The Challenges of The Humanities, Past, Present, and Future
The Challenges of The Humanities, Past, Present, and Future
The Challenges of The Humanities, Past, Present, and Future
Edited by
Albrecht Classen
www.mdpi.com/journal/humanities
Albrecht Classen (Ed.)
Guest Editor
Albrecht Classen
Department of German Studies
University of Arizona
Tucson, AZ 85721
USA
Editorial Office
MDPI AG
Klybeckstrasse 64
Basel, Switzerland
Publisher
Shu-Kun Lin
Assistant Editor
Jie Gu
1. Edition 2015
ISBN 978-3-03842-055-2
© 2015 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. All articles in this volume are
Open Access distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 license
(http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which allows users to download, copy and
build upon published articles even for commercial purposes, as long as the author and
publisher are properly credited, which ensures maximum dissemination and a wider impact of
our publications. However, the dissemination and distribution of copies of this book as a
whole is restricted to MDPI, Basel, Switzerland.
III
Table of Contents
Alcibiades Malapi-Nelson
Humanities’ Metaphysical Underpinnings of Late Frontier Scientific Research
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(4), 740-765 .................................................................... 1
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/4/740
An-bang Yu
The Encounter of Nursing and the Clinical Humanities: Nursing Education and the Spirit of
Healing
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(4), 660-674 .................................................................. 28
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/4/660
Vicki A. Spencer
Democratic Citizenship and the “Crisis in Humanities”
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(3), 398-414 .................................................................. 70
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/3/398
Evy Varsamopoulou
Timely Meditations: Reflections on the Role of the Humanities in J.M. Coetzee’s Elizabeth
Costello and Diary of a Bad Year
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(3), 379-397 .................................................................. 87
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/3/379
Pedro Talavera
Economicism and Nihilism in the Eclipse of Humanism
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(3), 340-378 ................................................................ 106
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/3/340
Mike Hulme
Climate Change and Virtue: An Apologetic
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(3), 299-312 ................................................................ 147
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/3/299
Vicky Gunn
Present Teaching Stories as Re-Membering the Humanities
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(3), 264-282 ................................................................ 161
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/3/264
IV
Paul Keen
“Imagining What We Know”: The Humanities in a Utilitarian Age
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(1), 73-87.................................................................... 202
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/1/73
Albrecht Classen
The Challenges of the Humanities, Past, Present, and Future: Why the Middle Ages Mean So
Much for Us Today and Tomorrow
Reprinted from: Humanities 2014, 3(1), 1-18...................................................................... 217
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/3/1/1
V
List of Contributors
Mauro Bergonzi: Dipartimento di Scienze Umane e Sociali, Università degli Studi di Napoli
"L'Orientale", Palazzo Giusso, Largo S. Giovanni Maggiore, 30-80134 Napoli, Italy
Albrecht Classen: Department of German Studies, The University of Arizona, 301 LSB,
Tucson, AZ 85721, USA
Domenico Fiormonte: Dipartimento di Scienze Politiche, Università Roma Tre, Via G.
Chiabrera, 199-00145 Roma, Italy
Francesco Fiorentino: Dipartimento di Lingue, Letterature e Culture Straniere, Università
Roma Tre, Via del Valco di San Paolo, 19-00146 Roma, Italy
Laura Fortini: Dipartimento di Studi Umanistici, Università Roma Tre, Via Ostiense, 234-
00146 Roma, Italy
Ugo Fracassa: Dipartimento di Studi Umanistici, Università Roma Tre, Via Ostiense, 234-
00146 Roma, Italy
Vicky Gunn: Learning and Teaching Centre, University of Glasgow, Glasgow G12 8QQ, UK
Mike Hulme: Department of Geography, King's College London, Strand WC2R 2LS,
London, UK; Rachel Carson Center for Environment and Society, LMU Münich, Leopoldstr.
11a, Münich D-80802, Germany
Paul Keen: Department of English, Carleton University, Ottawa, ON K1S 2Z8, Canada
Michele Lucantoni: Dipartimento di Filosofia, Comunicazione e Spettacolo, Università
Roma Tre, Via Ostiense, 234-00146 Roma, Italy
Alcibiades Malapi-Nelson: School of Liberal Arts and Sciences, Humber College, 205
Humber College Boulevard, Toronto, ON M9W 5L7, Canada
Massimo Marraffa: Dipartimento di Filosofia, Comunicazione e Spettacolo, Università
Roma Tre, Via Ostiense, 234-00146 Roma, Italy
Teresa Numerico: Dipartimento di Filosofia, Comunicazione e Spettacolo, Università Roma
Tre, Via Ostiense, 234-00146 Roma, Italy
Vicki A. Spencer: Department of Politics, University of Otago, PO Box 56, Dunedin 9016,
New Zealand
Pedro Talavera: Department of Philosophy of Law, Faculty of Law, University of Valencia,
46071 Valencia, Spain
Iris van der Tuin: Gender Studies and Philosophy of Science, Department of Media and
Culture Studies, Utrecht University, Muntstraat 2a, 3512 EV Utrecht, The Netherlands
Evy Varsamopoulou: Department of English Studies, University of Cyprus, 75 Kallipoleos
Street, P.O. Box 20537, Nicosia 1678, Cyprus
An-bang Yu: Institute of Ethnology, Academia Sinica, Taipei 11529, Taiwan
1
1.1. Duns Scotus: Continuum between Physical Entities and the Divine Being
After several centuries of having Aristotle’s works unavailable to Europe, the twelfth century
witnessed a revival of Aristotelian philosophy. After a millennium of a Christian philosophy largely
based upon Platonisminheriting at times its subsequent relative contempt for the physical realmSt.
Thomas Aquinas, a member of the newly formed mendicant Order of St. Dominic, embarked upon
the major task of relocating the fundamentals of Christianity upon the newly rediscovered Aristotelian
writings. This displacement created waves of tension throughout Christendom. There were deep
concerns regarding the outcome of combining the Christian faith with a philosophy which, even if
acknowledging the existence of the Divine, it did it in a way that could forever remove it away from
a human relational intimacy—Aristotle’s god was not a personal god; even less one that would
become man. Aquinas was eventually reivindicated by the Church, which three centuries later placed
his Summa Theologica besides the Bible on the altarthe only book ever that enjoyed such
honorin the closing Mass for the Council of Trent, when it defined its position against the
Protestant revolt.
2
One of the prominent figures who relentlessly attacked Aquinas’ ideas at the time was Blessed
Duns Scotus, a member of the order started by Saint Francis of Assisi. Both Doctors of the Catholic
Church, (Angelicus—Aquinas—and Subtilis—Scotus) their orders were founded just a century apart.
They embodied a profound reform of the Church at the time, accentuating poverty as a charisma, and
it quickly grew large all over Europe. During the lifetime of both philosophers, the mendicant feature
of both orders gave increasing space to an emphasis on education, eventually founding universities
with their distinctive character. The famed rivalry between the Franciscans and the Dominicans
(the first being somewhat prone to heresy and the second to orthodoxy) has arguably been somewhat
exaggerated, although it is widely recognized that each order characterized the two major flavors
of European universities for centuries to come—one under the light of an Aristotelian pre-Modern
realism (Dominicans), the other under a more Platonic take on reality, with heavy leniencies towards
mysticism (Franciscans) ([1], chapter 2).
Scotus was concerned about Aquinas’ understanding of concepts when these would ultimately
predicates of God (divine attributes). For Aquinas, when we speak of God as being good, we actually
mean this “goodness” in an equivocal way, not in the same way in which we use it when we refer to,
for example, humans. The goodness of God can be only analogically related to that of humansor of
creation, health, etc. Aquinas clearly emphasized the transcendent nature of God, and even if there
are cues in nature that can eventually lead us to Him (as in his famed Quinque Viae), we ultimately
know more about what He is not than what He is.
Scotus saw a problem right there. For him, negative knowledge was ultimately not knowledge
at all. This was just the start of the danger that was to come after following Aristotle. He feared that
if Aquinas had it his way, the human capability of reaching God would be truncated, and ultimately
metaphysics might even cease to exist1. Furthermore, Aquinas would think of “eing” as not necessarily
entailing “existence” (God is, more than merely exists, since “existence”, being contingent, necessitates
a “being” to give its very “existence” in the first place). For Scotus this equivocality could have a
catastrophic effect, given the nature of human intelligence. The primal object of the human intellect
is “being inasmuch as being” (ens inquantum ens). That entails that if something is, it will necessarily
fall within the realm of the intelligible. There is no being without existence. To affirm the contrary
would allow for the possibility of a being beyond intelligibility, which could lead to the denial of
existence of the Ultimate Being. Hence for Scotus there is a semantic continuum in our predication
of the attributes of a beingincluding Godfor otherwise there could be the case of a
beingincluding Godequivocally referred to, and thus removed beyond the grasp of our
intellectual might. In his own words:
1
Scotus’ concern antecedes Immanuel Kant’s questioning of the possibility of metaphysics as a science by four
centuries. Kant would later dispatch his famous ultimatum: “All metaphysicians are therefore solemnly and legally
suspended from their occupations until they shall have satisfactorily answered the question: How are synthetic
cognitions a priori possible?” ([2], Preamble: Section 5).
3
And lest there be a dispute about the name “univocation”, I designate that concept
univocal which possesses sufficient unity in itself, so that to affirm or deny it of one and
the same thing would be a contradiction. It also has sufficient unity to serve as the middle
term of a syllogism, so that wherever two extremes are united by a middle term that is
one in this way, we may conclude to the union of two extremes among themselves ([3],
p. 20)2.
For Scotus, in predicating, say the “cleanliness” of a man, we can refer to the moral aspect of
his persona or to his physical, bodily realm—among other levels of qualified existence. So one
can say that such man is clean and not clean, without committing contradiction, given that one is
applying cleanliness to different aspects, and still maintaining the univocity of being (univocatio entis)
regarding cleanliness. The meaning of the noun (or adjective) is the same for both cases, but the
variation occurs in the way or degree in which this notion is applied. When thinking of God’s attributes,
“the extremes united by means of a middle term possessing such a unity are themselves united with
each other”, so that we say about Him as being good in an infinite way, but of creatures as being good
in a finite, fallible way. The same is said of being: the radical opposite to nothingness is beingeven
if this being can be infinite (God) or finite (everything else). Regardless of the way in which being
opposes to nothingness, it is the same notion of being at work here, either applied to God or His
creatures. This ontological continuum3 should warrant our finite capacity of reaching the Infinite
One. After all, our knowledge would differ from the Creator’s in a manner of degree, not kindpace
Thomas Aquinas. This Scotian ontological bridge established between the physical and the non-physical
would re-emerge much later under a technological umbrella, as we shall see in part II.
1.2. Francis Bacon: Mechanical Arts against the Epistemic Darkness Set by Original Sin
The pervading notion in Christendom of humans having been conceived in the “image and
likeness of God”4, one of the tenets of faith that operated behind Scotus’ attack of Aquinas, evolved
in increasingly liberal ways the next two hundred years. The beginning of the sixteenth century
signaled the formal (theoretical and then political) rebellion against the Church in Europe. Tradition
has it that the Ninety-Five Thesis on the Power and Efficacy of Indulgences, was nailed on the
front door of the castle church of Wittenberg, by the Augustinian priest Martin Luther in 1507.
This revolt eventually amounted to the biggest breakaway in the body of Christianity after the
Great Schism of the eleventh century. Five hundred years later, the Protestant “reform” commands
2
Ordinatio I, distinctio. 3, part 1, quaestio. 2, numero 26.
3
Certainly the idea of a continuum as the default state of affairs of reality was already perused by the Ancient
Greeks. In the realm of the inanimate, it was understood that natura abhorret vacuum. Among living entities,
a careful continuity in “how rightly Nature orders generation in regular gradation” ([4], pp. II, 1) was recognized.
4
“God created man in his image; in the divine image he created him; male and female he created them”
(Gen. 1:27, NAB).
4
much scholarship5, it is not my intention to address it here. What is relevant, however, is the evolution
of the notion of imago Dei within the ranks of those who fostered the Scientific Revolution.
Although a plethora of non-religious circumstances were leading to the historic event, the reformers’
attack against the Church was symbolically triggered by the lack of clarification, on the part of the
Church, regarding what is referred to in the English title of Luther’s manifesto, namely, “the power
and efficacy of indulgences”6. During the ensuing struggle between the reformers and Rome, the
former gradually found scriptural passages that would allegedly justify their independence from the
Hierarchy in particular and the Holy Orders 7 in general. The Hierarchy (conformed by the bishops,
cardinals and patriarchs) is the only entity that can provide the sacrament of Holy Orders. Once a
society gets rid of it, priests could not be ordained, and the rest of the sacraments, which priests have
the mandate to deliver, cannot be provided. We would be in front of a sacrament-less Christianity,
which is what the reformers were afterin order to render the Church effectively useless.
Martin Luther held a profoundly dark outlook regarding what remained of human nature after
the Fall. Whereas for the Catholic Church this Fall deeply “corrupted” our nature, for Protestantism
it irreparably “shattered” it. For Catholicism, this wounded nature could still be healedvia the
sacramentssince the destruction was not complete. For Protestantism, we are so completely damned,
that only Christand Him alonecan save us. However, our underlying nature remains ultimately
broken. Simul iustus ad pecator (Simultaneusly justified and sinner) Luther would proclaim.
5
Arguably, Western civilization got wedged in such a way that it never healed. The instantiation of this division was
eventually settled, embodied on the one side by those countries who remained faithful to Rome (mostly southern
Europe) and on the other those who did not (Anglo-Saxony and northern Europe)—a cosmological split that was
naturally extended to their respective colonies. Eisenstein reports this rift as follows:
Sixteenth-century heresy and schism shattered Christendom so completely that even after religious warfare had
ended, ecumenical movements led by men of good will could not put all the pieces together again. Not only
were there too many splinter groups, separatists, and independent sects who regarded a central church government
as incompatible with true faith; but the main lines of cleavage had been extended across continents and carried
overseas along with Bibles and breviaries. Within a few generations, the gap between Protestant and Catholic
had widened sufficiently to give rise to contrasting literary cultures and lifestyles. Long after Christian theology
had ceased to provoke wars, Americans as well as Europeans were separated from each other by invisible
barriers that are still with us today ([5], pp. 172–73).
6
The actual title was Disputatio pro declaratione virtutis indulgentiarum.
7
With the sacrament of Holy Orders one is “ordered” a presbyter (a priest), a deacon or a bishop. In the case of a
priest, it institutes in that person ad perpetuum the capability of providing the other six sacraments. The provision
of this one sacrament is reserved solely to the bishop. “Since the sacrament of Holy Orders is the sacrament of the
apostolic ministry, it is for the bishops as the successors of the apostles to hand on the “gift of the Spirit”, the “apostolic
line”. Validly ordained bishops, i.e., those who are in the line of apostolic succession, validly confer the three degrees
of the sacrament of Holy Orders” ([6], para. 1576).
5
This shift carried existential and epistemological issues. For fifteen centuries there was a
relatively unbroken certainty that the seven sacraments were specifically instituted by Jesus Christ,
for us to attain self-realization in this life and salvation in the next one. That was never denied by the
earlier Eastern Christian split of the eleventh centurythe mentioned Great Schism. The sacramental
institution just “made sense”, having in mind the inescapable catastrophe depicted in Genesis 3. Until
we accept the redemption given by Christ, which is literally effectuated via the reception of the
sacraments, the Great Fall inherently dooms human existenceincluding our epistemic capacities.
Thus the human sacramental participation of divine grace allegedly heals our fallen natureallowing
us to return to the “essence of humanity,” lost as a consequence of Original Sin.
Such was the Christian view of man until then. However, now, given the post-Reformation
absence of sacraments, an anxious inquiry regarding the scope and limits of human capabilities
quickly set in. Prima facie, given the absolutely totalizing nature of the Fall, any hopeful human
endeavor is right from the start destined to crash. Specifically, accounts of the now lost Adamian
wisdom, which enjoyed pre-Fall super-human intellectual and cognitive capabilities, begun to
flourish. Scriptura Sola, now without the tutelary guidance of the Church and written in vernacular
languages, allegedly gave accounts of the encyclopedic knowledge that Adam enjoyed, e.g., in calling
creatures by their name. A veil of hopelessness seemed to rear its head for the possibilities of knowledge,
and indeed for any significant outcome from human experience whatsoever [7].
The strongest voice that defied this looming prospect arguably was the one to which we attribute
having theoretically fostered the Scientific Revolution: Francis Bacon. Immanuel Kant tellingly
opened his Critique of Pure Reason with a quote from Baron Verulam (Bacon’s honorific title). Kant
does this in order to highlight Bacon’s role in the new science, having “made the proposal that
partly prompted this road’s discovery, and partlyin so far as some were already on the trail of this
discoveryinvigorated it further” ([8], Bxii). Strong words that found echo in the copious amount of
scholarship on this author, the alleged articulator of the scientific method for early Modern science.
One aspect of Bacon’s work, however, that has arguably received less attention, was the main reason
behind the construction of the new science in the first placenamely, the retrieval of the lost epistemic
capabilities that humans were endowed with in virtue of having being created in imago Dei8.
Such relative absence in the scholarship is all the more surprising once we realize that “for Francis
Bacon, the reform of learning was not a secular pursuit, but a divine mandate” ([9], p. 51). Indeed,
Bacon did not mince words for clearly pointing out that Original Sin catastrophically affected man’s
intellectual capabilities, removing the mastery over nature that Adam once enjoyed. In The New
Organon, he asserts that “[f]or man by the fall fell at the same from his state of innocence and from
his dominion over creation” ([10], p. 189). The allusion to Genesis 3 is clear in his understanding of
the dramatic loss we underwent due to Adam’s fault. The Devil, represented in Genesis by a serpent,
8
Peter Harrison would extend the influence of the awareness of a doomed humanity vis a vis Original Sin beyond
Bacon’s motivations and into the very birth of Modern science, advancing that “the biblical narrative of the Fall
played a far more direct role in the development of early Modern knowledge—both in England and on the
Continent—than has often been assumed, and that competing strategies for the advancement of knowledge in the
XVII century were closely related to different assessments of the Fall and of its impact upon the human mind” ([7],
p. 240).
6
introduced darkness and confusion in the human mind forever. In The Great Instauration, the sharp
decrease in our intellectual capabilities is sorely lamented by Bacon in a Trinitarian prayer, which
asks for “illumination”, one of the Gifts pertaining to the Holy Spirit: “Lastly, that knowledge being
now discharged of that venom which the serpent infused into it, and which makes the mind of man
to swell, we may not be wise above measure and sobriety, but cultivate truth in charity” ([11], p. 74).
A grim depiction of our epistemic panorama is indeed laid out.
However, there is a way out from cognitive darkness. Again in the New Organon, after referring
to both our losses of innocence and of mastery over nature triggered by Original Sin, Bacon gives a
glimpse of hope: “Both of these losses, however, can even in this life be in some part repaired; the
former by religion and faith, the latter by arts and sciences.” ([10], p. 189). Our intellectual capacity
is corrupted, that much is clear. Hence we need a way to put it in check, to rely on something solid.
Reliance on our “natural lights” is out of the question, due to inherited state of contamination. The
way to get rid of the “idols”9 of the mind will thus entails a return to hard reality. However, not just
in any way. The Greeks were faithful realists, but their appreciation of nature, even with powerful
insights, did not produce growing knowledge. Their experience as great philosophers but not great
scientists stands as a warning for us:
Signs also are to be drawn from the increase and progress of systems and sciences. For
what is founded on nature grows and increases; while what is founded on opinion
varies but increases not. If, therefore, those doctrines had not plainly been like a plant
torn up from its roots, but had remained attached to the womb of nature and continued
to draw nourishment from her, that could never have come to pass which we have seen
now for twice a thousand years; namely, that the sciences stand where they did and
remain almost in the same condition, receiving no noticeable increase, but on the
contrary, thriving most under their first founder, and then declining ([10], p. 113).
Thus there is an element missing. We have to indeed observe nature, but not as a passive gatherer,
accumulating data and speculating about possible connections and causes, but rather making up
situations that would force the studied objects to behave in such way that we could satisfy our previously
construed questions. Immanuel Kant, who appropriately understood the Baconian dictum, captured
well Bacon’s suggestion for pressing nature, since Bacon himself was allegedly inspired by the torturous
questioning of witnesses in courtwhich often provide surprising and fruitful outcomes. In the
words of Kant, “reason must indeed approach nature in order to be instructed by it; yet it must do
so not in the capacity of a pupil who lets the teacher tell him whatever the teacher wants, but in
the capacity of an appointed judge who compels the witness to answer the questions that he puts to
them” ([8], Bxiii).
9
Idols of the tribe (race), of the cave (individual), of the marketplace (language) and of the theatre (authority) ([10],
pp. 95ff).
7
Making allusion to the Ancient Greeks one more time, this time specifically to Aristotle, Bacon
pointed out the crucial difference it makes to “push” nature into fitting inquiring categories, declaring
that “in the business of life, a man’s disposition and the secret workings of his mind and affections
are better discovered when he is in trouble than at other times, so likewise the secrets of nature reveal
themselves more readily under the vexations of art than when they go their own way” ([10], p. 130).
The Greek experience, in contrast…
is the opposite of what happens with the mechanical arts, which are based on nature
and the light of experience: they (as long as they find favor with people) continually
thrive and grow, having a special kind of spirit in them, so that they are at first rough and
ready, then manageable, from then onwards made smoothly convenient by use—and
always growing ([10], p. 113).
One cannot help but stopping for a moment to admire the brilliance of the suggestion. Our fallible
intellectual capabilities get anchored in physical substrata, but not imposing its faults nor letting
itself be paved upon by nature’s might. Instead, a reciprocal relation is formed, whose results let
themselves get noticed by a growth of knowledge. When this constructive conflict is not present in
the inquiry, the fate of the Greeks stands as a warning. The “mechanical arts” provide a key element
of solidity, whose determinism (in so far as mechanical) acts as a reliable platform for our otherwise
weakened reason to perform its questioning tasks. The notion of experimentum crucis, which constituted
a methodological pillar for subsequent developments in science, was used as a basic element upon
which much of scientific thinking regarding reliable parameters for experimentation was done.
However, one could be misled regarding the ultimate aim of this historical progress if we would to
take in consideration Bacon’s primal reason behind his proposal to reshape scientific inquiry:
[I]t is not the pleasure of curiosity, nor the quiet of resolution, nor the raising of the
spirit, nor victory of wit, nor faculty of speech, nor lucre of profession, nor ambition of
honour or fame, nor inablement for business, that are the true ends of knowledge; some
of these being more worthy than other, though all inferior and degenerate: but it is a
restitution and reinvesting (in great part) of man to the sovereignty and power (for
whensoever he shall be able to call the creatures by their true names he shall again
command them) which he had in his first state of creation ([12], p. 188).
The Protestant Reformation’s role in the Scientific Revolution pivots around a concerted
philosophical effort to overcome the epistemological crippling effects introduced by Original
Sin—effects only brought to the fore after the epistemic “antidote” (the sacraments) were no longer
available. Baron Verulam’s intention behind his revolutionary proposal is laid out clearly: to employ
the “new science” as the way out of the cognitive darkness inherited from our sinful first fathers.
Bacon’s longing for an Adamian nature that would excel in epistemic abilitiesnow lost—might
finally find rest, thanks to the restitutional capabilities of the newly formed “mechanical arts”.
Experimentation that fostered a mechanical explanation became the hardcore signature of early
Modern scienceepitomized in the great names of Galileo, Newton, Boyle and even J. C. Maxwell
8
at some point10. However, the set of interrogations that would construct the backdrop for the devised
experiment would all constitute, once the results are obtained, a model of a portion of realitya
phenomenon’s identified patterns of reaction to our experimentation. The nature of this model
generated itself inquiries, and its constitution, aims and even struggles were pondered in the centuries
to come. The aspect of constructability that a mechanical model inherently possess would go on to
inform realms that were perhaps not foreseen by Bacon himselfas we will see below. However,
first, let us explore one more instance of the evolution of this “mechanical epistemology”. This time
it came from one of Bacon’s most fervent admirers, two centuries later.
Canonically known after La Scienza Nuova (a treatise on how to lead nations that was to be
regarded later as the foundational text for philosophy of history), Giambattista Vico’s early writings
clearly indicated how dramatically important were Bacon’s insights for his own era. In an autobiography
where the Italian philosopher refers to himself in the third person, he speaks of his discovery of
Bacon. He recounts that “from his De augmentis scientiarum Vico [himself] concluded that, as Plato
is the prince of Greek wisdom, and the Greeks have no Tacitus, so Romans and Greeks alike have no
Bacon” ([14], p. 139). Vico, himself a Catholic, castigated Baco’s infamous vicious attacks against
Rome, but trying to balance things out, he gave the hostile Anglican philosopher its fair due, saying
of him that “without professional and sectarian bias, save for a few things which offend the Catholic
religion, he did justice to all the sciences” ([14], p. 139). Indeed Vico acknowledged Bacon’s original
contribution to scientific methodology, which would itself later reverberate into an augmentation of
empirical knowledge.
Vico’s metaphysics, developed years before La Scienzaand upon which the latter was
eventually basedhad a strong philological accent. He advanced the argument that in the case of the
Latin language, key linguistic terms had been formed out of philosophical insights rather than vulgar
tradesindeed “derived from some inward learning rather than from the vernacular usage of the
people” ([15], p. 37). Vico engaged into etymological archaeologies to bring into the open the deep
meaning of certain metaphysically dense concepts. As a way of guiding examples, he brought up
the verb intelligere, which means both “to read perfectly” and “to have plain knowledge”; the verb
cogitare, which means “to think” and “to gather”; and the noun ratio, which means both the recognition
of mathematical proportions and man’s endowed reason. Most tellingly, verum and factum were at
the time interchangeable (convertible), as it is shown in the Latin adagio verum esse ipsum factum:
“the truth is what is made, itself”or, the truth is precisely what is done 11. This assertion carries
some immediate epistemological and ontological consequences. For starters, the only one who can
fully know is God, for Heand He alonecreates its own object of knowledge.
10
It is widely acknowledged that J. C. Maxwell held on to visually mechanical explanations of “action at a distance”
in electromagnetism until the visual heuristics were no longer needed ([13], chapter 3).
11
“For the Latins, verum (the true) and factum (what is made) are interchangeable, or to use the customary language
of the Schools, they are convertible” ([15], p. 45).
9
Before casting Vico’s etymology-based metaphysics under a negative light, one could be
reminded that he is not alone in this understanding of divine knowledge as the only one which both
perfectly knows something and creates precisely that “something” while knowing it. Indeed Vico’s
views on this are not dissimilar from that of probably the most representative philosopher of the
Modern Era. Immanuel Kant, roughly a contemporary of Vico, had a very clearly exclusive adscription
of the faculty of “intellectual intuition” to God alone. For Kant, we are endowed with “sensible intuition”
(space and time being its pure forms); our faculty is passive, receiving raw sensible material from
the thing as it is presented to usall of which would construct the uniquely Kantian understanding
of “experience”, which then will be ordered by our intellect. This is within the core of the
“Trascendental Aesthetic” in the Critique of Pure Reason. Our intuitus derivativus does not create
the object of our intellect. In contrast, in the case of God’s intuitus originarious, to think about
something is to create that something:
Our kind of intuition is called sensible because it is not original. i.e., it is not such that
through this intuition itself the existence of its object is given (the latter being a kind of
intuition that, as far as we can see, can belong only to the original Being)…intellectual
intuition seems to belong solely to the original Being, and never to a being that is
dependent as regards both its existence and intuition (an intuition that determines that
being’s existence by reference to given objects) ([8], B72).
Vico’s take on truth as convertible to that which is built, is mindful of Bacon’s emphasis on our
need for reliance on experimentation for extracting the answers from nature. However, the line of
thought that goes from Vico’s claim regarding the verum factum to Bacon’s need for experimenting
with reality needs some explanation. God knows everything totally and perfectly because all things
that constitute this “everything” are already in Him; humans, on the other hand, are external to these
things—we have a superficial grasp of them, since they are not internal to us:
God reads all the elements of things whether inner or outer, because He contains and
disposes them in order, whereas the human mind, because it is limited and external to
everything else that is not itself, is confined to the outside edges of things only and,
hence, can never gather them all together ([15], p. 46).
This nature of ultimate knowledge has a bearing on science “in general”, namely, both for God
and humans. Science is “knowledge of the genus or mode by which a thing is made; and by this
very knowledge the mind makes the thing, because in knowing it puts together the elements of that
thing” ([15], p. 46). Scientific knowledge, thus, implies a creative process. One knows in the very
act of creating. Again, only God fully knows, because He creates. Having said that, there is a realm
where we in fact fully know, creating the very object that we know: mathematics: “Just as he who
occupies himself with geometry is, in his world of figures, a god (so to speak), so God Almighty is,
in his world of spirits and bodies, a geometer (so to speak)” ([16], p. 66). It is in mathematical
knowledge where we find the closest resemblance to divine cognition.
10
The situation is dramatically different when it comes to the understanding of the natural order, i.e.,
knowledge of physical things. Here, once again, both God and humans possess science, but ours is
essentially different from His. We drag an inherent stain in our scientific endeavors regarding the
natural realmnamely, our lack of ability to “create” (available to God alone) and our subsequent
need for abstraction. After all, “since human knowledge is purely abstractive, the more our sciences
are immersed in bodily matter, the less certain they are” ([15], p. 52). So Vico confided the aspect we
ought to emphasize while doing science in order to overcome this genetic limitation: “Just as divine
truth is what God sets in order and creates in the act of knowing it, so human truth is what man
puts together and makes in the act of knowing it” ([15], p. 46). Constructability“putting
together”should be the first criterion of truth, and thus, of scientific success.
In this vein, Vico reminded us that “God knows all things because in Himself He contains the
elements with which He puts all things together. Man, on the other hand, strives to know these things
by a process of division” ([15], p. 48). This “process of division”, quite literally fashions the essence
of human science, which itself amounts to the “anatomy of nature’s works” ([15], p. 48). This
“anatomy” goes beyond a mere figure of speech: we need to dissect, qua physician, the elements of
nature, and then cognitivelynot existentially, which is only divinely feasible—recreate the object
according to our inquiry. Thus, when Vico refers to “dissection”, he is referring to experimentation!
([17], p. 103).
Vico’s indebtedness to Bacon is more explicit when he makes allusion to an incipient Modern
scientific method. He asserted that “hypothesis about the natural order are considered most illuminating
and are accepted with the fullest consent of everyone, if we can base experiments on them, in which
we make something similar to nature” ([15], p. 52). Considering the ingeniousness of Bacon’s
proposal pointed abovenamely, by pressing nature to answer our own questionswe actually are
anchoring ourselves in reality, not removing our minds from it. This critical reverence towards
reality begets wisdom, which ultimately “in its broad sense is nothing but the science of making such
use of things as their nature dictates” ([18], CXIV: 326). According to Vico, Bacon did nothing less
than bridging our intellectual capacity with the natural world. However, it is Vico himself who
carries the Baconian lesson to its fulfillment: the experimental reconstruction of a phenomenon
under controlled conditions is just a first step towards the recreation of the object. True knowledge is
acquired when the model becomes the modeled.
Duns Scotus proposed a “univocity of being” where our difference from the Divine would be one
of quantity, not of quality. This view later morphed via Vico into the notion that true knowledge
would imply the necessity of building. Kant himself asserted that God’s intuitive knowledgeHis
equivalent of the kind of knowledge generated by our “pure intuitions of sensibility”would
necessarily imply creation. Moreover, Bacon gave back to us the confidence in the possibility of
knowledge (lost after Original Sin) by means of experimentation and the “mechanical
arts”mechanistic modeling that arguably fostered the Scientific Revolution.
11
It is Vico who most clearly stated, regarding the essential reliance of knowledge upon the
best possibly constructed model, that “Verum et factum convertuntur”: The Truth and the Made
convergeor in more colloquial language, “if you know it, build it”. Of course, only a Creator could
fully know its own creation. However, since the Scotian ethos defends that humans can epistemically
share His Light in an infinitely lower but real degree, we can in principle also know under such light.
This emphasis on constructability as criterion of truth (and also as part and parcel of a critique against
a Cartesian epistemology), has inspired later thinkers more concerned with the tractability of physically
embedded problems.
Vico’s prescient Verum Factum seems to neatly link the Univocatio Entis and Imago Dei views
into a zenith of knowledge attainment that drives an important aspect of contemporary scientific
research. Vico’s claim on the future “certain sciences” is telling: “The most certain sciences are
those that wash away the blemish of their origin and that become similar to divine science through
their creative activity in as much as in these sciences that which is true and that which is made are
convertible” ([15], p. 52). It should thus not come as a surprise that one can find in contemporary
times a cutting edge research laboratory named “The Giambattista Institute of Cybernetics and
Applied Epistemology” in the Netherlands. In fact, the whole rise and demise of cybernetics 12 could
be understood from the viewpoint of having suffered such fate due to the cybernetic legendary
emphasis on “embodiment” as the core its scientific methodologyitself deeply rooted in the drive
behind “Modern”13 scientific practice. The tension between, on the one hand a theoretical structure
per se, and on the other, the physical anchoring of such theory, gets all the more interesting once one
notices how contemporary science still understands its explanatory task in fairly Modern termsin
other words, roughly mechanistically14. These values are indeed essential to the core of the Western
tradition, as expressed in the longing for a divine knowledge that entails the possibility of radically
transforming (modifying, fixing and improving) a creation given to us for our disposalourselves
included. Such impetus for control and re-construction is ever more present with us, and in
tangible ways.
In 1945, the Manhattan Project physicist Richard Feynman, better known later for his Nobel price
research on quantum mechanics, refused a teaching invitation from Princeton Universitydespite
having earned his doctorate from there in 1942. Instead, Feynman accepted a teaching position at
CalTech, where he delivered a talk that would come down in history as the first addressing of the
possibility of manipulating reality at a level where the transformation and recreation of objects becomes
scientifically feasible. The one-time lecture, entitled “There’s Plenty of Room at the Bottom” [22]
remained, however, largely unknown, until Eric Drexler, a doctor in engineering from M.I.T., found
it and subsequently published it almost three decades later, as part of his book Engines of Creation:
12
Cybernetics was an Anglo-American scientific movement alive in the 1940’s and that lasted a decade. I am
currently writing a dissertation on the possible reasons for its collapse. Cybernetics might have been the strong
proxy between the humanistic advances laid out in the previous 3 Sections, and the later proposals in
techno-scientific outlooks displayed below. Lack of space precludes me from further articulating this missing link.
For a short introduction on cybernetics, see [19]. For a longer exposition on this scientific movement see [20].
13
As opposed to “contemporary”.
14
Although this is bound to continue changing. See [21].
12
The Coming Era of Nanotechnology [23]. Although the term “nanotechnology” was previously
coined a decade earlier by Norio Taniguchi (Tokio University of Science), it is after Drexler’s book
that the notion started to gain traction in the engineering andlaterin the science community. The
journal Nature has now a permanent section dedicated to nanoscale15 research.
Canonically, nanotechnology aims at the mechanical manipulation of matter at the molecular
levelliterally, atom by atom. Such level of reality is allegedly of utmost importance, since stuff can
be still “classically” understood under a Newtonian light and rearranged without incurring in quantum
indeterminacy16. Since a physical thing owes its nature to its particular atomic arrangement (one
modifies this arrangement and ends up with another thing), the possibilities immediately foreseen are
arguably flabbergasting. In principle, an eventual “molecular assembler” could transform any physical
entity into another physical entity, by means of reordering its atomic structure. Such an envisioned
feat would obviously transform the world as we know it in radical ways, replacing its economy,
resetting global health, and trivializing some deep problemssuch as the possibility of attaining
intelligence and life artificially (now amenable of being duplicated and enhanced, instead of “found”
or “created”).
Even if by consensus the field still is in its infancy, the first decade of our century has witnessed
some relatively important achievements, which keeps fostering interest in the field in a gradual but
relentless way. Feynman’s explicit proposal, even if only theoretical, tried to garner attention
towards that “untreated” level of reality in the midst of the Cold War. He predicted that research
performed at a nanoscale 17 would have as beneficiaries, among other fields, microscopy and
computation. Indeed only 6 years later, in 1965, George Moore would be proclaiming what would
be henceforth known as “Moore’s Law”: Every 18–24 months the amount of transistors that could
fit in an integrated circuit would double. Thereafter, somewhat expectably, two cornerstones in
nanotechnology occurred in a common area shared between computation and microscopy. In 1981
two IBM scientists constructed the first “scanning tunneling microscope”, which allowed humans,
for the first time, to actually see atoms separately. Eight years later, in 1989, another two IBM
scientists rearranged 35 individual atoms at will, forming the logo “IBM”. This last achievement
properly showed that what nanotechnology was aiming forthe mechanical manipulation of individual
atomsseemed to be in fact feasible [24].
By the turn of the millennium, the U.S. National Nanotechnology Initiative was founded,
receiving its first funding during the administration of President Bill Clinton. Quickly realizing
nanoscience’s potential for multilayered pervasive and disruptive consequences, in 2004 the European
Union produced a document entitled Towards a European Strategy for Nanotechnology [25]. There
the European community made clear its preferred emphasis on the possible benefits for society as a
15
One billionth of a meter.
16
Quantum effects, however, are part and parcel of the whole nanoscale somewhat “exotic” halo. Existing within the
threshold of 1–100 nm, the effects pertaining to the so called “quantum realm” are present, and thus, materials tend
to behave in a way that is absent at the macro-level (e.g., and otherwise inert material becomes conductive, etc.).
For an addressing of the quantum-related problems in nanoscale research, see Drexler’s “An Open Letter to Richard
Smalley” in ([23], Appendix).
17
The prefix “nano-” for these matters was not yet coined at the time, so he did not use it.
13
wholerather than on the human individual, as the American initiative would suggest. The same
year, the United Kingdom’s Royal Society released the report Nanoscience and Nanotechnologies:
Opportunities and Uncertainties [26]. In this report Great Britain called for focusing on investigating
the possible toxic side effects of doing research at the nanoscale. By 2005, further manipulation of
individual atoms was accomplished, this time by means of constructing a nanoscale “car”. A team
lead by Professor James Tour (Rice University) put together four fullerenes 18 united by a “frame”
composed of hydrogen molecules. The experiment was designed to find out in which way fullerenes
move across materials. When the surface (the “road”) got warmed up (e.g., to 200 degrees Celsius),
the diminutive cars began to run over the road at relatively “high speed”19. The idea of a nano-machine,
indeed proposed by Feynman as a future possibility, seemed to be closer to reality.
One needs to stop for a minute and consider the import of these advances. Indeed, they pertain to
the very heart of scientific practice tout court. Vico’s aim for an absolute recreation of the studied
object (the model) as the onlyor at least, the best—signature of true knowledge has certainly been
at the heart of the scientific mind since the beginning of Modern Science. Indeed the case could
be made that such aim is the essence of what is expected out of Bacon’s experimentum crucis.
Unfortunately, due to the very nature of realityleave alone the nature of human cognitionall we
could aimed for was the best possible description of a behavior manifested by a certain phenomenon
or object. Furthermore, when the mapping of a complex system’s behavior triggers an explosion of
variables, the set up model seems to be facing imminent demise. There comes a point where the range
of possible behaviors is just too immense to be captured and articulated. It would seem that at that
moment, doing a piece by piece mapping of the structure of the complex object itself becomes more
feasible. However, again, in light of the nature of reality and human cognition, this has shown to be a
practically unattainable feat, due to the staggering complexity of its structurewhich made scientists
focus on behavior in the first place (e.g., behaviorism’s reduction of the human person to a black
box).20 Ultimately, the endeavor for mapping and rebuilding the actual structure of an entitya.k.a.,
attaining truthwas right from the start inherently beyond our reach.
But now, the epistemic hope of knowing the object in an almost divine way 21 seems to be
amenable of physical realization. The Viconian horizon of literally re-creating our object of study as
proof of true knowledge could finally be within reach. Taking us closer to attaining ultimate knowledge
and control, the constructed model could become so close to the modeled object that any distinction
would be rendered trivial. Vico’s dictum of “if you know it, build it”, seems to be close to actual
instantiation at a qualitatively distinct level. After all, the famousif unfulfilled—cybernetic dogma
was that “the best material model for a cat is another, or preferably the same cat” ([30], p. 320).
Reordering atoms one by one, indeed restructuring the very fabric of reality, would have sounded to
Vico as the logical step towards the final understanding and mastery of nature.
18
A fullereneor “buckyball”is a spherical carbon molecule.
19
However, the “nanocar” lacked an engine, and thus, it was not a car in the full sense of the word (a.k.a., a machine
with four wheels, self-propelled by a motor) [27].
20
This dichotomy was an important source of tension for cybernetics. It might have in fact collaborated towards
cybernetics’ ultimate demise. See [28,29].
21
After all the thrust behind the Scientific Revolution, as indicated in the section pertaining to Francis Bacon).
14
Furthermore, the possibility of building nanomachines arguably surpasses Vico’s “verum factum”
stance, connecting it with the profoundly ambitious Baconian project—project that was recognized
and praised by Vico himself. Not only could objects be partitioned atom by atom, but these parts can
be so well rearranged that a working machine could arise. After all, that is what we see that living
organisms are conformed of: Countless nanomachines working in perfect synchronicity, making up
what is regarded as a living system. In fact, the summatory of such realities constitutes the totality of
biology. At this point, the distinction between the natural and the artificial has already collapsed. The
reckoning of the building blocks of reality subsequently allows for the manipulation and arrangement
of them all the way to a living mechanical process. In nanoscience, both the organic and inorganic are
equally dissected, treated and put together at will.
Currently operating scientific epistemologies stemming from this development might profoundly
affect our overall outlook regarding life, as the following section will show.
Scientists of the above mentioned Nanotechnology Initiative have been noticing that most
biological processes indeed happen at the nano level of reality. As examples, the width of the strand of
the DNA helix is around 2 nm; the average size of a virus is 40 nm; a small bacteria’s size is 200 nm;
and so on. The legacy inherited from the Scientific Revolution gradually deemed “natural” occurrences
as mechanical in natureto the chagrin of those who saw a machine and a living system as being
fundamentally at odds23. For instance, cybernetics took the mechanistic understanding of life to its
ultimate workable and theoretical extreme. As such, it gave examples in nature that speak of clever
mechanisms that must be underpinned by neatly working machinery. In cybernetic parlance, if nature
was capable of accomplishing such a feat, we should logically be able to do it as well, since a machine
by definition deems its type of materiality (or even lack thereof) as irrelevant, relying strictly on its
determinate behavior 24. One classically mechanistic case in biology occurring at the sub-cellular
level is that of the ribosome, which strikingly resembles a factory assembly lineand which gains
with this the strange “honor” of being referred to as a “molecular assembler” ([23], Chapter 1).
Biologists have in later years expressed interest in another instance in nature that offers an even
more striking example of machinery functioning at a nano-level. The bacterial flagellum has been of
22
I use “machinization” instead of “mechanization” in order to put emphasis on the ontology of the object qua
machine, instead of its process or behavior—without saying that they are unrelated.
23
The attempt of denial of a machine-organism isomorphism within the last century was largely nested upon the
alleged fact that a living organism can self-organize (to achieve biological homeostasis with its environment and
survive) whereas a machine cannot. In face of this, the cyberneticist William Ross Ashby embarked upon the
project of elaborating a more sophisticated and complete notion of a machine. This enriched notion can indeed
show powers of self-organization. Thus the bridge between the living and the non-living (which behaves as living)
was stablished: Machines could be alive. In fact, they always werein nature—but we did not notice it until
recently. For Ashby’s treatment of self-organization in machines, see [31,32].
24
For cybernetics’ addressing of the question regarding the nature of a machine in general, see [33]. For incipient
attempts at understanding the nature of a machine (mainly stemming from efforts to articulate the nature of an
algorithm) see [34,35].
15
interest to biologists, philosophers and even theologians for several reciprocally intertwined reasons,
which could all be put under one conceptual umbrella. If rigorously situated in a historical context,
the attraction exerted in the scientific community by this organism’s feature is indeed expectable.
What is curious is that, beyond scientists, some of the people behind this interest come from unlikely
flanks. Thanks to the progress in crystallography and nano-photography, we are now able to see as
part of the organism what could only be referred to as an “off-board” motor. The flagellum itself, a
tube 20 nm wide, is attached to a complex array of amino acids that make up a structure that not only
resembles an engine, but also seems to be an engine. One can identify pistons, camshaft, levers and
an axle. The rotation produced (which allows the flagellum to act as a propeller) is analogous to the
motion found in an engine, pistons moving an axle via the camshaft, which in turn makes an exterior
propeller quickly turn. Endowed with this acquired motility, the bacteria can freely navigate through
a liquid environment. The system seems to so neatly have found a way to achieve locomotion in a
thoroughly mechanical way, that Keiichi Namba, from the Graduate School of Frontier Biosciences
at Osaka University (and a world’s leading authority in bacterial flagellum studies), asserts that
25
Professor Namba does not hesitate in identifying in such a mechanism an actual engine: “The bacterial flagellum is
a rotary nanomachine that spins at hundreds of revolutions per second driven by the electrochemical potential
difference across the cytoplasmic membrane” ([38], p. 417).
16
It would seem that an evolutionary account of how the amino acid “pieces” of this engine are
put together would not be satisfactory. Moreover, this evolutionary blind-spot allegedly happens
at two-levels. At first glance, it would seem that, since we are talking about after all a machine, we
should be willing to accept some entailments. One of them is the claimed fact that a machine is
constituted by “parts”, and these parts cannot submit to an explanation dependent on evolution and
genetic mutation as a whole. These pieces should have always existed as such, without evolutionary
change. If the latter would be the case (if a piece would “change”) then it would not fit into the motor
and would render it useless –similarly to what occurs when a gear changes its shape and ruins an
engine. This observation would seem to trump the way in which evolution works.
What is behind this line of discourse is the falsificationist goal of finding an evolutionary niche
which could not be explained away by “natural selection”thus defeating Charles Darwin in his
own turf, given that he famously conceded that “[i]f it could be demonstrated that any complex organ
existed which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications,
my theory would absolutely break down” ([39], p. 146).
An answer to this raised observation has certainly emerged. There are instances where bacteria
show the lack of some amino acids (“pieces”) in the equivalent area that interfaces more directly with
its environment. The bacteria that caused the bubonic plague, for instance, have their flagella attached
to the body but not through a rotor. Instead it is stiff and fixed, serving as a needlethrough which
the bacteria transmit the contagious agent. This occurrence should point to a horizon where evolution
can still play the ultimate explanatory role. In this case it would be doing it by somehow getting rid
(supposedly via genetic mutation) of certain pieces of the “engine”, in order to provide another role
in the survival of the entity. However, such counterargument also has a rebuttal. It would seem that
the bacterial motility system of a rotary flagellum is older than its fixed counterpart, hence rendering
the latter as an unlikely ancestor. To which it is still answered that the flagellum’s ancestor might
have been completely extinguished, without trace. The discussion goes on.
Some “Intelligent Design” theorists exploit this issue as a workhorse against what they refer to
as a scientific tyranny of sorts exercised by Neo-Darwinism26 in American academia. Intelligent
Design (ID), according to its proponents, is a valid scientific alternative to the Neo-Darwinian widely
adopted standpoint. ID claims the allegedly verifiable fact that “design” (that which could only have
been accomplished by an intelligent agency) is present in nature by default. It was always the case,
the defenders would say, but now we get to see it clearer thanks to technological progress that furthered
sciencesuch as crystallographyand not just via philosophical reasoning27. They would stop short
of saying what kind of intelligence they are referring to, but since most of them seem to be practicing
Protestant science professors 28 , those who dispute this view –usually atheist philosophers 29 and
Catholic scientists30accuse them of attempting to smuggle religious “creationism” into the realm
26
Or the New Synthesis: Darwinian evolution later improved with Gregor Mendel’s theory of genetic mutation.
27
E.g., As in St. Thomas Aquinas’ fifth way within the Quinque Viae ([40], Part I, Question 2, Article 3).
28
E.g., William Dembski and Jonathan Welsh.
29
E.g., Daniel Dennett and Richard Dawkins.
30
E.g., Kenneth Miller and George Coyne, S.J.
17
of scientific discourse31. At this point (when the religious convictions of those engaged in the debate
are brought to the fore), a sort of justified ad hominem fallacy is invoked, and the whole environment
of discourse morphs into what is known as the not so surreptitiously ongoing “Culture Wars” 32.
It is in this context that ID advocates denounce the said “tyranny” of neo-Darwinism, which
allegedly monopolizes academic environments in meta-scientific (even political) ways, securing a
pre-epistemic (anti-religious) and epistemic (atheist) attitude in culture and society.
To be sure, it is not the first time in history that a religious motivation attempts to defeat a
certain scientific view due to the supposed negative consequences that the latter would entail. Jesuit
mathematicians (e.g., Giovanni Saccheri) were drawn towards the possibility of finding a geometry
that would not be Euclidean, in order to dismantle both the Critique of Pure Reason’s Transcendental
Aesthetic and the Prolegomena, so that Immanuel Kant’s challenge to metaphysics would get
eroded. In similar fashion, ID supporters tend to be particularly prone to find instances of machinery
in nature, in order to advance their claims regarding the presence of “design” in the natural world.
Allegedly, as indicated above, a machine by definition is constituted in such way (not only in its
being deterministic, but also in its being inherently constituted by an array of parts) that it defies
“natural selection”, thus obtaining for us a sort of reverse-Turing test for nature. If a natural entity cannot
be accounted for by evolutionas it is the case with a machinethen it has to be designed.
The debate continues, and it may not show signs of receding any time soon. Without attempting
to reduce, minimize or dismiss it, one could argue that deep divergences regarding the different
conceptualizations of notions such as “creation”, “design”, and most importantly, “machine” rest at
the core of the conflict. Be as it may, one feature particularly relevant for this section stands out. Of
31
The Catholic Church’s Magisterium has repeatedly referred to neo-Darwinism as more than “just a hypothesis”.
In 1996 John Paul II said while addressing the Pontifical Academy of Sciences:
Taking into account the state of scientific research at the time as well as of the requirements of theology, the
Encyclical Humani Generis considered the doctrine of “evolutionism” a serious hypothesis, worthy of investigation
and in-depth study equal to that of the opposing hypothesis… Today, almost half a century after the publication
of the Encyclical, new knowledge has led to the recognition of more than one hypothesis in the theory of
evolution. It is indeed remarkable that this theory has been progressively accepted by researchers, following a
series of discoveries in various fields of knowledge. The convergence, neither sought nor fabricated, of the results
of work that was conducted independently is in itself a significant argument in favour of this theory ([41], para. 4).
Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger (later Benedict XVI), then Prefect of the Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the
Faith, ratified in 2004 a document drafted by the International Theological Commission that read:
Since it has been demonstrated that all living organisms on earth are genetically related, it is virtually certain
that all living organisms have descended from this first organism. Converging evidence from many studies in
the physical and biological sciences furnishes mounting support for some theory of evolution to account for the
development and diversification of life on earth ([42], para. 63).
Regarding the last Pope, Francis (and the Catholic Tradition’s position) the Editorial of the journal Nature had
this to say on the matter:
…what is clear is that, contrary to widespread belief, the modern Catholic Church is science-friendly and Pope
Francis will no doubt continue, and perhaps deepen, that tradition. The Church’s strong support for Darwinian
evolution, for example, contrasts sharply with the backwards unscientific belief in creationism of many US
evangelicals and lawmakers—a concept that Pope Benedict XVI rightly criticized in 2007 as “absurd” [43].
32
For an extensive coverage of the issue, see [44,45].
18
all the people involved in this debate33, nobody seems to have a problem with one premise which, in
the past, would have likely stopped the dialogue in its tracks. Everyone seems to take for granted that
what we have before our eyes is, beyond any reasonable doubt, a machine. From a cybernetic lecture
of reality, there is considerable import in this assertionor realization. Facing the bacterial flagellum,
whatever vitalist or exceptionalist remnants of a metaphysic tradition that were seemingly still at
work in the most materialists thinkers at the time of cybernetics (mid-twentieth century), seem to be
extinct towards the second decade of the twenty-first century. The metaphysical safety-bumpers
seem to have worn off. Probably just a few of us today would go through any pain in acknowledging
that what we are witnessing is both a product of nature and a machine. A fully natural and fully machinal
entity34. This is probably the most typically cybernetic feature of all the ones we havesomewhat
unwittinglyinherited from cybernetics proper35.
The Baconian mechanical arts that were to rescue mankind from the damning epistemic darkness
set in by Original Sinand which mechanized the physical universe after the subsequently triggered
Scientific Revolutionseem to have indeed provided successful explanatory mechanisms. To the
extent in which biology is being physicalized, it was just a matter of time until the separating line
between the artificial and the natural became blurredvia the articulate consideration of what a machine
essentially is. As long as we have a scientific method in place with verifiable outcomes (experimentum
crucis) towards augmentation of knowledgeand we do—Bacon would have likely approved.
However, the Culture Wars ironically give us still another opportunity to witness novel approaches
in scientific modelingbesides the Baconian radical mechanization towards intentional modification.
The all-important issue of simulation in science will be shown as logically emerging from the
sometimes practically impossible frameworks that scientific experimentation requires. Its validity as
a modeling methodology occurred within an important turn of events within the ongoing Culture
Wars. This is the topic of the last section.
2.3. Simulation as Reality: Setting a Scotian Continnum between Immateriality and Physicality
During the fall of 2004, the public school of the town of Dover, Pennsylvania, introduced a
new biology textbook [50] where Neo-Darwinian evolution was presented alongside an “Intelligent
Design” alternative account. Following a mandate from the school committee, a statement had to be
33
Against ID: Kenneth Miller, Robert Pennock, Michael Ruse. For ID: Michael Behe, William Dembski, Steve Fuller
and Jerry Fodor (the last one more anti-Darwin than pro-ID, although he has written in ID blogs).
34
Ray Kurzweil, National Medal of Technology and Innovation laureate and Google’s current director of engineering,
advocates for a preparation towards an inescapable future where humans and machines will be completely merged,
rendering any meaningful distinction impossibleeven discriminatory. Fuller calls this stance the “cybernetic”
view of the future of humanity, seeing an understanding of anthropology as artificial theology. (See ([46], Chapter 1)
and ([47], Chapter 1)). However, a truly cybernetic view would refer to man in a present stage, and in an obvious
way, as just another instance of a typical machine.
35
Fully fleshing out the lineage between cybernetics and current scientific disciplines would entail a pain-staking
articulation that remains to be done. The closer attempt is probably Margaret Boden’s two volume work [48].
Jean-Pierre Dupuy’s book [20] attempts to unveil some of the cybernetic ancestral features of contemporary
disciplines, but according to Gualtiero Picinini, he falls short of completing the task [49].
19
read out loud by the biology teacher, referring clearly to the existence of both accounts, so that
the student could evaluate and decide on its own. By next fall, a number of concerned teachers and
parents had presented a law-suit against the school. The plaintiff sustained that such “strategy” was
in fact introducing religion in science class at a public high school. What occurred next signaled
the last chapter in the conflict that emerged several times out of the idiosyncratically American
“separation of church and state”.
Expert witnesses were called to testify. Several of those mentioned above were called up to testify
on the subject36. It soon became clear that what was at stake was the American legal take on the very
identity of science. The religious motivations behind the Scientific Revolutionevent that could be
understood, as per Francis Bacon, as a tension within Christianity in order to overcome a “genetic”
ignorance set off by Original Sin37were brought to the fore. The methodology of science, the
so-called “scientific method” took precedence. ID supporters claimed that Intelligent Design had a
valid space in the scientific discourse based upon this very method. They denied the interference of
any preconceived theological element, relying instead in methodological deduction after a hypothesis
and subsequent induction following the evidence. In this context, instances such as the bacterial
flagellum above mentioned were presented in detail, allegedly demonstrating in purely scientific
fashion that there is evidence in nature for the existence of “irreducibly complex” machinesdynamical
arrays whose perfectly fitting internal parts cannot be accounted for by evolution. As seen in the
preceding section, these parts needed to have been “intelligently designed” to fit each other and
function in tandem.
There was critical reaction against ID, signaling the alleged undisclosed feature indicated
above—a secularly masked creationism. However, soon it became apparent that “evolution” had to
be treated under the same judging scope. The taken for granted scandalously undeniable evidence for
the truth of evolution had to be shown. How do we know, with the sharp certainty that only science
could provide, that evolution is true? After all, ID was being attacked from those very grounds.
Accordingly, U.S. District Judge John E. Jones, a Republican Christian, asked for the same sort of
evidence that evolution advocates were claiming ID cannot produce.
Since ID theorists almost make a living out of reciting by heart the claimed Darwinian flaws,
evolution’s blind spots were so severely criticized that its advocates at some point indeed struggled.
Robert Pennock, a philosopher of science and expert witness in the trial for the side of evolution,
came up with an alleged proof that neo-Darwinian evolution is not just “a theory”, namely, perfectly
falsifiable and hence amenable of being discarded and superseded 38.
Avida39 is a computer program that generates an “evolutionary” environment in silico. More
specifically, the program is designed to create and maintain entities that compete for resources. Each
36
Previous note on the principal figures in the Culture Wars debate.
37
Section 2.
38
The perceived exchangeability between the notions of “hypothesis” and “theory” seems to occur mainly in the
English language. The statement of evolution as being “just a hypothesis” would in any case make more sense.
Evolution as “just a theory” can be translated to evolution as “just a tested hypothesis”—the canonical definition of
theorywhich would be of course problematic.
39
For an explanation co-written by Pennock of the role of Avida in scientific methodology, see [51].
20
has its own memory allocation and virtual central processing unit (CPU), and they are protected
from each other. They have to evolve in such way that they can gain access to time with the main
CPU. These digital entities have the capacity to modify (re-program) themselves, in order to reach a
better fit for survivalnot completely unlike sophisticated computer viruses that fight for their
“lives” in domestic computing environments. In Pennock’s words, “it is clear that natural selection
can be perfectly instantiated in A-life systems” ([52], p. 37). In case there is any doubt still lingering
so as to how to understand these words, he asserted that “this is not a simulation” of evolution.
Rather, it is an “instance” of it. The programor what it purported to show—did convince the judge40.
Thus the court declared evolution as a fact. Materiality was not deemed necessary to accept the
truism of evolution. Pennock further affirmed that:
While it is true that evolution of carbon-based organisms is the prototype of the concept,
this historical fact is not a sufficient reason to limit its scope. Why be carbon-centric? It is
the patterns of causal interactions that are relevant, not the particular material substrate.
…the material substrate of the Darwinian processes should be irrelevant to whether we
recognize something as an instance of Darwin’s evolutionary mechanism ([52], p. 32).
Thus even if the witnessed “evolution” happened entirely inside a machine, one nevertheless can
claim now to have “proof”at least in the eyes of the judgethat evolution is, plainly and simply,
true. Facing an instance of the awkward relation between scientific practice and institutionality, one
could object that a legal decision cannot make, let alone rule, science. This objection could recognize
in this court ruling, at most, a geo-culturally limited change of attitude regarding what is real and
what it is not in its own legal environment. Now virtual realities count as legal facts. However, once
we factor in Pennock’s statements, we can readily notice that this epistemological ethos has a theoretical
and empirical background that goes way beyond contemporary legalismsin fact, it is increasingly
shared by salient scientific enterprises. Indeed Pennock is by no means isolated in advancing these
views –and the judge probably knew that much. Some recent examples are relevant.
In 2006, a group of scientists lead by Klaus Schulten (University of Illinois at Urbana) simulated
an entire virus, modeling it atom by atom. Unsurprisingly, the study was published in the journal
Structure. The satellite tobacco mosaic virus, one of the smallest in nature, had its approximately one
million atoms “recreated” simultaneously. It required the sheer computing capability of one of the
most powerful machines on the planet, the National Center for Supercomputing Applications. Still, it
took 100 days to bring up to “life” only 50 nanoseconds of the “virtual” virus [53]. Later on in 2012,
Markus Covert (Stanford University) and his team recreated a complete organisma bacterium41.
This unicellular entity, the Mycoplasma genitalia, is the living being with the smallest genetic
footprint: 525 genes. Remarkably, this time the entity, recreated in silico, underwent a reproductive
40
To be sure, the ID side (the defendants) lost the case not only due to this finding. An early draft of the controversial
textbook was found, and in it, it was shown that the word “creationism” was scratched and replaced with “intelligent
design” on top. This was enough evidence to show, for the judge, that religion was being smuggled into science
class in a public school, thereby violating the constitutional separation between church and state in that country.
41
It is traditionally understood that a virus does not qualify as a “complete” organism, given that it needs a host to
survive. In fact, debates regarding its status as a “living” entity pivot upon this very issue.
21
process. Serving as a witness to the kind of progress that computation can develop in just 6 years, this
time the virtual entity lasted 10 h: The actual time the modeled entity takes to reproduce, and remarkably,
the time the constructed model took to do it as well. The constructed model and the modeled organism
were operationally identical, all the way down to their atomic existence. For attaining this, a cluster
of 128 powerful computers interconnected were required. It was the first time a complete organism
has been entirely reproduced inside a virtual environment [54].
In all fairness to cybernetics, these scientific accomplishments were the stuff that made up
the cybernetitians’ dreamsalbeit unaccomplishable at their time, due to the lack of technological
advancement in what regards manipulation of materials 42. However, cybernetics’ penchant for actual
(physical) model building43, at least theoretically, was not entirely newas we have seen in Section 3.
Although it became right from the start a sort of defining feature for the cybernetic enterprise, the
recreation of a studied object has deep roots in the Western tradition of philosophy, arguably reaching
a peak with Vico’s dictum for interchangeability between object and model as an insurmountable
footprint of truth. However, the tension between the mandate for material model construction and the
seemingly perennial temptation for abandoning all grips with physical reality since Plato, might have
proven to be deeper and more pervadingand might had spelled, at the time44, the demise of the
cybernetic project.
