although God was free to create
the world in whatever way he saw fit, once he had established its ratio-
nal plan (ratio), phenomena would occur according to recurrent natural
causes unless God intervened miraculously to alter his own laws. Short
of these miraculous incursions, as a favor to us and our human need for
regularity, He would leave the natural laws by which he had originally
ordered the universe to operate on their own.
For more conservative theologians, however, during the period
of debate over Thomism before his eventual canonization, even this
attempt to subordinate pagan metaphysics to divine creation restricted
God too much by implying that creation would ordinarily adhere to a
settled natural pattern, mediating between God’s will and our experi-
ence of phenomena. In this more fundamentalist, resolutely antipagan
theology – which often viewed itself as cleaving to St. Augustine and
which would reemerge with Luther – God constantly, endlessly, and
directly supervises every event in the universe at every moment in time,
sustaining it all through his active will. Otherwise, it would fall into
the disarray and decay that is the essence of all natural matter. Accord-
ing to the Augustinian formulation, as the efficient cause of the entire
universe including human voluntarism, God also continuously wills the
wills of all humans. The pursuit of no mere natural object of aspiration,
however noble or just it may appear, can ever enable us to live as we
should – indeed, this will only drag us down. God so conceived is the
great artificer who stands beyond all natural limitations and determina-
tions, because he is their originator. He does not create in accordance
with form; he creates form and imposes it on nature. Nature by itself
is mere matter in motion, as Hobbes would later put it. Left to itself,
it would fall into disarray. Its only potential for order and structure
comes from the forms God continuously imposes on it. In this reading,
modern physics, far from being a repudiation of Christian cosmology,
flows directly from it, shorn of God’s sustaining will, now to be replaced
by Machiavelli’s prince who creates “new modes and orders,” Bacon’s
scientist who converts nature into power “for the relief of man’s estate,”
300
glory and reputation
301
tyranny
24 The issue of creation out of nothing is at the heart of the contrast between reason
and revelation. As Strauss argues in the essay Progress or Return?, classical philosophy
and revelation can travel a certain distance along the same road together, inasmuch as
both recognize the centrality of justice to human existence. At a certain point, however,
they reach a fork in that road, and it is over the ultimate status of reality – for revelation,
the creation of the world out of nothing; for classical reason, the eternity of the universe.
These two cannot be reconciled. Strauss (1989). See also Newell (2010).
The Timaeus, used in medieval Christendom to show how Platonic philosophy
anticipated Christian revelation, is one of the closer points of contact between the
Abrahamic Creator God and Platonic cosmology. Yet the teaching of the Timaeus about
the demiurge is not ultimately compatible with the Creator ex nihilo of Christianity.
The demiurge fashions the world in accordance with a preexistent cosmic Good and
Mind that in effect reduces divine agency to a subordinate partner in bringing things
into being according to rational criteria that exist from all eternity – another version of
the eternity of the universe, the principle that according to Strauss decisively separates
reason and revelation. Timaeus says that everything depends on our choosing between
two alternatives – 1) that the whole sprung into being spontaneously from nothing or
2) that it comes into being regulated by this preexisting orderliness (Timaeus 1235b–
1236a). It is number two that is being urged on us. For classical philosophy as a whole,
it is impossible to conceive of the Creator God or revelation without recasting it as
chance or fortune (tuche). Revelation amounts to a cause without an antecedent cause
(or as Augustine puts it, a Creator who is not created), which, as Aristotle puts it, is
unintelligible, literally “without logos,” because it would see the world as issuing out
of sheer happenstance (Physics 196a25–196b).
In the history of Christian theology, the debate over creation took the form early
on of two alternatives: God created the world out of nothing or He created it from
preexisting matter, a view of God as an “arranger” more easily in harmony with pagan
natural philosophy as exemplified by the passage from Plato cited in chapter 6 (Republic
596d). Borrowing from Platonism, Origen argued that matter was preexistent with
302
glory and reputation
God as he created the world. However, Ireneus, wishing to expel Greek philosophy
altogether, argued that there was no preexistent matter. To this, Tertullian added the
argument that God also created the matter out of nothing from which the rest of the
world was then created. Thomas also held that God created matter out of nothing before
imposing form on it. As Colin Gunton puts it, “God is not to be likened to . . . a potter
who makes a pot from the clay which is to hand; he is, rather, like one who makes both
the clay and the pot.” Gunton (2001) p. 17. See also Copan (1996) and the exhaustive
discussion in Pangle (2003).
Thomas Aquinas addresses the issue in the Summa Theologica, in the discussion of
eternal and natural law. He asks: Is God’s creation of the world consistent with the
existence of a preexistent ratio, that is to say, a preexistent form, mind, or good (ST I. Q
44, 93)? The answer for Christians must clearly be no, for the reasons sketched earlier.
Nothing restrains, guides or limits God’s power to create out of nothing. That is why it is
a mysterium – it can only be expressed as paradoxes. Thomas’s solution to reconciling
Aristotelianism with Christian theology goes no further than this: it is a gift of God
that the world God creates out of nothing operates, after He creates it, according to
Aristotelian natural law. Not because it must do so. God could make it operate any way
He wants, could change it any or every nanosecond. The reason He makes it operate this
way is out of compassion for us, so that we will have reliable benchmarks and regularity
in making sense of the world. In sum, the Aristotelian natural law is operative only after
the creation, and only because God makes it so. See also Thomas, The Principles of
Natural Science Book 2, lecture 14, no. 268.
It should be stressed that even that compromise, which so clearly subordinated
Aristotelian natural reason to Christian revelation, was not enough for Thomas’s critics
like the Bishop of Paris, Etienne Tempier, who suspected that Thomas was trying
to sneak too much pagan philosophy into the faith and that even this endorsement
of Aristotelian natural law as operative only after the creation still placed too many
restrictions on God’s constant, unpredictable power for miraculous interventions and
power to sustain every single thing in the universe for every second of its existence by
the sheer force of His will, unconditioned and unmediated by any natural causality.
Etienne Tempier, Condemnation of 219 Propositions. In Lerner and Mahdi (1963)
pp. 337–354.
To be clear, I am arguing that, in his secularization of creation ex nihilo, Machiavelli
does not argue that, in mastering Fortuna, the prince can actually create matter out
of nothing. Rather, he can “introduce” whatever “form” he chooses into preexistent
matter. In this respect, he is somewhat closer to the neo-Platonic creationism of early
Church fathers such as Origen, which held that matter preexisted with God, than to
what emerged as the mainstream view of Irenaeus, Tertullian, and Thomas, according to
which God created both matter and form out of nothing. This is borne out, as I discuss
in Chapter 7, by Machiavelli’s ruminations on the insuperable limitations placed on
man’s will by the underlying generational substratum of nature (reflections adapted in
part from Lucretius’s materialism).
303
tyranny
names of antiquity to a clearer insight into the methods they must have
employed in creating entirely new “modes and orders.” At the end of
chapter 6, having introduced us to his pantheon of outstandingly virtu-
ous princes (Moses, Cyrus, Romulus, and Theseus), Machiavelli briefly
mentions Hiero of Syracuse as a “lesser example” than the greatest
princes but still one that “will have some proportion with the others”
and can “suffice for all other similar cases.” In other words, Hiero of
Syracuse did not attain the level of great civilizational founders like
Moses or Cyrus, but his methods illustrate on a lower level what those
greater men might also have done. For the present in chapter 6, we
are merely told that Hiero eliminated the old military and established a
new one. Shortly thereafter, in chapter 8, we are given the example of
another ancient tyrant, Agathocles of Syracuse, through which Machi-
avelli prepares us preliminarily and by stages for the new understanding
of virtue, in which crimes can be virtuous. Agathocles summoned the
Senate and the great men and had them slaughtered by the soldiers,
thereby becoming tyrant (not, as Machiavelli says, “king”). He then
takes us through three stages of reflection: 1) Because this slaughter
removed all opposition and dependence on others at one blow, Agatho-
cles owed little or nothing to fortune and is therefore virtuous according
to the new definition of virtu in chapter 6. But: 2) Murder, betrayal, and
fraud cannot be spoken well of or called virtue. However: 3) Cruelty
can be “well or badly used.” Well-used cruelty (“if,” he writes, it is per-
missible to speak well of evil, implying now that it may not necessarily
not be) is “done at a stroke, out of the necessity to secure oneself and
is not persisted in but turned to as much utility for the subjects as one
can. Badly used cruelty, by contrast, grows with time.” Therefore: 4)
Because Agathocles used cruelty well, the final judgment is that such
rulers can “remedy . . . their state with God and man.” In chapter 16,
having softened the reader up for his new concept of virtue by his intro-
duction in chapter 8 of the distinction between well-used and badly used
cruelty, Machiavelli is now more explicit than he had been at the end
of chapter 6 that Hiero did not merely eliminate the old army but had
it “cut to pieces.” The lesson of chapter 16 is that one should not rely
on mercenary troops, as do so many Italian states, but on one’s own
arms. He then quite openly places the murderous Hiero on a level with
David, God’s anointed, and arguably a prince of “outstanding” virtue,
using David’s refusal of King Saul’s gift of arms in fighting Goliath as
304
glory and reputation
a metaphor for relying on your own arms rather than those of another
man (as Cesare Borgia relied on his father the pope). Machiavelli also
endows David with a knife, not found in the biblical account, presum-
ably because a sling is too distant from action at close quarters and
therefore too reliant on Fortune (and God). Machiavelli can be very
Machiavellian, old Nick himself!
To resume our main theme: the prospect of this seemingly super-
human power over nature, once the exclusive preserve of God, is now
dangled by Machiavelli in front of secular rulers, a Nietzschean and mil-
lenarian dimension to his thinking that will require a new physics and
a new kind of training. It may perhaps even imply historical progress as
the retarding influences of the old morality are gradually drained away
through enlightenment and newer generations of potential princes are
ever more directly introduced to the new science of politics without a
Christian or classical competitor. We sift some of these lineages issuing
from Machiavelli in the Conclusion. In Machiavelli’s view, the founder
of new modes and orders need not possess a naturally moderate charac-
ter nor the good fortune to have associated with a wise legislator in order
to successfully establish his world. Plato’s equivocations and circum-
spection about employing tyranny to found a just regime, as well as the
elaborate pedagogy required to turn the soul away from its tyrannical
longings, can be swept away. Because Machiavelli reduces the “virtue”
of the prince to what is already the prince’s own unprompted and spon-
taneous urgings for power and glory at the expense of his competitors,
there is no need for a “pattern in the sky” to convert the potential tyrant
into a benevolent statesman or citizen friendly to philosophy.
To be sure, as we see in this chapter and the next, the new prince can-
not act spontaneously on his spontaneous longings. He needs training
and direction. That training is not a kind of paideia, however, through
which those spontaneous longings are sublimated and directed toward
the Good. Instead, the prince needs a method for acting on his impulses
that will bring about their own selfish agenda. Method differs from
character formation, the essential meaning of paideia. That is, while
Plato dwells on rehabilitating the passions by directing them toward
their own highest ends, achieving both the governance of reason and
emotional satisfaction for the soul, for Machiavelli, precisely because
the passions contain no such potentiality for transcendence, they can
only be manipulated externally by the prince’s will within himself – the
305
tyranny
306
glory and reputation
will to will.”25 Let the reader note that I say “anticipate.” I am argu-
ing that something akin to Nietzsche’s will to power, something akin to
what Heidegger means by global technology, are possibilities that dwell
within Machiavelli’s new thinking as harbingers of what Horkheimer
terms the “dark” side of modernity. Later on, however, I will be careful
to argue that Machiavelli does recognize limits on man’s power over
nature and that certain facets of his thinking are also antecedents of the
more benign liberalism of Spinoza and Locke. Indeed, how and whether
these dangerous and benign strains can be reconciled in Machiavelli’s
own thought is an excellent way of beginning to pose that question
about modernity as a whole.
As Machiavelli writes in chapter 15 of The Prince, he is not concerned
with imagined republics where men live as they ought, but the “effectual
truth” truth of how they do live and are to be governed. The act of the
founding becomes the cause of all stability; the ambition of the prince
becomes the cause of a successful founding. By collapsing the ends of
statesmanship into the genesis of power, Machiavelli is able to overturn
the Platonic formulation of the relationship of power to wisdom, so
that the “wise counsel” of the prince must now originate in his own
“prudence,” not in someone else’s. Machiavelli is as much aware as
Plato that all political constitutions decline with time, even the best
ones, just as he recognizes that some aspiring tyrants will turn out to be
brutal, rapacious thugs and nothing greater. His stress on the prince’s
need for disciplined method and self-control concedes precisely this
observable fact. However, because Machiavelli 1) agrees with a certain
strain of Christianity that nature strictly speaking has no independent
inner capacity for order and regularity and 2) rejects the limitations
placed on human ambition by both the classics and Christianity, he
is able to arrive at the prospect that a prince can, godlike, re-create
corrupt political “bodies” and “humors” so that they become healthy
ones through vigorous acts of reconstruction. Indeed, whereas for Plato
the decline of good constitutions into corrupt ones in Book 8 of the
Republic is a lamentable but unavoidable necessity of time’s passing –
of the fact that physis grows toward the permanence of Being but never
permanently attains it, falling back into becoming and decay (546) – for
307
tyranny
And truly, if a prince be anxious for glory and the good opinion of the world,
he should rather wish to possess a corrupt city, not to ruin it wholly like
Caesar, but to reorganise it like Romulus. For certainly the heavens cannot
afford a man a greater opportunity for glory, nor could he desire a better
one. . . . (W)here corruption has penetrated the people, the best laws are of
no avail, unless they are administered by a man of such supreme power that
he may cause the laws to be observed until the mass has been restored to a
healthy condition. (Discourses 1.10.6)
308
glory and reputation
27 See his discussion of Socrates and Plato in Augustine (1958) pp. 146–150 Many his-
torians have argued that as Greco-Roman antiquity unfolded, the transcendentalist
dimension of neo-Platonic philosophy and the longing for a single, spiritually pure god
in place of the frivolous anthropomorphic gods of the Olympian pantheon intensified,
preparing a way for Christian monotheism. Marcus Aurelius’s Meditations posits a
division between the fallen world of bodily necessity and an inward realm of pure soul
that alone is truly free that is almost Manichean or proto-Augustinian in its intensity.
Indeed, if we were unaware of his identity, we could almost be reading Augustine or
Meister Eckhart: “Of human life the time is a point, and the substance is in a flux and
the perception dull, and the composition of the whole body subject to putrefaction, and
the soul a whirl, and fortune hard to divine, and fame a thing devoid of judgement.
And, to say all in a word, everything which belongs to the body is a stream, and what
belongs to the soul is a dream and vapor, and life is a warfare and a stranger’s sojourn,
and after-fame is oblivion. What then is that which is able to conduct a man? One thing
and only one” (quoted in Newell [2001] p. 166). For Marcus, it is philosophy, but it
could as likely be faith. For the Stoic, all a man can do is bear up with integrity in the
whirlwind of flux, but for the Christian, repose awaits in the world to come, although
worldly fame is oblivion just as it is for Marcus.
In the City of God, Augustine poses a contrast between two irreconcilable ways of
life, the city of the flesh and the city of the spirit. A life devoted to worldly ambition
is vain, exploitive, arrogant, and restless. A life devoted to God is moderate, modest,
peaceable, and allows a man to be at peace with himself: “Let us imagine two indi-
viduals. . . . Of these two men, let us suppose that one is poor, or better, in moderate
circumstances; the other extremely wealthy. But our wealthy man is haunted by fear,
heavy with cares, feverish with greed, never secure, always restless, breathless from end-
less quarrels with his enemies. By these miseries, he adds to possessions beyond measure,
309
tyranny
the Idea of the Good and the realm of mere becoming, and his argu-
ments for the superiority of philosophy and the purity of the soul over
the satisfactions of ordinary politics, are indeed at times akin, espe-
cially in proto-Stoic dialogues such as the Gorgias, to the dualism of
Augustine, especially when contrasted with Aristotle’s attempt to locate
the prospects for virtue more squarely within ordinary politics (a prefer-
ence for the middle realm of what is “first for us” that is understandably
more congenial to Thomism, which, broadly speaking, tries to modify
the dualism of Augustine in a manner analogous to Aristotle’s mod-
ification of the “divine madness” of Plato). Nevertheless, this broad
similarity between Augustine and certain aspects of Plato is trumped
by a more essential difference. For Plato, however wide may be the gap
between conventional political honor and philosophical transcendence,
that highest way of life can only be ascended to by way of the virtues of
the best regime, the regime that is best not only according to nature but
according to logos, guided by the soul’s erotic ascent through political
nobility toward the Idea of the Good as the perfection of nature. At
bottom, the metaxy of Diotima’s Ladder is more representative of Pla-
tonic philosophy than its occasional excursions into dualism. Augustine
cannot follow Plato along this road, for the divine logos of Christian
revelation altogether surpasses nature, even entails its obliteration or
crucifixion.
For Augustine, the virtue that comes from obedience to God cannot
be understood in any sense as an erotic pleasure, however sublime. As
Augustine presents it, politics at best has a police function. It can dis-
courage the grosser manifestations of sinfulness for the sake of public
order. A Christian government’s first duty is to protect the Church as an
outpost of the City of God within the fallen purview of the City of Man.
but he also piles up for himself a mountain of distressing worries. The man of modest
means is content with a small compact patrimony. He is loved by his own, enjoys the
sweetness of peace in his relations with kindred, neighbour and friends, is religious
and pious, of kindly disposition . . . chaste in morals and at peace with his conscience. I
wonder if there is anyone so senseless as to hesitate over which of the two to prefer.”
In general terms, this theme is a familiar one from Plato, in, say, Socrates’ contrast
between the philosopher’s and the tyrant’s ways of life in Book 9 of the Republic, or his
claim that Callicles is a “double man” because he cannot reconcile natural happiness
with a lust for political power. Although there are reaches of Plato in which the division
between the body and soul is pushed to a proto-Stoic extreme, the crucial difference is
that, for Plato, the happiness of the soul is available within the natural world of the here
and now and most definitely by way of worldly civic virtue.
310
glory and reputation
On its own, considered apart from the useful work it can do to pre-
pare Christians for their salvation by protecting Christian institutions,
politics can only aim at domination. For even the justice that regulates
mundane political affairs does not originate within the natural realm
and the limits of mortal reasoning. It is rather a gift of God conferred
through the natural law whose content is specified by the Decalogue and
the superordinate revelation of the New Testament. On its own, secular
authority cannot achieve justice even of the secular variety, and “in the
absence of justice,” Augustine asks, “what is sovereignty but organized
brigandage?” ([1958] p. 88). The classics would have made a distinc-
tion between regimes organized according to a virtuous principle such
as aristocracy and those organized around the maximization of self-
interest, which could take the form of venal “garden variety” tyrannies
or collectively selfish and defective regimes like oligarchy, or imperial-
istic “tyrant” cities such as Athens as it was described in Thucydides.
Yet Augustine, much like Machiavelli was to do later (as we consider
in detail in the next chapter), collapses the distinction between good
and bad regimes and reduces them all to being defective. Whereas
Augustine does this to purify virtue by removing it from the natural
realm, Machiavelli does it to purify politics by removing it from the
transcendental realm. Augustine goes on, with what sounds like a slap
at Romulus’s founding of Rome:
For what are bands of brigands but petty kingdoms? They are also groups
of men, under the rule of a leader, bound together by a common agreement,
dividing their booty according to a single principle. If this band of criminals,
recruiting more criminals, acquires enough power to occupy regions, to cap-
ture cities, and to subdue whole populations, then it can with fuller right
assume the title of kingdom, which in the public estimation is conferred upon
it, not by the renunciation of greed, but by the increase of impunity. ([1958]
p. 88)
According to St. Augustine, this is what the Roman Empire over the
course of time achieved. However:
311
tyranny
312
glory and reputation
communities that believe they can achieve virtue within the limits of
nature. By arguing that dominion is the sole aim of a politics guided by
nature, Augustine in effect restores the Sophists’ low view of the city
for the sake of elevating revelation above its taint. For classical polit-
ical philosophy, the question of which constitution one lives under is
crucial for a happy life because the prospects for actualizing the soul’s
potentiality for excellence is inextricably linked to the laws and the civic
morality they enhance: it very much matters, for example, whether it
is an aristocracy or an oligarchy. For Augustine, however, the whole
traditional subject matter of the best regime, and how actual consti-
tutions measure up to it, although not unimportant as a preliminary
guidepost to virtuous living, pales into insignificance when we consider
the vanity and frailty of all merely human prudence. Thus, although St.
Augustine defends Christianity to its remaining pagan critics partly on
the grounds that the moral rigor enjoined on Christians by their faith
also makes them decent citizens of the City of Man, when he addresses
the expectations one may properly form of political life in its own right,
his tone is world-weary and despairing:
When it is considered how short is the span of human life, does it really matter
to a man whose days are numbered what government he must obey, so long
as he is not compelled to act against God or his conscience? . . . Is it reasonable
and wise to glory in the extent and greatness of the Empire when you can in
no way prove that there is any real happiness in men perpetually living amid
the horrors of war, perpetually wading in blood? Does it matter whether it
is the blood of their fellow citizens or the blood of their enemies? . . . And
even though a crooked world came to admit that men should be honored
only according to merit, even human honor would be of no great value. It is
smoke that weighs nothing. ([1958] p. 113)
The erotic unity explored in the Symposium between duty and plea-
sure is irrevocably dichotomized here into a realm of nature, in which
the drive for sensual gratification leads to the pursuit of power over oth-
ers, and the divine as the transcendence of nature and desire. No peace
and justice of any kind is truly to be found on earth; all lasting peace
and justice are transposed to the other world beyond this mortal life.
Given that all politics are fallen, what does it really matter what kind
of regime we live under? A brief comparison with Plato illustrates how
313
tyranny
314
glory and reputation
315
tyranny
316
glory and reputation
politics and acquisitive human nature helps explain the tendency in his
works to take what for the classics was a highly variegated and multi-
farious concept – that of Fortuna – and reify it into a single, unitary,
and overwhelmingly hostile and irrational force governing the entire
nonhuman world in opposition to man. For the ancients, Fortuna was
a phenomenon that could manifest itself in numerous ways – sometimes
hostile, sometimes unpredictable, but also as a benevolent, fecund force
of pleasure and prosperity. We considered some of the philosophical
nuances in our discussion of Cicero earlier in this chapter. A famous
Roman statue of Fortuna conflates her with the archaic figure of Mother
Earth, covered with the fruits of agriculture and dozens of life-giving
breasts and potent testicles. The Fortune of the Roman People was
worshipped throughout the empire as the benevolent guiding spirit of
Rome’s great success, peace, and virtue. All of these qualifications and
shades of meaning Machiavelli casts aside, reducing fortune to an over-
powering and empty singularity that goads man into fighting back.
The counterpoise to Machiavelli’s secularized Augustinian landscape
of politics as sheer dominion and acquisition is the reification of the
place formerly occupied in it by the saving will of the One God into
the overwhelmingly adverse power of Fortune, the Single Other, whose
power can also be utilized within ourselves so as to free ourselves of
our dependence on her, a kind of secular salvation. (I discuss the stages
of this process in the next section of this chapter.)
