54 4 2 PDF
54 4 2 PDF
54 4 2 PDF
54 (1993)
1
Echoes of Hellenistic Judaism's negative theology are found in the New Testament's
assertions that God and God's ways are invisible, immortal, ineffable, indescribable,
unsearchable, and untraceable (Rom 1:20; 11:33; 2 Cor 9:15, 12:4, 1 Tim 6:16).
2
Jean Danielou distinguishes the three sources: "For a Jew, to say that God is tran-
scendent is to say that he cannot be measured by any created thing, and is therefore
incomprehensible to the creaturely mind; but at the same time it is to assert that his
existence can be known. For the Plantonist, to say that God is ineffable is to say that he
surpasses any conception of him that the mind can form in terms of the sensible world;
but it is also to affirm that, if only the mind can shake itself free from all conceptions of
that kind, it will be able to grasp his essence. For the Gnostic, however, the matter goes
far deeper. God is unknown absolutely, both in his essence and in his existence; he is the
one of whom, in the strictest sense, nothing is known, and this situation can be overcome
only through the Gnosis" (A History of Early Christian Doctrine before the Council of
Nicea 2: Gospel Message and Hellenistic Culture, trans, and ed. J. Baker [Philadelphia:
Westminster, 1973] 335-36).
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 643
3
For two English translations of the Dionysian corpus, see The Divine Names and
Mystical Theology, trans, with Introduction by John Jones (Milwaukee: Marquette,
1980); The Complete Works, trans. Colm Luibheid (New York: Paulist, 1987). Other
literature on Pseudo-Dionysius: Vladimir Lossky, "La thgologie negative dans la doc-
trine de Denys TAr^opagite," Revue des sciences philosophiques et thiologiques 28 (1939)
204-21; Jean Vanneste, he mystdre de Dieu (Brussels: Descl6e, 1959); Walter M. Neidl,
Thearchia: Die Frage nach dem Sinn von Gott bei Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita und
Thomas von Aquin (Regensburg: Habbel, 1976); John Jones, "The Character of the
Negative (Mystical) Theology for Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagite," Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association 51 (1977) 66-74; Salvatore Lilla, "The
Notion of Infinitude in Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita/' Journal of Theological Studies 31
(1980) 93-103; Michel Corbin, "Negation et transcendance dans l'oeuvre de Denys/'
RSPT 69 (1985) 41-76; Paul Rorem, Biblical and Liturgical Symbols within thePseudo-
Dionysian Synthesis (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1984). See also
R. G. Williams, "The Via Negativa and the Foundations of Theology: An Introduction to
the Thought of V. N. Lossky," in New Studies in Theology, no. 1, ed. S. Sykes and D.
Holmes (London: Duckworth, 1980) 95-117.
4
The Divine Names 7.3 (872A). Citations within parentheses or brackets refer to the
third volume of Migne's Patrologia Graeca.
5 6
Ibid. 1.4 (593A). Ibid. 1.6 (596A).
7 8
Ibid. 1.6 (596ABC). Ibid. 7.3 (872A).