It is ironic that a model existent solely in virtual reality would come to undermine the survival
of Intelligent Design, since “ID clearly descends from the Franciscan side in accepting a univocal
account of language” ([1], p. 107). Indeed it was the Franciscan Duns Scotus who established a type
of strong relation between physical entities and disembodied realms. This connection found echo in
Newton’s idea of having access to God’s mind. Reacting against Original Sin’s epistemic darkness
via Bacon’s mechanical arts, we can recover that Adamian divinely infused knowledge, instantiated
in the only possible way that can show its divine origin: the radical (re)creation of objectsas Vico
foresaw. This closes the Scotian circle, where the attributes of humans and those of God are different
in degree, not in kind. This dynamic might entail a new context of thinking about the status of
what we understand as a human entity. Specifically, a synthetic biology spearheaded by a profoundly
mechanistic view of lifewhere the distinction between the natural and the artificial is
blurredmight have found a renewed strength thanks to the promises of a fundamental restructuring
of nature via nano-science.
3. Concluding Remarks
Whatever outcome may arrive regarding the status of “the human” from this deep restructuring
of the technological impetus, it would be useful to realize that the allegedly ideas driving these late
scientific foresights and technological goals are not radically newat least in spirit. Francis Bacon
42
In fact this very issue, shifting from behavior to structure in scientific modeling, caused deep internal tensions
within cybernetics, as indicated above [28,29].
43
Famouseven “media-friendly”—cybernetic autonomous machines were Claude Shannon’s “rats”, Grey Walter
“tortoises” and Ross Ashby’s “homeostat” [55].
44
Late 1950s.
22
45
This was a coordinated effort launched in 2000 to synchronize current developments in sciences and technologies
towards a unified vision that would allow for the possibility of a qualitative leap in the human experience:
The phrase “convergent technologies” refers to the synergistic combination of four major “NBIC”
(nano-bio-info-cogno) provinces of science and technology, each of which is currently progressing at a rapid
rate: (a) nanoscience and nanotechnology; (b) biotechnology and biomedicine, including genetic engineering;
(c) information technology, including advanced computing and communications; and (d) cognitive science,
including cognitive neuroscience ([56], pp. 1–2).
Correspondingly, a summarizing motto found in its founding document reads:
If the Cognitive Scientists can think it,
the Nano people can build it,
the Bio people can implement it, and
the IT people can monitor and control it ([56], p. 13).
46
Expressing a concern not dissimilar with cybernetic’s own during the 1940s ([57], pp. 2–3), a preoccupation with
the wide separation existing between different areas of scientific research was expressed. The countervailing
epistemic position would be that of a renaissance man (i.e., the polymath Leonardo Da Vinci). Accordingly, a new,
unifying view is proposed:
We stand at the threshold of a new renaissance in science and technology, based on a comprehensive
understanding of the structure and behavior of matter from the nanoscale up to the most complex system yet
discovered, the human brain…Developments in systems approaches, mathematics, and computation in conjunction
with NBIC allow us for the first time to understand the natural world, human society, and scientific research
as closely coupled complex, hierarchical systems. At this moment in the evolution of technical achievement,
improvement of human performance through integration of technologies becomes possible ([56], p. 2.
Emphasis added).
23
implementation takes a high-risk stance47 or one that advocates precaution.48. This dynamism of
mechanization, purified abstraction and ulterior re-instantiation might indeed hold the key for our
biological survival vis a vis a potentially radical ecological changeeven if in the process the very
notion of “human” gets trivialized all the way into oblivion.
The awareness that “human nature”whatever we understand by it—would indeed not survive
the advance of science is a common sentiment among scholars in the last decades. As if we would
have to give up on our philosophy in order to preserve our biology. If we remind them that the very
forces behind these pervasive technological disruptions are deeply rooted into what prominent
humanists proposed between the thirteenth and sixteenth centuries, the context for understanding this
progress can be geared towards a more enriched and embedded approacheven if what we obtain as
an outcome is beyond recognition. Having in consideration the metaphysical tenets behind these
disruptive technologies could further foster their advancement, correspondingly cultivating the
awareness that there is a hopeful, transcendent, notion of what it entails to be humanwhich inspired
these Medieval and early Modern intellectual forces in the first place. The difference is that now we
might be witnessing the beginning of the technological feasibility for this “next” human. It would
then seem then that the relevance of the humanities should be considered of utmost importance when
facing indeed a new way of human existence: As a “biological citizen”, aware of its “neurochemical
self”, and displaying “somatic expertise” with its own “biocapital”49. Indeed, the renewed fostering
of the humanities might be necessary for our very survival. If one is to thoroughly articulate the
underlying humanistic impetus behind pervasively disruptive technologies, the input of the
humanities could not only let itself be felt, but indeed guide the late scientific ethos towards human
alteration into self-critical flourishing.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the external editor, Albrecht Classen, and the various anonymous reviewers
for comments on earlier versions of this piece. Any persisting errors are entirely my fault.
Conflicts of Interest
References
1. Steve Fuller. Humanity 2.0: What it Means to be Human Past, Present and Future.
Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011.
2. Immanuel Kant. Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002.
3. Duns Scotus. Philosophical Writings: A Selection. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987.
47
As the founding, American document would suggest [56].
48
As the document produced by the European Union in response would propose [59]. For an account of the difference
between the American and the European views on NBIC, see [60]. The Canadian stance was aligned with its American
neighbor’s [61].
49
See chapters 5, 7 and the Afterword of [62].
24
25. European Commission. Towards a European Strategy for Nanotechnology. Luxembourg City:
Office for Official Publications of the European Communities, 2004.
26. Royal Academy of Engineering. Nanoscience and Nanotechnologies: Opportunities and
Uncertainties. London: The Royal Society, 2004.
27. Yasuhiro Shirai, Andrew J. Osgood, Yuming Zhao, Kevin F. Kelly, and James M. Tour.
“Directional Control in Thermally Driven Single-Molecule Nanocars.” Nano Letters 5 (2005):
2330–34.
28. John von Neumann. “Letter to Wiener.” In John von Neumann: Selected Letters. Edited by
Miklós Redei. Providence: American Mathematical Society, 2005, pp. 277–82.
29. John von Neumann. “The general and logical theory of automata.” In Cerebral Mechanisms in
Behavior: The Hixon Symposium. Edited by Lloyd Jeffress. New York: Wiley, 1951, pp. 1–41.
30. Arturo Rosenblueth, and Norbert Wiener. “The role of models in science.” Philosophy of
Science 12 (1945): 316–21.
31. William Ross Ashby. “The Nervous System as Physical Machine: With Special Reference to
the Origin of Adaptive Behavior.” Mind 56 (1947): 44–59.
32. William Ross Ashby. “Principles of the Self-Organizing Dynamic System.” Journal of
General Psychology 37 (1947): 125–28.
33. William Ross Ashby. An Introduction to Cybernetics. London and New York: Chapman and
Hall, John Wiley & Sons, 1956.
34. Alan Turing. “On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem.”
Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 42 (1937): 230–65.
35. Alan Turing. “Systems of Logic Based on Ordinals.” Proceedings of the London Mathematical
Society 45 (1939): 161–228.
36. William Paley. Natural Theology: Or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity,
Collected from the Appearances of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
37. Keiichi Namba. “Self-Assembly of Bacterial Flagella.” Paper presented at the Annual Meeting
of the American Crystallographic Association, San Antonio, TX, USA, May 2002.
38. Keiichi Namba. “Conformational change of flagellin for polymorphic supercoiling of the
flagellar filament.” Nature Structural & Molecular Biology 17 (2010): 417–22.
39. Charles Darwin. On the Origin of Species: By Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation
of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
40. St. Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologica. Notre Dame: Christian Classics, 1981, vol. 5.
41. John Paull II. “Address to the Plenary Session on the Subject ‘The Origins and Early
Evolution of Life’ (22 October 1996).” In Papal Addresses to the Pontifical Academy of
Sciences 1917–2002 and to The Pontifical Academy of Social Sciences 1994–2002. Vatican
City: The Pontifical Academy of Sciences, 2003, pp. 370–74.
42. International Theological Commission. “Communion and Stewardship: Human Persons
Created in the Image of God.” In Texts and Documents, Volume 2: 1986–2007. San Francisco:
Ignatius Press, 2009, pp. 319–52.
43. Nature (Editorial). “A pope for today: Latest pontiff looks to enhance social relevance of
Catholic Church.” Nature 495 (2013): 282, doi:10.1038/495282a.
26
44. Steve Fuller. Science v. Religion? Intelligent Design and the Problem of Evolution.
Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007.
45. Steve Fuller. Dissent Over Descent: Intelligent Design’s Challenge to Darwinism. London:
Icon Books, 2008.
46. Ray Kurzweil. The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology. New York:
Penguin, 2005.
47. Steve Fuller. Preparing for Life in Humanity 2.0. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013.
48. Margaret Boden. Mind as Machine: A History of Cognitive Science. Oxford and New York:
Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, 2006.
49. Gualtiero Piccinini. “Review of the Mechanization of Mind: On the Origins of Cognitive
Science, by J.P. Dupuy.” Minds and Machines 12 (2002): 449–53.
50. Percival Davis, and Dean H. Kenyon. Of Pandas and People: The Central Question of
Biological Origins, 2nd ed. Dallas: Haughton, 1989.
51. Richard E. Lenski, Charles Ofria, Robert T. Pennock, and Christoph Adami. “The evolutionary
origin of complex features.” Nature 423 (2003): 134–44.
52. Robert Pennock. “Models, simulations, instantiations, and evidence: the case of digital
evolution.” Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 19 (2007): 29–42.
53. Peter L. Freddolino, Anton S. Arkhipov, Steven B. Larson, Alexander McPherson, and Klaus
Schulten. “Molecular Dynamics Simulations of the Complete Satellite Tobacco Mosaic
Virus.” Structure 14 (2006): 437–49.
54. Jonathan R. Karr, Jayodita C. Sanghvi, Derek N. Macklin, Miriam V. Gutschow, Jared M.
Jacobs, Benjamin Bolival Jr., Nacyra Assad-Garcia, John I. Glass, and Markus W. Covert. “A
Whole-Cell Computational Model Predicts Phenotype from Genotype.” Cell 150 (2012): 389–
401.
55. Andrew Pickering. “A Gallery of Monsters: Cybernetics and Self-Organisation, 1940–1970.”
In Mechanical Bodies, Omputational Minds: Artificial Intelligence from Automata to Cyborgs.
Edited by Stefano Franchi and Guven Güzeldere. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005, pp. 229–45.
56. National Science Foundation. Converging Technologies for Improving Human Performance:
Nanotechnology, Biotechnology, Information Technology and Cognitive Science. Edited by
William S. Bainbridge and Mihail C. Roco. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2003.
57. Norbert Wiener. Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine,
2nd rev. ed. Paris and Cambridge: Hermann et Cie., MIT Press, 1948.
58. Steve Fuller, and Veronika Lipinska. “Transhumanism.” In Ethics, Science, Technology, and
Engineering: A Global Resource. Edited by Britt Holbrook and Carl Mitcham. Farmington
Hills: Gale, Cengage Learning, 2015.
59. European Commission. Converging Technologies: Shaping the Future of European Societies.
Reported by Alfred Nordmann. Luxembourg: CORDIS, 2004.
60. European Commission. “Research trajectories and institutional settings of new converging
technologies.” Report for Knowledge Politics and New Converging Technologies: A Social
Science Perspective. Reported by Steve Fuller. Luxembourg: CORDIS, 2008.
27
61. Defence Research, and Development Canada. NBIC Disruptive Technology Watch. Prepared
by Scott MacKenzie, Allen Chong, Tiit Romet, and Kimberly Thomas. Ottawa:Consulting and
Audit Canada, 2003.
62. Nikolas Rose. The Politics of Life Itself: Biomedicine, Power, and Subjectivity in the
Twenty-First Century. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009.
28
Abstract: Practicing the clinical humanities requires throwing oneself into the unpredictable locus
of suffering, where one is unable to infer the actual situation of the other, a process which fosters
self-disclosure. By using the term “clinical humanities” we are attempting to free the humanities
and social sciences from their self-imposed boundaries which have brought them to their current
dispirited condition. Bringing the depth of the humanities and social sciences into the clinical
field in the service of relieving suffering and setting up a humanities support network will help
the humanities renew itself by listening attentively to the great amount of suffering in the world.
Conceived in this way, the clinical humanities has its own methodology and way of generating
insight, and also has a unique contribution to make to the amelioration of suffering in all its forms.
In moving beyond their current condition and into the clinical field, the humanities and social
sciences take on a new conceptual framework and a distinctive rhythm. From this perspective, the
encounter between nursing and the clinical humanities might be seen as the unlikely meeting of
fundamentally different and incompatible fields. Indeed, the humanities and social sciences may
seem quite alien to nursing and clinical practice. In this paper I explore diverse aspects of the clinical
humanities and how they can be applied to nursing and nursing education. I also investigate some
innovative perspectives on healing and the clinical humanities and the implications they have for
nursing and nursing education.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Yu, A. The Encounter of Nursing and the Clinical Humanities:
Nursing Education and the Spirit of Healing. Humanities 2014, 3, 660–674.
After being defeated by the Communists in the long-running Chinese Civil War, the government
of the ROC (Republic of China) retreated to Taiwan in 1949 and made the island its redoubt while
preparing to retake the mainland. Thanks to the political and military support of the United States
(U.S.), as guaranteed in the Sino-American Mutual Defense Treaty, the ROC government succeeded
in retaining possession of Taiwan, which was seen by the U.S. as a key buffer state in its efforts to
contain the spread of communism. Over the following decades Taiwan was under martial law, and
with substantial U.S. assistance entered into a period of rapid industrialization and Westernization.
As elsewhere in the developing world, however, U.S. aid was contingent on the implementation of
economic reforms along American lines. At the same time, the neo-liberal perspectives of the U.S.
came to have a major impact on all aspects of life in Taiwan, a process sometimes referred to as
“neo-imperialism”. Thus it comes as no surprise that Taiwan’s system of higher education is very
much modeled on that of the U.S.
29
This is especially true in the case of medical education. Indeed, in present-day Taiwan there exists
practically no alternative to the Euro-American approach, in which medicine is seen as a branch of
the biological sciences. This has had a major influence on the medical culture of contemporary
Taiwan, such that the traditional Chinese understanding of health and illness, as well as the wide
variety of healing practices based thereupon (spiritual healing, qigong, etc.), are by and large rejected
by the mainstream medical establishment as “superstitions” or “quackery”. One notable exception is
the recent addition of traditional Chinese medicine to the types of treatment covered by Taiwan’s
national health insurance program. Being based on the rationality of the natural sciences, the Western
medical model attempts to objectify and universalize illness, diagnosis, and treatment, with the
result that such subjective factors as the affective states and emotional intelligence of nursing staff
is seen as irrelevant or even intrusive. Such a state of affairs has given rise to a medical system
characterized by materialistic values and hampered by a sense of alienation on the part of patients
and medical professionals.
The helping professions in contemporary Taiwanese society, including nursing and clinical
counseling, are becoming increasingly specialized and compartmentalized, such that the meaning of
“professional” has come to refer to a person who has acquired a highly specialized set of skills which
can quickly bring about objectively verifiable results. In comparison with the holistic view of health
and wellbeing in traditional Chinese medicine, such an approach is seriously lacking in cultural
depth. Indeed, Western medicine adopts the “fast food” approach to health care, and it seems that today’s
national health care systems treat health as just another commodity. It is equally apparent that in
Taiwan the humanities and social sciences are becoming increasingly isolated and superfluous due to
their general lack of interest in facing the fundamental issues of human suffering.
In response to this situation, in the spring of 2009 a team of scholars in Taiwan headed by
Professor Der-heuy Yee set up the Clinical Humanities Research Center (CHRC) and set about
investigating the interface between medicine and the humanities and the application of the results to
clinical practice [2]. The central idea of the clinical humanities is that health care is a key issue which
has spiritual implications in all spheres of life. In this context the term “clinical” refers to the relief of
human suffering by entering into the site of suffering. The clinical humanities strives to appropriately
apply the insights of both the humanities and social sciences—including such seemingly unrelated
fields as the fine arts, philosophy, literature, history, anthropology, psychology, and religion—to the
understanding and alleviation of suffering.
By using the term “clinical humanities” we are attempting to free the humanities and social
sciences from their self-imposed boundaries which have brought them to their current dispirited
condition. Bringing the depth of the humanities and social sciences into the clinical field in the
service of relieving suffering and setting up a humanities support network will help the humanities
renew itself by listening attentively to the suffering in the world. Conceived in this way, the clinical
humanities has its own methodology and way of generating insight, and also has a unique contribution to
make to the amelioration of suffering in all its forms.
In this paper I present the central concerns of the clinical humanities from the ontological and
epistemological perspectives, with a particular emphasis on how this emerging field can serve to
increase the depth and breadth of our understanding of suffering and healing. One of the key
30
purposes of the clinical humanities is to give more attention to the dynamic and transformative
nature of the “place of suffering”. Inasmuch as the place of suffering is characterized by the flow and
transformation of energy, the clinical humanities aims to function as a catalyst of healing. The main
approach is to integrate and apply the perspectives of the humanities and social sciences to gaining a
deeper, more comprehensive, and practical understanding of the abundant information which exists
at the site of suffering. Such insight can then be applied to the formulation of techniques which have
the capacity to bring about healing and transformation. Far from being an abstract concept or a
simplistic model of cause and effect, above all the clinical humanities aims to bring about practical
results [3].
In the clinical humanities the term “suffering” refers to not only mental and physical suffering,
but also to all types of “social suffering”, including racism, sexism, and poverty. Likewise, the term
“healing encounter” refers to the spontaneous healing which can result in the context of genuine and
caring human interaction.
Seeing that human suffering always occurs within a particular cultural milieu, our understanding
of suffering and its treatment must necessarily be indigenized. For this reason the CHRC has been
utilizing the concepts of ethos and the ethical act to develop various indigenized techniques for
treating both mental and physical suffering. Such an approach stands in stark contrast to that of
contemporary mainstream psychiatry, which is based on the concepts of normality and deviance, and
which tends to use invasive measures intended to bring about quick results. In the clinical humanities,
however, everyday life and the “body space” are taken as the “site of healing”, and the healing
techniques utilized are gentle and culturally sensitive.
Based on the results of our research, we are now endeavoring to deepen and expand our
understanding of suffering and healing, and to popularize the concepts of “lifeworld” and the clinical
humanities. In addition to bringing the humanities and social sciences back into the everyday world,
the clinical humanities can serve as a foundation for medical education and indigenized clinical
counseling, a foundation which is very different than the currently favored one based on empirical
science. Moreover, the clinical humanities transcends the limited perspectives built into the approach
to health and wellbeing currently used in mainstream medical treatment and clinical and counseling
psychology. Thus the clinical humanities can be seen as a way of bringing diversity to both clinical
psychology and nursing education [3].
One of the main objectives of the clinical humanities is to establish an alternative foundation for
the development of indigenous clinical and counseling psychology, cultural healing, and medical
care. The underlying principle of the clinical humanities is that all forms of suffering—mental,
physical, emotional, or existential—arise in a specific sociocultural context, and must be understood
in relation to this context. This is why indigenized versions of the helping professions are shifting
away from pathology and towards an ethicized social practice.
The “comprehensive care of body and mind” have already become buzz words in mainstream
medicine. Yet, without a deep grounding in the humanities, so-called holistic body-mind treatment is
merely another slogan. From the perspective of palliative care, such a grounding includes sensitivity
31
to such issues as ethics, religious sentiments, and bereavement. These issues require a depth of
understanding which is far greater than that required for daily life, and thorough familiarity with
them is essential for anyone working in the clinical humanities. This is the starting point for a medical
ethics embedded in the lifeworld.
When we point out this lack of human sensitivity in the field of medical care, some may object
that this is simply the current state of affairs in Taiwan, and that the same situation prevails in all
medical settings. However, our purpose here is not to compare the strong and weak points of the
various treatment settings in Taiwan. Rather, we want to emphasize the human sensitivity which can
be brought to bear on the issues of illness and death in different modes of providing care. One of the
most trenchant objections to the current paradigm of medical treatment is that, in its over-emphasis
on the elimination of symptoms, it also eliminates the lifeworld of the patient. In such a view, the
modern medical profession transforms “suffering” into mere “symptoms”, in the process banishing
the emotional element of illness and masking its true nature. Illness is necessarily an emotional
experience [4], and what sort of emotions we produce lies in the depth of our human sensitivity.
In the words of Gong [5]:
Illness is an experience, not scientific knowledge. In approaching illness as it is actually
experienced, we need to temporarily put aside the direct use of literal language and
concepts in order to avoid narrowing the horizon; we also need to maintain a high
degree of sensitivity towards the patient’s latent life narrative, and inquire into the
structure of the patient’s inclination.
Gong [5] quotes S. Kay Toombs decisive words:
In facing the most important ethical questions and carrying out open and intimate
dialogue, an individual shifts his attention from direct involvement with worldly
entanglements to his deepest inner emotions, in the process experiencing what to him
has ultimate meaning.
As a scholar of rare and severe illnesses, Toombs speaks about suffering in a very personal voice,
helping philosophy to occupy an increasingly prominent position in the discussion of medical
treatment. Senior psychiatrist Arthur Kleinman1 goes even further in the reflections he presents in
What Really Matters: Living a Moral Life amidst Uncertainty and Danger, where he attempts to
increase our understanding of psychiatry and apply its insights to the troubled moral life of contemporary
society [6]. These are some of the more prominent voices calling into question the dominant
paradigm in contemporary medicine and nursing care, especially its over-emphasis on the elimination
of symptoms.
In the course of our teaching, research, and clinical experience, we gradually came to wonder
whether it would be feasible to introduce the humanities into the alleviation of suffering, and whether
the humanities could expand beyond its traditional confines and into the field of caregiving. At the
1
Kleinman founded the Medical Anthropology Department at Harvard University, and beginning in the 1960s has
done research in Taiwan on mental illness and spirit mediums.
32
same time, the humanities and social sciences can develop a new way of thinking which is situational
and indigenized, and which has clinical applicability.
The CHRC brings together local and foreign scholars working in the humanities (e.g., art,
philosophy, Sinology, literature, history, and religion) and the social sciences (e.g., cultural psychiatry,
cultural psychology, psychotherapy, clinical psychology, medical anthropology, medical sociology,
nursing, and social work). Our long-term goal is to form an interdisciplinary research network with
the mission of exploring the accessibility and significance of the clinical humanities by organizing
study groups, workshops, training camps, and academic forums which examine a variety of new
approaches to the humanities and social sciences, as well as the possibility of designing an integrated
program in the clinical humanities.
Based on the above considerations, in the summer of 2009 we officially established the CHRC,
with Professor Der-heuy Yee (Graduate Institute of Religion and the Humanities, Ciji University) as
the director, and Professor An-bang Yu (Institute of Ethnology, Academia Sinica) as the executive
director. Based at the College of Humanities and Social Sciences of Ciji (Tzu Chi) University in
Hualien, the center serves as a platform for incorporating the humanities and social sciences into
medical and nursing treatment in a comprehensive manner. Because they are deeply involved with
ethical, interpersonal, socioeconomic, and psychological issues, the humanities and social sciences
have a natural role to play in the healing arts. Concretely speaking, our plan is to develop an
interdisciplinary academic network of professors and other professionals with extensive related
experience in order to achieve the following goals: (1) the development and elucidation of core
concepts and key terminology, as well as the classification of the categories, extent, and applicability
of the clinical humanities; (2) assisting participating professors in establishing related courses and
organizing educational workshops for the collective development of teaching materials; (3) organizing
workshops for the discussion of possible cooperative research projects and objectives; and (4) drafting
the curricula for several short-term classes and making these available to the members of various
academic societies.
In our view, practicing the clinical humanities requires throwing oneself into the unpredictable
locus of suffering, where one is unable to infer the actual situation of the other, a process which
fosters self-disclosure. By using the term “clinical humanities” we are attempting to free the humanities
from its self-imposed boundaries which have brought it to its current dispirited condition. Bringing
the depth of the humanities into the clinical field in the service of relieving suffering and setting up a
humanities support network will help the humanities renew itself by listening attentively to the
suffering in the world. Conceived in this way, the clinical humanities has its own methodology and
way of generating insight, and also has a unique contribution to make to the amelioration of suffering
in all its forms [2,7]. Before proceeding, it is necessary to elaborate on the meaning of healing.
In the view of Thomas Csordas [8] healing is not so much the elimination of illness, as a
transformation in the person, in which the body arrives at a new understanding and enters into
another reality. What is meant here by “body” is not merely the physical body, but may refer to any realm
of experience, including religious, emotional, aesthetic, linguistic, historical, or political. For example,
33
faith healing comes about through one’s relationship with God, by making a meaningful connection
with the sacred. The end result is a transformational experience which has a profound effect on the
person’s body, mind, and spirit [9].
According to Henri Bergson’s theory of immanence, healing is a type of inherent transformation,
the occurrence of which is quite unpredictable. And when healing does occur, it happens at various
speeds, yet it can become a continuous state. Moreover, this process freely extends from moment to
moment, and is beyond the control and comprehension of the ego, just as one’s thoughts freely flow
through time. From this perspective, healing is an immanent phenomenon, and its essential nature is
time. In this sense, healing is a type of freedom [10,11].
An additional goal of the CHRC is to integrate the clinical humanities into both teaching and
research. This includes helping teachers to seamlessly integrate the clinical humanities into their
courses and introduce their students to such topics as impermanence and awareness of the body. The
CHRC is especially concerned with the learning which takes place in the course of meeting suffering,
and how to deepen this learning in clinical practice in order to gain a diverse perspective on key
ethical issues.
One of the basic functions of the CHRC is the formulation of a practical development plan for the
localization and regionalization of education, research, and clinical work. Here, “localization” means
the seamless linking up of the work of the CHRC with the lifeworld of teachers and students, in order
to bring about the integration of theory and practice in the clinical humanities. “Regionalization”
means taking the “site of suffering” as the social category, and linking up those working in different
areas into a diverse network of healing resources in order to create a healing community of learning,
resource sharing, and mutual support. This would include: (1) setting up experimental healing
communities in various disciplines for the purpose of training in the theory and practice of the
clinical humanities; (2) compiling and distributing writings based on personal experience of natural
disasters, illness, and personal hardship; and (3) putting theory into practice by extending classroom
learning into real-life situations.
In the past the humanities and social sciences have been tightly encapsulated within their own
academic boundaries, remaining aloof from the many changes in perspective brought about by
post-modernism. It is quite clear that a post-modern approach to the humanities and social sciences
includes a blurring of traditional academic borders, in accordance with the trend of fluid boundaries
between academic disciplines. Although at present a number of disciplines in the humanities and
social sciences have begun to venture into related areas, they tend to do so in a tentative and limited
manner. Indeed, effective interdisciplinary work can generate a new domain of knowledge and open
up new realms of possibility.
“Nursing Humanities” to the M.A. and Ph.D. curriculums of Yangming’s Institute of Clinical and
Community Nursing. This short-term course focuses on the application of the humanities to various
methodological and epistemological issues in nursing, as well as effective ways for nursing
professionals to increase their knowledge and understanding of the clinical humanities [12].
Formulated in accordance with the overall aims of Yangming’s School of Nursing, the Nursing
Humanities course covers the following topics: (1) the meaning and practical importance of the
nursing humanities; (2) the educational goals of the “Nursing and the Clinical Humanities” module
at Yangming; (3) the humanities techniques of narration and introspection; (4) using narration and
introspection to explore various clinical issues in the nursing humanities; (5) ethics in theory and
practice; (6) case studies which illustrate ethical issues in nursing; and (7) the interpersonal relationship
between nurse and patient, doctor and nurse, nurse and nurse, etc. [13]. In short, the basic approach
of the Nursing Humanities course is to use lectures and discussions to familiarize participants with
the fundamental concepts and techniques of the clinical humanities, why they are important, and how
to apply them to their own work.
Mu’s ([12], p. 5) perspective on the Nursing and the Clinical Humanities module is made evident
in the following extract from the introduction to the module:
The Nursing and the Clinical Humanities module being held by National Yangming
University’s School of Nursing was designed by the school’s faculty and students in
collaboration with scholars in the humanities. It can be seen as a milestone in the
introduction of the clinical humanities into the curriculum of the School of Nursing.
In January 2010 we began holding a series of seminars and workshops for nursing
instructors and scholars specializing in various areas of the humanities. The instructors
shared their ideas about educational goals in nursing and how the clinical humanities
might be used to bring about various improvements in nursing education. For their part,
the humanities scholars shared their ideas on how their respective disciplines can be
applied to health care and how we understand illness and disease. The nursing instructors
also reflected on the best ways to integrate the nursing humanities into nursing education,
how to apply concepts in the humanities to nursing education, and what the nursing
humanities looks like in actual practice.
The Nursing and the Clinical Humanities module consists of four courses covering five themes:
psychoanalysis and humanistic care; inquiry in the clinical humanities (readings in illness and
ethnography); Western philosophy and humanistic care; art and humanistic care; and humanistic
care in the helping professions. The main learning goals of the module are as follows: (1) to
understand the various concepts, theories, and research methods used in the humanities and social
sciences which have a bearing on caregiving, and how they can be applied to the relief of suffering;
(2) to inquire into the meaning of the nursing humanities and become familiar with practical and
effective techniques for relieving suffering; (3) to learn how to apply various ideas and methods
from the humanities and social sciences to gaining insight into the experience of health, illness, and
suffering; and (4) to learn how to gain insight from clinical experience, learn through self-inquiry,
and understand the heuristic approach to nursing theory.
35
The main topics covered in each of the five themes included in the module are as follows:
(1) Psychoanalysis and humanistic care. This theme covers the history of psychoanalysis from
Sigmund Freud to Jacques Lacan; linguistic analysis as it pertains to the etiology of illness; theories
on human behavior; how the study of such pathological conditions as aphasia and hysteria led to
the development of such concepts as the “organ of the soul” and the “apparatus of the soul”; the
relationship between dreams, memory, and amnesia; and psychological defense mechanisms [14].
(2) Inquiry in the clinical humanities (readings in illness and ethnography). The focus of this
theme is ethnographic writings on illness, including how writing can be used to reflect on illness; the
position of illness in culture; the relationship between bodily experience and caregiving; and the
relationship between the experience of being ill, illness narratives, and psychological healing [15]. In
addition, this theme covers how bodily experience, metaphors for illness, and writing on illness are
culturally mediated, leading the ethnographer to see certain phenomena, but not others [16]. Finally,
the interdisciplinary approach of the clinical humanities is used to inquire into the future direction of
the nursing humanities [2,12].
(3) Western philosophy and humanistic care. This theme includes inquiry into such
Aristotelian ideas as beauty, goodness, love, and freedom; key concepts in existential philosophy,
such as Kant’s ideas on free will, Nietzsche’s “will to power”, Kierkegaard’s ideas on existentialism,
and neo-Aristotelian thought. Also covered are Hannah Arendt’s ideas on movement and thought;
responsibility and judgment; the relationship between conscience and freedom; and the meaning of
action, laboring, and making—all of which have a bearing on how value judgments apply to the
nursing profession. This theme also covers how Heidegger’s concepts of sein and dasein relate to
Confucian, Daoist, and Buddhist thought, with respect to ethics and the difficulties which arise in
clinical settings. Finally, considerable emphasis is placed on the ethics and duties of caregiving.
(4) Art and humanistic care. This theme covers the theories on aesthetics of such Western
philosophers as Descartes, Kant, and Heidegger; the intersubjective relationship between the artist
and his or her art; and the influence artistic creation has on caregiving. In addition, based on personal
experience in community building and organizing spaces for public art, the lecturer discusses how a
space is laid out influences artistic activity and our relationship with objects. Also covered in this
theme are how the characteristic features of traditional Chinese gardens and temples reflect the
designer’s views on nature and space, and the practical implications this has for humanistic care.
(5) Humanistic care in the helping professions. In this theme the perspective of Western
aesthetics is adopted to show how the helping professions can be seen as an art form, and how the
caregiver can be seen as an artist rather than an instrument. From the perspective of aesthetics, the
interpersonal experience which arises in the context of caregiving can be understood as the medium
for creating art. Furthermore, the site of caregiving can be seen as a humanities space full of symbolic
meaning, the changes in which the caregiver needs to respond to in an appropriate manner so as to
make caregiving an aesthetic experience.
In order to increase the quality of the Nursing and the Clinical Humanities module, the instructors
have adopted a flexible and exploratory approach to the course content and how they present it. Thus
36
the emphasis is not so much on the various concepts and theories in different areas of the humanities,
as on how the learning experience can raise meaningful questions and lead to a loosening of certain
rigid and entrenched views and practices in the nursing profession. Indeed, such an experimental
course opens up a discursive space conducive to free inquiry, self-inquiry, and taking a fresh look at
the key issues in the nursing profession.
For example, one of the central ethical concepts of the nursing humanities is what Emmanuel
Lévinas calls the attitude of “for others”. Caregiving consists of not merely practical care, but also
requires providing emotional and spiritual support. In the course of providing practical care for
patients, many of whom may have difficulty accepting their condition, a nurse is constantly confronted
with the grim realities of birth, aging, illness, and death, and may thus find it difficult to maintain
a positive and supportive attitude. Physical suffering is an inescapable fact of life. Thus, despite our
best intentions, we don’t have the ability to “become others”; the best we can do is adopt the attitude
of “for others” [17–19].
Yang ([17], p. 12) also points out:
Whereas Lévinas starts from the ethical viewpoint of “responsibility” to describe the
subject of suffering, Pierre Klossowski [20] starts from the ethical viewpoint of “volition”
in an attempt to describe the possibility of another type of subjective existence. For
Klossowski, responsibility leaps over will; that is to say that our ethical relationship
with others is not merely taking an attitude of “for others”, but also entails actively
aspiring to “become others”. In other words, if in the present moment I forget that I am
taking care of another person, in that moment I am having the kind of experience
Nietzsche spoke of as deliberately blurring the boundary between self and other. But what
sort of self-image did Nietzsche have in mind? And who is this person who will appear
someday [21]. For this reason, Lévinas takes Nietzsche’s “vision” and “prévision” as
referring to the appearance of someone whose arrival we have been looking forward to.
In sum, in the process of caring for patients, by fully identifying with the patient and entering into
the patient’s experience, and then applying the attitude which arises therefrom to the process of
providing practical caregiving, a nurse can engage in what Klossowski and Nietzsche call “life as the
application of art” and “practicing beauty” ([17], p. 13). At the same time, we need to ask just what
this type of approach to nursing care signifies in terms of the nurse’s perception of the patient. This is
a key issue and needs to be addressed from the perspective of phenomenology. Due to limitations of
space and the need to remain focused on the main topic of this paper, this subject will have to be
taken up in a future paper.
Based on the feedback provided in a focus-group discussion, the students in the Nursing
Humanities course derived the following benefits: (a) They learned that the basic approach of the
nursing humanities is to cultivate self-understanding and then extend this into the lifeworld of the
patient; (b) They gained an understanding of the perspectives, concepts, central values, and practices
in the humanities; (c) They learned how the perspective of the humanities can bring about innovation
in the nursing profession; (d) They learned how to internalize and apply the humanities perspective
to education and clinical work in nursing; (e) They gained an increase in self-awareness and
37
maturity; (f) They learned that neglecting to take the patient’s mental state into account makes
caregiving more difficult and less effective; (g) They learned how interaction with colleagues can
turn nursing work into an aesthetic experience, and also increase one’s understanding of and appreciation
for the value of nursing; and (h) They came to appreciate the value of innovative nursing techniques
and integrating the humanities into nursing [12].
5. Nursing Revisited
Putting the spirit of healing into actual practice in nursing education requires inquiry into the
clinical significance of nursing and healing. As for course design, this needs to be carried out with
sensitivity to the needs of the human spirit. The Nursing and the Clinical Humanities module
described above presents the perspectives of various disciplines in the humanities and social
sciences, and how they can be applied to such issues as caregiving, ethics, and health. Making use of
fieldwork and discussion, as well as the central ideas and research methods used in the humanities
and social sciences, we can see how each discipline has its own vision of care and compassion, and
how these can be skillfully applied to nursing. This approach also generates new ways of understanding
the clinical humanities, health, and healing. This module also emphasizes making use of the students’
clinical experience to probe into the meaning of nursing and healing, so as to generate practical
insight into the nursing humanities and elucidate how this cutting-edge discipline can contribute to
the future development of the nursing field.
From the standpoint of the philosophy of science Mu, ([12], pp. 9–10) states:
As for epistemology, in nursing knowledge develops out of clinical experience and the
actual process of caring for patients. How to understand the patient’s life experience
and current condition, and then apply this understanding to the caregiving process and
the development of new measures and techniques—this is the long-term vision of the
nursing humanities. This is a developmental process based on discussion, review, and
refinement of the close relationship which exists between the humanities and nursing.
In this process of interdisciplinary interaction and refinement, the ongoing task is to
adapt the knowledge and concepts of the humanities and apply them to the creation of
an innovative and patient-centered approach to nursing.
In this manifesto-like summary, Mu aptly elucidates the essential meaning of both the clinical
humanities and the nursing humanities. Yet, if we understand the clinical and nursing humanities as
requiring an extraordinary degree of character development, and see extensive knowledge of the
humanities as a prerequisite for adopting this approach, we would be setting our sights unrealistically
high. For, in light of the actual working conditions which currently prevail in the nursing
field—overworked nurses who have little authority in the medical hierarchy—we have to avoid
having unrealistic expectations of what nurses can and should do.
For example, in addition to primary prevention, the most effective way to reduce the overall cost
of medical care is to effectively bring volunteer caregivers (those who have an “ethical connection”
with the patient, i.e., family, friends, neighbors, volunteers, etc.) into all levels of the caregiving process.
Moreover, as medical ethics becomes increasingly focused on the wellbeing of the patient, more
38
attention is being given to the healing relationship itself. Thus, making nursing care more
person-centered and indigenized gives the patient a sense of not only being cured, but also being
“cared for” [22].
Concretely speaking, in “ethical nursing care”, affective awareness and empathy are used to quell
chaotic thought patterns. The emphasis is on a clear understanding of ethics and ethical relations. As
for methodology, “ethical nursing care” relies on the patient’s personal life experience to generate
self-awareness. The nurse is not so much a guide, as a provider of moral support, creating an open
space conducive to the unfolding of the patient’s inner world [3,22].
In the words of [23] Shen (2010):
At the heart of the clinical humanities is a thorough rethinking of the body-mind
discourse. In psychoanalysis the body and mind are seen as an inseparable unity, and
only with this recognition can we see the great significance the humanities has for clinical
practice... The clinical humanities gives primary importance to re-opening the discussion
of the body-mind issue and is premised on re-examining their interrelationship… In the
psychoanalytic view, illness involves not only physical pain, but also entails linguistic,
social, and cultural suffering. This implies that the humanities can help us deepen our
understanding of the healing relationship and the metaphors for pain, and can also serve
as an important and direct therapeutic tool.
Thus the aim of this paper is to use the perspective of the clinical humanities to examine various
facets of the nursing humanities. In sum, the nursing humanities is an extension of the practicality
of humanism, confirmed and implemented through “questioning, subversion, and reform” [24]. As
Szymborska ([25]) puts it, “Any knowledge that doesn't lead to new questions quickly dies out:
it fails to maintain the temperature required for sustaining life.”
In regards to nursing education, Tsai ([26], p. 5) has pointed out that “The heart of nursing is
knowing how to care for others. This type of knowledge is different than that of science. The latter is
guided by results, while the former is guided by ethics.” In my view, the Western approach to nursing
based on empirical science and the approach of the nursing humanities based on ethical and cultural
considerations are complementary rather than antagonistic. Professional nursing education needs to
include both perspectives. In the current situation, this means making a place in nursing education for
alternative medicine and the clinical humanities.
6. Conclusions
The encounter between nursing and the clinical humanities might be seen as the unlikely meeting
of fundamentally different and incompatible fields. Indeed, the humanities and social sciences may
seem quite alien to nursing and clinical practice. In the words of Yee [27]:
In the professional life of the nurse, the unknown is of utmost importance. On the one
hand, it challenges the nurse to transcend his or her inherent self-limitations; on the
other hand, it provides him or her with a point of entry into self-inquiry. But even
though introspection requires transcending these inherent limitations, they can also be
made the object of inquiry and introspection. This entails using the unknown as a
39
medium for bringing these inherent limitations into relief, thereby clearly revealing
their problematic nature, which in turn becomes the object of further inquiry.
Going a step further, we can examine the relationship between nursing and the clinical humanities
by referring to Arendt’s ideas on action, thinking, responsibility, and judgment [28]. In the words of
Wang ([29], p. 1):
Thinking is invisible, but judgment is visible. Genuine thinking is life itself; it’s an
essential element of life. For Arendt, inasmuch as life is a process, it consists not of the
results of thought, but of the process of thought. Yet, thoughts can become manifest by
being expressed through judgment; thus judgment is the concrete expression of thought.
Therefore, the reality of a thought is necessarily founded on judgment… Judgment means
making a choice about something in the future; it doesn’t mean merely making an
appraisal of something that has already happened. Judgment is a part of conscience.
Indeed, conscience and the innate sense of right and wrong lead to the question of moral
responsibility. In this connection Tsai ([30], p. 13) states, “Arendt interprets morality from the
perspectives of self-examination (especially self-dialogue) and the manifestation of one’s innate
sense of right and wrong.” As for Arendt’s conception of legal responsibility, Tsai ([30], p. 13) states,
“Moral responsibility doesn’t involve an individual’s transgressions or criminal activity towards others;
rather, it’s a matter of personal integrity and consistency, including the purity of one’s motivations.”
Of particular relevance to the clinical humanities are the paired concepts of action-thinking and
responsibility-judgment. In particular, when using the concepts and spirit of the humanities to reflect
upon nursing practice and education, it’s worth looking closely at how these two pairs of concepts
can be edifying for nurses and caregivers. Wang ([29], p. 2) asserts:
If we understand the humanities to be about people, since thinking is an essential
element of human life, then thinking and the clinical humanities are inseparably related.
If we understand the humanities to be about mind or spirit, since thinking is the core of
mental and spiritual life, then this also manifests the relationship between thinking and
the clinical humanities.
The nurse-patient relationship is a type of intersubjective healing relationship, an opportunity for
transformation which links up the intrinsic process of being and becoming for nurse and patient
alike. Genuine healing takes place in the process of self-transformation, an inner process which
manifests outwardly. As participant, companion, and catalyst, the nurse plays an essential role in the
healing process.
Arendt astutely points out a universal crisis in the modern world resulting from the loss of our
ability to understand and reconstruct the experiential freedom, authority, and political engagement
we once had. The atrophy of this key ability reaches its climax in extreme dehumanization and
objectification ([31], pp. 301–02).
Inasmuch as judgment is the concrete expression of thinking, the actuality of nursing and the
clinical humanities has to be established in judgment. Remaining constantly vigilant as to the
possible problems that may arise in the nursing profession in the future, as well as cultivating
40
practical foresight, are both part of putting the clinical humanities into practice. Healing is a process
in which the healing relationship facilitates an expansion of the patient’s awareness and energy,
thereby bringing about wholeness, balance, and transformation. Further, healing is a process in
which the cultivation of human affinity and sensibility engenders a sense of rest, relief, and ease in
body, mind, and spirit. The healing moment occurs in the intersubjective process, and entails a
transformation of one’s psychological state and mental activity, which in turn brings a sense of comfort,
renewed interpersonal activity, and renewed order and harmony in one’s engagement with society.
Gao ([31], p. 313) asserts that in Arendt’s view:
A self completely outside the network of interpersonal relationships can’t possibly
exist. In The Human Condition [32] she states that an individual has various roles to
play, and in the course of living and acting in the world, meaning and interpersonal
understanding are generated solely through dialogue with others and with oneself.
Thus, with respect to the fortuitous encounter between the clinical humanities and education in the
nursing humanities, putting theory into actual practice will be the primary challenge of all those
working in this emerging discipline in the future.
Encounter, always manifesting with a certain apprehension.
Departing, so as to arrive at some exceedingly distant place.
A place bound by memory…
Conflicts of Interest
References
1. Wislawa Szymborska. “Could Have.” In View with a Grain of Sand: Selected Poems.
Translated by Stanislaw Baranczak and Clare Cavanagh. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1995,
pp. 65–66.
2. Der-heuy Yee, An-bang Yu, and Wei-lun Lee. “An Exploration of the Clinical Humanities.”
Monthly Review of Philosophy and Culture 37 (2010): 63–84. (In Chinese)
3. An-bang Yu, and Der-heuy Yee. “Compassion in Action: Cultural Counseling as an Indigenized
Application of the Clinical Humanities.” Philosophical Practice 7 (2012): 1105–20.
4. Richard M. Zaner. “Preface.” In Voices and Visions: Clinical Listening, Narrative Writing.
Taipei: Cheng-Chi University Press, 2008, pp. xxxi–xliii. (In Chinese)
5. Jow-jiun Gong. “The Hermeneutic Phenomenology of Illness: From the Hermeneutics of
Illness to the Ethical Ground of the Physician-patient Relationship.” Journal of
Life-and-Death Studies 1 (2005): 97–129. (In Chinese)
6. Arthur Kleinman. What Really Matters: Living a Moral Life amidst Uncertainty and Danger.
New York: Oxford University Press, 2006.
7. Wei-lun Lee. “Psychotherapy as a Locale for Ethical Care: Reaching into Situated
Negativity.” Schutzian Research: A Yearbook of Lifeworldly Phenomenology and Qualitative
Social Science 1 (2009): 67–83. (In Chinese)
41
28. Hannah Arendt. Responsibility and Judgment. New York: Random House, 2003.
29. Wen-shang Wang. (Department of Philosophy, National Cheng-Chi University, Taipei,
Taiwan). “Action and Thinking in the Clinical Humanities.” Unpublished manuscript, 2012.
30. Ying-wen Tsai. A Hannah Arendt Reader. Taipei: Rive Gauche, 2008. (In Chinese)
31. Yan Gao. “Discussion on Arendt’s Phenomenological Humanism.” In Phenomenological and
Philosophical Research in China. Edited by Ni Liangkang. Shanghai: Yiwen Publishing, 2012,
volume 12, pp. 301–15. (In Chinese)
32. Hannah Arendt. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958.
43
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Bergonzi, M.; Fiorentino, F.; Fiormonte, D.; Fortini, L.;
Fracassa, U.; Lucantoni, M.; Marraffa, M.; Numerico, T. The New Humanities Project—Reports
from Interdisciplinarity. Humanities 2014, 3, 415–441.
1. Introduction
“All the so-called visual media turn out, on closer inspection, to involve the other senses
(especially touch and hearing). All media are, from the standpoint of sensory modality, ‘mixed media’.
The obviousness of this raises two questions: (1) why do we persist in talking about some media as if
they were exclusively visual? Is this just a shorthand for talking about visual predominance? […] (2)
Why does it matter what we call ‘visual media’? Why should we care about straightening out this
confusion? What is at stake?” [1].
This passage is taken from W. J. T. Mitchell’s essay There Are No Visual Media, important not
only in terms of media theory, but also because the reasoning at work here can be applied to the order
44
of savoirs too. The practices of knowledge are always trans-disciplinary in the sense that they
involve contexts, methods, and instruments institutionally assigned to different disciplines. Academic
disciplines, in the last thirty or forty years, have been changing their self-representation, showing less
cohesion and a tendency to move from the notions of “discipline” and “canon” to practices based on
collaboration around problems, i.e., “in clusters that may be too short-lived to be institutionalized
into departments or programs or to be given lasting disciplinary labels” ([2], p. 819).
In dealing with what appears to be obvious, and increasingly so, certain questions keep
coming up, and we should welcome them: why do we continue to conceal this obviousness? Why
do we persist in speaking of clear-cut disciplines, albeit indirectly (while actually yearning for
interdisciplinary practices)?
The same aspect applies to, and especially so, the well-known distinction between the so-called
two cultures, between humanities and sciences (a dichotomy that later degenerated into biased
expressions such as “soft and hard sciences”, etc.). It is a distinction that became institutionalized
in the late 19th century with the creation of two orders of knowledge to maintain a clear separation.
One of the intellectual figures behind this operation was Wilhelm Dilthey. Distinguishing between
Naturwissenschaften, i.e., the natural sciences and Geisteswissenschaften, the science of the spirit or
humanistic sciences, he established an essential difference between two objects and two methods that
in fact have nothing, which is clearly distinguishable [3].
Dilthey sees the object of humanistic sciences—man and his historical-social environment—as
basically defined by its historicity and their knowledge modality by a hermeneutic process of
comprehension, a Verstehen, i.e., a process of construction of sense and significance in which
subjectivity is allowed to participate. Comprehension takes place via an active projection of one’s
own experience and leads to a restructuring of the Self. The other, the extraneous, is understood (in
the sense of Latin cum-prehendere, “to seize”), i.e., inserted and made to act in its own space and time.
The natural sciences are just the opposite. Here, we do not have construction, just the discovery of
a given reality, the natural, and its laws. Their mode of knowledge is an Erklären, an explanation of
that which, in nature, is given and has only to be clarified. Natural phenomena are explained when
they reflect a general law, understood as eternally valid. This is the ideal of an objective knowledge,
which would like to abstract from subjectivity and temporality, which postulates a neutrality of the
subject of knowledge as well as an immutability of the object. It is the attempt to create a territory
of knowledge detached from temporality and subjectivity, and freed of the struggles of hermeneutic
understanding as to legitimate only an interpretation, which presents itself as a scientifically
given reality.
This “fiction” started tottering some time ago. For some time we have known that hermeneutics
cannot be confined to the examination of cultural phenomena, that even the data we retrieve from
nature imply an interpretation, that no object can be freed of temporality and the localized nature of
knowledge, no examination can be considered irrespective of the analysis of subjects of knowledge
and the conditions of its production, representation, circulation, and reception. That no perspective is
exempt from the hermeneutic circle, that every piece of data, everything, every observation is always
linked to a pre-comprehension. This is also true—Dilthey had already said this—for the natural sciences
too. Though not embracing necessarily a post-modern vision, it would appear difficult to release data
45
from their interpretation. It is just this—and not just today—that humanistic knowledge insists upon
recalling. And it is just for this reason that it is in crisis and under attack [4], deprived of its legitimacy
precisely because it endangers this old distinction, which holds its critical capacity in check. Thus,
the distinction between scientific and humanistic knowledge still remains active; it is still to be
deconstructed via cognitive practices, which draw the most radical consequences from the wavering
of this distinction.
New Humanities is an international research project, which has been created to work in this
direction. Thus, not a reflection upon the crisis or sense of regret about an asset legitimized by the
powers of the past, but a new research model and, as a result, an educational one—a new epistemic
for a new paideia. And the construction of this new cultural code cannot be considered irrespective
of the establishment of new relations not only between areas of knowledge but between the people
and the different cultures of the planet. There is nothing here about new ideas. Though in the West
we have preferred to ignore them, there have always existed educational experiments, which have
tried to draw the best from different traditions. In the last century the Nobel prize winner Rabindranath
Tagore founded Visva-Bharati [5] (Visva means “union”, and Bharat is India), a new concept of
university founded on certain key principles, among which the equal dignity of cultures and religions
in the world, interdisciplinarity and the idea that teacher and student decide together the time and
pace of their education [6].
We mention this institution (Nobel prize winner Amartya Sen was among his pupils) because our
project originated with the collaboration of a group of researchers, teachers, and students of Roma
Tre who wished to interpret the “crisis” of the humanities like a phase of regeneration and passage
towards a new form of human science which should: (1) acknowledge the interconnections between
disciplines and actively recognize that “scientific practices are modeled through notions such as
networks, assemblages, experimental systems, trading zones, and so on” ([2], p. 819); (2) take up
once more the dialogue between sciences of nature and those of culture which had slackened and was
then interrupted from the 17th century on, so as to go beyond their distinction; (3) absorb analytically
and systematically the epistemic leap imposed by the digital transformation of data, knowledge and
identities in a heated analytical dialogue with those technologies which have re-defined research and
representation methodologies in all fields. We are aware that in setting up this agenda we were not
alone but had illustrious predecessors. However, a detailed discussion on the epistemological and
historical aspects of interdisciplinarity was well beyond the scope of this paper. It is worth remembering
that interdisciplinary work has encountered historically a number of practical and theoretical obstacles:
from epistemic barriers (involving “incompatible styles of thought, research traditions, techniques,
and language that are difficult to translate across disciplinary domains” ([7], p. 47) to evaluation
criteria and tenure anxiety, from the lower academic status of interdisciplinary journals to institutional,
administrative and departmental drawbacks, etc.
New Humanities has tried to bypass some of these problems by organizing clusters around
specific research themes from which we selected the present five reports. We hope the differences in
style, length, and content of these reports will be justified by the heterogeneity of the case studies and
the events from which they originated. In the last two years the research group has organized about
fifteen seminars, meetings, conferences, and book presentations on seven clusters in which the
46
research was originally structured. Physics and sociology, biology and philosophy, mathematics and
literary criticism, computer science and history of art, are some of the areas, which have engaged in
dialogue and have been reshuffled, exploring unexpected connections or rediscovering old relations.
That does not necessarily mean that the knowledge and approaches presented are completely new or
revolutionary [8]; indeed some aspects under discussion in the essay are well established in their
disciplinary contexts. The sequence of the five reports does not follow the original chronological
order, but it lays down a research path which we think has a main theme, that of rethinking
the relation and dialogue between body and mind, between perception and consciousness. In the
background we find the question of the digital transformation of knowledge and cultural and
cognitive representations, a common ground for all the contributions. We hope our selection will
demonstrate that these challenges cannot be met by single discipline alone.
Clusters edited by Ugo Fracassa and Teresa Numerico are dedicated respectively to the problem
of vision and that of memory, both involving a background of algorithms and digital representations.
Following this, we have the cluster edited by Laura Fortini on the questions, which the digital raises
about bodies and the signs which represent them, and the text on narrative identity authored by
Massimo Marraffa. The last assemblage, edited by Domenico Fiormonte, Michele Lucantoni, and
Mauro Bergonzi, is the longest and probably the most challenging, as authors tried to set up a
dialogue between distant fields in the attempt to build a cross-cultural perspective on consciousness.
We are convinced that this brief core sampling in the activity of New Humanities presents
trans-disciplinary transfers and reflections that reveal, ever more fully, the transience of the confines
between nature and culture, natural sciences and humanities, producing a decentralization of the
single disciplines. Knowledge no longer appears fragmented in distinct and separate territories, but
transforms into a large inter-connective network, which constantly repositions its nodes. The challenge
today is to imagine new models to connect cognitive horizons and production modalities of knowledge,
which are with increasingly more insistence, breaking the boundaries of the single disciplines in which
they have been confined. According to the Ancient Indian wisdom (not “philosophy” in the Western
sense), “innovating means to expand our consciousness of what reality is and has never ceased to
be” ([9], p. 18). This is an interesting “extracting”, not-accumulative idea of progress (expanding
consciousness, not accumulating books or building monuments, etc.) that may help us also to think
about scholarship, and science in general, in a new way.
The seminar “Protocols of Vision”, organized at the University of Roma Tre on 15 March 2013,
dealt with questions concerning the cognitive nature of sensorial perception and the different forms
of consciousness—empirical, artistic, scientific—which might be the outcome. In particular, thanks
to the contributions of three scholars, Michele Rucci (Boston University), Lucia Foglia (McGill
University), and Ugo Fracassa (Roma Tre), from different disciplines (computer science, philosophy
and literary theory) the idea that there exists a simple “seeing” is challenged. The three approaches
converge ultimately upon the case study provided by the famous portrait The Afghan Girl by the
American photographer Steve McCurry for the “National Geographic” in 1984. To consider the
47
and on the other, what we “can” actually see relative to the non-visual information that interferes
with and modulates sensory information processing.
In 1986, Carlo Ginzburg recalled in a well-known essay, that the eye “is more sensitive to the
(perhaps marginal) differences between human beings than those between rocks and leaves” ([10],
p. 123): for those wondering about mental, emotional, and cultural interferences in vision, the
photographic portrait of Sharbat Gula, now a planetary icon of alterity at the end of the last
century ([11], p. 3) might now be worthy of an in-depth study. Once more in the news, with the
recent Italian exhibitions (in Perugia, Rome, and Genoa) the famous picture by the American
photographer encourages reflection about the influence on the act of seeing of culturally acquired
mental factors—including a certain post-colonial and gender deformation [12]—and raises specific
questions about the burden of these factors on the formation of each specific perception. Gula was
photographed again seventeen years after the first photograph and her life (and body) had changed
entirely. She was identified thanks to the Iris Scan (an algorithm patented by John Daugman,
professor of Computer Vision at Cambridge [13]), a practice that denies the most common and
typically human practice of recognition. Finally, in a similar perceptive adventure, the esthetic
vision of the portrait intervenes, an experience thanks to which it seems we can re-read the entire
Afghan Girl affair as a symptom of a true “western prosopagnosia” [14].
In this section we summarize the seminar that took place at Roma Tre on 13 May 2013 and
coordinated by Laura Fortini. The participants were Silvia Contarini, professor and co-director of
the Department of Italian Studies at the University of Paris Ouest Nanterre La Defense, Tiziana
Terranova, associate professor of Sociology of Communication at the University of Naples
“L’Orientale”, and Teresa Numerico, philosopher of science of the research group New Humanities.
In the 1970s a feminist literary criticism appeared which spent a long period of time, discussing
sessuazione [15] of language in literary texts, getting involved in particular with gender connotations
of the sign. In a memorable meeting, which took place in Urbino in 1983 [16], Nancy Huston, Patrizia
Magli, Rosi Braidotti Susan Rubin Suleiman, Nancy Miller, and others discussed the possibility of
positioning sexual difference within the system of signification. In later years in Italy the discussion
continued, with, among others, Patriza Violi’s study concerning the relation between language and
sexual difference [17]. However, from the 1990s on, the increasingly elaborate presence of writing
on line seems to have concealed sessuazione of the body in the literary text, if not in the form itself
of semiotic construction. The arrival of gender and queer studies too, has led to serious doubts about
the nature/nurture binomial, analyzed by Donna Haraway [18] and Judith Butler [19], among others.
In Italy, feminist literary criticism has not become part of the academic and cultural mainstream,
despite the clear crisis in Italian literary criticism, which is by now encountering, at least as far
as traditional assumptions are concerned, obvious difficulties in determination. What exactly is
critical activity today and how should it be defined? Even though the object of critical practice
changes each time—the literary text for example—what does not seem to change is the status of
criticism and thus its epistemological crisis.
49
and futuristic representation of possible emancipation from a tiring maternal role, as in the case of
the futurist Rosa Rosà (1918) [29]. On the other, the reality of a complex relation with machines,
like in Lo spazio bianco by Valeria Parrella [30], a novel dedicated to a premature birth and the
complex relation a mother mantains with the incubator bringing her daughter up.
Looking at the results of the seminar as a whole, we could say that the digital dimension
challenges bodies and signs with an intense post-human potential [31]. If the digital defines itself
as the place where texts do not have body, either textual or material, and bodies themselves seem
to lose certain connotations, literature, online or on paper, seems to maintain the capacity for
naming—of use in an attempt at defining uncertain, but also interesting, shifts in the confines of
our present. Forerunners in questions relative to the human and the post-human are writers like
Clarice Lispector and her excellent story The Passion according to GH (1964) [32], which has
meant so much in the sphere of feminist thought because of its reflections on links with the animal
world [33–35]. Or a text like L’iguana by Anna Maria Ortese (1965) [36], which investigates the
obscure and uncertain confines with something seemingly as unlike man as can be imagined, i.e.,
an iguana. Which means that, basically, paraphrasing Gertrude Stein, a sign is a sign is a sign, whose
corporeal articulation—gendered, human, post-human online or on paper—is an active, unavoidable
component of this present time.
This contribution summarizes the work of the seminar “Memory: mathematics, computer
science, literature”, held on 20 November 2013 at the University of Roma Tre. Participants were
Giuseppe Longo (Centre national de la recherche scientifique-Paris) Francesco Fiorentino (Roma
Tre), and the coordinator Teresa Numerico. The idea behind the meeting was an examination of the
practices of memory in different disciplines, in the knowledge that it is the way the “data” are
organized that affects what the outcomes of the cognitive process will be [38]. Furthermore, the
representation of memory and its role in consciousness affects the perception of the historicity of
scientific practices, as well as the variability of possible outcomes. Therefore, this section will
reflect upon the practices and policies of construction of sense through memory, in different disciplines
and in relation to the uses of conservation mediums and the transmission of consciousness.
In order to address memory from this broad and complex perspective, we involved scholars from
different fields, such as philosophy, literary theory, biology, computer science, theory of perception,
history, etc. Of course each of these areas contributed to the discourse with its research agenda and
theoretical views, and our aim could not be to merge or reduce them to a common denominator.
Perhaps the only justification for this experimental approach was that we all know that memory, as a
fundamental element for the construction of consciousness and for the reproduction of the living
being, can be many different things. It has different meanings, places, mediums, practices. So the
techniques used to study the ways it manifests itself and acts in different spheres of knowledge are
different but so too are the political uses we make of it. Therefore, it is crucial to elaborate a critical
analysis of the interdependencies between external memory and subjective memory, archiving tools
and techniques of the construction of the self, with a multiplicity of contexts and the discovery
of invariances.
51
According to Giuseppe Longo [39,40] memory is constitutive of mathematics too, which can
be defined as the science, which deals with the invariance of structures and establishes which
transformations preserve it. Memory, as an essential part of anticipation, constitutes the maintenance
of invariance of action. Anticipation extracts the invariant character of memory from a changing
context with the aim of preserving the possibility of next action. Such a contextual meaning
establishes the conceptual constructions of mathematics not in isolation with respect to other forms
of consciousness but by attributing to the first a maximum practical and historical stability. The
recognition of the invariance of mathematical structures in the fluidity of processes has therefore a
mythopoeic nature. That is to say, mathematics can be associated with the myth in that it too is
capable of bringing together the fact of being in this world (physical) and the capacity for human
communication. The construction of invariances however requires the use of a particular type
of memory.