Machiavelli’s identification of Fortune as the Single Other provides
some insight into Leo Strauss’s intriguing remark that Machiavelli’s
presentation of Fortuna “reminds one in some respects of the Biblical
God” ([1969] p. 214). He continues: “She takes the place of the Biblical
God. She is indeed not a creator and she concentrates entirely on the
government of men.” Strauss’s formulation implies that, in terms of the
theological paradox attempting to express God as that which “reveals”
in distinction to that which “makes,” Machiavelli attributes to Fortuna
the role of revelation. For, as Strauss goes on, it would appear that
Fortuna had established and “elected” the Roman people to greatness
because of its justice, meaning that “Fortuna is guardian or source of
justice.” The proof is that Fortuna punishes cities less the more they are
“filled with virtue, religion.” Yet “she is indeed not a creator.” I surmise
from this formulation that, as Strauss sees it, while Fortuna provides
Rome with the revelatory dimension of guardianship and election, the
317
tyranny
318
glory and reputation
these may have been a seed bed for a more universalistic politics to be
brought about by stages by the progress of history. This is why, in the
Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel distinguishes between the “indepen-
dence” (Selbstandigkeit) honored by the aristocratic morality of pagan
antiquity and the “freedom” (Freiheit) acknowledged as the goal of
humanity in the modern age. “Independence” is a kind of “lordship”
and self-sufficiency thought to be possible through the cultivation of a
naturally superior character, the model of “the best man” so important
in the Republic, Gorgias, and other Platonic dialogues, as well as in
Aristotle’s understanding of phronesis. The ancients, in Hegel’s view,
saw this aristocratic character as a reflection of the substantive hier-
archy of ranked ends that characterized nature as a whole, as when
Aristotle, for example, bases his justification of natural mastery on the
notion that nature as a whole is characterized by pairs of ruling and
ruled parts. Callicles’ erotic longing for completion through political
preeminence and Socrates’ attempts to educate it toward a properly
natural fruition – moderate politics in the service of the common good
guided by a philosophically grounded cosmology of friendship – would
be seen by Hegel as an instance of the classical belief that independence
could be achieved through a harmony with “Immediate Being,” the
supposition of an orderly cosmos within which human perfection finds
its permanent place. “Freedom,” by contrast, is the specifically modern
consciousness of a capacity to overcome the limitations placed on us
by nature, including apparently natural, substantive and fore-ordained
differences between ranks of human beings, through an exertion of
will. It is born of a sense of opposition between human satisfaction
and nature – not, as for the ancients, from the prospect of a harmony
between human nature and the cosmos. It owes its origin to the religious
concept of a divine will that stands beyond all natural determinations,
thereby reducing nature to empirical necessity.
Hegel believed that the progress of history was resolving this con-
tradiction between the “substantive” Being of the ancient world and
the “subjective” spirit of the modern, post-Christian will to freedom.
My concern is not to pursue that large issue here, but to consider how
the Hegelian distinction between ancients and moderns might enable
us to clarify Machiavelli’s relationship to modernity as a whole, partic-
ularly to the question of how techne becomes the engine for the con-
quest of nature, rather than, as for Platonismn, a key to self-forgetting
319
tyranny
28 As Wolin puts it, Machiavelli consigns the whole of political existence and human life
altogether to the recesses of Plato’s Cave, cut off from the sunlight of eternal truth,
a world of “fleeting sense impressions and phenomenal flux” (2006) pp. 211–212.
Consider also the essay by Kennedy, which argues that Machiavelli’s politics amount to
Augustine’s City of Man stripped of the City of God (2000). For Kennedy, it is bootless
to speculate whether Machiavelli (or later Hobbes) were believers. If they were, the fact
that they hid this proves their theories were entirely secularized: “Machiavelli would
agree with Augustine about the prevalence of evil in the saeculum, where men were
bereft of faith, especially faith in one another. But Machiavelli was to offer no city of
God as an alternative, or his faith in such a city was weakened by what he saw in the
church’s involvement in Roman, Florentine, and Italian politics in general, providing
him with examples for The Prince. The earthly city, it would seem, was all man had
and he should make the best of it, modelling it somewhat on the ancient polis, which
would try to control chance, or Fortune. Machiavelli may have been a believer, as
indeed may have been Thomas Hobbes (with whom he is often linked because of his
power-based political philosophy). But the extent to which he hides it is itself a sign of
secularism.” Kennedy believes that this adaptation of Augustine’s City of Man as all
that we can aspire to must make us see Machiavelli as more of a pessimist and less as the
founder of modern political science and the modern political era. But if we emphasize
320
glory and reputation
not merely the view of the saeculum that Machiavelli adapts from Augustine but also
his focus on transferring the constructivist power of God’s will to secular rulers, then
his debt to Christianity is compatible with the view of his political theory as dynamic,
future-oriented, and ultimately optimistic about man’s capacity to improve his lot in the
world. For another perspective on “Machiavelli’s anthropology as a secularized version
of Augustine on original sin,” see Cosh (1999).
321
tyranny
to appear to have than this last quality. Men in general judge more by their
eyes than by their hands, because seeing is given to everyone, touching to
few. Everyone sees how you appear, few touch what you are.
And he who said that our sins were the cause of it spoke the truth. But the sins
were surely not those he believed, but the ones I have told of, and because
these were the sins of princes, they too have suffered the punishment for
them.
322
glory and reputation
323
tyranny
324
glory and reputation
fight back and master it. We must come to see that, as chapter 6 puts it,
statesmen “need” to encounter opposition, oppression, disorder, and
corruption. These forces “make” them successful by compelling them
to struggle, and thereby give them the opportunity to make their coun-
tries prosperous. They must experience a life-and-death struggle. Only
if faced with the prospect that nature might overpower them will they
be galvanized to assert their mastery.
325
tyranny
misidentify the visible outcome of princely virtue for its invisible cause,
when in truth the visible stability and prosperity are caused by the pri-
mordial passions of the prince for power and glory. The writers, in other
words, reify the “things that are made” by a prince of sufficient virtu into
the preexistent and eternal causes for which virtue comes into being.29
2. Having separated himself from the world, the prince or would-
be prince must “imitate” Fortuna by letting Fortuna’s impetuosity
empower him through his passions. For example, Machiavelli says,
fortune likes to build things up in order to to knock them down. In
the political realm, a prince can imitate this dimension of fortune’s
behavior by triumphing over adversity, which always compels admi-
ration from subjects or adversaries. Someone who has attuned himself
deeply to fortune’s unseen rhythms can imitate fortune by anticipating
29 Blanchard (1996) discusses the importance of the distinction between touching and
seeing as a way of reflecting on how Machiavelli’s epistemology, and therefore his state-
craft, differs from that of Plato. However, for Blanchard, instead of viewing Machiavelli
as diametrically opposed to Plato, we should see in his statecraft “modifications of the
Platonic approach (rather) than . . . a complete rejection of Plato.” As he sums up this
modification: “Whereas Plato resolves the problematic [about man’s dependence on
chance] by founding the soul on that which is, and which is better than and prior to
man, Machiavelli supposes that man, starting from scratch, can construct his own foun-
dations.” Surely, though, this is all the difference in the world, not a mere modification.
For if man is primarily defined in terms of a soul that is higher than and anterior to
man, then that cannot be the same man who might start from scratch and construct
his own foundations. The repudiation of Platonic cosmology inevitably entails an alter-
ation in how we conceive of “man” as a political actor. If the Good is always already
given, as it is for Plato, then man can never “start from scratch.” Similarly, if art is not
contained within the order of nature, as in Platonic cosmology, but can be employed by
man to “construct” new foundations entirely on his own, then the world must already
be reenvisioned in such a way as to make it capable of being reconstructed, and man’s
technical capacity to do so must now be understood as standing outside of nature, rather
than, as for Plato, enfolded within it. Thus, although Blanchard is right to argue that
Machiavelli’s encounter with Plato is a genuine dialogue – as evidenced, for instance, by
the fact that Machiavelli’s discussion of the limits placed by chance on human affairs,
and how human reason, virtue, and art might overcome those restrictions, parallels the
discussion in Book 4 of the Laws – and although Blanchard is also correct to observe
that both Plato and Machiavelli begin by appearing to concede that the sway of chance
is overwhelming only to conclude that it can be overcome to a large degree, I would
argue that Machiavelli’s view that a prince can aspire to master nature and assimilate
reason to the will, thereby making himself the source of his own prudence, is not only
a modification of Plato’s view but a profound reversal, which changes the meanings
of all the cognate terms in the parallel as well. That is, just as Machiavelli overturns
Plato’s belief that man must find his place within nature, so do the meanings of fortune,
knowledge, virtue, art, and prudence all undergo a complete reversal of meaning.
326
glory and reputation
30 This passage, recommending that a prince cultivate conspiracies so as to stamp them out,
illustrates the active/passive dyad of the interior interaction between Fortuna and the
prince. In chapter 6, fortune provided the bare (and hostile and dangerous) “occasion”
for potential princes to imprint their will on “matter,” a blank slate to be filled with
their virtue. Here, the situation is turned around, and Fortune is reified into a weirdly
benevolent goddess who actively contrives to put such occasions in the prince’s path.
Fortune, Machiavelli says, “wishes” to make a new prince great. The new prince does
not have a hereditary position, which means he is already not reliant on the arms and
the fortune of others (as was, for example, Cesare Borgia). Therefore, Fortuna “makes”
enemies and obstacles for him so that, by crushing them, he can “climb higher” through
an enhanced reputation for victory entirely through his own efforts. Understanding the
weird favor Fortuna has done for him by throwing every possible threat and obstacle
at him, a “wise” prince, having established his power through overcoming the initial
impediments she created, will imitate her by deliberately encouraging conspiracies to
form so that he can continue to “increase his greatness” by crushing them. In other
words, what Fortuna does to the prince spontaneously, the prince will imitate methodi-
cally. This is the difference between “relying” on fortune, as do those who rest content
with the status they have inherited or been given, and those who master Fortuna by
channeling her spontaneity.
327
tyranny
328
glory and reputation
329
tyranny
prince can only subdue Fortuna if he “imitates” her. For the ancients, the
imitation of nature meant the attempt to inculcate the orderliness of the
world in one’s own character and habits, what the Stoics called integri-
tas. For Plato, philosophy and its ordered view of the whole must be the
supervisor and guide for correct poetic “imitation,” such that Homer
must be purged of his Dionysian sweetness, leaving only examples of
virtuous living, the philosophic images that will replace the tragic poets’
and Sophists’ shadow show cast on the wall at the rear of the Cave.
For Machiavelli, however, the imitation of nature means allowing the
multifarious, unpredictable, subtle, treacherous, and malignant currents
and moods of fortune to course through oneself; sampling them, savor-
ing them, but never being swept away by their current; instead, turning
their power outward in one’s manipulation of others, especially in one’s
manipulation of how the credulous many see one’s external reputation
for virtue. We see again how Machiavelli conflates the roles of philoso-
pher and poet. The hierarchy of philosophy over poetic imitation is
replaced by the alternation between control and release.
Thus, there is an interesting ambivalence in Machiavelli’s depiction
of manliness. On the one hand, he encourages a crude masculinity and
brute exertion of power:
Fortune is a woman, and it is necessary, if one wants to hold her down, to
beat her and strike her down. And one sees that she lets herself be won more
by the impetuous than by those who proceed coldly. And so always, like a
woman, she is a friend of the young, because they are less cautious, more
ferocious, and command her with more audacity. (The Prince chapter 25)
Even among the ancient exponents of tyranny, of the superiority of the
“manly men” (andres) who live for victory in the contest for distinction,
the hostile and unpredictable forces of the external world as Fortuna – as a woman –
because those forces will be less terrifying to the extent that the prince can reify them
as one single foe who must be subdued. My own position is something of a middle
ground between these two. Because I present the relationship of the prince to Fortuna
as a kind of dance between his psychic interior and the generative matrix of nature,
a dance in which the prince must tap into nature’s own spontaneity and capacity for
force, I agree with Zuckert that Machiavelli is arguing for a certain kind of mutuality
and reciprocity between the masculine and the feminine, grounding the belief that, based
on self-interest, women could be prudent as well as men, a basis for “liberal feminism.”
At the same time, though, I believe Pitkin is correct to see the prince’s dyad with Fortuna
as a potentially dark and terrifying fracas, and that although caution is sometimes to be
preferred to impetuosity, in general the hot-blooded virility of the young is a better bet
for bringing Fortuna under control.
330
glory and reputation
331
tyranny
will cultivate a reputation for honesty to the extent useful, but he will
always manipulate it from behind the scenes, capable of the slyest deceits
and most shameless reversals. In a way, therefore, Machiavelli’s prince,
although on one level excessively masculine in contrast with the classical
model of the gentleman, is on another level more “feminine” in the
sense that he takes on some of the qualities of fickleness, treachery, and
evasiveness attributed by Machiavelli to personified Fortuna herself.35
This alternation between the bold and the deceitful, the forthright
and the sly, undulates throughout the new psychology of the lion and
fox. For example, when he praises the “inhuman cruelty” of Hannibal
(The Prince chapter 17), Machiavelli is providing what he regards as
the unvarnished truth about the kind of firmness in governing that the
ancient authors also admired while flinching from identifying its actual
psychological source. However, Machiavelli also praises treachery and
deceit as routine methods for maintaining authority. In discussing “well-
used” cruelty, for instance, he cites the examples of Agathocles of Syra-
cuse and Oliveretto of Fermo. Whereas Agathocles convened the People
and Senate of Syracuse and had his enemies among them slaughtered in
the open, Oliverotto prepared to seize power first by luring the opposi-
tion to a “most secret” chamber and killing them out of sight. Reflecting
on this contrast between ancient and contemporary examples, one won-
ders: Has the incredible psychological hold of the “imagined republics,”
epitomized by the Church that is at once a world government and mili-
tarily powerless, yet can sway powerful men through their piety to serve
its own interests, introduced into the world a contradiction between
appearance and reality that is much sharper than anything known to
the ancients? That is to say, it may be more difficult, given the enor-
mous psychological hold of the illusory imagined republics, to kill one’s
enemies openly, because such pragmatism is considered sinful, but less
difficult to deceive them and kill them in secret because Christian naivete
35 In this connection, the summation by Lord (1979) of the relationship between the
Mandragola and Machiavelli’s larger political philosophy appears to be apt: to the
extent that man might aspire to overcome Fortuna, and if the proper mode for success
in doing so is akin to a hot-blooded youth’s wooing of a tempestuous woman rather than
to a cautious man’s trust in the rationality of the cosmos, then Machiavelli’s thought,
although neither precisely comedic nor tragic (certainly not tragic, inasmuch as will and
reason can plot a clear method for man’s triumph over necessity and chance), bears a
closer affinity to comedy, “if one understands by comedy the archetypical celebration
of the triumph of youth and desire over age, authority and duty.”
332
glory and reputation
has made men more credulous in general and more inclined to accept a
profession of virtue as its reality. One is reminded of how Shakespeare’s
characters so frequently alter their identities, from a woman playing a
man playing a woman, from a wastrel to a king. If one wants to appre-
ciate the full force of Machiavelli’s wit, one need only think through
his remark to the addressee of The Prince about what gifts a prince
like Lorenzo would most enjoy receiving and the means through which
Cesare Borgia lured the Orsini to Sinigaglia.36
The Machiavellian prince is profoundly interiorized and detached
from the visible world with its established customs and distinctions, in
this sense sharing the Augustinian soul’s alienation from the world. He
is as much Iago as Hannibal, as much an expert in the invisible levers
of power as in its ferocious open exercise, as much if not more fox
than lion, and both masculine and feminine by turns. All see him, but
few “touch” what he is. The abstraction of the self from any concrete
object of erotic longing in the world – a prerequisite for the mastery of
self and others – calls for a plasticity and mutability of character whose
feline slipperiness would have been excoriated as much by Callicles
as by Socrates. The exchange of traits between the “virtuous” prince
and the “malignant” goddess Fortuna is crystallized in a writing by
Bacon, who credited Machiavelli with having understood that the pur-
pose of knowledge is “the relief of man’s estate” through the extraction
of power from nature. Indeed, the methodological skepticism toward
received opinion and tradition that formed the basis of the new natural
science is arguably grounded in the Machiavellian ontology of alien-
ation from, and imitation of, Fortuna. Bacon describes the scientist
as someone who woos nature, who taps into nature’s inscrutable
rhythms, and to this extent imitates her and begins to merge with her.
Yet this empathy exists only for the sake of subverting nature’s power so
as to empower human projects, torturing nature through experimental
36 In this connection, consider Dietz (1986), who argues that Machiavelli’s advice to
Lorenzo in The Prince is meant to hasten his overthrow and restore the liberty of
Florence. To which one must respond, it could be true. However, it does not “[return]
The Prince to its specific historical context” if this is seen as something at odds with
his later legacy. After all, one can observe that Shakespeare’s plays are at once veiled
criticisms of the Tudors based on his own personal experience and observation and
ascend to universal truths that speak to the ages. There is no need to choose between
the “historical context” and the transhistorical experience, for the latter emerges out of
the former and is transmuted by ongoing acts of interpretation.
333
tyranny
37 Kass (2003).
334
glory and reputation
38 In criticizing Louis XII in chapter 3 for ceding the Romagna to Pope Alexander because
he was under an obligation to him owing to the resolution of his marriage, Machiavelli
observes that there is nothing “miraculous” about the fact that, by disobeying the
Romans’ rules for taking provinces, he failed. Because modern Christian rulers and
states are taught to want peace above all else and view success such as the ancients
achieved as vice, they cede the maximum of control over their own affairs, thereby
making themselves maximally vulnerable to the reversals of fortune, hence making
politics seem like a field of “miraculous” and equally accidental triumphs and defeats.
335
tyranny
336
glory and reputation
for a world in which one’s needs are recognized and granted some
grounding beyond oneself. Achilles is right, in other words, that the
world should answer in some way to his own needs. The key to reform-
ing such ambitious types is to educate their needs so that they come
to experience the equilibrium between the development of their own
best qualities and the harmoniousness characteristic of the most real
dimensions of the cosmos. Such men will then turn their anger inward
against their own aberrant impulses or restrict its outward exercise to
enemies of justice and decency, like the Auxiliaries in the Republic,
whose steadfast and moderate manliness is Plato’s replacement for the
doomed and brooding Achilles. They will no longer howl with anguish
like Achilles at their inability to achieve everything they desire, or, as
Socrates puts it in Book 10, cry like a small boy holding the place where
it hurts until someone kisses it better, because the noble harmony of
the world as they have been educated to apprehend it will suffuse their
passions and harmonize them within the soul (Republic 386a–388b,
390e–391c, 604d).
For Machiavelli, by contrast, it is necessary to release one’s passions
without being seduced by the longing they produce for some such ulti-
mate satisfaction in the world. Before one can hope to master nature
and the natures of one’s subjects, one must first win the battle against
the seductive inner promptings of nature in oneself. One must let one’s
will be empowered by the longing for might, satisfaction, and honor
while refusing to allow those passions to weave imaginary republics
of repose and harmony that captivate these longings and sap their pri-
mordial strength. For Fortuna in Machiavelli’s depiction, as we have
observed, loves to build something up so that she can knock it down,
and in Machiavelli’s estimation, there is no more of a tragic cathar-
sis in this nemesis than there is in being hit by a bus; there is nothing
redemptive about failure and suffering. This is why Machiavelli is much
more given to depicting princely virtue in terms of belligerence, violence,
deceit, and cold-hearted glory rather than as the fruition of eros. Plea-
sure and happiness as ends in themselves, as the achievement of repose
and tranquillity, are virtually absent from his prescription for princely
rule. Although opposed to the Stoic model of steadfast self-control,
even less does he want to return to the ancient philosophical school of
hedonism, the main successor in the dissident strain opposing the classi-
cal natural right of Plato and Aristotle, which argued that the pleasures
337
tyranny
338
glory and reputation
frighten the wolves. Those who stay simply with the lion do not under-
stand this” (The Prince chapter 18). At the same time, on the whole,
he prefers impetuosity to caution. Within classical thinking, this com-
bination would be a contradiction. If a wise calculation rules the soul,
the aggressiveness of ambition will be tamed. If spirited impetuosity
rebels against calculation, the cool-headedness of caution cannot pre-
vail. For Machiavelli, however, there is nothing contradictory about
this combination of opposites. The lionlike side of passion, left to itself,
tends to get carried away and make its possessor forget why he allows
himself to roar. Someone who manipulates his own rage by remote
control, with the coolness of the fox, is more likely to bring off suc-
cessfully those impetuous assaults on enemies and hostile “occasions”
that Machiavelli thinks are likelier to put one in control of one’s fate
than waiting cautiously for favorable circumstances to arise. Because
only if channeled efficiently – channeled away from the distraction of
erotic longing, even an eros for honor and mastery – can the power of
the passions be methodically focused against Fortuna.
Thus, to expand on an earlier motif, there is a larger meaning than is
sometimes supposed to Machiavelli’s advice that it is better for a prince
to be guided by fear rather than by love in his dealings with his subjects.
It does not merely mean that a prince should inspire fear rather than
be kind. This hardheaded tactic is only one consequence of the more
general implication that a prince should not practice the virtues in order
to become an object of love to his subjects. He should resist the delusion
that they can have friendly feelings for him based on their admiration
for his superior qualities of character.39 This is the kind of civic philia
between citizens and statesmen sketched by Socrates for Callicles and
elaborated by Diotima. In resisting this temptation, the prince will resist
39 Tolstoy’s War and Peace provides a vivid illustration of the erotic longing for honor that
may be stirred in a subject by his absorption in the nobility and beauty that he sees in the
prince when Tolstoy describes a review by the czar of his troops, as well as the young
nobleman Nikolai Rostoff’s transport of martial and patriotic ecstasy as he imagines
dying in battle for the splendid and kindly young emperor. The emperor’s outward
splendor perfectly mirrors the noble nature Rostoff attributes to him and toward which
he is irresistibly drawn: “The handsome young Emperor Alexander in his Horseguards’
uniform and three-cornered hat worn point forward, with his pleasant face and clear but
not loud voice, was the cynosure of all eyes . . . ‘My God! What would happen to me, if
the sovereign were to address me!’ thought Rostoff. ‘I should die of happiness! . . . Oh,
to die, to die for him! . . . My God! How happy I should be if he would only bid me to
dash instantly into the fire!” Quoted in Newell (2001) pp. 352–354.
339
tyranny
falling in love with his own reputation as magnified by his subjects’ love.
Otherwise, a prince-statesman can forget the levers of his power and
float away in rapture with his own reputation, until this infatuation
with the reified image of his own nobility makes him lose his “touch”
for sensing subterranean threats to his power from the discontented
or from secret plotters among his colleagues. Thus, whereas Socrates
wishes to help men like Callicles understand that their eros cannot be
satisfied by political achievement alone, Machiavelli wishes to help them
understand that eros is a distraction from political achievement.