644 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
only one? The problem is compounded by the fact that, although in the
third chapter of his Mystical Theology and elsewhere he clearly distin-
guishes rational affirmative theology from mystical negations and un-
knowing, in his Divine Names we often discover a mixture of positive
and negative theology within rational theological discourse. However,
even at the conclusion of the Divine Names, which is a work of con-
ceptual, affirmative theology, Dionysius mentions his preference for
"the way up through negations" which "guides the soul through all the
divine notions, notions which are themselves transcended by that
which is far beyond every name, all reason and all knowledge."9 Al-
though he does not treat his preferred way, that of mystical negation,
until the Mystical Theology, it has nevertheless already been function-
ing in the Divine Names as a corrective guide for affirmative notional
theology.10 Another passage clearly distinguishes the mystical from
the notional and philosophical way to God:
Theological tradition has a dual aspect, the ineffable and mysterious on the
one hand, the open and more evident on the other. The one resorts to symbol-
ism and involves initiation. The other is philosophic and employs the method
of demonstration The one uses persuasion and imposes the truthfulness of
what is asserted. The other acts and, by means of a mystery which cannot be
taught, puts souls firmly in the presence of God.11
I would argue that Dionysius has only one negative theology, a via
negativa which is based on a mystical, nonconceptual grasp of God's
transcendent supereminence and is opposed to all conceptual, affirma-
tive, positive theology.12 For Dionysius, God is absolutely unknowable
9
Ibid. 13.3 (981AB; Luibheid trans. 130). This passage and many others (ibid. 1.1
[588AB1; 7.3 [872AB]; Celestial Hierarchy, 2.3 [141A]; Utter 9.1 [1105CD]; Mystical
Theology 3 [1032D-1033D]) display the superiority, in Dionysius's eyes, of the mystical
way of negation. Lossky has some fine words on the Dionysian mystical way of unknow-
ing, which requires spiritual detachment, purgation, and the continual denial of predi-
cates in order to prepare for ecstasy, union, and finally divinization ("Th6ologie nega-
tive" 211-18).
10
Divine Names 13.3 (980B-981B).
II
Letter 9.1 (1105D; Luibheid trans. 283). Dionysius remarks that Blessed Hi-
erotheus, his esteemed teacher, was instructed (the word mucin originally meant to be
initiated into the mysteries) by divine inspiration, "not only learning but also experi-
encing the divine things" (Divine Names 2.9 [648B]; Luibheid trans. 65). The reference
to initiation reflects the liturgical underpinnings of Dionysius's mystical theology; his
Ecclesiastical Hierarchy also develops an epistemology of sacramental symbols as ways
to God. Rorem's study (above, n. 3) points out the many biblical allusions and liturgical
symbols which undergird the positive theology of the Divine Names.
12
A more extended argument for this position may be found in Gregory Rocca, "Anal-
ogy as Judgment and Faith in God's Incomprehensibility: A study in the Theological
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 645
17
Summa theologiae (ST) 1.12.1.ad 1,3; 1.12.7.ad 2.
18
SCG 3.49.2270.
19
Thomas expresses this view many times (SS 1.3.1.3; 1.8.1.1; SCG 1.11.66,69;
1.12.78; DP 7.2.ad 1,11).
20
SS 1.2.1.3; 3.24.1.1.2; 3.24.1.2.1; 3.35.2.2.2; 4.10.1.4.5; 4.49.2.1.ad 3; 4.49.2.7.ad 8;
W2.1.ad 9; 8.1; 10.11; SCG 1.3.16-17; 1.25.233-34; 3.49.2268; DP 7.5.ad 1, ad 5, ad 6,
ad 9; ST 1.3.5; 1.12.2; Compendium theologiae (CT) 1.26.
21
ST 1.12.2,4. John Wippel asserts that from the very beginning of his career Thomas
taught that we have no quidditative knowledge of God, and that when Thomas says that
what God is remains totally unknown to us, he is taking quidditative knowledge strictly,
in the sense of a comprehensive or defining knowledge (Metaphysical Themes in Thomas
Aquinas [Washington: Catholic University of America, 1984] 238-41).
22
Karl Rahner sees this as Thomas's more radical view of God's incomprehensibility
("An Investigation of the Incomprehensibility of God in St. Thomas Aquinas," Theolog-
ical Investigations [New York: Seabury, 1979] 16:244-54) and prefers himself to speak
of God's "holy inconceivability" ("The Experiences of a Catholic Theologian," Communio
11 [1984] 404-14, at 406). See also Paul Wess, Wie von Gott sprechen? Eine Ausein-
andersetzung mit Karl Rahner (Graz: Styria, 1970). Elizabeth Johnson retrieves the
tradition of God's incomprehensibility as a critical resource for feminist theological
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 647
discourse ('The Incomprehensibility of God and the Image of God Male and Female/' TS
45 [1984] 441-65; She Who Is [New York: Crossroad, 1992] 104-20).
