A Critique of The Use of Path
A Critique of The Use of Path
A Critique of The Use of Path
ADRIAN KAY
Adrian Kay is in the Department of Politics and Public Policy, Griffith University, Brisbane.
they may become more complex over time. However, for that potential to be
realized requires explicit recognition of some of the limitations of and
assumptions behind the concept.
In spite of this step, Pierson appears hesitant about the claim that public
policies may be path dependent: it appears as footnote 50 in Pierson (1993)
and is elsewhere described as ‘unorthodox’ (Pierson 2000b, p. 255). There is
justification for such hesitancy: one common and essential element in most
writers’ use of the term policy is purposiveness of some kind (Parsons 1995,
pp. 13–16). Policy expresses a general set of objectives or a desired state of
affairs. In a well-known definition of policy, public policy is: ‘anything a
government chooses to do or not to do’ (Dye 1972, p. 2). Policy is about
choice; the choice of reasons for (in)action, the choice of policy instruments,
the choice of how to respond to the consequences of policy outputs. Institu-
tions are different; no matter how broadly defined they are or whatever
intentional goal underlies their introduction or any function that may be
attributed to them, institutions count as such by their collective acceptance
as rules or constraints to govern behaviour. This holds whether or not institu-
tions are respected or whether or not they are followed, consciously or
unconsciously, as in internalized habits and routines.
The conceptual distinction between a policy and an institution is significant
in terms of the use of path dependency in policy studies and provides two
options for progress. The first is to proceed by analogy from institutions to
policy as the subject of path dependency and so allow the existing body of
work in historical institutionalism to be used to support theory-building and
empirical testing in specific studies of policy. The second option would be to
apply and theorize the concept in policy development sui generis. Almost all
recent work has proceeded using the first route since the second would
separate the concept of path dependency from historical institutionalism.
This is possible, as shown in the section on the origins of the concept, but
would require undertaking significant new theoretical work with uncertain
benefits. The issue of the robustness of the argument by analogy from
institutions to policy is considered in the section that follows. The initial
question considered here is: what does it mean to say that a policy is path
dependent?
There is no unique policy level or scale but rather several levels that may
be examined as ‘policy’, as Heclo (1972, p. 84) puts it:
As commonly used, the term policy is usually considered to apply to
something ‘bigger’ that particular decisions, but ‘smaller’ than general
social movements. Thus, policy, in terms of levels of analysis, is a concept
placed roughly in the middle range.
The first scale in this middle range is that of the policy system. In these
terms, policy is a ‘whole’ or system as in discussions of health policy,
defence policy or housing policy. It is not simply journalistic shorthand to
talk about policy development, there is a ‘whole’ or a ‘system’ at a policy
level that can be the subject of active and passive verbs and the object of
empirical investigation without stretching the limits of our imagination too
far. A policy system is a relevant and valid unit of analysis for the application
The question of what it is about a policy that is path dependent does not
admit a single, conclusive answer; rather, it remains an open and empirical
question for scholars applying the concept. It is incumbent upon scholars
using the concept, whether theoretically or empirically, to be clear about in
which sense the term policy is being used: in particular, which scale of per-
spective is being adopted – the level of the whole or particular constituent
elements of a policy or to policy level institutions?
dependency. Increasing returns are sufficient (but not necessary) for path
dependency. As Arrow (2000) points out, significant sunk costs and
sequencing arguments are sufficient to construct path dependency stories in
the economics of technology. Further, Arthur Stinchcombe’s celebrated
work (1968, Chapter 5) on constructing theories of historical causation
emphasizes the central importance of sunk costs. Thus, work should not focus
exclusively on increasing returns processes and it is moot whether this mechan-
ism type should be privileged over other sources of path dependency.
This is an important point since a number of non-increasing returns mech-
anisms have been suggested as underlying path dependency in policy
development. These include: (1) the effect of policy on interest groups as
when policies constrain some groups and enable others (Pierson 2000b); (2)
policies involve investment or disinvestments in administrative infrastructure
this transforms governmental capacity and the set of possible future policies
that may be enacted (Skocpol 1992); (3) policies involve the establishment of
formal or informal contracts with individuals (Kemp 2001; Pemberton 2003;
Kay 2003) which are costly to change. Further, there are network effects to
types of a contract; that is the transaction costs of agreeing another contract
of that type in that area of public policy will be considerably lower than a
different, and in particular bespoke, contract.