That statesmen avoid believing their own achievements are actually
summoned into being by a preexisting objective hierarchy of noble ful-
filment is good not only for princes but for popular regimes as well. As
we saw in Chapter 5, according to Machiavelli, a republican statesman
like Manlius had a character of such natural savagery that he was cruel
to everyone without distinction, so that his rigor to enforce the laws
was quite disinterested. This made him very much to be preferred to
statesmen like Valerius Corvinus and Scipio who, by trying to make
the people love them, thereby confused a private erotic relationship
with the maintenance of the republic. They subverted the impartial
rigor of the law by showering favors on their admirers and clients,
threatening to replace republican equality with the personal authority
of a monarch over his household. Thus, whereas Plato presents thu-
motic savagery as capable of being tamed by paideia (in the Republic)
or assimilated by an eros for political nobility (in the Symposium) as
two alternative routes to serving the public good, Machiavelli truncates
them. Thumotic savagery and an eros for honor are not two perspec-
tives on routes to the unity and health of the soul, with eros taking the
leading role, but two kinds of ambition – the more savage one helpful
to republics, the gentler one subversive of them. Manlius Torquatus is
pure thumotic indignation bereft of a Platonic education in the harmo-
nious beauty of the cosmos. Scipio’s eros for fame and the admiring
love of his fellow citizens, the kind of longing thought by Plato to be
a basis for public service, is for Machiavelli the germ of the Roman
Republic’s corruption into an “eastern” despotism sapped of its manly
rigor.
We recall that the love of a prince’s subjects, according to Machi-
avelli, is a voluntary obligation. The prince relies on them to incur this
obligation so long as he cultivates the virtues of soul recommended by
340
glory and reputation
341
tyranny
342
glory and reputation
343
tyranny
Ficthe, that thinker who goes furthest in casting nature as nothing but
sheer fodder for an endless dynamic for the assertion of human freedom,
“the material of our moral duty rendered sensuous.” There is another
side of Machiavelli’s thinking, however, most evident in the Discourses,
that bounds the capacity for the exertion of human willpower within
the surrounding contexts of time, circumstance, accident, human folly,
and the rise and fall of regimes. In other words, the radically voluntaris-
tic, proto-Baconian and proto-Ficthean side of Machiavelli is conjoined
with a more immanentist, organicist approach to the unfolding of his-
tory and the recurrent cycles of events. In this way, Machiavelli might be
seen as anticipating Hegel’s attempt to reconcile the search in history for
both freedom and community (“the unity of subject and substance”),
with the very significant difference that Machiavelli does not propound
a unifying synthesis between these two dimensions at the end of history.
344
VII
the republic in
motion
Machiavelli’s Vision of the New Rome
345
tyranny
346
the republic in motion
347
tyranny
348
the republic in motion
349
tyranny
350
the republic in motion
3 See the valuable study by Hornqvist (2004), who argues that the revival of Republican
Rome, with its emphasis on glory and liberality, was at the heart of Machiavelli’s project,
more important than the independence of Florence or the liberation of Italy. This con-
stitutes further evidence, along with works by Rahe (2005, 2009) and Sullivan (1996,
2004), of a solid intrinsic connection between Machiavelli’s own view of statecraft and
the influence later traceable to him over English republicanism, as opposed to a mere
retroactive appropriation or adaptation of his ideas.
351
tyranny
352
the republic in motion
353
tyranny
354
the republic in motion
can bewitch us, carry us adrift in the pursuit of their stable perfection,
causing us to forget the burden of time on human existence from which
they issued in their original vigor: “For time brings out everything, the
good and the bad” (The Prince chapter 3).
Because necessity and struggle are paramount, Machiavelli con-
cludes, it may be best to choose deliberately a sterile region where
necessity will “compel” people to be industrious, “therefore less given to
idleness . . . more united and less exposed by the poverty of the country
to occasions for discord.” On the face of it, the praise of industriousness
and the disparagement of idleness sounds in accord with both elements
of the Great Tradition in the West, Judeo-Christian revelation and the
pagan classics. Yet to make industriousness the ground of virtue in the
absence of other virtues takes what for the tradition was regarded as
a comparatively low virtue and elevates it into one of the highest. The
Christian and classical traditions did not approve of laziness, but they
did not praise industriousness to any great degree either, and certainly
not as the basis of political order and unity. One need only consider
Plato’s and Aristotle’s strictures on excessive commerce and the unlim-
ited sway of oikonomia, echoed by Thomas Aquinas. Laziness is bad
not primarily because it is unproductive but because it is a sign of a
character falling beneath itself at the most rudimentary level of master-
ing one’s passions, antecedent to higher virtues involving deliberative
choice rather than mere self-repression.5
For Machiavelli, on the other hand, civic disunity or discord stem
altogether from “idleness,” from a condition that, according to the tra-
dition, properly directed, made contemplation possible. What Machi-
avelli calls “idleness” includes the leisure (skole) that, according to
Aristotle, enables us to dwell on what most unifies us, philosophy and
deliberative citizenship (Nicomachean Ethics 1176b–1178b). Indeed,
Machiavelli collapses Aristotle’s distinction between mere relaxation
and leisure into idleness. For Aristotle, idleness might, if properly cul-
tivated, become the leisure that is indispensable for the actualization
of civic virtue through a full-time devotion to public affairs and, at the
highest level, cultivating the contemplative virtues. Far from preferring
labor to idleness (properly improved as leisure), Aristotle argues that
355
tyranny
356
the republic in motion
Unfortunately, Machiavelli goes on, not all men are content with a
modicum of prosperity but want an abundance and also “desire to
exercise command.” Because there are those who want to dominate,
a people cannot rest content with the internal security achieved by a
moderate degree of wealth wrested by collective labor from a sterile
site. They need to become “powerful,” but this requires settling in a
region “where the fertility of the soil affords the means of becoming
great, and of acquiring strength to repel all who might attack it, or
oppose the development of its power.” From first favoring the extreme
of sterility, then, Machiavelli goes to the opposite extreme of favoring
a “most fertile” environment, again avoiding the Aristotelian mean.6
The first stage of the argument, and the objection that Machiavelli
then raises to it, reminds us of Glaucon’s objection to the City of Sows –
that there are some people who are not content with security and the
basic necessities of life. Their “feverish” passions for wealth and mastery
require a city not only to protect itself from external aggression but to
become an aggressor itself. Whereas Plato and Aristotle respond to
this complexity in human nature by prescribing an internal ordering
of the constitution and an education aimed primarily at helping such
people transcend the passions that lead to tyranny and imperialism,
Machiavelli instead proposes to think through what type of constitution
those passions would require if no attempt were made to educate and
sublimate them toward civic and philosophical moderation. He aims
to conjoin the “feverish” soul with a stable republican constitution
and loyalty to the common good, a project that the ancients thought
impossible.
With respect to Plato specifically, this requires a major reorientation
of political psychology. In the pedagogical thought experiment of the
Republic, in which Socrates tries to draw Glaucon away from tyranni-
cal temptation by getting him to think about founding a just regime,
Socrates uses Glaucon’s objection to the City of Sows to introduce an
unrestrained eros for multiple pleasures, the seed of the tyrant’s dis-
ordered personality. However, having introduced eros to necessitate
357
tyranny
358
the republic in motion
of course recognizes the danger that the masterful types may turn their
ambitions toward internal political affairs and provoke usurpation and
civil war. But he believes that glory seeking can be turned outward by a
policy of republican imperialism in which such thrusting men will take
the lead, thereby carrying their people to new heights of grandeur and
wealth, protecting them from external aggression and finding in that
duty a justification for their own relentless ambition.
Whereas the psychology of tyranny is largely driven underground by
Hobbes as a theme for extensive and nuanced consideration, Machi-
avelli encourages those whom Callicles termed the “natural masters”
and brings to life their many varieties through his meditations on his-
tory. Indeed, it might be said that while the Platonic Socrates sifts
dialectically through opinions within the city about the Good, Machi-
avelli sifts dialectically through the historical patterns of cities in conflict
with one another to clarify the “effectual truth” about politics. This is
one reason Machiavelli’s writings are a source of much richer specu-
lation about the nature of tyranny and leadership than anything to be
found in Hobbes – a richer historical phenomenology of how states
and their internal parts are subject to the stimulus of external motions
forced on them by competing states. Machiavelli already foresees that
his “new path” will require “unknown lands” comparable to the one
discovered by Columbus, and the founding of a New Rome required
by the international and multinational scope of Machiavelli’s republi-
can prescription. Hobbes’s philosophy, by contrast, envisions politics as
nothing but a mechanism for internal order and control, one in principle
capable of limitless extension but bereft of the full-blooded patriotism,
love of the earthly fatherland, and the exhilarating scope of imperial
conquest and Elizabethan swashbuckling to which Machiavelli gives
rise. This is why, as we consider in more detail in the Conclusion, a
visionary of Atlanticist, Protestant republicanism like James Harring-
ton – a project for commercial imperialism already underway in Tudor
and Stuart mercantilism and exploding in the New World – could extol
Machiavelli’s republicanism while decrying Hobbes as an apologist for
absolute monarchy without any sense of contradiction. Hobbes is a
successor of Machiavelli, but only of a narrow version of his thought.
To resume: The danger of a fertile site is that its “pleasures and
softness” will “make men idle and unfit for the exercise of valor.” Or,
as Machiavell amplifies the point in 2.25, “the dissensions in republics
359
tyranny
are generally the result of idleness and peace, while apprehension and
war are productive of union.” Again, the achievement of the peace and
leisure that, for Plato and Aristotle, provide the milieu for subtler ethi-
cal choices and an interest in philosophy, for Machiavelli represents the
gravest threat to “virtue.” Machiavelli’s solution is not to attempt to
moderate these feverish passions through education (as Plato and Aris-
totle advise) but to incorporate into a fertile natural environment an
artificial replica of the necessity that nature imposes on people in a ster-
ile environment. The replica is “law.” Law takes the place of nature’s
direct compulsion provided by scarcity in a sterile environment. Laws
“offset the pleasures and softness” of a fertile environment with the
“rigors of a strict discipline.” Properly executed, these laws, by imitat-
ing the dire truth about nature – that it is, at bottom, hostile necessity –
not only prevent citizens living in a bounteous environment from being
corrupted, but produce “better warriors than what nature produces in
the harshest climates and most sterile countries.” We might recall in
this context Machiavelli’s preference, considered earlier in connection
with his treatment of Xenophon’s Education of Cyrus as a mirror of
princes, for the disinterested harshness of Manlius Torquatus (more
suitable for republics) in contrast with the generosity and mercy of
Scipio (more suitable for monarchy). As in The Prince, by imitating
nature in political life, we can master nature – improve on our natural
condition by gaining the power to restructure it for our own survival,
aggrandizement, and glory. This requires a new understanding of law.
For Aristotle, law is subordinate to the politeia, which embodies a divi-
sion of offices based on a partial account of justice and virtue. The
content of the law depends on the distinct regime (Politics 1287b15–
20, 1280a7–21, 1276b34–1277b16). For Machiavelli, because nature
is uniformly indifferent to human purpose and supplies no such teleo-
logical ordering, law becomes the abstract regulator of nature as field
of forces or happenstance. Through the “strict discipline” imposed on
their citizens by law, republics can imitate nature’s hostility while dis-
tancing themselves from a reliance on nature’s bounty.
In a fertile environment, the disorderly side of Fortuna flourishes.
Laws enable a republic to replicate consciously the severity that neces-
sity unconsciously produces when nature’s reversals and fluctuations
force a people to fight back through labor and industriousness. “Skil-
ful and sagacious legislators” can provide, through laws, a corrective
360
the republic in motion
361
tyranny
8 1.18 discusses the grave difficulties of refounding corrupt republics and why princely
natures are needed to do so. Because someone can become the “prince” in a corrupt
republic only by wicked and violent means, you either need that rare good man who
is willing to use wicked means to achieve a good end or hope that a bad man, having
achieved power, will somehow decide to labor for good ends: “From these causes arise the
difficulty or impossibility of maintaining liberty in a republic that has become corrupt.” In
such circumstances, the republic may need to be transformed into a monarchy where one
man will crush the turbulence of the many. In 3.1, Machiavelli returns to the importance of
refounding, employing unusually scientific/alchemical language: “Nothing is more true”
362
the republic in motion
than that everything, including republics, has a limited existence. However, only those
whose “bodies” do not become disorganized will run the full limit of their existence. In
“mixed bodies” like republics and religious sects, the aim should be to “bring them back
to their original principles.” Better still if they have institutional means for frequently
renewing themselves, or do so in response to “extrinsic accidents” such as war or the
threat of conquest. “It is a truth clearer than light that, without such renovation, these
bodies cannot continue to exist . . . ” The inclusion of religious sects arguably supports
the interpretation of Machiavelli as calling for a pristine, patriotic Christianity, not its
complete abolition.
363
tyranny
suggest in The Prince that a ruler might want to allow domestic con-
spiracies to reach a certain point – thereby deliberately encouraging to
a degree the disorder that Fortuna will try to reap in his affairs in any
event – so that he can then exercise his virtue by cutting them down,
mastering Fortuna by encouraging and then preempting her hostility.
Would the republican version of this policy be to seek out possible
foreign foes, let the danger they pose grow for a time or even goad
them into hostility, so as to galvanize the citizenry into going to war?
However this may be, the main thing to notice in this section of the
Discourses is how Machiavelli supplements the Platonic teaching on
founding. Plato had argued in the Laws that a well-founded regime
might require the good fortune of an ambitious tyrant coinciding with
a wise counsellor. Machiavelli concedes that good fortune might pro-
vide such a founder all on her own, while shearing away the role of the
philosophic counsellor. In other words, Lycurgus was presumably the
source of his own prudence, as Machiavelli advises in chapter 17 of The
Prince, not dependent for his prudence on another. Even more strik-
ingly, Machiavelli suggests that “chance” itself might perfect a republic
bereft of any such genius founder. Indeed, a republic like Rome that per-
fects itself by tapping into the forces of Fortuna will more successfully
surmount Fortuna’s reverses than a regime like Sparta whose internal
strength is the gift of the great good fortune of a single brilliant founder.
Institutions that have evolved over time to shunt, channel, and focus
Fortuna may preempt the role of the uniquely gifted legislator.
In contrast to the security and stability provided by a constitution
like Sparta’s set in place in the beginning without need of change, this
second course is “never effected without danger,” because “the major-
ity of men never willingly adopt any new law tending to change the
constitution of the state, unless the necessity of change is clearly demon-
strated.” A republic “perfected” in this way may therefore have to court
destruction before its citizens recognize clearly the need to change. Of
course this may actually lead to its destruction before the improvements
can take root, as happened, Machiavelli believes, to the Florentine
republic. But we will not be surprised to learn that this is the course that
Machiavelli prefers, successfully exemplified by the Roman republic.
We have already seen that, in his view, although “great good fortune”
of the kind allegedly demonstrated by the emergence of Lycurgus is
not to be spurned, even greater power and prosperity will result when
364
the republic in motion
men of virtue receive nothing from fortune but a barren, even adverse
“occasion” against which to struggle. We know from The Prince that
what princes achieve in these circumstances is entirely the result of
their own prowess. Their power remains more surely their own than
that of princes who receive even a portion of their authority from good
fortune, as with Cesare Borgia’s good fortune in having Pope Alexander
VI as his natural father. Here, we are given the republican parallel of
Machiavelli’s advice to princes. Sparta, with the great good fortune of
her founding, is an admirable example for republics to emulate, but
Rome is even more admirable. Because she started out with nothing but
bare “chance,” sheer adverse happenstance, the power she achieved by
fighting back against adversity became more surely rooted over time.
Sparta was complete from the beginning, hence inflexible and prone
to shatter when a truly hard blow from fortune finally came. Rome
evolved in an ad hoc manner, incorporating fortune’s unpredictable
impetuosity within her own institutions. By taking the risky course of
dynamic innovation through imperial expansion, Rome deliberately
exposed her institutions to that same dangerous necessity that, when we
are subjected to it by the natural environment, compels us, both princes
and peoples, to fight back by laboring for survival and power. More-
over, as in The Prince, leaders need not wait for fortune to throw up the
danger that will convince the people of the inescapable need for change.
By inspiring terror in the people, thereby tapping into fortune’s capacity
to inspire the fear needed for change by acting consciously as its agent,
leaders can expedite the needed reforms. (Although Machiavelli depicts
Lycurgus as a founder who sprang directly from “great good fortune,”
we are of course entitled to wonder, based on Machiavelli’s own guide-
lines that we considered in Chapter 5 in connection with the life of
Cyrus, to what extent he shaped the Spartans’ generational memory of
him.)
In classical political thought, the purpose of a good constitution and
the civic education it reinforces is to transcend, to the degree possi-
ble within the limitations of human nature, the ravages of “chance” –
not in the sense of fighting nature and mastering it by accumulating
power, but in the sense of immunizing oneself from vulnerability to the
temptations provided by perishable goods, and hence to the inevitable
reverses of fortune, by educating the soul to moderation. To the extent
that the soul’s potentiality for transcendence is actualized through an
365
tyranny
So that a legislator who gives to a state which he founds, either of these three
forms of government, constitutes it but for a brief time; for no precautions
can prevent either one of the three that are reputed good from degenerating
into its opposite kind; so great are in these the attractions and resemblances
between the good and the evil.
366
the republic in motion
Up until the last words of this formulation (“so great are the attrac-
tions and resemblances between the good and the evil”), Machiavelli
remains within the horizon of both classical and Christian teachings
on government. It is the classical political philosophies themselves that
emphasize how unlikely it is that the right circumstances – the right
locale, virtuous citizens, prudent statesmen framing good laws – will
come together to form a good constitution. In setting forth his picture
of an optimal aristocracy in Book 7 of the Politics, Aristotle uses a verb
meaning “to pray” when detailing what conditions would have to be
present for virtue to flourish, for however brief a time, in a political
community (1330a34–1330b8). As we have seen, Plato in the Laws
regards the conditions for a good founding as tantamount to the gift of
a god, while in the Republic he regards the best regime, next to impos-
sible to come about in the first place, to be foredoomed to decay and
collapse (546a–547a). No one is more aware than Plato or Aristotle of
the fragility of even minimally virtuous constitutional arrangements, of
even mere constitutional truces between aggrieved parties that might
allow public life to rise a little above the level of constant wrangling for
power and distrust between rich and poor. So, in stressing the “brief
time” for which all such arrangements last, Machiavelli does not tell
us anything for which there is not abundant acknowledgment in the
classical sources. No one is more informative than Plato and Aristotle
on any specific issue of everyday political circumstance – the difficulty
of getting different parties to agree even on relatively negotiable eco-
nomic disputes, let alone larger issues of justice; the danger that the
need to defend one’s country from aggressors will distract energy from
domestic political life and summon forth tyrannically minded men who
will use national security as an excuse for subverting the rule of law
at home; the temptation to become the imperialistic aggressor one-
self and end the uncertainty about economic scarcity. They are any-
thing but optimists or dewy-eyed idealists. As we have observed, they
are well aware that education and noble rhetoric need the backing of
force. The revenge of Strepsiades against Socrates in the Clouds is a
sign that the Sophists do not understand that passions of anger based
on the love of one’s own cannot always be neutralized by rhetoric.
The Platonic Socrates, however, knows this lesson, just as his com-
panion Xenophon, in his real-life military campaigns, understood the
need for harsh discipline, unlike Proxenus, a follower of Gorgias, who
367
tyranny
368
the republic in motion
369
tyranny
370
the republic in motion
summons into being the lower and more primitive economic and famil-
ial elements that develop into the polis. The “kinds” of constitutions,
embodying as they do permanently valid distinctions between justice
and injustice, as opposed to their mere generational substratum, are
given under the aspect of eternity.
When Machiavelli argues that “chance” is the sole origin of the
visible forms of constitutions, we might recognize an element from the
pre-Socratic argument that Plato and Aristotle were concerned to refute,
according to which, as the Athenian Stranger summarizes it, the appar-
ent stable reality of the world around us is in fact the transitory appear-
ance of a more profound, underlying series of “great motions . . . out
of necessity, according to chance.” The Heracleitean belief that perma-
nence was a mere shell or husk temporarily masking a more profound
mutability led, in Plato’s and Aristotle’s judgment, to the belief that the
passions are the part of human life corresponding to the great motions
that underlie and generate the visible world and that their limitless
gratification constitutes the only natural way to live. Not surprisingly,
Machiavelli does return in part to this pre-Socratic and Sophistical view.
But he does not merely return to it. The pre-Socratics and Sophists had
argued that this primordialist ontology rendered pointless any attempt
to account for intrinsic ethical or rational distinctions among the visi-
ble, completed forms of constitutions. As Thrasymachus puts it in his
general definition of government, behind the facade of the various con-
stitutions, the ruling element pursues its own advantage and designates
this as just, gulling the ruled into going along with it. “Justice” is uni-
versally “the advantage of the stronger”: the specific regime principles
themselves are mere accidental local coloration and custom. At bot-
tom, the pre-Socratics and Sophists think, the natural life of “getting
the better” can be lived without any intrinsic connection to the kind of
constitution. One can get along in a democracy, oligarchy, monarchy,
or what have you by aping the local conventions and taking advantage
of others where one can safely get away with it. The only political way
of life that is in complete harmony with nature is that of the tyrant,
which for Plato and Aristotle amounts to the destruction of all politics
as shared rule or as rule with an ethical responsibility toward the souls
of the ruled. As a kind of antipolitics, tyranny is simply the nature of
man as it was understood by the Sophists showing itself openly in its
pure individuated selfishness.
371
tyranny
372
the republic in motion
strayed too far from observable political reality, that they set up too
simplistic a dichotomy between nature and convention, when in truth –
as Socrates tried to convince Callicles – human nature is so constituted
as to find its own prospect for satisfaction in and through convention,
through cooperation with others; that indeed the specific politiea under
which a man lives, or aspires to live, will be mirrored in his very soul
(Gorgias 513). It is not the scope and subject matter of ancient thought
that Machiavelli rejects, but rather its specific philosophical and meta-
physical content. In his own genealogy of regimes, he does not simply
banish the distinctiveness and integrity of the respective constitutions
by reducing their various forms to their origins in the undertow of
chance. Rather, he tries to demonstrate how the distinct forms emerge
phenomenologically through history, action, psychology, and experi-
ence. He conjoins the problem of the form of the constitution with the
problem of its origins in chance and necessity, a synthesis that neither
pre-Socratics nor Socrates would have thought tenable – the emergence
of political form or reason out of chance. What follows is a genealogy
of how regimes rise and decline in a world drained of both classical and
Christian transcendence, a world in which time does not participate in
the eternal, leaving a profane cycle of tenuous stability and more funda-
mental decay. No longer are we to see regimes as solicited into existence
by the final cause or purpose toward which they partially and imper-
fectly arise. The causal priority of the end is replaced by the generative
source in historical happenstance. “These variations of governments,”
as Machiavelli puts it, “arise by chance among men.” The variations
do matter, however, especially when we come to the history of Rome.
373
tyranny
rulers are no longer necessarily the best men but come to “surpass others
in sumptuousness and lasciviousness and every other kind of license.”
The hatred these arrogant libertines provoke in the people leads the
rulers in turn to become more tyrannical. Finally, certain citizens who
surpass the others “in generosity, greatness of spirit, riches and nobility
who were unable to endure the dishonest life of that prince” establish
an aristocratic republic in which “they governed themselves according
to the laws ordered by them, placing the common utility before their
own advantage.”