The mathematical invariance exists only as an intentional construction. In this sense a perfect
memory as a digital database cannot construct any invariant characteristics. The productive capacity
of recall is the present reactivation of mnestic content, which Edelman [41] describes as a situation in
which “the brain repositions itself in a living state” in the act of remembering [40]. The machine,
with its perfect “memory” can, at most, help to engage in proof-checking but in no sense does it work
on the activation of original demonstrations. Only animal memory and human deliberative capacity
have the chance to construct proof which can demand the introduction of new concepts and structures
which transcend the use of rules in a formal system. The only indispensable assumption to obtain
interesting, creative responses is the active capacity to invent the present and construct connections
between the structures of human memory [42,43].
Longo thus shows how memory is the basis of the construction of invariance in mathematics.
In this perspective, even an abstract science like mathematics has a clearly historical consistency
since knowledge is constructed via the intentional, creative, and deliberative acts of a community.
Such are mnemonic acts too.
Therefore, we cannot avoid getting to grips with the reorganization of memory produced by the
new use of this term in the sphere of the digital revolution. Human memory is multi-faceted and
multiform [44] and cannot be compared to digital memory. However, it is clear that the use of the
same term to indicate two very distinct concepts has had an influence on the redefinition of the
so-called “family similarities” which contribute to the construction of rules for the use of the term. So
it seems also useful to reflect on the genealogical effects produced by the use of this term in the
digital machines field and the role of a linguistic habit on the semantic transformations of the initial
term [45].
Personal memory is associative and reconstructive, imaginary, constantly active and dynamic.
Totally unlike the rigidity of electronic memory, which conserves every bit in an exact, inscrutable
mapping. The concept of memory in the two devices has a clearly different significance. Human memory
seems difficult to control, precisely because it is impenetrable, indeterminate, and at the same time
extremely fragile. As Wendy Chun suggests, “the memory of the machine is at the same time incredibly
precise and absolutely unstable from a technical point of view” ([46], p. 140). The opposite of human
memory, extremely solid and tirelessly deceiving. In short, the differences could not be bigger, but
52
we are by now used to considering digital memory as the best replacement of human memories. The
desire to stabilize the hardware leads the project to construct digital memory, metaphorically, so that
it can contain and reproduce that which it contains ([46], p. 139). The political idea behind the digital
is the stabilization of the datum, the petrification of memory in data, which are represented as
objective, neutral, elementary. “Raw data is an oxymoron” says the title of an interesting collection
of essays [47] in which the fictional nature of the raw datum is stressed.
“Facebook’s job is to improve how the world communicates”, says Zuckerberg. Projects like
Wikipedia or Google Books aim at restoring human knowledge conserved in books (Google Books),
and in the heads of the experts (Wikipedia). Google Scholar sets out to organize scientific knowledge
and make it universally accessible, and the scope of Google is “to organize the world’s information
and make it universally accessible and useful” [48].
In all these money-making projects, as in other public ones [49] it is possible to see the myth of
exhaustiveness of knowledge and the archiving of information as a “total experience”. But archives
always exist as partial and violent institutions and the present constitutes itself in opposition to these,
as Derrida sustains in Archive Fever: “The archive takes place at the place of originary and structural
breakdown of the said memory. There is no archive without a place of consignation, without a
technique of repetition, and without a certain exteriority. No archive without outside” ([50], p. 11).
It is therefore impossible to replace the function of recall and the reconstruction of the past in
memory with that of archiving without losing the function itself of archiving. Without memory,
without an outside, even the archive declines and above all loses its exteriority form, from which it
should be able to escape, which gives sense and at the same time can be transformed and recomposed
into an ever newer sense.
If libraries, archives, repositories of scientific articles, personal diaries and descriptions of
collective adventures are all consigned and imprisoned in a cloud of data (never mind if open or
closed), how do we subvert the archive and construct the history of society and knowledge? The
Cloud, a shared space but also private, where collectively we save our contents, is a perfect example
of the collapse of memory, archive and that set of rules which interpret the information, giving
them a sense.
As if the theme of archiving policy did not exist, as if we might exteriorize the support and conserve
intact the practices of reminiscence, strengthening them efficiently without transforming them.
If the operation of sorting out data becomes the interpretation tout court of sense, if no datum is
able to escape the extraction of meaning activated by the algorithm thought up for the machine, then
the crucial political question is: how can we activate the dynamics of transformations in interpretation?
No human interpreter can compete with the “interpretative” potential of the machine and no operation
of extraction of meaning of data can ever be critically checked [51]. Google Glass is another example
of the transformative perspective of memory and consequently of knowledge adopted by web
companies. The promise (or the illusion) of a new form of perception, a new form of vision that
will allow the “glasses” to see what the user sees, and to offer an interpretation or support for an
understanding of the actual vision. The offer of a unique, coherent, effective interpretation of data by
a proprietary and opaque device could change irreversibly the way we interpret and understand our
present and anticipate our future. The risk of the device however is not just to fall short of user
53
expectations—after all a minor problem. The real risk is that Google Glass will alter our perception
and understanding of the idea of the interpretation of the world around us, even when it fails. In fact,
the more it fails the more its influence can alter the human idea of understanding and interpreting
signs, events, and objects around us.
But history and criticism originate with the polysemic dynamics and variability of concepts and
texts, like the variability of genes which allow us a selection and conservation of the species, together
with the variability of environments and reactions to them, which allows the epigenesis of those
traits, which are more suitable for survival [20]. It is memory in its creativity and variability, which
guarantees the process of history. Memory is saved only if it erases, only if it extracts its own
pathway to sense from the sea of data in which it navigates. Human memory is very selective: it is
capable of preserving and organizing memories, by forgetting.
If the archive is universal and the answers to every question are univocal, if there is no distance
between private memory and public archive, if all we know we find in the same tested sources which
distil overall shared knowledge, then the dream of variability and multiplicity at the heart of the
hypertextuality becomes only an illusory myth and the net is lost in the delirium of omnipotence of
algorithms of ranking and sorting out of data, the fruit of machine-learning techniques.
And yet, when memory becomes public practice it is always political, even though in managing
the construction of objectivity there are now complex devices made up of the interaction between
human beings and machines of which we lose awareness in a game of cross-references and reflections
which never seem to have an end. In this assemblage—as visible as it is opaque—personal and
collective traces are activated in the comings and goings of cross-references, which transform our
relation with ourselves and with our machines for memory.
The question still awaiting a response concerns the possibility of effective action of empowerment
produced by extroflection and then collectivization of memory. No mediatic device is ever neutral
with respect to the organization and the content itself, which is traversed by them. Once more, this is
a remediation [52], but what is alive and what is dead after the migration is accomplished.
The mediums determine and organize memory and its practices, the collective and even more so
the personal. Each dominant medium with its codes imposes itself as a metaphor of memory. The
ever-present danger is that a medium might restrain and regiment memory as imaginative capacity,
which constructs knowledge about the past, necessary for the present. The danger is already to be
seen in Plato’s Phaedrus, which opposed memory understood as storehouse of data and memory as
process of reminiscence, which is always creative [53]. Plato warned that external memories could
work as deactivators of the capacity for anamnesis. This is a reminiscence, which is accomplished
through the activity of a subject interacting with another subject in a maieutic process.
It is not by chance that Plato formulated his critique of writing in a written text, mobilized the
inter-textual vocation of literary writing against the fixity of the textual support to transform it into
a stimulus, to the extent that it draws the reader towards a memory which is outside it, in the
interaction—implicit or explicit—with other texts.
However, this implies a writing practice which awakens the awareness of its limits to make
possible the anamnesis of what is inaccessible for the writing medium itself, its code, its possibility
of representation.
54
Every medium has a potentially critical attitude and is capable of subverting the uses it is put to,
the practices it is implied in. And yet the medium is never neutral. The uses of a medium are not free:
they are determined, envisaged, directed by the technical structure of the medium itself. However,
they are not fixed. There is a negotiation with the medium’s technical possibilities. The medium
becomes transcendible when the experience of its mediality is produced, i.e., the limits which it
imposes on the representation and that which it excludes. The experience of mediality is always
experience of what is not graspable by the medium and by its code and this is why it does not become
part of memory handed down. But every medium has within itself the potentiality of letting us know
at least the lack of what it can no longer hold on to.
Today, this possibility seems more than ever threatened by digital media, which, in the exhibition
of an ever-present, accessible totality, obscure every absence. Everything is consigned, also in the
sense of immobilized, imprisoned in the registers of conservation and retransmitted as raw data. The
capacity to forget and select the information to which we wish to attribute sense, is nullified. And yet
the transience of the support constitutes a serious risk for the duration of this total conservation.
Therefore, more than ever we need to activate critical practices, which reveal the hidden gaps like
the outside of the archive, necessary so that memory can construct vital variation. It is necessary to
preserve the creative original action of the memory as a faculty of the imagination and the present,
which, albeit in the sphere of regulated procedures and precise bonds, does not remain subordinate to
the presumed neutrality and objectivity of the datum codified in the devices of conservation and
transmission of consciousness.
In conclusion, the work of this cluster aimed at singling out, critically, the practices of obfuscation
of memory policies in action in the use of certain devices and discovering how to escape from their
totalizing nature. The objective is still to preserve the historical, temporal, and contingent nature of
cognitive choices so as to protect their reversibility and variability. To this end, it would seem crucial
to recognize memory as a selective faculty which acts in the present, erasing more than it conserves,
maintaining the awareness of the ever-more precarious, unstable value of its outcomes.
The aim of the research cluster “Narrative Identity: Nature, Ontogeny, and Psychopathology”
was to critically re-examine the main concepts and theories concerning the nature, ontogeny, and
pathologies of the construct of narrative identity, and in such a way, to provide researchers from
different areas with a forum for exploring this many-sided subject. What follows is a theoretical
and empirical framework within which the interdisciplinary team of speakers, Gianluca Barbieri
(University of Parma), Erica Cosentino (University of Calabria), Francesco Ferretti (University of
Roma Tre), Pietro Perconti (University of Messina), Dolores Rollo (University of Parma), investigated
these issues during a seminar we organized at the University of Roma Tre in December 2012. This
framework consisted of a developmental story about how self-consciousness, conceived of as a
cognitively demanding form of consciousness (“narrative identity”), emerges by drawing on literatures
in cognitive sciences, dynamic psychology, text linguistics, and the philosophy of mind.
The ordinary term “consciousness” conflates two quite different kinds of psychological
functions. First, consciousness is a state of vigilance, i.e., the agent’s being actively present to the
55
world: this is a matter of forming first-order representations of states of affairs, which may function
to guide the agent’s behavior. Second, consciousness is self-consciousness, i.e., the agent’s being
present to herself: this is a matter of being in a higher-order mental state, namely a representational
state that has a first-order representation as its object. Studies in cognitive ethology and developmental
psychology seem to show that animals and infants under one year of age are conscious in the
first-order sense of being conscious: they are able to automatically and pre-reflexively form a series
of representations of states of affairs and operational plans of action, and hence to interact with
persons and things in a flexible but not self-conscious manner.
Only some species take a step beyond the basic interactive monitoring of the environment that
characterizes the simple, primary consciousness of all animals. They attain self-consciousness, and
this in at least two different senses.
Great apes like chimpanzees, and in our species infants from 15–18 months of age, can be said
to reach a state in which they are able to make a clear distinction between their own physical
bodies and the surrounding environment. More precisely, they first become capable of physical
self-monitoring, i.e., focusing attention on the material agent as the physical executor of actions;
and then their bodily self-monitoring comes to completion as the objectification of their own
bodies (Merleau-Ponty’s corps propre), and thus as a full-fledged bodily self-awareness [54].
In its simplest form, then, the description of the self is a description of physical identity.
At an early stage the bodily self-consciousness is likely to be structured by a non-verbal and
analogic representation of the (physical) self; but very soon it begins to be mediated by the verbal
exchange with the caregiver. In other words, in our species the “chimpanzee-style”, purely bodily
self-consciousness is almost immediately outstripped and encompassed by a form of descriptive
self-consciousness that is strictly linked to linguistic tools and social cognition mechanisms. Here
begins the process leading to self-consciousness as introspective recognition of the presence of the
virtual inner space of the mind, separated from the other two primary experiential spaces (corporeal
and extracorporeal). This is the foundation of human consciousness in the Lockean sense of the
term: self-consciousness as personal identity.
This psychological and introspective self-description is likely to take shape in the act of
turning on oneself the capacity to mind-read other people; and this is likely to occur around the age
of 3–4 years and in an interpersonal context, viz. in a relationship with the caregiver that is made of
words, descriptions, designations, evaluations of the person. Through the dialogue with the caregiver
(and then with other social partners) the 3–4 year child constructs itself by constructing its own
identity, both objective (for others) and subjective (for itself). And following G. H. Mead’s well-known
lesson, we are able to say that the identity-for-itself largely derives from the identity-for-others; viz.
we see ourselves, and define ourselves, in the first place introjecting the way in which others see
and define us [55].
This transition from a bodily and social identity to an introspective one is not an all-or-nothing
issue: it gradually takes place in an interplay of mind-reading [56] and linguistic-narrative capacities
modulated by socio-cultural variables [57,58]. The child who at 3–4 years of age turns his third
person mind-reading capacities upon himself under the influence of caregivers’ mind-related talk,
at around 4–5 years of age begins to grasp his subjective identity as rationalized in terms of
56
autobiography. This is “narrative identity”, i.e., a cognitive structure that can provide the jumble of
autobiographical memories “with some semblance of unity, purpose, and meaning” ([59], p. 527).
Research findings show that the complexity and coherence of this structure increase during adolescence
until early adulthood [60]. This raises the question of what kind of narrativism is involved here [61].
In this process of narrative self-construction there is an essential psychodynamic ingredient.
Dynamic psychology and developmental psychology tell us that affective growth and the construction
of identity cannot be separated; the description of the self that from 2–3 years of age the child
feverishly pursues is an “accepting description”, i.e., a description that is indissolubly cognitive (as
definition of self) and emotional-affective (as acceptance of self). In brief, the child needs a clear
and consistent capacity to describe itself, fully legitimized by the caregiver and socially valid. On
the other hand, this will continue to be the case during the entire cycle of life: the construction of
an affective life will always be intimately connected to the construction of a well-defined and
interpersonally valid identity [62].
We believe the main result of the research cluster, which is continuing to develop its ideas, was
to highlight the need for a synthesis of different perspectives on self-consciousness as narrative
self. In the current debate the theme of self-consciousness tends to be approached with a limited
focus; and hence the different facets of self-consciousness (its non-conceptual versus higher-level
forms, or its inter-subjective and temporal aspects) remain relatively isolated [63]. We, at the Rome
seminar, made an effort to make up for this thematic isolation and achieve a more integrated view,
putting together perspectives that are usually kept separate. So the contributions were informed by
philosophy of mind, cognitive sciences, text linguistics, but were also receptive to some aspects of
psychoanalysis in an attempt to get the most out of the psychodynamic notion of a defense mechanism.
We are presenting here a summary of the main contributions to the seminar which took place at
Roma Tre on the 18 September 2103 with the participation of Emilio Del Gudice, quantum phycisist
(Istituto di Fotonica e Nanotecnologie—Milan), Massimo Marraffa (Roma Tre), philosopher of
science and historian of psychology, Mauro Bergonzi (University of Naples, “L’Orientale”), historian
of Indian religions and philosophies, and Michele Lucantoni (Roma Tre), philosopher of biology.
Unlike the other reports in this collection, the complex nature of the topic did not allow us to write
an individual summary. The objective of the seminar was to initiate a dialogue, not to construct a
consistent discourse which would necessarily have brought about an improper amalgamation of
ideas and disciplines which are significantly different, as well as distant, over time and space. The
intention behind the project was to examine the idea of consciousness, which emerges from a number
of Emilio del Giudice’s writings. This idea was then associated with the model of consciousness
elaborated by the quantum phycisist Amit Goswami (see Michele Lucantoni’s conclusions) who
explores in detail the links between quantum mechanics and ancient Indian sapiential thought,
especially the advaita-vedānta school (one of the six darshanas or theoretical-interpretative systems
which derive from the Veda, considered “orthodox” by Hinduism). The two physicists start off
differently, but come to the same deep ontology: a unique universal consciousness. We have
57
decided to connect Goswami and Del Giudice by involving Mauro Bergonzi, a scholar of the
Vedanta philosophical tradition, in order to explore the connections between Quantum Physics and
the Non-dualist Indian Thought [65].
So, where does consciousness reside? What does that which Francis Crick defined “the last
great mystery of science” consist of [66]? And above all who will have the last word about that
personal experience which seems to contain the whole universe? The basic assumption, shared by
all the participants, is that since any appeal to quantitative criteria would inevitably fail, a plurality
of voices might be the only plausible, desirable way to approach the “truth” concerning consciousness.
In this exploration we will discover that the thousand-year old path, which unites the two parallel
quantum edges is the non-dualist sapiential thought conserved in the vedic Upaniṣads. These
ancient Indian spiritual, philosophical, and mystical writings seem to have foreseen, at the dawn of
every gnosiology, the most profound aspects of the relation between consciousness and reality.
6.1. Quantum Field Theory and the Physics of Living Matter: A Hypothesis on Physical Phenomena
Let’s start with a metaphor about the development of science in recent millennia. The metaphor
consists of a comparison between this development and that of a child when someone gives him a
toy. Science is the child and the toy is nature. At the beginning the child plays by following the
instructions, then if he is smart enough, the child wants to know what it is like inside and breaks it.
Once the toy has been smashed into hundreds of pieces, most of the time the child stays there looking
at it. There is also the chance that the child will try to re-assemble it, giving him a toy, which is like
the other one because it is made up of the same pieces. So there are three phases of approaching the
toy, which correspond exactly to the three stages of science. At the beginning, human beings looked
around nature and began to make catalogues, a list of all that exists—a gigantic challenge. It is
necessary to establish correlations empirically, which is hardly a simple task. For example, the stroke
of genius in understanding how babies are born: establish a correlation between a sexual act taking
place one day and the birth of a baby nine months later is by no means a trivial matter—it means
following a long distance concatenation of cause and effect.
The first stage in science is by no means a simple one and in fact it has taken millennia—just
think of the time spent grasping the irregularities of all celestial motion. This phase lasted, at least
in the western world, up to the Renaissance. After the Renaissance, another approach took shape,
which consisted of chopping nature up into tiny pieces. Clearly, nature dismantled is no longer
nature: dismantling nature is an act of death, you kill the living being to see what’s inside—death
as an essential part of life. We discovered that the living being is made up of cells, which are in
turn made up of nucleus and cytoplasm. Then molecules arrived, atoms, protons and electrons, then
quarks—no longer to be broken down—in an organism formed as a “matrioshka”. We now find
ourselves on the threshold of the third phase, which involves recomposing it all and seeing how it
holds together.
Quantum mechanics was born exactly 113 years ago. What is the difference between quantum
physics and classical physics? How did we come to recognize that classical physics was not enough
to explain certain phenomena? The criterion consists of taking the reasoning behind previous
physics to extreme consequences. This is why theoretical physics is important: with rigorous logic
58
we can derive all the consequences of principles. When we enter a blind alley we are forced to
begin a conceptual revolution. Quantum mechanics thus originates with a logical crisis in classical
physics. We see that it is wrong to consider bodies as inert and separate, that they can receive energy
only, exclusively, from the interaction with other bodies. Therefore we have a spontaneous fluctuation
of all bodies in connection with their interaction with the vacuum and since the vacuum is everywhere,
this is an interaction we cannot avoid. Thus, if this is the case, it means we cannot make use of an
isolated body, the principle, which is behind the conceptualization of classical physics.
Nobody can any longer be isolated because thanks to its fluctuations in the vacuum it is
constantly communicating with other bodies, there is always an interaction. For almost a century,
this result—which is a revolution in thinking—has gone unobserved and has been hidden behind
the idea of the existence of paradoxes, interpretations, which attributed to the observer and his
interaction, the reason behind the spontaneous fluctuability of bodies. The observer, perturbing: the
atom is small, the observer is large, the latter cannot do otherwise—he perturbs. However, macroscopic
quantum systems like superconductors have been discovered. I might have a superconductor cable
a hundred miles long and the size ratios invert (the observer becomes microscopic). Thus, we do
not have interaction with the observer, but rather an interaction with the vacuum in which the
body is exposed to the fluctuations of all the other bodies of the universe. We are approaching
our conclusion.
To sum up, from a formal point of view, the results of quantum mechanics we should recall
Bell’s theorem: he was a physicist who posited in terms of formal logic the outcomes of quantum
mechanics. He maintains: “The following set of three statements is logically incompatible, so one
of the three just has to go: (1) physical reality is described by quantum mechanics; (2) physical
reality is susceptible to an objective description—in that it is independent of the observer; (3) physical
reality is describable as a set of localized events in space and time. These three statements cannot,
all three, stay together” [67].
Einstein, who is one of the fathers of quantum mechanics and predicted the connections
formalized by Bell, was of course a brilliant scientist but he did not go that far ahead. For Einstein,
reality had to be objective and at the same time localizable [68]. He was ironic about the fact that
if, in order to understand an object it is also necessary to know what is happening in the constellation
Andromeda, then science is over. Science becomes possible only when it can localize objects: he
was solidly bound to objectivity. His statement implied the falsity of quantum mechanics, which
becomes only an approximation to reality, while awaiting a truer theory.
So Einstein’s party, which remains a minority, brings down the first of the three statements.
Niels Bohr and the entire Copenhagen school, which dominated 20th century physics, brings down
the second statement concerning objectivity. He argued that since quantum mechanics is true and
remains a problem of localizability, one would say that objects, even before they are localized,
produce these incredible fluctuations which lead to indeterminism [69]. Suppose I have a boat and I
do not want to admit the relation with far-off maritime motions, I can declare that sometimes the
boat itself produces rash movements. This is a form of blindness because it takes account of
apparent objectivity but does not go very far. It is David Bohm who drops the third statement. And
he argued that it is not true that we can conceive of reality as a set of separate objects [70]. This is
59
the most important point. Given the fluctuation of every body, the body produces an electromagnetic
potential, which travels afar and connects the other bodies. The fluctuation of a body is immediately
communicated to other bodies, which produce a sort of collective dance. Naturally the extent of
these oscillations can vary in size so that the experimental consequences can also be small, because
they are covered by environmental factors, which is why at times classical physics, especially when
it works at high temperatures, clearly represents reality without appealing to quantum mechanics
because the fluctuations produced by the thermal agitation impact are large enough to cover
micro-fluctuation. If, however, one works at low temperatures, these micro-fluctuations re-emerge
and are observable—the reason why quantum mechanics was discovered at low temperatures.
Once we understand the mechanism, we can make the following concluding statement. It is
possible that the different fluctuations of the different bodies reach harmonization, so that a collective
movement is created which magnifies the fluctuation as a whole. Just suppose I have a group of
singers, each one produces a whisper in phase (i.e., mutually synchronized) one with the other: in
the end a huge concert emerges. The important thing is to put one’s own fluctuations into phase.
Here, energy is of little importance. Energy exits as a final result. What is important is the
rhythm, the phase, which does not have an energetic content. If the elements in a system are in
phase, this can work with infinitesimal energy consumption. This is the principle difference between
computer and brain. The computer is made of objects, which are not in phase so that every element
of the computer, to do something, has to spend energy. However, if we used the game of spontaneous
fluctuations—which cost nothing because they are produced naturally—and we managed to pilot
them so as to produce a symphony in phase, what would emerge would be music and not the usual
noise of discordance. This is what really happens. We have seen that liquid water naturally emits a
sound, which has the structure of a musical score. This is the physical basis, which allows us to
understand how the matter, at a certain degree of development, produces a psyche. What is a psyche
if not a logos? And what is a logos if not a set of harmonized fluctuations which produce meaning?
Indian non-dualism and some of the philosophical implications of Quantum Physics discussed in
this cluster seem to share the view that reality is an indivisible whole, while the perception of
separate entities is just a mental construct without any cogent ontological foundation (including the
idea of an individual “ego” dwelling “within” a single body/mind).
On the other hand, consciousness as such (not to be confused with its incidental “contents”, like
perceptions, sensations or thoughts) is a basic principle which cannot be consistently explained as the
end result of any physical or mental cause, since no “explanation” or “cause” could appear without
consciousness already being there as a precondition. So consciousness is an irreducible reality prior
to any perception, sensation or thought. Its evidence is doubtless, for at any time anybody can verify
with absolute certainty (through one’s own direct experience) that he/she exists and is aware.
Therefore, since all phenomena can be perceived, known or explained if and only if consciousness
is already there, it is impossible to regard consciousness as the end product of any other phenomenon
without bumping into an epistemological paradox.
60
Moreover, according to non-dualism, “consciousness” and “world” are just two different descriptions
of one and the same indivisible reality (respectively in terms of the “first” or of the “third” person),
while the alleged separation between “subject” and “object” is nothing but an illusory mental construct.
This stance could encourage new perspectives in the current philosophical debate engendered by the
amazing discoveries in the fields of Quantum Physics and Cognitive Sciences.
The Sanskrit word advaita means “non-dualism” and points to the simple fact that in reality
separation does not exist: there are differences, endless differences, but no actual separation. If the
universe is a consistent totality, how does the perception of separate entities arise?
In perception, through names and concepts, we organize sense data in patterns that we recognize
as separate objects (houses, cars, trees, and so forth). According to philosophers like Kant and
Wittgenstein, empirical data are mainly constructed by way of conceptual thought and language.
Benjamin Lee Whorf pointed out how the grammatical structure of our mother tongue radically
influences the act of perception itself: through the naming process we arbitrarily engender an illusory
segmentation of the unified universe into a world of apparently separate entities [71]. On the basis of
this view, every experience is an interpretation of bare sense data through language, so that we
cannot perceive what we have not a word for. Moreover, all that is perceived through different names
appears as a fragmented set of discrete entities.
In Indian thought, the ancient precursor of this constructivist perspective was the concept of
nāma-rūpa. Nāma means “name” and rūpa means “perceptible form”. They are joined together in
one compound word just to emphasize that we can only perceive a form through a name. No name,
no form; many names, many forms. So our perception of a multiplicity of separate entities comes
from language, as stated in the Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upaniṣad.
Later on, Śaṅkara and advaita-vedānta maintained that the illusory perception of multiplicity
arises by superimposing concepts (stocked in memory) on “what is” now, in such a way that the
indivisible Whole appears as a mass of discrete entities limited by their names. Superimposition
(adhyāsa) and limitation (upādhi) through names and concepts are the origin of māyā’s illusion.
Therefore, through language our thought assigns specific names to various aspects of this huge,
indivisible process called “universe”, giving rise to the perception of many different forms. Each
word is like a “frame” that traces a conventional as well as arbitrary edge around some aspects of the
Whole, differentiating an “inside” as opposed to an “outside” and thus creating the illusion that a
specific form is independent and separate from all other forms identified by different names. Moreover,
names are static, incapable of capturing actual movement, just like photography, which is obliged,
for example, to show a man running by means of many different photos of men frozen in motion.
Thus, after creating an illusory multiplicity of fixed and separate entities through language,
we mistake this inadequate description of reality for reality itself, whereas the universe is just one
formless process, which appears as an amazing expanse of different, but not separate aspects.
In Indian non-dualist inquiry into our true identity (ātmavicāra or ātmavidyā), the core question
is: “Who am I?” The response can already be found in the early vedic Upaniṣads, where our true self
(ātman) is conceived as an impersonal and boundless awareness that coincides with the totality of
being (brahman). Subject and object cannot be separated, as they are both emerging from one and the
same source: being-awareness.
61
By inquiring into the foundation of individual identity, through a meticulous work of reduction of
appearances, at the bottom of our immediate and direct experience we find (as both Śaṅkara and
Cartesio remark) the undeniable and certain evidence of our being and awareness (sat-cit). Without
firstly existing and being aware, we can neither perceive nor assert anything. Dualistic perception
forces an illusory gap between objects and consciousness that is deceptively considered an individual
attribute. However, according to the non-dualist perspective, both the individual ego (identified
with a single body-mind complex) and the so-called “external” objects are only different (but not
separate) contents of one and the same universal consciousness, which encompasses all existence.
No content can be perceived if primarily awareness is not there: any object appears always in, to, and
as consciousness.
In Western philosophical tradition, the Reverend Berkeley [72] had already remarked that,
according to the evidence of our direct experience, anything concerning external reality is primarily
an object of perception appearing in and as consciousness. Therefore, it is impossible to prove the
existence of a world apart from consciousness, given the inseparable and unavoidable coexistence
of both: in fact, since they always appear together, they are not two separate entities, but rather two
different aspects of the same reality.
So the boundary between subject and object is not real: the terms “consciousness” and “world”
refer only to two different perspectives (in first or third person) describing one, indivisible reality,
just as “ascent” and “descent” are two different words for the same slope, depending which way one
is going.
For example, one single experience can be named either as “hearing” (if described in terms of the
subject who hears something), or as “sound” (if described in terms of the object heard). However, in the
actual experience of hearing, one cannot establish a precise boundary where sound ends “out there”
and hearing begins “in here”: in fact, there is just one, immediate experience and only later on, in order
to describe it, the thinking mind says “I heard a sound”, creating a deceptive subject/object duality.
Indian non-dualism can offer a critical contribution to the current mainstream of contemporary
neurosciences that regards the origin of consciousness as a side-effect emerging from a certain
degree of organization of a material device like the brain (wet-ware).
Firstly, due to the lack of philosophical accuracy, neuroscientists often confuse “consciousness”
with the “contents of consciousness”, the objects of consciousness (thoughts, images, perceptions,
memories) that can be observed and studied experimentally—as linked, it is true, to the functions of
the brain—with the very fact of being conscious (consciousness as such), which cannot be observed
as an object by science, since it is the source itself of any observation.
Secondly, the stance of a cause/effect relation between brain and consciousness presumes
a hierarchical causal order ranging from biological matter to consciousness: y (consciousness)
depends on x (the brain) in order to exist. But how can we assert the pre-eminence of the brain over
consciousness if it is only via the consciousness that it becomes possible to perceive and know the
brain? To what extent should we regard as “scientific” a theory asserting that y depends on x when it
is also true that x depends on y, unless we acknowledge that both of them are only two sides of the
same coin?
62
Goswami provides science and philosophy with a new way of conceiving the puzzle of
consciousness. His proposal scourges the invisible confines of the imagination without renouncing to
the support of a measured scientific argument, to which he entrusts the force of his intuitions and
faith in universal consciousness. We use the word “faith” because Goswami seems little inclined to
respect the cornerstone of the experimental implementation proper to western science. In fact, the
way in which this revolutionary architecture of reality is presented to us provides subjectivity with a
role transcending our personality (our ego?) as to embrace that infinite coexistence of consciousness
in which the singularity embodied in individuals acts as synolon.
The monopoly of studies concerning consciousness is held by the neurosciences and the sciences
of artificial cognition [66–77]. Leaving aside for now the latter, the peak that an erudite neuroscience
can reach is a correlation between the neuronal activities and the phenomenology of experience in
the first person [78].
In the most trivial versions of the discipline, the problem of the correlation does not even present
itself since consciousness is perceived as an unwelcome guest: evolutionary tinsel qualified as
epiphenomenon—an appendix stripped of causal power—which emerges mysteriously from the
work patterns of the brain [79]. We are convinced that every epiphenomenalism is nourished by
an enigmatic paradoxality: as we fear that reality is not reflected and resolved by the system of
63
knowledge pleaded by a certain physics (as to save the certainty of a manageable universe), we
appeal to the last stage of magic art which is epiphenomenalism.
The magic is in accepting that a phenomenon (consciousness/immaterial)—without a clear
definition of “phenomenon” in physics—supervenes [80] to another phenomenon (biological activity
of the brain/material) without causal prosecution or retroaction. How can a causal chain of corporeal
happenings culminate in an event, which violates the fabric of causal relations and connections
inscribed in space-time? Here we see the paradox reasserted and unveiled. To avoid asserting directly
the insufficiency of a physicalist vision, we appeal to an obvious metaphysics, which undermines the
principles of the physicalism itself! Goswami is shrewd in grasping that a vision of the world crushed
against a raw and naïve materialism ends up generating sclerotic and indirectly obscurantist
propositions, incapable of explaining the phenomena it pretends to observe. According to quantum
mechanics there are six dogmas, which mark scientific thought and which impede a clear vision of
things [81]:
1. Causal determinism
2. The continuity of events
3. The locality of all objects
4. Clear objectivity
5. Monism and materialistic reductionism
6. Epiphenomenalism
The fact that consciousness remains tangled up in the net of these six assumptions is clear,
indisputable: where is consciousness supposed to be? If I observed my brain caught up in listening to
Miles Davis, I wouldn’t find trumpets flooding the imagination, but strips of neurons busy with
a continuous release of electro-chemicals. In this case we do not have objects of thought to be
measured and positioned in the space-temporal plot. This last observation interposes itself on the
path to consciousness like a threshold to cross. Beyond this threshold an unknown universe is waiting
to be discovered and understood. Amit Goswami builds a bridge between the old and the new: the
quantum principle of non-locality [81] seems a compulsory stage in sparking off a revolution, the
protagonist being the inseparable unity of consciousness and material, both resting upon the fullness
of the vacuum.
Our question is if we will ever be ready to embrace a reality so solidly dependent on the human
presence; a reality where the abode of daily routine will be definitively assigned to the marvelous
lands of the spirit.
7. Conclusions
The aim of this work was to initiate a dialogue between disconnected areas of knowledge because
of the persistent disciplinary fragmentation inherited by educational and research institutions based
on the model established in 19th century Europe [82]. Of course this attempt, for obvious reasons,
can only be partial and epistemologically incomplete. However, we should at least trying to remedy
the damage produced by this separation on our university system and at the same time seek out for a
new model. And if a third way exists, it will be inevitably be founded on a “virtuous incompleteness”
64
of all epistemological models. The task of the New Humanities researcher will be to transform the
isolation of competences into a stable alliance for opening new scenarios.
The present contribution has only begun the work in this direction. Placing studies like “Protocols
of Vision” side by side with spiritual and scientific exploration like “Contribution of Quantum
Physics to the Idea of Consciousness”, or intersect the naturalistic scenarios of “Narrative Identity:
Nature, Ontogeny and Psychopathology” with the radically different perspectives like those proposed
by “Signs and Bodies Between Digital and Gendering”, has been a healthy critical exercise for
challenging and deconstructing the old disciplinary boundaries. We think that insisting on this
work of synthesis is the only way to avoid regression to a sort of unwary society, unable to express,
transmit and criticize the complex and interconnected structure of today’s knowledge and culture.
Acknowledgments
We dedicate this work to the memory of Emilio Del Giudice, brilliant scientist and friend, who
died prematurely on the 31 January 2014. In the words of his fellow scientist Mae-Wan Ho, he was
considered by many the “Prometheus of the New Science”, a “gentle intellectual giant [who] will be
immortalized in our collective memory and in the memory of generations to come” [83]. Without his
challenging ideas and intellectual generosity, the New Humanities project would never have existed.
We are also very grateful to Antonella De Ninno for her accurate review of the transcription of
Emilio’s original conference. Translation and revision of the article is by Colin Swift.
Author Contributions
Domenico Fiormonte is first author and was responsible for editing and revising all the
contributions. Francesco Fiorentino and Domenico Fiormonte authored the “Introduction”; Ugo
Fracassa edited the Section 2 “Seeing, Knowing, Recognizing: Protocols of Vision in Science, Art
and Life”; Teresa Numerico and Francesco Fiorentino authored the Section 3 “Memory Construction:
Invariants, Variability and Media”; Massimo Marraffa wrote the Section 4 “Narrative Identity:
Nature, Ontogeny and Psychopathology”; Laura Fortini authored the Section 5 “Signs and Bodies
Between Digital and Gendering”; Domenico Fiormonte and Michele Lucantoni edited the Section 6
“The Contribution of Quantum Physics to the Idea of Consciousness: a Culturally In-Between
Hypothesis” (except for Section 6.2 which was authored by Mauro Bergonzi).
Conflicts of Interest
1. William John Thomas Mitchell. “There Are No Visual Media.” Avaliable online:
http://www.mediaarthistory.org/refresh/Programmatic%20key%20texts/pdfs/mitchell.pdf#pag
e=1&zoom=auto,0,798 (accessed on 25 July 2014).
65
2. Mario Biagioli. “Postdisciplinary Liaisons: Science Studies and the Humanities.” Critical Inquiry
35 (2009): 816–33.
3. Wilhelm Dilthey. Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften (1910–
1926). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981. (In German)
4. For an overview of the “humanities crisis” see the first part of the article by Paul Keen in the
volume I of this issue of Humanities: Paul Keen. “Imagining What We Know: The Humanities
in a Utilitarian Age.” Humanities 3 (2014): 73–87. Among the books, conferences and
initiatives devoted worldwide to the crisis of the humanistic disciplines and institutions, we
would like to mention the 4Humanities project, a web resource and community created by an
international group of “digital humanities scholars and educators to assist in advocacy for the
humanities”. See Available online: http://4humanities.org (accessed on 26 July 2014).
5. Visva Bharati. Avaliable online: http://www.visvabharati.ac.in (accessed on 25 July 2014).
6. “The Western Universities give their students an opportunity to learn what all the European
peoples have contributed to their Western culture. Thus the intellectual mind of the West has
been luminously revealed to the world. What is needed to complete this illumination is for the
East to collect its own scattered lamps and offer them to the enlightenment of the world. (…)
The Western universities have not yet truly recognized that fullness of expression is fullness of
life. And a large part of man can never find its expression in the mere language of words. It must
therefore seek for its other languages,—lines and colors, sounds and movements. Through
our mastery of these we not only make our whole nature articulate, but also understand man in
all his attempts to reveal his innermost being in every age and clime.” Rabindranath Tagore.
“An Eastern University.” In Creative Unity. New York: Macmillan, 1922. Avaliable online:
http://bichitra.jdvu.ac.in/search/english_search.php (accessed on 25 July 2014).
7. Jerry A. Jacobs, and Scott Frickel. “Interdisciplinarity: A Critical Assessment.” Annual Review
of Sociology 35 (2009): 43–65.
8. For an overview on interdisciplinary studies, see Robert Frodeman, Julie Thompson Klein,
and Carl Mitcham, eds. Oxford Handbook of Interdisciplinarity. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2010. Useful resources are also: Joe Moran. Interdisciplinarity, 2nd ed. London and
New York: Routledge, 2010; Maria Karanika-Murray, and Rolf Wiesemes. Exploring Avenues
to Interdisciplinary Research: From Cross-to Multi-to Interdisciplinarity. Nottingham:
Nottingham University Press, 2009; Julie Thompson Klein. Crossing Boundaries: Knowledge,
Disciplinarities, and Interdisciplinarities. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1996.
Although not directly linked to our idea, we would also like to mention a project that shares
similar objectives: the online conferences project Interdisciplines. Avaliable online:
http://www.interdisciplines.org (accessed 26 July 2014).
9. Raffaele Torella. Il pensiero dell’India. Roma: Carocci, 2011.
10. Carlo Ginzburg. Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method. Translated by John Tedeschi and
Anne C. Tedeschi. Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press, 1992.
11. Wendy S. Hesford, and Wendy Kozol. Just Advocacy?: Women’s Human Rights, Transnational
Feminism, and Politics of Representation. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 2005.
66
31. Rosi Braidotti. The Post-Human. Cambridge and Malden: Polity Press, 2013. Il postumano: La
vita oltre l’individuo, oltre la specie, oltre la morte. Traduzione italiana di Angela Balzano,
Roma: DeriveApprodi, 2014. (In Italian)
32. Clarice Lispector. A Paixao Segundo G.H., Edição Critica. Coord. Benedito Nunes. Sao Paolo:
CNPq, 1988. La passione secondo G.H. Italian Translation by Adelina Aletti, with a note by
Angelo Morino. Torino: La Rosa, 1982; Milano: Feltrinelli, 1991. (In Italian)
33. Luisa Muraro. “Commento alla ‘Passione secondo G. H.’” Dwfdonnawomanfemme 5 (1988):
65–78. (In Italian)
34. Hélène Cixous. L’heure de Clarice Lispector. Paris: Des Femmes, 1989 (In French)
35. Donna J. Haraway. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2008.
36. Anna Maria Ortese. L’iguana. Firenze: Vallecchi, 1965; Milano: Adelphi, 1986. (In Italian)
37. This section is edited by Teresa Numerico and Francesco Fiorentino.
38. Geoffrey C. Bowker. Memory Practices in the Sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005.
39. Giuseppe Longo. “Memoria e costruzione del senso in matematica.” New Humanities,
20 November 2013. Available online: http://www.newhumanities.org/seminars
/20-novembre-memoria-matematica-informatica-letteratura/ (accessed on 25 July 2014) (In Italian)
40. Giuseppe Longo. “Synthetic Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Sciences.” Speculations,
2014, in Print.
41. Gerald Edelman. The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness. New York:
Basic Books, 1990.
42. Giuseppe Longo. “Incompletezza.” In La Matematica. Torino: Einaudi, 2010, volume 4,
pp. 219–62. (In Italian)
43. Giuseppe Longo. “Reflections on (Concrete) Incompleteness.” Philosophia Mathematica 19
(2011): 255–80.
44. Erich R. Kandel. In Search for Memory. The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. New York:
W.W. Norton & Company, 2006.
45. Teresa Numerico. “For a Genealogy of Digital Memory.” Available online: http://www.
newhumanities.org/seminars/20-novembre-memoria-matematica-informatica-letteratura/
(accessed on 26 July 2014). (In Italian)
46. Wendy H.K. Chun. Programmed Visions: Software and Memory. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2011.
47. Lisa Gitelman. “Raw Data” Is an Oxymoron. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2013.
48. Google mission. Available online: http://www.google.com/about/company/ (accessed on
25 July 2014).
49. For example Linked Open Data by Tim Berners-Lee. Available online: http://linkeddata.org
(accessed on 25 July 2014).
50. Jacques Derrida. Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1998.
51. According to Bowker and Star a system of organization of information which is neutral does not
exists. Every choice is the dynamic mirror of the interaction of the forces of power. Geoffrey C.
Bowker, and Susan L. Star. Sorting Things Out. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2000.
68
52. Jay D. Bolter, and Richard Grusin. Remediation: Understanding New Media. Cambridge:
MIT Press, 2000.
53. Francesco Fiorentino. “Scrittura memoria letteratura.” Available online: http://www.new
humanities.org/seminars/20-novembre-memoria-matematica-informatica-letteratura/ (accessed
on 26 July 2014). (In Italian)
54. Giovanni Jervis. “The Unconscious.” In Cartographies of the Mind. Edited by Massimo
Marraffa, Mario De Caro and Francesco Ferretti. Berlin: Springer, 2007, pp. 147–58.
55. George Herbert Mead. Mind, Self, and Society. Edited by Charles W. Morris. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1934.
56. Theory of Mind is the branch of cognitive science that investigates how we ascribe mental states
to other persons and how we use the states to explain and predict the actions of those other
persons. More accurately, it is the branch that investigates “mindreading” or mentalizing or
mentalistic abilities. These skills are shared by almost all human beings beyond early childhood.
They are used to treat other agents as the bearers of unobservable psychological states and
processes, and to anticipate and explain the agents’ behavior in terms of such states and
processes. These mentalistic abilities are also called “folk psychology” by philosophers, and
“naïve psychology” and “intuitive psychology” by cognitive scientists (see M. Marraffa.
“Theory of Mind.” The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2011. Available online:
http://www.iep.utm.edu/theomind (accessed on 26 July 2014)).
57. Dolores Rollo, and Francesca Buttiglieri. “Mother and infant talk about mental states: Systemic
emergence of psychological lexicon and theory of mind understanding.” In Processes of
Emergence of Systems and Systemic Properties: Towards A General Theory of Emergence.
Edited by Ganfranco Minati, Mario Abram and Eliano Pessa. Singapore: World Scientific,
2009, pp. 777–86.
58. Francesco Ferretti, and Erica Cosentino. “Time, Language and Flexibility of Mind: The Role of
Mental Time Travel in Linguistic Comprehension and Production.” Philosophical Psychology
26 (2013): 24–46.
59. Dan P. McAdams, and Brad D. Olson. “Personality development: Continuity and change over
the life course.” Annual Review of Psychology 61 (2010): 517–42.
60. Robyn Fivush. “The Development of Autobiographical Memory.” Annual Review of Psychology
62 (2011): 559–82.
61. Pietro Perconti. “I limiti delle storie su se stessi.” In Prima e terza persona: Forme dell’identità
e declinazioni del conoscere. Edited by Fabrizio Desideri and Paolo Francesco Pieri. Bergamo:
Moretti & Vitali, 2013, pp. 45–56. (In Italian)
62. Gian Luca Barbieri. Tra testo e inconscio. Strategie della parola nella costruzione dell’identità.
Milano: Franco Angeli, 2007. (In Italian)
63. Katja Crone, Kristina Musholt, and Andrea Strasser. “Introduction: Towards an integrated
theory of self-consciousness.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 84 (2012): V–XVI.
64. This cluster is edited by Domenico Fiormonte and Michele Lucantoni. Mauro Bergonzi is
author of Section 6.2. We have summarized the original contribution of the late Emilio Del
Giudice who should be considered co-author of Section 6.1.
69
65. For reasons of space we have decided to leave Massimo Maraffa’s contribution out of this
section. However, we would like to thank him for his essential contribution that allowed us to
include in our original discussion the perspective on consciousness of western cognitive sciences.
66. Christof Koch. The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. Englewood:
Roberts and Co. Publisher, 2004.
67. John Stewart Bell. “On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox.” Physics 1 (1964): 195–200.
68. Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky, and Nathan Rosen. “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of
Physical Reality be Considered Complete?” Physical Review 47 (1935): 777–80.
69. Niels Bohr. “Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete?”
Physical Review 48 (1935): 696–702.
70. David Bohm. Quantum Theory. New York: Prentice Hall, 1951.
71. Benjamin Lee Whorf. Language, Thought and Reality. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1956.
72. George Berkeley. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. 1710. University
of Oregon: Renascence Editions, 1999.
73. Nisargadatta Mahārāj. I Am That. Bombay: Chetana, 1973.
74. Max Planck. “Das Wesen der Materie”. Speech held in Florence, Italy, 1944. Archiv zur
Geschichte der Max-Planck-Gesellschaft, Abt. Va, Rep. 11 Planck, Nr. 1797, München,
Germany, 1944. (In German)
75. Erwin Schrödinger. What Is Life? with Mind and Matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1974.
76. George Spencer Brown. Laws of Form. New York: The Julian Press, 1972.
77. Gerald Edelman. Second Nature: Brain Science and Human Knowledge. New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2006.
78. Juan Francisco Varela. “Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard
Problem.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (1996): 330–49.
79. Daniel Dennett. Consciousness Explained. New York: Back Bay Books, 1992.
80. Robert Nozick. Invariances: The Structure of the Objective World. London: Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 2001.
81. Amit Goswami. The Visionary Window: A Quantum Physicist’s Guide to Enlightenment.
Wheaton: Quest Books, 2006.
82. Hermann Röhrs. “The Classical Idea of the University. Its Origin and Significance as Conceived
by Humboldt.” In Tradition and Reform of the University under an International Perspective.
Ed. Hermann Röhrs. New York: Peter Lang, 1987, pp. 13–27. See also Thorsten Nybom. “The
Humboldt Legacy: Reflections on the Past, Present, and Future of the European University.”
Higher Education Policy 16 (2003): 141–59.
83. Mae-Wan Ho. “Illuminating Water and Life”. Entropy 16 (2014), in print.
70
Abstract: As a consequence of the recent global recession, a new “crisis in the humanities” has been
declared, and ideas of how best to defend the humanities have been vigorously debated. Placing
this “crisis” in the context of neoliberal reforms to higher education since the 1980s, I examine the
argument expounded by Martha Nussbaum that the very foundation of democratic citizenship is at
stake. I indicate a number of problems with Nussbaum’s case. First, to resist the neoliberal agenda
that pits disciplines against one another, I maintain that we need to understand the humanities
broadly to include the social sciences. Second, I indicate that the humanities are not just important
to democracies, but are a vital aspect of any society because they form a crucial part of human existence.
Third, I argue that the humanities are important to democratic societies not merely because they
promote critical thinking about our political processes and sympathetic understanding as Nussbaum
argues. More fundamentally, the diversity of the humanities in both their content and approaches to
knowledge is central to freedom. Finally, I warn against framing the challenges facing the humanities
in terms of a crisis discourse that deprecates freedom in accord with the neoliberal agenda.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Spencer, V.A. Democratic Citizenship and the “Crisis in
Humanities”. Humanities 2014, 3, 398–414.
1. Introduction
In the fall out from the recent global recession, commentators on higher education in the United
States have emphatically declared a “crisis in the Humanities” [1–5]. Yet, in the United Kingdom,
Australia, and New Zealand—the three countries I possess most familiarity with—recent proposals
to prioritize technocratic skills and business needs are merely the latest in a long line of neoliberal
reforms to higher education that were initiated in the 1980s when academic autonomy was first
arrested [6–9]. During Margaret Thatcher’s premiership, academics lost security of tenure and the
university grants committee that had been run by academics was replaced with a funding committee
on which academics constituted a minority. Priority was also placed in funding student places in
accord with the national priority for “highly qualified manpower” [9]. Since then, universities have
been increasingly transformed into business corporations with the introduction of student fees for
domestic students in 1981, and the need to generate funds from external sources seen as a core role of
the academic enterprise. The Higher Education Funding Council for England is now located in the
Department for Business, Innovation, and Skills, the “department for economic growth” [10], and in
the budget cuts to public funding in 2010, the humanities and arts were targeted causing outcry
among their advocates [11]. As in the United States, when dealing with scarce resources, politicians
in Britain have tended to favor the sciences over the humanities.
Though neoliberal reforms in Australia and New Zealand have followed their own unique
trajectories, governments in these countries have often taken their lead from higher education
71
reforms initiated in the United Kingdom. The result has been no less than a mini-revolution in the
higher education sector, one that has affected the sciences, as well as the humanities. In a climate
where the profit-motive reigns supreme, the commodification of the sector has seen many scientists
struggling to defend the importance of their non-applied research that will never have any direct
commercial value. Nonetheless, from the perspective of some in the humanities, even having an
indirect potential to contribute to the profit-motive is an enviable position to be in. What is undeniable
is that within this climate, advocates for the humanities have been scrambling to produce arguments
in their defense, and to justify the very existence of some fields of study whose use-value to the
present and/or business has been less than immediately obvious. For some, like Martha Nussbaum,
the very “future of democratic self-government” ([1], p. 2) is at stake.
In this paper, I maintain, like Nussbaum, that the study of the humanities plays a vital role in the
promotion of empathy, and the development of self-examining thinkers with the knowledge and
analytical abilities to question political authority. Nevertheless, I indicate that an exclusive focus on
this argument poses the danger of prioritizing certain disciplines over those whose contribution to
democratic self-government is less evident. I argue instead that the importance of the humanities lies
in its diversity in both its content and approaches to knowledge. The value of the humanities extends
beyond its use-value to business or the democratic polity by helping us understand human existence
in all its manifestations. It is also this diversity that forms the foundation stone of freedom and that
we therefore have a duty to foster. It is precisely this diversity that is threatened, however, by the
neoliberal agenda that privileges its singular conception of freedom based on profit. If we are to resist
this neoliberal agenda, we need to form alliances wherever possible by widening the debate and
asking more fundamental questions about the kind of society we wish to live in. For, the neoliberal
attack on diversity and its creation of perpetual crises poses a serious risk not just to the humanities,
but also to the free individual everywhere.
Before I proceed to the main argument, it is first necessary to clarify what I mean by the
humanities. In Not for Profit, Nussbaum claims exclusively to promote the humanities, which she
distinguishes from both the sciences and social sciences, because “nobody is suggesting leaving
these [other] studies behind” ([1], p. 7). By contrast, in its 2013 report, The Heart of the Matter, the
American Academy of the Arts and Sciences identifies the humanities and social sciences, unlike the
physical and biological sciences, as together possessing unique problems due to a lack of investment
in the United States [12]. For example, Congress is currently considering a 22% cut to the National
Science Foundation’s Social, Behavioral and Economics Sciences Directorate [13]. Likewise, in the
2010 cutbacks to higher education in Britain, the social sciences were targeted along with the
humanities [14]. In Australia, during the 2013 election campaign, Prime Minister Tony Abbott promised
that “wasteful” and “futile” research would no longer be funded through grants from the Australian
Research Council. The four projects highlighted for criticism expanded across the arts, humanities,
and social sciences [15,16]. Nussbaum indicates that supporters of economic growth fear artists who
are “not the reliable servants of any ideology” ([1], p. 24); but this is no less the case with academics
72
in the fields of social and political thought, as well as many social scientists who conduct empirical
work that challenges increased inequities and other injustices perpetuated by their governments.
Neoliberalism operates by pitting universities, departments, and individual researchers
against each other in an attempt artificially to increase “market” competition. Collegiality across
departments—and often within them due to competition for scarce resources among fields within a
discipline—is broken down as academics compete with each other to attract student numbers as a
source of income. The research output of universities and departments are regularly assessed, and
league tables produced. These exceptionally time consuming and expensive surveillance exercises
militate against the development of collegial relations across disciplines and institutions. Although it
is a normal reaction when under attack to bunker down and defend one’s own turf, strategically it is
crucial to resist this temptation by forming alliances wherever possible.
In the case of the humanities and “social sciences”, many would also dispute that they are easily
demarcated as separate intellectual enterprises. Both assist us to understand the human world
including its impact on the non-human world, whilst the sciences focus on the natural world. The
American Academy defines the humanities as “the study of languages, literature, history, film, civics,
philosophy, and the arts”, whilst the social sciences include the disciplines of “anthropology, economics,
political science and government, sociology, and psychology”. The social sciences, it claims,
“examine and predict behavioral and organizational processes” by “[e]mploying the observational
and experimental methods of the natural sciences”. The impetus for “non-scientific” disciplines to
prove their “scientific” credibility goes at least as far back as the seventeenth century when Descartes
“denied to history any claim to be a serious study” ([17], p. 103). In an effort to establish history as a
viable field of study, many thinkers during the eighteenth century adopted scientific methods in an
attempt to uncover fundamental laws governing history and the behavior of human societies. Yet, as
much as positivism has been (and still is) evident in departments of political science and government
in the United States, it is also highly contested within the United States and largely rejected outside it.
Debates over methodology in all of the so-called “social sciences” seriously question the veracity of
the Academy’s claim that they apply the methods of the natural sciences. On the contrary, whilst we
deal with facts, many of us consider our work is far more “artistic” and interpretative ([17], p. 132).
Although a detailed discussion of methodology is beyond the scope of this paper, recognition of
the interdependence between the humanities and social sciences shows how important the humanities
are and the scope of their influence. When the humanities are broadly understood to include the
social sciences, the impetus to justify the value of these disciplines on the extent to which they
conform to the sciences where “real” knowledge is attained is radically disrupted. Scholars in the
humanities need not apologize for failing to be scientists, or see themselves as engaged in an increasingly
marginalized sphere of activity, but they can stand on their own intellectual strength based on their
difference and re-position their place as center stage in the study of the human world.
Moreover, Nussbaum’s democratic argument that promotes “[t]he ability to think well about
political issues” and “[t]he ability to judge political leaders critically, but with an informed and realistic
sense of the possibilities available to them” ([1], pp. 25, 26) is dependent on equipping students with
the knowledge provided in the “social sciences” and, in particular, political studies. Anthropology
with its focus on culture; sociology with its attention to class, race, and gender studies; and human
73
geography with its interest in development also provide crucial insights into our own and other
societies that assist students better to understand the complex world in which we live and that have
the potential to influence policy-making. Nussbaum ([1], pp. 23–24) rightly indicates that literature
and the arts have the ability to open our eyes to new ways of viewing our world and to increase
sympathy between people, but so do the study of different cultures and the plight of people that
face social, sexual, and racial oppression in the present. It thus does no service to the humanities in
Nussbaum’s own terms of their value to democracy to divorce them from the social sciences. Indeed,
in her chapter on creating citizens of the world, she concedes the importance of economics, history,
and political science along with language learning in the creation of a multicultural education ([1], p. 91).
Let us therefore examine more closely the argument for the humanities—when we understand
them broadly—for the creation of the kind of citizens we need in order to maintain a healthy
democracy. Nussbaum’s case is three-fold. First, the humanities specialize in the promotion of the
“cultivated capacities for critical thinking and reflection [that] are crucial in keeping democracies
alive and wide awake”. Second, the knowledge contained in studying other cultures and the international
political economy “is crucial in order to enable democracies to deal responsibly with the problems
we currently face as members of an interdependent world”. Third and finally, humanities and the arts
are adept at cultivating empathy with others and sympathy for their circumstances, which need “to be
greatly enhanced and refined if we are to have any hope of sustaining decent institutions across the
many divisions that modern society contains” ([1], p. 10).
Arguably, these skills are necessary for all societies and not merely democratic ones. Sympathy
and compassion are not uniquely democratic values, but feature in a range of moral and religious
traditions. Nor do the humanities and the arts necessarily promote these values. As Nussbaum ([1],
pp. 28–29, 35, 109) realizes, antidemocratic movements have been highly effective in their utilization
of the arts to foster hatred toward marginalized groups, and many stories perpetuate misleading
caricatures and sexist stereotypes. Whilst the arts cultivate the imagination, that imagination can be
dark and brooding, as can human existence. If we look, moreover, to the political values and personal
lives of many artists whose works we admire, they will often disappoint in terms of their empathy for
others. Philosophers, too, are not well-known historically for their progressive gender relations, and
contra Nussbuam’s claims about the democratic features of Socrates’ approach to knowledge, Socrates
far from supports democratic values in The Republic [18].
The challenges of multiculturalism and globalization extend well beyond democratic boundaries.
Non-democratic societies that previously focused one-sidedly on the promotion of technical skills
are increasingly recognizing the value of the humanities in fostering innovation and understanding in
a globalized world [19]. For example, in a 2012 Humanities Educators’ Conference with the theme
“Fostering Critical Thinking, Inspiring Active Learning”, the Minister for Education in Singapore,
Heng Swee Keat, declared:
Humanities educators play a vital role in preparing our young people as Singaporeans
with a global outlook. Our students need civic literacy, global awareness and cross-cultural
74
skills so that they can interact with people of diverse backgrounds with confidence and
empathy. They should also be able to think critically and creatively when solving problems
at work and in life, and tackle problems that do not even exist today [20].
The Hong Kong Academy for the Humanities was also established in 2011 to promote the value
of the humanities. The kinds of questions posed in the humanities about the things that concern us;
the ways in which we view them, that is, the categories in which we understand our world; and
the imaginative impulse to view things differently are at the core of human experience whether it is
democratic or otherwise.
Yet many would concur with Nussbaum that the humanities are particularly vital to a
well-functioning democracy. As she writes: “Democratic participation makes wider demands, and it
is these wider demands that my primary argument supports” ([1], p. 11). For one, democracy depends
upon people participating in the political system at the very least through the great majority of the
population voting in regular elections. If those voters are literate, informed about social and political
processes in the past and present, and can think critically so they do not simply accept without question
whatever politicians and the media claim—all of which are skills the humanities specialize in
developing—the general belief is that we will have a more robust political system with leaders kept
adequately in check by being held accountable for their actions. Thus, democratic leaders and
philosophers from Thomas Jefferson to John Stuart Mill have argued for the importance of universal
education to the development of representative democracy ([21], p. 280).
There is nevertheless a tension here highlighted by Mill’s logic that led him to argue that the more
qualified one is, the more votes one deserves ([21], pp. 284–86). Few would accept the elitism of that
argument today, in part, because the more egalitarian argument entailed in the idea of the right
to vote predominates. One needs no skills to vote; it is simply a right accorded to human beings by
virtue of their citizenship in a democratic polity. That right is commonly interpreted also to entail
a right not to vote derived from the more general liberal right of one’s freedom do as one wishes
as long as one does not infringe on others’ freedom. The liberal framing of this right is therefore
divorced from any notion of a duty to participate that, as David Miller indicates, is more indebted to
a republican conception of citizenship [22]. It is also based on the assumption that no one is in a
better position to understand one’s interests than oneself. One might decide that one’s interests are
best served by supporting a party that attempts to create a peaceful society that is committed to a
reduction of inequity, but one might think otherwise. The idea that the individual ought to be free to
pursue his or her own conception of the good plays a central role in both liberal and libertarian
thought alike.
Not all liberals, however, believe that freedom is merely a matter of being left alone. Nussbaum
challenges this classical liberal conception and champions a conception of freedom based on
self-governance. Freedom requires “good” citizens—and not just an elite few—who understand the
importance of democratic participation. This requires that they are not only critical thinkers, but also
sympathetic toward others so they do not merely consider their self-interest in their political
decision-making. For this reason, she rejects the current emphasis on vocational training and
technical skills, and instead promotes a “good” education that “is not just about the passive assimilation
of facts and cultural traditions, but about challenging the mind to become active, competent, and
75
thoughtfully critical in a complex world” ([1], p. 18). It is also an education that gears its instruction
and the kind of books that are read toward those that develop people’s compassion and empathy for
others ([1], p. 37). These are laudable goals and whilst I might disagree with her focus on Socrates
as an appropriate model for a democratic interlocutor, who promotes the empathy, humility, and
respectful listening skills essential for intercultural dialogue, I sympathize with her desire to develop
self-examining and critical thinkers who possess the empathetic skills to understand others in their
own terms.
Another side to democracy is nonetheless evident in the way it operates in many advanced
industrial societies today. Mass participation is minimized in favor of representation by politicians
whose loyalties—whether they are to a party whip with the power to deselect them or lobby groups
with the funds to devastate their next election campaign—often override any concern they might
have to listen to their constituents. The professionalism of political life—or what is called the
presidentialism of the prime minister’s role in Westminster systems of government—has accorded
greater power to leaders who in some cases even fail to listen to the advice of their cabinet ministers
in favor of their own network of analysts [23]. Parties have become increasingly run from the center
with the voices of their members having minimal impact so that membership has been in rapid
decline. In the United Kingdom, for example, only 1% of the electorate was a member of one of
the three major parties in 2010, compared to 3.8% in 1983 ([24], p. 2). Similar trends have been reported
in Australia [25] and New Zealand ([26], pp. 236–37). Mass demonstrations—as were evident in
the United Kingdom and Australia prior to the Iraq war—also have had little, or no, effect on
political decisions.