All these policy specific mechanisms are based on definite, conscious
choices that have the foreseeable consequence of high future switching
costs; none relies on an increasing returns process. Insofar as policy-making
does not involve small, unintentional and random actions that have signifi-
cant consequences because of increasing returns, the argument by analogy
from the economics of technology to policy is weak. There are, however,
examples that suggest that increasing returns processes can occur in policy
development. In the reform of the primary care sector in the UK after 1997, a
series of primary care models were piloted. By a series of chance factors, a
particular primary care trust model quickly became popular. This model
subsequently became the government’s template for all future combinations
of primary care organizations. There was no particular feature to this model
to recommend it over any of the others that were piloted between 1997 and
2000; instead, it was the case that this model was adopted early in the
government’s reform process, something that made it considerably easier
(or cheaper) for subsequent primary care groups to use it, and with such
a momentum it became the template adopted by the government for all
primary care agglomerations.
An emphasis on policy as choice raises important questions of rationality.
In the mechanisms noted above, agents make choices according to the costs
and benefits of the consequences of different options. Any borrowing from
economics inevitably situates the agent in terms of responding to these costs
and benefits in a manner consistent with straightforward parametric ration-
ality. The assumption of this type of rationality serves certain purposes in
formal economic modelling, but to use it in more informal, intuitive and
dependent in the sense that it rejects the traditional postulate that the same
operative forces will generate the same results everywhere in favour of the
view that the effect of such forces will be mediated by the contextual fea-
tures of a given situation often inherited from the past’ (Hall and Taylor
1996, p. 941). In these terms, path dependency is a metaphor, but this does
not imply any attenuation in the explanatory force of the concept. Indeed,
this may reflect the ‘history’ part of historical institutionalism. Metaphors
can contribute to the narrative of unique policy paths. A narrative conveys
not just information but understanding. It arranges events in a way that
renders them intelligible. It is therefore tempting to describe narrative as a
form of explanation. This is something accepted by many historians (Roth
1999).
A metaphor can help improve a policy story by providing reasons. A rea-
son is a rationale, which provides the explanatory context for the action.
Reasons can explain in the absence of mechanisms. Some historians will
accept this claim (Turner 1999; Roth 1999), often as a sine qua non of conducting
historical inquiry. However, the concept of path dependency is ambiguous in
these terms. For some narrative explanation is a reduced form of causal explan-
ation, useful when there is uncertainty about the mechanism operating or
where a reason is accepted as existing that implies the mechanism.
For others, narratives can never explain. For example, in a widely cited
paper, Goldstone (1998) examines path dependency from the perspective of
historical sociology and asserts that narratives tend to be based on ‘Dr
Suess-like explanatory principles’ (Goldstone 1998, p. 832): events are
wholly contingent and unique and they just happen to happen this way and
are not very likely to happen that way again. Narratives cannot be causal
(and therefore enjoy explanatory power) ‘unless there is some assertion of a
necessary or highly probable connection between events A, B, and C in the
series of events that make up the narrative’ (p. 835). This demand for well-
established mechanisms serves to highlight their scarcity outside the intel-
lectual borrowings from the economics of institutions and provides a clear
challenge for policy scholars.
The notion of context bound rationality is at the heart of path dependency
yet remains underdeveloped in terms of the policy literature. This does not
defeat the concept but highlights a challenge for scholars wishing to employ
the term. Path dependency literature is most developed around the follow-
ing two claims: (1) that the analogy from economics to institutions can be
extended to policy; and (2) that micro economics can be borrowed as the
micro foundations of path dependency in policy development. However,
these claims require a rational choice actor making the decisions. The assump-
tion of this type of rationality is a strict corollary of claims (1) and (2).
institutionalist school, ‘in its emphasis upon path dependence and historical
legacies it is rather better at explaining stability than change’ (Hay 2002,
p. 15). Thelen (1999) argues that path dependency is also too deterministic in
that once the initial choice is made, then the argument for future develop-
ment becomes mechanical. There is one fork in the road, and after that, the
path only narrows.
In terms of policy studies, one possible counterargument is based on the
interpretation of stability in path dependency. Specifically, the notion does
allow policy change; policy legacies constrain rather than determine current
policy. Policy does change but within a particular set of change options; thus
the policy may be said to exhibit stability. There are two main implications
of the constrained change argument. The first is that these choice sets may
be large or the paths wide; and the wider they are the less the notion of path
dependency can account for current policy development. In alternative
terms, the weaker is the ‘echo’ of past policy developments in the present,
the more other concepts, framework and theories are required.