23
SS 1.2.1.3; 1.3.1.1; 3.14.1.2.1; 4.49.2.3; SCG 3.49.2268; 3.55; ST 1.12.7; 1.62.9;
1-2.4.3; 2-2.27.5; 3.10.1; DDN 1.1.34; DP 7.3.ad 5; DV 8.1.ad 9; 8.2; 20.4-5; CT 1.106;
1.216.
24
DV 8.2.ad 6; cf. 8.4.ad 6; DP 7.1.ad 2.
25
Rahner realizes the mystery of heaven's beatific vision, especially when we remem-
ber that the blessed see God as a simple whole and as incomprehensible: "The assertion
of the direct vision of God and assertion of his incomprehensibility are related for us here
and now in a mysterious and paradoxical dialectic" ("An Investigation" 247).
26
ST 1.12.7.ad 3. H.-F. Dondaine, in an article replete with rich historical data,
manifests how Thomas displayed his originality in keeping to a middle course between
the Augustinians and Albert the Great on the question of whether we know God essen-
tially or comprehensively ("Cognoscere de Deo 'quid est*," Recherches de thCologie anci-
enne et mCdiCvale 22 [1955] 72-78).
27
DDN 1.3.104; 7.1.702; SCG 3.49.2270; DP 9.7; ST 1.11.3.ad 2; 1.13.10.ad 5.
648 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
When we proceed into God through the way of negation, first we deny of him
all corporeal things; and next, we even deny intellectual things as they are
found in creatures, like goodness and wisdom, and then there remains in our
understanding only the fact that God exists, and nothing further, so that it
suffers a kind of confusion. Lastly, however, we even remove from him his very
28
For more on the three forms of Aquinas's negative theology, see Rocca, "Analogy as
Judgment" 151-58.
29
Objective modal negations are the same as the via negativa understood as the second
moment of the threefold way to God, which means that Aquinas's negative theology
encompasses more than the via negativa.
30
For a full account of Aquinas' treatment of subjective modal negations, see Gregory
Rocca, "The Distinction between Res Significata and Modus Significandi in Aquinas's
Theological Epistemology," Thomist 55 (1991) 173-97.
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 649
existence, as it is in creatures, and then our understanding remains in a
certain darkness of ignorance according to which, as Dionysius says, we are
best united to God in this present state of life; and this is a sort of thick
darkness in which God is said to dwell.31
31
SS 1.8.1.1.ad 4; cf. DDN 13.3.996.
32
Although it is true that after 6 December 1273 Thomas added nothing in writing to
his major academic works then in progress, scholars date his brief letter to the abbot of
Monte Cassino (Epistola ad Bernardum Abbatem Casinensem) to early 1274 when he
was on his way to the second council of Lyons. The letter deals with a recondite issue
about predestination found in Gregory the Great's Moralia. In this case, as also in the
legend about his commentary on the Song of Songs to the Cistercian monks of Fossanova
during the last few weeks of his life, Thomas's charity outweighed his disinclination to
write or dictate. See Antoine Dondaine, "La lettre de Saint Thomas a l'abbg du Mont-
cassin," in St. Thomas Aquinas 1274-1974: Commemorative Studies (Toronto: Pontifical
Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974) 1.87-108.
33
ST 1.3.4; see Rocca, "Analogy as Judgment" 164-73, 462-93.
34
SS 1.2.1.3; 1.22.1.2; 1.35.1.1.ad 2; DV 2.1; DP 7.5-6; ST 1.13.2,6,12.