It is in the interests of those in power even in democracies to ensure the populace does not become
thoughtful and critical about our political processes. If parties increasingly want to control their
internal dynamics in a top-down manner, they are not looking for alternative perspectives. The irony
of neoliberalism in the higher education sector, too, has been greater government control over the
sector by reducing academic freedom and expanding bureaucratic control. Between 2003–2004 and
2008–2009, professional managers in the British tertiary sector increased by 33% and academics
only by 10% [27], whilst Australia now has a sector with 55% non-academic staff across all
universities [28]. Though administrative staff are crucial in supporting academics in their research
and teaching, this bureaucratic growth has often been accompanied by a decline in academic control
over core activities in favor of hierarchical line management and greater government control in
determining national priorities. A range of compliance mechanisms have been developed from the
United Kingdom’s Quality Assurance Agency that oversees course design and learning outcomes for
students to annual performance audits for academic staff. Often the justification is greater democratic
accountability; if taxpayers’ money is involved, then we need to develop open mechanisms to ensure
they receive value for money. The institutional culture that has ensued in many places is based on the
premise that academics are not to be trusted to perform well without punitive surveillance measures
in place [29]. By contrast, the new managers are rarely, if ever, accountable for their decisions to the
teaching and research community that (in theory, at least) they are meant to serve.
The answer to reducing bureaucratic control is not to reduce government funding; on the contrary,
bureaucratic growth has operated in tandem with decreased funding. Where universities in Australia
76
have been given autonomy, it has been in terms of increasing non-government avenues for income
generation but that, in turn, has merely justified further the shift away from academic control within
universities in favor of increasing business and managerial interests. Money is redirected from
teaching less popular or expensive courses irrespective of their educational value toward marketing
campaigns, glossy mission statements, and expensive compliance mechanisms. Meanwhile, individual
academics are routinely gagged from commenting on areas beyond their field of expertise such as
administrative decisions that affect their working lives ([29], p. 32; [30]). We have a product to sell,
so we need to keep any disgruntlement in house, and on a business model we need happy consumers.
This means our students need to be proud of their institution, and believe it is at the forefront of
research and teaching innovation. The upholding of this image means the impetus is strong to
sacrifice critical thinking about the direction of our institutions and government mechanisms that
measure our performance. Despite all the cynicism that exists, for example, toward the New Zealand
Performance-Based Research Fund exercise due to the ways its rules can be manipulated by various
universities and disciplines to their advantage, we all nonetheless complied in submitting our
portfolios, and our institutions simply looked for the best spin they could make with the statistical
data. Conformity to the rules of the game—no matter how much they are found wanting by thoughtful,
critical people—is what counts.
Of course, there is a degree of merit in the notion of the happy consumer. Many academics are, for
example, committed to teaching students well, and hope they will receive positive student evaluations
in recognition of their work. Does being a good educator necessarily correlate, however, with happy
students? It does according to the neoliberal model of education that focuses on providing skills
training, but is it really my job, as a political theorist, to make all my students feel comfortable so
they leave my lecture with a satisfied smile? Or is it my role to challenge them so they feel decidedly
uncomfortable at some point during a semester? Is confusion, at least initially, not an important step
in learning new concepts and ways of thinking? To be sure, there are better and worse ways to guide
students through that process, but confusion is unavoidable as they learn to assess difficult material
for themselves. Sometimes, too, no matter how much we simplify philosophical material so it is
more accessible to our students, it can be difficult and even tortuous to read and engage with. Yet, we
consider it worthwhile for the insights that are gleaned by doing so. Hence, there remains the
importance for students at a certain stage in their development to read the originals for themselves
so they can determine what they think of them rather than experience them only through others’
interpretations. As much as some students might wish to be shown the “right” way, it is not our role
simply to replace their current ideology with a new one and thereby produce followers for our cause.
A commitment to critical thinking about society and our role in it is about letting the desire to control
others go, and constitutes a radically subversive position also in contemporary democratic societies.
Thus, whilst I concur with Nussbaum on the benefit of nurturing thoughtful, critical thinkers in
our respective societies, we first need to ask more fundamental questions about the kind of democratic
society we wish to live in. We also need to examine our role in society as academics and the part we
play in perpetuating the current neoliberal agenda. To take just one example, “the publish or perish
mentality” has been keenly pursued by academics wishing to obtain tenure and promotion, but it is
having dire consequences in many of our disciplines where we know that the greatest figures in our
77
fields would never have produced the works we admire if they had faced similar strictures.
Thoughtful, considered thinking takes time, and whilst increased funding to employ more academics
in the humanities would considerably assist in this regard, the current challenges facing the
humanities cannot be reduced solely to a funding issue.
Nussbaum has produced a spirited defense of the humanities by appealing to a tradition of
education she identifies in the United States that is based on critical thinking rather than the
profit-motive. She also ([1], p. 93) recommends the American liberal arts model that includes general
courses for all students—over the kind of specialization that exists in European countries—for all
democratic countries. There are certainly advantages to a model that combines the development of
more technical and scientific skills with the incorporation of humanities subjects. One is that the
value of the humanities in enriching people’s worldview is recognized by diverse groups in society
including engineers and scientists [31]. However, in terms of the democratic value of the American
liberal arts degree, it is noteworthy that whilst the voter turnout rate in the United States is now
comparable to that in Britain, it is far worse than in New Zealand, the Netherlands, Norway, Spain,
Italy, Greece, Sweden, and Denmark ([32]; [33], p. 53). Also, Europe possesses a long tradition of
producing some of the most radical and critical thinkers in the humanities. There is thus more than
one educational model at the tertiary level that can achieve critically informed, democratic participation.
The danger of focusing solely on the democratic value of the humanities is that it can readily lead
to the prioritization of certain disciplines within it such as political studies. Somewhat surprisingly,
Nussbaum does not propose the study of politics; instead, as a philosopher, she prioritizes the
compulsory teaching of two philosophy courses including logic. Yet the privileging of one form of
thinking over another is highly problematic. As a scholar indebted more to the German tradition of
philosophy, I am less enamored with the advantages of the Anglo-American analytic tradition that
still dominates many philosophy departments in the United Kingdom, Australia, and New Zealand.
As Isaiah Berlin ([34], p. 19; [35]) indicates, a sentence can be both logical and grammatical, but
nonetheless nonsensical. Logicians are also deeply divided over what constitutes a “good” proposition.
Honing one’s debating skills can be a valuable exercise, as Nussbaum suggests, particularly if one is
planning on a political career. Debates are nonetheless directed toward the winning of an argument,
something that can interfere with the kind of listening skills required for genuine intercultural
dialogue. Nussbaum maintains that the Socratic legacy of reasoning she supports is not about winners
and losers because Socrates submits himself to the same examination as he does his interlocutors so
“all are equal in the face of the argument” ([1], p. 51). Yet, in The Protagoras, by determining the
rules of the discussion on his terms, Socrates delegitimizes alternative modes of argumentation and
thereby increases his chance to regain the upper-hand in the dialogue [36]. The strength of the
humanities instead lies in teaching us that there is not one way to argue, and not one way to foster
critical thinking.
At the university level, too, the argument for gearing the books that are read toward those
that promote empathy is deeply contentious. Franz Fanon’s The Wretched of the Earth is no less
important to read on the subject of power because it advocates violence [37]. Through literature and
78
drama, too, we learn about the complexity of human existence and much of that is not directed
toward empathy or compassion. It is the diversity of human experience that the humanities excel in
illuminating and that enable us to gain greater understanding of our existence. We can, of course,
teach empathy as a methodology aimed at attempting to understand others’ arguments and experiences
from their perspective. However, whilst I adopt such a hermeneutic method in my classes, it is a
different proposition to consider making it mandatory. The disputes I have, for example, with rational
choice theory, or positivism, or realist approaches to international relations constitute debates that need
to be conducted, not legislated upon. Sometimes we hear students complain if a course adopts a
particular ideology or framework of thinking with which they do not agree. In contemporary
neoliberal times, Marxist academics, for example, are bound to run against the grain. Yet knowledge
within the humanities operates within different disciplinary and theoretical perspectives, and whilst I
promote critical thinking by teaching a range of philosophical perspectives on a topic, there also
remains considerable value in learning from a scholar immersed within a tradition. To teach our
students to respect this diversity by being open to learn from it, we need to support it within our
respective fields.
For, the value of the humanities collectively lies in its diversity in both its content and approaches
to knowledge. Medieval history is important for both the research skills it provides its students and
to understanding the present, but even if I do not benefit directly from the knowledge generated
by colleagues in medieval history it does not follow that it possesses no value. Also, if courses in
international relations attract a hundred more students than those in medieval history, it does not
mean that they have a hundred times more value. Nor is it the case that because international relations
might inform students so that they become more considered voters, and I thereby benefit as a citizen
of a state with more peaceful foreign relations, that courses without a similar missionary intent have
no value. Indeed, if such benefits to society were the standard of success for the humanities, we
would need to conclude that they have been to this date an abject failure. Moreover, while I may
never individually benefit from the existence of courses in medieval history, they nevertheless enrich
the society in which I live. It might be objected that I therefore obtain the kind of instrumental benefit
I would with improving our democratic system, but in the case of medieval history it is highly
probable that I will remain entirely divorced from any direct benefit from its teaching. By contrast,
even people who never vote would benefit if the decisions of their politicians were based on a more
informed understanding of world affairs.
Nevertheless, I do possess an interest in being a member of a society that cherishes diversity and
I therefore possess a duty to sustain its diversity. I may never take a class in medieval history, but
having the option to do so increases my freedom of choice. More importantly than my self-interest, it
provides freedom to those students and historians who specialize in the field to do so. Although I
might not wish to follow that path, it is possible that my neighbor or friends’ child might. While
neoliberals claim that they allow everyone to purse their own conception of the good, in practice,
they narrowly conceive freedom in market terms. In current education policy, for example, arguments
about autonomy form the basis to reward those subjects that attract greater student numbers and to
cut those that fail to have mass appeal.
79
At the same time, however, the market can be understood in more liberal terms. Thus, John Stuart
Mill insists in On Liberty on the importance of diversity to freedom of expression ([21], pp. 116–17).
As he argues, it is possible to find insights in a range of material also when one otherwise disagrees
with it, and even if 99% of people agree a publication is egregious, it is always possible that those
99% of people are wrong. Enabling the market place of ideas to flourish unfettered by censorship is
seen as essential to the capacity to learn and progress. According to Mill, we should therefore “thank”
those “who contest a received opinion”, and “open our minds to listen to them” ([21], p. 105).
Few in the humanities today would accept so uncritically the idea of a “free” market place of ideas
undistorted by power relations. Many would also add the caveat that when confronted with hate
material of various kinds, there ought to be limits to freedom of expression. Yet Mill’s argument with
respect to diversity and freedom for which he was indebted to the German philosopher Wilhelm von
Humboldt maintains its relevance; if the profit-motive becomes the sole criterion for what is taught at
tertiary level so that entire fields are rendered redundant, then censorship is exponentially increased.
It might be covert rather than overt censorship, but it is no less effective. Historians will still be able
to access library books on medieval times and conduct their own research even if the teaching of a
course in their field is considered irrelevant, but as publishing options wither away in response so,
too, will the incentive to work in the field. If students never have exposure to medieval history,
extraordinary initiative by individuals will moreover be necessary for them ever to consider it as a
field of endeavor. Whenever the market closes another door to their possible endeavors, the freedom
of future generations is thus diminished.
It does not follow that the autonomous critical thinker favored by Mill and many liberals is the
only appropriate model to adopt. Mill advocated a life so dedicated to autonomy that he made invalid
alternative forms of life more devoted to reverence [21]. We could also follow Nussbaum’s Socratic
method of reasoning in our study of alternative traditions of thought, as we would examine our own.
However, to do so, before we have attempted to understand them in their own terms and to appreciate
them from the perspective of the people for whom they possess meaning, means we are liable to miss
any wisdom they might possess in our attempt to assimilate them into our own way of thinking and
examining. Thus, we will also fail to fulfill the more primary role of the humanities that unites its
various disciplines, namely, to help us understand human existence in all its diversity.
The aesthetic value of the humanities and its creative dimension have been recognized throughout
history, and fulfill an important part of who we are as human beings by enlivening our imaginations
in multifarious ways. This value is not reducible to the capacity of the humanities to teach us empathy
or sympathy, or their usefulness to democratic participation, or their ability to help us understand the
present, despite the importance of these ends. When a poet eloquently describes nature, he or she can
open our eyes to a new way of viewing the world, but a poet’s propensity to transport us to the
sublime is a significant achievement in itself. There is not one way of experiencing the humanities,
just as there is not one way of being human. The strength of the humanities as a whole lies precisely in
this diversity. For this reason, too, the value of the humanities extends far beyond democratic societies.
80
It is this diversity, however, that is currently under threat from neoliberal policies. The dilemma
we face is not whether the humanities will survive; the importance of the humanities and the skills
they provide are sufficiently well understood in democratic societies that the demise of the humanities
is nowhere seriously countenanced. Yet the humanities are being transformed, and the question we
confront is to what extent its diversity will be impoverished. In some UK universities, scarce
resources have resulted in the closing of departments deemed irrelevant and the burgeoning of others
considered more viable in attracting student numbers. In England between 2006 and 2012, full-time
undergraduate degree courses fell by 31% (27% throughout the UK), restricting student choice [38].
Within departments, too, academics vie for the intellectual importance of their subjects against their
colleagues more concerned to ensure student popularity. In departments of politics, this has often led
to a prioritization of papers dealing with current international affairs or domestic public policy over
those more difficult courses devoted to the theoretical underpinnings of the discipline. Of course,
diversity will always be less in smaller departments and universities. It would also be naïve to
suggest we entirely ignore the pressures to attract student numbers. However, neither students nor
university administrators are in the best position to know the educational value of particular topics to
a discipline, and wherever possible we need to resist the pressures to concede solely to their demands
by protecting the diversity of our offerings.
Where academic control over educational content has already been lost, such resistance may be
unfeasible. Thus, it is crucial for academics where they still possess a level of autonomy to resist
attempts to remove it. Effective resistance can only exist, however, when academics put aside their
urges either to protect their particular field in a way that casts other academic fields, like the sciences,
as the threat, or to exploit an opportunity for expansion of their particular interest within their discipline
when it is at the expense of others. Above all, to protect the pluralism on which the intellectual
integrity of our disciplines is dependent, the forming of alliances wherever possible both within our
own disciplines and across them is vital. As noted above, the liberal arts structure in the United States
might have advantages in this regard. However, great scientists everywhere recognize the value of
the humanities, and those who do not might be convinced at least by the need to protect non-applied
research. If the Australian case is a potential gage of the development of neoliberal reforms in higher
education, it is also naïve to think that the sciences will not elsewhere be eventually affected more
directly. In the 2014 Australian federal budget, for example, research funding to the sciences in all
areas other than medical research was cut by A$450 million in addition to the A$470 million over the
previous two budgets [39]. The issues at stake are not merely a concern for those of us in the humanities.
Yet the framing of these challenges in terms of a crisis discourse is counterproductive. The
politics of neoliberalism is characterized by the creation of crises. To be sure, crises are not entirely
manufactured. The terrorist attacks on the New York World Trade Center and the Pentagon were
momentous, but the “war on terror” that was subsequently created by the Bush administration
effectively placed the world in a permanent state of crisis. Having established we were in a perpetual
warlike condition—with a war on terror never winnable—then the imminent threat of Saddam
Hussein and his alleged weapons of mass destruction were employed to justify the US-led attack on
81
Iraq. Having created a crisis, governments then offer solutions to calm the fear they have generated.
Rational and critical thinking is in the meantime sacrificed in the interests of “necessity”. In both the
United States and the United Kingdom, intelligence agents and those in power ignored evidence that
did not accord with their preconceptions, and in some instances misused the available information to
suit their own political ends [40,41]. As it became evident post-invasion, no real necessity existed.
Yet the cruelty inflicted on the Iraqi population with over 120,000 civilian deaths from violence
estimated between March 2003 and October 2013 was real [42]. As Judith Shklar maintains in
Ordinary Vices, fear deprecates freedom in the name of “necessity”, and can far too easily lead to
cruelty ([43], chap. 1).
Here lessons can also be gleaned from the case of Australian higher education. According
to Michelle Carmody, higher education in Australia—and not just the humanities—has been in a
perpetual state of crisis for the past 20 years, and the solution to outcries at this occurrence has not
been to return government funding to previous levels or to reduce bureaucratic control. Instead, each
crisis has led to another neoliberal solution sold to the public with the rhetoric of increased freedom
through workplace flexibility and greater freedom of choice for students [44]. The latest “necessary”
solution is further to cut government funding to higher education, whilst providing universities
with the “autonomy” to charge whatever fees they wish for their degrees [45]. Managers of the older
universities that are likely to benefit financially from deregulation have welcomed the change. Yet,
the unique conditions in the Australian sector (see [46]) mean any idea that a fair market can be
created is a pure fallacy, as is the successful adoption of America’s private sector model of higher
education in a country that lacks a developed philanthropic culture amongst its elite.
The “necessity” of these changes has not derived from successive governments having insufficient
funds during these constant crises. During the lifetime of the Howard government from 1996–2004,
higher education was cut by 4% whilst the defense budget almost doubled from A$10.4 billion to
A$19.9 billion [47,48]. Nor has the Australian economy since suffered the kind of recession
experienced elsewhere in the world. The neoliberal rhetoric is a chimera, and not merely because
individual freedom is not created through job insecurity with almost half of Australian academics
now unconvinced they possess autonomy and control over their working lives ([29], p. 32), or
because student choices are not free if they are determined by their capacity to pay. The commodification
of education further means students increasingly consider the value of their degree not for any
intellectual enrichment it might offer them, but only for its use-value in the market place; their
freedom is thereby diminished.
As idealistic, romantic, and old-fashioned many might think attempting to turn back the clock on
the neoliberal university might be, neoliberalism has created a discourse of freedom and choice that
provides the possibility to challenge its credibility. It is also feasible to eliminate much of the
bureaucratic red tape and wastage that exists in the Australian system to redirect funding back into
actual research and teaching [46]. It would take political leadership, but it is not inconceivable or
entirely impractical. Where neoliberal reforms to higher education are not so advanced, and the new
managerial class has not been so firmly embedded into the system, resistance is clearly more viable.
To resist successfully, though, we need to open the discussion beyond the role of the humanities and
consider what role, if any, the intellectual has to play in our various societies today. At the very least,
82
6. Conclusions
Rather than plunging from one crisis to another without ever catching our breath, we need
to have the audacity to resist the neoliberal drama and pause to think. We also need to ask
fundamental questions about the kind of society we want to live in. Everyone has a stake in this
debate; as Charles Taylor aptly put it in his critique of neoliberalism in the 1980s, it matters to the free
individual everywhere
that certain activities and institutions flourish in society. It is even of importance to him
what the moral tone of the whole society is—shocking as it may be to libertarians to
raise this issue—because freedom and individual diversity can only flourish in a society
where there is a general recognition of their worth. They are threatened by the spread
of bigotry, but also other conceptions of life—for example, those which look on originality,
innovation, and diversity as luxuries which society can ill afford given the need for
efficiency, productivity, or growth, or those which in a host of other ways depreciate
freedom ([49], p. 207).
In this debate, the humanities are central, and yet simultaneously the current situation in the
humanities is merely symptomatic of a wider neoliberal attack on freedom itself. If we broaden the
debate, we will have far greater chance of finding allies. Neoliberalism has a highly impoverished
conception of freedom, but the desire for self-governance and a respect for diversity cross many
political and philosophical divides. We thus need to recognize that the problem for those of us in the
humanities is not an isolated one produced by the recent, global recession; rather, it is the consequence of
the far greater threat that neoliberalism poses to the diversity on which freedom depends.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Bruce Buchan, Bryce Edwards, and Brett Nicholls for their useful
suggestions and assistance in the writing of this paper.
Conflicts of Interest
References
1. Martha Nussbaum. Not for Profit: Why Democracy Needs the Humanities. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2010.
2. Stanley Fish. “The Crisis of the Humanities Officially Arrives.” Opinionator: The New York
Times, 11 October 2010. Available online: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/10/11/
the-crisis-of-the-humanities-officially-arrives/?_php=true&_type=blogs&_r=1 (accessed on
7 May 2014).
3. Gary Gutting. “The Real Humanities Crisis.” The New York Times, 30 November 2013.
Available online: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/11/30/the-real-humanities-crisis/
(accessed on 16 May 2014).
4. Gordon Hunter, and Feisal G. Mohamed. “The Real Humanities Crisis Is Happening at
Public Universities.” New Republic, 6 September 2013. Available online:
http://www.newrepublic.com/article/114616/public-universities-hurt-humanities-crisis
(accessed on7 May 2014).
5. Benjamin Winterhalter. “The Morbid Fascination with the Death of the Humanities.” The
Atlantic, 6 June 2014. Available online: http://www.theatlantic.com/education/archive/2014/
06/the-morbid-fascination-with-the-death-of-the-humanities/372216/ (accessed on 7 June 2014).
6. Alan Ryan. “Humanities Crisis? Which Humanities Crisis?” Times Higher Education,
1 August 2013. Available online: http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/comment/opinion/
humanities-crisis-which-humanities-crisis/2006072.article (accessed on 22 May 2014).
7. Raewyn Connell. “Neoliberalism and Higher Education: The Australian Case.” Universities in
Crisis: Blog of the International Sociological Association, 20 February 2013. Available online:
http://www.isa-sociology.org/universities-in-crisis/?p=994 (accessed on 2 May 2014).
8. “Editorial: Joyce Unfair to Force Change on Universities.” The New Zealand Herald,
22 April 2014. Available online: http://www.nzherald.co.nz/opinion/news/article.cfm?
c_id=466&objectid=11241853 (accessed on 24 April 2014).
9. Peter Wilby. “Margaret Thatcher’s Education Legacy is Still with Us—Driven on by Gove.”
The Guardian, 15 April 2013. Available online: http://www.theguardian.com/education/2013
/apr/15/margaret-thatcher-education-legacy-gove (accessed on 7 May 2014).
10. Department for Business, Innovation, and Skills. Available online: http://www.gov.uk/
government/organisations/department-for-business-innovation-skills (accessed on 20 May 2014).
11. Anushka Asthana, and Rachel Williams. “Growing Outcry at Threat of Cuts in Humanities at
Universities.” The Observer, 28 February 2010. Available online: http://www.theguardian.com/
education/2010/feb/28/outcry-threat-cuts-humanities-universities (accessed on 14 May 2014).
12. Commission on the Humanities and Social Sciences. The Heart of the Matter: The Humanities
and Social Sciences for a Vibrant, Compelling, and Secure Nation. Cambridge, MA: American
Academy of the Arts and Sciences, 2013. Available online: http://www.amacad.org (accessed
on 7 May 2014).
84
13. Michael Stratford. “Battle Over NHS Begins.” Inside Higher Ed, 14 March 2014. Available online:
http://www.insidehighered.com/news/2014/03/14/house-subcommittee-approves-bill-would-cu
t-nsf-social-science-research#sthash.OYC7v8gI.dpbs (accessed on 14 May 2014).
14. British Academy for the Humanities and Social Sciences. “President Warns that Drastic
Research Funding Cuts Would Imperil UK’s Future Success.” British Academy for the
Humanities and Social Sciences, 17 June 2010. Available online: http://www.britac.ac.uk
/policy/Past_Present_and_Future.cfm (accessed on 27 May 2014).
15. Lisa Wynn. “Australian Government Attack on Government-funded Social Science
and Humanities Research.” Culture Matters: Applying Anthropology, 10 September 2013.
Available online: http://culturematters.wordpress.com/2013/09/10/australian-
government-attack-on-government-funded-social-science-and-humanities-research/ (accessed
on 16 May 2014).
16. Paul Jump. “Tony Abbott Win Leads to Humanities Funding Fears.” Times Higher Education,
9 September 2013. Available online: http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/news/
tony-abbott-win-leads-to-humanities-funding-fears/2007137.article (accessed on 17 May 2014).
17. Isaiah Berlin. “The Concept of Scientific History.” In Concepts and Categories: Philosophical
Essays with An Introduction by Bernard Williams. Edited by Henry Hardy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1980, pp. 103–42.
18. Plato. The Republic, 2nd ed. Translated by Desmond Lee. London: Penguin, 1974.
19. Andrew Delbanco. “The Humanities Crisis.” Project Syndicate, 12 November 2013.
Available online: http://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/andrew-delbanco-on-
the-role-of-science-and-humanities-in-higher-education (accessed on 27 April 2014).
20. Heng Swee Keat. “Opening Address at the Humanities Educators’ Conference.” Ministry of
Education, Singapore, 30 May 2012. Available online: http://www.moe.gov.sg/media/speeches
/2012/05/30/opening-address-by-mr-heng-swee-keat-at-humanities-educators-conference-201
2.php (accessed on 7 May 2014).
21. John Stuart Mill. Utilitarianism, on Liberty, and Considerations on Representative
Government. Edited by H. B. Acton. London: Dent and Sons, 1972.
22. David Miller. Citizenship and National Identity. Cambridge, UK: Polity, 2000.
23. Rod Rhodes. “The Cost of Politics of the Blair Presidency.” Papers on Parliament No. 44.
Parliament of Australia, January 2006. Available online: http://www.aph.gov.au/
About_Parliament/Senate/Research_and_Education/~/~/link.aspx?_id=60E3E1BC98B6477F9
808D1BCE67B47B7&_z=z (accessed on 23 May 2014).
24. Feargal McGuiness, and Rob Clements. “Membership of UK Political Parties: Commons
Library Standard Note SN/SG/5125.” United Kingdom Parliament, 2 December 2012.
Available online: http://www.parliament.uk/business/publications/research/briefing-papers
/SN05125/membership-of-uk-political-parties (accessed on 23 May 2014).
25. Norman Abjorensen. “The Parties’ Democratic Deficit.” Inside Story: Current Affairs
and Culture from Australia and Beyond, 10 February 2010. Available online:
http://inside.org.au/the-parties-democratic-deficit/ (accessed on 23 May 2014).
26. Raymond Miller. Party Politics in New Zealand. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
85
27. Tarqi Tahir. “The Irresistible Rise of Academic Bureaucracy.” The Guardian, 30 March 2010.
Available online: http://www.theguardian.com/education/2010/mar/30/academic-bureaucracy
-rise-managers-higher-education (accessed on 18 May 2014).
28. Nicholas Graves, Adrian Barnett, and Philip Clarke. “Reform Australian Universities by
Cutting their Bureaucracies.” The Conversation, 18 March 2013. Available online:
http://www.theconversation.com/reform-australian-universities-by-cutting-their-bureaucracies
-12781 (accessed on 18 May 2014).
29. Emmaline Bexley, Richard James, and Sophie Arkoudis. “The Australian Academic Profession
in Transition: Addressing the Challenge of Reconceptualising Academic Work and Regenerating
the Academic Workforce.” Commissioned report prepared for the Department of Education,
Employment and Workplace Relations, Centre for the Study of Higher Education, University
of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia, 2011. Available online: http://www.cshe.unimelb.edu.au
/people/bexley_docs/The_Academic_Profession_in_Transition_Sept2011.pdf (accessed on
19 May 2014).
30. Allan Maki. “Tenured Saskatchewan Professor fired for Opposing Restructuring Plans.” The
Globe and Mail, 14 May 2014. Available online: http://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/
national/education/tenured-saskatchewan-professor-fired-for-opposing-university-restructurin
g-plans/article18665598/ (accessed on 17 May 2014).
31. Deborah K. Fitzgerald. “At MIT the Humanities are Just as Important as STEM.” The Boston
Globe, 30 April 2014. Available online: http://www.bostonglobe.com/opinion/2014/04
/30/mit-humanities-are-just-important-stem/ZOArg1PgEFy2wm4ptue56I/story.html?s_campai
gn=sm_tw (accessed on 8 May 2014).
32. International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance. “Voter Turnout.” Available
online: http://www.idea.int/vt/ (accessed on 27 May 2014).
33. Jack Vowles. The New Zealand Electoral Politics in New Zealand: The Significance of the 2011
Election. Wellington: Institute for Governance and Policy Studies, 2014.
34. Isaiah Berlin. “Verification.” In Concepts and Categories: Philosophical Essays with an
introduction by Bernard Williams. Edited by Henry Hardy. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1980, pp. 12–31.
35. Isaiah Berlin. “Logical Translation.” In Concepts and Categories: Philosophical Essays with an
introduction by Bernard Williams, edited by Henry Hardy. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1980, pp. 56–80.
36. Plato. Protagoras and Meno. Translated by W. K. C. Guthrie. London: Penguin, 1956.
37. Franz Fanon. The Wretched of the Earth. Translated by Richard Philcox. New York: Grove
Press, 1963.
38. University and College Union. Choice Cuts: How Choice Has Declined in Higher Education.
London: University and College Union, 2012. Available online: http://www.ucu.org.uk/
media/pdf/c/h/Choice_cuts_report_Feb12.pdf (accessed on 23 May 2014).
39. Suzanne Cory. “Abbott’s War on Science.” Business Spectator, 15 May 2014. Available online:
http://www.businessspectator.com.au/article/2014/5/15/technology/abbotts-war-science
(accessed on 20 May 2014).
86
40. John N. L. Morrison. “British Intelligence Failures in Iraq.” Intelligence and National Security
26 (2011): 509–20. doi:10.1080/02684527.2011.580604.
41. Robert Jervis. “Reports, Politics, and Intelligence Failures: The Case of Iraq.” Journal of
Strategic Studies 29 (2006): 3–52. doi:10.1080/01402390600566282.
42. Iraq Body Count. “Documented Civilian Deaths by Violence.” Available online:
http://www.iraqbodycount.org/database/ (accessed on 1 June 2014).
43. Judith N. Shklar. Ordinary Vices. Cambridge, MA and London: Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press, 1984.
44. Michelle Carmody. “The Neoliberal University in Australia: Permanent Crisis.” Revista
Congreso Universidad 2 (2013): 1–6. Available online: http://www.congresouniversidad.
cu/revista/index.php/congresouniversidad/article/viewFile/188/174 (accessed on 12 May 2014).
45. Christopher Pyne. “Christopher Pyne’s Vision for Higher Education.” The Sydney Morning
Herald, 25 May 2014. Available online: http://www.smh.com.au/comment/christopher-pynes-
vision-for-higher-education-20140525-zrniw.html (accessed on 28 May 2014).
46. James Allan. “Why Our Universities Are Failing.” Quadrant Online, 8 April 2014.
Available online: http://quadrant.org.au/magazine/2014/03/australian-universities-just-good
-enough/ (accessed on 17 May 2014).
47. Michelle Gratton, and Farrah Tomazin. “University Crisis is Howard’s Legacy: PM.” The Age,
4 March 2008. Available online: http://www.theage.com.au/news/national/university-crisis-
is-howards-legacy-pm/2008/03/02/1204402365150.html (accessed on 27 April 2014).
48. Andrew Carr. “FactCheck: Is Defence Spending Down to 1938 Levels?” The Conversation,
3 September 2013. Available online: http://www.theconversation.com/factcheck-is-
defence-spending-down-to-l938-levels-17437 (accessed on 1 June 2014).
49. Charles Taylor. Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 1985, volume 2.
87
Abstract: What may be the relevance of the European tradition of the humanities and of humanism
today? In his novels, Elizabeth Costello and Diary of a Bad Year, the South-African writer, academic,
and current resident of Australia, J.M. Coetzee, both enriches and puts into question the European
traditions that have shaped scholarship, literary writers and academic professions in the humanities.
His characters’ meditations on the value of literature, humanism, and the humanities, their present
crisis and future possibilities, are timely interventions made from a complex, critical, comparative,
cultural and geographic distance. The metafictional investigations of the two novels test the limits of
the genre in a manner consistent with more experimental strains of postmodern fiction, while the two
protagonists reflect two main personae of the author as itinerant, ageing academic and writer. It is the
position of this paper that Coetzee constructs a minor literature within the major language of English;
this is made evident by the entirety of his oeuvre to date though it becomes thematized in these two
works. This paper will trace some of the contours, confrontations and dialogs of the two books and
explore certain tangents of the radical quests and questions they put to their readership.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Varsamopoulou, E. Timely Meditations: Reflections on the
Role of the Humanities in J.M. Coetzee’s Elizabeth Costello and Diary of a Bad Year. Humanities
2014, 3, 379–397.
1. Introduction
What is the relevance of the European traditions of literature and of the humanities today? This is
the question explored in J.M. Coetzee’s Elizabeth Costello [1] [2003] and Diary of a Bad Year [2]
[2007], in which I will trace three inextricably related crises: of literature, the humanities,
and language.
Coetzee is of Dutch descent but writes in English, not in Afrikaans, and the significance of this
choice may be understood in the terms Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari gave to “minor literature”,
their example being that of Franz Kafka, a Czech Jew writing in German in Austro-Hungarian
Prague. Here is the definition Deleuze and Guattari provide of a minor literature:
A minor literature doesn’t come from a minor language; it is rather that which a minority
constructs within a major language […] The three characteristics of minor literature are
the deterritorialization of language, the connection of the individual to a political
immediacy, and the collective assemblage of enunciation ([3], pp. 16, 18).
An equally striking illustration of minor literature is, in my estimation, the poetic oeuvre of
Paul Celan, a Romanian Jew deliberately choosing to write his poetry in German, the language of
his education and of his mother’s literary preference, despite the traumatic weight of violence and
betrayal in the immediate aftermath of the Second World War and Nazi genocidal campaign.
88
Whereas the full impact of the nuances of the deterritorialization of language in the case of Kafka
and, especially, Celan, is diminished in translation (hence the significance of the bilingual edition of
Celan’s poems in the Michael Hamburger translation) [4], it can be directly gauged in the English
prose of Coetzee’s novels [5]. Like Czech or Romanian German in Kafka or Celan, respectively,
Coetzee’s South African English is a deterritorialized language; by writing in this language, Coetzee
immediately is set at a distance from both his South African, Africaans-speaking ethnic milieu and
the Apartheid State of the Dutch colonial minority [6].
While German is the language of the Austro-Hungarian Empire and German literature enjoyed a
high cultural status in Europe already since the Romantic period, English is similarly a language of
empire, and English literature had long been held in regard not only in Europe but in the expansive
British empire. Deleuze and Guattari’s designation of a minor literature has, however, nothing to do
with a minority status of the language in which it is written: “A minor literature doesn’t come from a
minor language; it is rather that which a minority constructs within a major language” ([3], p. 16). Firstly,
the language of a minor literature “is affected with a high coefficient of deteterritorialization” ([3],
p. 16); writing in German alienates Kafka and, especially, Celan (for obvious historical reasons) from
their Czech and Romanian native population context, respectively. Similarly, English alienates
Coetzee from his native Afrikaner context (something poignantly illustrated by his autobiographical
novel, Boyhood). However, the South African context though comparable has an added, ironic twist
with respect to this first criterion for a minor literature. As William Beinart notes in his history of
Twentieth-Century South Africa, despite the imperialist program of increasing the English-speaking
population through immigration schemes at the end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of
the twentieth, in the belief that anglicization would strengthen and benefit the State, this racial
ideology backfired [6]. The assumption was that “‘race’ or culture determined political interest and
behavior” ([7], p. 75), what happened instead was that working-class awareness made many align
with anti-imperialist politics and gave rise to class conflict amongst English-speaking whites; “a few
even made contacts with blacks in socialist organizations” ([7], p. 75). What is more interesting,
following the end of Apartheid, as “black people were drawn into the core political processes, English
increasingly became the shared language of national politics” ([7], p. 281). In the example of
Coetzee’s South-African English, what is a schoolbook language, a language “cut-off from the
masses” ([3], p. 16), later becomes one of the factors for a revolutionary change in national
consciousness since it brought together groups that the Apartheid regime kept apart.
As a second characteristic of minor literatures, Deleuze and Guattari stipulate “is that everything
in them is political ... its cramped space forces each individual intrigue to connect immediately to
politics” ([3], p. 17). Whether one considers the early, overtly anti-colonial novels, The Master of
Petersburg, the autobiographical novels, or the more recent reflective, philosophical novels, in each
text the socio-political is never a background to a personal or familial plot [8]. The political concerns,
dilemmas, anxieties are part of the personal situation, they are an overtly thematized aspect of ethical
and aesthetic matters, which also means that the latter are never abstract discourses. Notwithstanding
the novels’ focus on the individual, there is another way in which everything is political and that is
that everything in them “takes on a collective value”, which fulfills the third criterion Deleuze and
89
Guattari set for a minor literature: “the role and function of collective, and even revolutionary,
enunciation” ([3], p. 17).
As a South African with links to both an Anglophone and a Germanic (Dutch) European
tradition, J.M. Coetzee enriches and puts into question the European traditions that have shaped him
as both academic scholar in the humanities and literary writer. If Kafka’s stories render typical
meaning-producing narrative and interpretive structures uncanny and unstable, while Celan’s
ever greater breakdown and re-assemblage of German words and syntax veers away from
representationalism [9], Coetzee’s narratives create fault lines within the fictional universe that force
our attention onto the problematics of the poetics of storytelling, making the reader share in the
discomfort and anxiety of the authorial creative process. If narrative fiction is a kind of language, a
use of language that also depends on a sensus communis for its real-life contexts and coordinates,
then Coetzee deterritorializes the novel in his prose narratives. Narrative meanings are caught up in a
relentlessly metonymic structure just as his characters are caught up in a movement of displacement
from which any reassuring or certain sense of origin is unattainable or non-existent. The political
immediacy that his individual characters connect to is defined by empire; typically, they are colonizers
or colonized, immigrants, refugees, asylum seekers, shipwrecked or stateless persons in an environment
that is at least vaguely threatening or indifferent to them. Even when his narrators start from the
master’s position, they devolve towards the minor: “To hate all languages of masters” ([3], p. 26).
The narratives “break forms, encourage ruptures and new sproutings” which, when reconstructed create
a “content that will necessarily be part of a rupture in the order of things” ([3], p. 28). We do not find
difficulty in assigning Elisabeth Costello and Diary of a Bad Year to the genre of the novel, if we
take all this into account and consider the following description of the genre: “An assemblage, the
perfect object for the novel, has two sides: it is a collective assemblage of enunciation; it is a
machinic assemblage of desire” ([3], p. 81).
The two novels, Elizabeth Costello and Diary of a Bad Year, are semi-fictional, not because of
the autobiographical dimension they may or may not have, but because much of their writing is
non-fictional—in the form of the literary essay, philosophical reflections or academic debate; as
such, whether or not the opinions of the fictional authors or speakers are also those of J.M. Coetzee is
irrelevant to their generic description and overall import and impact on the reader. Rather than
considering them as distinct characters in a conventional sense, the various writers (academic or
literary but even an author of a letter) that feature in Coetzee’s novels constitute what Deleuze and
Guattari signify by “a collective assemblage of enunciation”; the third criterion for a minor literature.
Elizabeth Costello the fictional Australian author who features in most of the novel by that name;
Lady Elizabeth Chandos—of the same initials –who is the fictional author and wife of the (also
fictional) Lord Chandos, invented by Hugo von Hofmannsthal, of the 11 September, 1603 dated
letter to Francis Bacon in the post-script to the novel; and Mr. C, the author figure in Diary of a Bad
Year, indirectly identified as Coetzee himself, all form a collective assemblage for the author function.
The meditations of this collective assemblage, or authorial personae, on the value of literature
and the humanities, their present crisis and future possibilities, are timely interventions made from
a complex cultural critical and geographical distance, which ought to compel our attention. Their
timeliness is not restricted to their date of writing or publication. What renders the meditations timely is
90
their untimeliness, understood as both a negation of this restriction and even as their being
contre-temps, at the wrong time or against the times. More precisely, to use Nietzsche’s terms from
Untimely Meditations [10], “acting counter to our time and thereby acting on our time and, let us
hope, for the benefit of a time to come” ([10], p. 60).
On a more thematic level, both books foreground an intense awareness of time or timeliness as a
problem for an embodied individual embedded in the modern world: the crossing of time zones, jet
lag, old age, ageing and sexuality, saying things at the wrong time and the reverse, repetition and
even a parodic fantasy of limbo or the afterlife, but also marking time with one’s writing, as in Diary
of a Bad Year. The question of time is also the question of life, the question of the good life, of ethics.
Coetzee brings together in Elizabeth Costello but also in Diary of a Bad Year, literary writing that is
critical and even deconstructive on a subject that can be given the title “The uses and disadvantages
of literature for life” [11]. Here, however, we should give to the term “literature”, the wider sense of
writing that encompasses fictional, historical, and philosophical writing.
The act of writing, the writing of a novel, of lectures, of award speeches, of philosophical reflections
for publication, of a confessional statement, and by extension, literature in general (as cultural
institution, personal activity, public responsibility, and form of entertainment), is repeatedly, and often
dramatically, staged in these two semi-fictional novels, while simultaneously the (institutional)
authority and (cultural) power of both the literary and critical author are subverted. Altogether, these
works are illustrative of our still being, in the words of Jean-Luc Nancy and Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe,
living the legacy, whether we are aware of it or not, and indeed the problematic, of Jena, of the Early
German Romantics, as set out in the Athenaeum and Critical Fragments, the Letter on the Novel, and
other seminal texts of what they rightfully designate as the first modern European avant-garde. What
this means is given in part by this statement:
[…] it means that literature, as its own infinite questioning and as the perpetual positing
of its own question, dates from romanticism and as romanticism. And therefore that the
romantic question, the question of romanticism, does not and cannot have an answer. Or,
at least that its answer can only be interminably deferred, continually deceiving,
endlessly recalling the question […] “The romantic kind of poetry [Dichtart] is still
becoming; that is its real essence: that it should forever be becoming and never be
perfected” [12].
In Elizabeth Costello (of which The Lives of Animals [1999] forms a part), and in Diary of a Bad
Year, Coetzee’s authors act as members of a virtual Republic of Letters; it is with equally serious
consideration that they address, engage with and respond to others, irrespective of their social or
professional status, their gender, class, or color. The books themselves are the indispensable means
of their radical democratization of this humanist, enlightenment and romantic notion of a republic of
letters. Elisabeth Costello and her male counterpart in Diary of a Bad Year, another ageing but
eminent Australian author (born, like Coetzee, in South Africa) debate, contemplate and put into
doubt others’ or their own strong opinions on what could be said to fall under the general rubric of
studia humanitatis (an enlarged version of the present day “humanities”, to include social and
political thought, literature, history, philosophy).
91
2. Elizabeth Costello
The lessons that make up Elizabeth Costello constitute a critique of literature and the humanities
through the (auto)biographical fiction of an authorial figure [13]. In the first six lessons, Elisabeth
Costello’s lectures on literature are embedded in the personal everydayness of the speaker in a
narrative that openly shows the “wiring” behind realism as a literary style by the real author. Though
the actual author never interrupts the narrative to rupture the fictional world, the exposure of realism
as a fictional mode is achieved by the various metafictional techniques of self-reflexivity. Furthermore,
no one is allowed to appear either glamorous or authoritative, nothing goes without being challenged,
undermined, passionately and personally criticized. At first, Elisabeth Costello is introduced in good
realist form: we are given her date of birth, present age, countries of residence, and marital history,
after which follows the explanation that she is traveling all the way from Australia to Williamstown,
Pennsylvania, to receive one of the most generous literary prizes, the Stowe prize, at Appleton
College, and give a speech at the prize ceremony.
The speech itself is then a total subversion of the already tired realism of this story. The title
“What is realism?” immediately launches into a description of Kafka’s famous story “Report to an
Academy”, briefly discussed as proof of the end of realism, of the debunking of the realist illusion by
its exposure as just that, an illusion, and by the multitude of uncertainties and ambiguities of Kafka’s
story that are not merely epistemological ones, but deeply ontological ones, shared by herself and her
contemporaries. The son’s argument with his mother on the appropriateness and relevance of her
topic and its development turns into another kind of argument on realism and animal lives. The
chapter ends with his view of the open mouth of his sleeping mother, and while staring down into it
and imagining the rest of her inner organs, he protests (in his mind): “No, he tells himself, that is not
where I come from, that is not it” ([1], p. 34); yet another rejection of realism. The protest is not
merely attributable to a kind of (male) squeamishness with regard to the (female) human anatomy,
but against the reduction of reality to a purely materialist vision of being.
The graphic anatomical orality of this ending is then followed by a look at the claims of orality
in African literature. The novel in English lays claim to a very specific matrix of genesis in
eighteenth-century England, where the insistence on realism—as opposed to the excess of the
romance tradition in prose fiction—has the most formative and polemical role. The rise of the realist
mode in prose fiction however, cannot be separated from the focus on the individual as guarantor of
the truth of experience and of individualism in the growing literary industry. These remarks by no
means exhaust the parameters, context or conditions for the origins of the English novel, but they do
matter in pointing out the radical difference of this genre from other traditions of storytelling
elsewhere, and therefore raise the question of its universality. In chapter/lesson 2, “The Novel in
Africa”, Elisabeth Costello finds herself accepting an invitation to give a lecture series on a cruise
ship. There she encounters an old acquaintance and former lover, the African writer Emmanuel
Egudu, whom she describes as having ceased to produce anything of substance for some years now,
cashing in on his identity as African novelist to make a living on such cruises. His speech, given in full,
offers well-known arguments on orality in African culture, the essential difference and distinction of
92
Africans and other ideas known from the Negritude movement. He presents these in support of
the essential difference of the African novel from the European novel. The speech is highly contested
by Elisabeth in an exchange she has with the speaker in the presence of two lay members of the
audience, who also have their viewpoints. The disagreements of Elisabeth, the elusive answers of her
interlocutor, the entirely different approach of the non-writers and the sexual jealousy with which
the chapter ends, hinting that perhaps Elisabeth’s vehement disagreements were not entirely fuelled
by disinterested aesthetic judgments, all serve to undermine any pretence to rational authority, yet
also sustain a polyphonic narrative debate. It is a debate that has affected for some decades now the
formerly facile assumptions of academic departments of (English) literature, especially in Anglophone
countries. It is worth noting also how this chapter, as the previous one put forward critiques and
critical debates that arise from a comparative perspective. The legitimacy of comparativism itself
will come under attack in the section to follow.
If the arguments of the previous lesson are partly fuelled by personal feelings, this issue is brought
into the foreground of the following two lessons. The Lives of Animals picks up and most fully
develops the “hobbyhorse”, as her son calls it, of Elisabeth Costello. Again, it is an invitation to
speak that she has accepted. This time she is to give two lectures at her son’s college. Rather than talk
about her novels, she flouts disciplinary divisions and institutional conventions and talks about
animals: their status as living beings, but especially the industrial production, slaughter and consumption
of animals, linking this vast topic and its ethical ramifications with literature and philosophy as two
different ways humans approach the differences between human and (other) animal being. From
an ethical it becomes an ontological and also an aesthetic discussion, breaking down not only the
distinctions between humans and animals, but also trampling the prerogatives of disciplinary
specialization and, for some, committing sacrilege by making a comparative reference to the mass
murder of Jews during the Holocaust with the industrial mass production and murder of animals to
fulfill dietary and other purposes of humans. Here, the greatest diversity of ideological positions, are
shown, once again, to have personal roots, to be inexorably products of embodied and ideologically
embedded existences.
Thus far we have been exposed to the limitations of realism, the hidden and unhidden biases of
universalism, the arrogance and error of human supremacism in the animal world, based typically on
the spurious prerogative of language. Each chapter underlines and undermines the continuing fallacies
of humanism without, however, offering an easy way out, or total refutation, of humanism. The next
two lessons are highly complementary chapters and also return us to issues in the previous lessons:
the interrelation of the aesthetic and the ethical. In “The Humanities in Africa”, the writer has a
debate with her sister, a Catholic missionary nurse who runs a hospital for dying children in Africa.
The debate is occasioned by the indictment of the humanities in her Sister Bridget/Blanche’s
acceptance speech for an honorary doctorate. The Sister argues that the humanities failed and are
dead, for some centuries now. The contemporary disciplines comprising the humanities, especially
literary studies, constitute a form of study that perverted from its original raison d’être, i.e., as a
means for the salvation of the soul through the development of the knowledge and method needed for
Western Europeans to read and interpret the Greek New Testament for themselves, into a secular and
fragmented set of disciplines with no ultimate purpose or usefulness in the world. The value of
93
literature, especially the written text, is, thus, contested by two independent cultural histories:
Negritude and African oral traditions of performance (the thesis of the Nigerian writer’s talk), and
late Medieval and Renaissance Europe or Western Christendom on the other. The aesthetic dimension
is prevalent in the African contestation, the ethical dimension in the European one. What then, could
be the point, purpose or project of the humanities today? On what basis could one argue for their
legitimation? The collective assemblage that constitutes the “machinic desire” of this novel present
key facets of this contemporary problem, inviting us, as readers, writers, authors, students and
teachers, to engage in the discussion. The outcome cannot be known but the engagement itself
implies a commitment to salvaging what is worthwhile, refuting what can no longer be accepted as
valid or relevant, and perhaps a move towards a new future for the humanities, a post-humanist one
in many respects.
The next lesson, “The problem of Evil”, picks up from the earlier indictment of the Catholic
church as promoting an aestheticization of suffering by its manner of focusing on the representation
of the Passion and the dying Christ on the cross. It also links up the theme of the Holocaust from the
chapters on the lives of animals with the problem of evil in general, and specifically, the question of
whether evil should be represented in literature. Elisabeth Costello has been invited to a conference
on the theme of evil in Amsterdam, where, just having read a fictional account of the trials and
execution of those German officers who had planned to assassinate Hitler, she has been stunned by
the author’s uncanny ability to get inside the head of the brutal executioner and Nazi cruelty, to take
the readers to scenes that in fact had no witnesses, apart from the executioner, who presumably never
gave an account. Feeling “touched by evil”, she intuits that the author must also have been touched
by evil in his imaginative historical description of their degradation, suffering and slow deaths.
Disconcerted by the unexpected presence of the actual author in the audience, she contemplates
a variety of solutions (mostly self-censorship) but in the end decides to go ahead and read the
original paper.
Elisabeth argues that of such evil we must be silent, because of the power of its affect not just
on the mind, but on the soul, too. Her view is that everything affects the soul; “This soul is”, as
Jean-François Lyotard refers to it, “but the awakening of an affectability” [14]. It is a view that also
tacitly aligns her with the aesthetics of the classical Greek world, since in ancient tragedy, the
representation of extreme violence on the stage was forbidden, thus, the aestheticization of violence
was elided. Despite violence and human evil being at the heart of tragedy, it was the meditation on
the motives and effects of violence that mattered. The two stances, Elisabeth’s and the classical one
converge on the agreement that everything has an effect on the soul, that representation of violence
aestheticizes violence—she describes herself as being excited and carried away by the
narration—and that in the case of the graphic depiction of evil, these effects carry too high a risk.
Contrary to the dangers inherent in imagining and depicting evil, the lesson “Eros” probes the
sexual relations between humans and gods/goddesses in ancient Greek myths; the greater curiosity
behind this attempt to imagine sexual intercourse with a god or goddess is whether such intimacy
would allow one “to get a sense of, a god’s being?” ([1], p. 188). Perhaps this is the most untimely of
the meditations since, as Costello notes immediately after, it is “a question that no one seems to ask
anymore” ([1], p. 188). She then offers her own articulation of this question: “Other modes of being.
94
That may be a more decent way of phrasing it. Are there other modes of being besides what we call
the human into which we can enter; and if there are not, what does that say about us and our
limitations?” ([1], p. 188) In other words, we return to the question of the limits of the imagination
that was first raised in the lesson on the poets and the animals. Moving once more in favor of the
direction of the sympathetic imagination, of feeling, both as sensation and sentiment, the chapter
concludes with a reference to love as offering a vision of the pattern that brings and holds disparate
entities together.
The playful metaphysical musings of the lesson “Eros” are continued in the final lesson. “At the
Gate” is a fantasy of the afterlife and judgment in an obvious and signaled postmodern, parodic take
on Kafka’s “Before the Law”. Elizabeth Costello must provide a statement of beliefs to a board
of judges in order to be allowed to pass through the gate into a realm of brilliant light. Her initial
resistance to this demand, on the grounds that belief runs counter to the vocation of the writer, is
dissolved in the end by the surprising epiphany that “She lives by belief, she works by belief, she is a
creature of belief” ([1], p. 222). Equally surprising, perhaps only to the readers, is her exasperation at
her tendency to view everything around her, even in the afterlife, as and through literariness. Her
own final words in this lesson are the exclamation: “A curse on literature!” when the vision of an
old dog lying beyond the gate prompts the automatic production in her mind of “the anagram
GOD-DOG” ([1], p. 222). The writer’s exasperation at her conditioning that produces the hubristic
perception of the most sacred word, leads her then to the double hubris of cursing her own confessed
faith in literature. Literature, and by extension language, can also block one’s apprehension of reality
and should not be mistaken for an adequate path to all truths either since not only the signifier and the
referent are arbitrarily linked but the sign may easily slip into or be substituted by another sign.
This curse emitted by Elizabeth Costello nevertheless realizes itself, albeit anachronistically, in
the post-script, which refers us to the 1902 letter “Ein Brief” by Hugo von Hoffmansthal, in which a
fictional character, Lord Chandos, writes a letter denouncing all literary endeavour to a real historical
person, Francis Bacon. As is well known, this fictional letter was the proclamation of a truthful
statement by Hoffmansthal himself to end his short but acclaimed career as a poet and turn instead to
the writing of librettos. Coetzee provides a brief quote from Hofmannstahl’s letter:
At such moments even a negligible creature, a dog, a rat, a beetle, a stunted apple tree, a
cart track winding over the hill, a mossy stone, counts more for me than a night of bliss
with the most beautiful, most devoted mistress. These dumb and in some cases inanimate
creatures press toward me with such fullness, such presence of love, that there is nothing
in range of my rapturous eye that does not have life. It is as if everything, everything that
exists, everything I can recall, everything my confused thinking touches on, means
something ([1], p. 226).
He then gives a second letter, written by an invented wife, Lady Elizabeth Chandos, some twenty
days supposedly after the date of the original by her husband. It is a secret letter to Francis Bacon, in
which she confesses to having read her husband’s letter, prompting her to write her own in an attempt
to override the authority of her husband’s account of his subjective experience for the sake of their
conjugal happiness, as well as for the good of all.
95
What is this fictional supplement to the Lord Chandos letter doing as a postscript to a book that
has chronicled the crisis of literature and the humanities, as institutions in their present form, through
the crises of its academic author-protagonist?
Coetzee’s rewriting, or supplementation of the Chandos letter from the perspective of his wife,
Lady Chandos, is an appeal on behalf of her husband. Here, postmodernism reads romanticism (more
specifically, it is possible to situate the Lord Chandos Letter within romantic decadence or romantic
modernism). A comparative reading of the original with this hypertextual version will point to,
amongst other things the continued crisis of literature that has now deepened into a crisis of language
itself. Retreating from the extreme affectation of the soul in the experience of sublimity, Lady
Chandos asks for a return of attention to the exigencies of the everyday, and through its 9/11 dating,
to the ethical urgency for action, for words to be useful again for doing things. Though the original
letter by Hoffmansthal does not include a direct explanation of why the addressee should be the
eminent English humanist, Bacon, Coetzee’s Lady Chandos provides us with a clue: “he writes to
you, as I write to you, who are known above all men to select your words and set them in place and
build your judgments as a mason builds a wall with bricks” ([1], p. 230). Here, rather than looking to
the gods or God (i.e., the ancient Greek or Judaeo-Christian ultimate form of authority—a Lacanian
big Other), the letter issues an appeal to a great figure of tradition (Hoffmansthal, Lord Bacon), an
appeal for salvation, and it would seem, for a new “golden age” of literature, of culture, in which
transcendence will again be possible.
If from the realm of the afterlife Elizabeth Costello has met her fellow in Lady Elizabeth Chandos,
the impassioned and direct plea for the relevance of literature, for a new (post-)humanism, and
therefore for a newly-oriented humanities, would not be incompatible with the unease, doubts,
uncertainties, critique and crises of the more hesitant and guarded postmodern author, Elizabeth Costello.
Nor, indeed, would it be implausible to divine some share of that unease in the situation of the factual
author, J.M. Coetzee, who between 1997 and 2003, the period of the writing of all the sections of
Elizabeth Costello had suffered the condensation of these crises of literature and the humanities in
his own literary, academic life [15].
Considering how the Greek origin of the word crisis (“krisis”) signifies both the act of forming a
judgment and the condition of suffering, it is possible to identify a link between the last two sections
of the book. It is a crisis of legitimation, for the author/creator and for literature/language that links
the intertextual dialog with Kafka and Hoffmanstahl in these final sections of Elizabeth Costello.
If, instead of the allusion to “Before the Law”, we consider Kafka’s short story “The Silence of the
Sirens”, in which modernism reverses the matrix of the mythical encounter between Odysseus and
the sirens in order to create an allegory of its present condition, a further illumination of the postscript
can be effected. Here Kafka rewrites the siren song episode as an enigma which, even more uncannily
than in Hoffmanstahl’s prefiguring of Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer’s reading of the
episode in Dialectic of Enlightenment [16]. In their first chapter, Adorno and Horkeimer read the
cunning episode where Odysseus has himself tied to the mast of the ship and blocks his crew’s ears
so they do not hear the sirens and be enthralled by their song or his own cries to untie him as an early
96
sign of the progressive alienation of modern Western humanity from nature through the subject’s
reliance on instrumental reason, and of the relegation of art (epic/narrative art) to impotent
decoration. Kafka’s sailor revisits the site of the Sirens’ island but finds tragedy turned into farce
since the sirens do not sing to him. Is this an answer/punishment to humanity for resisting their
epic/lyrical power of sublimity leading to death? Or is it just Kafka’s perennial fear of not being able
to write? The condensed polysemy of this new myth allows for more than one answer. If we consider
the Homeric episode, Kafka’s story, Adorno and Horkeimer’s polemical interpretation together with
Hoffmansthahl’s “Ein brief” and Coetzee’s supplement as a single palimpsest, we may look back to
Kafka’s revisitation of the episode in “The Silence of the Sirens” as the first moment of the absurd, of
the siren’s threat having become the threat of meaninglessness, of lack of signification as well as
significance. It foretells the opposite of being overwhelmed by the power, meaning and beauty of the
original siren song. The end comes not by fire, but by ice; the fear of being consumed by transcendence is
replaced by the horror of being abandoned to an impermeable solipsism. However, here again we
note the uncanny resemblance of Kafka’s story to the theoretical re-articulation of the sublime by
Jean-François Lyotard in terms of the threat of privation, of the “Is it happening?” no longer
occurring. Kafka’s story can be ready as an exemplary fantastic narration of that catastrophe.
Thus, in the postmodern moment we have a revisitation of both modernist and late romantic
anxieties. In Lyotard there is the fear or dread of privation; in Kafka the terrifying silence of the
sirens is dreadful for the utter lack of emotional affect. Yet both stories report the disaster of
aesthesis, a phrase used by Lyotard to describe the Burkean and Kantian interface in the discourse of
the sublime. The disaster of aesthesis indicates a problem with subjectivity; what happens if/when
there is no “anima minima” to enable sublimity and the “Is it happening?” of art/literature? Additionally,
if one moves on from Lyotard’s consideration of the issue, we must ask, as do Coetzee’s later works
in their entirety: how does literature/the arts in general and their study in the university figure in the
project of sustaining this “anima minima”?
Truth, anima minima, the arts and humanities, the future (of the) university, but also literature and
sublimity, from which we started, are, for these writers, and the connections I’ve drawn between
them, intricately and inextricably linked. For those postmodernist or late modernist writers and
thinkers, such as Coetzee and Adorno, the sublime becomes either the object of an impossible
yearning/haunting, inadmissible and irreconcilable with the negativity bequeathed by much
modernism (Coetzee’s view) or plain irrelevant if not ridiculous for the contemporary consideration
of aesthetics, art, literature, the humanities. However, though Adorno contends, in his Aesthetic
Theory, that suffering is the secret and inalienable raison d’être of art, its special prerogative that
justifies its continuing relevance, he virtually rejects the sublime, out of the bias held against
Romanticism [17]. To refer once more to Paul Celan, it is his work that vindicated lyrical poetry after
Auschwitz; in his poetics the necessity and possibility of a sublimity stemming from extreme
suffering is present even as it impossibly shrinks representational poetics into near-immateriality,
thus intensifying the emotive and performative force of the poem in the direction of a very Kantian,
very Lyotardian also, understanding of the sublime. For Lyotard, the sublime is not just now, to cite
the title of Barnett Newman’s 1948 essay, “The Sublime is Now”, which he refers to, it is also
necessary [18]. For Kafka, too, it was necessary; without it no literature was worthwhile. Is this not
97
what his 1904 letter to his schoolmate Oskar Pollak famously says when he disdainfully dismisses
books that leave him indifferent, declaring as his principle of poetics a principle of aesthesis: “a book
must be the axe for the frozen sea inside us” [19]? Aesthetics has replaced, and guides, poetics in
modernity and postmodernity alike.
If not achieving the sublime, these works gesture towards it, or point to its absence, since it is also
not only the task of the writer, the task of the book, but also the task of the reader. As Maurice
Blanchot reminds us, the book does not exist until it is read [20], which means that in the hands of the
reader, the book may or may not become the work, may or may not attain the function of the axe,
since, in Heideggerian terms, the axe-book would remain a mere tool, not a work of art, without a
“sea inside us” to act upon, even if frozen. What happens if, where once there was a frozen sea, there
now is a desert? What good may an axe be in the desert? Here, I refer once more to Lyotard’s
postulation of the anima minima, of the bare modicum of subjectivity still needed, with all its
metaphysics, if there is to be aesthesis.
Thus, in these last three parts, what seemed initially perhaps to be a strange series of three
digressions due to their formal and uniformal palimpsestuousness, turn out rather to be a literary
enactment of the previous chapters’ more diegetic, dramatic and theoretical discourse of Coetzee’s
Costello, who on and off had referred to literature as salvation, to the entire history of the humanities
in Europe as having been such an attempt. A failed and perhaps mislead attempt, to put it in other
words, to achieve what Plato called “the care of the soul”; an ideal, but the only ideal that could ever
make Europe worthwhile according to the Czech philosopher Jan Patočka in Plato and Europe [21].