Now we are at the transition to Phase Two, the transition from the
primitive origin of authority in the prepolitical state of nature to the
cycle of regimes as we know them now, and similar to the typologies
of Plato and Aristotle. The difference is that whereas for Plato and
Aristotle the regimes are present at any time in principle, for Machi-
avelli they are first historically created by those possessing “greatness
of spirit.” In effect, the Platonic and Aristotelian typologies are engen-
dered historically out of the prepolitical state of nature and the primitive
compact. Somewhat as in Book 8 of the Republic, decline sets in after
the original high point of an aristocratic regime devoted to the common
good. However, for Machiavelli, the high point is the regime Socrates
describes as “timocracy” – for Machiavelli, those possessing “great-
ness of spirit.” Socrates’ own version of “aristocracy,” the regime ruled
by philosopher-kings, is absent. Just as Socrates depicts the decline
of regimes as a series of rebellions by less virtuous sons against their
fathers, Machiavelli observes that the children of the aristocracy (his
version of aristocracy, the men possessing generosity, greatness of spirit,
riches, and nobility) succeeded the fathers and turned to “avarice, to
ambition [and] to usurpation of women,” causing the aristocratic gov-
ernment to degenerate into oligarchical oppression. The people rebel
against the oligarchy and institute a popular government. However,
echoing Plato’s strictures against the hedonism and selfishness of popu-
lar government, Machiavelli observes, “it came at once to license, where
neither private men nor public were in fear, and each living in his own
mode, a thousand injuries were done every day.” To escape from anar-
chy, they returned to the government of a prince, starting the cycle over
again.
How does Machiavelli reconcile these accounts? The Sophists usually
stopped at the emergence of laws and government from the dangers of
374
the republic in motion
the prepolitical state of nature. They had little apparent interest in cat-
aloguing the specific characteristics and institutional arrangements of
various regimes (unlike Aristotle, who collected constitutions) because
all were alike in imposing conventional restraints on our selfish natures,
constraints we only obey because we are more afraid of what others
would do to us if these constraints were removed than we are hope-
ful about what we could achieve for ourselves by harming others. By
contrast, the Platonic and Aristotelian accounts assume first and fore-
most that the defining characteristic of a constitution is the specific end
and conception of justice around which its laws, offices, and mores are
organized, and that human nature cannot fulfill itself entirely unless it is
a part of some political community. To understand Machiavelli’s new
synthesis, we must be attentive to the new content with which he tries
to endow these traditional questions.
First of all, in explaining the decline from aristocracy to oligarchy,
democracy, and tyranny, Machiavelli puts more emphasis on violent
usurpation and revolution than did Plato. In Book 8 of the Republic, it
is the dissatisfaction of the sons with the intrinsic motives of their fathers
for practicing virtue that leads to newer and increasingly more lax defini-
tions of virtue. The sons of the timocrats, for example, rebel against their
fathers’ austerity because they believe that they need a certain degree
of wealth to protect their honor from insult and injury, especially from
the many. They begin simply by relaxing some of the restrictions on
private property that Socrates had prescribed for the best regime; only
gradually do they degenerate from this to an exclusive concern with
wealth accumulation. By contrast, Machiavelli stresses that it is the fact
that the sons of the aristocrats have never faced the terrible dangers that
their fathers faced in overthrowing the preconstitutional tyranny that
allows them to degenerate into idle luxury and softness. In this way,
the dire necessity and peril of the first account of the development of
primitive authority out of the state of nature is carried over into the
ostensibly more Platonic discussion of the distinct ends of government.
The primordial passions operative in a grosser way in the first, more
genetic account (the establishment of a “robust” monarchy to secure
survival and safety from random oppression) become the basis for the
changes in the form of the constitution analyzed in the second, more
eidetic account (the genealogy of distinct regimes). In this way, Machi-
avelli develops the maxim from the previous chapter of the Discourses
375
tyranny
about the need for a bracing dose of peril to restore peoples to the vigor
of their virtue. We can surmise in advance that Machiavelli’s diagno-
sis of the very best kind of constitution will find a way of deliberately
introducing a healthy dose of fear and peril to each succeeding genera-
tion, so that “changes of fortune” and “reverses” will prevent the sons
of the aristocrats from degenerating into libertinage and disorder.
Similarly, whereas Plato chronicles the decline from oligarchy to
democracy as the extension of the oligarchs’ concerns with money-
making to the wider populace, who in turn want to start spending
that money on luxuries and enjoying themselves, Machiavelli depicts
this change as a revolution of the people, who are outraged and dis-
gusted at the overbearing power and arrogance of the moneymaking
elite: “This disposition soon produced an avenger, who was sufficiently
well seconded to destroy them.” Again, Machiavelli does not search
for the causes of decline primarily in dissatisfaction with the intrinsic
way of life under one kind of regime as opposed to another. Instead,
he reaches back into the more primitive emotions of fear and outrage
against despotic oppression that characterized the initial development
of order out of the primitive origins, and shows how these continue to
be operative social forces during much later stages of development. We
also observe here the strong and weak sides of “the people” in Machi-
avelli’s view. At their worst, they want libertinage and luxury. At their
best, led by savage and commanding men, they react with anger against
privilege and oppression, and so lend the power of their numbers to
a restoration of the law-bred austerity and severe order that replicate
within the state the adverse necessities that nature imposes on us prior
to the emergence of the state, thus stimulating virtu. Primordial origins
continue to generate political development.
We should note a final echo of the Platonic understanding in Machi-
avelli’s genealogy, in order to see how, beginning with similar obser-
vations about political phenomena, he proceeds in a new and radically
different direction in addressing the problem of the best regime. The
transition from the genetic account of Phase One, which explains the
evolution of rudimentary political order into a patriarchal monarchy
that tries to extend the natural pattern of family life to a larger clan,
to the typology of constitutions properly speaking in Phase Two is,
as we have observed, signaled by the emergence of a minority of men
characterized by “grandeur of soul.” They are the ones who lead the
376
the republic in motion
revolution against the first primitive tyranny and establish the virtuous
republic. In their greatness of soul, wealth, courage, and refusal to be
ruled by despots, they contrast with the “feeble and timid,” presumably
the majority who, without the inspiration and leadership of these rare
men, would have continued to knuckle under, hating the tyrant but pre-
ferring to live under him than to risk their lives in rebellion. It is “under
such powerful leaders” that “the masses armed themselves.” There is a
return here to one of the crucial arguments with which Socrates sought
to persuade Callicles and Glaucon of the inadequacy of the Sophists’
account of justice as a compact made by naturally selfish individuals.
Unlike Antiphon and some of the Sophists who, like Hobbes later,
believed that all people are motivated by self-preservation, Callicles
and Glaucon (like other of the Sophists and their followers) tended
to supplement this unedifying version of the social contract by stress-
ing an important exception to it. They focus on the few “real men”
(andres) who would never have agreed to it in the first place, preferring
always to rule than be ruled and willing to court the consequent dangers
(Gorgias 483; Republic 359a–c). We have observed in earlier chapters
that the Sophists were hampered in giving a fully persuasive account of
the qualities of soul that would characterize such a person, the natu-
ral master who is noble by nature rather than by convention. Because
of their dichotomous distinction between human nature as motivated
by prepolitical drives for survival, power and pleasure, and conven-
tion as uniformly artificial and unconnected with any natural need,
the Sophists had little basis on which to account for the observable
qualities and psychological subtleties of superior statesmanship in the
world around them. They admired power, but they tended to depict it
in crude subpolitical terms: in Callicles’ speech, the natural master is
rather like a petty thief, a stealer of cattle, except that he carries off his
thefts on a grand scale. Only an understanding of everyday observable
politics – its laws, its customs, its education, and the kinds of human
character its principle of justice solicits – can explain how this crude
Herculean master could evolve into a subtle and sophisticated ruler like
Pericles.
By making the city prior to the individual and by arguing that, con-
trary to the Sophists, we cannot understand the nature of the individual
until we understand the soul “writ large” as the city, Socrates can pro-
vide this psychological account of leadership in a far more compelling
377
tyranny
way than can the Sophists. Callicles and Glaucon are both drawn to
tyranny, certainly to being the leading statesman. But they want such
political mastery to entail the noble and admirable qualities of a fully
developed and civilized character – skill at governing, generosity to
friends, a degree of philosophical cultivation, an exposure to the fine
arts, cultivated conversation, and the merited admiration of their fellow
citizens or subjects for doing large and good things for their country.
This erotic longing to find a naturally satisfying way of life within fully
evolved conventional political existence, a way of life that unifies and
consummates the talents and virtues solicited by conventional politi-
cal life, is what Socrates plays upon. He wants to convince them that,
instead of seeing convention as an antonym for nature, a realm of prim-
itive passions and conflict standing across a gulf from an evolved city,
they should join Socrates in searching for a specific set of conventions
that, in contrast with defective sets, allows human nature to fulfill itself
within the politiea in a way that it never could in the subpolitical state
of nature.
A part of this argument is for Socrates to reject the very premise of the
Sophists’ genetic account of nature. The Sophists presented tyranny as a
crude natural force, emerging spontaneously from the “great motions”
issuing from nature construed as necessity and chance, a primordial
strife that is covered over by the unnatural constraints of conven-
tional equality, piety, and law-abidingness. In the Republic, Socrates
gets Glaucon and Adeimantus to agree that, even in its most primitive
origins devoted to bodily self-preservation, the city is never merely a
compact among individuals but is from the outset organized by a divi-
sion of labor based on the objective validity of techne (369a–371a). In
this way, Socrates makes genesis coeval with eidos because the stability
and architectonic ranking of the arts already foreshadow the clarity
and stability of the Ideas toward which all generated phenomena are
drawn in fulfilling their ends. Having introduced a reasonably orga-
nized community into even the most primitive origins of political life,
Socrates proceeds to goad Glaucon into objecting that life in this City
of Sows would lack the urbane grandeur of the erotic passions (372a–
373d). In this way, he encourages Glaucon’s implicit dissatisfaction
with the Sophists’ impoverished psychology while compelling Glaucon
to express his erotic longings within an already agreed-on principle
for distinguishing the passions as clearly as possible from one another
378
the republic in motion
(the division of eros from thumos and desire in the tripartite structure
of the soul) and educating them to find their place within an ordered
community. In sum, Socrates tries to convince Glaucon that his instinct
about tyranny and the greatest passions is correct: they do not come
to light in a primitive prepolitical situation, as the Sophists argued, but
in fact develop rather late, when the political community and its need
for order and rank and its eros for nobility are already fully in place.
This means, however, that in order to clarify his erotic longings, Glau-
con must accept the need for them to be sublimated politically and, if
Socrates is successful, channeled into the service of the common good.
Eros and justice are often enemies, but if Socrates is right, they arise
(“naturally grow”) together enmeshed with nomos (372e).
Machiavelli agrees that only with the emergence of “grandeur of
soul” do we leave the primitive origins and enter the world of developed
political life, statesmanship, and constitutionalism. He also thereby
agrees that grandeur of soul is only inadequately satisfied by the rudi-
mentary authority based on physical survival and security that charac-
terizes the state of nature. Again we see that Machiavelli is aiming for
much higher stakes than merely reverting to the arguments of ancient
Sophistry and materialism. He wants to sketch a new theory of constitu-
tional authority that is complex and refined enough to solicit and satisfy
the fullest political talents and the most subtle sagacity in statecraft, but
without following the Platonic and Aristotelian route whereby the origi-
nal, purely political grandeur of this soul, its pristine vitality and fecun-
dity as it first emerges from the primitive demands of the primordial
origins into the dawning possibilities of consummate might and achieve-
ment, is lured away from these dynamic origins and rich potentiality by
philosophy and moderation. This is why Machiavelli runs together the
constitutions that Plato distinguishes as aristocratic and timocratic – the
rule of philosophers and the rule of the spirited class of warriors – into
his own version of an aristocracy that promotes the common good. With
this he implies that justice and the common good are better served by an
overweening sense of honor and martial prowess than by a moderation
instilled by philosophy or by an education – like that of the Auxiliaries –
that provides a pale imitation of philosophy. Precisely the vigor, even
the belligerence, of the warriors is needed to combat the corruption and
libertinage toward which the people, if left to their own devices, are
disposed.
379
tyranny
380
the republic in motion
381
tyranny
382
the republic in motion
Callicles and Glaucon admire before they are subjected to the Socratic
elenchus and its attempt to implant an education in moderation in their
characters. For Plato, restraint can come only to the extent that the
savagery of thumos is tamed by civic education or by an eros ultimately
devoted to philosophy. For Machiavelli, restraint is maintained by the
general necessity, the overwhelming peril, at the heart of existence,
which can be replicated by severe laws that admit of no exception to
their discipline. In this way, moderation becomes lawfulness, a deeroti-
cized kind of control. It is not, as in Platonic statecraft, the orderliness
that the pursuit of substantive satisfaction confers on the soul as its pas-
sions are drawn off from grosser objects of satisfaction toward higher,
more lasting ones, but the general necessity imposed on the passions by
the overwhelmingly powerful primordial genesis in which the passions
themselves are rooted, the Godlike singularity of Fortuna.
Moreover, to recall our general thesis about Machiavelli first
broached in Chapter 1, to the extent that Machiavelli fully liberates
thumos as a passion, he presupposes its rigorous subjection to the impo-
sition of order on nature by the will. Whereas Plato attempts to restrain
thumos within the harmony of the affects ordered by reason so that its
openness to honor and the divine might flourish, Machiavelli liberates
it only after entirely bestializing it.
Thus prudent legislators, knowing the vices of each of these modes of gov-
ernment by themselves, have chosen one that should partake of all of them,
judging that to be the most stable and solid. In fact, when there is combined
under the same constitution a prince, a nobility, and the power of the people,
then these three powers will watch and keep each other reciprocally in check.
383
tyranny
this is the constitution that can best achieve the minimal requirements
for a stable political association, ameliorating the explosive tensions
between rich and poor that tend to cause the greatest civil unrest.
By mixing the principles of two defective constitutions, oligarchy and
democracy, Aristotle sketches a constitution that combines the inclu-
siveness of the democratic claim to authority with the meritocracy of the
oligarchical claim, while weakening the one-sidedness of each party’s
claim (for, although democrats are right to say men are equal, they are
not equal in all respects, and although oligarchs are right to say they are
unequal, they are not unequal in all respects, nor is superiority in wealth
tantamount to superiority in all virtue). A moderate middle class of the
least rich and the least poor will elect magistrates based on merit with
perhaps a small property qualification, leading to a deliberative govern-
ing body that may in the course of time deserve to be called aristocratic
(Politics 1294a35–b14). Aristotle identifies this particular constitution
by the generic term “constitution” (politeia) because it is the pattern for
reform that most existing cities have a chance of actually implementing.
It takes care of stability by reducing class conflict and allows a relatively
high degree of public virtue to emerge. Machiavelli’s remark that “all
kinds of government are defective” is a direct gloss on Aristotle’s intro-
duction to the discussion of the mixed constitution in Books 3 and 4
of the Politics, for Aristotle observes that each of the six archetypal
constitutions, even the good ones, tends to define authority too sharply
and exclusively, limiting it too narrowly to one portion of the body
politic and thus provoking indignation and a feeling of being exploited
in those who do not share in it. From the viewpoint of including as
many people of sufficient virtue (if not the highest degree of virtue)
for self-government as possible, “all such constitutions,” Aristotle also
concludes, “are defective” (1283a23–29).
Once again, Machiavelli’s employment of a traditional rubric of
statecraft is a carapace under which he radically alters its content. For
it must be stressed that Machiavelli’s illustration of a successful mixed
constitution is not Aristotle’s “polity,” but Lycurgus’s constitution for
Sparta, a constitution that Aristotle criticizes as being on the whole
wrong-headed (Politics 1270a29–1271b20, 1324b5–15, 1333b5–20).
When Aristotle recommends mixing and blending antagonistic political
forces, this is because he believes the debate between democrats and oli-
garchs implies, even at its most heatedly partisan, an implicit possibility
384
the republic in motion
385
tyranny
386
the republic in motion
and for thereby abandoning from the outset any hope that these con-
tending factions could be educated to transcend their passions so that
they could deliberate in common according to logos about the meaning
of the just and unjust, thus fulfilling their natures as political animals:
And because the [ephorate] was too powerful, and equal to a tyranny, the
kings were also compelled to cultivate popular favor, so that in this way
too the constitution was jointly injured, for out of an aristocracy came to be
evolved a democracy. (1270b6–17)
[The] lawgiver clearly does the same here as in the rest of the constitution: he
makes the citizens ambitious and has used this for the election of the elders,
for nobody would ask for office if he were not ambitious; yet surely ambition
and love of money are the motives that bring about almost the greatest part of
wrongdoing that takes place among mankind . . . (It) would be advantageous
that kings should not be appointed as they are now, but chosen in each case
with a regard to their own life and conduct. But it is clear that even the
lawgiver himself does not suppose that he can make the kings men of high
character: at all events he distrusts them as not being persons of sufficient
worth. (1271a9–26)
387
tyranny
10 I substantially agree with Sullivan’s argument (2004) that Machiavelli’s prescription for
institutional checks and balances within a republic so as to preserve the liberties of both
the common people and the great, while harnessing their competitive energies for the
mutual aggrandizement of all, is central both to the English Republicanism of the sev-
enteenth century and to more explicitly liberal thinkers like Locke. For reasons I discuss
at greater length in the Conclusion, I have a more difficult time reconciling Hobbes with
either stream, especially the republican one, because his theory of absolute sovereignty
would rob political life of the republican dynamism Harrington and others admired
in Machiavelli’s view of Rome, while his defense of individualism on the grounds of
mere self-preservation eschews any need for a self-governing commonwealth, the brunt
of Locke’s critique. As Mansfield observes with respect to Machiavelli’s republicanism,
but in a way that could also anticipate the proceduralism of the prescription for the
American founding, “The business of government is not so much positive legislation to
benefit the people as the negative exchange of accusations that entertains the people.
While making use of ambitious princes, republics must take care to appease the popular
fear and dislike of ambition.” Mansfield in Machiavelli (1996) p. xxix.
388
the republic in motion
389
tyranny
390
the republic in motion
391
tyranny
392
the republic in motion
imported goods: “Thus they have been prevented from adopting either
French, Spanish or Italian customs, and these nations are the great
a corrupt city – not to spoil it entirely as did Caesar but to reorder it as did Romu-
lus.” True glory comes from reshaping and reinvigorating the fallen matter of nature.
However, as long as princes long for the glory of the “imagined republics,” of “the
writers” like Xenophon and his depiction of Cyrus, they will choose the path of Caesar
and corrupt the people. What era could be more corrupt, on Machiavelli’s arguments,
than Machiavelli’s own, the nadir of effemination? The new prince will have his work
cut out for him but also a perhaps unprecedented prospect for achieving “the glory of
the world.”
In chapter 19 of The Prince, there is a parallel discussion to the one in the Discourses
of the good emperors. Whereas in the Discourses he stresses that the Antonines were
good rulers compared with the fallen period before and after them inaugurated by
Caesar, in this context, in which the focus is more on the virtue of the singular prince
than on republican statesmen, he is less critical of their successors, especially Septimius
Severus, whom he praises for astutely embodying the qualities of the lion and the
fox. Severus was able to keep the soldiers, the nobles, and the people in line through
a judicious mixture of terror and rewards, leaving them “astonished and stupefied,”
similar to the words (“satisfied and stupefied”) he used to describe Cesare Borgia’s
effect on the Romagna by using Remiro d’Orco to crush disorder and then executing
him and leaving his dismembered body in the public square, thereby terrifying the people
through an intermediary and satisfying their hatred of that intermediary by killing him
(as Stalin did with successive secret police chiefs). Moreover, Severus recognized that,
if forced to choose between satisfying the soldiers and the people, one must choose the
soldiers, because one needs their power more, whereas today (in Machiavelli’s own era)
rulers must please the people because they are more powerful than the soldiers, who
are often mercenaries. It might appear from this praise of Severus that Machiavelli is
qualifying his remark in the Discourses that the people form the soundest basis for rule:
“As regards prudence, I say that the people are more prudent and stable, and have better
judgement than a prince; and it is not without good reason that it is said, ‘the voice of
the people is the voice of God’” (1.58). However, we must bear in mind that, in that
particular context in the Discourses, he is offering a prescription for a healthy republic
like early Rome. Here in The Prince, by contrast, he is talking about a ruler’s need
to be cruel when “the body which you choose to maintain you . . . is corrupt.” Corrupt
republics and principalities both need founders or refounders who can reinvigorate them
through a jolt of harshness and terror. Hence, in the context of the corrupt period after
the end of the Antonines, a terrifying ruler like Severus was best. The main foil for the
cruel and cunning Severus in this chapter is the gentle Marcus Aurelius, who, because
he came at the end of a comparatively uncorrupt era, was able to satisfy the people,
nobles, and soldiers without such harsh measures.
Putting the discussion of the Antonines in The Prince and the Discourses together,
then, we arrive at the following rank order: the ancient Roman Republic was the least
corrupt of the Roman regimes, the principate founded by Caesar and Augustus the
most corrupt, and the Antonine emperors an interval of relatively less corruption –
more corrupt than the republic, but less corrupt than Caesar’s principate – after which
the Caesarian era’s corruption resumed and required much harsher measures.
In a moment of wry humor in chapter 19 of The Prince, Machiavelli refers to Marcus
Aurelius as “Marcus the Philosopher.” When we recall that Marcus broke the chain of
393
tyranny
elected emperors that Machiavelli saw as the Antonine age’s finest feature and returned
to the Julio-Claudian practice of hereditary emperors, destroying the interval of peace
and security by allowing his own worthless son Commodus to inherit the throne, we
realize that even a philosopher is not capable of doing what the ancients always say we
should do, that is, placing the good of the political community over the love of one’s
own, especially love of family.
394
the republic in motion
one system the hostilities that the good regimes in Aristotle’s typol-
ogy sought to transcend. Of the two approaches, however, Machiavelli
prefers Sparta, for “Athens lived a very short time in respect to Sparta”
(1.2). Aristotle had judged the Spartan constitution to be worthwhile
only at a relatively low level of human merit. In the Nicomachean Ethics,
courage, Sparta’s chief virtue, is one of the two lowest-ranked virtues of
character (along with bodily continence), because courage stems from
the compulsion to survive when faced with the threat of death and so
cannot not be chosen, whereas higher virtues lacking in Sparta such as
liberality are not compelled by self-interest and involve a greater degree
of choice as to how they are actualized (Nicomachean Ethics 1119a20–
b13, 1111b1–1112a11). For Aristotle, Sparta’s longevity and stability
certainly entitled it to a measure of commendation, if rather sparse.
Characteristically, what for the ancients represented the lowest level of
political virtue that they could admit into the discussion of the proper
aims of government represents for Machiavelli the only element of their
pragmatism that is worth salvaging. Hence Lycurgus merits discussion
and high praise in Machiavelli’s consideration of the various regime
principles, whereas Aristotle is not even mentioned by name.