650 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
When it is said that "God is good," the meaning is not "God is the cause of
goodness" or "God is not evil/' but "that which we call goodness in creatures
preexists in God," and preexists according to a higher mode. From all of this,
then, it does not follow that to be good belongs to God insofar as he causes
goodness, but rather vice versa, that because he is good he diffuses goodness to
things.35
Aquinas is quite willing to walk a tightrope, for although his negative
theology denies that we have any intuitive concept of God's essence or
being, his positive theology affirms that we can make true judgments
about that same divine reality; and although he supports a robust via
negativa, he will not permit affirmative propositions about God to be
reduced to a merely negative interpretation.
How can Aquinas hold all of this together? How can he swing be-
tween the poles of positive and negative theology, partaking of both
while being reduced to neither? He accomplishes this balancing act by
means of the analogical predication of the divine names.36
But which type of analogy does Aquinas have in mind, and what is
the nature of that analogy? Up until about forty years ago the reigning
interpretation of Aquinas on analogy was that of the Dominican Car-
dinal Cajetan de Vio, who, in his 1498 De nominum analogia et de
conceptu entis,37 proposed a fourfold typology of Thomistic analogy and
explained the nature of genuine analogy in highly conceptualistic
terms. Basing himself mainly on a combined reading of two early
texts, 38 Cajetan holds that Aquinas recognizes only four analogical
types: of inequality, of attribution, of improper metaphorical propor-
tionality, and of proper proportionality.39 According to Cajetan, how-
ever, only the last type is genuine analogy, for it alone posits real
perfections in both God and creatures, according to a fourfold propor-
tionality (e.g., creatures' being : creatures :: God's being : God). In the
analogy of attribution, however, the perfection only really exists in the
prime analogate, while it is merely attributed to the secondary analo-
35
ST 1.13.2; cf. 1.13.6.
36
In many texts (SS 1.4.1.1; 1.34.3.2.ad 3; 1.45.1.4; DV4.1.ad 10; ST 1.13.3), Aquinas
subdivides predications which refer positively to God's being into those which are met-
aphorically true and those which are true according to the proper and literal meaning of
their terms (and hy "literal" he does not mean an iconic idea with a physical referent but
rather the strict truth of a judgment). His theory of theological analogy is meant to
explain how we can speak truthfully about God in a nonmetaphorical fashion. Contrari-
wise, much of contemporary writing on theological epistemology tends to blur the dis-
tinction between metaphor and analogy.
37
Ed. P. N. Zammit (Rome: Angelicum, 1934); trans. E. A. Bushinski and H. J. Koren,
in The Analogy of Names and the Concept of Being (Pittsburgh: Duquesne, 1953).
38 39
SS 1.19.5.2.ad 1, and DV 2.11. De nominum analogia, chaps. 1-3.
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 651
43
Opus Oxoniense, Ordinatio 1.8.1.3, nos. 81-82; 1.3.1.1-2, nos. 26-30 (Opera Om-
nia, ed. C. Balic [Vatican City, 1950] 4:190, 3:18-20); Quaestiones subtilissimae in
Metaphysicam 4.1.5.
44
Cyril Shircel, The Univocity of the Concept ofBeing in the Philosophy of John Duns
Scotus, (Washington: Catholic Univ. of America, 1942); fitienne Gilson, Jean Duns Scot
(Paris: Vrin, 1952); Michael Schmaus, Zur Diskussion uher das Problem der Univozitdt
im Umkreis des Johannes Duns Skotus (Munich: Bayerische Akademie der Wissen-
schaften, 1957).
45
De nominum analogia, chaps. 4-10.
46
Montagnes, La doctrine de Vanalogie 150-58; Henri Bouillard, The Knowledge of
God, trans. S. D. Femiano (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968) 105-7.