What directions this solicitude over the anima minima, the psyche or, as one prefers, the spirit or
soul, may take can be gauged by the impassioned contestations and experiments in the history of
humanist scholarship and the contemporary humanities, which Coetzee’s highly metafictional novels
manage to distill and dramatically convey outside the ivory tower of the university.
Coetzee dramatizes the relations between lay and professional readers, literary authors and
academics, poets and philosophers, religious thinkers and secularists in an intricate web of personal
relations that underpin and affect the professional disputes. Laying all bare, getting into the
consciousness now of the son of the famous mother, now of the writer herself, Coetzee issues a
challenge to two major pillars of the world of letters and the humanities per se: academe and the
institution of the author. Both are powerful institutions emerging from modern European history that
nonetheless today and, arguably, for more than a few decades now, are experiencing a severe crisis.
Elizabeth Costello’s linking of the question of literature to the purpose of the humanities and to
the university—a link which, according to Jean-Luc Nancy and Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe in The
Literary Absolute characterizes (Early German) Romanticism, and by extension therefore, our own,
still, concept of the liberal arts in the university—continues in the next novel Coetzee published,
Diary of a Bad Year.
98
In Diary of a Bad Year, Coetzee approaches the figure of the writer from a different gendered
perspective, but much more importantly in fact, from a different visual perspective: that of contrast
and simultaneity. The novel is divided into two parts. The first part “Strong Opinions”, derives its
title from a book commissioned by a German publisher, in which six authors from different countries
“say their say on any subjects they choose, the more contentious the better. Six eminent writers
pronounce on what is wrong with today’s world” ([2], p. 21). For the first twenty pages, we read two
parallel texts; each page is divided into two sections by a line: above the line are the texts of Strong
Opinions, while below the line is a continuous “common denominator” of the author’s personal life
in diary form. Thus, we are given the impression of spying on the author at work, in his home
surroundings. While the diary shows a continuity of interest instigated by his accidental encounter
with an attractive young woman in the laundry room of the communal block of flats, the texts of
“strong opinions” have an impersonal and episodic structure since they are all different entries. From
the fifth to the 25th entry, the pages are split into three sections, the addition at the bottom of the page
is a novelistic text in which features the personal life of Anya, the 29 year old Filipina from the
laundry room, now becomes his personal typist and, therefore, reader of the strong opinions, and
her boyfriend, Alan, a well-read 42-year-old Anglo-Australian broker. The top part of the page is
taken up by a series of numbered, short essays on 31 different contemporary issues, landmarks of
socio-political thought or institutions: The origin of the state, anarchism, democracy, Machiavelli,
terrorism, guidance systems, Al Qaida, universities, Guantanamo Bay, national shame, the curse,
pedophilia, the body, the slaughter of animals, avian influenza, competition, intelligent design, Zeno,
probability, raiding, apology, asylum in Australia, political life in Australia, the left and the right,
Tony Blair, Harold Pinter, music, tourism, English usage, authority in fiction, the afterlife.
During the course of the writing/typing up of the commissioned reflections, Anya, well-aware of
the attraction she holds for the 80-year-old writer, is slowly drawn into conversations with him about
the content of strong opinions, and even about the purpose of thought and writing, in general and
with respect to specific topics. Out of a growing sympathy and charitable feelings, she assumes
occasional tasks of housekeeping and cleaning for him. He cares about her opinions, where others
did not, including herself, and she cares for his living conditions, where no one else will, including
himself. The romance plot is thickened by the intensifying jealousy of her boyfriend and the
“competition” or “contest” of the two men for her affections culminates in Alan’s nefarious plans to
swindle the writer of all his money, willed to be bequeathed to an animal care organization, “the
Anti-Vivisection League of Australia” ([2], p. 146), which he has discovered by installing spyware
on the writer’s computer through the unwitting medium of Anya. Once he reveals his information
and plans to her, she is faced with the ethical dilemma of betraying one or the other man’s
confidence: becoming Alan’s conscious accomplice and also future receiver of stolen funds or
revealing all to the writer.
In the second part of Diary of a Bad Year, there are once again, numbered reflections on the top
part of the page and two further sections, the writer’s personal diary and Anya’s personal story of the
99
same events: a total of 24 further topics appear, that start with the personal “A dream”, “on fan mail”,
“my father” and “insh’ Allah”, on which pages the middle section, in which the writer’s personal
diary had appeared, is still divided by two lines but left blank, and end with reflections on “Dostoevsky”.
In the development of the novelistic plot there is change and a denouement; Anya has persuaded her
boyfriend not to rob the writer, the writer invites the two over to celebrate sending off the completed
manuscript to the German publisher, where Alan makes a drunken scene and none-too-cryptically
gives hints of what he had planned to do. Finally, Anya leaves Alan and goes to stay with her mother
in another city. She says goodbye to the writer and later writes to him, signing the letter, “admiring
fan”. This second part, formally entitled “Second Diary”, but which we discover on reading Anya’s
letter to him from Brisbane, contains the pieces he had edited out because he did not judge them as
being “proper Strong Opinions”. These “Soft opinions”, as she calls them, are her favorites and they
are all more personal, more revealing of the author, than those that make up “Strong Opinions”: after
the first four already mentioned are “mass emotion”, “the hurly-burly of politics”, “the kiss”, “the
erotic life”, “ageing”, “idea for a story”, “La France moins belle”, “the classics”, “the writing life”,
“the mother tongue”, “Antjie Krog”, “being photographed”, “having thoughts”, “the birds of the air”,
“compassion”, “children”, “water and fire”, “boredom”, “J. S. Bach”, and last “Dostoevsky”. In an
essay considering the Nietzschean overtones in the book’s critical and often skeptical engagement
with opinions, Paul Patton observes that the novel is “a celebration of life” and, the ending in
particular, which valorizes Anya’s preference for the “soft opinions”, points towards “an affirmation
of everyday life, the life that we share with animals, but that is also expressed in our opinions,
thoughts, fantasies and dreams” [22].
Diary of a Bad Year has, together with Elizabeth Costello, a modest place reserved for the
fictional plots of novel writing. The novelistic frame grants the meditations an embedded existence.
They seem also, so far at least, to herald a reflective pause in Coetzee’s novel writing. In this sense
too, they could be described as timely meditations. They are a kind of reckoning. His next book,
Summertime (2009) [23], was a posthumous-styled biography of Coetzee the author. In the
much-awaited novel, The Childhood of Jesus (2013) [24], Coetzee resumes a more predominantly
fictional manner of narrative, but for that no less intensely committed to an interrogation of the
relevance of education and academic learning to the immediate meaning and decision-making needs
of ordinary people, while also insisting through a convincing literary narrative, on the absolute
necessity of literary and philosophical discourse (whether one designates it as some form of humanism
or not) if one is to be able to cope with the complexities and contingencies of real life and satisfy the
desire for constructing life-sustaining meanings.
The “opinions” in Diary of a Bad Year recall, by their terse and pithy style, their provocation to
thought and their personal inflection, both the fragments published by the Jena circle and Nietzsche’s
aphorisms and fragments. The fragment evades the dangers of even inadvertent authorial paternalism;
they are an invitation to thought, to dialogue and debate. A double, then triple precaution against the
tendency towards mastery of theoretical discourse is further taken by the tripartite division of the
page and the space, and voice, allocated to the personal/autobiographical and to the interest of the
plot: i.e., interaction with others. As Jonathan Lear explains, “the aim of the style is [...] to defeat the
reader’s desire to defer to the ‘moral authority’, the ‘novelist’ John Coetzee [...] Coetzee’s authority
100
lies in his ability to divest himself of authority” [25]. Referring to the definition of rhetoric in the
Phaedrus as “a peculiar craft of leading the soul with logos” and the purpose of education set forth in
the Republic “as turning the whole soul around”, Lear considers how the page divisions constitute “a
rhetorical move in the Platonic sense. This is Coetzee’s attempt to lead the whole soul” ([25], p. 70).
The three parts of the page read vertically expose to the reader “a spectacle of embedding [...] we see
how the moral stances that are officially to be presented in book form are embedded in the fantasies,
happenings, musings, and struggles of the author’s day-to-day life” ([25], p. 70). The point of this is
also to take a stand against the danger of thought, especially ethical thought, becoming a mere
academic or literary exercise and a substitute for genuine thought and engagement [26]. Adding to
Lear’s just appraisal of the philosophical (Platonic) objectives of Coetzee’s strategies, it is worth
remarking that by turning the pages sequentially in order to follow the real-life entanglements of the
author in the surprises, disappointments and dangers of his entanglement in the lives of others, our
reading follows a spiral trajectory, returning to familiar but never identical acts. Thus, whether
intellectual contemplation, the business of everyday life or interpersonal encounters that may awaken
what Lear calls “metaphysical ache”, a desire for reality no matter how unpleasant it may at times be
for us; but it is equally entails “a living recognition of the reality of others [...] not only recognizing
their dignity but crying out against their humiliation, degradation, and torture” ([25], p. 86). It is not
difficult to recognize how what Lear describes as the purpose of the textual strategies Coetzee adopts
in Diary of a Bad Year can be identified also throughout his novelistic work, including the most
recent, Childhood of Jesus.
The novels involve us in a rich historical and ideological debate that compels us to reconsider the
role of literature, with respect to the author and the critic function represented in these texts. At the
same time, they raise the question of the post-modern re-integration of the aesthetic with the spheres
of ethics and science, and challenge us by setting before us one very ubiquitous yet ugly alternative to
the raison-d’être of the humanities: that of the banker/speculator. In L’Université sans condition,
Jacques Derrida contemplates the significance of the profession of the Professor, of the verb “to
profess”, at the root of each, and chooses to “underline less the authority, the supposed competence
and assurance of the profession or of the professor than, once more, the commitment, the declaration
of responsibility” [27].
Could the role of literature, of the humanities, and of the university itself be related to that
other mission also of the university, so frequently, as Derrida notes in L’Université sans condition,
emblematized in many particular institutions’ coat of arms, that is, the mission of “veritas”, truth?
Truth, and the ancient adage, “the care of the soul”, renewed in modern terms/times by Michel
Foucault and Jan Patočka, but also by others, Lyotard, Derrida and Emmanuel Levinas amongst
them, is the regime for the anima minima, the “substance-soul” as Lyotard names it, and for that
purpose, there must be, in the way that Derrida stipulates, a university without condition, an
unconditional university, and that unconditionality is a condition for its future state, one which is not
yet embodied by its present condition, and one which designates that the conditions of this unconditional
university could just as well pertain outside, or beyond the university institution(s). That this is
101
feasible, Coetzee’s work gives us just one such example. One should be able to question everything,
to include the most heretical views. In The Master of Petersburg, Coetzee’s homage to Dostoevsky,
the anarchist student Sergei Gennadevich, states his exasperation with universities: “A university is
a place where they teach you to argue so that you’ll never actually do anything” [28]. He and
his comrades reject words as having the power of physical action, as having any significant effect.
This is contrary to the view of literature that Elizabeth Costello has held, as it is contrary to the
understanding of literature in Diary of a Bad Year. Literature, the humanities and the university can
have a transformative effect on the individual, can constitute an event. For Derrida, this event, in its
unknowability, its unpredictability, would go even beyond the force of language in performative
speech acts. As for Coetzee’s own views of Dostoevsky, in Diary of a Bad Year, the last word he has
to say, the last of the “soft opinions” is on the importance of Dostoevsky’s novels:
I read again last night the fifth chapter of the second part of The Brothers Karamazov, the
chapter in which Ivan hands back his ticket of admission to the universe God has created,
and found myself sobbing uncontrollably. ([2], p. 223) These are pages I have read
innumerable times before, yet instead of becoming inured to their force I find myself
more and more vulnerable before them. Why? It is not as if I am in sympathy with Ivan’s
rather vengeful views […] So why does Ivan make me cry in spite of myself? ([2], p. 224)
The answer has nothing to do with ethics or politics, everything to do with rhetoric […]
Far more powerful than the substance of his argument, which is not strong, are the
accents of anguish, the personal anguish of a soul unable to bear the horrors of this world.
It is the voice of Ivan, as realized by Dostoevsky, not his reasoning, that sweeps me
along. ([2], p. 225) And one is thankful to Russia too, Mother Russia, for setting before
us with such indisputable certainty the standards towards which any serious novelist
must toil, even if without the faintest chance of getting there: the standard of the master
Tolstoy on the one hand and of the master Dostoevsky on the other. By their example
one becomes a better artist; and by better I do not mean more skilful but ethically better.
They annihilate one’s impurer pretensions; they clear one’s eyesight; they fortify one’s
arm’ ([2], p. 227).
Here, beauty and compassion, the two things that Costello had singled out as the moving,
life-affirming qualities of art bequeathed to us from the ancient Greek and Italian Renaissance
cultures, are once again held up in their monumentalistic significance—in Nietzsche’s sense, for
whom the use of this conception of the past for someone is that “He learns from it that the greatness
that once existed was in any event once possible and may thus be possible again” ([10], p. 69).
Derek Attridge points out, in his introduction to the collection of Coetzee’s critical reviews,
Inner Workings, “Coetzee’s non-fictional and semi-fictional writing taken as a whole represents a
substantial and significant contribution to the continuing discussion of literature’s place in the lives
of individuals and cultures” [29]. I would add: of institutions and of traditions. Coetzee responds in
defense of literature, not only by staging all the different angles from which literature, and its traditional
institutional study within the humanities, can be discredited, but also by showing that literature,
especially the novel, can still be the space for this event. It is a space that cannot be provided by any
102
other textual or wider cultural form, the space in which any manner of discourse can be given a
platform, in the real contexts of intimate histories of individuals, and with the unique attention to the
beauty of language by which we as humans inhabit the world, providing delight, even when the limits
and limitations of language, or of our animality, throw up a seeming dead-end or inscrutable mystery.
4. Conclusions
Coetzee’s writers carry on vulnerable, imperfect, aged and weary shoulders a demand that they
should unassumingly, ingloriously, and even at the risk of disgrace, render literature a matrix through
which all, whether writers or readers, may realize that they themselves can become what they are: the
unacknowledged legislators of the world, and so complete the revolutionary project of Romanticism,
what Novalis called the romanticization of the world [30]. Going even further back than the Romantics,
the Renaissance Humanists’ creation of an imaginary, virtual Republic of Letters is a significant
predecessor to the ethical ideals of this kind of postmodern novel. The literary worlds of Coetzee’s
books, in which we, as readers, participate, suggest the continuing relevance but also need for a
virtual, imaginary, republic of letters, radicalized so that neither classical or encyclopedic erudition
nor letters or introduction are needed. In this renewed humanist republic of novel writers and readers,
what we all do have, and what Coetzee’s novels insist upon, are opinions and beliefs. What we often
lack, is the chance to question, or sometimes, to even become aware of the nature of our beliefs and
opinions, to articulate them coherently but also freely, to compare them with those of others, on all
subjects, without fear of censorship or condemnation [31]. With unflagging ethical concern to realize
the radical democratic potential of the novel form, Coetzee’s novelistic aesthetics deploy a set of
strategies that divest the authorial figure of any authority to dictate opinion and belief. In equally
dark times as those of the original Renaissance humanist republicans, perhaps even darker, in view of
the imminent threat of ecological apocalypse, “little communities” [32] dispersed throughout the global
readership can, through the medium of the “fragile craft” of the book, realize the legitimacy and validity
of their own claim to “maintain a different kind of society, with its own rules and values”, ([32], p. 5)
to question the authority held by a person or an institution, in the extreme plasticity and sociality of
this kind of novel.
Conflicts of Interest
1. J.M. Coetzee. Elizabeth Costello. London: Vintage, 2004. All further citations will be from
this edition.
2. J.M. Coetzee. Diary of a Bad Year. London: Vintage, 2008. All further citations will be from
this edition.
3. Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari. Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature. Translated by Dana
Polan. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, 1986. First published as
Kafka: pour une littérature mineure. Paris: Les éditions de Minuit, 1975.
103
4. Paul Celan. Paul Celan: Selected Poems. Translated by Michael Hamburger. London:
Penguin, 1996.
5. One could also include the works of James Joyce (Ulysses and, especially, Finnegan’s Wake)
and Samuel Beckett (both English and French writings). Deleuze and Guattari’s category of
minor literature can thus clearly be said to pertain to anti-realist modes or tendencies in modernist
and late-modernist literature.
6. Apartheid, or racial segregation, and its concomitant set of laws that forcibly relocated
“black”, “coloured” and “Asian” people into separate areas, and eventually deprived black
Africans of citizenship, was enforced by the National Party that held power from 1948 to
1994. It came to an end with the first democratic elections in 1994 when the African National
Congress won and Nelson Mandela became president.
7. See William Beinart. “War, Reconstruction and the State from the 1890s to the 1920s.”
In Beinart, Twentieth-Century South Africa. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001, Chapter
Two (First edition published in 1994).
8. For a reading of three of Coetzee’s anti-colonial novels, Dusklands, Waiting for the
Barbarians and Foe which juxtaposes postcolonial theory with Deleuze & Guattari’s work,
see Grant Hamilton. On Representation: Deleuze and Coetzee on the Colonized Subject.
Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2011. My own interest here however is in the relevance of Deleuze &
Guattari’s theorisation of a minor literature with the revolutionary potential of such literature
to speak to the crisis of the humanities in his late, self-reflective, writerly novels (postmodernist
Künstlerromane), Elizabeth Costello and Diary of a Bad Year.
9. By “representationalism”, what is meant here is the linguistic unity of signifier-signified-referent,
which enables the immediate comprehension of a word by its automatic link to an existing
meaning in a shared linguistic community of the speakers of that natural language. By cutting
up words, separating morphemes and using highly elliptical syntax, Celan’s poetry eventually
develops further and further away from conventional ways of inferring meaning from poetic
language through reliance on the representation of a common world of shared meanings that
the ordinary use of words and the rule-abiding formation of phrases would facilitate. In an
essay on Celan that focuses largely on translation, Coetzee writes of Celan’s “unremitting,
intimate wrestlings with the German language, which form the substrate of all his later poetry”
and so “translation of the later poetry must always fail” (J.M. Coetzee. Inner Workings, Essays
2000–2005. London: HarvillSecker, 2007, p. 131).
10. Friedrich Nietzsche. Untimely Meditations. Translated by Reginald John Hollingdale.
Cambridge: Cambridge Univesity Press, 1983. This essay was originally published 1874. All
further citations will be from this edition.
11. Here I am paraphrasing the title of Nietzsche’s essay, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of
History for Life”, in Untimely Meditations.
12. Athenaeum Fragment 116, cited in Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, and Jean-Luc Nancy. The
Literary Absolute: The Theory of Literature in German Romanticism. Translated by Philip
Barnard and Cheryl Lester. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988, p. 83. First
published as L’absolu littéraire. Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1978.
104
13. Six of the lessons/chapters of Elisabeth Costello and its postscript had appeared in some form,
typically in critical academic journals or as lectures (The Lives of Animals). Of these, the last
three chapters: “Eros”, “At the gate” and the postscript, “Letter of Elisabeth, Lady Chandos”,
depart significantly from the style of the previous six sections, having the form of extended
personal meditations on encounters with the radically other, or a radical othering of the self.
14. Jean-François Lyotard. Postmodern Fables. Translated by Georges van den Abbeele.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997, pp. 242–43. First published as Moralités
postmodernes. Paris: Éditions Galilée, 1993.
15. The order of the publication of the last four lessons and the postscript are as follows: Lesson 5,
“The Humanities in Africa” (2001); Post-script, “Letter of Elizabeth, Lady Chandos” (2002);
Lesson 6, “The Problem of Evil” (2003). “Eros” and “At the Gate” appeared only with the
novel itself, in 2003.
16. Theodor Adorno, and Max Horkeimer. “Excursus I: Odysseus or Myth and Enlightenment.”
In Dialectic of Enlightenment. Translated by John Cumming. London: Verso, 1997, especially
pp. 32–36. First published as Dialectik der Aufklärung. New York: Social Studies Association,
1944.
17. Theodor Adorno. Aesthetic Theory. Translated by Robert Hullot Kentor. London: Bloomsbury
Academic, 2004. First published as Aesthetische Theorie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970.
18. Jean-François Lyotard. “The Sublime and the Avant-Garde.” In The Inhuman: Reflections on
Time. Translated by Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2004.
First published as L’Inhumain: Causeries sur le temps. Paris: Editions Galilée, 1988.
19. Franz Kafka. Letters to Friends, Family and Editors. Translated by Richard Winston. New
York: Schocken Books, 1977. Kindle edition. First published as Briefe 1902–1924. Prague and
Berlin: Schocken, 1959.
20. Maurice Blanchot. “The Work, The Book.” In The Space of Literature. Translated by Ann
Smock. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1982. First published as L’Espace littéraire
(Éditions Gallimard, 1955).
21. Jan Patočka. Plato and Europe. Translated by Petr Lom. Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2002.
22. Paul Patton. “Coetzee’s Opinions.” In Strong Opinions: J.M. Coetzee and The Authority of
Contemporary Fiction. Edited by Chris Danta, Sue Kossew, Julian Murphet. New York and
London: Continuum, 2011, p. 60.
23. J.M. Coetzee. Summertime: Scenes from Provincial Life. London: Vintage, 2010.
24. J.M. Coetzee. The Childhood of Jesus. London: Vintage, 2014.
25. Jonathan Lear. “Ethical Thought and the Problem of Communication: A Strategy for Reading
Diary of a Bad Year.” In J.M. Coetzee and Ethics: Philosophical Perspectives on Literature.
Edited by Anton Leist and Peter Singer. New York: Columbia University Press, 2010, p. 67.
26. See, especially, Jonathan Lear. “Ethical Thought and the Problem of Communication: A
Strategy for Reading Diary of a Bad Year.” In J.M. Coetzee and Ethics: Philosophical
Perspectives on Literature. Edited by Anton Leist and Peter Singer. New York: Columbia
University Press, 2010, pp. 65–66.
105
Abstract: This article is based on the conviction that the major problems nowadays are not
technical, but ethical, and are incumbent on homo qua homo. The origin of these problems is the
advancement of economicism as a supreme interpretation of human and social reality, which means
the primacy of the “market” and considering human beings in terms of what they have rather than
what they are. Economicism emerges in “modernity” and assumes that everything that does not
have market value is either devaluated or rejected. In consequence, the human being has been
devaluated and has turned into a simple object of the market. “Postmodernity” mixes economicism
and techno-scientificism (chrematistics and instrumental rationality) with nihilism (absence of
values), giving way to a technological and decadent capitalism that has erased “humanism” and the
very idea of the human being. Thus, we are in urgent need of a humanist recovery of the “human”
based on a rehabilitation of ontology.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Talavera, P. Economicism and Nihilism in the Eclipse of
Humanism. Humanities 2014, 3, 340–378.
1. Introduction
The thesis I shall attempt to defend sets out that the abandonment of the humanities is directly
linked to the eclipse of humanism, which began with the economicist paradigm of modernity and
was consummated with postmodern decadent thinking, which has largely adopted an anti-humanist
and nihilist direction, sustaining the futility of the very idea of being human. Foucault puts this in
terms that could not be clearer: “The discoveries of Levi-Strauss, Lacan, Dumezil not only erase
the traditional view of man, but also, in my view, tend to render the very idea of man useless for
research and thinking. The most burdensome inheritance which in turn has been passed down to us
from the 19th century—and which it is now time to rid ourselves of—is humanism” [1].
Nevertheless a peculiar phenomenon has come about: the economicist reductionism of
modernity has given rise to postmodern anti-humanism; but the nihilist nature of postmodernity, far
from overcoming the enlightenment paradigm, has contributed to augmenting techno-scientific
development and the omnipotence of the market, reducing human beings themselves to an object
that can be technically manipulated and economically quantified.
The historical epoch, which is known almost unanimously as “modernity”, came into being
near the middle of the fifteenth century under the sign of the primacy of the “market”. Economic
modernization contemplated the individual as a being who exchanged commodities, was solely
concerned with his/her own wealth and stressed the visual, the quantitative and the disjunctive.
Its motto was perfectly portrayed by the Frenchman, Guizot, during the reign of Louis Philippe
of Orleans: “Enrichissez-vous!” The market became the only social institution that had to be
vigorously defended.
107
However, economic modernization maintained a degree of autonomy from the cultural sphere
because of its different epistemological and anthropological foundations and by way of its distinct
organization. In effect, cultural modernization, which came about at the end of the eighteenth
century, displayed a clear sense of hostility towards modernity: it defended the supremacy of secondary
qualities and subconscious impulses over the predominance of geometric rationality. Theophile
Gauthier’s motto of l’art pour l’art was directly aimed at Guizot’s slogan, as was Oscar Wilde’s quip
in his play Lady Windermere’s Fan: “A man who knows the price of everything and the value
of nothing.”
This hostility between economic modernization and cultural modernization became evident in
the nineteenth century with the simultaneity of the defense of progress carried out by Spencer (the
salient advocate of homo oeconomicus) and the spread of decadentism propagated by Baudelaire
and Verlaine. However, the autonomy of these social spheres was slowly disappearing in so far as
the economic world increasingly extended its power. At this moment, politics had abandoned all
hopes of holding sway over the mercantile sphere, and it mimetically copied all of its procedures to
the point that what was most important was the trademark and not the ideology. Culture and art, in
turn, had become yet another element of consumption, something which is fragmentary and pleasant
to juxtapose alongside that which is analytical and boring; aspects which are both characteristic of
the age of production.
The advancement of economicism as a supreme interpretation of human and social reality
produces hand-in-hand, on the plane of factual reality, the end of humanism and the success of
post-structuralism and the poignantly called “pensiero debole” (weak thinking), which is none
other than simple nihilism, the abandonment of rationality, and indeed of the very idea of the
human being.
The most well-known advocate of “weak thinking”, Gianni Vattimo, states that our culture
has adopted Nietzsche’s nihilist conception, which means accepting the death of God and, with it,
levelling the foundations of supreme values [2]. The essence of this “nihilism” consists of finally
reducing all “use value” to “exchange value”, and in the final analysis, human beings themselves
are reduced to and identified as “exchange value”. In this way, all values, freed from their foundations,
become equivalent and interchangeable, and all reality becomes available ([2], p. 28). Herein, we
have the peculiar convergence of economicism and nihilism, which will be analyzed later on. When
everything is reduced to “exchange value”, all reality takes on the nature of money; in other words,
it can be exchanged indistinctly for any other thing. The apotheosis of “exchange value” extended
to the whole of life includes human beings themselves, whose singularity (humanity) is dissolved
to become something that is available and interchangeable, radically dispossessed of any hope of
absolute value that supposedly granted them dignity. In short, nihilism ends up generating the
merchandization of what is human by reducing it to a mere “exchange value”. Consequently, the
absolute hegemony of economicism, which has been imposed on society as the ultima ratio for
politics, culture, the arts and the economy itself, does not originate solely from a spillover of the thirst
for wealth and well-being, but rather from the loss of what is human as an absolute criterion of
reference; it follows that attempts to submit the market and finances to a supposed “business ethics”
fail time and time again. Overcoming economicism (the globalization of “exchange value”)
108
inescapably requires overcoming nihilism, something which can only be done from the perspective
of rehabilitating humanism.
With this in mind, this article analyzes the causes through which economicism has ended up
becoming the fundamental exponent of modernity, then the manner in which postmodernity has
adopted a nihilist drift and converged with economicism. Finally, I shall draw attention to a series
of proposals that could form the basis for a “new humanism” capable of overcoming the economicist
and nihilist drift and in which thinking and action would once again revolve around the
“human/non-human” axis. In other words, the possibility to state in intellectual terms what is “good”
for man as a counter argument to that which dehumanizes him drains him of his very being and
reifies him.
From the very appearance of the term, “modernity” has been intimately linked to the exigency
of “exactness”, of rigorous measurement [3]. This exigency has accompanied modernity throughout
the centuries, thereby constituting the key element in its epistemological horizon. Indeed, the
expression “modern” appeared for the first time (as Panofsky has stressed [4]) in the work of
the great painter and art historian Giorgio Vasari (1511–1574) to designate the new way of
painting paradigmatically as exemplified by Leon Battista Alberti (1404–1472) and Leonardo
da Vinci (1452–1519) and which was characterized by its scientificity as opposed to the maniera
antica of the classical painters or the maniera vecchia of the Byzantine artists.
Modernity came about in the Florence of the Medicis with the discovery of perspective
by Brunelleschi, around 1420, of what he called costruzione legittima. Modernity appeared when
the exigency of exactness present in the world of art was immediately copied in the scientific world,
and it would subsequently be offered as the paradigm of all forms of knowledge. The
“geometrization” (Euclidization) of art, which was introduced with perspective, would have
profound consequences in the realm of general thought: it increasingly attempted to undervalue
the oral in favor of the visual, the qualitative in favor of the quantitative or the analogical in favor
of the disjunctive. To each of these processes there corresponds a salient figure: Leonardo da
Vinci, Galileo and Descartes, respectively. I shall come back to this point, but I would first
like to analyze what perspective implies, not so much for the history of art, but rather for the
history of thought and vis-à-vis the conception of the world.
As Panofsky wrote in his book on perspective and in his book on the Renaissance, the
dimension of perspective implies the belief in space, which is at the same time infinite and
homogeneous. As he states: “Infinity is implicit in the fact that any set of parallel lines
independently of their place and direction, converge onto a single point of escape” [5]. This
was a new concept that had been introduced by Nicolas de Cusa and which was later developed
by Descartes.
The requirement of perspective (or put another way, the requirement of exactness) tended to
devalue the qualitative dimension of objects, favoring the exclusive consideration of distance over
their symbolic value. As Lewis Mumford was very sharp to grasp in his excellent book, Technics
and Civilization: “The space of the hierarchy of values was replaced by the system of magnitudes
109
[...]. Dimension no longer means divine or human importance but rather distance” [6]. This
depreciation of the symbolic and the qualitative explains how the rump of a horse can appear in the
forefront in Velázquez’s painting The Rendition of Breda, something that was unthinkable in the
pre-modern world.
Linked to this depreciation of the spatially qualitative is the reduction of the temporal sphere to
the instantaneous moment due to the coincidence between exactness and instantaneity. As Ortega y
Gasset points out, “Velázquez was determined to despotically set the point of vision. His entire
painting was born out of a sole act of vision and all things had to strive in order to be able to arrive,
as much as they possibly could, close to the visual line” [7]. This instantaneousness is the result of
the radical break between the subject and the object, which also produced the loss of direct contact
with things. This devaluation of the object is equally evident in Velázquez’s work, as was pointed
out in the book Velázquez y la Modernidad [8], constructed along the lines of Ortega’s intuition
mentioned above.
This unique perspective was based on the Euclidean reduction of geometry, the foundation of
Western modernity. Therefore, it is not surprising that multiple perspectives should have returned
to painting with the appearance of the new non-Euclidean geometries at the end of the nineteenth
century [9]. However, now, it was a matter of continuing to expound on the consequences of the
requirement of exactness within modern thought. This entailed, first of all, the shift away from the
oral in favor of the visual.
This shift found a privileged place within the thinking of Leonardo da Vinci (1452–1519),
the most brilliant artist of the different dimensions of design: painting, sculpture and architecture.
In Aphorism 326, he writes, “The eye is the most noble of all the senses”, since it is the sense that
grasps objects with the greatest exactitude, whereas the sense of hearing is very inferior given its
greater imprecision. Leonardo enters into the old debate introduced by Simonides of Ceos and
Horatio on the hierarchy between poetry and painting, and he insistently stresses the superiority of
the latter over the former, because only painting is science. Poetry is as fleeting as the auditory
sensations, whereas visual sensations, according to him, are not fleeting [10].
As Kristeller [11] points out, this hegemony of the design arts, which would be unified by the
very inventor of the word “modern”, Vasari, is responsible for the disenchantment of the world,
which has been accompanying modernity since its origins (supposing the latter is capable of being
comprehended in its deepest origin) and which only appeared in its decline (when this radical
penetration was missing). Indeed, the sacred in its unveiling is fundamentally united to the sense of
hearing, since God can never be seen, whereas He can be heard. The rationalization form of knowledge
leads to the profanation of reality: everything can be seen and therefore there is nothing sacred, as
Max Weber so rightly pointed out in his Wissenschaft als Beruf: “Everything can be dominated by
means of calculus and foresight” [12].
A further step in this modernizing process can be appreciated in the work of Galileo (1564–
1642), for whom there is a shift from the qualitative to the quantitative, which accelerates the
homogenization of reality. As he points out in his book, Il saggiatore [13], it is necessary to
establish a radical separation between objective realities, which are susceptible to being known
with exactness, such as numbers, figures, magnitudes, positions and motion, and what can only be
110
known subjectively and approximately, such as sounds, tastes and smells. Maintaining Leonardo’s
thesis, Galileo stresses that the senses of hearing, touch and taste cannot provide rigorous knowledge,
but rather only confused and ambiguous knowledge, which is not worthy of being considered as
scientific in nature.
In his excellent and short article “From the world of the “more or less” to the horizon of
exactitude” [14], Alexander Koyré called attention to the important role that technical discoveries
played in this process, such as the appearance of mechanical clocks, which enabled the exact
measurement of time and the appearance of the telescope, in addition to the growing use of Arabic
numbers and algebra, as compared to the impossibility of carrying out exact calculations with
Roman numbers, given their complexity.
This entire process of modernization culminated in the work of the French philosopher René
Descartes (1596–1650), who systematized and made explicit all previous developments. His “clear
and distinct idea” is nothing else, but the dimension of exactness, which was being sought ever
since the Florence of the Medicis. In Descartes emerges the notion of subjectum, with his aim
towards certainty and the will of dominion, but closely linked to this, there is internal breakage and
laceration. Indeed, the requirement of exactness leads to the sole acceptation of univocal concepts
and to the elimination of analogous concepts in such a manner that the very subject appears to
be radically split in two: as res extensa subjected to space and geometry and as res cogitans, or
self-conscience, placed outside of space and time. “From that I knew that I was a substance the
whole essence or nature of which is to think, and that for its existence there is no need of any place,
nor does it depend on any material thing; so that this ‘me,’ that is to say, the soul by which I am
what I am, is entirely distinct from body, and is even more easy to know than is the latter; and even
if the body were not, the soul would not cease to be what it is” [15].
The most immediate and intimate reality, the psychosomatic unity of the human person, is an
insuperable aporia in Descartes’ work, starting from disjunctive and exact thought, which denies
analogy. Descartes, in effect, felt obliged to solve this aporia, either by resorting to the supernatural
explanation according to which body and soul would be like two clocks simultaneously handled
by God or else in a more contradictory fashion according to the remainder of his philosophy by
suggesting (in his letter of 28 June 1643, to Princess Elisabeth de Bohéme ([15] t. III, p. 43)) that
time is better spent talking and resting, since thinking would only be capable of making one aware
of the opposition between body and soul, but not of their relationship.
Throughout the modern period, univocal and exact thought as axes of thinking generated a
number of unresolvable dilemmas as regards the individual and society. Indeed, the demand for
identity and rejection of analogy and complementarity would end up declaring certain essential realities
as incompatible once considered from a disjunctive perspective. From this disjunctive thinking, it
was affirmed both the negation of identity of the individual in opposition to God (nominalism,
Luther) and the negation of God in opposition to human reality (Marx, Nietzsche and advocates of
atheism). Furthermore, other false disjunctives were raised: between the individual and society,
opening the way to radicalism in individualistic and collectivist doctrines; between obligation and
happiness, the sources of puritanism and hedonism, respectively; and various others [16]. This
dislocation of the world resulting from thinking in terms of identity-opposition and not in terms of
111
The shift from the oral to the visual, from the qualitative to the quantitative and from the
analogical to the disjunctive, led to the devaluation of the aspects related to culture and politics in
favor of strictly economic aspects, which then came to be considered as the basis of civilization.
This can be seen by analyzing the inversion, which has been preached within modernity concerning
human relationships, as they had been studied by Aristotle in his Nichomachean Ethics and in his
Politics ([3], pp. 25–34).
Aristotle, in his Politics, established a hierarchy of human needs according to their importance
and duration, giving rise to the distinction between politics and economics. The former referred
to the highest order of needs, those related to “good living” and which touch on the need a human
being has for recognition, immortality or permanence in memory. Such needs are usually attained
by the exercise of the spoken word, since a human being is the only animal who has the power of
speech [17].
Economics, whose etymological root is underlined by Aristotle, refers to the nómos of the oikós,
of the home, and its primary focus is not so much relationships between people, but rather relationships
between people and things. What is important here is the satisfaction of basic human needs, in this
case either of a strictly biological and ephemeral nature on a daily basis, such as food, or something
more cultural and stable, such as clothing and shelter. The basic activity that characterizes economics
is utilization or usage (crea), and what Aristotle ponders in this sense is essentially care, good
administration (“household management”), as he argued in Nichomachean Ethics [18]. From this, it
follows that economics should so clearly appear to be linked to ecology and to the correct use of
things for the satisfaction of needs. Equally, economics thus understood appears as a presupposition
for politics. Without a minimum of goods, it is impossible to practice virtue. Without resources, as
regards food, clothing and shelter, there is no room for thinking about recognition or aspiring to be
remembered, except by inadequate means.
Chrematistics is quite distinct from politics and economics; its focus is to acquire and potentially
accumulate goods by means of commerce ([17], 1256a–1257a). As compared to what happens in
economics, the fundamental concept is not the “use value”, the worth of a thing measured in terms
of satisfying human needs, but rather the “exchange value”, the purchasing power a thing has to
enable one to acquire other things. Aristotle distinguishes between “retail chrematistics”, which can
be justified in order to acquire goods necessary for survival, and “wholesale chrematistics”, which
arises when the aim of augmenting one’s goods and money has overreached the mere satisfaction
112
of such things as are necessary to commodious living; and a Hope by their Industry to obtain them” [22].
Hobbes’s political philosophy, by making fear of death and the profit motive the mainstay of social
stability, offers a completely inverted view of classical political philosophy, which was based on
freeing man from fear and searching for the common good [23]. In any case, what was to be an
almost unanimous view among the authors of the period was the proposal that sustains fostering the
so-called pacific and benevolent passions, among which the profit motive is given a prominent
position (and the free commerce that facilitates this), to ward off the danger of pernicious passions,
above all the thirst for power and sexual libido. All of them came to state that the search for personal
profit is enormously beneficial for the stability of the political community, in that it corrects the
principal defect in man: fickleness, as Machiavelli reveals in Chapter 17 of The Prince. In short,
the search for financial profit accordingly appears as the best and most appropriate means by
which to engender the stability and well-being of the political community ([21], p. 89).
Consequently, the desire to accumulate wealth (traditionally called greed) was no longer
considered to be harmful and pernicious (a vice), typically associated with people who were
detestable (the miser is a proverbial figure in literature) and was now considered to be a beneficial
passion: one which guarantees the protection of interests, “self-interest”. This new way of seeing the
profit motive gave rise to a profound change in the mentality: to pursue “self-interest” becomes the
inescapable premise of rationality, and those who do not pursue or defend self-interest do not act
rationally and ostracize themselves from society. However, in the context of a society expressed in
terms of the market, to defend self-interest means maximizing profit (financial profit) in all acts.
It was Bernard Mandeville, with the publication in 1714 of this famous work, The Fable of the
Bees [24], who first gave form to this conceptual change (seventy years before Adam Smith
developed his theory of the “invisible hand”), claiming that the general good emerges from private
vices (such as greed), because the market converts the pursuit of personal interests into well-being
for everyone (each person gets what they are looking for). This mentality impregnates all thinking in
modernity and results in defining human beings in terms of their relationship with the market: in
other words, like the homo faber: “the subject who produces in order to exchange”. The definition of
man as a “being who exchanges”, put forward by Adam Smith, becomes paradigmatic: “Nobody
ever saw a dog make a fair and deliberate exchange of one bone for another with another dog” [25].
This meant a profound change compared to the anthropological conception found in classical
philosophy: the essence of what is human no longer lies in the order of being and is now displaced
to the order of doing, the capability to create things that are not consumed, but rather used and
exchanged. Benjamin Franklin was to define this in more precise terms: “Man is a tool-making
animal” [26]. In other words, what is truly valuable is that which has a market value, which can be
exchanged, i.e., which has “exchange value”. The general acceptance of this proposal converts the
market into the center of social life and the mainstay of political action.
This hegemony of the market also had major repercussions for the triumph of the formalist
conception of law. In an instrumentalist world that gives exclusive value to tools, it is logical that
law only appears as justified to the extent that it can become yet another tool; that is, a means that
serves different ends (in this case, at the service of the market). Economicism thus drains law of
any rational and ethical reading of law and changes it into an instrument at the service of the class
114
that represents the development of the economy: the bourgeois economy. Adam Smith was most
explicit when he claimed that the presence of what is legal can only be justified in terms of the
defense of the owners against those who could potentially subvert their property. We can read this
in his The Wealth of Nations that: “Civil government, so far as it is instituted for the security of
property is, in reality, instituted for the defense of the rich against the poor, or of those who have
some property against those who have none at all” ([25], Book III, chap. 2).
The primacy and exaltation of self-interest was also to result in investing in a moral ranking
of wealth. In effect, classical thinking always defended the superior ethical value of poverty—to
have the goods that are necessary for subsistence and to forgo what is superfluous to one’s
needs—proposing this as an ideal life from the stoics to Christianity [27]. The economicist
conception of modernity proposes the very opposite: wealth is the ideal in life. The result of the
subsequent influence of protestant thinking was to bestow wealth with a religious dimension, as
illustrated by Max Weber, converting it into a sign of divine predilection [28]: the rich have been
blessed by God, while the poor have been punished and repudiated and only deserve to be scorned.
The poor are wretched. Those who do not have goods end up losing their dignity and being ostracized.
The wealth motive also ends up shedding its religious connection and secularizes itself ([28],
p. 69) and, with it, liberating the market from all ethical ties. It was the neo-classical school towards
the end of the 19th century that coined the model of the homo oeconomicus with which the
economy finally divorced itself from ethics, identifying rationality as maximizing profit. This is a
profit that has progressively become more calculable and predictable with the increasing use of
mathematics in the economic sciences [29]. Therefore, personal interest and personal profit are
consolidated as the most relevant motives of human action, whose legitimation lies in the belief
that the egotistical behavior of everyone will lead to general prosperity.
This independence of the market with respect to ethics constitutes, precisely, the foundation of
the modern science of political economy, a term that was rediscovered in the seventeenth century
by Antoine de Montchrétien. However, the usage of this term is inappropriate, since for all intents
and purposes, this “new science” is nothing other than the theory of trade and money, that is to
say simple chrematistics. Its method is that of arithmetic, as pointed out in the title of the important
work by Sir William Petty, Political Arithmetic (1676): only the visual and the quantitative count,
that which can be measured and counted; the rest is repudiated [30].
This quantitative paradigm implies important consequences vis-à-vis the vision of human beings
and in their relationships with nature. Firstly, the negation of differences and hierarchies among
human needs leads to confusion between real needs and unbridled desire. This originates the
conception of man as homo oeconomicus. What counts is the indefinite enrichment of individuals,
since the well-being of society will be generated thanks to the famous “invisible hand” of which
bourgeois economists have been incessantly speaking since Adam Smith and which is nothing
other than the ideological and profane utilization of the idea of Christian Providence aimed at banishing
the sentiment of compassion in view of the surrounding poverty. With the absence of a hierarchy
among human necessities and by not appreciating anything except what is visible, accumulation
becomes an instrument to attain an impossible and pathetic immortality: “[The] Modern individual
cannot support economic equality because he has no faith in his own transcendence, in the symbols
115
of spiritual immortality; only physical value can provide him with liberation from death” [31].
Thus, accumulation appeared as the remedy for recognition.
As said earlier, the extent to which what is valuable is determined by “exchange value” means
that all things finally lose their intrinsic value and are reduced to their monetary value. This produces
a relationship between the subject and things, which is no longer based on ethical considerations—a
good or bad choice—but rather, based exclusively on chrematistic considerations: more or less
profit. The conception of the homo oeconomicus means precisely excluding all references to ethics
and all value judgments from the sphere of choice by the subject and to identify rationality with
decisions leading to maximizing profits. Adam Smith explains it in the following terms: “In all
countries where there is a tolerable security, every man of common understanding will endeavor to
employ whatever stock he can command, in procuring either present enjoyment or future profit. If
it is employed in procuring present enjoyment, it is a stock reserved for immediate consumption.
If it is employed in procuring future profit, it must procure this profit either by staying with him, or
by going from him. In the one case it is a fixed, in the other it is a circulating capital. A man must
be perfectly crazy, who, where there is a tolerable security, does not employ all the stock which he
commands, whether it be his own, or borrowed of other people, in some one or other of those three
ways” ([25], Book II, chap. 1).
The underlying idea that governs the behavior of homo oeconomicus is strictly as follows: those
who do not maximize their profits (increase their earnings) are “perfectly crazy”. Additionally, this
maximizing can be quantified strictly in economic magnitudes: either through savings, accumulation or
exchange. “Intelligent” (rational) decisions always lead to maximizing the profits of certain individuals,
who are both egotistical and calculating. The problem lies in the fact that the homo oeconomicus
model, reductionist by definition, was conceived for the study and research of the behavior of
individuals in an exclusively economic context. However, modernity extends this model to include
all human reality and takes for granted that everything humans do only makes sense “in” and “for”
the market, and the basis for this rationality is predominantly economic and not ethical [32].
When utilitarian philosophy intruded into the sphere of economic analysis, it took this somewhat
rudimentary interpretation of human behavior and raised it to the category of scientific analysis. In
effect, the principle of utility proposed by Jeremy Bentham (“the greatest happiness of the greatest
number”) and his proposal for a new ethic based on “maximum pleasure and the minimum degree
of pain” (good is equated with what is useful, and useful with what increases pleasure and minimizes
pain) diverted the analysis of rational behavior towards a calculation of utility, that is, towards
pondering the consequences of each decision: “Nature has placed mankind under the governance of
two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as
well as to determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and wrong, on the
other the chain of causes and effects, are fastened to their throne. They govern us in all we do, in all
we say, in all we think” [33].
From this viewpoint, those who are rational are those who make decisions in terms of
“opportunity cost”: each option (to be here or there, work on this or that) inherently and simultaneously
entails some gain and some loss. Therefore, those who are utterly rational are those who know how
to choose, in terms of opportunity that which provides them with greater utility (maximum welfare
116
and minimum suffering) between the various options possible. Maximizing utility thus becomes a
criterion with a much greater bearing to justify rational decisions, although translating this into
strictly economic terms continues to be a maximum profit and minimum cost as regards both
production, as well as consumption of goods. In this way, the market not only makes this possible,
but also forces individuals as regards their welfare to opt for a maximizing behavior. If the individual
acts otherwise, this results in marginalization.
With the introduction of the utility calculation, economicism definitively excludes all moral
references to human behavior and manages to reduce decisions to chrematistic terms, even those
that are not directly in pursuit of economic profit, for example, desire for recognition, charity,
altruism, the search for glory, honor, etc., since the economic agent can be assigned utility for
behavior that pursues these variables. In effect, utility translated into terms of maximizing pleasure
can be achieved by owning goods, as well as divesting oneself of them. The determining factor is
the amount of welfare that it produces for the subject. Those who commit suicide maximize because
they value death more than life; the acetic values the simple life over consumption, whereas the
monk values silence more than communication, etc.
The end result of reducing all reality to a calculation of utility also includes human beings
themselves. This is how Gary Becker (Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences) saw it when he analyzed
the behavior of the family in these terms, proposing that children should be considered “long-term
consumption goods” that produce utility; the most expensive are those of a higher quality and
facilitating their exchange [34]. In short, the explanation of human behavior from the premise of
a rational agent that acts by maximizing its utility, however this may be interpreted, eliminates
all manner of moral conception of human nature and opens the door to nihilism, which would be
hallowed in the post-modern period. If we take a classic example, the decision to produce “canons
or butter” (an entirely banal question) no longer belongs to the terrain of moral deliberations, but
rather to the market. Put another way, the decision is qualified as rational to the extent that it
responds to the calculation of utility designed to maximize well-being benefits. This is why the
market (in the positive sense) ends up being qualified as a neutral mechanism; that is, something
that is desirable not for ethical reasons, but rather for “technical” reasons, since it guarantees all
individuals Pareto optimality.
The very idea of homo oeconomicus—the conception of human life as something that only has
meaning in terms of the individual procurement of monetary gain—assumes that it is the rhythm of
production, and nothing else, that guarantees the appropriate organization of society. Usage has
no value, only exchange does. This form of social organization uses “exactness” as its model. The
motto of the modern organizer is that society has to work like clockwork. From this, as Schumacher
has pointed out, “the ideal of industrial Modernization would be to eliminate what is alive,
including human life, and to transfer the production process to machines since these can work with
greater precision and can be wholly programmed, whereas this cannot be done with people” [35].
However, in the meantime, while we have to continue relying on human labor, this work has to be
regulated to the fullest. This gave rise to Chesterton’s pointed remark that, “the modern planner is
only concerned with workers in the same way as with clocks: when they stop” [36]. However, this
concern is limited to voluntary slow-downs or strikes and not extended to forced lay-offs or
117
unemployment, since the latter is increasingly contemplated as a requirement of the system itself and
needed to avoid greater break-downs.
Exactness, the condition of growth, generates (along with the concentration of capital) a
detrimental effect on human beings. This can be observed especially in two spheres: the rupture of
the balance between science and art, between work and leisure; and in the rupture between
production and consumption. The first harmful effect can be seen by reading the works of Claude
Henri de Saint-Simon (1760–1825), who is the prototype technocratic organizer. In his various
writings, and most especially in his Industrial System, Saint-Simon points out the opposition between
the useful work of scientists, engineers, bankers and industrial workers, who increase wealth by
directly satisfying economic interests, and the useless work of parasites, such as philosophers,
theologians or jurists, which is solely guided by sentiments and which limits itself to reproducing
wealth, but without increasing it. Thus, whereas the former are good for something clear and precise,
the latter are lost in empty realities [37]. Saint-Simon proposes conceding power to engineers and
bankers, so that they can fight to eradicate all useless activities and favor imposing productive
work. Their mandate would be beneficial, because their interests coincide with the interests of the
collectivity ([37], p. 1044). It is a matter of having them, through their stimulus, convert society
into an authentic “megamachine” dedicated to production. This would entail the increased division
of labor, prescribed from Smith onwards, and a substantial increase in the number of working days.
As Mumford recalls, until the beginning of the eighteenth century, more than half of the days of the
year were feast days [38].
The other harmful effect would be produced between the model of the producer and the model
of the consumer. This was developed by Alvin Toffler: “The same person who as a producer was
spurred along by his family, his school and his boss to renounce to gratification, to be disciplined,
controlled, restrained, obedient, to be a member of a team, was equally spurred along as a consumer
to seek immediate gratification, to do away with discipline, to seek his own individual pleasure, in
a word to be a completely different type of person” [39].
This contradiction of the “modern world” is due to its incapacity to distinguish between two
realities that are apparently closely related, although, in fact, they are quite different: “poverty” and
“misery”. This distinction has been sketched with incomparable vigor by Charles Péguy himself
in “De Jean Coste”. Poverty, akin to Horatio’s paupertas, would be the state in which one would
have enough to live, without luxury, but with decorum. It is a type of purgatory that makes human
beings understand their limits and opens them to love and care for others. Misery, akin to Horatio’s
egestas, is, on the contrary, a true hell that one lives through in a state of authentic despair with
regard to tomorrow and from which it is urgent to free mankind [40].
Modernity is not capable of understanding this distinction due to its quantitative characteristic
based on the criterion of “sufficiency” to satisfy needs. It can only distinguish between having
a lot, wealth, a model to be emulated, and having little, a model to be avoided. This indifference
regarding the distinction between poverty and misery impedes the struggle against the roots of the
main present-day type of economic marginalization, unemployment, since it refuses to see this
problem as the result of the lack of solidarity and the unjust distribution of both income and the number
of working hours. In this manner, the new technologies serve to increase the misery of those who
118
cannot supply anything else but the “labor of the body”, which is disdained as something unnecessary.
Economicism tends to reduce the dimension of need to the sphere of economic resources. It has
also caused the devaluation of “caretaking”, in accordance with the primacy of chrematistics. This
is very closely linked to what has become known as “sexism”: the lack of consideration for tasks
that were historically entrusted to women. These tasks were directly related to configuring and
protecting humanity in its dimensions of greatest indigence, and therefore, they were of capital
importance. However, due to their lack of exchange value, they were considered inferior.
In the devaluation of caretaking, there is also the conception of human beings as homo labilis:
the tendency to not see life as anything else but the occasion for immediate pleasure and, therefore,
shunning anything that could imply abnegation, dedication or sacrifice vis-à-vis others. This
hedonism, so closely linked to the chrematistic mentality, at best favored the bureaucratizing of
such caretaking, shutting it up in more or less comfortable ghettoes and leaving the radical indigence
of the human condition on the fringe out of range from social visibility.
The failure of “economicism” was already underlined by Fritz Shumacher in his most famous
book, Small is Beautiful, published in 1973 with the significant subtitle: A Study of Economics As If
People Mattered [35]. After the publication of his posthumous book, A Guide for the Perplexed [41],
the value of his thinking became more striking. What is most fascinating about Schumacher’s
contribution lies in the courage with which he confronts the modern theories of the economists who
consider the extension of the market to be a solution for all problems, whereas Schumacher stresses
that the market itself is the source of the basic insufficiencies of modernity: “The market only
represents the surface of society and its meaning refers to a momentary situation, such as it exists
here and now. There is no deep delving into the essence of things or into the natural facts that lie
behind them. In a certain sense, the Market is the institutionalization of individualism and of
irresponsibility” ([35], p. 44).
Schumacher stresses that the greatest limitation of the market paradigm lies in its eradication of
the qualitative, provoking important consequences in the comprehension of human affairs: “In the
market, for practical reasons, there is the suppression of innumerable qualitative distinctions that
are of vital importance for individuals and society and that are not allowed to come to the surface.
Thus does the reign of quantity celebrate its triumph in the Market. There everything is made equal
to the rest. To make things equal means to give them a price and to make them interchangeable. To
such a point is modern thought based upon the Market that what is sacred (the person) is eliminated
from life because there can be nothing sacred in something that has a price” ([35], p. 46).
The current cultural situation continues to distinguish itself by the extraordinary influence of
post-modern discourse, in its most decadent version, as a response to the (still open) debate on the
crisis of modernity and whether the fundamental theses of the Enlightenment are still applicable:
the absolute rationalization of the world and society by means of science, indefinite and irreversible
historical progress, revolution as a fundamental method for liberating peoples and individuals,
liberal democracy as the definitive form of political organization and the market as a guarantee of
general well-being. The postmodern refutation of the Enlightenment thesis claims that, on the basis
119
of historical evidence, none of these prophetic expectations have been fulfilled. In contrast, the
magnitude of the “perverse” effects caused are such that, on balance, the 20th century is a far cry
from being qualified as the most positive in human history. This explains the scope and degree of
deception expressed in postmodern thinking [42].
However, it is not that easy to reconcile this theoretical verification of the failure of modernity
with the present-day spectacle of uninterrupted technological progress and the omnipresent market
that facilitate and promote an opulent life-style in the West and a fascinating array of artistic and
cultural movements of all kinds. The most lucid hermeneutics of this apparent contradiction is
perhaps that posed by the anthropologist and sociologist, Arnold Gehlen [43], and which could be
summarized as follows: the premises of Enlightenment are dead, but their consequences live on.
The name he gives to this is “crystallization”. Put another way, the two fundamental consequences
of modernity live on, technological progress and the market. However, there has been an absolute
disconnection between both realities and the common principles to which they responded in the
premises of enlightened thinking: achieving the moral progress of humanity; and the definitive
emancipation of the human being.
In effect, widespread education and culture has not brought about a greater understanding
between individuals and peoples (nobody now thinks that the sapere aude promotes the total
emancipation of mankind). In politics the liberal democratic and bureaucratic socialism systems are
preserved, because they have managed to generate functional systems, entirely regardless of their
meager power of conviction. The sciences and technologies find themselves confined within a
non-modifiable system subject to techno-structure, but separated from their vital aspirations. We
continue to see that, despite the immense scientific work in recent decades, they have not produced
one single innovation comparable to those by Max Planck, Einstein or Heisemberg. It is only in the
field of human biology and cybernetics where there have been substantial advances, but under an
ambivalent and disquieting cloud (the manipulation of the genetic basis of humans and loss of
intimacy). Finally, in the areas of artistic and cultural production, the last significant contributions
date to around 1910; but this process of subjectivization of art has already fulfilled its main
expressive potential. There is not even room to speak today of “avant-garde”, because now there
are no longer advances in anything, nor a resistance to make a break. According to Gehlen, we
would have entered into post-history ([43], pp. 322–23).
From the context of this post-history state of affairs of consequences without principles
(disconnection between technology-market-culture and humanist values) emerges the story that has
made the deepest impression on the spirit of Western Europe: that offered by thinkers labelled
“post-modern”. This is a thinking that rises up against the hegemony of all-embracing, utilitarian
and instrumental reasoning, but does not do so from an alternative rationality, but rather from a vital
experience; that is, it acts as a spokesperson for a feeling of disenchantment, from the deception
experienced by man today in light of the failure of enlightened rationality and, with it, the definitive
failure of reason. Post-modernity, as stated by Lyotard [44], rather than a current of thought, is a
“sensibility”; that is, an experience that has been forged in the heat of the profound cultural crisis
fanned by the decline of enlightened reasoning. In this disenchantment and post-modern skepticism
in the face of reason, two contributions fundamentally converge: that begun by the Italian aesthetes
120
(Vattimo, Castoriadis) and that which originated from the French post-structuralists (Barthes,
Baudrillard, Deleuze, Derrida, Foucault and Lyotard). Although both movements, in their attempts to
prevail over modernity base themselves on anti-humanist and nihilist proposals, it proves paradoxical
that they finally take up (surely to their regret) the two most significant elements of modernity,
techno-science and the market, and integrating them into this so-called “post-modern sensibility”. As
will be explained later, the former openly focus on techno-scientific reality, even as a path towards
post-humanism. For their part, the French post-structuralists incorporate economicist logic implicitly
by reducing the subject to the pure irrationality of desire and reality to a pure fragment.
Postmodern sensibility states that modernity has not only generated disappointment at a
theoretical level, but also great practical disappointment, hence its utter failure. Modern reasoning,
which was hailed as the salvation of humankind and the means for man to achieve happiness, after a
century of hegemony, has revealed itself to be dominating, enslaving and destructive for humankind.
Seen from its technical dimension, it has created machines of destruction; and from its theoretical
dimension, it has abetted in the legitimization of any kind of ideology and means, as long as it
reaches its ideals, or variations of these. We are not looking at the practical failure of a sound ideal;
instead, we have arrived at the necessary and inevitable consequences of theory, since Enlightenment
is none other than theoretical domination, which becomes technical domination. Put another way, the
failure of modern reasoning is not due to the fact that the means chosen are wrong, but rather that the
very dynamics of modern reasoning have generated these consequences due to its mistaken and
paranoid attempt to dominate and subjugate all reality ([44], p. 22).
Postmodern sensibility confirms this “cultural climate”, which reflects disenchantment in the
face of the failure of scientific and technical reasoning that has dominated the modern world and is
committed to dislodging this “all-embracing reasoning” from its hegemony over reality. Along
these lines, it proposes adopting an anti-enlightenment approach, which it has no reservations in
qualifying as anti-humanist, subordinating the subject to a process of “deconstruction” “unmaking”.
Think well, feel well, act well, according to this “episteme of unmaking”, means rejecting the
tyranny of totalities, because totalization in any human endeavor is potentially totalitarian [45].
To fight against totalizing reasoning basically means to fight against the subject that it has forged.
In effect, post-modernity expresses an ontological rejection as regards the subject produced by
Western philosophy and rooted in Cartesian “cogito”, understanding that this is the artifice of
instrumental, totalizing and dominating rationality; it is the subject of the “will to power” hailed by
Nietzsche. This is the subject that the humanism of modernity has placed as the center and absolute
reference of oneself. To de-construct this subject necessarily involves adopting an anti-humanist
position, because, as Gianni Vattimo states, in postmodernity, man is no longer the center; he is
heading towards an unknown, towards “X”, or rather he is heading nowhere ([2], p. 23). In effect, it
is humanism itself that has brought about the dehumanization of man: either because it has eclipsed
humanist ideals in favor of man dominated by rationally productive techniques or because it has
bureaucratized everything in social and political organization [46]. Olwald Spencer (1918) and later
Ernst Jünger (1932) already admitted that our civilization was in decline given that our activities are
121
no longer those of creation, typical of an early age, but rather those of technical, scientific and
economic organization, which culminate in the establishment of a domination, which, when all is
said and done, ends up being military ([44], p. 16). Heidegger himself, in his famous Letter on
Humanism (1947), argues that the disenchantment of the world, its enslavement in the direction of
technics and the servitude of humanitas towards mercantile rationality are not attacks against
humanism, but rather the outcome of humanism itself; the uprooting of all that is natural for that which
is cultural, the will of human rationality to dominate completely what is real [47].
This deconstruction process of the subject requires the dissolution of the foundation and,
consequently, abandoning humanism. In effect, both in technics, as well as in metaphysics or in
humanism, one always discovers a search for the foundation upon which reasoning is built and which
is arrived at through reasoning. All said and done, any attempt and search for foundation is nothing
more than the affirmation of metaphysics, and this always generates violence and domination. Here
lies the error of humanism, having assigned man the role of a conscious subject; that is, a foundation
of himself. This is why Vattimo states in clear terms that postmodernity means absence of foundation;
the definitive prevailing over metaphysics, without having to feel remorse. The crisis of modernity is
not solved with criticism, or with a new foundation, or with a new humanism; the only solution is to
do away with all of them ([2], pp. 45–46). Heidegger’s anti-metaphysical position needs to be
interpreted along these lines: not as a humanist yearning to return to be what we have forgotten, but
rather as the history of a “long farewell to being”, of an never-ending weakening of being, of a
definitive prevailing over metaphysics. A radical “slimming of the subject” is a stage in the cure
for humanism. The subject is a mask, a transmitted fable. This is no longer important: it is
presence-absence in a society transformed more and more into a very sensitive organism of
communication. In short, we inhabit a world that is no longer true, that has become a fable, and
postmodern man has stopped being subject, has been left empty and has become a mask [48].