Machiavelli’s preferred solution to the defectiveness of all the regime
principles lies in a new direction, a combination that could not be envi-
sioned by the classical tradition regardless of whether it was talking of
high standards or low ones: “The disunion which existed between the
Senate and the people produced such extraordinary events that chance
did for her what the founder had failed to do” (1.2.7). Rome was per-
fected by “her” disunity. The very forces of change and strife, the strug-
gle for power, prestige, and wealth, that the ancients had thought made
political unity (to say nothing of perfection) difficult if not impossi-
ble become, in Machiavelli’s prescription, their only sure basis. Unlike
Sparta, the Roman constitution developed over time, so that it was
not cut off from the shifts of fortune. Unlike Athens, Rome did not
fruitlessly substitute one type of constitution for another. It retained
whatever proved useful from past experience and incorporated it into
the new forms that necessity prompted. Thus, to expand on an ealier
observation, after the monarchy was overthrown, “those who expelled
it immediately appointed two consuls in place of the king.” This pre-
vented the senatorial class from wielding absolute power. Similarly, the
people extracted from the aristocracy the creation of the office of the
395
tyranny
13 For example, the Romans turned the Tarquinian kingship of pre-Republican times into
the purely ceremonial “king of the sacrifices,” so that the people would not have to miss
the old rituals. Republics should preserve a semblance of traditional forms even when
their content has changed, “so that it may seem to the people that there has been no
change in the institutions, even though in fact they are different. For the great majority of
mankind are satisfied with appearances, as though they were realities, and are often even
more influenced by the things that seem than by those that are” (1.25). The phraseology
recalls the maxim from chapter 18 of The Prince: “Everyone sees how you appear, few
touch what you are.” On the character of the Hegelian historical dialectic, see Newell
(2009a).
396
the republic in motion
into being and back into which they pass away, a republic like Rome
can survive its own dissolution again and again, gaining new strength
each time. For the primordial underpinnings out of which these legal
and institutional forms emerge and into which they eventually collapse
is the life force of the acquisitive, expansionist republic itself. By tapping
into the disorder at the heart of existence, by letting itself be energized
by the clash of natural and political bodies, such a republic cannot be
undone by a reliance on any permanent form. Rather than attempt to
approximate the stable unity of the whole, such a constitution leaps into
the void of its own untutored impulses, developing itself in response to
perilous necessity by continual self-division and supersession. It opens
itself up to Fortuna, lets Fortuna provoke it to develop new techniques
and institutions: “Fortune favored her” because Rome’s virtues always
arose fresh from the crucible of the direst necessity. In this sense Rome
took the same stance toward Fortuna collectively that, as we discussed
in Chapter 6, Machiavelli prescribes for the individual prince.
Aristotle had criticized Lycurgus for assuming that people were inca-
pable of voluntary goodness. Machiavelli now states that one must
always “start with assuming that all men are bad and ever ready to dis-
play their vicious nature.” In this way, the Christian doctrine of original
sin, one of whose consequences is that perfection cannot be aimed for
through participating in political life, is now secularized so that, once
drained of its otherworldly orientation, it can be used as human material
for a new kind of political perfection, not through the teleological flow-
ering of the soul but, on the contrary, through its suppression. “People
are good,” as Machiavelli has told us, “only upon compulsion.” The
freedom to choose without compulsion – for Aristotle, what chiefly
distinguishes the human telos from that of other biological organisms
(Nicomachean Ethics 1097b25–1098a15) – always leads to “confusion
and disorder.” Summing up his earlier advice, Machiavelli reminds us
that, where the hostility of nature manifested by “poverty and hunger”
does not directly force men to become industrious, “the law immediately
becomes necessary” to replicate artificially nature’s spontaneous sever-
ity. The division and clash of powers within the Roman Republic kept
the law’s capacity to compel virtuous behavior constantly fresh and vig-
orous. The Senate and the People, the one constantly vying to dominate
and the other constantly struggling not to be dominated, imposed neces-
sity on each other recurrently through their ongoing struggles. Each thus
397
tyranny
kept the other strong and orderly, preventing either one from lapsing
into luxury, enervation, and laxity, and thereby kept each other’s pas-
sions keen. Disciplined repeatedly by this internal battle, the ambitions
of each class expended themselves on foreign conquest, not on each
other. The Senate led the people into war, recompensing them with a
share of land and riches, albeit frequently extracted from the aristocracy
by the people under threat of insurrection or desertion. Swollen with
new allies and tributaries, the Republic’s increased numbers pressed
outward to a new perimeter of expansion, vitality maintained by the
ongoing domestic class struggle.
Machiavelli is emphatic that he does not make these arguments
because he is in favor of mindless, widespread violence and bloodshed
for their own sake. On the contrary, he observes that during the three
hundred years in which the nobles and people fashioned the division
of powers among Senate, consuls, and tribunes in a series of truces in
their struggles for predominance, only a handful of people were exiled
or put to death. In Machiavelli’s view, letting ambitions contend with
one another is the likeliest way of preventing them from destroying the
republic. They check each other’s success internally and bring power,
stability, and prosperity to the weaker states that are absorbed. The
chaos, violence, and partisan hatred is much worse, he maintains, in
states like Athens precisely because each party believes that the con-
stitutional ordering it wants represents an approximation of the final,
unchanging truth about the universe. It therefore places an intolerable
burden on the self-interest and honor of those whom it excludes, and
in the course of time on the repressed ambitions of the ruling class itself
(as we saw so vividly illustrated by the rebellion of the young aristocrats
in Xenophon’s Education of Cyrus).
As we have observed, Machiavelli notes that the traditional writers
on government have always criticized the example of Rome for its “tur-
bulence and disorder,” claiming that only “extreme good fortune” pre-
vented these defects from destroying her. Machiavelli suspects that “all
these things can only alarm those who read of them” – that what really
scandalizes the traditional-minded critics of Rome is not the violence of
the republic’s actual history, which was minimal, but the way in which
the actual basis for Rome’s success so manifestly contradicts their belief
that political life must reflect the stability and repose divined in the order
of the cosmos by philosophy and philosophical morality. Machiavelli
398
the republic in motion
agrees with the ancients that a republic needs “good education,” which
depends, in turn, on “good laws.” Good laws, he continues, spring in
turn “from those agitations which have been so inconsiderately con-
demned by many,” rather than, as the ancient philosophers would have
prescribed, mirroring the eternal orderliness and moderation of the cos-
mos. In truth, he concludes, “every free state ought to afford the people
the opportunity of giving vent, so to say, to their ambition.” For “the
demands of a free people are rarely pernicious to their liberty.” Whereas
the ancients hoped an education in virtue would teach people to tran-
scend to some degree the necessities operative on human nature through
the passions, Machiavelli believes that the best education for statecraft
is an experience of how the passions clash and how these clashes might
be harnessed to maximize security and prosperity for the state.
Still, however much Machiavelli might appeal to hard-headed com-
mon sense and an experience of the real world, this rhetorical stance
should not lead us to overlook the fact that a kind of theoretical guid-
ance and character formation for princes and statesmen is as crucial
to Machiavelli’s new science of politics as it was to that of the classics,
albeit with a radical transvaluation of content from ends toward means,
or from the teleological fulfillment of nature to its methodical control.
As we have previously seen at some length in Machiavelli’s diagno-
sis of the ills of politics, people in fact are often more spontaneously
inclined to the deluded belief in the “imagined republics” of classical
and religious morality than they are to a clear-headed assessment of
how to achieve their own self-interest. Before Machiavelli’s successors
can appeal to Realpolitik, or to the “real world” as opposed to the
mere “ideals” of justice and community extolled by the ancients, the
real world first has to be completely altered in how it is perceived by
statesmen and citizens. Machiavelli is a “writer” who aims to undo
the spell of the traditional “writers.” “Reality,” the observable world,
has to be theoretically reconstructed so as to yield the proper theory
of politics from observation. Otherwise, the siren song of Platonic eros
and Christian otherworldliness will continue to beckon, which to its
adherents is every bit as much observable from experience as is the
reality of self-interest. Here we can anticipate a famous conundrum of
early modern rationality: does Bacon derive his project for the mastery
of nature from his observations about nature, or does he arrange his
observations about nature to justify and render possible our mastery of
399
tyranny
it? Does Hobbes derive his teaching on power and the social contract
from the new physics of matter in motion? Or does he append the new
physics as a preface so as to ground in natural philosophy an approach
to politics primarily derived from observation and history but further
buttressed by this theoretical reconstruction of observable reality? We
explore these issues in the Conclusion to this book.
To recall Machiavelli’s question: Would it have been possible for the
Romans to have established a government that, following the classical
prescription, put an end to this constant struggle between nobles and
people? Machiavelli explores this question in order to sum up the results
of his cumulative undermining of the traditional rubrics of political
philosophy. Again we are presented with the two alternatives of Sparta
and Rome. As Machiavelli presents Sparta here, it embodies the closest
historical approximation of the classical prescription for the best con-
stitution that both Plato and Aristotle advanced: She was strong enough
to defend herself, but not so powerful as to provoke her neighbors. Her
laws discouraged commerce and encouraged an austere equality, which
helped make her unattractive to foreign aggressors seeking riches, in
turn keeping the internal temptation to war and glory-seeking at bay.
If, he writes, such as state
remains quiet within her borders, and experience shows that she entertains
no ambitious projects, the fear of her power will never prompt anyone to
attack her; and this would even be more certainly the case if her constitution
and laws prohibited all aggrandizement.
And I certainly think that if she could be kept in this equilibrium, it would
be the best political existence, and would insure to any city real tranquility.
But as all human things are kept in a perpetual movement, and can never
remain stable, cities naturally either rise or decline, and necessity compels
them to many acts to which reason will not influence them . . . (1.6.4).
As the use of Sparta as his example reveals, Machiavelli will not even
grant that the ancient thinkers were able to grasp what kind of republic
400
the republic in motion
401
tyranny
If (Rome) had been more tranquil, it would necessarily have resulted that
she would have been more feeble, and that she would have lost with her
energy also the ability of achieving that high degree of greatness to which
she attained; so that to have removed the cause of trouble from Rome would
have been to deprive her of her power of expansion. (1.6.3)
when they regret their error it will be too late to bring him down (1.33). This could be
a description of Xenophon’s Cyrus.
402
the republic in motion
403
tyranny
404
the republic in motion
call for and honor their best talents of enterprise and command, a city
whose love would be worth possessing and whose nobility would be
worth loving. Having stimulated an erotic longing for union with the
beautiful and good through political eminence, Socrates then attempts
to convince them that only a moderate political order mirroring the
cosmic order glimpsed by philosophy will offer their eros an approxi-
mation of the repose and dignity for which it yearns – a public philia
complementing the moderation of private friendship, a reciprocal bond
between honorable equals rather than the all-consuming passion of the
tyrant to possess one’s country as a triumphant lover would possess his
beloved. In the very best instance, these lovers of the city will be led by
their eros for the beautiful and good through civic virtue toward the
philosophic life itself, the noblest of all.
It is precisely the instinct for “grandeur” characteristic of men like
Callicles and Glaucon that Machiavelli denies can ever be conjoined
with such a moderate political ordering. As we have seen, however,
the root of the problem lies in the potential for misunderstanding this
grandeur that exists in the “princely” type of men themselves. Because it
is human nature to seek satisfaction and tranquility, to follow the erotic
longing for completion, it is all too easy to persuade oneself that the
world has already provided such a safe haven; that one must only mod-
erate one’s passions and bring one’s own behavior into accordance with
this eternally preexisting unity and harmony in order to be successful
and happy. The princely men must therefore be taught not to let them-
selves be taught about this promised ascent from bodily desires to noble
pleasures, a hierarchy of goods mirroring the order of the world. They
need method rather than eros; self-consciousness rather than the elab-
orate civic pedagogy suggested by the Republic, Nicomachean Ethics,
and other traditional writings. They must reach deeper into the primor-
dial underpinnings of their first, unmediated impulses for success and
glory. They must learn that this vital potentiality for grandeur springs
from the dynamism and the creativity of disorder, not from the enerva-
tion of a delusory success, and so come to see that their best prospect
for achieving it is conjoined with an imperial republic whose achieve-
ments are constantly fueled and invigorated by its capacity to tap into
the disorder of nature through its institutionalized strife. That is why
“the greatness of its empire could not corrupt it for many centuries,
and (Rome’s lawgivers) maintained it full of as much virtue as has ever
405
tyranny
406
the republic in motion
15 Consider Tawney (1950) and Grant (1991). The complex debate about the meaning
or existence of Machiavelli’s religiosity is discussed in the Interlude at the end of this
chapter.
407
tyranny
into the body politic to jolt it out of the enervation and complacency
of too long a period of success. In this way, the regime becomes a local
historical modality of the law, and the distinction between good and
bad regimes is replaced by the criterion of legitimacy.
To collapse the distinction between good and bad regimes as Machi-
avelli does might seem to restore ancient conventionalism. Although
there are similarities between Machiavelli’s argument and ancient con-
ventionalism, there are, as we have seen, more important differences,
and as we reach the conclusion of this book, it will be useful to sum-
marize them schematically.
According to the Sophists, one can react to the meaning of nature as
chance by 1) private vice and the manipulation of convention through
rhetoric to create a public appearance of virtue, 2) the defense of con-
vention as a bulwark against the chaos of the state of nature, or 3)
embracing tyranny as the most natural way of life. But because the
Sophists tend to see nature as the upsurge of spontaneous motions,
they doubt that it can be methodically controlled on the political level.
Those who claim that it can run into difficulties. Hence, for example,
Thraysmachus’s search for a techne of injustice is frustrated by Socrates’
demonstration that techne is self-forgetting, not self-aggrandizing, and
leads to order, harmony, and beneficence. Protagoras, more insightful,
doubts that statecraft is rigorous knowledge at all, seeing it as more
akin to a local “way,” like picking up a language, analogous perhaps
to Burkean “prejudice.”
Machiavelli is after much bigger stakes than any of these varieties of
ancient conventionalism. In his new science of politics, the disorder of
nature is the source of political power, stability, and rationality. It can
be tapped and channeled by correctly designed institutions. By imitating
the impetuosity of Fortuna, we can gain methodical control over “her”
reverses by anticipating them, preempting them and fighting back. It is
the belief in fixed conventions – in political order – that leads to decay,
chaos, and weakness and does not, as Protagoras maintained, act as a
bulwark against them. So chance (tuche) does not have to be fenced
off or concealed under a rhetorical guise that preserves nomos. Instead,
Machiavelli says: Let chance in; let selective spurts of chaos invigorate
and set in motion the levers of power. Statecraft will be more methodical
and more consistent if we allow politics to be empowered by disorder.
We need not be helpless in the face of the rise and decline of regimes
408
the republic in motion
409
tyranny
balancing of passions like eros and thumos, while vicious and tyranni-
cal acts stem from (while aggravating) their disharmony. Both virtuous
and vicious acts take place within the boundaries of nature. You can be
educated to pursue eros toward its highest objects, civic virtue and phi-
losophy, thereby directing eros away from tyrannical excesses, but you
cannot extirpate it or step outside of nature. Thumos can be kept at bay
through laws and education, but not overcome or jettisoned. The thu-
motic man of Platonic psychology is angry, moralistic, self-righteous,
and prone to religious zealotry. For Machiavelli, therefore, he is not
cold-blooded and focused enough; too much lion, not enough fox. He
requires, not paideia, but the correct method.
iii. By draining the natural world of transcendental purpose and plac-
ing it in the otherworldly Beyond, a certain strain of Christianity already
reduces nature to Fortuna. Once we part ways with our loyalty to that
otherworldly kingdom, we can allow the natural world of purposeless
happenstance already drained of teleological purpose by Christianity
itself to empower us with its sheer force and impulse. These passions
contain no immanent potential for transcendence. Not only can we aim
to control the external world, but we can treat our own inner passions
as pure other, pure foe, or energy to be imprisoned until needed.
In these ways, then, Machiavelli prepares a new synthesis. Reason
can and should still govern the city, just as Plato and Aristotle main-
tain. Viewing nature as genesis does not require us to view politics as
tragic in the sense that chance and necessity must doom the reason of
the statesman, as in Oedipus Tyrannus. The assimilation of reason to
willpower promises to free man altogether from nature, or at least to an
extraordinarily greater degree than anything envisioned by the classics.
The rational clarity of the Platonic Ideas becomes the goal to be imposed
on nature by the willpower of the Abrahamic God’s efficient cause, the
power to create ex nihilo, transferred to the secular prince. Because
Machiavelli is not simply seeking to restore classical wisdom, even
its strictly pragmatic political wisdom in contradistinction to its tran-
scendentalist leanings, but is calling for a wholesale transformation of
human and political life and how we understand them, he cannot in my
view be strictly termed an Averroist. More on this later in the chapter.16
16 Lukes (1984) makes the simple but telling observation that, despite his admiration for
Roman courage as opposed to modern pacificity, and for the Romans’ always being
410
the republic in motion
411
tyranny
18 For a thoughtful discussion of the paradox whereby Rome engenders its own subversion,
consider Coby (1999).
19 As Strauss comments, the omission of Jerusalem reveals the rhetorical quality of Machi-
avelli’s reverence for antiquity, because the “Mosaic laws and orders” are arguably “of
the most ancient antiquity.” Strauss (1969) p. 93.
412
the republic in motion
under the empire and inhabited its dead husk when it fell, replicat-
ing its universal political order as a universal eccleisiastical order (The
Prince chapter 12). In Discourses 2.2, Machiavelli begins by making
a sharp distinction between the pagan religion of Rome and “our”
religion: the Roman religion promotes glory, whereas our religion pro-
motes humility. (He had earlier observed in 1.11 that “whoever reads
Roman history attentively will see in how great a degree religion served
in the command of the armies, in uniting the people and keeping them
well conducted, and in covering the wicked with shame.”) He qual-
ifies the contrast between Rome’s religion and “ours” by going on
to suggest that it is a false interpretation of Christianity to conclude
that it must inevitably make us effeminate and unable to defend our
country: “And although the world appears to be made effeminate and
heaven disarmed, it arises without doubt more from the cowardice of
the men who have interpreted our religion according to idleness and not
according to virtue” (2.2.2). He then suggests another reason for this
effeminization, which shows that there is a link between Rome and the
humility-saturated version of Christianity he decries. Through her con-
quests, Rome extinguished republican liberty everywhere (“eliminated
all republics and all civil ways of life”). By extinguishing the spirit of
liberty everywhere, the Roman Empire effeminated itself and prevented
the world’s virtue from finding a new imperial homeland. Finally, in
Discourses 3.1, Machiavelli remarks that all religious republics will
decay with time unless returned periodically to the vigor of the orig-
inal rise by recurrent refoundings. Although the notion of a religious
republic might seem to refer exclusively to modern Christian states,
Rome, too, was a religious republic – religion was essential to its suc-
cess, according to Machiavelli – and the examples he uses to illustrate
the need for re-founding are drawn from Rome as well as from modern
times. In 3.17, in remarking that officials could commit outrages even
during the early republic when Rome “was still uncorrupt,” he con-
cludes that “it is impossible to order a perpetual republic because its
ruin is caused through a thousand unexpected ways.” Although every-
thing possible should be done to return a republic to the vigor of its
origins, there is nothing more true than that “all the things of this world
have a limit to their existence” (3.1).
Altogether, then, Machiavelli appears to concede that all republics
will eventually wane. Even the best-founded republic of all, Rome,
413
tyranny
whose religion was subordinate to, and a means toward, civic vigor
and patriotism, eventually succumbed to its own inner decay. How
likely is it, then, that any virtuous republic founded now, in a world
already under the sway of Christianity, which for Machiavelli not only
does not support citizen virtue and patriotism but actively undermines
it, could avoid this eventual decay, if indeed it could ever be founded in
the first place?
Machiavelli’s writings do contain one possible response to this
dilemma, an adaptation of certain strains of Christian political theory
and especially that of the emerging Reformation. Machiavelli’s stric-
tures against Christianity are abundant and well known: it has effem-
inated man, subverted his loyalty to the earthly fatherland in favor of
the heavenly beyond, and extolled unarmed prophets who fail instead
of armed ones who succeed. Yet clearly Christianity was in some sense
“armed.” As an institutional religion, it had been a great success. As
Machiavelli sardonically notes in chapter 11 of The Prince, only eccle-
siastical authorities “have states and do not defend them; have subjects
and do not govern them; and the states, though ungoverned, do not
care.” Yet rule they did. Christ’s teaching might have been “unarmed,”
and thus brought the unarmed prophet Savanarola to ruin, but could
one really characterize it altogether as a political failure, given its enor-
mous authority over the centuries as the civilizational conglomerate of
Christendom? In The Prince, Machiavelli diagnoses the rise of institu-
tionalized Christendom as the church slowly replaced the decaying husk
of the Roman world state with a spiritual world state of its own, pri-
marily based on moral authority but nonetheless equipped with some
worldly force.
The crucial element in the Christian spiritual world state’s power was
its psychological hold over the faithful. This insulated it against many
of the dangers of its otherwise feckless pursuit of worldly power and
allowed ruthless popes like Alexander VI – arguably one of the most
successful statesmen of Machiavelli’s era, the master pulling the strings
of his son Cesare – to operate free of censure or a candid grasp by
others of what they really were. Christianity’s psychological hold also
undermined the effectiveness of men like Cesare, who would have been
capable in the ancient world of any iniquity, yet whose capacity for
“well-used” cruelty was rendered fickle and inconsistent by his residual
vulnerability to a belief in Christian morality. Similarly, the King of
414
the republic in motion
415
tyranny
21 According to Tinsley, Luther “became convinced that the ‘imitation’ of Christ conflicted
with the essence of the Christian gospel as he had come to interpret it. He found himself
unable to reconcile the presuppositions of the practice of the imitation of Christ with
his doctrine of justification by faith. The imitation of Christ he believed must inevitably
involve a denial of grace and conceal an incipient doctrine of works.” Tinsley (1972)
pp. 45–67.
416
the republic in motion
417
tyranny
underlying atomic structure, and how the clash of atoms generates infi-
nite, utterly irreconcilable worlds, introduces an undertow of insupera-
ble necessity and limitation to his view of the world and an insuperable
limit on man’s power to master Fortuna absolutely, however much he
might radically reshape it. The new prince may indeed be able to intro-
duce form into matter, but not create or re-create matter itself. He may
be able, through the introduction of “new modes and orders,” to trans-
form the conditions of political existence right down to the ground, but
not of existence per se.
Returning to the relationship between Machiavelli’s republican pre-
scription and America, might it not be the case at present that, as
America extends its power, influence, and economic might to the fur-
thest reaches of the globe, two challenges are emerging to the empire’s
sway that Machiavelli would immediately recognize? On the margins
of the empire, hardier and angrier peoples who have either not tasted
the promised material benefits or despise them are stoking the fires of
communal honor and a fear of being overwhelmed. These are motives
that, as we have seen, Machiavelli certainly appreciates as preconditions
for the continued rise of healthy and vigorous republics into a greater
historical sphere. More significantly, within the population of the impe-
rial heartland itself, there is arguably growing an ever more powerful
counterfactual longing for a global peace, a universal society “beyond”
politics with its unedifying compromises and clash of interests – the
parallel of that “effemination” that Machiavelli was obliged to concede
was inevitable even for Rome. Within today’s imperial republic, during
the apparently endless sunny noon of its Antonine age, with the legions
securing the borders and unprecedented wealth and relaxation enjoyed
within them, the citizens grow ever more bored with the republican
hardhihood of their origins, ever more enervated through their hedo-
nistic satiation, and ever more attracted to the dream of that coming
global paradise when all conflict will end forever.