47
Etienne Gilson writes that "the Thomist doctrine of analogy is above all a doctrine
ofthe judgment of analogy" (Jean Duns Scot 101). Claiming in general that analogy is
the semantic expression of the judgments philosophers make and the result of how
language must work in order to do justice to insight, David Burrell also discerns in
Aquinas a view of analogy as usage based on insightful judgments {Analogy and Philo-
sophical Language [New Haven: Yale, 1973] chaps. 1-2, 6-7, 9). A few other scholars
have also begun to view analogy as judgmental rather than conceptual. W. Norris
Clarke sees analogy as based on our ability to make the judgments we do ("Analogy and
the Meaningfulness of Language about God: A Reply to Kai Nielsen," Thomist 40 [1976]
61-95, at 64-72). For Colman O'Neill, all analogy is judgmental because it occurs when
a predicate is transferred from its normal linguistic context to a new one not originally
its own; to speak of "analogical concepts," he says, is a "disastrous misunderstanding"
("La predication analogique: L'el&nent n£gatif," in Analogic et dialectique, eds. P. Gisel
and P. Secretan [Geneva: Labor et Fides, 1982] 81-91, at 82). He writes that "the
theological theory of proper analogical predication deals with the very complex phenom-
enon of complete statements which express judgments inspired by faith about the reality
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 653
48
use of analogy. Theological analogy, in particular, is in Thomas's
eyes the only valid way of explaining epistemologically, in a second-
ary, after-the-fact reflection, what takes place in the primary ontolog-
ical and theological judgments that bear upon God's very being.49
Aquinas's theological analogy is actually an epistemological reflection
upon the truth status of the theological judgments he has already
made, and so one cannot understand his view of analogy without ap-
preciating the truth of his basic theological positions.50 And only if
Thomas's use of theological analogy is understood more as a matter of
judgments than of concepts can it thread its way amidst various
threatening shoals.51
One would look in vain, however, for an explicit statement from
Aquinas that theological analogy is a matter of theological judgments.
My contention that his theological analogy is a matter of judgment is
an interpretation of his thought based on two main reasons: the posi-
tioning of analogy's treatment within his theological works; and the
of God.... It is false to place this theory on the same footing as those which deal only
with concepts" ("Analogy, Dialectic, and Inter-Confessional Theology," Thomist 47
[19831 43-65, at 57).
48
What Thomas means by analogy here is not to be confused with the so-called ar-
gument from analogy, which comprises four terms and is much used in biology and the
other sciences; see Mary Hesse, Models and Analogies in Science (Notre Dame: Univ. of
Notre Dame, 1966).
49
See Rocca, "Analogy as Judgment" chaps. 6-7, 10, 13.
50
O'Neill writes that theological analogy "has to do with the linguistic expression of
a knowledge about God that is held, whether rightly or wrongly, to be already acquired
and to be true, even though necessarily imperfect. Those who speak in this way of
analogical predication take it as given that there are judgments about God, whether of
faith or reason, in which, by means of concepts drawnfromthe created world, the human
person attains the reality of God himself. All that the theory of analogy is meant to do
is to account for the oddities of linguistic expression which result from this conviction"
("Analogy" 45).
51
The conceptualistic understanding of analogy is rightfully subject to the critique of
those who claim that since it is tantamount to univocity it derogates from God's glory
and transcendence. Consider Barth's famous pronouncement against such a view of
analogy: "I regard the analogia entis as the invention of Antichrist, and think that
because of it one cannot become Catholic. Whereupon I at the same time allow myself to
regard all other possible reasons for not becoming Catholic as shortsighted and lacking
in seriousness" (Church Dogmatics [Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1936-77] 1/l.x). Eliza-
beth Johnson summarizes Pannenberg's critique of analogy so understood: "Analogy is
a relation requiring a logos common to both analogates. The structure of analogy un-
derstood in this way held goodfromprimitive human thought to the Neoplatonic causal
schema, and no subsequent concept of analogy, whether early Christian, medieval, or
modern, has ever broken through the confines of that Neoplatonic schema and its pre-
suppositions If one is opposed to univocity, however slight, existing in the essential
characteristics of Creator and creature, one must oppose analogy" ('The Right Way to
Speak about God? Pannenberg on Analogy," TS 43 [1982] 673-92, at 687).