What postmodernity proposes is to promote what is human without a new humanism: “the
possibility to truly facilitate all the “other” possibilities which make up existence” ([2], p. 30). The
major values of humanism (being, truth, goodness, etc.) are fables, sagas, transmitted messages. One
does not have to continue interpreting fables as truths, but rather “live the fabled experience of reality,
and experience which is also our only possibility for freedom” ([2], p. 32). From here on, the door is
left open to nihilism, which does not attempt to exalt absolute, total or metaphysical nothingness, but
simply state the weakening of the founding being of traditional metaphysics. Vattimo defines this as
the “situation in which man abandons the center to head towards X” ([2], p. 21). Postmodern man is
nihilist, because he has understood that there is no meaning, there is no metaphysical foundation:
“nothing remains of being as such” ([2], p. 22).
Techno-scientific reality, however, has great interest for this anti-humanist postmodernity,
to the degree of considering it a powerful instrument for liberation and later self-construction of
postmodern man. Science is not a fetish that is erected as a sole and definitive knowledge of reality,
because then, “we would fall into the defects of metaphysics” [49]. Science must not set up fiction as
reality, but rather it should help us to recognize that reality is fiction. In effect, the techno-scientific
reality of the world, deprived of its dominating reasoning fetishist nature, takes on a liberating role,
because it allows man to conceive of infinite possibilities of making and being made. Postmodern
122
man (who Vattimo calls overman), who clearly belongs to the techno-scientific world, “finds in
science and in technics the framework of external security within which he can liquidate all the
structures, intimate and external, of domination” ([49], p. 142). In other words, science and technics
must be used by the overman to free himself from all conditioning, including biological and genetic
and, thus, escape the domination and subjugation that the structures of society have exercised over
him, which is a pure fable. As Gilbert Hottois pointed out [50], techno-science exhibits multiple
emancipating and diversifying aspects: a creativity of possibilities that allows the true realization of
the individual.
The well-known and controversial essay by the German professor, Peter Sloterdijk, Regulations
for the Human Park [51], works along this liberating affirmation line of techno-science. Originally,
it constituted a response to Heidegger’s Brief über den Humanismus (“Letter on Humanism” [47]),
on the fiftieth anniversary of its publication. The terms used in the text prove to be very revealing,
particularly when defining humanity as a “human zoo park” and when speaking of “domestication”
(Zahmüng) as the task of the new man, who must be like a “tamer of human beings”. Defining
himself as “simply Nietzschean”, he restricts himself to stating the failure of humanism and pointing
out a new scientific truth: the convenience of “a domestication of man by man” in which modern
genetics would play a decisive role. Therefore, we would find ourselves faced with a new man who
has to accept the new power he has over himself, namely biotechnology: the opportunity to reform
the properties of the species genetically. Furthermore, all of this is without this new man being
subject to a higher authority (God, fate, etc.) in the exercise of this new power. This new man has
little in common with Nietzsche’s overman. He has moved beyond questions of good and bad, not
out of disdain for the established order, but because this order has dissolved, and this can be very
clearly perceived in the area of new technologies. The new overman is the man of the new
technologies, especially biotechnology. With this, Sloterdijk assures us that this is not an attempt to
return to the Nazi eugenic techniques (he was obliged to clarify this point in response to harsh
criticisms). The issue that the man of biotechnology is overman means that faced with a technical
action, with no fixed regulatory limits, objectives or sufficient guidelines, there is only room for a
liberating dimension that is not subject to the metaphysical prejudices of good and bad ([51],
p. 19). Arguing along these lines, he speaks of “cold objective thinking” and not confusing the new
man with the worst Nietzschean vision of the overman (a kind of gigantic and carnivorous dominator),
but instead the individual who is able to come to terms with the absence of foundations. This man
is strong enough, as Nietzsche wrote in his Untimely Meditations, to “choose for himself his own
mask” in an indeterminate and pluri-cultural world [52].
As we can see, the anti-humanist orientation of postmodernity ends up drifting towards a
post-humanist conception, firmly upheld by defenders of the so-called “biolitical revolution” [53],
for whom the human species has become a concept that can be revised, if not obsolete. For
example, Tristam Engelhardt argues along these lines when he states that: “in the long term there is
no reason to think that only one species will come out of ours. There could be as many species as
there are opportunities to substantially remodel human nature in new environments as reasons to
refuse to do so” [54]. From post-humanist writers, others emerge from the perspective of relativism,
such as Richard Rorty [55], for whom we have to abandon the task of “establishing” supposed
123
truths in ontology, metaphysics or religion, as Nietzsche had already suspected. Contemporary man
has to go even further and renounce the idea that there are true or false answers to the questions we
ask ourselves. He states that: “it is very likely that human creativity could soon run out and that in
the future there is non-human world which eludes our endeavors to conceptualize” ([55], p. 178).
Gilbert Hottois [56] considers manifestations of human culture (history, art, philosophy, moral
values, etc.) to be nothing more than attempts to symbolize or “encode” a reality in movement.
Therefore, all concepts that accompany these attempts are relative, including the concepts of
humanity or the individual. The attempt to fix and impose one of these concepts is completely
contrary to techno-scientific development. What happens today is that philosophy can be seen as
impotent and incapable of symbolizing or “codifying” the techno-scientific universe. He even
speaks in ironic terms of the failure of deconstructive thinking (along the lines of Wittgenstein’s
linguistic games) to satisfactorily express being in the techno-scientific world ([56], pp. 112–20).
This is why he proposes substituting philosophy for techno-scientific research and development
linked to the market, since technics and money are the two major operators in the contemporary
world: “It is the techno-scientific actors that continually invent and produce the future. Reality is
de-constructed and re-constructed indefinitely under the sole driving force of technics and the
market” ([56], p. 123). “Symbolic orders and hierarchies emerge in the chaotic space of global
mercantile mobilization; they influence it for a given time and on a local basis, but cannot structure
it in a lasting manner nor stabilize it at a global level. The power, liberty or desire for exchange and
change know no limits” ([56], p. 159). Hottois ends by admitting that: “techno-sciences open up to
a functional transcendence of the species: they allow for effectively overcoming the natural limits
associated with the human condition.” ([56], p. 163). In short, the anti-humanism of postmodernity
has drifted into a post-humanism that has located the idea of techno-science in terms of the final
horizon of thinking. The refutation of all foundation has elevated science above itself to the point
of coming to be seen as a kind of substitute messiah, a “default” ideology for a post-human future.
The nihilist climate of postmodernity is particularly evident among the French post-structuralists
(Barthes, Baudrillard, Deleuze, Derrida, Foucault and Lyotard), whose thinking paradoxically (and
perhaps to their regret) contributes to consolidating the economicist logic of modernity, which is
discussed below.
Post-structuralism appeared in France in a climate of skepticism with regard to the possibilities
of “changing the world” after the two-fold failure in May 1968: student protest and the “Prague
Spring”. This skepticism was precisely the constituent cause of its scant originality (for authentic
creation to come about, a minimum of enthusiasm is required) and explains how inadequate its
attempts were to overcome modernity, given the fact that its approaches are narrowly linked to
modernity, as openly acknowledged by post-structuralists themselves.
The link between post-structuralism and modernity presents a two-fold dimension. First,
the epistemological dimension: the dissolution of truth in “text”, or in other words, the denial of
reality within the never-ending process of interpretation. Barthes and Derrida have insisted, more
than anybody else, upon this aspect. Second, the anthropological dimension: the dissolution of
124
However, postmodernity and Nietzsche himself (and, of course, post-structuralism), far from
opposing the logic of chrematistics, can be considered as a radical off-shoot of the same. Two of its
dimensions show this clearly.
The first of these dimensions refers to the primacy of the will and the subject’s power of
disposal, precisely the key to the emancipating message of Enlightenment. The novelty is to be
found in the fact that the emancipating dimension and the subject’s power of disposal have passed
from the world of property and things to the world of the body. The title-bearer of the right of
disposal is not so much the sui iuris, but rather the “child”, that is to say the unconscious, the desire.
There would be no hostility whatsoever vis-à-vis the emancipating ideology, but rather an extension
of the emancipating process of the desire. Voluntarism without barriers would lead to the (anti-)
Freudian ideal of the total liberation of impulses. What is disposable, and therefore in the ultimate
instance, what is alienable, far from being reduced, becomes extended. This unconditioned disposition
of the bodily would be taken advantage of by commercial interests.
The second aspect in which we can find chrematistic logic refers to the primacy of what is
fragmentary and what is disintegrated over what is global and whole. This was mentioned earlier
when pointing out the defense of schizophrenia, which was proposed as the sole remedy against
paranoia by Deleuze and Guattari, both of them following (in spite of themselves) the logic of
capitalism. However, it can be seen as the result of applying a scientific-naturalistic methodology
to the human being. The decadent view of the human being as something “worth very little”, which
appears in the post-structuralist writers, dissolves the notion of substance and cause and reduces
individual to a “succession of sensations”. All of this, however, was already to be found in
Hume [70].
The fragmentation of the person into successive instances would be, in turn, something that
was derived from the pure bourgeois spirit. According to Karl Marx (whilst submerging himself
wholesale in that same spirit), this tends to destroy all that is permanent by converting it into
the ephemeral and eliminating all that is sacred, thereby promoting the extension of indifference
within the human relationships. As Jameson points out, postmodernity coincides with the logic of
consumerism. In effect, the transformation of reality into images and the fragmentation of time
into a set of perpetual present moments are a replica or a reproduction of the logic of consumer
capitalism [71].
It is possibly in the sphere of politics where the unchanging and reactionary character of the
late modernist authors is better revealed. Politics is incapable of being understood by the
post-structuralists, among other things, due to their incomprehension of the institutional, which
derives from the primacy of the unconscious and the instantaneous. It is not at all a matter of only
criticizing those “institutions” (which would be perfectly legitimate), which from Goffman onwards
are designated as “total institutions” (prisons, psychiatric hospitals, military barracks), in which the
individual is totally molded, but rather a matter of casting aside all that is institutional, in so far as
it implies the category of “duration”. The juridical and the political would be pure repression, no
matter whether they are the fruit of individual arbitrations, reflection or a collective consensus.
Democracy turns out to be even more impossible in its two-fold appeal to the ‘given word’ and to
the ‘common good’. In effect, in agreement with Nietzsche, what is common to everyone is already
127
in itself something that cannot be good (“what is common is never a good” ([62], n. 43), and
therefore, the search for consensus is in itself negative. Therefore, democracy cannot be anything
except “decadence” and “self-deception” [72].
Both politics and art would be nothing other than simulation, mere fiction. However, politics
would be so in a deceptive, fraudulent manner, at least for the masses, whereas art would be so in a
declared manner. The pretension of the truth of politics is what makes it especially odious, whereas
art would be directly lived as a simple invention. Politics is nothing other than pure representation,
pure theatre. Representation as a simple game is inevitable, and it is absurd to be morally outraged
by it. The post-structuralists believe that we have unavoidably entered the age of the comedian, of
the clown, as Robert Musil had already pointed out in his Essays [73]. Additionally, in a more
or less cynical manner, they take part in this “sad spectacle” by means of their opacity, their
“logomachies” and their play on words. It is easily understood that elitism, the scorning of the
masses and submission to the consumer society characteristic of the post-structuralists, should have
been presented as the true postmodernity.
The gigantic echo reached by the post-structuralist authors in the Western World only
demonstrates the urgent need for a “change in human mentality” based on opening the door for a
“new humanism”; a new mode of thinking reality from a “non-economical perspective”.
As opposed to the nihilist trend employed by decadent postmodernity as an answer to the crisis
of modernity, there are two other important lines of thinking, which, from radically opposed
ideological positions, have attempted to offer a “humanist” response by re-affirming the identity
of the subject and of values as a basis for building a just, rational and human society. The first
concerns writers from the “Frankfurt School” who, following the ideological and methodological
lines of critical Marxism, proposed a change to the epistemological paradigm, which leans towards
reinstating enlightened reasoning as a primordial element for recovering the subject and the
humanity of the subject. The second concerns writers who have been labelled “neoconservatives”,
whose thinking, essentially focused on the area of culture, considers a strategy of recovering Western
spiritual values as a premise to re-incorporate a fragmented and disoriented society. Neither of
these two lines of thinking, in my view, has managed to propose a sufficiently solid front against
the relentless nihilist drift of Western societies under the indisputable primacy of technology
and market.
The most forceful attempt to confront a crisis of modernity comes from the Frankfurt School of
writers (C. Offe, A. Wellmer, J. Habermas, K.O. Apel), who continued along the lines of
“critical theory” begun by Max Horkheimer with the publication of this book Traditional and Critical
Theory [74]. “Critical theory” confirms the predominance of techno-scientific instrumental rationality
in contemporary societies, which, in the words of Marcuse, has produced a “one-dimensional man”
model, which has been reduced to a mere cog in the techno-economic wheels of capitalism and has
ended up being dominated by consumerism [75].
The dense compilation by Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment
(1947) [76] and the later work by Adorno Minima Moralia (1951) [77] were the culmination of this
128
relentless criticism aimed at scientific reasoning as the sole foundation of human knowledge and
practice that has taken place in the Western capitalist system. The critique of capitalism turned
into a critique of Western civilization as a whole. Indeed, the Dialectic of Enlightenment uses the
Odyssey as a paradigm for the analysis of bourgeois consciousness. In these works, Horkheimer
and Adorno introduced many themes that have come to dominate the social thought of recent years;
indeed, their account of the domination of nature as a central characteristic of instrumental rationality
in Western civilization was given long before ecological and environmental issues had become
popular concerns. The analysis of reason now goes one stage further. The rationality of Western
civilization appears as a fusion of domination and of technological rationality, bringing all external
and internal nature under the power of the human subject. In the process, however, the subject itself
is swallowed up, and no social force analogous to the proletariat can be identified that will enable
the subject to emancipate itself. Hence, the subtitle of Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged
Life [77].
The most current representative writer following this line of thinking is Jürgen
Habermas with his book The Theory of Communicative Action [78]. As is known, he believed
that modernity is an “unfinished project”, whose fundamental premises are still valid, but
whose consequences today must be purged of reductionisms caused by the undue hegemony of
instrumental rationality [79]. In the path of “critical theory”, Habermas states that technical
reasoning—instrumental or strategic reasoning—has been colonizing the other areas of human
rationality, turning into the raison par excellence. He states that all of the processes of the
“technification” of social life—politics, education, culture, etc.—illustrate the predominance of
instrumental reasoning and, in tune with Adorno and Horkheimer, confirm that the intrinsic logic of
“systemic” rationality is manipulation, the domination of the other by the other. The domination of
nature becomes the domination of some human beings over other human beings and, finally,
becomes a “nightmare of self-domination” ([79], pp. 151–59).
However, Habermas claims that the origin of the breakdown of modernity is not in rationalization
as such, but rather in the failure to provide a “balanced” development and institutionalization of all
of the dimensions of reasoning needed to understand the modern world. The solution, then, does
not consist of renouncing enlightened reasoning, but rather rehabilitating other dimensions, which
have been overlooked with the predominance of instrumental rationality. Emancipating projects
in themselves are not harmful for humanity, but rather only insofar as they are invaded by
manipulating and dominating reasoning. One has to “purge” this emancipating reasoning (“critical
reasoning”) from the manipulating bias of dominating reasoning, which should confine itself to its
specific sphere of domination and control of nature. In other words, each of these dimensions of
reasoning has to be linked to the specific interests pursued by human society. Put another way,
“knowledge” and “interest” need to be linked. Knowledge that is constructed (scientific-natural,
historical-sociological or philosophical-theological) has to be very closely related to interests
(domination, relationship or emancipation) present in society ([78], I, pp. 175–81).
On the one hand, modernity has turned scientific-natural knowledge, which is a response to the
interest in dominating nature, into knowledge par excellence, while relegating knowledge that
responds to interests concerning relations (social) and emancipation to a secondary role or (even
129
worse) identifying these relations in terms of the former model. Consequently, social interaction
and emancipation have been contaminated by unrelated knowledge and interests. The path that
leads to solving the problems of the world today depends on liberating socio-historical knowledge
and emancipating knowledge (and its corresponding practices) from a methodology and interests
that do not concern them. In other words, when it comes to relations and emancipation, there are
rational “alternatives”, which are not manipulating and dominating. Here, Habermas proposes
“communicative rationality”, which is based on a primary and shared use of language ([78], I,
pp. 264–65).
Therefore, how is market and economic rationality built into this framework? Habermas’s
answer is somewhat disappointing. Despite his critical posture, in the Marxist vein of confronting
capitalism, he settles for relegating economic rationality to the specific sphere of “market interests”,
seeing the market in terms of a “subsystem” that is developed on the fringes of communicative
rationality. However, other than being critical, he finds it difficult to explain how to confront the
reality of a market whose instrumental rationality constantly breaches the limits of the economic
framework. In effect, under the influence of N. Luhmann and particularly T. Parsons, Habermas
makes an approximation of the capitalist economy, conceiving of it as a subsystem ([78], II, p. 234).
Habermas’s thesis holds that in the early stages of modernity, Western European societies had to
confront a new systemic problem: material reproduction in a context of growing social complexity,
which made coordinating economic social action unfeasible through communicative action. The
mechanism that finally solved this problem was the institution of the capitalist market, which
emerged unintentionally from the interaction of monologically-oriented individuals. However, it
managed to achieve the status of an institution by making economic action and material reproduction
possible in the new context of a complex society ([78], II, p. 247). The market emerged as a neutral
mechanism coordinating individual economic actions, which were driven by egotistical self-interest.
In short, it can be seen as institutionalizing “instrumental action”, which proves functional for material
reproduction in complex societies. It thus constitutes a new level of collective learning for human
kind ([78], II, p. 249).
The capitalist market took shape in a process that could be described as natural. It did so by
“disengaging” itself from the “life-world” (culture and values) as a self-regulated subsystem and
by means of its own non-linguistic communication: money. This differentiation of the capitalist
economy as a subsystem, in turn, implies a restructuring of the State in systemic terms, as a
self-regulated subsystem working from the basis of “power”. However, for Habermas (particularly
in his later work, Between Facts and Norms [80]), the structuring of the State as a system, as
opposed to the capitalist economy, would need to build a political foundation through the prevailing
channels of democratic legitimation in modern societies. Habermas’ diagnostic is that the economic
subsystem, once differentiated from the “life-world”, tends to transcend its own limits (driven
by the capitalist class strategy to confront the working classes, as he somewhat hazily explains)
and project itself again over the “life-world” colonizing it. In other words, substituting “money” for
communicative action as a means of social integration ([78], II, pp. 465–89). This brings about
anomie, demoralization and loss of freedom, which can be seen in late capitalist societies already
studied by authors from a wide range of disciplines, such as E. Durkheim, M. Weber or Th.
130
Adorno. Habermas’ criticism is thus limited to stating the excesses of the capitalist market economy,
which has the tendency of going beyond its own sphere, coordinating instrumental action, and to
trespass areas where it is should be prohibited, namely, social integration through communicative
action. However, this is precisely the scenario in which we find ourselves: instrumental rationality,
which is emblematic of the market, has burst its banks, and neither has Habermas found the way to
hold it back, because money (the non-linguistic means of instrumental relations) proves to be
incompatible with communicative rationality, which is characteristic of the “life-world”.
Habermas’ proposal had already met resounding criticism in his first work published by his
disciple, Axel Honneth, The Critique of Power [81]. Honneth questions Habermas’ adoption of
basic suppositions of the systems theory, because to consider the economy as a subsystem cleanses
it of all political and moral components, idealizing it as a sphere, which is solely characterized by
its institutionalization and non-adherence to regulations and instrumental action ([81], p. 419).
Despite this characterization of the capitalist economy as a subsystem in functionalist terms, Habermas
tried to update the theses of Karl Marx and George Lukács concerning the inherent reification in
capitalism. The result was clearly unsatisfactory, as it bestowed upon the economic system a character
of non-adherence to regulations and the capability to govern itself, which placed it out of reach
from critical capacity of democratically constituted social will ([81], pp. 373–81). For Habermas,
the economic subsystem as such cannot be criticized or transformed by the politically organized
collective. All that is left is to question its excesses, its transgression of the limits placed on it (the
material reproduction of society and trespassing into areas that should remain off limits (symbolic
and social reproduction). That is, Habermas managed to make a topic of functional and structural
imperatives of the market economy at the cost of shielding them from any criticism and attempts to
in-depth transformation, by conceiving this economy model in systemic terms. In other words, in
terms of a consolidation that cannot be de-differentiated and furthermore neutral from the perspective
of regulations, and so, it cannot be set against any regulatory principles ([81], pp. 394–416). In
short, Habermas puts forward a kind of acritical theory of capitalism, since he is only theoretically
fit to question the excesses, but not its constitutive structure.
It is precisely for this reason that Habermas encounters problems integrating the globalization
phenomenon (with its multiculturalist and economicist reality) into the universalizing proposal of
communicative rationality. Habermas readily acknowledges the radical novelty of globalization in
The Postnational Constellation [82]. However, he does not accept the consequences that this
radical change of the economic, social and political context has for his theory of communicat ive
action, which is still designed as a contra-factual response to the challenges of social integration,
which arise from the “legitimation problems of late capitalism” [83].
As is well known, for Habermas, societies have to be conceived simultaneously as a “system”
(institutions, society) and as a lebenwelt “life-world” (the subjective world of values and culture),
which provides the regulatory resources to set the moral standards of the system. Communicative
action is what makes a point of rational connection possible (symbolic consensus) between the
“life-world” and the formal world of the “system” constituting a common objective with universal
pretensions ([78], I, pp. 179–80; [82], pp. 167–68). Habermas confirms the existence of a “world
system” along these lines. However, he also states that the globalization of the “system” does not
131
run parallel to an adequate social integration of the “life-world”. This proves to be extremely
problematic for his thesis. In effect, the enormous fragmentation of the “life-world” (multiculturalism)
obliges him to acknowledge that in the “world society”, there is a systemic formalization, but not a
social integration, which would provide identity. The result is an insurmountable dualism between
“communicative action” and “system” that is unable to explain multicultural social links, not only in
the global arena, but even in the national arena itself. In his theory, individuals and peoples who live
in real interaction are effectively situated in different societies and in different “evolutionary states”
to the degree that their “life-worlds” are different. However, this contradicts daily contemporary
experiences. In summary, the originality of the recent globalization tends to break with the
socio-evolutionary dynamic with which Habermas rationalizes both culture and society. Therefore,
in this new scenario, in which various cultures live together in various socio-evolutionary stages,
it is very difficult to conceive of communicative action producing social integration in the context
of a socio-evolutionary process of progressive rationalization of culture and society. Furthermore,
all of this does not take into consideration that the daily practice of social integration in first
world cultures tends more towards a kind of “pragmatic irrationalism” rather than towards a
socio-evolutionary process of rationalization.
Finally, as pointed out by Spaemann, his advocated methodology of “discussion free from
domination” (Herrschafstfreiheit), which hardly goes beyond the pragmatic plane, is based on the
fundamental categorization of the subject as pure relation. That is, communicative rationality ends
up incorporating a subject into the system whose “life-world” (identity) is totally available, since
the system favors consensus even above the subject itself: the discrepancy cannot easily be
integrated into the system [84]. Additionally, to state that the identity of the subject is something
that is substantially available does not constitute a very solid argument in the face of the nihilist
direction posed by the postmodernists.
The second line of alternative thinking to the nihilism of decadent postmodernity is that argued
by writers labelled as “neo-conservative” (neo-con), from the American arena. The intellectual
roots of the neo-con movement can be traced back to the 1940s, with writers, the majority of
Jewish origin, with a Marxist and Trotskyist background, such as Irving Kristol, Nathan Glazer,
Daniel Bell, Seymour M. Lipset, Daniel Patrick Moynihan, among others. Liberal Catholics also
joined the movement, such as William Bennett and Michael Novak, and then later, others, such as
P. Berger, Th. Lukmann and J.R. Neuhaus [85].
In the 1960s, neo-con thinking burst on to the scene grouped around the journal, The Public
Interest, founded in 1965 by Irving Kristol and Daniel Bell. It is in this publication that the neo-con
began to cloak the traditional conservative opinions of the language of the social sciences and took
up much of the theses of Leo Strauss, of Jewish origin and professor at the University of Chicago.
Strauss’ thinking is grounded in the idea that liberal democracy, with its emphasis on individual
liberties, has led Western societies into decadence and disaster. However, Strauss did defend liberal
democracy in the face of communism or fascism and publically aired his admiration for Churchill for
opposing these totalitarian regimes. Strauss was deeply concerned that the philosophical crisis of
modernity could undermine the Western world’s confidence in itself. This accounts for his insistence
on taking seriously and understanding the Western philosophical tradition [86].
132
Strauss taught that liberalism in its modern form contained within it an intrinsic tendency towards
extreme relativism, which, in turn, led to two types of nihilism. The first was a “brutal” nihilism,
expressed in Nazi and Marxist regimes. In On Tyranny [87], he wrote that these ideologies, both
descendants of Enlightenment thought, tried to destroy all traditions, history, ethics and moral
standards and replace them by force under which nature and mankind are subjugated and conquered.
The second type—the “gentle” nihilism expressed in Western liberal democracies—was a kind of
value-free aimlessness and a hedonistic “permissive egalitarianism”, which he saw as permeating the
fabric of contemporary American society [88]. In the belief that 20th century relativism, scientism,
historicism and nihilism were all implicated in the deterioration of modern society and philosophy,
Strauss sought to uncover the philosophical pathways that had led to this situation. The resultant
study led him to advocate a tentative return to classical political philosophy as a starting point for
judging political action [89].
For Strauss, the time had come for elite to rise up and prevail over the weakness and lack of social
cohesion caused by relativism induced by post-Socratic philosophy. The main tool employed by
these new elite would be an artificial mythology constructed around the notion that the United States
enjoyed a unique and well-established destiny in the control of the ignorant masses through
deception, religious fervor and perpetual war. This mythology, or “Straussian text”, would have
an “exoteric” meaning, accessible to the average reader, and another “esoteric” meaning, the true
meaning aimed at its real target readers, namely the social hierarchy. For Strauss, the rebirth of
modern societies had to be led by a caste of apt politicians prepared to spread these myths with
conviction, the purpose of which was to furnish the lives of the ordinary people with purpose and
meaning. In this enterprise, these politicians should back themselves up with absolute moral or
religious values, so as to snatch society from the grips of relativism. A good politician, however, did
not necessarily have to believe in these values, even those religious ones; appearances would
suffice ([88], pp. 23–29).
One consequence of this proposal is reflected in the adoption of “American exceptionalism” as
a political principal. This was a concept that had already been developed by Alexis de Tocqueville
in Democracy in American and that for neo-con thinking constitutes a profound influence on
American national identity, on occasions linked to the conviction of a providential destiny. In effect,
the exceptionalism historically has been influenced by a messianism, both religious (God is on our
side), as well as secular (our values and institutions are the best). As a consequence, the neo-cons
legitimized the moral imperative of spreading this message to the rest of the world on the basis of this
exceptionality of values and the American political system [90,91].
While neo-con thinking is mainly occupied with theorizing about foreign policy, its approach to
economics leaves no room for doubt: free market and the development of capitalism, although
without adopting the thesis of Hayek’s radical neoliberalism, which entirely excludes all forms of
public intervention in questions of the well-being of citizens [92]. His economic thinking lies in the
separation between morality and market: the correct functioning of the market is based on the
existence of strong moral convictions in individuals; but morality has to be looked for outside of the
market and is only found in tradition. The market must provide individuals with material goods in an
efficient manner, but lacks a moral criterion that can guide them along the right path in order to
133
satisfy their needs. The market is only part of human life, but proves fundamental, because the
breakdown of the market causes social disintegration [93].
In effect, neo-con thinkers maintain the market principle as their main point of reference, that is
the free exchange of goods is the principal factor for progress and social development. However,
they point out that the capitalist system is not altogether good, because it is going through a
“spiritual crisis” that is causing the breakdown of society. The fundamental ill of this system is the
“liquidation” of ethics; in the elimination or disappearance of the traditional values that sustain the
capitalist economy. This “liquidation” of ethics has resulted from a profound cultural crisis linked
to currents in postmodernism that propose styles of life that differ from traditional styles of life:
instead of promoting workers who are disciplined and embrace order, they encourage individuals
who are not in the least productive and quite hedonist; just the opposite of what the system needs.
Therefore, one has to put an end to this hedonist malaise and recover the “productivity ethic”,
order and discipline that would guarantee the smoother working of the market and avoid social
disintegration. This accounts for their attempts to endow the market with post-enlightenment
legitimation, channeling techno-economic rationality towards a new capitalism. It is an attempt to
reconstruct the nexus between morals and market with the rehabilitation of forgotten values from
the Western Tradition, which is found in Judeo-Christian civilization and interpreted in puritanical
terms [94].
In order to culturally (morally) mend the (American) capitalist system, only a moral and cultural
step backwards is entertained. That is, we have to recover the values of times gone by (the puritan
religious tradition) typical of capitalism; but without the anachronisms. To this end, we have to
reinforce the compensating intermediate institutions: family, Church, personal friendships and
freely-formed associations. It is these that can help to recover the values of puritan ethics: order,
discipline and capacity for sacrifice. Here, a person finds value and is driven towards a behavior of
solidarity in the social setting [95–97].
As can be seen, the neo-con proposal of looking back towards values and traditions, which
accompanied the expansion of American capitalism in its origins, proves to be adulterated from the
start, because what is transcendental and decisive in this proposal are not values, but rather
safeguarding the market. Values only play an instrumental role as a justifying strategy for the
hegemony of the market, but without questioning the basis of this hegemony: the maximizing
instrumental rationality of profit. Although it seems obvious that there is a need to impose moral
values on the market, this is not the path to follow in order to overcome economist rationality; suffice
it to say that the growing marginalization seen in advanced capitalist societies, the increasing
economic inequality between rich and poor countries and, particularly, the open defense of the arms
race expressed by somewhat more than a minority of these thinkers.
6. The Need for a New Humanist Story of “What Is Human”: The Rehabilitation of Ontology
As has just been discussed, the weak alternatives to decadent postmodernity by the Frankfurt
School and neo-conservative thinkers do not constitute real avenues to pursue in order to disable
the reigning nihilism in society, which abandons human beings to the mercy of the manipulating
and consumer games of technics and the market. In this extremely complex and growing panorama,
134
which is subject to the tyranny of “exchange value”, a humanist recovery of “what is human” is an
essential and urgent intellectual undertaking; one which would restore the subject’s most genuine
and originating identity.
In any case, as pointed out by the post-Jungian psychologist, James Hillman [98], to pose
the task of recovering what is human nowadays, which would overcome anti-humanist criticism (a
“post-modern humanism”) means avoiding the “humanist fallacy”. This consists of believing that
man is the center and the measure of all things, in order to rediscover (as did Petrarch on the peak
of Mont Ventoux, by Augustinian means) not man, but the spirit of man; and the spirit of man is
not restricted to human experience, as its depth is, as Heraclitus pronounced, unfathomable. This is
the great challenge to the humanistic recovery of what is human, if it is at all possible: to overcome
the consequences of enlightened anthropocentrism, scientific objectivism, as well as irrationalist
subjectivism, whose common denominator consists of reducing all that is real to empirical facticity.
That is, to rediscover that the reality of what is human is not limited to what is bodily or
psychologically human. If we are unable to connect with the transcendental dimension that bestows
upon us genuine human identity, then all that is left is to endorse, along with Foucault, the
definitive death of man (and with it, all humanism) and confirm the beginning of the Nietzschean
post-humanity heralded in Sloterdijk’s The Rules of the Human Park, which considers any attempt
to understand the subject outside the scientific paradigm as futile, being the only paradigm that
bestows upon us, through genetic engineering, the real capability to “tame man” and transcend our
species as it is today towards the super-human and, thus, providing a remedy for the total failure of
humanist values [51].
The prospect of developing a different narrative as regards what is human will only be possible,
in my view, if we adopt the decision to “go back to the origin”. This return should in no way be
seen as a nostalgic or romantic conjuring up of the past, or as the patchwork of folkloric traditionalism.
Neither is it an attempt in any way to evoke terminal authoritarianisms or late puritanisms. To go
back to the origin responds to an attempt at radicality: to move forwards to the point of emergence.
Additionally, the most radical for human beings is the meaning of their own humanity. Origin and
meaning are two indispensable elements to connect with what is genuinely human. This tells us
that to construct this new story of what is human must begin with recovering ontology. Basically,
this consists of recovering the capacity to capture the meaning of human life and the ethical nature
of actions. These are the two spheres on which I am going to focus.
First, the sphere of meaning constitutes the nucleus of what is most genuinely human, of what
only the human being possesses. We are standing before the most fertile notion of contemporary
thinking (phenomenology, hermeneutics, personalism, etc.), which we must continue to explore in
more depth. Because of meaning, which is neither subjectivity, and its representations, nor actual
reality, a common terrain opens up for human beings, a space for communication and for shared
worlds. We humans live from meaning, because it allows us to share a common logos, which is at
the base and precedes all manner of scientific and technological progress. The recovery of what is
human has to pass through the stage of recovering meaning, something that we have “forgotten”
and that we do not “remember”, which is found precisely in a clouded human nature.
The concern for originating and for meaning was primordial in phenomenology and particularly
135
in the last of Husserl’s works: The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Philosophy [99]. It
studies the roots of the loss of ontology in modern science, from Galileo to present day, on the
basis of the double reduction of physics to geometry and this to algebra. It attempted to reach
exactitude, but in return, meaning was lost ([99], n. 2). Faced with this situation, Husserl proposes
recovering the originating reality from which science derives, since the realities that science
excludes are the biggest issues for humanity: questions that imply the meaning or the absence of
the meaning of human existence ([99], n. 4). Mathematical idealities attempt to substitute the real
world: the world that is truly perceptible to us. Husserl calls it “life-world” (Lebenswelt) ([99],
n. 34a–b). Lebenswelt is the world of pre-scientific and extra-scientific life. It is the real world
according to our intuition that we experience as beings of flesh and blood, for which all scientific
idealization, all technical construction and all sociological structuring have a posterior and derived
meaning ([99], n. 34c–d). Lebenswelt is the “originating world of meaning” ([99], n. 34d).
The crisis of the sciences (and humanity) comes from having broken the link with this
Lebenswelt realm of originating evidence and, with it, the loss of having lost its own telos, its
finality. This is because meaning is signification and reference, as well as intentionality towards an
end. The therapy proposed by Husserl is not the return to an exclusively pre-scientific life or the
escape to an extra-scientific life. His program consists of rediscovering the transcendentality of a
Lebenswelt, which brings together all the worlds—scientific, economic, sociological ([99],
n. 53–54)—and developing a life-world ontology ([99], n. 51). The difficulties this task poses are
evident, but its inspiring premise is still valid: the problem does not lie in the scientific, economic
or sociological structures, but rather in their lack of meaning, because of their disconnection from
the living world.
Martin Heidegger also undertook a vigorous search for the roots, the original. In his Letter on
Humanism, he specified that “ek-sistence” (a concept different from existence) consists of “dwelling
proximally to being” ([47], p. 232). This led him to point out that genuine thinking must reach the
level of ontology, conceived in terms of the search for the roots, the encounter with the original, which
is at the same time the search for the permanent of what establishes the human residing ([47],
p. 237). Working from the original significance of dwell as to stay or remain, Heidegger finds the
origins of the present crisis in the loss of that habit, and consequently, he concludes that “first and
foremost it is necessary to learn to dwell” ([47], p. 241). The search for the original (Ursprung) and
permanent (bleiben), the understanding of true human dwelling, leads to capturing the meaning.
Additionally, this is the object meditative thinking proposed by Heidegger: a thinking that is
questioned by meaning [100].
The major danger for human dwelling lies in the false belief that man is the only player in
unveiling what is real. This supreme danger, more so than all the wars, and destruction lie in
technics, because it converts everything into calculable and manipulable; and this is precisely
the essence of materialism: not that everything is material, but rather that all entity is simply
work material. “Unveiling” thinking (bessinliche Denken) that looks for the meaning, as opposed
to mere “calculating” thinking (rechnende Denken) only attentive to manipulation, offers a
profound understanding, even of the meaning of technics itself. Because technics also unveils the
phisis, given that man utilizes it to bring to light what was in fact hidden in its cells and fabrics [101].
136
Genuine thinking in Heidegger finally leads to dachten (remember) and to danken (give thanks).
Man warns that existing means for him to be at one with the “sacred”, with the “divine”. Only
thus can man truly dwell on Earth, conjure up the danger of uprooting and find the path to authenticity
(true self) [102].
Both Husserl and Heidegger find a powerful antecedent in Henri Bergson’s proposal for the
recovery of ontology. In La Pensée et le Mouvant, he records his opposition to those who attempt
to marginalize man, in his daily existence, from the sphere of knowledge reserved exclusively for
the sciences. Their concern for numbers and measurements renders them unable to answer themselves
alone questions concerning meaning. From here, his statement that, “at least one part of our reality,
our humanity, can be recovered in its original purity” [103].
In short, the construction of this new humanist story of “what is human” has to begin by
re-proposing the centrality of meaning, which must be looked for in the reality itself, pre-scientific,
of human nature and through meditative thinking. This is a thinking that wades through memory
and that in the proximity of the sacred, reminding the human being of what it means to dwell in the
world. This “dwelling in the proximity of the sacred” connects with another forgotten dimension
of what is human: the “inalienable” essential constituent element dignity: the only transcendental
foundation of human rights.
In effect, this meaning of the word “inalienable” has ever been linked to fundamental rights (the
essential consequences of human dignity); however, the economicist mentality has downgraded
and understood it in the weak sense of “inviolable” vis-à-vis others, but capable of being renounced
by the subject himself. The “inalienable” was hinted at in the Roman conception of law when it
referred to res extra-commercium, among which there was the inclusion of res communes and res
sacrae. This intuition of the Roman mentality maintained a sense of limits to avoid chaos (hybris).
The United States Declaration of Independence, Jefferson’s doing, constitutes an extraordinary
novelty in this respect, since the replacement of property by “the pursuit of happiness” allows us to
understand the word “inalienable” in its powerful and rigorous sense. In effect, the renunciation of
happiness seems much more anti-natural and absurd than the disposition of property. The admission
of inalienable rights implies a conception of the person different from an isolated and self-sufficient
monad and from the postmodernist conception of a “playful mask”. It forces the understanding of
the human person in agreement with its originating terminology as prosopon, as a being open to
reality, as relationship with the origin, with others, with nature, with oneself ([3], p. 147). This idea
of the connection between the inalienability and the grandeur of human beings means that the
individual stops considering her/himself as pure unsatisfied desire, from the moment in which s/he
opens up to others and experiences the fact that s/he is not sovereign, but rather the guardian and
custodian of reality for her/his contemporaries and for the future generations.
To protect the “inalienable”, we need to overcome the anthropological dualism between res
extensa and res cogitans: the opposition between the individual will as a subject and the rest of
reality reduced to a mere object capable of being manipulated at the mercy of that will and, therefore,
entirely alienable. The body is not a tool or just another commodity that can be disposed of; it is
not something that I have, but rather something that I am, as Gabriel Marcel, among others,
conscientiously pointed out throughout his work [104]. The human body is not a thing. The individual
137
does not possess his or her own body as an alienable, relinquishable and divisible good susceptible
to becoming the object of commercial transactions (the sale of sperm, ovules, organs, etc.). From
this, it follows that we cannot speak of “rights over my own body” in the sense of free disposition,
but rather as a right duty to its diligent and responsible use and care.
The road towards the ontological recovery of what is human, as we have seen, also touches on
rediscovering the ethical dimension of human actions. In this aspect, the rehabilitating thinking of
practical philosophy, inspired by Aristotle, has offered valuable suggestions. Robert Spaemann ([84],
pp. 89–112), welcoming the distinction made by Alisdair MacIntyre [105], proposes removing
reasoning from the certainty paradigm, into which Descartes introduced it and which has proved
unable to confront the enormous complexity of the real, and re-introduce it into the truth paradigm.
According to the certainty model, access to reality depends exclusively on the adequate method
that guarantees objectivity. However, rationalization at all costs, typical of this model, has brought
with it the greatest explosion of irrationality known to date. Additionally, the supposed humanizing
transformation of the world has brought us an unprecedented height of dehumanization. According
to the truth model, the radical and genuine is not objectivity, but rather reality. Additionally, we
cannot automatically access the foundation of reality by the mere application of a rational method.
Such access requires a laborious apprenticeship, which is fed from a long tradition of thinking.
There is no science without history, education, research communities or ethical and political
components: a science separate from these is a fiction. Our ways of knowing owe much to
know-how or craftsmanship than pure speculation, exempt from historical and ethical connotations
and motivations. The methodological ideal of the certainty paradigm implies univocal rationality,
while the truth paradigm means an open and analogical use of reasoning. The first model attempts
to offer security at the cost of reductionism; the second assumes uncertainty and contrasting
hypotheses until hitting on the one that best fits reality, assuming vulnerability and the possibility
of error, but giving priority to advances in the knowledge of reality in contrast to the obsessive
justification of a thesis ([84], pp. 119–22).
This concerns substituting an epistemological paradigm (such as a basic model for the theory of
truth) for an anthropological paradigm that is neither psychologist nor relativist. The difficulties
run deep, because we are dealing with conceiving the truth as perfection of the person, and this
proves incompatible with rationalism and subjectivism. Consequently, the recovery of ontology, as
suggested by Alejandro Llano [106], implies re-establishing the original connection between truth
and virtue; that is, between truth and perfecting the person. The idea of virtue is of central importance
in the recovery of what is human, but it only makes sense from a perspective of practical reasoning,
which overcomes the subject-object dialectic consecrated by rationalist ethics. For the terminal
rationalism of our times, reality is pure facticity, a collection of external and demonstrable facts;
while subjectivity is and empty and self-referential capsule. Reality is divided into two isolated
worlds. In the first, we have rational calculation (rational choice): in the field of scientific, determinist
and neutrally assessed evidence. The subjective, in contrast, would be the field of the irrational,
where there is no place for the universal, because it is governed by the preferences, desires and
feelings of each individual. This is the realm of moral emotion and spontaneity, which validates all
of the options. In a panorama of this kind, the concept of “virtue” is completely bereft of meaning
138
if we understand it as growing in being when the person, in their actions, “follow the truth”. Virtue
is gaining freedom, which is obtained when the person orients his/her life towards truth. It is an
anthropological gain, that is, a gain in the perfecting of the person, which is realized through
acquiring habits. This concept of virtue is drifting today in the midst of great mistakes, but its
recovery (as MacIntyre has pointed out ([105], pp. 204–44)) is of vital importance.
From the perspective of virtue, human beings see themselves as being able to grow cognitively
and ethically, which remains a stable part of their person in the form of habits. It follows that the
increase of cognitive and practical habits is only one way to grow in perfection and, with it, grow
in freedom. Cognitive and practical habits are those that allow a person to “take charge” of the
profundity of their human condition and their own historical situation [107]. The perspective of
habits is that which allows for really overcoming the objectivity-subjectivity dialectic, because it
appeals to an increase of the perceptive capabilities in the person, and this is manifest in the
anthropological meaning that experience acquires in this context. In effect, scientific objectivism
appeals to the “experiment”, to the empirical verification of the fact. In contrast, the habit perspective
(practical reasoning) refers to “experience”, in the humanist sense, which is knowledge that deals
with the context and the surroundings ([84], pp. 35–36). It is the sense in which we commonly speak
of an “experienced person”: not someone who accumulates theoretical knowledge or who shuts
themselves within subjectivity, but rather who knows how to maintain within themselves the trace
of their vital contact with the world and people, in such a way that they have learned to behave
more appropriately and wisely. We are therefore talking of a knowing of things and of a knowing
oneself: appropriating the real, respecting their own being ([107], pp. 137–38).
The central role of virtue in the humanist recovery of “what is human” is directly linked to
the ethical thinking of Aristotle’s. This is a thinking that underlines, at least, three fundamental
elements of human actions. Firstly is the importance of the dimension of praxis, as distinct from
poiesis (and this difference shows the way to overcome economicism and modern productivism).
Secondly is the re-evaluation of the dimension of ethos, of experience, which leads to distinguishing
the ethical truths as opposed to simply theoretical truths (this leads to overcoming ethical rationalism,
which overlooks experience). Thirdly is the noteworthy role played by phronesis (prudence) as a
fundamental factor in the formation of ethics (which leads to overcoming ethical emotivism and the
division between reasoning and sentiments).
Aristotle tackles the difference between praxis and poiesis from the very first lines of
Nicomachean Ethics ([18], Book I, No. 1). The starting point is the intentional nature of all human
actions. However, he sets out one clear difference in the end, as some are the same actions (praxis)
and others are certain works (poiesis). In effect, poiesis is the sphere of what in Rome was called
facere: the type of activity carried out exclusively with an eye toward achieving a result, of a given
thing that one attempts to give rise to; therefore, “the end of production (poiesis) is distinct from
production itself”. This means that “production (poiesis) is not an end in the absolute sense, but only
something which is relative with regard to the creation of a given thing” ([18], Book VI, No. 5).
Praxis, on the other hand, refers to what was later called agere, that is, those actions that are
realized for their own ends, that are none other than good practice (eupraxis) ([18], Book VI, No. 2).
“In action what one does is an end (in the absolute sense), so a virtuous life is an end and the object
139
of desire is this end” ([18], Book VI, No. 5). However, the importance of the distinction lies in the
more elevated character of praxis over poiesis, to the degree of stating in Politics ([17], Book VIII,
1325 b, 28), that the activity of divinity can be considered praxis, but never poiesis.
In effect, the primacy of praxis is what guarantees the superiority of the personal over the world
of objects and, in this sense, is a way of overcoming the thinking of modernity, which gives primacy
to technics and production, even for writers, such as Marx, who reclaim the notion of praxis, but,
as Hanna Arendt reminds us, having lost its original sense and reduced to the concept of labor,
which brings in its wake the reduction of man to animal laborans [108]. In the task of recovering
what is human, it is important to avoid confusion between work and employment, which is the
outcome of the predominance of instrumental reasoning. Hanna Arendt criticizes the exaltation of
work as a central human activity, because of the risk of giving primacy, in economicist terms, to
productive and lucrative tasks. However, she offers no alternative to her distinction between labor,
action (praxis) and work in its technical or artistic dimension ([108], pp. 161–63). In my view, it
would be more correct to state that there is no true human work without the praxical dimension or
ethics. Human action is multidimensional and not only produces functional effects, but above all,
it has to produce perfecting effects. The same subject can be a lawyer or an engineer and also the
father of a family or a writer of short stories. The importance of reflecting on the fact that work is
something more than employment lies in passing from one plane that is purely objective and
functional to a dimension that is subjective and personal. Additionally, from this, it follows that the
full sense of human work cannot be conceived from an anthropology impoverished by economicist
pragmatism. The fundamental value of work is the anthropological perfecting, intellectual and
ethical gain that is earned and extended through work (praxis). When this aspect is systematically
marginalized, this causes an absence of theoretical tension and ethical enthusiasm, and then,
creativity diminishes, while conformity increases: everything tends to come to a halt. This is the
most renowned pathology found in consumer societies ([108], pp. 137–39). It follows that overcoming
economicism lies in the line of an anthropological interpretation (not instrumental) of work. The
added value of work is, foremost, gaining human perfection above and beyond economic performance
(although this is advisable). It follows that in the task of recovering the human, the social recognition of
the humanist value (ethical and sapiential) of work is fundamental; this has been considerably
obscured with its merchandization. From this point of view, what is decisive for progress in
productivity is not money, but rather an increase of theoretical and practical habits. For there to be
more work, we have to work better, and in order to work better, we have to think better and make
better decisions. This is not incompatible with technology; quite the opposite: the connection
between technology and humanism is the major challenge today: to establish a proper relationship
between ethics and technics that would guarantee the true perfecting of the individual ([106],
pp. 137–38).
In this same sense of the primacy of praxis, one has to understand that ethics does not belong to
the sphere of “logos apophantikòs”, which concerns things that are necessary (such as geometry,
algebra or metaphysics), but rather, ethics belongs to the sphere of “ortos logos”, to right reasoning,
which deals with the contingent, about what can be another way ([18], Book II, No. 9 and Book VI,
No. 4). Aristotle’s right reason implies the possibility to humanly reach perfection, since this means
140
a permanent rectification of intention to accommodate desire and the search for good in each case.
For this reason, practical truth, as opposed to theoretical truth, is never totally true, because it always
allows for “even better”. All of this implies that in ethical life, it is impossible to theoretically know
principles independently of their practical application. In other words, the ethical model can only
be personified el hombre esforzado (Spoudaios), he who has brought up to date to the maximum all
of the powers and has interiorized the habit of ethical and dianoetic virtues ([18], Book II, No. 1). It
also follows from here that in Aristotelian thinking, prudence (phronesis) takes on a fundamental
importance, which involves the link between ends and means, between rationality and emotivity,
thus overcoming rationalism and logical empiricism. Of course, reasoning has an important place
in ethics, but this is not the same type of reasoning that operates in purely theoretical matters
(that which cannot be otherwise), but rather practical reasoning, which has to take into account
the circumstances ([18], Book II, No. 1) and which requires dialogue and argumentation, not
demonstration, as already pointed out by S. Toulmin [109] and Ch. Perelman [110].
Additionally, a final consideration: When we seem to be heading for a post-literary culture, the
need proves even more pressing to rediscover the fruits of reflecting on the original and genuinely
human content in classic, ancient and more recent texts. It is in these that we find set out the figure
of the homo civilis, the good man, the good citizen, who knows how to keep himself from the
excesses of the homo oeconomicus and the corruption of the “zoon politikon”. On the basis of this
literary wisdom, I propose the rehabilitation of the homo humanus, who undertakes the greatness
and profundity of his humanitas.
Conflicts of Interest
References
1. Michel Foucault. Les mots et les choses. Une Archéologie des Sciences Humaines. Paris:
Gallimard, 1966, p. 39.
2. Gianni Vattimo. La fine della Modernità. Torino: Einaudi, 1985, p. 23.
3. Jesús Ballesteros. Postmodernidad: Decadencia o Resistencia. Madrid: Tecnos, 1989,
pp. 17–24.
4. Erwin Panofsky. Meaning in the Visual Arts. Garden City: Doubleday, 1955, Chapter V.
5. Erwin Panofsky. Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art. Stockholm: Almqvist &
Wiksell, 1960, p. 190.
6. Lewis Mumford. Technics. and Civilization. New York: Harcourt Brace and Co., 1934, p. 179.
141
7. José Ortega y Gasset. “Sobre el punto de vista en las artes.” In Obras completas. Madrid:
Revista de Occidente, 1946–1979, p. 443 (translation mine). M. Heidegger expresses himself
in a similar way as Ortega in his important essay “The Age of World Picture”: “To be modern
means to see the world as an image, which is the same as the apparition of individual as a
subjectum within what exists”; and “to be a subjectum means to be able to objectivize, that is
to objectively visualize, to quantify with exactness, to calculate, since the modern freedom of
subjectivity is wholly resolved in the objectivity which is inherent to it” (Martin Heidegger.
“The Age of World Picture”. In The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
Translated by William Lovitt. New York: Harper and Row, 1977, pp. 115–54).
8. José A. Maravall. Velázquez y la Modernidad. Madrid: Alianza Editorial, 1987.
9. Arnold Hauser. The Sociology of Art. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.
10. Leonardo Da Vinci. Aforismos, 4th ed. Spanish translation by Ernesto García. Madrid:
Espasa-Calpe, 1965, see aphorisms: 34–37 and 314–450.
11. Paul Oskar Kristeller. Renaissance Thought and Its Sources. New York: Columbia University
Press, 1979.
12. Max Weber. Science as a Vocation (delivered as a speech at Munich University, 1918).
Munich: Duncker & Humblodt, 1919.
13. Galileo Galilei. Il Saggiatore (1623). Spanish translation by José María Revuelta. Madrid:
Aguilar, 1981, p. 197.
14. Alexander Koyré. “Le monde de ‘l’a-peu-pres’ a l’univers de la précision.” In Etudes
D’histoire de la Pensée Philosophique. Paris: Gallimard, 1971, pp. 191–228.
15. René Descartes. “Meditations de prima philosophia, VI.” In Oeuvres Philosophiques. Paris:
Garnier, 1973, vol. II, p. 177 and following.
16. This mode of thinking by way of disjunctives leads to the insipid questions found in public
opinion polls which necessarily lead those who believe in complementariness to appear as
people who “do not know/have no answer”.
17. Aristotle. “Politics. Book 1” In Aristotle in 23 Volumes. Translated by Horace Rackham.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, London, William Heinemann Ltd., 1944, vol. 21,
section 1256a–1257b.
18. Aristotle. “Nichomachean Ethics.” In Aristotle in 23 Volumes. Translated by Horace Rackham.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, London, William Heinemann Ltd., 1944, vol. 19, section
1133a–1134a.
19. Karl Polanyi. The Great Transformation. New York: Holt, 1944.
20. Jacques Pirenne. Histoire Economique et Sociale du Moyen Age. Paris: PUF, 1933.
21. Albert Otto Hirschman. The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism
before Its Triumph. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977.
22. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, cap. XIII, 9. In Hobbes’s Leviathan: Reprinted from the Edition
of 1651. Edited by William George Pogson. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1929, p. 96.
23. Robert Spaemann. Zur Kritik der Politischen Utopie. Zehn Kapitel Politischer Philosophie.
Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1987, p. 190.
142
24. Bernard Mandeville. The Fable of the Bees: Or Private Vices, Public Benefits (1714). Irwing
Primer edition. New York: Capricorn Books, 1969.
25. Adam Smith. “The Division of Labour.” In An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations. Edwin Cannan edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976, Book
I, Chapter 2, vol. 2a, p. 456.
26. Benjamin Franklin. Autobiography and Other Writings (1771). Edited by Russell Nye.
Cambridge: Riverside, 1958, p. 269.
27. Horace. “Epistle to Lucilius.” In Horace, Satires and Epistles; Persius Satires. Edited by
Niall Rudd. London: Penguin, 2005, pp. 68–79.
28. Max Weber. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism and Other Writings. Translated
by Peter Baehr and George Wells. London: Penguin 2002, pp. 9–12 and 15–16.
29. Anselm Dietz. Der Homo oeconomicus. Hamburg: Gütersloh, 2005, pp. 54–63.
30. William Petty. Political Arithmetic. In The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty. London:
Routledge/Thoemmes Press, 1997, vol. 1, pp. 233–313.
31. Ernest Becker. The Fight against the Bad. New York: Free Press, 1973, p. 143.
32. Alfred Suchanek. “Homo oeconomicus.” In Lexikon der Wirtschaftsethik. Edited by G.
Enderle Friburg: Herder, 1993, pp. 426–31. See also: Marco Mansdörfer. Zur Theorie des
Wirtschaftsstrafrechts. Hamburg: C.F. Muller, 2011, pp. 20–32.
33. Jeremy Bentham. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789).
London: T. Payne and Sons, 1981, vol. 1, Chapter I.
34. Gary Becker. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1976, pp. 123–38. See also: A Treatise on the Family. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1991, pp. 159–66.
35. E. Fritz Shumacher. Small Is Beautiful. Economics as if People Mattered (1973). New York:
Harper-Perennial, 2010, p. 125.
36. Gilbert K. Chesterton. The Return of Don Quijote (1926). Cornwall (UK): House of Stratus,
2008, p. 38
37. Henri Saint-Simon. “L’Organisateur.” In Oeuvres Complètes. Paris: Anthropos, 1966, vol. 2,
pp. 1002–12.
38. Lewis Mumford. The Myth of the Machine. NewYork: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1967,
Volume I. Spanish edition: El mito de la máquina. Translated by Diego Núñez. Buenos Aires:
EMECE, 1969, p. 419.
39. Alvin Toffler. The Third Wave. New York: Bantam Books, 1980, p. 46.
40. Charles Péguy. “De Jean Coste.” In Oeuvres en Prose. Paris: Gallimard, 1987, vol. I, p. 1018
and following.
41. E. Fritz Shumacher. A Guide for the Perplexed. New York: Harper-Perennial, 1978.
42. Alejandro Llano. Humanismo Cívico. Barcelona: Ariel, 1999, p. 145.
43. Arnold Gelhen. Anthropologie et Psychologie Sociale. Paris: PUF, 1990, pp. 311–28.
44. Jean François Lyotard. La Condition Postmoderne: Rapport sur le Savoir. Paris: Éditions de
Minuit, 1979, p. 12.
143
45. Abrecht Wellmer. The Persistence of Modernity. Essays on Aesthetics, Politics and
Postmodernism. Translated by Dennis Midgey. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991, p. 231.
46. Alain Touraine. Critique of Modernity. Oxford: Blackwel, 1995, pp. 21–24.
47. Martin Heidegger. “Letter on Humanism.” In Basic Writings: Martin Heidegger (1947).
London: Routledge, 1977, pp. 215–59.
48. Gianni Vattimo. Oltre l'interpretazione. Roma-Bari: Laterza, 1994, pp. 146–47.
49. Gianni Vattimo. Il soggetto e la maschera. Milano: Bompiani, 1974, p. 296.
50. Gilbert Hottois. Essais de philosophie bioéthique et biopolitique. París: Vrin, 1999, p. 68.
51. Peter Sloterdijk. Regeln fur den Menschenpark. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1999.
In September 1999, Peter Sloterdijk delivered a speech to a circle of intellectuals at Schloss
Elmau in Bavaria that was to give the attending media an incentive to inaugurate a heated
debate over the accuracy of his observations and especially over whether he advocates
harnessing genetic technology to the improvement of human kind. Under the motto Rules for
the Human Park. A Response to the Letter on Humanism, the speech was subsequently
published in a book form with like title. (Spanish translation: Normas sobre el Parque
Humano. Madrid: Siruela, 2003).
52. Peter Sloterdijk. “Vivre chaud et penser froid.” In Multitudes, nº III (2000): 21–22.
53. Hervé Kempf. La Révolution Biolithique. Humains artificiels et machines animées. Paris:
Albin Michel, 1998.
54. Tristam Engelhardt. The Foundations of Bioethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997, p. 68.
55. Richard Rorty. Philosophy and the Mirror of the Nature. Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1979.
56. Gilbert Hottois. La science entre valeurs modernes et postmodernité. Paris: Vrin, 2005.
57. Roland Barthes. The Pleasure of the Text. New York: Hill and Wang, 1975.
58. Michel Foucault. Nietzsche, Freud, Marx. Paris: Minuit, 1965.
59. The critic and translator Barbara Johnson has emphasized Mallarmé’s influence on
twentieth-century French criticism and theory: “It was largely by learning the lesson of
Mallarmé that critics like Roland Barthes came to speak of ‘the death of the author’ in the
making of literature. Rather than seeing the text as the emanation of an individual author’s
intentions, structuralists and de-constructors followed the paths and patterns of the linguistic
signifier, paying new attention to syntax, spacing, intertextuality, sound, semantics, etymology,
and even individual letters. Theoretical styles of Jaques Derrida, Julia Kristeva, Maurice
Blanchot, and especially Jaques Lacan also owe a great deal to Mallarmé’s critical poem”
(Barbara Johnson. ‘Translator’s Note’ to Stéphane Mallarmé.” In Divagations. Translated by
Barbara Johnson. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007, p. 301).
60. Jaques Derrida. Dissemination. Translated by Barbara Johnson. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1981, p. 315.
61. Frederik Niestzche. The Case of Wagner, Nietzsche Contra Wagner, and Selected Aphorisms.
Translated by Anthony Ludovici. Edimburg-London: Foulis, 1911 (free online 2007), n. 6.
144
62. Frederik Niestzche. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Judith Norman and edited by
Rolf-Peter Horstmann. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002, annotation number 254.
63. Frederik Niestzche. “The song of the nightwalker”. In Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Translated by
Adrian Del Caro; Edited by Robert Pippin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
64. “What is philosophy for him except a sort of philology without end that is forever developing,
a philology that shall never be pinned down? And if interpretation can never end, this simply
means that there is nothing to interpret. There is nothing absolutely primary since deep down
everything is interpretation. Each sign is in itself the interpretation of other signs, and not the
thing being offered to interpretation” (Michel Focault. “Nietzsche, la généalogie, l’histoire.”
In Hommage à Jean Hyppolite. París: PUF, 1971, pp. 145–72).
65. François Lyotard. The Postmodern Explained: Correspondence 1982–1985. Translated by
Don Barry. Edited by Julian Pefanis and Morgan Thomas. Minnesota: University of
Minnesota Press, 1993.
66. Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus. Translated by Robert Hurley, Mark
Seem and Hellen R. Lane. London and New York: Continuum, 2004, vol. 1 of Capitalism
and Schizophrenia.
67. Commentators have almost unanimously insisted upon the continuity we are presenting
between modernism and post-structuralism. The most lucid of all these commentators is
probably Andreas Huyssen. After the Great Divide: Modernism, Mass Culture, Postmodernism.
Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1986.
68. Frederik Niestzche. Unfashionable Observations. Translated by Richard T. Grey. Stanford:
Stanford University Presss, 1995, part III, n. 6.
69. Frederik Niestzche. The Dawn of Day. Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality. Translated by
John Macfarland Kennedy. New York: Mc Millan Co., 1911.
70. François Lyotard. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Translated by Geoff
Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1984. Hume, in
the book quoted, expresses the same idea: “human’s life is of no more importance for the
universe than the life of an oyster” (p. 119).
71. Frederik Jameson. Postmodernism. The cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Durham: Duke
University Press, 1991, pp. 79–87.
72. Frederik Niestzche. Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits. Translated by Reginald
John Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996, annotation number 72.