The second issue is that, explicit in the notion of a policy path, is the
notion that policy may be represented as a single point variable in policy
space. As such, it is a vector, that is, it has a velocity and has a direction.
Because policy has a velocity that can change, policy time can unfold
unevenly and nonlinearly. As such, policy change is often characterized by
moments of crisis (Hay 2002). The problem for the notion of path depend-
ency as constrained change, is the velocity of change. Where the velocity of
policy is subject to change – acceleration or deceleration – this can assist the
formulation of accounts of crises that precipitate policy change. However, it
is difficult to reconcile acceleration in policy time with policy stability.
On the other hand, the notion of policy direction may assist constrained
change accounts of policy development. A stable policy path when
projected into policy space may well imply significant cumulative policy
change over time or, in other terms, a significant distance from the initial
position in policy space and time. A stable equilibrium path does not neces-
sarily imply a fixed point in policy space; change occurs as a function of
time. Rose and Davies (1994) show the importance of compounding effects
as small, incremental and constrained changes in annual budget allocations
can accumulate to significant policy shifts over a period of a decade or more.
Further, a change in direction may appear at one distance to be a small
perturbation but by shifting the direction of the policy may turn out in retro-
spect to have been a critical juncture and a problem for the validity of path
dependency as a description. Kay (2003) argues that the development of the
EU’s CAP is an example of this possibility: although considered minor at the
time the reforms of 1988, rather than 1992, were the critical juncture in shift-
ing the direction of the CAP from a price support to direct income payment
system.
Nonetheless, the limitations of path dependency as a conception of policy
change have been highlighted in recent empirical applications in public
policy: Kemp (2001) with respect to housing benefit reform in the UK;
Pemberton (2003) with regard to pensions; Greener (2002) on the NHS; and
Kay (2003) with respect to the CAP. Each of these studies finds path depend-
ency in policy development alongside some policy change. They consider
change as a reaction to the unintended consequences or side effects of
policy, or from pressure for reform due to exogenous shifts in the wider
policy environment; for example, where the distribution of power between
interested groups moves. These studies show that once a dualism between
policy stability and policy change is established, the notion of path depend-
ency is only useful for accounting for the former.
The dualism between stability and change can be avoided by considering
the sedimentation of policy decisions or the growing complexity of policy
space that is implied by the notion of path dependency. As noted earlier, the
dynamics of subsystem accumulation are theoretically underdeveloped in
the literature but seem promising in terms of path dependency in public
policy (see, for example, Pemberton 2003 and the UK pensions’ policy). The
development of UK pharmaceutical policy since the 1980s is another
example of new policies being added on as a ‘patch’ or ‘fix’ to satisfy pres-
sure to mitigate the consequences of the original policy: relatively high
prices for medicines were agreed by the government to reward innovation
by the industry under the extant Pharmaceutical Price Regulation Scheme
(PPRS); this contributed to the rapid increases in public expenditure on
medicines since the late 1980s. The PPRS remains unchanged and poten-
tially path dependent but its budgetary consequences precipitated a series
of new policies aimed at controlling the demand for medicines in the NHS –
for example, cash-limited prescribing budgets. The accumulation of these
policy patches is an example of policy change and the path dependency of
particular policy subsystem is a contributory factor to their explanation. The
idea of policy space becoming more complex as new policy elements accrete
around an existing path-dependent subsystem may encourage some theo-
retical work to examine linkages between policies. However, currently no
such work appears in the literature.
second, whether the inefficiency remains remediable, that is, that a pareto
improvement can be identified and is achievable from the current situation.
For some writers, the question of whether path dependency implies the
persistence of inefficient institutions is an open and empirical question (see,
for example, Hay and Wincott 1998); for others, path dependency is more
clearly something which inhibits the introduction of ‘better’ or perhaps
more rational policy or organizational form (see, for example, Greener 2002).
Overall, the normative implications of path dependency are less pressing for
scholars outside the boundaries of neo-classical economics; it is generally
accepted that inefficient policies or institutions may persist. However, it is a
much stronger claim that policies in a path-dependent process are necessarily
inefficient or, alternatively, that contained within the concept is the imputa-
tion of inefficiency. The claim is strong at a theoretical level since the
concept would require significant elaboration in terms of both policy design
and the pressures that sustain path dependent and inefficient policy. There
is also the problem of indeterminism: path dependency emphasizes that
policy paths are unique and arrived at by a series of small and contingent
moves. As such, it is difficult to say that there exists another path that could
have been arrived at which is more efficient and without such a relevant
counterfactual it is difficult to accept the imputation of inefficiency.