654 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
Nothing can be predicated univocally about God and creatures, since no effect
whose production does not require the total power of its agent cause can re-
ceive a full likeness of the agent, but only a partial one; so that what occurs
among effects separately and plurally, exists in the cause simply and unitedly,
as the sun by its single force produces many different forms in all things
beneath it. Likewise, all perfections existing in creatures separately and plu-
rally, preexist in God unitedly. Thus, whenever any perfection term is predi-
cated of a creature, it signifies that perfection as distinct in idea from all
others: e.g., when we call a human wise we signify a perfection that is distinct
from the essence, power or existence of humans; but when we call God wise we
do not intend to signify anything distinct from the divine essence, power or
existence. And so, when wise is predicated of a human, the name somehow
circumscribes and comprehends the reality meant; but this is not the case with
God, where wise does not comprehend the divine reality but lets it remain as
surpassing the name's meaning. It is clear, then, that the name wise is not
predicated with an identical meaning of God and humans, and the same can be
said for all other names.52
ST 1.13.5.
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 655
Thomas does not clarify why he favors the one-to-one over the many-
to-one proportion, but it is clear from elsewhere that it has to do with
his desire to underscore divine freedom and transcendence, for if God
and creatures were given a common name by reference to some third
reality, then in his view that third reality would somehow be prior to
God and determine God's being. 54
53
Ibid.
54
SCG 1.34.297. This move is simply the epistemological correlative of Aquinas's
ontological rejection of any reality beyond or above God, whether it be Greek Necessity/
Fate, Platonic Forms, or Whiteheadian Creativity.
656 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
56
Analogy for Aquinas is a kind of systematic and intelligible ambiguity or equivoc-
ity, as distinct from a haphazard and accidental homonymy. The idea of an intelligible
ambiguity goes back to Aristotle's logic and metaphysics, whereas the name analogia
finds its home in mathematical and biological contexts. See Rocca, "Analogy as Judg-
ment" 179-96; Harry Wolfson, Studies in the History of Philosophy and Religion, ed.
Isadore Twersky and George Williams (Cambridge: Harvard Univ., 1977) 1:455-77;
2:514-23.
56
A detailed investigation of what Thomas understands by analogical discourse may
be found in Rocca, "Analogy as Judgment" chaps. 6-7.
57
SCG 1.34.298.
58
SS 1.24.1.1.ad 4; 1.48.1.1.ad 3; 1.35.1.4; DV 2.11; 10.13.ad 3; SCG 1.32-34; DP 7.7;
ST 1.13.5-6,10. See Montagnes, La doctrine de Vanalogie 67-70, 181-83; Hampus
Lyttkens, "Die Bedeutung der Gottespradikate bei Thomas von Aquin," Neue Zeitschrift
fur systematische Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 6 (1964) 280-83.
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 657
59
J. H. Nicolas is uncomfortable with any paradoxical interpretation that underscores
the extreme negativity of Aquinas's theology, for Thomas spent his whole life searching
for and saying "ce que Dieu est," and it is contradictory to say that one knows the divine
attributes without knowing the divine essence, since each attribute is the divine essence
partially known ("Affirmation de Dieu et connaissance," Revue thomiste 64 [1964]
200-222, at 200-204, 221-22). Nicolas's position, however, is directly rooted in his
assessment of what Thomas understands by judgment and truth: since judgment is
nothing more than the application of a previously known form or concept to a subject,
then any true judgment about God will have to use a concept of God's essence or attrib-
utes which in some manner attains "ce que Dieu est"; for him, then, to posit that our
affirmations of God imply no knowledge, even imperfect, of what God is, cannot be
consistent with Thomas's notion of truth. See Denis Bradley, "Thomistic Theology and
the Hegelian Critique of Religious Imagination," New Scholasticism 59 (1985) 60-78, at
77-78. Wess also sees an incompatibility between Thomas's notions of the mystery and
the natural knowability of God, but it is clear he does not understand the difference
between judgment and quidditative insight in Thomas when, in a Kantian fashion, he
criticizes the Thomistic proofs for God's existence because they cryptically rely on the
Anselmian ontological proof, which requires an adequate concept of God (Wie von Gott
sprechen? 107, 123-26).