73. Robert Musil. Essays. Paris: Seuil, 1984, p. 170.
74. Max Horkheimer. “Traditional and critical theory.” In Critical Sociology: Selected Readings.
Edited by Paul Connerton. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976.
75. Herbert Marcuse. One-Dimensional Man: Studies in Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society
(1964). London: Routledge, 1991.
76. Max Horkheimer, and Theodor Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment. Translated by Edmund
Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2002.
145
77. Theodor Adorno. Minima Moralia. Reflection from Damaged Life. London: Radical Thinkers,
1981. See also: David Held. Introduction to critical theory: Horkheimer to Habermas.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980.
78. Jürgen Habermas. The Theory of Communicative Action (1981). Translated by Thomas
McCarthy. Boston: Beacon, 1984. See also: Raymond Geus. The Idea of a Critical Theory:
Habermas. and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
79. Jürgen Habermas. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (1985). Translated by Frederick
Lawrence. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987, pp. 81–89. See also: “Technology and Science as
Ideology.” In Toward a Rational Society. Student Protest, Science, and Politics. Tanslated by
Jeremy J. Saphiro. Boston: Beacon Press, 1971, pp. 119–21.
80. Jürgen Habermas. Between Facts and Norms (1992). Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998.
81. Axel Honneth. The Critique of Power: Reflective Stages in a Critical Social Theory (Studies
in Contemporary German Social Thought). Cambridge: MIT Press, 1991.
82. Jürgen Habermas. The Postnational Constellation. Political Essays (1998). Translated by
Max Pensky. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001, pp. 95–96.
83. Jürgen Habermas. Legitimationsprobleme im Spätkapitalismus. Frankfurt am Main: Surkham,
1973. Spanish edition: Problemas de Legitimacion del Capitalismo Tardío. Translated by
Juan Echeverry. Madrid: Cátedra, 1999, pp. 67–80.
84. Robert Spaemann. Essays in Anthropology: Variations on a Theme (1987). Translated by
Guido De Graaff and James Mumford. Oregon: Cascade Books, 2010.
85. Francis Fukuyama. America at the Crossroads: Democracy, Power and the Neoconservative
Legacy. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2006, pp. 21–24.
86. Leo Strauss. “The Crisis of Our Time.” In The Predicament of Modern Politics. Edited by
Howard Spaeth. Detroit: University of Detroit Press, 1964, pp. 41–54.
87. Leo Strauss. On Tyranny. New York: Free Press, 1991, pp. 22–23.
88. Leo Strauss. “What Is Political Philosophy?” In Leo Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?
and Other Studies. Glencoe: The Free Press, 1959, pp. 18–19.
89. Leo Strauss. The City and Man. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1964, pp. 10–17.
90. Robert Kagan, and William Kristol. Present Dangers: Crisis and Opportunity in American
Foreign and Defense Policy. San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2000, pp. 3–25.
91. William Bennett. “Morality, Character and American Foreign Policy.” In Robert Kagan and
William Kristol. Present Dangers: Crisis and Opportunity in American Foreign and Defense
Policy. San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2000, pp. 289–307.
92. Frederik Hayek. The Road to Serfdom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1944.
93. Murray Friedman. The Neoconservative Revolution Jewish Intellectuals and the Shaping of
Public Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. 44.
94. Zeev Sternhell. The Anti-Enlightenment Tradition. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2010.
95. Peter Berger, and Thomas Luckmann. The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the
Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Anchor Books, 1966.
96. Michael Novak. The Spirit of Democratic Capitalism. New York: Simon and Shuster, 1982.
146
97. Richard J. Neuhaus. Naked Public Square. Religion and Democracy in America. Michigan:
Eerdmans, 1986.
98. James Hillman. The Force of Character. New York: Random House, 1999, p. 395.
99. Edmund Husserl. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Philosophy (1936).
Translated by David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970.
100. Martin Heidegger. Sein und Zeit. Tubingen: Niemeyer, 1927, pp. 42–51, 117–26. English
version: Being and Time. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1996.
101. Martin Heidegger. “The Question Concerning Technology.” In Martin Heidegger. Basic
Writings, 2nd ed. Edited by David Farrell Krell. New York: Harper Collins, 1993.
102. Walter Richardson. Heidegger, Trough Phenomenology to Thought. La Haya: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1963, pp. 15–18.
103. Henry Bergson. La pensée et le mouvant. París: Seuil, 1969, pp. 27–74.
104. Gabriel Marcel. Etre et Avoir. París: Aubier, 1935.
105. Alisdair MacIntyre. After Virtue. Indiana: Notre Dame University Press, 1981, pp. 51–79.
106. Alejandro Llano. Humanismo Cívico. Barcelona: Ariel, 1999, pp. 146–47.
107. Alejandro Llano. La Nueva Sensibilidad. Madrid: Espasa, 1988, p. 133.
108. Hannah Arendt. The Human Condition. Chicago: University Press, 1958, pp. 111–82.
109. Stephen Toulmin. An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1950, pp. 137–42.
110. Chaim Perelman. Justice et Raison. Paris: PUF, 1963, pp. 68–77.
147
Abstract: The prominent Australian earth scientist, Tim Flannery, closes his recent book Here on
Earth: A New Beginning with the words “… if we do not strive to love one another, and to love our
planet as much as we love ourselves, then no further progress is possible here on Earth”. This is
a remarkable conclusion to his magisterial survey of the state of the planet. Climatic and other
environmental changes are showing us not only the extent of human influence on the planet, but also
the limits of programmatic management of this influence, whether through political, economic,
technological or social engineering. A changing climate is a condition of modernity, but a condition
which modernity seems uncomfortable with. Inspired by the recent “environmental turn” in the
humanities—and calls from a range of environmental scholars and scientists such as Flannery—I
wish to suggest a different, non-programmatic response to climate change: a reacquaintance with the
ancient and religious ideas of virtue and its renaissance in the field of virtue ethics. Drawing upon
work by Alasdair MacIntyre, Melissa Lane and Tom Wright, I outline an apologetic for why the
cultivation of virtue is an appropriate response to the challenges of climate change.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Hulme, M. Climate Change and Virtue: An Apologetic.
Humanities 2014, 3, 299–312.
1. Introduction
The prominent earth scientist, and 2007 Australian of the Year, Tim Flannery closes his
recent book Here on Earth: A New Beginning with the words “… if we do not strive to love one
another, and to love our planet as much as we love ourselves, then no further progress is possible here
on Earth” ([1], p. 281). This is a remarkable conclusion to his magisterial survey of the state of the
planet under a changing climate. After surveying the deep history of life on Earth and humanity’s
increasing influence over it, the solution Flannery arrives at is not more knowledge—more striving
after science and technology—but a striving after love.
Flannery is not alone amongst contemporary environmental scientists in valorising love. The
ecologist Brendon Larson in the peroration to his book Metaphors for Environmental Sustainability
reflects: “I can return to the ramblings in the natural world … falling in love with it, and thus wanting
to express that love ... in the most apt words I can” ([2], pp. 228–29). And we don’t have to look
much further to locate other prominent environmental scientists and social scientists whose concern
for the future of climate on Earth leads them to invoke other human virtues. Sheila Jasanoff in her
essay, “Technologies of humility”, published a few years ago in the journal Nature, explains her call
for humility as “a plea for policy-makers to cultivate, and for universities to teach, modes of knowing
that are often pushed aside in expanding scientific understanding and technological capacity” ([3],
p. 33). Alastair McIntosh uses the subtitle “climate change, hope and the human condition” to his 2008
book Hell and High Water, where for him “Hope is about setting in place the preconditions that
148
might reconstitute life and then getting on with it” ([4], p. 250). And then there is anthropologist Tim
Leduc in Climate, Culture, Change suggesting that “wisdom may be the most fundamental factor that
inter-disciplinary climate research needs to clarify, as it responds to [climate] warming” ([5], p. 40).
Love, humility, hope and wisdom; in my pursuit of understanding climate change and what it
signifies for the world, I am interested in these apparently orthogonal interventions by such authors
as they contemplate the state of climate and the fate of the Earth. In all the climate models I have
examined, used and criticised over 30 years I have not yet come across a variable for love or an
equation for calculating humility. The thermometer may have been essential to tell the story of
a warming world, but environmental scientists have not yet invented or seen the need for a
hope-ometer. What is it then that draws such scientists and scholars to place the fate of the planet in
the hands of such intangible human qualities? These are not qualities that feature in the usual
discourse of climate change conducted by political scientists, economists, engineers and environmental
scientists—even if they are familiar to virtue ethicists.
In this article I explore this—perhaps surprising—acquaintance by climate and environmental
scientists with the ancient idea of virtue. And by virtue I adopt the definition offered by theologian
Tom Wright: “practising habits of heart and life that point toward the true goal of human existence” ([6],
p. 12). Drawing upon work by Alasdair MacIntyre, Melissa Lane and Tom Wright, I later outline an
apologetic for why the cultivation of virtue is an appropriate response to the challenges of climate
change. Contrary to the novelist Ian McEwan who claimed with regard to climate change that
“Cleverness got us into this problem and I don’t think virtue is going to get us out of it” [7], I suggest
that virtue may be the most enduring response that we have. But before developing this apologetic I
need to explain the dead-end we have reached with regard to climate change. Why have we—and by
‘we’ I mean knowing politicians, scientists, entrepreneurs, campaigners, citizens—failed to reign-in
humanity’s growing influence on the world’s climate? Why do we talk up climate change, but play
dumb when challenged about the response? Why has another global gathering of politicians, diplomats
and negotiators—most recently at Warsaw in December 2013—again prevaricated and stalled?
2. “The Plan”
For more than 25 years the conventional view has been that an international political solution
to climate change can be negotiated if driven by the engine of science. That is, if a strong enough
scientific consensus on the causes and consequences of anthropogenic climate change could be
forged and sustained, then the compelling force of such rationality would over-ride the differences in
worldviews, beliefs, values and ideologies which characterise the human world. Such a scientific
consensus would bring about the needed policy solutions. This is the “If-then” logic of computer
programming, the conviction that the right way to tackle climate change is through what Dan
Sarewitz at Arizona State University has called “The Plan” [8]. And there are those who still believe
in this project. They excoriate others who obstruct and obscure this pure guiding light of
rationality—a position adopted, for example, by Naomi Oreskes and Erik Conway in their recent
book Merchants of Doubt [9].
From the vantage point of 2014 we can now see that the credibility of such a narrative hinged on
a set of circumstances peculiar to the late 1980s and early 1990s. These included: (i) the belief in
149
the “end of history” and the triumph of (neo-)liberal democracy; (ii) the seeming continued
marginalisation of religion in public life; and (iii) the emergence of a globalised environmental
science. This latter enterprise secured its first big success in 1987, when the predictive power of the
newly minted Earth System science was co-opted by the Montreal Protocol on Substances that
Deplete the Ozone Layer. It was the convergence of these circumstances in the years around 1990
that helped fashion the conventional climate change project—“The Plan”—and allowed it to surge
forward with optimism.
At the time it seemed entirely reasonable that with one of the last “enemies” of progressive
Enlightenment liberalism having been swept away (i.e., communism), a new irrepressible world
order would emerge. And it would be one that would now fully exploit the predictive power of
fruitful globalised science. The putative threat that a burgeoning carbon-fuelled humanity—thriving,
ironically, through the fruit of this very same Enlightenment—was posing to climatic stability would
be defused. This project would demonstrate decisively the force of scientific rationality over the
fading and divisive powers of religion and ideology. Scientific consensus would forge political
consensus and political consensus would yield victory. And victory would be the Salvation of
the planet.
3. Failed Salvation
This “salvation project” has now run its course, abjectly halted by a combination of the events
of December 2009 (the COP15 meeting at Copenhagen and the Climategate fiasco) and the world
financial crisis. Even though the project still has its believers, the world has seen another climate
conference—COP19 in Warsaw—pass away. The Kyoto Protocol remains alive—but only on a life
support machine—and the haggling amongst developed nations over $100 billion of new funding for
mitigation and adaptation investments in developing countries is yielding very little. The old-guard
believers in “The Plan” are dwindling in number and many are reluctantly and uneasily shifting their
beliefs. The world of Rio+20 in 2012 looked and felt very different to the one George H W Bush
(senior) inhabited when he made his way to Rio de Janeiro 20 years earlier. Instead of the end of
history, what we are witnessing is a flowering of the irrepressible diversity of human beliefs, ideologies
and scepticisms. This flowering is manifest in various ways: (i) around the world in resurgent
religious confidence and vitality; (ii) on the internet through increasingly combative exchanges; and
(iii) in the West through a deep questioning of the capitalist neo-liberal paradigm. There is no better
example of this latter mood than The Dark Mountain Project in the UK, which announces itself as
“the new cultural movement for the age of disruption” [10]. This diversity of human beliefs and
aspirations is irrepressible because of the foundational human need for alterity: the need to define
ourselves in relation to ‘the other’. Cosmopolitanism has its limits.
Far from the end of history, then, and the inexorable onward march of the secular project, we are
witnessing an overdue reconsideration of the place of rationality in human knowing. There is a
challenging re-examination underway of the role of religion in the public sphere [11,12]. Secularisation
has taken an unexpected turn. New forms of deliberation and decision-making which accommodate
entrenched plurality—both religious and ideological—are having to be invented. This is well illustrated
by Bruno Latour’s 2013 Gifford Lectures, “Facing Gaia: a new inquiry into natural religion” [13].
150
We need to recognise that two climates have changed since the late 1980s: local cultural, economic
and political climates have changed as much as has the global physical climate. Not surprisingly,
cumbersome international efforts at dealing with climate change have been increasingly wrong-footed
by these new cultural and political dynamics. And in the vanguard of those who have realised
the futility of more of the same tired programmatic climate change agenda are some progressive
environmentalists. These fall into two camps.
On the one hand are those like Ted Nordhaus and Michael Shellenberger in the United States who
announced a few years ago “the death of environmentalism”. At the Breakthrough Institute they have
inspired a new breed of climate pragmatists who are promoting a universal call for human dignity in
development to be at the centre of a new re-constructed climate policy agenda. On the other hand are
those environmental thinkers who realise the need to engage in more direct public argument over
cultural values, in particular to question the dominant extrinsic values which drive material consumption.
This is epitomized for example by Tom Crompton’s work with the UK environmental NGOs and his
strategy document Common Cause: The Case for Working with Values and Frames [14].
These two reactions to the sterile politics of climate change—to the futility of “The Plan”—adopt
different reasoning and language. But they are united in their conviction that scientific knowledge
about climate cannot be the primary motivator and driving engine of change. Indeed, the more
trenchant critics would now argue that the product of climate science—uncertain predictions presented
as a solidified and settled consensus—has perhaps acted as much as an obstacle as it has a spur to
policy enactment. Science has done what it can. It has shown us the extent of the interpenetration of the
human and the material—“we are without nature” [15]; the Earth’s climate is now a prosthetic to
humanity. And yet we remain confronted with the limits of our programmatic responses to climate
change, whether they be political, economic, technological or social engineering. Climate change is
a condition of late modernity, yet it is a condition which modernity does not know how either to
alleviate or to live with.
It is in the context of this historical trajectory and these cultural dynamics of environmentalism
that I suggest a different direction. In my pursuit of the idea of climate change I want to focus
attention on the ancient idea of virtue, the possibility that the “wickedness” of climate change as a
problem demands a flowering of human “goodness”. Some of the language that I adopt will seem far
away from the usual vocabulary of climate change—“tipping points”, “two degrees”, “emissions
trading”, “low carbon economy”, “climate adaptation”. But listen carefully to the new voices speaking
in the desert—some of whom I mentioned at the beginning—and one will hear a new language
emerging around the fringes of climate change research, discourse and action… the language of
empathy, story-telling, trust, wisdom, humility, integrity, faith, hope and love. I want to suggest that
this is a vocabulary which, carefully deployed and realised, constitutes a re-discovery of virtue.
I need to be clear. A focus on human virtue is not a political programme. This is no techno-fix for
climate change, no system for Earth governance, no exercise in social engineering. And the argument
that I make reaches beyond a narrow naturalistic (utilitarian) approach to ethics and morality, such as
recently developed by Sam Harris in his book The Moral Landscape [16]. Those who were
151
disappointed with my earlier book Why We Disagree about Climate Change [17] because they
interpreted it as evasive, will probably continue to be disappointed. Indeed, the seeds of my current
line of thinking were already sown in Why We Disagree, as environmental commentator Richard D
North astutely observed in his review of the book: “Mike Hulme’s point is that Man’s response to
anthropogenic global warming ought to transcend thinking about agency, efficacy or instrumentality.
Anthropogenic global warming ought to be the catalyst for a redesign of Man, rather than of a human
attempt to redesign the climate he lives in. Anthropogenic global warming should thus be seen
reflexively. It’s about what anthropogenic global warming works on Man, not what Man works
on climate” [18]. So I am certainly not offering to “solve” climate change, nor even suggesting it can
be solved.
But the position I develop allows, I believe, the secular project to engage with climate change—at
least the secular project as defined by philosopher Charles Taylor. In A Secular Age [19], Taylor
argues that the dilemma of secularism is not how to manage, position or suppress religion. Rather
it is a problem of how diversity, plurality and alterity are recognised and respected in political
decision-making in contemporary societies. This is true even in cosmopolitan societies. Perhaps it is
true especially in cosmopolitan societies. In conversation with Taylor in 2009, sociologist Craig
Calhoun remarked: “The public sphere is … a realm of cultural formation in which argument is not
the only important practice … creativity and ritual, celebration and recognition are all important.
[The public sphere] includes the articulation between deep sensibilities and explicit understandings
and it includes the effort—aided sometimes by prophetic calls to attention—to make the way we
think and act correspond to our deepest values or moral commitments” ([12], pp. 132–33).
At the end of Why We Disagree, I drew attention to the very acute dilemma climate change
presents us with. It is the challenge of embarking on a global project of climate management (or even
engineering) when the very values required to design and deliver such a project are deeply contested.
It is a dilemma which science is powerless to resolve. Worse still; by seeking to use science as the
primary means to resolve the dilemma, we are obscuring the nature of the dilemma itself. Climate
change thus operates as the exemplar of a much wider conundrum with which political philosophers
and science studies scholars continue to struggle: what sources of authority are adequately founded,
and appropriately transcendent, to justify and empower political projects which reach beyond
conventional jurisdictions? There are a variety of responses to this conundrum as it applies to climate
change. My response here draws upon humanist values and traditions, both religious and non-religious.
It recognises the limitations of modernity and recognises the multiplicities of knowledges (different
rationalities) that remain potent in the world today. It extends my horizons beyond the natural
sciences and social sciences, with which I primarily worked in Why We Disagree, towards the
environmental humanities, in particular the deployment of virtue ethics alongside geographical
sensibility and imagination (see also Sandler and Cafaro’s book Environmental Virtue Ethics [20]).
5. Virtue
I mentioned before that for some environmental commentators, such as Tom Crompton,
the challenges of climate change and the failure of “The Plan” has led to a public questioning of
values. But for others, the searching has gone deeper. For them, the idea of climate change has been
152
less a catalyst for re-shaping human values than it has been a provocation to re-discover the nature
and practice of what we may call, along with the ancients, human virtue: this tried and tested exercise
in contemplation, self-discovery and human living. Or, in the words of Calhoun above, “to make the
ways we think and act, correspond to our deepest values or moral commitments”. Taking seriously
the challenges to human well-being raised by climate change, some entrepreneurial humanists
and theologians—and, more surprisingly, some scientists such as those with whom I opened this
essay—have asked us to contemplate anew virtues such as wisdom, humility, integrity, faith, hope
and, above all, the virtue of love.
So let me sketch out an apologetic for such calls to virtuous living as they apply to climate change:
to show how the exercise of virtue can transform both the quality of public deliberation and the
efficacy of the human individual as a public actor (cf. [21]). Practicing virtue can offer substantive,
instrumental and normative benefits for dealing with the challenges of climate change. Substantively,
through the exercise of virtue public knowledge of climate change will be modified, if not transformed.
Instrumentally, when contributing to public discourse and deliberation about responses to climate
change, the exercise of virtue can inspire and deliver change. And, normatively, in the personal realm
it is right and good to be virtuous: virtue is indeed the true telos of Man. I start by emphasising
the relevance of individual virtue when engaging with the idea of climate change, drawing upon
Christian tradition and particularly the work of Tom Wright, ex-Bishop of Durham and now
professor of New Testament and Early Christianity at the University of St. Andrews, in his book
Virtue Reborn [6]. I then very briefly engage with two other more collective applications of virtue
philosophy as advanced by particular authors: the idea of civic virtue, persuasively laid out by
political scientist Melissa Lane in her recent book Eco-Republic: Ancient Thinking for a Green Age [22]
and virtue ethics, made popular in recent years by the Catholic philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre in his
classic work After Virtue [23], and recently reviewed by Guy Axtell and Philip Olson [24].
Some words first, then, about the exercise of individual virtue in the context of climate change.
There are of course many lists of human virtues, from that of Aristotle onwards. I am not particularly
interested in a close scrutiny of the different logics behind these various lists, other than to note
that they share one common feature: they encompass those qualities which, if owned, will enable an
individual to secure eudaimonia: a state of blessedness, happiness, well-being. Whether they be
Aristotelian, Pauline or more contemporary, virtues are recognised by the prevailing culture as
enabling human life to be lived at its best. I wish here to consider the virtues of wisdom, humility,
integrity, faith, hope and love, and I offer a brief word about each in the context of climate change.
There has been a resurgence of interest in the idea of wisdom, both as embodied in traditional
human cultures or religions, but also as understood as a form of knowledge in its own right. We
might approach the virtue of wisdom through the idea of phronesis—practical wisdom or “expert
knowledge in the fundamental pragmatics of life” ([25], p. 188)—as popularised by social scientist
Bent Flyvbjerg [26] and by Alasdair MacIntyre. Or we might approach wisdom as psychologist
Robert Sternberg has done in terms of balance [27]—the wise person knows how to weigh competing
interests and strategies across the temporal, the narcissistic and the geographical dimensions of
living. Either way, paying greater attention to the search for, and the exercise of, wisdom counteracts
deficiencies in modernist and reductionist forms of knowledge about climate change.
153
Particular forms of knowledge or technology may also be critiqued through the virtue of humility.
Humility draws attention to the limits to scientific knowledge, especially such knowledge of the
climatic future with its essential openness and indeterminacy. Various authors have valorised humility
in this context and contrasted it with displays of hubris in much climate science research, writing and
advocacy. This contrast is revealed most acutely perhaps in the new discourse of planetary climate
engineering, as Clive Hamilton has shown [28]. More broadly, Sheila Jasanoff makes the case for
humility in the design of climate policies: “Policies based on humility might: redress inequality
before finding out how the poor are hurt by climate change; value greenhouse gases differently
depending on the nature of the activities that give rise to them; and uncover the sources of
vulnerability in fishing communities before installing expensive tsunami detection systems” ([3], p. 33).
Third, integrity is an important virtue in the context of trust. This was acutely observed in the
controversies surrounding the emails released from the Climatic Research Unit at the University of
East Anglia a few years ago. Were climate scientists to be trusted for the quality of their work and for
the integrity of their dealings with colleagues and opponents alike? What norms and values guided
their behaviour and were these recognised to be virtuous in wider cultural settings? The virtue of
integrity also draws attention to the eternal human struggle for personal lives to be lived with honesty
or, in the language of social psychologists examining climate change and pro-environmental behaviours,
by closing the “value-action gap”: we do not execute what we profess. Attention to such matters
would, for example, draw upon ideas of professional and practice-centred virtue ethics [29].
Faith can be considered a virtue and it too plays a central part in relationships of trust. And faith is
an integral part of the scientific endeavour as much as it is central in social relations. More than a
virtue, faith becomes a necessity. An examination of faith becomes an examination of the relationship
between belief and doubt, between “certainty” and “uncertainty”. Faith is the way in which humans
navigate between the poles of dogma and ignorance and it applies to secular or personal knowledge
as much as to religious or spiritual knowledge. We can see quickly how this becomes relevant in the
context of climate change knowledge and discourse. But in the context of responding to climate
change this raises the key question “Faith in what?”—in science, technology, political authority,
democracy, deities, the idea of progress?
And so faith is inseparable from the virtue of hope: Faith in what? Hope for what? Hope is one of
the most important of virtues, even if it goes largely unrecognised in Aristotelian or other secular
lists. Hope captures the human relationship with the future. If human knowledge is inescapably
bound up with the notion of faith, then our relationship with the future is written in the language of
hope (see [30]). Of course we may see the general future—or our own personal future—as hopeful or
hopeless, but the virtue of hope captures something about the unquenchable human desire for something
better. Hope, then, is a virtue which needs nourishing, in both public and personal settings.
Finally there is the virtue of love. But what is love? When Tim Flannery invoked love at the end of
his book Here on Earth he most likely was thinking of the idea of biophilia—literally, the love of
living things—introduced by Edward O Wilson in his eponymous 1984 book [31] and further
developed by Steve Kellert at Yale University. But love is multi-faceted and perhaps ineffable, as
countless human thinkers, poets, prophets and song-writers have explored through the ages. C S
Lewis offered his own attempt to grasp the complexity of love in The Four Loves [32], in which he
154
laid out a Christian typology of love according to affection (storge), friendship (philia), sex (eros)
and charity (agape). Love in the forms of philia and agape—and its close companions, compassion
and self-sacrifice—needs cultivating in public and private spheres.
Let me now consider how this commitment to virtue as a guiding disposition in response to
climate change can operate in different settings. First, the idea of civic virtue: the cultivation of
personal habits which can transform the success of the community. In Eco-Republic, Princeton
scholar Melissa Lane revisits Plato’s model for defining the relationship between society and the
individual—what Plato called “the city and the soul”. At the heart of Plato’s argument was that the
exercise of individual virtues—the pursuit of the good—in public life matters profoundly for the
well-being and stability of a just society. Or as the Jewish proverb from about 500 years before Plato
claimed: “Through the blessing of the upright a city is exalted, but by the mouth of the wicked it is
destroyed” [33].
Lane extends Plato’s argument in two ways. First, she shows how in the contemporary world “the
city” embraces material planetary ecologies, most notably the climate, upon which human sustenance
crucially depend. This is the eco-turn of Plato’s Republic. Second, she contends that the guardianship
of civic virtue is not the preserve of Plato’s elite—the wise rulers—but is a role to which all
participants in the Republic are called. This, then, is the democratic turn. And this requires a more
virtuous, engaged and demonstrative role for individual human agency in the demos. (This argument
is also developed by Colin Farelly [34]). Here virtue ethics and discourse ethics meet. As Tom
Wright describes in Virtue Reborn, “We are going to need [virtue] in the days to come, as world
population increases, food sources and supply chains present new problems and the world’s climate
changes alarmingly. We cannot assume that the whole world will steadily become more and more
dominated by Western-style liberal democracy, with people meekly voting every once in a while and
doing their own thing between elections” ([6], p. 201).
And then finally a brief mention of virtue ethics and climate change. From MacIntyre’s classic
defence of virtue ethics [23] let me highlight two points which I think are relevant for thinking about
climate change. First is his historicisation of the arguments among the three main families in ethical
theory—consequentialist, Kantian and virtue-based. For MacIntyre, consequentialist and deontological
ethics in Western tradition have become detached in recent centuries from any larger moral narrative
in which they may originally have been grounded in. For him they have lost authenticity and power
as a consequence. This is an outcome of modernity, the same modernity—we might claim—which
has placed humans as controller of the Earth’s climate. And as contemporary climate ethicists such as
Dale Jamieson and Stephen Gardiner have argued [35,36], a condition created by modernity requires
a response guided by more than the ethics of that same modernity. Or to quote Einstein: “We can’t
solve problems by using the same kind of thinking we used when creating them”. The second point to
emphasise is how, for MacIntyre, morals and virtues can only be comprehended through their relation
to the community from which they arise. Rather than deriving our principles of justice from behind
an imagined Rawlsian veil of ignorance, which detaches and abstracts us from our social relationships
and cultural commitments, MacIntyre’s virtue ethics commits us to derive our ethics from within
155
these inter-human matrices of meaning and belonging. And for me this offers a more credible,
situated and plural way—not necessarily an easier or more universal way—of thinking about the
intractable ethics of climate change.
7. How to Proceed?
The above comments are only an initial outline of arguments from an ex-climate scientist that may
be put forward for a virtue-based engagement with the challenges raised by climate change. For some
I am sure the cultivation and exercise of virtue is just too abstract, too philosophical, to count as
‘climate change action’. Indeed, as Zyl observes, “Critics of virtue ethics have argued that its focus
on character rather than action, as well as its rejection of universal rules of right action, renders virtue
ethics unable to shed much might on the question of what ought and ought not to be done in specific
situations” ([37], abstract). Surely something more ambitious and programmatic is called for? “It is
Hulme again indulging in defeatism and quietism”, I hear them say. “He is running away from the
real challenges of climate change”. But let me finish with a few short reflections on two different
practical traditions for cultivating virtue—one ancient and religious, and one contemporary and
secular—suggesting that the cultivation of virtue is in fact far from abstract, even if it doesn’t stop
climate changing.
The ancient tradition I offer comes from the Christian faith. Bishop David Atkinson has explained
how climate change challenges Christian theology and practice: “the questions posed by climate
change reach to the heart of faith: our relationship to God’s earth and to each other; the place of
technology; questions about sin and selfishness, altruism and neighbour love; what to do with our
fears and vulnerabilities; how to work for justice especially for the most disadvantaged parts of the
world and for future generations” [38]. A Christian response to climate change therefore involves the
community of believers, in theological terms ‘the body of Christ’. And since one of the abiding goals
of Christian community is the pursuit of holiness, Christians need to ask how virtue can be acquired
and exercised? Or as Tom Wright puts it, “How can we acquire that complex ‘second nature’ which
will enable us to grow up as genuine human beings” ([6], p. 220). Wright then offers a virtuous circle
in which five elements work together to cultivate character: community, stories, scripture, practices,
examples. One can recognise in this schema elements that are not unique to Christian tradition. They
are ones that can be developed in many different cultural settings by paying attention to: the wisdom
of the past; human life stories or myths; rituals which reinforce connectivity and commitment;
community which reaffirms individuals’ self-worth.
And to emphasise the universal appeal of such a virtuous circle, let me cite a modernist equivalent.
This comes from the writings of the philosopher Alain de Botton and his recent “Manifesto for
Atheists: ten virtues for the modern age” [39]. For de Botton “the project of being good”—of being
virtuous we can say—“is as vital, or even more important than the project of being healthy” [40]. Or
by extension we might paraphrase, “being virtuous is even more important than stopping climate
change”. His ten virtues for the atheist to cultivate include patience, hope, forgiveness and sacrifice
and at least partly resonate with both Aristotle and St. Paul. There is “no scientific answer” de Botton
says as to which are most important, “but the key thing is to have some kind of list on which to flex
our ethical muscles” [40]. And how this is to be done bears a strong resemblance to Wright’s virtuous
156
circle: partaking in ritual, belonging to community, being inspired by human stories of faith, hope
and love.
8. Conclusions
I have suggested that there is a renewed interest from environmental scientists and environmental
social scientists in the idea of virtue and, in particular, its relationship with the sorts of questions
which the challenges of climate change ask us. This interest is also evidenced, for example, through
the work of environmental virtue ethicists such as Phil Cafaro [41]. I have given a short account of
how the conventional plan of climate salvation is failing and how this failure has led to this new
exploration of an ancient idea. I have given some token arguments of how the individual virtues of
wisdom, humility, integrity, faith, hope and love have relevance as we comes to terms with the
condition of a prosthetic climate and I have connected these to the collective projects of civic virtue
and virtue ethics. Finally, I have suggested that the cultivation of virtue is a very practical ambition
and one which can draw upon religious tradition and resources, which themselves can be partly
replicated in secular contexts.
My approach to climate change taken here may seem strange to those who see the dangers of
climate change as large, immanent and totalising. (Although I am not convinced this is the right way
to frame these risks). And the approach may seem irrelevant to those who believe these dangers can
be diffused only through various programmatic policy interventions. Yet the possible magnitude and
urgency of these dangers can only be judged relative to other dangers facing people in the world, to
our value commitments and to our own sense of what matters deeply. And the record to date—as I
have shown—can only lower ones expectations about what conventional programmatic policy
intervention around climate change can deliver.
I am suggesting something different. Rather than putting science, economics, politics or the
planet at the centre of the story of climate change I am suggesting that we put the humanities—our
self-understanding of human purpose and virtue—at the centre. When we talk about climate change
we should not start with the latest predictions from the climate models, nor whether we have passed
some catastrophic tipping point; nor whether or not the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change
should be trusted. We should start by thinking about what it means to be human. What is the good life
and what therefore is an adequate response to climate change? The issues about human life on a
changing planet are firstly humanistic and not scientific, as recognised by the European Science
Foundation’s recently completed Responses to Environmental and Societal Challenges to our
Unstable Earth project (note the implication in the project acronym, RESCUE, of a still-needed
salvation). The Anthropocene, they concluded, “creates a completely novel situation posing
fundamentally new questions, including issues related to ethics, culture, religion and human rights,
and requiring new approaches and ways of thinking, understanding and acting.” ([42], p. 13) This
goes well beyond the capabilities of “integrated knowledge systems” or the “processes of Earth
system governance”, themes beloved by the global change research community.
My purpose in drawing attention to the idea of virtue is to appreciate the insights of the humanities
and the relevance of the world’s religious faiths for thinking about climate change actions. Although
there are existing initiatives which seek to do this more broadly around religion and ecology
157
(e.g., [43]), and there are recent examples of edited collections and books which explore religion and
climate change [44–46], the large international global change research programmes tend to be either
unaware or else distant from them [47]. Reacting to the idea of climate change is about understanding
and cultivating the human imagination and developing an acute sense of good character as the telos
of Man, as much as it is about applying the instruments of reason and technology. I’m not sure that
this is exactly what underlies the global conversation about “the world we want” which was an
outcome of Rio+20; but perhaps it is at least a step in the right direction. We need to ask what is the
telos of Anthropos; what is the goal of Man—or what are “the aspirations of all citizens” as the call
from Rio+20 put it? Is it about (human) survival—at any cost? Is it about sustained economic growth
or maximising human longevity? Is it about social justice or securing some notion of political
freedom? What I am suggesting here is that we need a more explicit Aristotelian contemplation on
the good life, the nature of well-being and the cultivation of virtue. The question then becomes less
“the world we want” than it is ‘the people we should be’.
This may well not be an easy argument to take. It requires a brave move to doubt the efficacy of
solutions-oriented programmes to climate change—market fixes such as emissions trading, techno-fixes
such as climate engineering, behavioural fixes such as social marketing, political fixes such as Earth
system governance or even ethical fixes such as utilitarian or deontological ethics (see [48] for an
argument against the latter form of programmatic universalism). And yet the cultivation and exercise
of virtue is something that all of us humans can do. Indeed, perhaps it is something that all of us are
called to do—to realise Calhoun’s “unused intuitions that are somewhere buried”, to sustain the mutual
evocation of goodness and human dignity that alone transcends our diversity. Climate change
provides us this opportunity. As the esteemed Emeritus Professor of Geography at the University of
the Wisconsin-Madison, Yi-Fu Tuan, has argued recently, “the good shall inherit the Earth” [49].
Acknowledgments
An earlier version of this article was delivered at Queen’s University Belfast on 1 May 2013 as
the Annual Religious Studies Lecture. The valuable questions and comments of John Barry,
John Brewer, Jon Agnew and David Livingstone following this lecture are acknowledged. The
author also benefitted from a Rachel Carson Writing Fellowship at LMU Munich which supported
the preparation of this article. The valuable suggestions and corrections of three anonymous referees
are also acknowledged.
Conflicts of Interest
1. Tim Flannery. Here on Earth: a New Beginning. London: Allen & Lane, 2011.
2. Brendon Larson. Metaphors for Environmental Sustainability: Redefining our Relationship
with Nature. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2011.
3. Sheila Jasanoff. “Technologies of humility.” Nature 450 (2007): 33.
158
4. Alastair McIntosh. Hell and High Water: Climate Change, Hope and the Human Condition.
Edinburgh: Birlinn, 2008.
5. Tim Leduc. Climate, Culture, Change: Inuit and Western Dialogues with a Warming North.
Quebec: University of Ottawa Press, 2010.
6. Tom Wright. Virtue Reborn. London: SPCK, 2010.
7. The Guardian. “Ian McEwan Reveals the Inspiration for His ‘hero’ of His Climate Change
Novel Solar.” Part 1, c. 13 minutes. Available online: http://www.guardian.co.uk/science
/video/2012/jul/27/scienceofclimatechange-ianmcewan (accessed on 27 April 2014).
8. Dan Sarewitz. “Does climate change knowledge really matter?” WIREs Climate Change 2
(2011): 475–81.
9. Naomi Oreskes, and Erik Conway. Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists
Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming. London: Bloomsbury
Publishing, 2010.
10. The Dark Mountain Project. “The manifesto.” Available online: http://dark-mountain.net/
about/manifesto/ (accessed on 27 April 2014).
11. Rowan Williams. Faith in the Public Square. London: Bloomsbury Press, 2010.
12. Eduardo Mendieta, and Jonathan Vanantwerpen, eds. The Power of Religion in the Public
Sphere: Judith Butler, Jürgen Habermas, Charles Taylor, Cornel West. New York: Columbia
University Press, 2011.
13. Gifford Lectures. “Professor Bruno Latour: Facing Gaia: A new enquiry into natural religion.”
Available online: http://www.bruno-latour.fr/node/487 (accessed on 27 June 2014).
14. Tom Crompton. Common Cause: The Case for Working with our Cultural Values. London:
WWF-UK, 2010.
15. David Alberston, and Cabell King, eds. Without Nature? A New Condition for Theology. New
York: Fordham University Press, 2010.
16. Sam Harris. The Moral Landscape: How Science Can Determine Human Values. London:
Bantam Press, 2011.
17. Mike Hulme. Why We Disagree About Climate Change: Understanding Controversy, Inaction
and Opportunity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
18. Richard D North. “Climate change (AGW): Let’s take it seriously.” Available online:
http://richarddnorth.com/2009/12/climate-change-agw-lets-take-it-seriously/ (accessed on
27 April 2014).
19. Charles Taylor. A Secular Age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007.
20. Ronald Sandler, and Phil Cafaro. Environmental Virtue Ethics. Lanham: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2005.
21. Ronald Sandler. Character and Environment: A Virtue-Oriented Approach to Environmental
Ethics. New York: Columbia University Press, 2007.
22. Melissa Lane. Eco-Republic: Ancient Thinking for a Green Age. Oxford: Peter Lang, 2011.
23. Alastair MacIntyre. After Virtue, 3rd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007.
24. Guy Axtell, and Philip Olson. “Recent Work in Applied Virtue Ethics.” American Philosophical
Quarterly 49 (2012): 183–203.
159
25. Dragos Simandan. “The wise stance in human geography.” Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers 36 (2011): 188–92.
26. Bent Flyvbjerg. Making Social Science Matter: Why Social Inquiry Fails and How It Can
Succeed Again. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
27. Robert Sternberg. “WICS: a model of positive educational leadership comprising wisdom,
intelligence and creativity synthesized.” Educational Psychology Review 17 (2005): 191–262.
28. Clive Hamilton. Earthmasters: Playing God with the Climate. New Haven: Yale University
Press, 2013.
29. Justin Oakley, and Dean Cocking. Virtue Ethics and Professional Roles. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 2001.
30. Allen Thompson. “Radical Hope for Living Well in a Warmer World.” Journal of
Agricultural Environmental Ethics 23 (2010): 43–59.
31. Edward Wilson. Biophilia: The Human Bond With Other Species. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1984.
32. C. S. Lewis. The Four Loves. London: Fount Paperbacks/Collins, 1977.
33. Proverbs 11:11 (New International Version).
34. Colin Farrelly. Justice, Democracy and Reasonable Agreement. New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2007.
35. Dale Jamieson. Reason in a Dark Time: Why the Struggle against Climate Change
Failed—And What it Means for Our Future. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2014.
36. Stephen Gardiner. “Ethics and climate change: An introduction.” WIREs Climate Change 1
(2010): 54–66.
37. Liezl van Zyl. “Virtue Theory and Applied Ethics.” South African Journal of Philosophy 21
(2002): 133–44.
38. Operation Noah. “Why climate change is a confessional question.” Available online:
http://www.operationnoah.org/confessional-question (accessed on 27 April 2014).
39. Alain de Botton. Religion for Atheists: A Non-Believers Guide to the Uses of Religion.
London: Vantage, 2013.
40. Alain de Botton. Interview on BBC Radio 4 Saturday Live, 16 March 2013.
41. Phil Cafaro. “Introduction: Special Issue on Environmental Virtue Ethics.” Journal of
Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 23 (2010): 3–7.
42. European Science Foundation. Responses to Environmental and Societal Challenges to our
Unstable Earth. Strasbourg: European Science Foundation, 2012.
43. “The Forum on Religion and Ecology at Yale.” Available online: http://fore.research.yale.edu
(accessed on 19 June 2014).
44. Dieter Gerten, and Sigurd Bergmann, eds. Religion in Environmental and Climate Change:
Suffering, Values, Lifestyles. New York/London: Continuum Press, 2012.
45. Robin Veldman, Andrew Szasz, and Randy Haluza-Delay, eds. How the World’s Religions
are Responding to Climate Change: Social Scientific Investigations. Abingdon/New York:
Routledge, 2013.
160
46. Michael Northcott. Climate Change and Christian Ethics. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 2013.
47. Mike Hulme. “Meet the Humanities.” Nature Climate Change 1 (2011): 177–79.
48. Menno Kamminga. “The Ethics of Climate Politics: Four Modes of Moral Discourse
Environmental Politics 17 (2008): 673–92.
49. Yi-Fu Tuan. “The good inherit the Earth.” In Envisioning Landscapes, Making Worlds:
Geography and the Humanities. Edited by Stephen Daniels, Dydia DeLyser, Nicholas Entrikin
and Doug Richardson. Abingdon/New York: Routledge, 2007, pp. 127–40.
161
Abstract: The ways in which Humanities scholars talk about teaching tell something about how we
interact with the past of our own discipline as well as anticipate our students’ futures. In this we
express collective memories as truths of learning and teaching. As cultural artifacts of our present,
such stories are worthy of excavation for what they imply about ourselves as well as messages they
pass onto our successors. This paper outlines “collective re-membering” as one way to understand
these stories, particularly as they present in qualitative interviews commonly being used to research
higher education practice in the Humanities. It defines such collective re-membering through
an interweaving of Halbwachs, Ricoeur, Wertsch and Bakhtin. It proposes that a dialogic reading
between this understanding of collective re-membering and qualitative data-sets enables us to both
access our discursive tendencies within the Humanities and understand the impact they might have
on student engagement with our disciplines, noting that when discussing learning and teaching, we
engage in collectively influenced myth-making and hagiography. The paper finishes by positing that
the Humanities need to change their orientation from generating myths and pious teaching sagas
towards the complex and ultimately more intellectually satisfying, articulation of learning and
teaching parables1.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Gunn, V. Present Teaching Stories as Re-Membering the
Humanities. Humanities 2014, 3, 264–282.
1
This paper came together after I delivered a keynote presentation at the Higher Education Academy’s 2nd Annual
Arts & Humanities Learning and Teaching Conference: Storyville: Exploring narratives of learning and teaching.
I aim to capture the tone of this keynote’s “performance” in order to catch the spirit as well as the content of
its delivery.
162
Yet, simultaneously, the sentences above create and make public imaginary limits on how the
Humanities seem to understand themselves. They enclose the nature of our collaboration in a rhetoric
of uniqueness (uniquely indescribable but somehow linked to an interaction with the dead), cultivating
boundaries of inclusion and exclusion. For some, the story becomes a tale of happy-ever-after and,
for others, it becomes a bête noire. After all, the story conveyed above, if viewed in dramatic terms,
could be read as the tale of the necromancer: the ‘dead text’ is the focus of our epistemological
desires rather than humanity. Anxiety about this, for example, is writ large in Mikhail Epstein’s
manifesto on the transformative Humanities [4]. But what if you prefer a story in which the interactive
creativity of the Humanities is better described as flying with dragons than sleeping with the dead?
From the outset, we need to remember two vital and simultaneous aspects to tales: they can
function personally to ameliorate loneliness (allowing me to recognize others like me and assume
a broader accord) and socially (communicating boundaries to be traversed by those who are
not—yet—like me). The idea that ‘narrative is ontological’ (Munt [2], p. 5), means Humanities’
scholars must address the question of whether our daily communications, including those about how,
what, and why we teach, invite students to come into communion with us or act to exclude. Our tall
tales have an impact. If Munt is right and stories allow for identification with and recognition of one
another, which in turn results in a coherent web or network, our stories (and not just our practices)
about learning and teaching have the capacity to foster both belonging and alienation. As such those
of us dwelling in history, classics, literature, philosophy, theology have an ethical responsibility to
analyse them and consider their possible effect on our students’ learning (as well as the conceptual
construction of our disciplines).
2. Introduction
Debates about what the Humanities are for and what it is they should teach and foster in
universities seem to have become ubiquitous in the last decade [1,4–7]. From this has come a
burgeoning literature expressing why the Humanities “matter” [8–10]. Maintaining a legitimate
sense of place within universities at the same time as responding to transformations in both our
research processes and teaching environments has created, in some, a sense of crisis. For others,
however, it presents an opportunity to revisit the material world within the Humanities [11] as well as
the space for propagating new genres and disciplines ([4], p. 290), and reforming the undergraduate
curriculum [12,13]. In responding to the identification of where enhancement to learning and teaching
needs to occur if we are to attend effectively to the, “why the Humanities matter” agendas, it has
provided fertile fields from which to harvest swathes of qualitative data (See [14,15] as examples of
this). This is perhaps particularly true of those of us who work in the advancement of higher education
but are still embedded/wedded to our work in the Humanities’ disciplines in the traditional sense. For
all, a perception of crisis, or at least the need to change, drives an underlying sense of urgency.
In the abounding discussion stories about learning and teaching are told and some of these
tales provide the basis of this paper’s orientation. I start from a pragmatic place: Stories about what
a Humanities education is for and why it matters emerge as much informally and locally in
conversations as much as globally through publications: how do these stories impact subsequently on
our students perceptions of what being in the Humanities means in terms of imagining the discipline
163
and studying within it? How might these students come to work for themselves and for the good of
the Humanities from their understanding of these stories? Arguably, the implied cues in our discussions
function as part of the inter-subjective canon of disciplinary socialization. They are an aspect of the
day-to-day level of organizational cultures and as such play into the “technologies of the self”,
conducting personal adoption and incorporation of certain narratives so that membership can be felt
and shown. This is not to deny student agency (through rejection or transformation of the stories) or
to reify the idea that we are the dominating force in their undergraduate lives (and thus that they
inherit our stories because of that dominance), rather it is to point out the potential of our stories
to have unintended directional power via relational networks. What is inferred from our stories
open and close avenues of academic pursuit and consequently influence degrees of engagement and
inclusion. As such, where our students’ learning is concerned, we evade their symbolic power at
our peril.
The question is, of course, how do we construct a convincing interpretation to critique our own
discursive tendencies and their apparently panoptic powers? To date, higher educational studies on
such tendencies rely heavily on inductive research methods primarily dependent on qualitative
interviews without exploiting any Humanities’ theoretical paradigms at the coding and analysis
stage. As such a trick is being missed: as ‘insider researchers’ of our own practice, Humanities theories
have much to offer in terms of helping us to understand ourselves as much as our texts. This is not to
refute the importance of qualitative data as an intellectually fecund resource (and indeed two such
data-sets will be referred to here because of what they can illustrate [14,15]). Rather what is stressed
here is that to gain more robust pictures of what might be happening, where disciplinary contexts
have themselves produced theories about how cultures operate, it is effective to bring them into
dialogue with inductive methods focused on capturing our experience as academic teachers in
the Humanities.
From this place, the pivot of the article is: An underused but effective heuristic tool for accessing
how our university-based stories about pedagogical instruction are both composed locally and
function socially is collective re-membering (both the notion of and mechanisms behind how
memories can be social, collective, delineated spatially, and replayed outside of their original
time-space frames) and the theorizing underpinning it. We should embrace it as such when trying to
understand present disciplinary conversations about learning and teaching, as well as how cues taken
from them might impact on our students’ futures.
To create a structure from which to explore how we might come to say the things we do in
qualitative interviews (arguably the artifacts of such conversations) and what, in turn, might be
inferred from the content of such narratives, I concentrated specifically on writings about collective
memory: Recruited for the key protagonists were: Maurice Halbwach’s, The Collective Memory
(1980), On Collective Memory (1992) [16,17]. Added to these were cameo but relevant roles to
be played by components of Paul Ricoeur’s, Memory, History, Forgetting (2004), James Wertsch’s
(2002) concept of collective remembering and Bakhtinian (Bakhtin, 1986) notions of speech
genres [18–20]. The method which unfolded symbolizes a promiscuous polymathery on my part and,
164
from the outset, I acknowledge that liberties may have been taken with the scholarship of others to
create an interpretative framework. Structured interdisciplinary reading inevitably transfigures the
material on which it has drawn. Consequently, for specialists in the original canons, its results
often seem lacking in rigour and thus intellectually irritating. However, the emphasis in this paper is
on the transformation of the components into a slightly different whole through their interweaving.
To explore the implications of these interwoven readings, what follows is divided into the
following sections:
z A theoretical methodology that draws together: the nature of our qualitative data around learning
and teaching, the concept of collective memory, evidence of the limited geography in which we
come to construct narratives about pedagogy and instruction, and the potential to identify
particular speech genres within the data-sets. This means that to understand how our stories are
constructed we need to combine the social theorizing of Halbwachs and Ricoeur, with the
anthropological observations of Wertsch, and Bakhtin’s concept of speech genres. In the
interpretative dialogue between these works, four closely mingled assumptions about what
might be present in qualitative data related to learning and teaching emerges: Firstly, stories of
significance (even if apparently mundane) are recalled in interviews; secondly, we re-member
(recollect, recognize ourselves and others, and re-materialize) the teaching context when we
reflect on what we consider to be important about the links between teaching and learning in
such interviews; thirdly, re-membering involves not only our individually separable perceptions
and experiences but, via the process of recall, also the framing of them through an interaction
with a culturally shared repertoire of concerns, sentiments, and problem-solving approaches that
link us to our disciplinary predecessors as well as current colleagues; fourthly, and
consequently, that the concept of collective re-membering, predicated on the “irreducible
tension between active agent and cultural tool” [19,21], is a pragmatically useful interpretative
device when considering our findings. As a result of such a theoretical methodology, it is
asserted that the phrase collective re-membering is of more use than collective memory when we
consider our present teaching stories.
z Two short case studies which illustrate the implications of the theoretical methodology when
exploring the types of stories Humanities’ lecturers seem to build and maintain in conversations
about aspects of their teaching: Firstly, myths about transformational reciprocity in our discussion
of research-teaching linkages and, secondly, saints’ lives or sagas of inattention and suspicion
around institutional-level educational agendas such as employability and global citizenship
(particularly referred to collectively in the UK and Australia under the rubric of “graduate
attributes’ agendas”). These examples present story categories that emerged whilst I undertook
two qualitative research projects around how research-teaching linkages and graduate attributes
respectively currently operated within the Humanities [14,15] and a brief reference to each of
the data-sets introduces the case studies purely to establish the scene. Whilst by no means the
fulcrum of this paper, the gathering and interpretation of these projects’ related data represent
the back-story of the more theoretical discussion outlined here.
165
z A final section raising the question of whether we erect and excavate simultaneously the wrong
stories in our current designs of qualitative research when studying learning and teaching. This
section concludes that it would be better to cultivate different types of narratives within the
research process (particularly those being used by lecturers in the disciplines to understand
teaching practices). If we want to capture the nuances of our experience as academic teachers of
the Humanities, we actually need to shift the narratives/narrative resources on which we have
come to depend when talking about learning and teaching.
In the spirit of storytelling and deliberate playfulness that lay behind this article’s first outing as a
conference keynote, I have also pressed Herodotus into service to provide illuminating metaphors.
I have thus co-opted his description of Babylonian customs to emphasize or elucidate points. I ask
my readers, therefore, to imagine they are travelling along the Euphrates to Babylon, where a river of
interpretation runs through a city built from the fired bricks of primary and secondary sources.
4.1. Plot 1: Excavating the Emic Foundations of Our Stories: Bringing Qualitative Data Together
with the Concept of Collective Memory
Forms of qualitative inquiry, with narrative at their heart, dominate the higher education (HE)
learning and teaching landscape. The prominence of the single, semi-structured interview is embedded
across the journals which deal with higher education practice-based research. In particular, over the
last decade, a significant amount of emic material has been recorded and analyzed in terms of the
outcomes of research-teaching linkages across Anglophone and European universities [22]. The
Humanities have certainly not been immune to this trend [14,23]. Through our conversations with
and as educational developers and researchers we have arguably been reflecting back local customs,
meanings, and beliefs, rather than illustrating our material practices and how these might be
contradictory or dissonant to our narratives about those practices [24]. These conversations are only
concerned with communicating the meanings we ascribe to our actions, harmonizing ideal and
experience and giving only one side of an insider’s view [25]. Through them we tell our stories.
Additionally, the ascription of meaning is part of the constant dialogue between individual
memory and the socio-cultural tools which help in its formation. As Ricoeur observes, “it is essentially
along the path of recollection and recognition that we encounter the memories of others” ([18],
p. 120). Our stories tell of how we make meaning of teaching situations and in so doing generate
recollection, recognition, and thus to a certain extent re-materialization through conversation. Our
recall of such stories in interviews is thus in part informed by collective (and in this case, often
disciplinary) memories. With regard to making meaning of current learning and teaching situations
and what we value as important, this suggests the possibility of uncovering a shared repertoire of
concerns, sentiments, disciplinary morality, and phraseology that links our narratives to the past.
In effect, it suggests a Halbwachs-like underlying mechanism operating between our contemporary
experience and that of our disciplinary predecessors. Thus, what we say in qualitative interviews is a
location not only for the excavation of our individual story but also the collective re-membering
166
retained in the story. Our transcripts hint at the past beyond our immediate experience, expanding the
time-frame in which the story was generated. (Reflecting on Halbwachs, Ricoeur refers to this as a
widening of the temporal horizon of younger generations, [18], p. 394).
4.2. Plot 2: Discovering that Collective Memories are Constructed in the Public Square
If collective re-membering fashions our stories into a form of archaeological artifact, we need to
excavate the factors involved in the propagation of a commonly shared repertoire that links the
contemporary generation of disciplinary academics to the past. Here, Herodotus can help. When
describing Babylonian customs, Herodotus notes that the sick do not consult physicians but rather, if
someone is ill, they are laid in the public square and if the passers-by have had a similar ailment or
know someone themselves who has had the disease, they: “give him advice, recommending him to
do whatever they found good in their own case, or in a case known to them.” (Herodotus, Histories,
1:197). We have a similar process when it comes to learning about how to resolve issues in teaching.
Studies make it quite clear that when we have a problem-solving situation in our classrooms,
we are highly likely to prefer the example or advice of an associate to abstract theory or empirical
findings ([26], p. 116).
Like the Babylonians, when it comes to teaching, rather than going for a robust evidence-base,
Humanities academics enter the disciplinary public square to see how colleagues made meaning out
of an apparently similar situation. In this we encounter a context where how we remember the
circumstances and what is important to value is directly influenced by the “interruption” of our
colleagues. In turn, those colleagues may well be recalling what they heard previously. This process
is similar, then, to Halbwach’s notion that collective memories are “recalled to us through others
even though only we were participants in the events” ([16], p. 23). We have the original experience,
but in discussion with others, there is the potential for a collectively influenced reframing. How we
make sense of the circumstances becomes entwined with the register of sense-making of our
predecessors as well as our contemporaries.
4.3. Plot 3: Finding the Public Square Turned into a Disciplinary Gated-Community
The prologue noted how stories can function to invite in or exclude those who encounter them,
which raises the question of whether our collective re-membering operates in such a way that the
public square conversations increasingly occur within a virtual fence, one that includes and excludes.
The work on significant conversational networks about learning and teaching analyzed in Roxä and
Märtensson [27,28] demonstrates how the bulk of conversational “passers-by” in the public square
are drawn from our immediate disciplinary circle. The resultant network is based on trust, privacy,
and shared intellectual problem-solving regarding teaching. What this means is, we have a clique to
whom and from whom we construct our understanding of teaching. Our insularity can turn the public
square into a virtually gated community.
Given that collective culture will orchestrate forgetting as well as re-membering, the skewing
of our meaning-making towards a dominant or authoritative narrative within it becomes more
probable [29,30]. This is not to deny the role of contestation and mediation within the process, which
167
Halbwachs failed to address ([30], p. 379) and is increasingly the focus of debate [19]. Instead, it is to
indicate the possibility of repetitions across generations that would result in a shared repertoire
(sometimes regardless of changes to the material circumstances) because of the apparent legitimacy
and authority associated with collective memories.
Recognizing this is important because, if Boyer and Wertsch ([31], p. 113) are right, the cultural
“tools” represented in such repetitions express a particular agenda or goal (an implicit plot perhaps)
without seeking recourse to explicit standards of veracity (as is witnessed when our discourse slips
into nostalgia, for example). Indeed, if we examine what our qualitative data-sets suggest about our
agendas related to the links between research, teaching and graduate attributes, what is exhibited
maps onto evidence of how collective re-memories function, including:
(1) Toleration of distortion (such as inconsistencies between espoused over-all beliefs about
learning and teaching and the narrative resources used to illustrate what we mean);
(2) Smoothing over of paradoxes;
(3) Inattention to omissions. In re-narration, for example, problematic and ambiguous content is
often omitted ([32], p. 15). For Halbwachs this is one of the ways we deal with “inconvenient
memories” ([17], p. 50);
(4) Assimilation of our senior colleagues’ memories. This may “widen our temporal horizon”,
giving us access to practical wisdom evolved over time, but it might also imprison the
conversations in a passive persistence of first impressions ([18], pp. 394, 427), circumscribing
criticality and consequential expertise acquisition;
(5) Amalgamation of phantoms which allow our immediate past to be linked to
decontextualised beliefs about disciplinary predecessors we have not known. These
phantoms often help locate our identity in a more positive history of the discipline. This
process, in turn, can lapse into nostalgia and stereotyping, suppressing negative aspects
of the longer past in the service of the kind of people we are or assume ourselves to be
(see: [21]). These phantoms, in effect, enable us to engage historical representations to
provoke and solidify particular identity-oriented affect and meaning (see: [33], p. 16).
In this such phantoms lead to:
(6) Provision of forms of moral regulation.
In the process of translating practical wisdom from one situation to another, the plot may be subtly
driven by established frameworks so that sight of the need to be creative is lost. Moreover, the
translations cultivate a portfolio of narratives that exclude those who fail to accept the incorporated
distortions, impressions, phantoms, and moral regulation.
(as defined by [20], pp. 60–62) and secondary discourse genres (of particular relevance here is the
secondary literature produced about the nature of a given discipline that could be characterized as
manifesto-like: ([20], p. 62; [34]). This liminal discourse genre, articulated in the light of work by
Hengst and Miller, Maingueneau and Hyland [34–37], is discussed more fully elsewhere ([38],
pp. 75–77). In short, however, it:
z Represents a phase before formalization;
z Relates to how the speaker brings their Self into play with their discipline;
z Captures cultural and moral themes;
z Is developed in a relatively unmediated communion within specific significant networks in
the disciplinary teaching arena and consequently is generative of a gated community.
More specifically, these liminal discourses absorb academic desires and values which in turn can
be transferred through interpersonal reception. How students engage with them explicitly relates to
the key point of this paper: stories can appear to be invitations “in” or seem to reject and as such, we
need to understand what they look like and how they seem to operate amongst the student body if we
are to really come to grips with student disciplinary development.
If there are inherent connections between such a liminal discourse genre and collective
re-membering, relevant narrative forms generated through communication processes are worthy of
critique. In terms of relevance to this paper’s subsequent focus on the types of stories which represent
narrative forms of collective re-membering, the important point to note is: such a genre plays a role in
both reflecting back primary speech genres and generating forward the more formalized texts identified
as part of secondary speech genres (e.g., manifestos). Effectively, this is a dialogic process in which
the local gets projected outwards and the global reflected back inwards. It is because of this process
that, when we come to look at the story types, secondary texts relating to arguments about the nature
of the Humanities are compared with the interview data.
With all these interwoven ideas in mind, the key question becomes: what in our story types
suggests the embedding of collective re-membering and its attendant sense of recognition and
identification? Ideally, we should be able to observe shared concerns, sentiments, disciplinary
morality and even phraseology. There may also be a hint of an extended time-frame, suggestive of
the incorporation of our predecessors’ experiences. In terms of excavation, our interpretation is
underpinned by an understanding that there was an original impulse behind the development of such
collective re-membering, an original need that generated a way of dealing with or justifying a
particular situation which subsequently became a fixed conversational object. Arguably, a dissonance
between this fixed object and associated explanations might hint at an artifact of collective
re-membering and thus should be the target of critical attention (otherwise we might indeed be
caught in the passive persistence of first impressions). The two case studies below attempt to
illustrate this and also suggest why being aware of such story types is of importance for our students’
engagement with our disciplines. The first case study draws together insights from a qualitative
169
research project based on 7 semi-structured interviews from the Humanities in Scottish universities [14].
The 7 interviewees were two Historians, one Classicist, one Philosopher, two Theologians and one
person from Film and TV Studies. The second case study reflects on 5 semi-structured interviews,
one each from Classics, English Literature, Theology and two from Celtic Studies, all at one
research-intensive institution in Scotland [15]. Both case studies explore particular propensities in
the qualitative data sets as well as the secondary literature on the nature of our disciplines: a leaning
towards myth-making in terms of the pedagogy of the Humanities being intrinsically reciprocal and
an inclination to saga-making with respect to educational agendas that we associate with any
emphasis on the utility of higher education.