So there is a sense in which Machiavelli not only showed the route to
the new Rome but foresaw its downward spiral. Machiavelli thought
that Rome had contained “as much virtue as has ever adorned any other
city or republic” and hoped that the rise to such greatness could begin
again. However, he knew that even Rome would have to atrophy due to
her very success and that even the methodical and conscious imitation of
her spontaneous career would carry the danger of this same long-term
418
the republic in motion
23 Compare Augustine’s description of the man who is totally immersed in the City of
Man as opposed to the man who lives on earth preparing for the City of God (1958)
pp. 87–88.
419
tyranny
conflation of the prince with the prophet of godlike will with respect to
his discussion of the “one prudent orderer” exemplified by Lycurgus:
“If Machiavelli had not specified one man so prudent, he could have
been speaking of a divine beginning at one stroke” ([2001] p. 33).
Such a “prince” (the ancients may have called him a tyrant, but
Machiavelli will not) like David or Philip of Macedon (a typical Machi-
avellian equation of a divinely anointed ruler with a pagan one) will
raze everything and build everything anew, make the poor rich and
the rich poor, and resettle populations like a herdsman moving his
flocks. The biblical quote Machiavelli uses to describe David is actually
a description of God himself: “(He) filled the hungry with good things
and sent the rich away hungry” (Luke 1.53). This appears both to con-
firm the godlike scope of the most virtuous prince and to imply that
God himself is a tyrant. Whoever does not have the stomach for ruling
in this godlike and “very cruel” way, Machiavelli recommends, should
remain a citizen reliant on the rule of law and established institutions.
Few are wise enough to do so, however, becoming either ineffectual
tyrants or lukewarm citizens, because “men generally decide upon a
middle course, which is most hazardous, for they know neither how
to be entirely good nor entirely bad.” This choice between civic virtue
and tyranny reminds us of the contrast between Sparta’s caution and
Rome’s boldness, the only true alternatives in contrast with the illu-
sion of the “middle way.” If the citizen as described here might parallel
Sparta in the earlier discussion, might the godlike tyrant parallel the
Roman Republic? For although good to its own people and those taken
on as allies, did not Rome, in addition to being founded by just such a
tyrant, in conquering others perform many of the same acts of destruc-
tion, resettlement, and the transfer of wealth attributed here to David
and Phillip of Macedon?
As another instance of almost cavalier blasphemy, let us take Cesare
Borgia’s use, praised by Machiavelli in chapter 7 of The Prince, of his
brutal lieutenant Remiro d’Orca. After employing Remiro to suppress
civil disorder, allowing Remiro to attract the people’s hatred while
insulating himself from it, Cesare, peace having been restored, acts
as the people’s avenger against his own enforcer: “He had (Remiro)
placed one morning in the piazza . . . in two pieces, with a piece of
wood and a bloody knife beside him. The ferocity of this spectacle left
the people at once satisfied and stupefied.” Is a bizarre pantomime of
420
the republic in motion
Christianity implied here? That is, God, the source of so many woes and
disappointments for his people, distances himself from them through
an intermediary who then dies for “their” sins, but tacitly satisfies the
people by allowing them to take revenge on him through the crucifixion
of his intermediary.
But we cannot leave it at pronouncing Machiavelli an atheist and
blasphemer, for there is still the question about whether and to what
extent he recognizes an important role for religion in political life.
Moreover, as we have seen throughout this book, Machiavelli’s critique
of Christianity is shadowed at all times by his revaluation of aspects of
its own ontology. Not only is the founder presented in a prophetlike,
millenarian light, but so are what I have termed the princes of thought,
best exemplified by Machiavelli himself. The divinization of politics
is not the equivalent of out and out atheism because it battens off
the experience of revelation and recognizes and attempts to fashion a
simulacrum of its psychological power.
The preface to part 2 of the Discourses gives us a further sense of
what it would mean to call Machiavelli a prince of thought. Employing
his rhetorical invocation of antiquity, Machiavelli writes that he will
“boldly and openly” (perhaps like the Columbus of thought treading
an as yet untrodden path in the preface to part 1) compare the virtu-
ous past with the inadequate present, so as to “excite in the minds of
young men” the desire to imitate the ancient virtues whenever “for-
tune presents them with the occasion.” In other words, Machiavelli
will “excite” the “desire” of potential young statesmen and princes to
restore ancient virtue (but not ancient philosophy). He will replace the
intermediary role of “the writers” with his own new way of writing,
in which historical events take the place of dialectic. In this way, he
will prepare them for whatever “occasion” that fortune will present
them with, just as he says in chapter 6 of The Prince that princes of
“outstanding virtue” make use of the occasion Fortuna offers them.
It could seem as if, whereas Plato argues that the Idea of the Good,
suitably interpreted by his Socrates, might excite the erotic longing of
potential statesmen, Machiavelli is arguing that he himself will be the
source of their excitation, the fashioner of their image of nobility, draw-
ing upon not ancient philosophy but the direct unvarnished experience
of ancient nobility. This of course inevitably entails an act of reflection
and the projection of something new upon the ancient past, for we
421
tyranny
cannot actually enter into how the ancients understood themselves and
their virtues if we fully jettison their concern with philosophy. More-
over, because Christianity is arguably a valid continuation of aspects
of ancient philosophical transcendentalism, and even of the pagan reli-
gious longing in late antiquity for the One God, Christianity can claim
as readily as Machiavelli’s image of ancient virtue to have preserved
something fundamentally important from the ancient world and its
heritage. Insofar as Machiavelli makes himself a more direct source of
inspiration to the young than the ancient writers and reshapes their
access to the ancient past, is not his role vis-à-vis these potential new
rulers and statesmen not more interventionary, more Godlike, in the
Abrahamic sense, than Plato’s role as a medium through whose writ-
ings the immortally and changelessly true might be glimpsed? Is he
not a new kind of prophet? However this may be, whereas Plato and
especially Aristotle try to draw young men toward maturity by means
of the cultivation of their initially spontaneous longings for nobility,
Machiavelli offers to help them directly, as they are right now; to fur-
ther enflame them with the glories of the past. (The counterpart to his
advice in The Prince that Fortuna prefers a hot-blooded young wooer.)
This willingness to excite the passions of young men to restore ancient
virtue stands in sharp contrast with Hobbes, who particularly fears the
effects on young men both of ancient authors like Aristotle and of the
ancient exemplars of virtue, who in his view flatter their vain conceit
that they are fit by nature to rule, only one instance of the narrowing
of Machiavelli that Hobbes undertakes in his pursuit of pure political
method.
Several representative passages from the Discourses further illustrate
the complexity of interpreting Machiavelli’s stance toward religion. Let
us consider them by stages.
1. In the preface to Book 1, he writes: Despite “the general respect
for antiquity,” it (antiquity) is often “more admired than imitated, or so
much neglected that not the least trace of this ancient virtue remains.”
Readers take pleasure in reading about the ancients, he argues, but
do not try to imitate their “noble actions” because they are believed
“impossible, as though heaven, the sun, the elements and men had
changed . . . and were different from what they were in ancient times.”
But for Christians, of course, they had changed (particularly “heaven”
and “men,” inasmuch as God had become a man and through his
422
the republic in motion
death and resurrection saved all men from death). Thus, Machiavelli’s
appeal to reverence for the ancients (including at 2.5.1 a not disparaging
reference to Aristotle’s view about the eternity of the visible universe
while indicating his own preference for Lucretius) masks an attack on
Christianity’s claims to have transformed man from an honor seeker
into a peace lover worshiping the Creator God and Savior.
2. Discourses 2.2 discusses the difference between the ancients’ edu-
cation and religion and ours, issuing in a withering critique of ours.
Machiavelli writes that ours “causes us to attach less value to the hon-
ors and possessions of this world, while the pagans, esteeming those
things as the highest good, were more energetic and ferocious in their
actions.” This is the counterpoint to the preface to Book 1, where
Machiavelli argued that we can imitate the ancients because nature has
not changed. For as he writes here, what “our religion teaches as the
truth and the true way of life” is a mere addition or overlay to a more
constant underlying natural leaning toward honor and possessions, a
leaning distorted by ancient philosophy as well. The fact that such a
teaching can hold us in its grip despite our underlying and constant
natural disposition toward honor and gain points to the enormous
power of man to re-create appearances, to the point of almost blotting
out nature, through the “imagined republics.” Machiavelli continues in
the same withering vein: “The pagan religion glorified only men who
had achieved great glory, such as commanders of armies and chiefs of
republics, while ours glorifies more the humble and contemplative men
than the men of action. Our religion . . . places the supreme happiness
in humility, lowliness and a contempt for worldly objects, while the
other . . . places the supreme good in grandeur of soul and body, and
all such other qualities as render men formidable; and if our religion
claims of us fortitude of soul, it is more to enable us to suffer than to
achieve great deeds.”
3. Reading on, however, we learn that our religion is but a distortion
of the original and true Christian teaching, a seemingly more virile
and worldly Christianity that perhaps dovetails with the Reformation’s
invocation of the pristine origins of the faith (on which more below):
“Although it would seem that the world has become effeminate and
Heaven disarmed, yet this arises from the baseness of men, who have
interpreted our religion according to the promptings of indolence rather
than virtue.”
423
tyranny
4. So far, then, we have been presented with the view that Chris-
tianity has irreparably distorted the ancient love of honor, although
that love of honor is still underlyingly true about human nature, sup-
plemented by the view that a more honor seeking and patriotic core
of the original Christianity might be salvaged, its current distortion
owing only to human baseness. Another passage from 2.30.5 com-
pletes the dynamic. Here, Machiavelli observes that, owing to the dif-
ference between today’s republics and ancient republics, we now careen
between extraordinary defeats and extraordinary victories with no con-
sistency of purpose, because “where men have little virtue, Fortune
more signally displays her power.” Then the language becomes mil-
lenarian. These fluctuations in events will continue until “some ruler
shall arise who is so great an admirer of antiquity” that when he rules,
Fortune will not be able “to display her influence and power . . . with
every revolution of the sun.” Precisely because Fortuna is so muta-
ble and unpredictable, she cannot even be relied upon to thwart the
return of ancient valor. Indeed, the new prince may “arise” from her
very fluctuations and, armed with Machiavelli’s teaching, tap into her
power and force her into equilibrium. First, Machiavelli argued that
we should restore the ancient and enduring natural love of honor as
against the wild distortions introduced into human conduct by Chris-
tianity. Then he argued that we might salvage a pristine Christianity
closer to that natural and enduring stalk, to fortify us against these wild
fluctuations. Now he is arguing that the wildness of those fluctuations
might occasion the rise of a prince who would transform nature again,
but this time in a healthy way. (His preference for Lucretian cosmology
over Aristotelian may stem from Lucretius’s belief that innumerable
entirely different worlds have existed in the past and will exist in the
future.)
Putting together these passages, then, we arrive at the following
stages of Machiavelli’s argument: 1) Today’s men, however much dom-
inated by Christianity, are wrong to think they cannot restore ancient
virtue, because nature has not changed. He silently avoids the fact that,
for any believing Christian, nature has been fundamentally changed by
the death and resurrection of God. 2) Failing this restoration of ancient
virtue, they could at least restore a manlier version of “our” religion.
3) The fluctuations of Fortuna restore on a secular level the transfor-
mative dynamic of Christianity by which the death and rebirth of God
424
the republic in motion
did change nature, so that Machiavelli can now openly argue that a
new prince may emerge who will further transform nature for the sake
of man’s security and well-being. The stages show how Machiavelli’s
rhetorical appeal to antiquity, initially couched in the view that nature
has not changed, gradually drops its mask to reveal a new scope for
the transformation of nature prefigured by revelation itself (cosmolog-
ically, Aristotle gives way to Augustine, with the place of the Creator
God taken by the new prince).
425
tyranny
426
the republic in motion
427
tyranny
that some of his exemplars like Galileo were to some degree already
scientific moderns, one might observe about Masters that Leonardo
was to some degree still a premodern in his study of astrology and
alchemy. My own view is that, although Machiavelli’s understanding
of nature probably does owe something to Renaissance astrology, and
especially to the ancient medical concept of “humors,” whether one
regards these bodies of knowledge as premodern or (as I am inclined to
think) protomodern, his own political ontology is not wholly reducible
to any of these influences, but is, in its desacralized Augustinian view of
politics as dominion and his emphasis on the will to master nature for-
merly attributed to God, a unique new synthesis of ancient and modern
themes and of reason and revelation.
In an interesting variation on these quandaries, Lukes (1984),
although rejecting as self-evidently ridiculous the idea that Machiavelli
was a conventionally believing Christian, also argues that the spiri-
tual power of Christianity was one that Machiavelli wished to enlist
in his own cause, and not merely reject, which meant that, much as
he might have admired the pagan civil religion of the Romans, he
neither could nor wished entirely to return to it. Lukes sees in The
Mandragola a formula by which religious leaders could assist political
rulers in spreading the new political science while, precisely because they
are religious leaders, they could assist the prince in this way without
being “accused of temporal aggrandizement when secretly promoting
the aims of the armed politician through careful manipulation of church
doctrine. . . . Savanarola’s mistake is not that he remains unarmed, but
that he does not form a secret alliance with a capable prince.” In other
words, precisely the apparent otherworldly focus and detachment from
power politics of the Christian spiritual leader could be a powerful
weapon in promoting the new politics, in contrast with the blatant
politicality of the Romans’ civil religion. This very much comports with
my own view of how Machiavelli wants to make use of the univer-
salism of Christianity while endowing it with new content. If Lukes
is correct (and I think he is), then there is a more direct and fungible
connection than is sometimes apprehended between Machiavelli and
Hobbes’s later, more forthright attempt to assimilate the authority of
the Church and its teachings to the Sovereign’s needs in maintaining
the social compact. Of course one should add in the case of Savanarola
that, were he to form a secret alliance with a capable prince, the content
428
the republic in motion
429
tyranny
430
the republic in motion
431
tyranny
432
conclusion
Tyranny Ancient and Modern
433
tyranny
1 Matteo (2007) p. 245. For a detailed discussion of Machiavelli’s reception through his
earliest translators, see Anglo (2005).
434
conclusion
435
tyranny
436
conclusion
2 Machiavelli does not always favor republics over principalities, or the overthrow of
principalities in order to establish republics. Although some republics like Rome were
for a time capable of being restored to liberty from an interval of corruption (“los-
ing the head while the trunk was still sound”), some peoples under princely rule
have been so thoroughly corrupted that it would be better for the current prince
to be replaced by another prince than for them to try to live as a republic (Dis-
courses 1.17). As Gilbert observed in a still valuable work (1954), quoting Ranke, it
is arguable that Machiavelli thought Italy’s condition to be so desperate that even con-
quest and unification from without was an acceptable cure. A good example of Machi-
avelli’s indifference as to whether Italy is unified by a prince or a republic is chapter
4 of The Prince, in which Machiavelli segues from Pope “Alessandro” in chapter 3,
patron of Cesare and a master manipulator, to “Alessandro” (the Great’s) conquest
of Asia. Unification faces two challenges: centralized states like that of Darius or the
Ottoman Sultan that, although hard to conquer, pass intact into your hands and are
easy to maintain, and decentralized states like France, which are easy to conquer but,
owing to their many feudal statelets, and hence their memory of independence, are hard
to hold until the local noble bloodlines are extinguished, as the Romans demonstrated.
Machiavelli’s Italy is both decentralized because of its many small states (like France) and
centralized owing to the Church’s authority (like “Asia” or “the Turk”). A new “Alessan-
dro” will have to find a way of combining both modes of occupation – perhaps by being
less of an otherworldly ruler like the pope and more of a worldly one like the sultan,
who combines secular and religious authority, an expansion of secular state power that
was already emerging in the sixteenth century owing to Luther and the Reformation and
was to some extent a return to the Caesaropapism of the early Christian and Orthodox
emperors.
437
tyranny
438
conclusion
3 Strauss’s judgment about the comparative merits of The Prince and the Discourses is
nuanced. He begins by arguing that it is “prudent” to assume that Machiavelli’s “teach-
ing in either The Prince or the Discourses is all-comprehensive.” However, he qualifies
this by observing that whereas The Prince is a “call to action” to liberate Italy, the
Discourses is “leisurely” because it is aimed at the development of “potential princes,”
particularly through a meditation on “the spirit of antiquity.” Leisure is the precondi-
tion for philosophy, and, in this sense like the Republic, the Discourses is aimed toward
potential leaders, not actual ones. In this regard, therefore, its scope would appear to
be both broader and more contemplative than that of The Prince. Finally, as Strauss
observes, although “we find in the Discourses a number of statements to the effect that
republics are superior to principalities, we do not find in The Prince a single statement
to the effect that principalities are superior to republics.” This would comport with my
view that the teaching of the Discourses is both more philosophical and more republican.
Finally: “Princes are superior to peoples as regards the founding of states, peoples are
superior to princes as regards the preservation of states.” Assuming that preservation
(which includes refounding) is even more important than founding, this would put the
Discourses ahead of The Prince. Strauss (1969) pp. 22, 25.
439
tyranny
sins he imagined, but those which I have related. And as they were the
sins of princes, it is the princes who have also suffered the penalty.” In
other words, the sin of princes is ignorance about the “effectual truth”
of statecraft, specifically of the chapter’s general maxim that, because
there cannot be good laws without the enforcing power of good arms,
we should omit the discussion of good laws entirely and focus only on
how to acquire the arms. This maxim constitutes another reversal of
the classics, for whom military policy, if discussed at all, should only
be a subordinate factor in a city’s just constitution because focusing on
it too prominently might elevate the aims of foreign policy, warfare,
and conquest over those of internal self-government.
Living in the wake of the Enlightenment, where we might view the
maxim of Marlowe’s Machiavelli (“there is no sin but ignorance”) as
a droll drawing room quip savoring of Metternich or Kissinger, we
need to reimagine how shocking many people would still find it in early
modernity. In stark contrast with classical philosophy, which held that
wisdom was the highest human aim, the Abrahamic faiths uniformly
proclaimed it the height of pride and folly to suppose that the study
of nature by the unaided human intellect could achieve wisdom in the
absence of divine authority. Indeed, human observation and learning on
their own were likelier to compound one’s ignorance, like one who mis-
takes a stick bent by its reflection in the water for the real thing. As the
Ecclesiast wrote in a sentiment that might be admired by pious Jews,
Christians, and Muslims alike: “My son, be admonished: of making
many books there is no end, and much study is a weariness of the flesh.
This is the end of the matter; all hath been heard: fear God, and keep
his commandments; for this is the whole duty of man.” For the biblical
faiths, reliance on any merely human wisdom about nature virtually
summed up the meaning of sin, whereas a disavowal or avoidance of
such knowledge, far from being (as Marlowe’s Machiavelli would have
it) the only sin, reflected a humility appropriate to man’s fallen con-
dition in contrast with the vainglorious pursuit of knowledge without
obedience to God. Hence, the maxim placed by Marlowe on Machi-
avelli’s lips would truly have been a Count Floyd moment for many
theater-goers – very scary! Its shocking quality becomes clearer when
we recall that man was expelled from Eden for wanting to eat from
the tree of knowledge. In this acute sense, from a religious perspec-
tive, ignorance, or at least ignorance about philosophy, far from being
440
conclusion
the only sin, is arguably the only virtue, and the pursuit of knowledge
absent a submission to God the only vice. Of course, we must bear in
mind at the same time that the Marlowe Machiavelli’s implicit defense
of wisdom over ignorance is of the new wisdom of man’s capacity to
master nature, in this respect as alien to the classical understanding of
wisdom as it is to the biblical faiths.
Machiavelli is mentioned by name in several of Shakespeare plays
(“Am I politic? Am I subtle? Am I a Machavel?” asks the Host in
The Merry Wives of Windsor), perhaps most notably when Richard III
claims that, in his capacity for deceiving others, he can outdo Machi-
avelli himself (“set the murderous Machiavelli to school”). Richard’s
ability to “frame (his) face for all occasions,” to “add colours to the
chameleon” and change “shapes with Proteus,” certainly does recall
Machiavelli’s maxim in The Prince that one must appear to cultivate
all the virtues for their own sake while not actually doing so, because
“all see you, few touch what you are.” Still, the capacity for deception,
ruthlessness, treachery, and murder does not in itself add anything fun-
damentally new to our understanding of human behavior that is not
found either in the Bible or the classics. People were well aware of this
side of human behavior before Machiavelli appeared to openly endorse
it, and aspiring tyrants and glory seekers had always acted on it and
were known to have done so. In my view, the deeper and more dis-
tinctively Machiavellian portrayal of the new prince in Shakespeare’s
plays is not Richard III but Henry Bolingbroke in Richard II. This play
captures as perhaps no other of Shakespeare’s plays does so clearly the
passing away of the old politics of the classical/Christian conglomerate
and the emergence of the new prince called for by Machiavelli, even
though that transition is set anachronistically in the fourteenth century
(not the only time Shakespeare uses the past as a way of commenting on
the Tudor and Elizabethan present). Old John of Gaunt depicts the clas-
sical/Christian conglomerate rooted in the soil of the island kingdom:
“This seat of Mars/This other Eden, demi-paradise, this fortress built
by Nature for herself . . . This nurse, this teeming womb of royal kings”
(2.1). Nature is beneficent, orderly, and self-regulating, producing kings
by hereditary descent whose Christian legitimacy prevents corruption
and usurpers from arising. We might recall Machiavelli’s brief depic-
tion of hereditary principalities in chapter 2 of The Prince – one emerges
much like the last, like one brick being laid upon another in a wall.
441
tyranny
442
conclusion
443
tyranny
The consolation of mystical insight for the foolish loss of worldly power
is an irony that Machiavelli might well appreciate.
444
conclusion
445
tyranny
446
conclusion
4 In addition to his overall superb scholarship and rare ability to relate theoretical princi-
ples to the flow of events and personalities, I am specifically reliant on Rahe’s reading of
Harrington, how he compares and contrasts with Hobbes, and, in my own assessment
of what I term the many faces of Machiavelli, Rahe’s argument that the English repub-
lican experiment conducted between 1649 and 1660 was already aiming, Puritans and
Machiavellians alike, more than a century ahead of the Jacobins, to spread the revolution
against traditional divine right monarchy and “priestcraft” throughout all of Europe.
Rahe (2008).
447
tyranny
5 I very much agree with Rahe (2005), as against the Cambridge school, that the American
founders, however much they may have admired classical antiquity, were not primarily
influenced by classical political philosophy but by the new science of politics, as Hamilton
regarded it, filtered to them, on the one hand from Montesquieu, and on the other from
the English republicanism of Harrington and Locke, stretching back to their common
stalk, Machiavelli. See my own discussion of the Founders’ and especially Hamilton’s
dislike of the ancient Greek polis and his belief that the new science of politics had
remedied the defects of classical republicanism. Newell (2009) pp. 129–206.
448
conclusion
449
tyranny
in the state of nature through the war of all against all. The Sovereign’s
power to terrorize is an institutionalized salutary reminder that we are
always better off obeying the contract, and the importation of Machi-
avelli’s more general prescription for the use of law to replicate the
severity of nature through periodic acts of republican refounding into a
more narrowly focused technique for autocratic repression.