60
O'Neill notes that since judgments use concepts, there is a paradox inherent in all
theological discourse: theological judgments affirm transcendence even though by
means of limited concepts ("La predication" 87-89; "Analogy" 52,57). Those who speak
of theological analogy as a projection, perspective, or tending towards God are also aware
of this paradox (Edward Schillebeeckx, Revelation and Theology [New York: Sheed and
Ward, 1968] 167,175,177,205-6; William Hill, Knowing the Unknown God [New York:
Philosophical Library, 1971] 88-97, 123, 144). Gilson remarks that true analogical
judgments about God orient us toward a goal, "the direction of which is known to us but
658 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
know the truth that God exists without knowing what the divine ex-
istence is in itself.
To be can mean two different things, signifying either the act of being, or the
propositional composition which the mind devises by joining predicate to sub-
ject. Taking to be in the first sense, we cannot know God's being, nor God's
essence; but only in the second sense. For we know that this proposition which
we form about God when we say "God is," is true.61
Thomas's positive theology is rather like a blind person pointing to and
making true judgments about a reality which he or she cannot actually
see. Even analogy itself is thoroughly suffused with a conceptual un-
knowing as referred to God, and with the various dialectical moments
of negative theology outlined above.62 Moreover, if we tend automati-
cally to think ofjudgments as built up out of concepts, so that the truth
which, because it is at infinity, is beyond the reach of our natural forces" (The Christian
Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas [New York: Random, 1956] 110). Clarke holds that
through the mediation (not representation) of the analogous concept, God is situated at
an "invisible apex" in an upward direction, and that a knowledge is gained which is
"obscure, vector-like, indirect, non-conceptual," such that God must be affirmed and yet
is still beyond representation ("Analogy" 93-95).
61
ST 1.3.4.ad 2. ST 1.13.12 and SCG 1.36 teach that we can form true affirmative
propositions about God. Although the divine nature is one and simple, the mind can only
know it through a plurality of judgments; but the mind also realizes that one and the
same simple God corresponds to its various judgments.
62
A few writers have interpreted analogy within a Thomistic perspective as involving
the threefold way to God, but without ascribing the notion as such to Aquinas. Bouillard
notes that analogy has all three moments since "it is a synthesis of a thesis and an
antithesis," where the way of eminence is the synthesis (Knowledge of God 109). Mcln-
erny asserts that even affirmative divine names have moments of negation and emi-
nence ("Can God Be Named by Us? Prolegomena to Thomistic Philosophy of Religion"
Review of Metaphysics 32 [1978] 53-73). O'Neill considers the threefold via within
analogy as a dialectic of mutually correcting judgments, not of contrary concepts which
could then result in some "higher" concept of God ("Analogy" 52-53, 59-60); even the
judgment "God exists" shows moments of negation and eminence ("La predication" 8 5 -
88). Those who compare analogy with dialectic often make Hegel the dialogue partner of
Thomas. For the theological importance of the two traditions of analogy and dialectic,
see Pierre Gisel and Philibert Secretan, eds., Analogie et dialectique (Geneva: Labor et
Fides, 1982); for the confrontation between analogy and dialectic, see Bernhard Lake-
brink, "Analektik und Dialektik: Zur Methode des Thomistischen und Hegelschen Den-
kens," in St. Thomas Aquinas, 1274-1974: Commemorative Studies (Toronto: Pontifical
Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974) 2:459-87. David Tracy shows the complementarity
of analogy and dialectic: just as analogy (based on manifestation) without its own neg-
ative moment becomes wooden univocity, so dialectic (based on proclamation) left to
itself becomes equivocity and destruction (The Analogical Imagination [New York:
Crossroad, 1981] chaps. 5,10). O'Neill considers analogy the fundamental matrix within
which dialectic can find a home, for dialectic itself cannot be basic ("Analogy" 43-54,
62-65).