At an empirical level, the claim that policies are necessarily inefficient is
also strong. Developments in performance measurement in the public sector
might allow arguments that, for example, health care or education policy are
better in one system than another. Despite this, it is difficult to assert, within
a particular political system, that there exist policy options which represent
a welfare improvement over the current policy (net of switching costs and
increased transaction costs) and there is widespread recognition of this by
policy actors. Without these two conditions holding, the normative implications
of path dependency in terms of public policy are attenuated. Nonetheless,
empirical works on path dependency in policy development seem willing to
impute inefficiency to some degree (Wilsford 1994; Kemp 2001; Greener
2002; Pemberton 2003; Kay 2003). This is often not so stark as labelling poli-
cies in terms of efficiency and certainly involves no quantitative analysis;
however, it is not an over-interpretation of these works to tease out the
implicit assumption that a policy would be ‘better’ without path dependent
process acting as a barrier to effective reform.
CONCLUSION
This paper has examined the recent literature on path dependency in terms
of explaining public policy development. The first section highlighted the
problems with policy as a unit of analysis, in particular whether it can be
conceived as a composite whole or is it a series of decisions and actions at
different scales that do not cohere as a whole? Although the notion of path
dependency does not provide any definitive guide in this regard, I have
argued that it does make sense to talk about a policy ‘whole’ or system with
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
I would like to thank three anonymous referees and Professor Rhodes for
their helpful and encouraging comments on an earlier version of this article.
All errors remain my own.
REFERENCES
Arrow, K.J. 2000. ‘Increasing Returns: Historiographic Issues and Path Dependence’, The European Journal of
the History of Economic Thought, 7, 1, 171–80.
Arthur, W.B. 1994. Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy. Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press.
Baumgartner, F. and B. Jones (eds) 2002. Policy Dynamics. London: University of Chicago Press.
David, P.A. 1985. ‘Clio and the Economics of QWERTY’, American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 75,
332–7.
Denzau, A.D. and D.C. North. 1994. ‘Shared Mental Models: Ideologies and Institutions’, Kyklos, 47, 1, 3–31.
Dye, T.R. 1972. Understanding Public Policy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Elster. J. 1976. ‘A Note on Hysteresis in the Social Sciences’, Synthese, 33, 371–91.
Elster, J. 1998. ‘A Plea for Mechanisms’, Chapter 3 in P. Hedstrom and R. Swedberg (eds), Social Mechanisms:
an Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Georgescu-Roegen, N. 1967. Analytical Economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Georgescu-Roegen, N. 1971. The Entropy Law and the Economic Process. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Goldstone, J.A. 1998. ‘Initial Conditions, General Laws, Path Dependence, and Explanation in Historical Soci-
ology’, American Journal of Sociology, 104, 3, 829–45.
Goodin, R.E. 1998. ‘Institutions and their Design’, in R.E. Goodin (ed.), The Theory of Institutional Design.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Greener, I. 2002. ‘Understanding NHS Reform: the Policy-transfer, Social Learning, and Path Dependency’,
Governance, 15, 2, 161–83.
Hacker, J.S. 1998. ‘The Historical Logic of National Health Insurance: Structure and Sequence in the Develop-
ment of British, Canadian, and US Medical Policy’, Studies in American Political Development, 12, 57–130.
Hacker, J. 2002. The Divided Welfare State: The Battle Over Public and Private Social Benefits in the United States.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hall, P.A. 1993. ‘Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State’, Comparative Politics, 25, 3, 275–96.
Hall, P.A., and R.C.R. Taylor. 1996. ‘Political Science and the Three New Institutionalisms’, Political Studies,
44, 4, 936–57.
Hall, P.A., and R.C.R. Taylor. 1998. ‘The Potential of Historical Institutionalism: a Response to Hay and
Wincott’, Political Studies, 46, 5, 958–62.
Hay, C. 2002. Political Analysis: a Critical Introduction. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Hay, C. 2004. ‘Theory, Stylized Heuristic or Self-fulfilling Prophecy? The Status of Rational Choice Theory in
Public Administration’, Public Administration, 82, 1, 39–62.
Hay, C. and D. Wincott. 1998. ‘Structure, Agency and Historical Institutionalism’, Political Studies, 46, 5, 951–7.
Heclo, H. 1972. ‘Review Article: Policy Analysis’, British Journal of Political Science, 2, 83–108.