Rule by institutionalized terror was probably not Hobbes’s preferred
path to consolidate the social contract, but modernizers in a hurry were
to seize on it. We are very far now from the benign utopianism of Bacon
or even Harrington’s exuberant republicanism, although for reasons we
will consider, Hobbes is at the juncture of both corridors, the light and
the dark. For now, suffice it to say that the Hobbesian Sovereign at
his most fear-inspiring as the methodical crusher of all human impulses
not reducible to conformity to the social contract leads directly along
the dark corridor to Rousseau’s Legislator, who “re-creates” human
nature with a godlike determination, and from there to the “incorrupt-
ible” Robespierre, a prime example of the “secular saint” who destroys
thousands, without personal malice, for the sake of the collective. It
leads finally to ascetic police state mass murderers including Dzerzhin-
sky and Himmler, for whom the cleansing of class and race enemies in
order to create a perfect community of interchangeable human integers
is a duty requiring all sentiments of pity, or even of personal anger,
to be overcome for the sake of the ideal. Here is the most extreme
working-out of Machiavelli’s designs for the deeroticization of tyranny.
Awful prospects. Yet it is fair to say that, as moderns, we remain
ambivalent in our assessment of the tyrannical founder – an ambiva-
lence, moreover, in the history of political ideas that, as we have seen in
this book, goes all the way back to Plato’s Laws. For, although I have
distinguished for purposes of analysis between a light and a dark corri-
dor to modernity, it would be more precise to say that, in the warp and
woof of political history from which these motifs are abstracted, the
dark corridor has at least two shafts and is not always or entirely sep-
arable from the more benign face of modernization. Nationalist mod-
ernizing revolutions have often been accompanied by autocrats. In this
sense, Kemal Ataturk or the last Shah of Iran could be classified as
Hobbesian Sovereigns, attempting to bring their peoples into the world
of secular liberalism and materialism from above, postponing or forbid-
ding democratic self-government until the new modern character type
450
conclusion
7 Especially in Taming The Prince (1993), Mansfield begins with the classical understand-
ing of the relationship between tyranny and monarchy in Aristotle, and the qualified
451
tyranny
endorsement of a form of monarchy guided by reason that might well resemble a tyranny
in its absolutism and eradication of citizen participation. He then examines Machiavelli’s
unvarnished endorsement of princely coercion, including large-scale violence, and poses
the question of how we might explain the “banalization” of the Machiavellian prince in
the institutions of the modern liberal constitutional polity such as the “executive power”
and “war powers” of the American presidency. How, he asks, does this banalization or
“taming” occur? “The answer is that the history of Machiavellism is chiefly a process of
domestication, whereby Machiavelli’s thought was appropriated and absorbed by liberal
constitutionalism so that it could be regularized and legitimated” (p. xxiii). This comports
with my suggestion that the Hobbesian Sovereign, already a narrowing of the Machi-
avellian prince to a mechanism for sheer control and umpirage of the social contract,
could as efficiently or more efficiently be deployed as a completely impersonal constitu-
tional mechanism for checks and balances exemplified by the American Constitution. The
essence of the superiority of what Hamilton regards as the new science of politics over
that of the ancients is this reliance on impersonal institutions in contrast with the vagaries
of personal rule. I would only add that there is a competing stream in modern political
philosophy, what I have termed the light path exemplified by Spinoza and Locke, in con-
trast to the dark corridor that leads to the more unvarnished endorsement of executive
power, that helps mitigate the potential in the modern executive power for spilling over
into dictatorship. I wholly agree with Mansfield that both Skinner and Pocock, by begin-
ning with an already tame Machiavelli, occlude our understanding of why he needed to
be tamed. The side of liberalism that dispenses with Machiavelli’s harsher prescriptions
does not come from Machiavelli himself as much as from the modification of his view of
the relationship of man to nature undertaken by the holism of Spinoza.
452
conclusion
453
tyranny
454
conclusion
Hobbes, the solid and lasting change in human conduct will come not
primarily through terror and direct coercion, but through the steady
and peaceable spread of “right reason,” of enlightenment. Under the
influence of the new psychology of appetitive desire, man will come to
set aside martial strife and pride and, as Voltaire urged, to cultivate his
garden. When James Madison argues that the new American republic’s
checks and balances will allow “ambition to counter-act ambition,” the
Machiavellian surface of this observation is underlain by the Hobbesian
premise that ambition will already have been largely channeled into the
competition for success through the peaceful arts of commerce. It is
not that a Cato will counteract a Catiline but that a Bill Gates will
counteract a Warren Buffet.
As I stress that a potential project for “permanent revolution” – the
project for the endless reengineering of the human soul through terror –
is, although a dark possibility lurking in Hobbes’s political science,
likely not his preferred prescription, I want to reemphasize my view that
modern revolutionary terror is at best no more than partially explained
by aspects of early modern political theories like those of Machiavelli
and Hobbes even at their most ominous. For reasons I discuss presently,
the meaning and scope of modern tyranny changes drastically with
Rousseau, his detestation for bourgeois liberalism, his rejection of early
modern natural right (especially of Hobbes’s view of the state of nature
and the social contract), and his romanticization of “the people,” a shift
in the ontology of tyranny that carries us beyond the thematic limits of
this study. Before turning to a sketch of that boundary transformation,
however, let me continue with this broad overview from within the
premises of my focus in this book on the conquest of nature and of eros
characteristic of early modern political thought.
As the modern age and the Enlightenment unfolded, people certainly
continued to know about the dangers of tyranny as set forth by the
classics, but the rising belief in the progress of history led to the conclu-
sion that the dangers of tyranny were being steadily overcome as well.
For Hegel, history begins in the “slaughter-bench” of the pursuit of
mastery, but it will end in peace and the brotherhood of man. The Phe-
nomenology of Spirit begins historically with the master-slave dialectic
and ends with a verse from Schiller’s Ode to Joy. For Marx, even more
than for Hegel, history to date has been one unending, blood-soaked
struggle for tyrannical mastery by one ruler or class over all the rest, but
455
tyranny
8 Consider Hegel (1997). See the discussion in Newell (2009a); (1994) pp. 107–122.
456
conclusion
457
tyranny
experience and observation, they would have the facts and not opinion
to reason about, and might have ultimately arrived at the knowledge of
the laws which govern the material world” (Bacon [1854] pp. 343–371).
Like Machiavelli as he depicts him here, Bacon appears to be exhort-
ing us to set aside improbable cosmologies like those of the ancients,
based on factually unverifiable myths such as the Platonic Forms or the
Aristotelian Unmoved Mover, in favor of the patient accumulation of
facts about the world as it is, not as it ought to be. This corresponds to
Machiavelli’s claim that he is setting aside the pretensions of the “imag-
ined republics” of the ancients so as to focus on the “effectual truth” –
the real world, as we might say, rather than the ideal. Yet just as Machi-
avelli presents this appeal to observable experience as the gateway to a
Promethean assault on nature, the possibility of which is not exclusively
derivable from observable experience itself, Bacon, too, reveals that the
allegedly empirical observation of nature can only proceed once nature
has already been intellectually assaulted and subdued by an act of will
in the mind of the scientist. Like Machiavelli’s emphasis on the will, the
radical voluntarism of Bacon’s scientific method wholly outstrips any
precedent to be found in ancient materialism, the pre-Socratics, or the
Sophists, the “Homeric-Heracleitean doctrine” that evolved a view of
nature as cycles of motion out of an already existing poetic emphasis on
the tragic limitations placed on human action and reason by necessity
and chance.9
458
conclusion
extent always elude the grip of human mastery, partly for reasons based on Machiavelli’s
view of Lucretian materialism itself. Thus, it is not true for Machiavelli strictly speaking
or in every instance that we can “only know what we make,” for we can know that
fortune will always limit man to some degree, and our own desires will never remain
stable or contented; we will not be able to devise any solutions for these impediments
that reach right down to the bottom of the world’s existence so as to uproot and transform
it entirely. Not every Bacon scholar agrees, however, with Kennington’s interpretation
of Bacon, which makes Baconian mastery seem almost to anticipate Fichte’s voluntarism
or Nietzsche’s will to power, or, indeed, Kuhn’s quasi-Nietzschean view of science as a
paradigm shift. Travis Smith (2009), for example, thinks Bacon’s promise of mastery for
the relief of man’s estate is partly a rhetorical means for gaining broader popular support
for a scientific project whose tangible benefits will remain in doubt for some time to come.
Rousseau famously regarded Bacon as the very archetype of the philosopher motivated
by a pure love of the truth.
459
tyranny
for hot-blooded youth over cautious old age. However, it is hard not to
detect in Bacon’s words a transition from the comparative delicatezza of
Machiavelli’s multifaceted and balletic wooing of Fortuna to something
more akin to the cloddishness of a methodological soccer club. Perhaps
Swift had this rape of nature in mind when he named his parody of
Bacon’s Royal Society – an island of scientific technocrats flying over
the inherited traditions of the Old World like the islands of the new
world beckoning to the west – Laputa, the whore, nature whored.10
Just as Machiavelli counsels the prince to expel erotic longing from
his own character and replace it with methodical discipline, Bacon says
that the scientist must probe nature with a “chaste and severe course
of inquiry” (Bacon [1960] p. 28). Just as Machiavelli urged this inner
process of deeroticization so that one might guard oneself against the
allures of the imagined republics, the psychological key to our reliance
on Fortuna, leading to the rejection of the Great Tradition in its entirely,
Bacon argues that “the entire work of the intellect (must) be commenced
afresh, and the mind itself be from the very outset not left to take
its own course but guided at every step” (Bacon [1960] p. 34). Just
as, for Machiavelli, seeing nature as it really is must be preceded by
one’s inward-turning alienation from its bewitching outward sheen of
beneficence encouraging the belief that nature upholds peace and justice,
for Bacon as well, rigorous science requires that the mind be reshaped in
abstraction from all received experience and tradition “and the business
done as if by machinery” (Bacon [1960] p. 34).
For Bacon, before we can conquer nature, we must purge our minds
of her influence over us through the seductive traditions of the past or
the apparently beautiful patterns of the visible world. This inner self-
purgation corresponds with a preference for breaking nature down into
her constituent parts and forsaking the allure of the surface harmony, a
discipline that Machiavelli had urged princes to practice on themselves
and in their relationship with their subjects (for “all see you, but few
touch what you are”). For Bacon just as for Machiavelli, in other words,
the study of nature is grounded in a secularized Augustinian distrust of
10 The ungallant description of “her” outer chambers as places where “numbers have
trodden” suggests she has been pretty undiscriminating in her earlier admission of
wooers. More brutal and deeper penetration is apparently required to get past this
antechamber of aging Aristotelian ponces.
460
conclusion
the looks of the world, the visible flourishing of phenomena that led
Plato and the ancients to reason upward through those orderly appear-
ances toward the perfect archetypes of the Forms. For Machiavelli and
Bacon, whatever order the world possesses will be fashioned by the
sustaining will of the prince, or the prince of science, transferred from
God to man.
I suggested in Chapters 5 and 6 that Machiavelli’s fully rounded
view of the proper approach of the prince to Fortuna is more complex
than mere hot-blooded subjugation, however stirring that metaphor in
chapter 25 of The Prince may be to ambitious young men. Instead, it
is an inner dyad alternating between the unseen recesses of the prince’s
character and the unseen spontaneous forces of Fortuna herself. For-
tuna as the unseen source of origination bonds with the prince’s inner
character, a primordial as opposed to a transcendental link between
man and the world. The prince must imitate fortune’s impetuosity in
order to channel and tap into her power. Paradoxically, complete mas-
tery comes by way of complete submission. Only by renouncing our
hopes from nature can we gain freedom from her, which is also free-
dom over her.11 In this sense, for Machiavelli, the knowledge of nature is
assimilated by the will to subdue her through imitating her own lack of
intrinsic teleological purpose. So, too, does Bacon argue that “human
knowledge and human power meet in one.” If we do not know the
cause, its “effect cannot be produced.” Most important, “nature to be
commanded must be obeyed.” When we understand nature, we can
harness and replicate her spontaneous effects so as to maximize man’s
power over her: “That which in contemplation is as the cause is in oper-
ation as the rule” (Bacon [1857] I.iii). To know something is to be able
to make it, but this mastery of nature through technique is preceded by
submission to nature’s sheer power of genesis.
We considered in earlier chapters how, according to Machiavelli,
the centuries-old conglomerate of the classical and Christian “imagined
11 Pesic (1999) makes the interesting argument that the Baconian scientist’s stance toward
nature should not be seen exclusively as “torture” but as more akin to a wrestling match.
This comports with my view of the Machiavellian prince’s relationship with Fortuna as
a kind of dance or dyad in which the prince mush channel fortune in order to subdue
her, and while I see the Baconian stance as more straightforwardly dominating, Pesic
has a point that the scientist must also internalize the flow of nature – in effect, to woo
and not merely conquer.
461
tyranny
462
conclusion
463
tyranny
morality forged by the classics as part and parcel of the delusions of the
many, making them subject to the pretensions of what Hobbes would
come to call the “vainglorious.” A part of Machiavelli’s populism is
evident in his belief that, although the people want only to survive and
enjoy their property, the nobiles always want to displace the prince,
and so are the chief fomenters of instability. Contrary to what Aristotle
argued, there is no distinction in principle between aristocracy and oli-
garchy. Whatever they may call themselves, their motives are venal (The
Prince chapter 9). In the fluid world of the rise and fall of states, self-
described aristocrats are oligarchs plotting to become tyrants. What
Plato and Aristotle regarded as the better sort of men, the gentle-
men, whose innate or inherited nobility might incline them toward the
nobility of philosophic independence from the sway of base passion,
are lumped together by Machiavelli with countless other varieties of
deluded hopes, ambition, and self-indulgence. Standing over against all
of these moralizers – the people, the so-called nobles and their flatterers,
the philosophers of old – is Machiavelli’s new prince, an amalgam of a
ruler and a thinker, whose reason is assimilated to his will and the mark
of whose excellence is his inner austerity, his rigorous self-purgation of
the delusions of the old conglomerate. One might well ask at the end
of the day who has a better opinion of the people, Machiavelli or the
classics? Plato and Aristotle believe that the common people, although
not best equipped or situated to actualize their virtue, can be educated
or habituated to do so to some extent by rising above base desires.
Machiavelli, by contrast, encourages the people to pursue their base
desires in an alliance with the prince by liberating them from the sway
of belief in ancient moral philosophy and its intertwining with Chris-
tian revelation – a liberation that will require the methodical reshaping
of their natures by a cadre of leaders so as to save them from their
own attachment to the Great Tradition. When Machiavelli, in urging
the prince to forsake the nobles for the people, remarks that “who
builds on the people builds on mud,” we realize that a mud founda-
tion is a very strong one and at the same time a simile for lowness of
character.
There are many parallels with Machiavelli in Bacon’s thought for
the need to purge both natural science and political morality of its joint
delusions about the teleological beneficence of nature: what Machiavelli
termed “imagined republics,” Bacon terms “the idols of the tribe.”
464
conclusion
The idols and false notions which are now in possession of the human under-
standing and have taken deep root therein, not only so best men’s minds that
truth can hardly find entrance, but even after entrance is obtained, they will
again in the very instauration of the sciences meet and trouble us, unless men
being forewarned of the danger, fortify themselves as far as may be against
their assaults. (Bacon [1857] 1 xxxviii)
465
tyranny
(I)t is fit that I publish and set forth these conjectures of mine which make
hope in these matters reasonable, just as Columbus did, before that wonderful
voyage of his across the Atlantic, when he gave the reasons for his conviction
that new lands and continents might be discovered besides those which were
known before; which reasons, though rejected at first, were afterwards made
good by experience, and were the causes and beginnings of great events.
(Bacon [1857] 1.xcii)
466
conclusion
12 Tuck (1993) sees in Bacon’s project a synthesis of Judaism and Protestantism. This
certainly comports with the view of Rahe (2005, 2008) and Sullivan [1996, 2004]) that
English republicanism was a synthesis between Puritans and Republicans, meaning to
say between the Reformation and modern secular political thought. It also comports
with the earlier linkage between Machiavelli and Luther, especially given that the Refor-
mation early on identified with the ancient Hebrews. Others, however (Lampert in Bacon
[2000]; Kennington [2004]) see Bacon as entirely antireligious and purely rational, such
that Bacon’s new science sparked, in Lampert’s words, “the actual holy war fought in
Europe . . . the warfare of science against religion that tamed sovereign religion.” We
can never resolve with certainty or complete transparency the degree to which those
wars were carried out by rationalists wishing to overthrow Christianity or by Protes-
tants wishing to overthrow the Church of Rome, or to what degree the actors viewed
themselves as one, the other, or both (for example, Milton, Protestant theologian and
the defender of freedom of speech). Both sides, Protestant and modern rationalist, were
united in their wish to jettison classical teleology, the buttress both of classical philoso-
phy and Thomism, the latter of which sanctioned both the sovereignty of the Church in
religious matters and of divinely anointed monarchy over republicanism. A part of the
antiteleological temperament of the Reformation, and of English Protestants, was their
self-identification with the ancient Hebrews, owing among other things to the Hebrews’
monotheism, comporting with the Protestant trend against Trinitarian consubstantia-
tion and toward an elevation of God the Father at the expense of the Son, excluding
altogether the Mother of God as a polytheistic abomination. In another vein altogether,
Leon Kass (2003) has identified the Jewish God’s radical distance from nature – leading
to a distrust of the looks of the world, and in direct contrast with Platonic philosophy
467
tyranny
in which the visible world crowned by the Sun is seen as the paradigm for knowledge –
with the distrust shown by modern Baconian science toward teleology (an “idol of the
mind”) and a corresponding emphasis on the will to master the knowledge of nature
by standing outside of nature. There are many paths, in other words, to the notion of
Bacon’s thought as a synthesis of modern rationalism with the Reformation and with
Judaism.
13 In this connection, see Clarke (2008) who plausibly argues that Bacon distinguishes
himself from Machiavelli by signaling “his rejection of an imperial model based on
violent conquest. . . . In its place, he erects a new imperial model dedicated in principle
to humanity, prosperity and cosmopolitanism.”
468
conclusion
469
tyranny
470
conclusion
471
tyranny
472
conclusion
473
tyranny
474
conclusion
is not truly independent or set apart from the many who are con-
cerned with mere survival and comfort. He argues in chapter 15 of the
Leviathan that aspiring tyrants who believe they can get away with
achieving dominion simply have not thought through how the dangers
of failure, including being crushed by the authority they want to usurp,
must always outweigh through fear any merely prospective gains they
could make by continuing to struggle for predominance. But this, after
all, one might object, is a mere assertion or expression of hope on
Hobbes’s part, because people then and now manifestly do continue to
take the risk. However that may be, this side of Hobbes’s argument,
in my view his preferred outcome, leads not to totalitarianism but to
enlightenment – the belief that the new psychology of pedestrian appeti-
tiveness will by degrees work its way into the human character, leading
man to shed aggression and intolerance in exchange for the right to
comfortable self-preservation.
The same paradox we have identified in Hobbes – an ostensibly
more realistic presentation of human nature than that of the premod-
ern tradition in order to usher in a far more optimistic set of expec-
tations about the complete withering away of tyrannical aggression
and oppression than anything the premodern tradition would have
envisioned – becomes an in-built feature of much of modern political
thought. Spinoza is a case in point. Like Machiavelli, whose wisdom he
acknowledges, Spinoza gives a realistic, pragmatic, this-worldly account
of Moses in order to deflate the claims of revelation that Moses was a
divinely guided prophet. In Spinoza’s depiction, Moses used force judi-
ciously and created a religious faith so as to unite his people. In the
first instance, this real-world account appears to bring power politics
to the fore as against concerns about divine revelation and the life of
faith. As Wildavsky (2005) puts it concerning this secular approach to
interpreting Moses’ authority, by stripping Moses of his “sacerdotal”
character, we can better appreciate his genius, courage, prudence and
ingenuity as a ruler, including how he sometimes verged on “despo-
tism.” However, insofar as Spinoza’s long-term goal is this-worldly
peace, tolerance, harmony and stability, the realistic side of politics
exemplified by Moses’ leadership will eventually give way to a spiritu-
alized liberal democracy where the hard-headed realism of the founder
can be dispensed with. On reflection, therefore, we realize that the fun-
damental aim of Spinoza (presaged by Machiavelli in presenting the
475
tyranny
realistic Moses, the secular leader or, to use Machiavelli’s more poetic
language, “armed prophet”) was to tame Mosaic politics by separating
them from the nonnegotiable zeal and righteousness sustained by a faith
in God and God’s justice. This tension between unsentimental realism
about politics in the present for the sake of a peaceful, bounteous, toler-
ant, nonaggressive future undulates, as we consider in the next section,
throughout the Enlightenment. Even later rebellions from the fascist
right against what it regarded as liberal weakness and pacifism were
unable to escape its contradictions. Carl Schmitt tried to derive the
primacy of the friend-enemy distinction from Hobbes’s warlike state of
nature as a weapon against what he saw as the creeping and despiritual-
izing bourgeois materialism of Europe. He could not, however, success-
fully derive a more robust code of political strife from Hobbes’s view
of the state of nature because the most consistent long-term outcome of
Hobbes’s initially unvarnished presentation of honor seeking – domi-
nation and strife as man’s spontaneous natural condition – is, through
the construction of the social compact, precisely that bourgeois hamster
wheel that Schmitt and many other fascists and National Socialists so
loathed.14
Let us restate the central paradox of early modern political theory in
its approach to tyrannical honor seeking as it originates in the thought
of Hobbes. Political realism is advanced against what is caricatured
as classical and Christian idealism or unworldliness so as to promote
a project for political and social peace beyond anything ever thought
possible by the allegedly unrealistic ancients. The principled rebellion
against this emerging bourgeois world, and against early modern nat-
ural right, begins with Rousseau and Hegel, who recognize the super-
ficiality and naivete of liberalism’s hopes and so strive to reintroduce
more full-blooded notions of honor, civic virtue, the warrior’s code,
and manly patriotism, often invoking the heroic republicanism of the
ancient world. Yet in many ways these critics of the Enlightenment
remain in the thrall of its paradox. Hegel’s philosophy of history begins
in the master–slave encounter, his strident celebration of history as a
“slaughter bench” in which selfish passion alone can advance justice,
and his broadsides against Kantian naivete for thinking that political
14 On Schmitt and Hobbes, see Strauss (1995). On Moses as a political leader, consider
Wildavsky (2005).
476
conclusion
477
tyranny
478
conclusion
At the same time, however, beginning with the Age of Reason and
the Enlightenment, we also find a tendency to believe that, with how-
ever many fits and starts and occasional relapses, the history of the West
15 For a full discussion of Tocqueville on the danger posed to grand ambition by democracy
and Lincoln’s differing view in the “Lyceum Speech,” see Newell (2009) part 2.