AQUINAS ON GOD-TALK: HOVERING OVER THE ABYSS 659
63
Clarke writes that God cannot be defined or meant before discovering him, at least
philosophically: 'The philosophical meaning of God should be exclusively a function of
the way by which He is discovered* ("Analogy" 84 n. 9). Without special reference to
Aquinas, other authors make similar points: Michael Levine holds that the judgment of
God's existence is necessary for any literal or analogical talk about God (" "Can We
Speak Literally of God?' " Religious Studies 21 [1985] 53-59, at 53-54); more generally,
Richard Swinburne argues that the analogical meaning and coherence of any words or
thoughts about God depend on the prior truth of certain statements about God (The
Coherence of Theism [Oxford: Clarendon, 1977] 1-5, 48-49, 70-71, 278-80, 294-96).
With reference to Aquinas, David Burrell states generally that in talk about God, mean-
ing is not so much presupposed as it is constituted by judgment ("Aquinas on Naming
God," TS 24 [1963] 183-212, at 202). Even more universally, Bernard Lonergan con-
tends that for Thomas knowledge always measures meaning, and that there is a "clear
reduction of meaning to knowledge" (Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas, ed. David
Burrell [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1967] 152-53).
660 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES
meanings and if we do not know how our concepts apply to God? Aqui-
nas will respond that, at the level ofjudgment, the theological sentence
cannot be equivocal precisely because it is true, although it expresses
its truth by projecting creaturely concepts toward an infinite mystery
which remains absolutely inconceivable. Whereas he rejects univocity
due to God's incomprehensibility, he repudiates equivocity on the
grounds of the believer's ability to know some truth about God. In
Aquinas's eyes, those who consider all speech about God to be inher-
ently equivocal are reduced in the end to holding that we can never say
anything true about God, even that God exists.
CONCLUSION
Aquinas's theory of God-talk, a subtle and nuanced view which hov-
ers over the divine abyss between the crags of purely positive and
purely negative theology, evinces Christianity's penchant for invoking
and positively identifying a God who is at the same time essentially
mysterious and hidden, a God who is neither univocally dissolved into
us humans nor equivocally placed beyond every ability of ours to know
and name in prayer and worship. Thomas's God-talk blends both the
positive and the negative, but the positive is foundational for the neg-
ative, for God is the pure positivity of infinite Being who in creation
has also acted positively on our behalf. This stance accords well with
the views of other theologians who also see God as pure positivity,
albeit in terms different from Aquinas's—Kasper, e.g., who sees God
as pure and positive Love, or even Barth, who toward the end of his career
finally admits that a God-talk based on the world of creation and
redemption must have something positive to say if Christ is ultimately
the positive "Yes"fromGod to that world and from that world to God.
Aquinas's analogy-based theological epistemology only escapes idol-
atrous univocity, however, to the degree that it is based on judgment
rather than concept, is continually interpreted by the dialectics of neg-
ative theology, and is conscious that the concepts used in its true judg-
ments about God cannot give us any insight into the inner nature of
God. His theological epistemology gladly grasps, as the only viable
alternative, the inescapable paradox that in all our theologizing we
link judgmental truth with conceptual agnosticism.
Finally, Thomas's theological epistemology implies that when we
talk about God, the very meanings of the words we use are somehow
dependent upon what we hold to be true about God. From his perspec-
tive, our theological epistemology is ultimately based on the perceived
truth-status of our foundational theological judgments, not the other
way around. This suggests that the theory of God-talk to which we
subscribe will always be indebted to the truths about God we hold dear.