Hempel, C.G. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: The Free Press.
Hodgson, G.M. 2001. How Economics Forgot History: the Problem of Historical Specificity in Social Science.
London: Routledge.
Holzinger, K. and C. Knill. 2002. ‘Path Dependencies in European Integration: a Constructive Response to
German Foreign Minister Joschka Fischer’, Public Administration, 80, 1, 125–52.
Howlett, M. and M. Ramesh. 2003, Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems. 2nd edn. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
John, P. 2003. ‘Is There Life After Policy Streams, Advocacy Coalitions and Punctuated Equilibria: Using
Evolutionary Theory to Explain Policy Change?’ Policy Studies Journal, 31, 4.
Kaldor, N. 1970. ‘The Case for Regional Policies’, Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 18, 337–48.
Kay, A. 2003. ‘Path Dependency and the CAP’, Journal of European Public Policy, 10, 3, 405–21.
Kemp, P. 2000. ‘Housing Benefit and Welfare State Retrenchment in Britain’, Journal of Social Policy, 29, 2, 263–79.
Krasner, S. 1984. ‘Approaches to the State: Alternative Conceptions and Historical Dynamics’, Comparative
Politics, 16, 223–46.
Lindefeld, D.F. 1999. ‘Causality, Chaos Theory, and the End of the Weimar Republic: a Commentary on
“Henry Turner’s Hitler’s Thirty Days to Power”’, History and Theory, 38, 3, 281–99.
McDonald, T.J. (ed.). 1996. The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Nooteboom, B. 1997. ‘Path Dependence of Knowledge: Implications for the Theory of the Firm’, in
L. Magnusson and J. Ottosson (eds), Evolutionary Economics and Path Dependence. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
North, D.C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Ostrom, E. 1999. ‘Institutional Rational Choice: An Assessment of the Institutional Analysis and Development
Framework’, in P. Sabatier (ed.), Theories of the Policy Process, Boulder, CO: Westview Press, pp. 35–72.
Parsons, W. 1995. Public Policy. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Pemberton, H. 2003. ‘Lock-in or Lock-out? Path Dependency and British Pensions’, Paper presented to PSA,
Leicester, April 2003.
Pierson, P. 1993. ‘When Effect Becomes Cause: Policy Feedback and Political Change’, World Politics, 45, 595–628.
Pierson, P. 2000a. ‘Not just What but When: Timing and Sequencing in Political Processes’, Studies in American
Political Development, 14, 1, 72–92.
Pierson, P. 2000b. ‘Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics’, American Political Science
Review, 94, 2, 251–67.
Pierson, P. 2000c. ‘The Limits of Design: Explaining Institutional Origins and Change’, Governance, 13, 4, 474–99.
Pritchard, D. 2002. ‘Are Economic Decisions Rational? Path Dependence, Lock-in and “Hinge” Propositions’,
Reason in Practice, 2, 3, 31–45.
Raadschelders, J.C.N. 1998. ‘Evolution, Institutional Analysis and Path Dependency: an Administrative-
History Perspective on Fashionable Approaches and Concepts’, International Review of Administrative
Sciences, 64, 4, 565–82.
Roberts, C. 1996. The Logic of Historical Explanation. University Park, PA: Penn State University Press.
Rose, R. and P.L. Davies. 1994. Inheritance in Public Policy: Change Without Choice in Britain. London: Yale
University Press.
Roth, P.A. 1999. ‘The Full Hempel: a Review Essay of Clayton Roberts, The Logic of Historical Explanation’,
History and Theory, 38, 249–63.
Skocpol, T. 1992. Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: the Political Origins of Social Policy in the United States.
Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard.
Stinchcombe, A.L. 1968. Constructing Social Theories. London: University of Chicago Press.
Thelen, K. 1999. ‘Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics’, Annual Review of Political Science, 2, 369–404.
Tholfsen, T.R. 1967. Historical Thinking: an Introduction. New York: Harper and Row.
Tilly, C. 1991. ‘How (and What) are Historians Doing?’, in D. Easton and C.S. Schelling (eds), Divided Know-
ledge. London: Sage.
Turner, H.A. 1999. ‘Human Agency and Impersonal Determinants in Historical Causation: a Response to
David Lindenfeld’, History and Theory, 38, 3, 300–06.
Wilsford, D. 1994. ‘Path Dependency, or Why History Makes it Difficult but Not Impossible to Reform Health
Care Services in a Big Way’, Journal of Public Policy, 14, 251–83.