16 Quoted in Newell (2001) p. 279.
17 Quoted in Newell (2001) p. 297.
479
tyranny
480
conclusion
481
tyranny
Was there in his statesmanship, even in later days when he had great work
to do, an element of that opportunism which, if not actually base, is at least
cheap? Or did he come as near as a man with many human weaknesses can
to the wise and nobly calculated opportunism which is not merely the most
beneficial statesmanship, but demands a heroic self-mastery? (Charnwood
[1917] p. 74)
482
conclusion
483
tyranny
We cannot determine to what height the human species may aspire in their
future advance toward perfection; but it may safely be presumed that no
people . . . will relapse into their original barbarism. . . . The benefits of law
and policy, of trade and manufactures, of arts and sciences, are more solid
and permanent.
After Auschwitz and the Gulag, not to mention Chairman Mao, the
Khmer Rouge, and the Taliban, it is difficult, to say the least, to believe
in our “advance toward perfection.” Surveying the tumult of twenti-
eth century politics in his 1960 classic Political Man, Seymour Martin
Lipset acknowledged and drew upon the regime types first elaborated
by Plato and Aristotle, including tyranny, despotism, oligarchy, democ-
racy, and the danger posed to popular government by “the appeal of
irresponsible demagogues.” There was ample evidence for reconsider-
ing Aristotle’s contention in the Politics that the desire to tyrannize
was not reducible to the desire for pedestrian material gratification –
that a man did not become a tyrant “in order to get in out of the
cold” (1267a2–17). The Enlightenment had believed that someone’s
desire to dominate and oppress others derived from the frustration of
his desires for security from harm and for material pleasures that are
in themselves harmless. The solution lay in removing the frustration
needlessly caused by religious and moral restrictions on self-interest
and private pleasure, thereby dissipating the sources of war and hatred.
After the unprecedented devastation of World Wars I and II and the
484
conclusion
485
tyranny
486
conclusion
487
tyranny
world, was killed in a near-empty bedroom. The point is not that these
leaders were actually incorruptible or did not have secret vices and
purloined wealth. The point is that their personal lives were entirely
sundered from their monumental public image, whereas past despots
lived on a scale and in a way (think of Nero’s Golden House or Louis
XIV’s Versailles) that merged their capacity for luxury, adornment, and
refinement with their public identities as rulers.
Reclusive in their “Spartan quarters,” modern totalitarian tyrants
purge and recreate human existence on a vast scale, through the destruc-
tion and transportation of millions of people, in the service of doctrines
that proclaim an ideal, beyond compromise, of equality, virtue, class-
lessness, and communal or racial purity. Although capable of setting
in motion prodigies of terror that in the past one can find only in
descriptions of the most vengeful deities – and which the Enlighten-
ment believed would vanish with the end of Europe’s religious wars –
in person our tyrants tend to be gray, mild, lacking in vanity of dress
or manner, studious, gluttonous, and fussy. Many witnesses testify to
Hitler’s shyness and tentativeness in private, in contrast with his thun-
dering public performances, while Stalin’s speaking style even in public
was tediously dry and pedantic, reflective of his early seminary train-
ing. Sometimes they are histrionic in the manner of an overwrought
professor or café intellectual, eager to lay out their crankish opinions
on all facets of life from the cycles of empire to music, diet, and groom-
ing (such unendurable monologues were common to Stalin, Hitler, and
Castro). As Flaubert sums up his character Senecal in L’Education sen-
timentale, the would-be Jacobin of 1848 who ends up as the police
agent of Napoleon III, they “smell of the pedagogue and the priest.”18
We wonder what secret of our age would finally explain the connection
between such unprepossessing individuals and the titanic scale of their
destructiveness.
A brief example from the ancient and modern literature will crys-
tallize this contrast. In Aristotle’s description, the tyrant at his worst
is a monster of desires who outrages his subjects by plundering or
ravishing them (Politics 1312b17–38, 1313b32–1315a40). Citizens are
driven to tyrannicide by the need to rid society of this bloated exploiter.
This powerful condemnation, repeated and embellished by humanist
18 See the discussion of eros and revolution in Flaubert’s novel in Newell (1995).
488
conclusion
489
tyranny
490
conclusion
491
tyranny
492
conclusion
493
tyranny
into a hostile world that must be fought with and subdued before it can
be made to yield the material balms that will make aggression disap-
pear. Running counterpoint, one might say, to the optimistic strain of
the Enlightenment with its hopes for a peaceful and prosperous future
for all is this ongoing project for the reconstruction of human nature
as individualistic, spurred by the existential anxiety of one’s solitari-
ness and vulnerability. For Hobbes, only ceaseless anxiety in the face
of our finitude will keep our desire keen to embrace the benefits of the
social contract and live as long and as well as we can. Here is where the
light and dark corridors radiating out of Machiavelli’s project through
Hobbes may most closely intersect.
Tempting as it may be, however, to follow Heidegger in equating
modernity altogether with technology (indeed, for Heidegger, its origins
run back to the ancients themselves, to Plato’s metaphysics), we must
beware of so doing, because it involves a massive distancing of oneself
from the world of observable political experience, a world in which,
however much they may need to be supplemented or qualified, the fun-
damental premises of classical political philosophy are still operative –
at least as an earlier level of the archaeology of tyranny added to by
Machiavelli and the moderns – and provide a starting point for diag-
nosing tyranny in our own era, even if it is not the whole story. For
to assimilate modernity entirely to technology, as Heidegger does, is
to obliterate any proximal distinctions – based on our own experience,
historical memory, and learning – between more or less just or unjust,
more or less legitimate or illegitimate, regimes.
As Heidegger famously wrote in An Introduction to Metaphysics
(1959), viewed from the perspective of the unstoppable juggernaut of
global technology, summing up the entire destiny of the West from
Anaximander to Fordism, it makes no difference whether one lives
under Franklin Roosevelt’s America or Stalin’s Russia: As the two
superpower variants of global technology’s relentless unfolding, they
are “metaphysically the same.” Yet all of our experiences, the lessons
we draw from history, our capacity for discriminating judgment, and
our whole heritage of political philosophy both ancient and modern,
tell us that this is not so: it does make a difference. Tyranny may come
to us in the guise of invisible or impersonal technology, with its threat
of annihilation or total control. But it also still announces itself, as it
always has, in the open manner of cynical and murderous pirates like
494
conclusion
20 In Storing (1962).
495
tyranny
496
conclusion
497
tyranny
498
conclusion
499
tyranny
500
conclusion
501
tyranny
502
conclusion
503
tyranny
504
conclusion
505
tyranny
506
conclusion
507
tyranny
23 On the relationship between German Idealism, and particularly the thought of Heideg-
ger, and totalitarianism, see Newell (1984, 1988a, 1988b, 1988c).
508
conclusion
on the new basis of the mastery of nature for a politics of prosperity and
power. It was still possible for the early moderns to entertain the distinc-
tion between tyranny and legitimate authority, as witness Harrington’s
and Locke’s stout rejections of Hobbesian absolute monarchy, without
repudiating the maximization of security and material well-being. For
Heidegger, however, all such distinctions among regimes, or between
just and unjust regimes, whether classical or from the modern social
contract school, along with any attempt to expound a rational teleology
of historical progress, are but ancillary instruments in the juggernaut of
global technology, such that the attempt to distinguish between Amer-
ica and the Soviet Union is baseless, because they are “metaphysically
the same,” twin “pincers” of the debased materialism threatening “the
people’s” recommitment to the primordial destiny of its origins in Being.
Readers who have made it this far may wonder why in this study I
have not discussed at length the sense in which religious institutions or
movements can be tyrannical. Of course, it has been implicit all along
as I have dwelled on Machiavelli’s sustained critique of the Church and
of what he takes to be Christianity’s deleterious consequences for patri-
otism and its attempt to dominate political life through its institutions
and theology, and as I have speculated on what psycho-spiritual teach-
ing he might have envisioned to guide the new Rome of the future. I
have, however, omitted a discussion of the sense in which the millenar-
ianism of the Joachites, or the search for a pure Christian community
bereft of priesthood or Church typified by the Cathars or Anabaptists,
could be seen as prototypes for later revolutionary millenarianism, as
discussed, say, by Cohn (1970) and more recently by Landes (2011).
Voegelin, moreover, saw Joachite millenarianism as an antecedent for
Machiavelli’s own version of an apocalyptic prince in his creation of
“new modes and orders.”
The reason is as follows. In limiting myself to the contribution of
early modern political thought, headed by Machiavelli and Hobbes,
to the understanding and practice of tyranny, I have centered on their
emphasis on willpower and the reduction of political life to domin-
ion which they import, in a secularized version, from the Augustinian
strain of Christianity. As they seek to elbow out their mainstream com-
petitors, the Church and Christian theology, the early moderns take a
mainly negative view of faith as what Hobbes termed “the Kingdom of
509
tyranny
510
conclusion
for erotic wholeness from the telos to Fortuna.To that extent as well,
the religious millenarianism that we might see as secularized in mod-
ern revolutionary totalitarianism does not proceed directly by way of
Machiavelli and the early moderns. Instead, these modern revolutionary
movements including the Jacobins, Bolsheviks, and Nazis reach back
behind the early moderns in an atavisitc longing for the lost golden age
of the distant past, before the rise of bourgeois materialism, when the
people were whole and as one. To my mind, the early modern period is
mainly characterized by the attempt to control, even crush, or at least
tame and coopt religious faith into the liberal separation of church and
state. It may be socially useful in bolstering liberal values, but it must be
kept strictly within its boundaries of personal freedom of worship. Not
until Rousseau’s transposition of eros to the origins does the prospect
for the divinization of the people and the state emerge.
511
epilogue
The Hermeneutical Problem of Tyranny
Throughout this book, I have tried to show that there are fundamen-
tal differences in the understanding of tyranny between classical and
modern political philosophy, mirrored in the historical reality of mod-
ern tyranny itself, especially at its most radical totalitarian extreme. In
arguing this, do I necessarily commit myself to the view that human
nature in general has actually changed? Let me end with a few spec-
ulative remarks on this basic but enormously complex hermeneutical
problem.
I will begin by posing some fairly blunt alternatives. Is nuclear
weaponry, for example, no more than the outcome of the long evo-
lution of the human capacity to inflict destruction stretching back to
the Roman catapult? This is conceivable. On the other hand, did man’s
ability to split the atom, which presupposes modern natural science
and its refutation of ancient cosmology, introduce an entirely new force
into human history – the capacity to destroy human civilization? If so,
the destructive reach of tyrannical power has arguably been fundamen-
tally transformed from what it was before the twentieth century. In the
human realm, are Hitler and Stalin merely recognizable tyrants from
the classical typology equipped with military and technological power
that did not exist in the ancient past? Or (as I am inclined to believe)
did their secular millenarianism and projects for the futuristic recon-
struction of the world and the creation of a “new man” through geno-
cide introduce a fundamentally new element not comprehendible within
the ancient categories, perhaps closer to religious millenarianism and
fanaticism?
If we are asking whether tyranny has fundamentally altered its char-
acter, it would seem that we are led inevitably to the broader question
513
epilogue
514
epilogue
burden here to attempt to resolve it, only to sketch some of its contours
as they flow from the theme of this book.
Readers will recall from the Introduction that I questioned the ten-
ability of Leo Strauss’s view in apparently maintaining that, although
there is a fundamental break between ancients and moderns over the
meaning of tyranny and statecraft in general, the underlying truths
about human nature and classical political philosophy remain constant
and are preferable to the available modern alternatives. As he puts it
in a formulation characteristically rich in ambiguity: “Once we have
learned again from the classics what tyranny is,” we will have taken
“the first step toward an exact analysis of present-day tyranny, for
present-day tyranny is fundamentally different from the tyranny ana-
lyzed by the classics” (Strauss [1968] p. 189). But I myself, of course,
am partly guided in my own analysis of the differences between ancient
and modern tyranny by Strauss’s conception of such a break, which
in both Strauss’s case and my own is implicitly critical of Heidegger’s
view of tyranny as the tyranny of the Platonic forms, Platonic meta-
physics “completing itself” as technology (1954). So my attempt to
distinguish modern tyranny from ancient tyranny does invite the ques-
tion as to whether and to what extent the ambiguities about human
nature and historical change sketched here are characteristic of Strauss
himself, and how the theme of tyranny might point to and illuminate
some broader issues in Strauss’s hermeneutic and his relationship to
historicist thinkers such as Heidegger.
Let me begin by restating the fundamental alternatives. If ancient
and modern tyranny (along with the other dimensions of statecraft) are
underlyingly identical, then arguably nothing of fundamental impor-
tance for political philosophy has been done or thought about since
the classics. If, by contrast (and as I lean toward), ancient and modern
tyranny are fundamentally distinct from one another, then arguably
there may be nothing permanent about human nature and political
life. To the extent that Strauss embraces (as he appears at times to do)
the view that there is something fundamentally distinct about modern
tyranny, he might indeed be seen as embracing a historicist view. The
difficulty cannot be avoided by arguing (bluntly and for the purposes
of brevity and clarity) that the classics got it basically right, whereas all
modernity from Machiavelli through Hegel to Nietzsche, Heidegger, and
their epigones has been a compendium of various kinds of distortions
515
epilogue
516
epilogue
would overcome the dualism of the modern Cartesian subject, and hence
in some measure restore the holism of the classics. Yet by making history
the basis for that wholeness, historicism in another way ventured even
further from classical rationality than the admittedly truncated version
of it retained by Hobbes and other moderns. (I elaborate on this theme
in my essay, Did Plato Believe in His Own Metaphysics? And Did
Strauss? [2010].)
These issues certainly do bear on the provenance of tyranny. In main-
taining that modern tyranny does differ from ancient, I open myself
to the contention that I am taking a historical approach to the issue
and downplaying the underlying constants in human nature. As I see
it, however, and as I suggested in the Introduction and have tried to
demonstrate throughout, we can only think through the possibility of
such underlying constants in human nature and political philosophy if
we first pose the differences between ancients and moderns in their most
extreme dimensions, for me summed up by the deeroticization charac-
teristic of modern tyranny. Strauss himself famously argued the paradox
that we need “historical studies” precisely in order to overcome doc-
trinal historicism and reawaken the possibility that the classics might
be true. I do hold open the possibility, briefly alluded to in the Intro-
duction, that there may be some underlying constants in the ancient
and modern approaches to tyranny and statecraft, perhaps centering
on thumos and a reconceiving of it under the aegis of modernity and
the will, some of which I have tried to do in this book. More generally,
there might be some elastic and broadly characterized human leanings
toward honor, justice, nobility, and happiness sufficiently underdeter-
mined as to prevent an absolute dichotomy between the ancient and
modern approaches to statecraft. We might, for instance, read Aristo-
tle’s characterization of human nature as a civic animal with its capac-
ity for virtue, deliberation, and honor more as a series of leanings or
probabilities than as fixed, fully determined categories, introducing an
elasticity into politike that I tried to articulate in Chapter 3 with respect
to whether a monarchy or a republic was the best regime. This prospect
of recurrent but underdetermined human experiences that orient us to a
sense of wonder about life and the possibility of its further illumination
by the search for the truth can arguably be explored without falling prey
to the extreme of pronouncing that either the ancients or the moderns
are in the main completely right about everything or the extreme of
517
epilogue
518
bibliography
519
bibliography
520
bibliography
521
bibliography
522
bibliography
523
bibliography
524
bibliography
525
bibliography
526
bibliography
527
bibliography
528
bibliography
529
bibliography
Pesic, Peter. “Wrestling with Proteus: Francis Bacon and the ‘Torture’ of
Nature.” History of Science 90:1 (1999).
Petrarca, Francesco. “On the Remedies of Good and Bad Fortune.” Renais-
sance Philosophy. Vol. 1: The Italian Philosophers. Fallico and Shapiro
eds. and trans. New York: The Modern Library, 1967.
Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni. “Oration on the Dignity of Man.” Renais-
sance Philosophy. Vol. 1: The Italian Philosophers. Fallico and Shapiro
eds. and trans. New York: The Modern Library, 1967.
Pitkin, Hannah. Fortune Is a Woman. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1999.
Plato. Gorgias. Dodds ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979.
. The Laws of Plato. Pangle trans. New York: Basic Books, 1980.
. Platonis Opera. Burnet ed. 5 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1902.
. Plato’s Theaetetus. Benardete trans. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1984,
. The Republic of Plato. Adam ed. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1920.
. The Republic of Plato. Bloom trans. New York: Basic Books, 1968.
. The Statesman. Skemp trans. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1961.
. The Symposium of Plato. Bury ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1932.
. Timaeus. Zeyle trans. Indianapolis: Hackett, 2000.
Plutarch. Makers of Rome. Scott-Kilvert trans. Baltimore: Penguin Books,
1968.
Pocock, J. G. A. The Machiavellian Moment. Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1975.
Popper, Karl. The Open Society and Its Enemies. Vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1971.
Rahe, Paul A. Against Throne and Altar: Machiavelli and Political Theory
under the English Republic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
. Machiavelli’s Liberal Republican Legacy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2005.
. Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the
American Revolution. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press,
1992.
Ranasinghe, Nalin. Socrates in the Underworld: On Plato’s Gorgias. South
Bend: St. Augustine’s Press, 2009.
. The Soul of Socrates. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000.
Randall, J. H. Aristotle. New York: Columbia University Press, 1968.
530
bibliography
531
bibliography
Storing, Herbert ed. Essays on the Scientific Study of Politics. New York:
Holt, Rhinehart and Winston, 1962.
Sullivan, Vickie. Machiavelli, Hobbes and the Formation of a Liberal Repub-
licanism in England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
. Machiavelli’s Three Romes. DeKalb: Northern Illinois University
Press, 1996.
Strauss, Barry. The Battle of Salamis: The Naval Encounter That Saved
Greece – and Western Civilization. New York: Simon and Shuster, 2004.
Strauss, Leo. The City and Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977.
. Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1974.
. “Notes on Carl Schmitt’s The Concept of the Political.” In Meier,
Heinrich. Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: The Hidden Dialogue. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1995.
. On Plato’s Symposium. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001.
. On Tyranny. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1968.
. “Plato’s Apology of Socrates and Crito.” In Studies in Platonic Polit-
ical Philosophy. Pangle ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983.
. The Political Philosophy of Hobbes. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1952.
. “Progress or Return?” In The Rebirth of Classical Political Rational-
ism. Pangle ed. and intro. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989.
. “The Problem of Socrates.” In The Rebirth of Classical Political
Rationalism. Pangle ed. and intro. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1989.
. Thoughts on Machiavelli. Seattle: University of Washington Press,
1969.
. Xenophon’s Socratic Discourse: An Interpretation of the Oeconomi-
cus. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1970.
Syme, Ronald. The Roman Revolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2002.
Tacitus. The Annals and the Histories. Church trans. New York: Modern
Library, 2003.
Tarcov, Nathan. “Machiavelli and the Foundations of Modernity: A Reading
of Chapter 3 of The Prince.” In Educating the Prince: Essays in Honor of
Harvey Mansfield. Blitz and Kristol eds. New York: Rowman and Little-
field, 2000.
. “Quentin Skinner’s Method and Machiavelli’s Prince.” Ethics 92
(1982).
Tarnopolsky, Christina. Prudes, Perverts and Tyrants: Plato’s Gorgias and
the Politics of Shame. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010.
532
bibliography
533
bibliography
534
bibliography
for Liberal Democracy. Jensen ed. New York: Rowman and Littlefield,
1996.
. Plato’s Philosophers: The Coherence of the Dialogues. Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 2009.
. Understanding the Political Spirit. Zuckert ed. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1988.
Zuckert, Michael. “Appropriation and Understanding in the History of Polit-
ical Philosophy: On Quentin Skinner’s Method.” In Launching Liberalism.
Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2002.
535
index
537
index
538
index
Heidegger, 15–18, 20, 23, 182, 183, 318, Homer, 42, 132–133, 178, 207, 210,
331, 453, 492, 494, 501–502, 248–250, 271, 330
507–509, 515–516, 518 The Iliad (work), 50, 207, 250
critique of Plato, 15, 507–508, 515 Horkheimer, Max, 13, 307, 456
An Introduction to Metaphysics (work),
494 Kant, 21, 22–23, 24, 97, 139, 163, 273,
relationship to Arendt, 182 298, 343
relationship to Hobbes, 16–17, 453 critique of tragedy, 24
on the centrality of technology to on the centrality of the will to modern
modernity, 15, 306, 466, 492, 494, moral autonomy, 18, 22–23, 298
501 Kennington, Richard, 24, 456, 458–459
Herodotus, 47, 205, 235–237, 240, 242, Kojeve, Alexander, 13–14, 15, 453,
247 501
Histories (work), 235–236
Machiavelli’s preference for his account Lilla, Mark, 17, 19
of Cyrus, 205, 235–238, 240, 242, Lucretius, 132, 178, 417, 418, 423, 424,
247 429, 431
Hobbes, 2, 7, 10, 16, 23–24, 25–30, 32, De Rerum Natura (work), 280
75–132, 136, 142, 154–155, 156–157, influence in Machiavelli’s Florence,
173–174, 178–179, 182–183, 216, 417–419
300–301, 323, 324, 334, 342, Machiavelli’s assesment of his natural
358–359, 381, 388, 399, 422, 433, philosophy, 417–418, 424
435, 436, 446–456, 468–477, relationship to Bacon and Hobbes, 132
493–494, 495–499, 503 relationship to the pre-Socratics and
The Citizen (work), 78 Sophists, 178
critique of Aristotle, 76–77, 172, Ludwig, 18
173–174, 182–183, 469–472 Luther, 300, 321, 325, 407, 415, 426, 430,
critique of Plato, 78 431, 438, 467
interpretation of Thucydides, 157, 472 critique of Thomism, 407, 415, 426
Leviathan (work), 77, 174, 342, 447, preference for Augustinian theology,
451–452, 468–469, 475 300, 325, 415, 426, 438
political psychology, 30, 76–359, 447, relationship to Machiavelli, 325–326,
451–452, 454–455, 469–475, 426, 430, 431–432, 467
495–496
reductionism regarding thumos, 78–80, Machiavelli, 6–7, 10–12, 14, 17, 19–20,
472–473, 498 23–25, 26–32, 57–58, 61, 65, 67,
relationship to Bacon, 74, 142, 182, 381, 69–71, 72–73, 76, 77, 78, 81, 91,
446, 456, 468, 501–502 113–114, 115–119, 121, 122, 124,
relationship to Machiavelli, 75–79, 142, 132, 138–139, 151–152, 154, 173,
182, 183, 253, 324, 358–359, 381, 174, 177, 183–184, 186, 199, 205,
388, 422, 428, 433, 436, 451–452, 206, 207–208, 209, 227–228,
454, 498, 503 271–274, 275, 277, 283–285,
relationship to the pre-Socratics and 287–288, 292, 294–308, 311–312,
Sophists, 132, 177–178, 377, 381, 316–318, 319–321, 326, 336,
474 337–346, 348, 350–376, 379–381,
on the re-construction of nature, 382–388, 409, 410–437, 444–450,
153–154, 178–179, 300–301, 451, 452–455, 456, 458–459, 462,
334–335, 446, 453, 468–469, 503 463–469, 475–476, 480–481,
on the Sovereign’s employment of terror, 493–494, 496, 497–498, 500–504,
30, 78, 80–154, 244, 342, 449–450, 505–507, 508–511
473–474 The Art of War (work), 411
539
index
540
index
541
index
542
index
543
index
544