The first of the liminal discourse genres to illustrate are teaching myths. A key story we retell in
the literature to describe the nature of our scholarship suggests that the link between research and
teaching is based on a fundamentally transformational process which is a “multi-dimensional,
mind-altering experience” rather than a vocational one ([39], p. 10) and is achieved through
conversational/dialogic reciprocity. I found a similar assumption present in the transcripts that I
gathered as part of the 2008–2009 Research-Teaching Linkages project [14]. As one of my interviewees
summed up: “on the Arts side of the university we are not engaged in vocational training. We are
engaged in developing multi-sided people who can engage with a whole range of different problems
and techniques such as information retrieval, constructive engagement/critical engagement with
information, sifting information and also making judgments on the basis of the past or past
experience.” (Historian).
In bringing that data-set together with the secondary discourse genres, it became clear that
reciprocal conversation is behind this development and occurs between three inter-linked groups: our
texts, our colleagues and our students (not necessarily in that order of importance).
5.1. Reciprocity with Our Texts: When does Collaboration with the Dead Become Necromancy?
From the outset I noted the extent to which it is possible to identify with Collini’s notion that our
scholarship has a relational element with those who died generations and centuries ago. Additionally,
anyone who has spent time reading, contemplating and changing their ideas about disciplinary
canons in the light of Gadamer [40], will argue (and I am one of these people) that interpretative
hermeneutics related to how we read our texts, also change how we read ourselves, which in turn
affects the direction of our lives. Add to this our engagement of students in the process and there is
clearly the potential for a triangular collaboration of present-day minds, historical intellectual
activity, and creativity. Yet, as Epstein notes, in our focus on our texts, have we turned away from
humans? Have, “to a certain extent, the Humanities stopped being human studies and become textual
studies, ...criticism rather than creativity and suspicion rather than imagination?” [4]. If this is the
case, do our claims to a holistic rather than a purely textual hermeneutic approach reflect a collective
re-membering more than a present-day actuality? What is clear is that the Humanities are developing
170
students’ ability to make qualitative judgements about the type and nature of information, what is
much less clear is how this is turned to questions about humanity. We are not quite necromancers,
yet, in our fixation with creating analytical frameworks to think originally about our texts and the
curation and categorisation of the canon of our disciplines inherent in this, have we been led away
from bigger humanistic questions? Have we become so centred on original ways of thinking about
the text that questions of human being and doing are side-lined in our teaching?
I admit that this was not a particular feature of the interviews I undertook, but is a common thread
in current debates about managerialism and the loss of collegiality across the Humanities [41]. I think
there is another aspect of the Humanities myth lurking in this discussion and we need to ask ourselves:
what do we really mean by collegiality in the Humanities? Perhaps we actually just use “collegiality”
as an antonym for corporate purpose ([42], p. 78) rather than as a description of the quality of our
relationships. How for that matter are polymaths collegial? In terms of the notion of gated
community mentioned earlier, the key point to acknowledge is that our peer-based social networks
operate through hierarchies of status [28]. This means that dominant and subordinate cultural tools
play out dependent on the systems we use to legitimate them (and the value we place in those
systems). We need to be far more critical about our claims to collegiality as they, more than other
stories here, relate to collective re-membering that not only accepts distorted pictures of the present
but also passes on distortions from the past.
The reciprocal and often transformative relationship of mutual conversation between participants
in disciplinary exploration is a central myth of the Humanities identity. In our secondary discourse
genres, the dialogue between students and staff which moves our disciplines forward is typically
described as being dependent on novices as much as experts. In all of this, dialogue is an
inter-dependent, balanced, shared process, where students and staff play equally important, if
different, roles. The novices bring fresh eyes [43], freed from the universalizing effects of socialization
into disciplinary norms. In this, the conversation between staff and students is an interwoven web
between research and teaching (Jan Parker is a particular proponent of this sense of mutuality ([44],
p. 23), but see also: [45,46]). Indeed, an extension to this perspective sees students as the subversives
upon which critical reinterpretation is reliant, because they are not so dependent on established
disciplinary paradigms [43].
On reflection, however, how this reciprocity manifests is unclear. Indeed, it was the lack of clarity
around this notion of reciprocity in the research-teaching linkages data-set that first started me
wondering about how collective influence with a past as well as in the present might be playing out
within the Humanities. When discussing the pedagogic environments in which dialogue occurs, the
academics divided into two groups:
171
x Those who perceived the importance of dialogue but who teach in more didactic
manner/learning environments; (Historian; Classicist);
x Those who perceive the importance of dialogue and use learning environments most likely to
foster interaction between themselves and the students; (Both Theologians).
In this apparent dichotomy one would perhaps consider the second group as most congruently
aligned with respect to dialogic belief and practice. Yet, the same academics’ views of the student
members in the dialogue as participants in the research process evoked common themes that did not
consistently overlap with the perceptions of the pedagogic environment. Thus:
x Students were fully participatory and informed the final research product of an individual
lecturer. As the philosopher commented: “I see all the lectures as conversations and I want to
know what people think about the idea because they have fresh minds.” (Philosopher). One of
the historians we interviewed also noted that his research-content-based teaching was still
very much a two-way process, from which he benefitted, suggesting that he gained through,
“Being challenged, students asking questions that are difficult and things that I hadn’t
thought of and would need to go and check out….” (Historian)
x The students were participatory because of the amount of their engagement with the
subject, but they did not significantly influence the lecturer’s research output (Film and
Television Studies).
Additionally, the forms that the dialogue takes, as expressed by the interviewees, were rarely
articulated as two-way conversations. Even where the lecturer stated explicitly that it is a two way
process, probing elicited a range of strategies, most of which relate to the lecturer doing something
for the students rather than the students working alongside the lecture:
(1) Empathy through expertise: (Classicist) “being a researcher…enables you to see what a
first year student encountering a classical text for the first time will in fact need and actually
that’s the real research-teaching linkage at pre-honours level—the idea that you are sufficiently
far on in your grasp of the subject to be able to put yourself in the place of the person who
is encountering it for the first time…” and help them unpack the subject through
that understanding.
(2) Facilitating connections: (Theologian) “…we [the researcher] are also making new
connections that aren’t immediately apparent for the students…what I am seeking to do is to
teach the students a process and use my own experience as a researcher/writer to make that
available to the students…I’m really trying to make connections for the students….
essentially what students are getting is my fresh thinking about how the whole area is
developing…” (At the same time this Theologian clearly sees student process as more than
just excitement: “it’s [his teaching] very much on that model of personal engagement in the
sense of not just engaging the student in being excited about the subject but the actual
student’s experience being a resource of authority and actually a data source…it’s not just about
mining a theological tradition”.
172
(3) Setting the parameters of the discussion: “Oh the process [of research-led teaching] is two
way. …it’s interesting because over the last couple of years I have talked to the consciousness
class about the need for emotions [in the studies of consciousness]…it’s a two way process,
you tease ideas out together. I got much more out of the paper yesterday when I was talking to
the students than I did when I was reading it by myself…” (Philosopher).
What is clear from the interviews is that the myth of dialogue is an ideal with far more variable
embodiments in practice and most of these embodiments suggest a misalignment between perception
and practice. In the tall tales captured in my interviews with staff, fresh, unfettered minds clearly feed
both our thinking and our publications. Such nurturing is at the heart of our originality. Yet, our
shared narrative resources suggest a misalignment between:
x Firstly, the spoken importance of the dialogic relationship in which the novice is critical:
lectures are conversations and we want to know about student thoughts because, “they have
fresh minds”;
x Secondly, a narrative resource incorporating the sub-plot of the power of our own research
interests to determine content and sometimes process. Thus, we make the connections not
immediately apparent for the student, which means students are getting our “fresh thinking
about how the whole area is developing…”.
x Thirdly, the implication, from the recalled direction of intellectual creativity, that it is less
two-way mutuality and more uni-directionality, with us (and the disciplines we embody)
being the beneficiaries. We might note that research-content teaching is still very much a
two-way process but one, nonetheless, from which we benefit explicitly. Our gains come
through being challenged and, through that challenge, “getting so much more out of our
own reading”. So the students ignite our new understandings, but is this a shared process?
And, perhaps more to the point, how do we show them that it is?
In terms of identifying an example of collective re-membering, what is evident here is an
incongruence between reciprocity and our understanding of how students are involved in that
relationship. In the hope of reciprocity we omit the common experience of delivering something to
the students, but then reintroduce it as we try to explain how such reciprocity manifests. The critical
question we need to ask, is from where did such a discourse emerge and why? I noted earlier that
underneath collective re-membering may be a justification of a way of managing a situation that then
becomes a fixed object. Arguably, the discourse of reciprocity has arisen out of perceived crises with
the place of the Humanities in the university, particularly in this case the massification of higher
education that has lead to an apparent de-interpersonalisation of Humanities’ pedagogical approaches.
What we are left with are the phantoms of concern and sentiment of reciprocity, but when we try to
explain these we fall back into common phrases that indicate the importance of us as deliverers of ideas,
with students’ “freshness” providing a particular sense of what they bring to the disciplinary equation.
This then, is a collectively reinforced myth of metamorphosis induced through dialogue woven
through a narrative from which we could infer that we “suck the fresh minds of the young” to
maintain our intellectual fecundity. Our sub-plot hints that we might actually be vampires-of-thought
rather than just half of mutual epistemological growth. What does this mean in terms of this paper’s
173
opening statements about how stories function? If this narrative is operating socially for our students
as well as personally for us, how does it influence their learning behaviours? How does such a story
interact with the practical realities of the classroom to cultivate a sense that, despite a myth of
mutuality, originality in our disciplines emerges from the expert drawing on the students rather than
through a more equal collaborative activity? Do our students think they need to become vampires to
be original? This becomes even more problematic when we realize the moral value we place on
originality, with the sense that its absence from someone’s thinking is evidence of conformism,
lazyness, and a lack of intellectual authenticity [47].
When discussing the ideas behind this keynote with a friend from Psychology, he pointed out that
relationships can be experienced as personal and yet not be interactive [48]. If we perceive it
personally, if it touches us, it has an essence of reciprocity, but this is not necessarily an essence
others in apparent relationship with us feel. Our myth of research-teaching linkages as being jointly
reciprocal, the fresh minds of novices, and the consequent generation of originality in our and the
students’ thinking is a story we relate to on a personal level, as are the notions of collegiality and
collaboration with the text. These are storylines that reflect our inner world of hope, intent, and
assumed affinity.
However, as social “instruments”, the storylines simultaneously construct communication
outwards, drawing from both one’s personal psychology and also the collective when recalling how
we achieve links between research and teaching. What seems to be expressed in our myth is an
internal dialectic between shared recognition (leading to reciprocity), on the one hand, and
self-assertion (leading to control and ownership), on the other [49]. Our myth captures and projects
outwards an inevitable tension between the expert’s need to be recognized at the same time as
recognizing students’ intellectual independence [50]. How this functions to constrain a sense of
equality (and attendant social solidarity) is a key question in terms of student engagement and our
hopeful narratives offer students a much less inclusive encounter with us than we, perhaps, realize.
The second of the liminal discourse genres relevant here are those narratives which contain
a peculiar mix of individual intellectual heroicism (as defined by the discipline and focused on
originality) and hagiographical conventions. These pious teaching sagas (for want of a better name)
seem to operate as ways of re-membering what makes our disciplinary views about what we should
teach unique and quasi-essential. In effect, they enable us to define ourselves through particular virtues
and, though not quite the abstinence fuelled rhetoric of the fourth century (CE) ascetic, they illustrate
what we believe is necessary to renounce in the cause of the Humanities. There is, thus, an implied
“purposeful lifestyle” incorporated into the sagas and we should at least be aware of the potential
this has to influence student choices. These narratives are seductive in their simplicity, arranging
disembodied, morally-laden tropes into texts about what it is or is not appropriate to favour.
When it comes to how these teaching sagas are expressed in the secondary literature, the
hagiographical tropes tend to divide into three inter-dependent clusters: firstly, a continued reflection
back to a monkish vocation, with the “culture of the West once again saved by ascetics” ([7], pp. 10, 42);
174
secondly, an underlying assumption of the morally superior non-vocational as opposed to vocational [6];
and, thirdly, education for a social good rather than for profit [5]. Arguably, such tropes paradoxically
obscure and materialize Humanities’ cultural phantoms at the same time, particularly the ones that
attempt to mark them out as being part of a unique vocation that should not be compromised through
attachments to material advantages. Indeed, useful discussion of the genealogy of such phantoms can
be found in ([8], pp. 59–88). Of course, the inconvenient memory omitted from this secondary genre
is that academics in the Humanities are already tied into systems of material advantage: state,
beyond-state, and increasingly student sponsored.
Where the pious sagas are manifested most strongly in that liminal space prior to expression in the
secondary sources is in relation and often opposition to ideological agendas around employability,
entrepreneurialism and, perhaps less obviously, global citizenship. How they play out in the dataset
that I gathered on graduate attributes [15] is through a conversational rhetoric of vague inattention,
suspicion and ambivalence. Phrases relating to entrepreneurialism and work-related learning often
make it clear that it is (inattention) or should be (deliberate inattention born of suspicion) at the
bottom of any taxonomy of attributes undergraduate students might be working towards in the
Humanities. As the Classicist commented: “‘Equipped for Global Citizenship?’ I tend to be suspicious
of anyway…how are we defining citizenship?... I would probably not take it much into consideration
except to the extent that a bureaucrat was obliging me to. Even them I might try to simply frame other
goals that I have in such a way as to appear to fulfill that requirement. I don’t especially want
students to be career aware, I tend to be relatively suspicious of that phrase.”
The acknowledgement behind this is that it just “doesn’t seem to easily fit” or is not something
explicitly being pursued (One of the academics from Celtic Studies noted: entrepreneurial is
quite hard to fit into Celtic Studies straight off.”), though it emerges from knock-on effects of the
students’ studies (This Celtic Studies scholar went on to state: “entrepreneurial, global citizenship
and ethically-minded—they’re not things that I teach on a surface level or that I particularly encourage
my students towards…I think they’re kind of knock-on effects of what I’m doing but it’s not
something I am consciously striving for.”). Phrases relating to global citizenship portray it as a
potentially worthy goal in some cases or just impossible to deliver in others. For the English literature
scholar there was a sense that employability and entrepreneurialism where of importance but best
developed through extra-curricular activities. Their reaction to Global citizenship was, however,
unequivocal: “Global citizenship makes me feel slightly nauseous, just the term; I mean it’s nonsense,
we’re not global citizens.” Interestingly, amongst the students I interviewed, there was a similar lack
of perceived importance of entrepreneurial and work-related attribute development, but much more
of a sense that being prepared to become ethically minded, global citizens was critical. If they had
ideological concerns about employability they did not about global citizenship.
I propose that, for some academics, narratives of inattention and suspicion are converted into
renunciation hagiographies which, in their turn, gain legitimacy through publication. This is not to
deny the imperative of the Humanities to challenge and critique both ideological positions and
compliance-oriented educational demands. Nor is it to valorize naivety. It is, instead, to reflect that
the translation from suspicion to renunciation has the power to lead us away from responsibilities to
our students and their futures. Yet these very responsibilities can only be effectively engaged with
175
through the mechanisms valued by the Humanities: critical creativity, in depth textual analysis that
allows us to anticipate possible and probable consequences for our futures, and imagination.
Academics interviewed for my projects were not articulating particularly heroic tropes, more
typically they were either expressing overt negativity or neutral non-engagement (except where they
were already working within a more applied paradigm such as practical theology and archaeology).
The critical issues for me in this are two-fold:
(1) Suspicion, ambivalence and neutrality hint at a lack of responsibility for directing
undergraduate experience beyond the gated communities. In a world of limited resources,
deflecting responsibility and avoiding the real opportunities for creative engagement in
problem-solving is becoming increasingly unsatisfactory if not downright unethical.
(2) By not engaging formally in the discussion about our students’ broader futures, certain
voices which claim to be authoritative in the Humanities get disproportionate cover about
what we are doing and how we are doing it (See: [8], p. 63). This includes voices that make
very Anglophone assumptions which fail to recognize the complexity of social, cultural,
environmental, and economic needs across the globe.
Ultimately, critical, creative transformation in which imagination and thought are harnessed to
solve as well as identify intellectual and practical challenges need not be dependent on stories that
negate either the vocational or the material. But how can we tell and value new tales?
I realize that the previous sections paint an overly pessimistic picture of our myths and sagas. This
is, of course, a deliberate attempt to ferment debate. In the methods used, I have generated a noir tale
all of its own. I want to clarify now what I have been hinting at all along: some of the shortcomings,
at least in terms of the content and narrative resources of the stories, actually relate to how the stories
come to be told. The method of qualitative interview upon which we have come to depend encourages
an unbalanced privileging of myth and saga. These genres in their turn smooth over how we understand
ourselves, harmonize the real-life paradoxes of learning in the Humanities, silence divergent views,
and replay the past through all the foibles and avoidance of inconveniences that make up collective
re-membering. The tales in the transcripts can become the collective memories. These stories may
assist in the integration of fragments of experience into a coherent whole, but in their re-narration
they incrementally change the plot of what we think we experienced. Having given these stories
credibility and legitimacy through our reliance on the method (and the demands on us to publish the
related outcomes), we are involved in a process of collective forgetting tied to constituting our
secondary discourse genres. Myths and sagas are being reified.
What is needed now is a method that rebalances our narratives towards tales of paradox. In other
words, we need a way of telling our stories so that conventions about learning and teaching are
disrupted and dissonances brought to the foreground. This is already being recognized in teacher
education [51]. From the work of scholars in theology and religious studies, moreover, we know that
myth has a complementary narrative form, the parable. This is a form of story that challenges our
preference for idealized worldviews and the related process of converting the mythic into a reality [52].
176
It has a brief, concentrated plot that troubles the reader, taking them beyond their comfort zone
of understanding, to new insights [51]. Through a pattern of data collection which requires the
articulation of parables about the links between research, teaching and broader attributes in the
Humanities, we might establish a form of qualitative inquiry that captures more fully the nuances of
our beliefs and practices. This would shift our focus from immediate recall and its associations with
collective re-membering, to a more satisfying, complex, and ultimately authentic way of making
sense of the power of learning and teaching in the Humanities.
8. Conclusions
And thus our time together on this particular Babylonian plain draws to a conclusion. The
Euphrates has been transfigured into a pathway of local personal memories interacting with the clay
of collectively crafted brick remembrances. Comfortable myths and sagas unearthed from academic
discourse are, however, as potentially exclusive as they are hopefully inclusive and their symbolic
implications need to be exposed. In such a vein it is perhaps no surprise to find that Herodotus’
description of Babylon is itself more folktale than accurate depiction. Yet generations of scholars
pursued studies intending to assert his reliability, even as other forms of evidence emerged to
demonstrate his limitations [53]. Beguiled by the harmonizing flourishes of the story, we can be
seduced into considering it as the rather than a truth.
The need to critically interrogate myths and sagas around learning and teaching, their emergence
from our daily acts of speech and recall, and their connection with the place of the Humanities in
the academy is important. Finding a method to do so is surely a Humanities’ imperative, especially as
the material worlds of scholarship, knowledge generation and curation change, but also given the
increasing calls for us to reassert our role within the realm of human (as well as) textual studies. To
assist in critiquing our own stories, we might need to draw on, metaphorically speaking, another
Babylonian custom. With a certain degree of relish, Herodotus notes that, “at some point in her life
every woman of the land is required to sit in the sanctuary of Aphrodite and have sex with a strange
man” (Herodotus, Histories, 1:199). For us to really break the cycle of gated communities and reductive
rather than expansive collective memories, we too might need to interact intimately (intellectually)
with strangers, seeing the temple of Aphrodite as the edifice in which interdisciplinarity and
interprofessionalism are fostered.
9. Epilogue
Stories invite in but can also repel. In so doing they generate networks of recognition and
alienation. For me, learning and teaching in the Humanities is about soaring with dragons whilst
teaching others to fly, rather than being a necromancing, vampire-of-thought under the tyranny of a
suspicious mind. However, perhaps a parable would illustrate that flying with dragons and suspicion-fed,
thought vampirism are both integral parts of an Humanities education, providing a paradoxical
context from which we and our students can be cultivated to achieve great things.
177
Acknowledgments
I am indebted to my “critical writing friend”, Susan Carter of Auckland University, for editorial
and motivational support. I am also grateful to the original conference organizers who, through their
invitation, forced me to make coherent sense of niggling concerns around Humanities’ teaching
stories that I had been considering for too long without writing down. Additional thanks go to
the students of the University of Glasgow’s Doctorate in Practical Theology where I still teach,
particularly to Gordon Kirkwood for pointing out to me the importance of parables in storytelling.
The funding for the qualitative research mentioned here came from QAA Scotland as part of their
Quality Enhancement Themes work.
Conflicts of Interest
References
13. Vicky Gunn. “Arts & Humanities’ Undergraduate Dissertations: Regenerating Early
Researcher Socialization for Diverse Futures (UK Perspectives).” In Supervising and Writing
a Good Undergraduate Dissertation. Edited by Roisin Donnelly, John Dallat and Marian
Fitzmaurice. Bussum, Netherlands: Bentham Science Publishers, 2013, pp. 149–86 [e-book].
14. Vicky Gunn, Steve Draper, and Mel McKendrick. Research-Teaching Linkages: Enhancing
Graduate Attributes in the Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences. Glasgow: Quality
Assurance Agency for Higher Education (Scotland), 2008. Available online:
http://www.enhancementthemes.ac.uk/docs/publications/enhancing-graduate-attributes-arts-H
umanities-and-social-sciences.pdf?sfvrsn=14 (accessed on 10 June 2014).
15. Vicky Gunn, and Jamie Wightwick. “Final Report of the Graduate Attributes
Working Group.” University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK, 2010. Available online:
http://www.gla.ac.uk/media/media_218773_en.pdf (accessed on 10 June 2014).
16. Maurice Halbwachs. The Collective Memory. Translated by Francis Ditter and Vida Ditter.
New York: Harper Colophon Books, 1980.
17. Maurice Halbwachs. On Collective Memory. Edited and translated by Lewis Coser. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1992.
18. Paul Ricoeur. Memory, History, Forgetting. Translated by Kathleen Blamey and David
Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004.
19. James Wertsch. Voices of Collective Remembering. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 2002.
20. Mikhail Bakhtin. Speech Genres and Other Late Essays. Translated by Vern McGee. Austin:
University of Texas Press, 1986.
21. James Wertsch. “Collective Memory.” In Memory and Mind in Culture. Edited by Pascal
Boyer and James Wertsch. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009, pp. 117–37.
22. Jan Schapper, and Susan Mayson. “Research-led teaching: Moving from a fractured
engagement to a marriage of convenience.” Higher Education Research and Development 29
(2010): 641–51.
23. Gerda Visser-Wijnween. The Research-Teaching Nexus in the Humanities: Variations among
Academics. Leiden: Mostert & Van Onderen, 2009.
24. Alastair Ager, and Maryanne Loughry. “Psychology and humanitarian assistance.” The
Journal of Humanitarian Assistance, 1 April 2004. Available online: http://sites.tufts.edu
/jha/archives/80 (accessed on 10 June 2014).
25. Anne Jones. “Generic attributes as espoused theory: The importance of context.” Higher
Education 58 (2009): 175–91.
26. Catherine Scott, and Steve Dinham. “Born not made: The nativist myth and teachers’
thinking.” Teacher Development 12 (2008): 115–24.
27. Torgni Roxä, and Katarina Märtensson. “Significant conversations and significant
networks—Exploring the backstage teaching arena.” Studies in Higher Education 34 (2009):
547–59.
179
28. Torgni Roxä, Katarina Märtensson, and Matthias Alveteg. “Understanding & influencing
teaching and learning cultures at university: A network approach.” Higher Education 62
(2011): 99–111.
29. Paul Connerton. How Modernity Forgets. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
30. Farhat Shahzad. “Collective Memories: A complex construction.” Memory Studies 5 (2011):
378–91.
31. Pascal Boyer, and James Wertsch, eds. Memory and Mind in Culture. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 2009.
32. Harald Welzer. “Re-narration: How pasts change in conversational remembering.” Memory
Studies 3 (2010): 5–17.
33. Roger Simon. The Touch of the Past: Remembrance, Learning, and Ethics. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2005.
34. Dominique Maingueneau. “Analysis of an Academic Genre.” Discourse Studies 4 (2002): 319–
42.
35. Julie Hengst, and Peggy Miller. “The heterogeneity of discourse genres: Implications for
Development.” World Englishes 18 (1999): 325–42.
36. Dominique Maingueneau. “Literature and discourse analysis.” Acta Linguistica Hafniensia 42
(2010): 147–58.
37. Ken Hyland. Academic Discourse. London: Continuum, 2009.
38. Vicky Gunn. “Mimetic desire and intersubjectivity in disciplinary cultures: Constraints or
enablers to learning in higher education?” Studies in Continuing Education 36 (2014): 67–82.
39. Tatiana Yarkova, and Aleh Cherp. “Managing the sacred? Perspectives on teaching excellence
and learning outcomes from an international postgraduate university.” European Journal of
Higher Education 3 (2013): 24–39.
40. Hans Georg Gadamer. Truth and Method, 2nd rev. ed. Translated by Joel Weinsheimer and
Donald G. Marshall. Albany: SUNY Press, 1989.
41. Cath Lambert, Andrew Parker, and Mike Neary. “Entrepreneurialism and critical pedagogy:
Reinventing the Higher Education Curriculum.” Teaching in Higher Education 12 (2007): 525–
37.
42. David Watson. The Question of Morale: Managing Happiness and Unhappiness in University
Life. London: McGraw-Hill, 2009.
43. Catherine Cubbitt. “Images of Saint Peter: The Clergy and the Religious Life in Anglo-Saxon
England.” In The Christian Tradition in Anglo-Saxon England: Approaches to Current
Scholarship and Teaching. Edited by Paul Cavill. Cambridge, UK: Brewer, 2004, pp. 41–54.
44. Jan Parker. “Humanities Higher Education: New Models, New Challenges.” In Contemporary
Themes in Humanities in Higher Education. Edited by Ellie Chambers. Dordrecht: Kluwer,
2001, pp. 21–43.
45. Mary Henkel. “Teaching and Research: The Idea of a Nexus.” Higher Education Management
and Policy 16 (2004): 19–31.
46. Ben Knights. “Intelligence and Interrogation: The identity of the English student.” Arts and
Humanities in Higher Education 4 (2005): 43–61.
180
47. Joshua Guetzkow, Michèle Lamont, and Grégoire Mallard. “What is Originality in the
Humanities and Social Sciences?” American Sociological Review 69 (2004): 190–212.
48. Steve Draper, University of Glasgow, personal communication, 2013.
49. Jessica Benjamin. “Beyond the Doer and Done to: An Intersubjective View of Thirdness.”
Psychoanalytic Quarterly 73 (2004): 5–46.
50. Barbara Schapiro. “Negotiating a Third Space in the Classroom.” Pedagogy: Critical
Approaches to Teaching Literature, Language, Composition, and Culture 9 (2009): 423–39.
51. Robert Bullough. “Parables, Storytelling, and Teacher Education.” Journal of Teacher
Education 61 (2010): 153–60. Available online: http://jte.sagepub.com/content/61
/1-2/153.full.pdf+html (accessed on 10 June 2014).
52. Herbert Anderson, and Edward Foley. Mighty Stories, Dangerous Rituals: Weaving together
the Human and the Divine. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1998.
53. Wouter Henkelman, Amélie Kuhrt, Robert Rollinger, and Josef Wiesehöfer. “Herodotus and
Babylon Reconsidered.” In Herodot und das Persische Weltreich. Herodotus and the Persian
Empire (Classica et Orientalia CLeO Band 3). Edited by Robert Rollinger, Brigitte
Truschnegg and Reinhold Bichler. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz Verlag, 2011, pp. 449–70.
181
Abstract: This article develops a philosophy of the humanities by reading C.P. Snow’s famous
thesis of “the two cultures” through the early work of Alfred North Whitehead. I argue that, whereas
Snow refers to Whitehead’s Science and the Modern World, he ultimately paves the way for a
reductive interpretation of humanities scholarship, which is a move that can be repaired by delving
into Snow’s own reference to Whitehead following a diffractive reading methodology. This way of
reading was first formulated in the context of feminist epistemology (but can be found elsewhere
and under different names) in an attempt to generate constructively conceptual rather than closed
hermeneutical readings of theoretical texts by making the reading dynamic and open-ended (in Karen
Barad’s terms: reading their insights “through” one another). As such, reading diffractively shies
away from relying on classification and is playful with the past, present, and future of the humanities.
The article argues that the diffraction of Snow and Whitehead hinges on theories of “beauty” and will
demonstrate (with Whitehead) that humanities scholarship originates in a total environment in which
works of art—as the subject matter of humanities research—stand out and preserve themselves as
“enduring objects”.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: van der Tuin, I. “Without an Analytical Divorce from the Total
Environment”: Advancing a Philosophy of the Humanities by Reading Snow and Whitehead
Diffractively. Humanities 2014, 3, 244–263.
1. Introduction
The work of C.P. Snow (1905–1980) is a standard reference for “the humanities”. His concept of
“the two cultures” situates the humanities vis-à-vis the sciences and stages a mutual and hierarchical
misunderstanding between the two scholarly fields. Just like the famous distinction between
Geisteswissenschaften (the humanities) and Naturwissenschaften (the natural sciences), a distinction
between the scholarly disciplines (together encompassing Wissenschaften per se) made by the German
philosopher Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1911), Snow’s work has gone down in history as a disjunctive
affair. However, as Michel Foucault has argued, “[…] throughout the nineteenth century, from Kant
to Dilthey and to Bergson, critical forms of thought and philosophies of life find themselves in a
position of reciprocal borrowing and contestation” ([1], p. 162). In other words, Dilthey’s differentiation
between the methodologies of Verstehen (understanding) and Erklären (explaining) is hardly sustainable
because the two disciplinary realms mentioned above spill over into one another (i.e., they are
182
excessive) 1 . Snow’s text “The Two Cultures” is unclear as to whether the distinction that is
introduced in it is desirable. For this reason, Snow published a “second look” upon the matter just a
few years after the delivery and publication of his groundwork. In this text, Snow refers to a text
written by Alfred North Whitehead (1861–1947) and, I will argue, that this reference provides the
key to encompassing observations such as Foucault’s into the way in which we tend to think of, and
lecture about, the humanities (even when this is done in Snowian terms). This article asks the
following questions: to what extent are Snow’s two cultures excessive? Must we add to Foucault’s
analysis about the impossibility of fencing in the thought traditions of the nineteenth century and
conclude that Snow did not manage to contain his twentieth-century classification? Phrased differently,
is the search for the demarcation line between “the humanities” and “the sciences” flawed?
In this article I close-read Snow’s work following the procedure of “diffractive reading”. My goal
is to come to an understanding of a philosophy of the humanities that is not predeterminedly (or
rather: whig-historically, that is, falsely progressive) confined to the way in which textbook accounts
of humanities philosophies and methodologies represent both the humanities as such and texts
supporting its difference from the sciences. Karen Barad has developed the methodology of diffractive
reading in conversation with Donna Haraway [3,4]. The latter completed the toolbox of semiotics
(consisting of “syntax”, “semantics”, and “pragmatics”) with “diffraction” in order to affirm how
“interference patterns can make a difference in how meanings are made and lived” ([4], p. 14). This
description of diffraction demonstrates that the aspiration is to grasp differences that cut across the
well-known hierarchical patterns of capital-D Difference. In other words, while the stifled and
stifling patterns of gender, sexuality, ethnicity, et cetera, are confirmed, also confirmed is the fact that
difference is—at the same time—differently constructed and experienced. Diffractive reading, then,
reads for these different differences and does so in ways that are “respectful of the entanglement of
ideas and other materials in ways that reflexive methodologies are not. In particular, [the] method [is]
attuned to the entanglement of the apparatuses of production, one that enables genealogical analyses
of how boundaries are produced rather than presuming sets of well-worn binaries in advance” ([3],
pp. 29–30). This way of reading generates constructively conceptual rather than closed hermeneutical
readings of theoretical texts by reading their insights “through” one another. Hermeneutical readings
can be closed because either “the text” is given a label that comes to overcode it, or its “genre” is put
in a lineage based in sequential negation, or both. As such, diffractive readings—and we can infer that
some readings deemed hermeneutical are in fact diffractive—shy away from relying on classification,
which is considered an illegitimate importation into scholarship. The methodology can also be found
outside of the context of feminist epistemology. Steven Shaviro for instance does not use the term in
Without Criteria but makes the following succinct statement:
1
Whereas the German term “Geisteswissenschaften” seems to cut across the dichotomy between the sciences and the
humanities as it stirs questions about the scientificity of the humanities, Dilthey’s subsequent distinction between
“Verstehen” and “Erklären” re-installs the gap and Geisteswissenschaften is, therefore, part and parcel of the
nineteenth-century Western birth of the disciplines, notwithstanding the interest Dilthey had in sociology, which
weakens the dichotomy in the same stroke [2].
183
In this book, I have tried to establish a sort of relay between [Alfred North Whitehead
and Gilles Deleuze], so that each of them helps to resolve difficulties in the work of the
other. […] I am less concerned with reconstructing Whitehead’s thought precisely than
in delineating the outlines of the encounter between Whitehead and Deleuze, an
encounter that changes our apprehension of both of them. ([5], p. xiv, p. 27, footnote 9;
emphasis added)
Diffractive readings—which one can begin purposefully or “stumbles upon”—can free texts and
insights from sedimented interpretations (prompted by “the canon”) and implement de-sedimentation
in such a way that texts and their insights remain available for future theoretical work on a particular
topic (here: the humanities)2. The diffractive reading methodology allows for scholarly work to remain
in movement, because it does not follow its canonical confinement or—worse—wholesale dismissal.
By choosing a diffractive reading strategy, I situate this article on the intersection of the two topics
of this special issue of Humanities: philosophy of the humanities, on the one hand, and, on the other,
theories of time and temporality. I demonstrate how—just like life in the late eighteenth century—it
is another classical theme—namely beauty—that forms the hinge point of the freeing of Snow or, rather,
the humanities. It will shortly become clear that I need the work of Whitehead for this and that Snow
himself has paved the way for this. I evaluate the importance of my discussion for the contemporary
humanities at the tail end of the article, when I discuss the following questions: what can the changing
landscape of the humanities today gain from my discussion of twentieth-century canonical sources?
To what extent should we argue that this landscape—with its new denominators of the “environmental”,
“medical”, “digital”, “post-human”, “blue”, et cetera, humanities—is changing at all?
2
Gregg Lambert has reminded me of the fact that Jacques Derrida ([6], pp. 10, 86) used “de-sedimentation” in
Of Grammatology as something like a synonym of “de-construction” (according to which the destruction of a text
or oeuvre, or an idea or set of ideas is not a demolition). Although the differences and similarities between
diffraction and deconstruction—both in the work of Derrida and as a result of its (flawed) canonization (as a
methodology)—are still to be researched, I wish to mention here that the diffractive methodology involves the
deliberate or accidental study of at least two texts/corpuses at once (which could possibly lead to a dissimilarity
with deconstruction) but that Barad—in a conversation with her colleagues Vicki Kirby and Astrid
Schrader—moves to Derrida in her later work [7–10]. An important first observation with regards to the similarities
between deconstruction and diffraction could be that whereas diffraction is explicit about its methodological status
(one can purposefully begin a diffractive reading of text A and text B, as suggested by Barad; see e.g., [3], p. 232),
its workings are as immanent as deconstruction’s workings (one can also “stumble upon” a diffractive reading,
when text B presents itself to the reader while immersed in the reading of text A and as intrinsically connected
to—even part and parcel of—the latter text; here “intertextuality” is echoed and a study of the differences and
similarities between diffraction and intertextuality is in place). The following summarizing statement by Derrida
(quoted in: [11], p. 6) suits diffraction perfectly fine: “Deconstruction is not a method or some tool that you apply
to something from the outside […] Deconstruction is something which happens and which happens inside; there is
a deconstruction at work within Plato’s texts, for instance”. The quote goes well with diffraction, because as soon
as a text is diffracted by another text, it has always/already been affected. My previous work has explained this with
the strange temporality of Althusserian interpellation [12]. Kirby has made clear how the strange causality of
Derridean différance can be used to the same effect (see [13], p. 292).
184
C.P. Snow’s “The Two Cultures” is the transcript of his Rede Lecture held at the University of
Cambridge on 7 May 1959. The transcript has become a much and heatedly debated text—published
first in the same year as the lecture was given—that is firmly secured in our collective consciousness
for its description of the widening gap between scientists and literary intellectuals, and its plea for an
educational reform that would close the gap so as to produce responsible scholars and citizens. Snow,
himself both physicist and novelist, argued:
Literary intellectuals at one pole—at the other scientists, and as the most representative,
the physical scientists. Between the two a gulf of mutual incomprehension—sometimes
(particularly among the young) hostility and dislike, but most of all lack of understanding.
They have a curious distorted image of each other. Their attitudes are so different that,
even on the level of emotion, they can’t find much common ground ([14], p. 15).
Snow’s frustration is with the literary intellectuals in particular; these humanities scholars (who
later on became known as “theorists”) do not understand processes such as the industrial and scientific
revolutions, and have nothing to add to the urgent question of poverty as perceived by Snow.
In “The Two Cultures: A Second Look”, Snow refers to Alfred North Whitehead’s 1925 Science
and the Modern World as one amongst a few exceptional examples of scientists embracing not only
hard-core scientific issues, but also issues of worldly concern (including aesthetics) ([15], p. 53).
The last chapter of Science and the Modern World neatly seconds Snow’s concerns as we encounter
Whitehead claiming:
Another great fact confronting the modern world is the discovery or the method of training
professionals, who specialise in particular regions of thought and thereby progressively
add to the sum of knowledge within their respective limitations of subject. […] This
situation has its dangers. It produces minds in a groove. But there is no groove of
abstractions which is adequate for the comprehension of human life ([16], pp. 196–97).
Mirroring Henri Bergson, who has argued in Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic
that “the mind crystallising in certain grooves” ([17], p. 32) distorts sound knowledge production in
a way that is comical owing to the fact that “a mechanism [is] superposed upon life” ([17], p. 28),
Whitehead’s plea is one for a different education. However, Whitehead argues not only for a socially
relevant education, like Snow, but he also pushes the issue of beauty to the limit, whereupon he is
enabled to formulate his educational wishes from an angle significantly different from Snow (and
coming close to Bergson, whose metaphysics is based on a “creative evolution”). Whitehead’s angle
is particularly relevant for a project of establishing a history and philosophy of the humanities that does
justice to a (changing?) humanities landscape as it seems to be able to circumvent the fact that history
and philosophy of science are generally predicated on the humanities as their constitutive outside.
185
Mathematician, logician, and philosopher, Whitehead draws attention to the fact “that we neglect
to strengthen habits of concrete appreciation of the individual facts in their full interplay of emergent
values, and that we merely emphasize abstract formulations which ignore this aspect of the interplay
of diverse values” in the educational context ([16], p. 198). Thus—and here my diffractive reading
takes flight—whereas Snow ([14], p. 22) stresses “how beautiful the thinking is” of the physicists
and Nobel Prize laureates T.D. Lee and C.N. Yang3 in terms of the violation of “[i]ntuition, common
sense” ([14], p. 22) thus prompted, Whitehead upholds an opposite take on intuition by claiming it to
be the preferred alternative to intellect and common sense alike in the Bergsonian sense. (Bergson
has famously argued that rational objectification as well as habit “spatialize time” and have no eye
for the fact that the temporality of phenomena may materialize in a myriad of ways, wherefore linear
time and the teleology implied reduce the durational phenomena under study.) Albeit that Whitehead,
in Science and the Modern World, is ambiguous about the relation of his own work to Bergson’s (see
e.g., [16], p. 52), his Bergsonism is not only to be found in the distinction of intellect and common
sense, on the one hand, and intuition, on the other. He also argues that “the very nature of things”
consists of “the spirit of change” and “the spirit of conservation”, which is to say that “[t]he character
of existent reality is composed of organisms enduring through the flux of things” ([16], p. 201). This
comes close to Bergson’s “upward” and “downward” movements expressed in Creative Evolution
and The Creative Mind [19,20]4. Whitehead’s plea is that “[t]he center of gravity of the other side of
training should lie in intuition without an analytical divorce from the total environment” ([16],
p. 199). Deeming this total environment originary, Whitehead makes a case for schooling in art
and aesthetics, because “[g]reat art is the arrangement of the environment so as to provide for the
soul vivid, but transient, values” ([16], p. 202). This is how Whitehead, standing on the brink of a
new phase in his work (cf. [22], p. 114), wanted to interfere in the problem of minds in a groove,
the problem, that is, of the two cultures.
Snow associates beauty with the simplicity of the physics theorem, while Maura C. Flannery, for
example, has argued that beauty (in biological science) can be intensity, complexity, unity, form, or
rhythm [23], and Whitehead too is explicit about the reductive nature of the notion of beauty that
we came across in the work of Snow. First of all, Shaviro has remarked that in Whitehead a certain
reductionism underlies a statement about “the beauty of [physics] theorems, the elegance and internal
self-consistency of its mathematics” ([5], p. 15). This kind of privileging of beauty seems to deeply
subvert the common-sense epistemology of natural science as representing the theory and practice
of neutral and distant scholarship, but when the privileging proves to be so central, have we actually
thought through how the beautiful affects our notions of truth and objectivity?5 This question goes
further than historical studies of science allow us to go, because, whereas these studies prove the
messiness of (f)actual scholarship 6, they often assume a projectivism (instead of an objectivism)
3
Lee and Yang got the Nobel Prize in 1957 for proving the violation of the fundamental and purportedly absolute
law of parity conservation. See [18].
4
The relation between Bergson and Whitehead is contested, as can be concluded from [5,21,22].
5
See for a recent discussion [24].
6
Steven Shapin calls this how science is “never pure” [25].
186
that generates an unreal opposition between the impact of beauty and a deeper layer of theorization.
An example can be found in James W. McAllister’s Beauty & Revolution in Science:
I presume that the value to which the aesthetic appreciation of scientific theories refers
does not reside in the theories themselves but rather is projected into theories by
individual scientists, scientific communities, and observers of science. This amounts to
the claim, which I think is very plausible, that we cannot fully describe a scientific
theory’s aesthetic value without referring to the effect of properties of that theory on
scientists or other observers ([26], p. 31).
What we see here is that whereas the theories themselves are deemed agential (theories are
agents which have an impact on scholars and the general public, following Barad’s definition of
the agential contributions of “a host of material-discursive forces—including ones that get labeled
‘social’, ‘cultural’, ‘psychic’, ‘economic’, ‘natural’, ‘physical’, ‘biological’, ‘geopolitical’, and
‘geological’—that may be important to particular (entangled) processes of materialization”, see [3],
p. 66), they are also shielded from aesthetic appreciation. In the end, a theory itself has nothing to
do with aesthetics. According to Whitehead’s attempt at non-reductionism, language is a fundamentally
creative process that asks for a pluralist rather than a static perspective ([5], pp. x–xi). Accordingly,
we might ask how the theorems of physics are able to contain what we presume they fully capture.
Thus, second of all, “‘beauty’ and ‘creativity’ are for Whitehead entirely generic notions” that
“apply univocally and indifferently to all entities and to all forms of existence” ([5], p. 155).
Locking up beauty in artificial (static) language, like Snow does and McAllister too, is not a solution
to the problem of the two cultures, but rather its foundation. The question of beauty is, for Whitehead,
an intuitive and—to use a term of Félix Guattari [27]—“transversal” one.
Where Snow endorses a reductive take on the intuition—common sense—intellect triad,
upholding “beautiful” intellectualism at the expense of intuition (and common sense), we see the
first signs of him keeping up the binary that he set out to shift (a shift that this article attempts to
push to the limit). In “The Two Cultures”, as well as “A Second Look”, Snow reflects upon the
problem of dualism in an attempt to undo the suggestion of his own argument being bewitched by
the power of dialectics. However, it is only by reading Snow and Whitehead diffractively that the
bottom of this issue is reached. After all, it is the performative nature of any academic practice
that is taken advantage of in a diffractive reading, whereas a reflection implies a gesture that is
itself dichotomous in terms of the word-world and subject-object relations, as well as in terms of
quarrelling philosophical schools. A reflection (subject, word) is never enough should one wish to
shift the (oppressive or liberating) power a certain structure might have over one’s writing. The
only option is the plunge into reality, going along with writing as a creative activity that embraces
the total environment, instead of considering it to be a representational activity that presupposes the
possibility of neat linguistic capturings of “this” or of “that” (object, world). This also shifts the notion
of reflection, the conclusions of which must be affirmed as always/already carried away by the
creative force of reality and the writing practice. We will soon see that it hasn’t been enough for
Snow to claim repeatedly that “[t]he number 2 is a very dangerous number: that is why the dialectic
is a dangerous process” ([14], p. 18; [15], p. 55).
187
Snow’s argument centers on his ethnographical insight in the two exclusive communities
of scientists (exploring nature) and humanists (exploring and bringing forth culture). When he
describes the impoverishment of the latter, he states:
They still like to pretend that the traditional culture is the whole of “culture”, as though
the natural order didn’t exist. As though the exploration of the natural order was of no
interest either in its own value or its consequences. As though the scientific edifice of
the physical world was not, in its intellectual depth, complexity and articulation, the
most beautiful and wonderful collective work of the mind of man. Yet most non-scientists
have no conception of that edifice at all ([14], p. 21).
Albeit actively searching for messiness and even possibly discovering what I will below call
a “metaphysics of naturecultures”, this quote demonstrates that Snow remains attached to what
Whitehead in one of his Tarner Lectures from 1919, also held at Cambridge, coined is “the bifurcation of
nature”. In the citation, Snow lays out a strong idealism and anthropocentrism. After having engaged
with Whitehead’s Science and the Modern World, it is hard to conceive of the benefits of teaching
humanities scholars about value as imposed on a near-mute natural world and the mind-centeredness
of projecting beauty into scientific theories. The affirmation of the exploration of the natural order
“in its own value or its consequences”, potentially paralleling Whitehead’s take on value as “belong[ing]
to the order of nature” ([22], p. 157; emphasis added) instead of being “paradigmatically human” ([22],
p. 156), has not been pushed to the limit by Snow. He wrote “A Second Look” in part because he
had been accused of showing approval for the observed distribution between natural science and the
humanities. How can the work of Whitehead bring Haraway’s “more promising interference
patterns” ([4], p. 16) to Snow’s influential thesis? For including the fleshing-outs of natureculture
metaphysics in a history and philosophy of the humanities it is not enough to look at Snow alone. We
will have to be attentive to Whitehead’s self-positioning too. What does it mean that Whitehead says
that “‘[v]alue’ is the word I use for the intrinsic reality of an event” (quoted in: [22], p. 156)?
In “Theories of the Bifurcation of Nature”, the Tarner lecture as published in the 1920 essay
collection The Concept of Nature, Whitehead differentiates between the extreme and intermediate
forms of bifurcation theory. The extreme form makes use of a strict causal model that revolves
around “mind” and “nature”. Whitehead observes that it apparently proves to be extremely difficult
to consider nature in its totality. There are always “two natures” or “two divisions, namely […] the
nature apprehended in awareness and the nature which is the cause of awareness” ([28], pp. 30–31).
In causal terms, Whitehead talks about two different tracks following the example of a confrontation
with a fire:
188
Unless we produce the all-embracing relations, we are faced with a bifurcated nature;
namely, warmth and redness on one side, and molecules, electrons and ether on the
other side. Then the two factors are explained as being respectively the cause and the
mind’s reaction to the cause ([28], p. 32).
A natural scientist led by bifurcation theory is only to go into “the cause of the fact of
knowledge” ([28], p. 32) and, therefore, she works from a fundamental idealism as she assumes
to have mind on one side—a mind that can only deal with its own products, which is a
Kantianism—and nature on the other. This is another way of saying that we can only go into
“relata” ([28], pp. 33, 35), whereas Whitehead himself wants to express how “[b]eings do not
preexist their relatings” ([29], p. 6), all-embracing relations.
Whitehead argues that “there is but one nature, namely the nature which is before us in perceptual
knowledge” ([28], p. 40). Albeit that The Concept of Nature differs significantly from Science and
the Modern World, the beginnings of the notion of the “total environment” as originary are discernable in
the former too, as Isabelle Stengers infers that in the former publication,
[n]ature is […] neither knowable—definable, for instance, as a system of relations
between entities—nor unknowable, the famous “mute reality” upon which we project
human, linguistic, or social categories. […] Nature is that about which relevant
knowledge may be produced. If we pay due attention to it, we can learn, discern
relations, and multiply entities and ratios ([22], p. 106).
Whitehead does not work with a foundational knowing subject (“mind”). He is interested
in “situating the mode of attention that gave rise to the bifurcation of nature in a way that verifies
that it is always possible to discover more in nature, but without ever discovering in it that which
would enable what is known to be ‘explained’” ([22], p. 107). In the work of Whitehead, ontology
and epistemology are fundamentally intertwined, which stirs what Barad has called an
“onto-epistemology” [3]. His aversion to explanation is based in its dualist character. (Here we see
that Whitehead moves beyond the Bergsonian intellect—common sense—intuition triad; Whitehead
affirms intellect too because it can be reconfigured following the answer to the question: what did
a certain intellectual stance have to assume in order to have materialized as such? Since the
unraveling of this assumption will always uncover a certain embodied situation, Whitehead is able to
affirm intellectualism).
The intermediate form of bifurcation theory is what Whitehead summarizes as “the theory of
psychic additions”, which leads us back to McAllister’s interpretation of beauty as projected into
theories. The intermediate form of bifurcation theory is founded upon the Cartesian/Lockian distinction
between primary and secondary qualities and assumes that “the nature we are discussing is always
the nature directly known”, which is celebrated by Whitehead, but at the same time, unfortunately,
“it holds that there are psychic additions to nature as thus known, and that these additions are in no
proper sense part of nature” ([28], p. 42). It is important for our discussion that Whitehead phrases
the former in terms of space, time and matter—that which is configured according to “spatiotemporal
positions” ([28], p. 43), or Euclidian grid lines [30]—and the latter in terms of “artistic additions of
colour, warmth and sound” ([28], p. 43). Here we see, not only the historical and systematic origins
189
7
It is with an alluring 1801 quote of Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling that Whitehead ends his exposition: In
the “Philosophy of Nature” I considered the subject-object called nature in its activity of self-constructing. In order
to understand it, we must rise to an intellectual intuition of nature. The empiricist does not rise thereto, and for this
reason in all his explanations it is always he himself that proves to be constructing nature. It is no wonder, then, that
his construction and that which was to be constructed so seldom coincide. A Natur-philosoph raises nature to
independence and makes it construct itself, and he never feels, therefore, the necessity of opposing nature as
constructed (i.e., as experience) to real nature, or of correcting the one by means of the other (quoted in: [28],
pp. 47–48). Should one decide to construct a genealogy of the contemporary humanities based in natureculture
metaphysics, inclusion of Romanticism must therefore be secured.
190
Thus, Whitehead also upholds a strong belief in science. He “assume[s] as an axiom that science
is not a fairy tale” ([28], p. 40) but is not susceptible to anything ascribed by Snow to the men of
science or, alternatively, to Snow by us. In fact, the case of Whitehead, in both practice and theory,
diffracts Snow’s account because Whitehead is himself a scientist that does not buy into the do’s and
don’ts of his supposed culture8 and, on a more fundamental level, he should not be asked whether he
has ever read Shakespeare ([14], p. 22) because his engagement with science is his engagement with
art, precisely because his engagement with science is an engagement with one nature, the embrace
of the total environment as originary. Whitehead demonstrates how Snow’s suggestion that “the
scientific edifice of the physical world [is] the most beautiful and wonderful collective work of the
mind of man” is predicated on an impoverished take on natural science and nature per se and that
Snow’s solution of the two-culture problematic is also impoverished, or even non-existent, as it is not
played out on the onto-epistemological level. Beauty cannot only be in, or of, the theorem.
Snow states that “[t]he scientific process has two motives: one is to understand the natural world,
the other is to control it” ([15], p. 56). Apart from the fact that the humanities are completely left out
here, this statement confirms a dialectic between fundamental and applied science 9. It should also
be noticed that Snow’s model is one of explanation (Erklären)—predicated on subject-object and
word-world distinctions—whereas Stengers puts it differently in Thinking with Whitehead:
Where scientific materialism postulates localized entities as the ultimate reference for
all explanation, the philosophy of the organism [which is how she refers to Whitehead’s
work in this quotation] will ask that the concepts to be constructed exhibit the way nature
“explains itself” ([22], p. 144).
Whitehead works with a much more expansive starting point vis-à-vis Snow. When nature
explains itself (cf. [9]), there is no room for a priori distinctions. Snow, however, is convinced of the
fact that a “clashing point between two subjects, two disciplines, two cultures” generates creativity
and that there is little of such clashing happening around him ([14], p. 23). Here we see that Snow
employs a logic of relata and that Whitehead’s one nature or total environment is nothing but an
afterthought or consequence for Snow. The latter’s discussion of the work of those literary intellectuals
that have tried to understand industrialization by immersing themselves in nature—Henry David
Thoreau’s 1845–1847 Walden experiment is an example Snow mentions pejoratively ([14],
p. 28)—makes clear that Snow considers it to be impossible to encounter the industrial (or the
8
Whitehead strongly compromises the famous idea about “scientific communities” of Thomas S. Kuhn
(see [31])—which is related to Snow’s “cultures”—when he states of minds in a groove that “[t]his criticism of
modern life applies throughout, in whatever sense you construe the meaning of a community. It holds if you apply
it to a nation, a city, a district, an institution, a family, or even to an individual. There is a development of particular
abstractions, and a contraction of concrete appreciation. The whole is lost in one of its aspects” ([16], p. 197). This
demonstrates that purely descriptive historical work on paradigm-sharing scientific communities is never enough
or always/already partial as in “biased”.
9
As it happens, Snow states that “technology is the branch of human experience that people can learn with
predictable results” ([14], p. 40). Note that this sentence was written around the same time as Gilbert Simondon
formulated his ideas about the fundamental unpredictability of technological progress [32]. According to the latter,
the potentials of human/non-human, organic/inorganic systems only get to be determined when clicking together.
191
artificial, the artistic) in nature. Thus, in conclusion, whereas Snow points forward to a “third
culture” of socially relevant scholarship in the fields of among others social history, political science,
and “social arts such a architecture” ([15], p. 58)—which reminds me of the actualized scholarship
boosted by the liberalization of Higher Education around May 1968—it would have been more
beneficial for him to follow up on his own reference to Whitehead, who situates nature, as it were, as
a forethought. This is not to say that Whitehead has been pushed to the limit in my discussion (cf. [22],
p. 111), but, then again, that was not my concern. It has been my concern in this article to demonstrate
how his modest and early-career “nature [is] what we are aware of in perception” ([28], p. 28)
revolutionizes Snow’s “two cultures” with their grooved minds on the most fundamental level and
stimulates, what can be called, a “non-reductive naturalism”, an umbrella concept that serves a
natureculture metaphysics.
The consequences of Whitehead recommending the study of art are similar to how his take on the
beautiful ultimately cracks the code of Snow and affords a generous engagement. Snow’s reductive
notion of beauty lays bare how he falls back onto various dualisms, whereas Whitehead is able to
propagate by way of an answer to Snow’s problematic what Haraway has called “naturecultures” and
Bruno Latour “collectives” via the (projected!, not undertaken) study of art [29,33]10. Art is affirmed
here to be quintessential to shaking off what prevents us from reaching the nature “that we are aware
of in perception”. Through an art work, as no other, we encounter nature as one—a nature that is
mind-independent (exit extreme form of bifurcation theory) and includes what used to be called
primary and secondary qualities (exit intermediate bifurcation)—because a work of art makes itself
known from the total environment that is originary. With Whitehead, the fact that art has become
overcoded as Culture with a capital C (art as an allegorical affair which can only be appreciated when
its metaphors can be understood and explained) becomes as reductive as physics theorems because
“[a]esthetics precedes cognition” ([5], p. 16) in natural science and the humanities. The encountering
of an artwork thus precedes the meanings that make a work a piece of art worthy of scholarship (cf. [35]).
As an intuitive habit 11, aesthetic experience in Whitehead revolves around the notion of value.
Stengers affirms that Whitehead’s take on value—precisely one of those notions that we usually
consider to be of Human origin or to be constitutive of the exceptionally Human—has to be integrated
in the order of nature ([22], p. 156). She explains: “Value is required by an author capable of using
the same term, whether in reference to an electron, a living organism, or an industrial firm. The
organism has now come into contact with its requisites” ([22], p. 157). In other words, value has
nothing to do with transcendence or psychic additions; rather, it is the condition of possibility of
10
Somebody who has undertaken such a study is Whitehead’s student Susanne K. Langer. See, e.g., her 1953 book
Feeling and Form, which is dedicated to Ernst Cassirer [34]. Later in this article it will become clear that this
reference to Cassirer is food to future diffractive readings or we can conclude that Langer’s book itself is a
diffractive reading of Whitehead and Cassirer.
11
Note that Whitehead also shifts the pejorative rendering of habit that we find in the work of Bergson. However, we
must not forget that the famous reconfiguration of habit by Félix Ravaisson [36] has been appreciated by Bergson,
an appreciation we find in the latter’s lengthy in memoriam of Ravaisson written in 1904 (see [37]).
192
concept formation unaffected by dualism (cf. [38]). Value “is what is realized by all that exists,
in the sense that what exists succeeds in enduring, succeeds in maintaining its individual way of
gathering-together, that is, of making things hold together in a determinate way. Value indicates
success in and for itself” ([22], p. 157)12. The active work of art (not the Subject or its supposed
opposite of the mute object) is paradigmatic here as this work stands out in the total environment
and preserves itself; it is the perfect example of a Whiteheadian “enduring object” ([5], p. 18) or
what Latour calls, with reference to the sciences, an “immutable mobile” [40]. The work of art exhibits
a gathering-together of everything that we are prone to singling out as ingredients put in interacting
boxes by the skillful artist or the masterful scholar. Therefore, the gathering-together is prior to or
underneath the differentiation that unquestionably happens when the artwork affects a viewer
(whether a scholar or not)13.
The gathering-together produces something enduring or immutable through the intra-active14
workings of color patches on a canvas, oxidized bronze for a sculpture, or words in a poem. Such
a process of actualization does not contradict the originarity of what happens inter se relating
luminescent patches, molecules, or words. The gathering-together provokes the enjoyment of vivid
values. Whiteheadian process scholar William Dean, for example, states about a poem of William
Carlos Williams:
The problem confronted by such a poem is not that of understanding, of explanation
or of establishing the rational relation among the logical subjects—wheelbarrow,
rainwater, and white chickens. Rather, the problem is that of sheer knowledge, of how
to accede linguistically to the aesthetic value in the sheer relationality and facticity
before one’s eyes ([42], p. 109; cf. [43], pp. 51–53).
12
Lambert calls this gathering-together “the creation of a territory with the work of art” [39].
13
Étienne Souriau explains that this process is also at work in the studio of the artist. Making a sculpture, the artist
does not plan, but rather, encounters his work: “A pile of clay on the sculptor’s base. An undeniable, total,
accomplished, thingy [réique] existence. But nothing of the aesthetic being exists. Each hand or thumb pressure,
each stroke of the chisel accomplishes the work. Don’t look at the chisel, look at the statue. With each act of the
demiurge the statue little by little breaks out of its chains. It moves towards existence—towards the existence that
will in the end blossom into an existence that is intense, accomplished, and actual. […] Often there is no warning:
up to a certain point the finished work is always a novelty, discovery, or surprise. So that’s what I was looking for!
That’s what I was meant to make!” (quoted in: [41], p. 310).
14
A term coined by Barad [3].
193
Enjoying vivid values comes with perception. But this perception does not start in the mind, or
from the Human, as there would be nothing to take account of without the active involvement of the
piece of art15. The proposition that reveals itself in this process is perceptual knowledge or that what
we are aware of. Gathered together and thus standing out in the total environment, Williams’ poem
with its intra-acting words makes a mark and even the viewer qua viewer is a result of this process,
again and again. This self-explanatory nature is not dependent on a Subject for the marking (“This
work of art represents…”) nor are we looking at an external, purely contingent, meaningless
physicality (no mark, no perception; no perception, no mark). (Here and now we are knee-deep in
Whitehead’s philosophy and can only recognize the inclusive level from which Snow’s distinctions
have come about).
Rightly, Shaviro, in Without Criteria, situates such Whiteheadian work on the level upon which
stalemated subject, instrument, and object are mangled (onto-epistemology) and he goes as far as
claiming that “[i]n the vast interconnections of the universe, everything both perceives and is
perceived” ([5], p. 27). Perception, therefore, gets an expansive meaning:
Clear and distinct human sense perception […] is one sort of prehension. A new entity
comes into being by prehending other entities; every event is the prehension of other
events. All this applies […] not only to the encounter between subject and object, but
also to encounters between one object and another, as well as to what is commonly
called the “identity” of the individual subject ([5], p. 29).
Shaviro explains that this inclusive “prehension”, which is at the basis of the gathering-together,
does not prompt a “representational correspondence between ideas and things” ([5], p. 144,
footnote 1), but that “adequacy is a goal that we will never fully reach” ([5], p. 145; cf. [46], p. 43)16.
As a goal, “[a]dequacy has to do with extension […] it continually needs to be constructed, in the
ongoing process of philosophical speculation” ([5], p. 144, footnote 1) and, by implication, in all
ongoing naturalist processes.
It is here that we have to position Shaviro’s endorsement of the Kantian beautiful, at the expense
of the latter’s sublime. The beautiful is not about “the rupture of appearances and the emergence of a
traumatic ‘Real’, but rather [about] the ‘purposeful adaptation of Appearance to Reality’” ([5], p. 160).
15
Again, this process is also at work at the poet’s desk. As Virginia Woolf wrote in Orlando: “He was describing, as
all young poets are for ever describing, nature, and in order to match the shade of green precisely he looked (and
here he showed more audacity than most) at the thing itself, which happened to be a laurel bush growing beneath
the window. After that, of course, he could write no more. Green in nature is one thing, green in literature another.
Nature and letters seem to have a natural antipathy; bring them together and they tear each other to pieces. The
shade of green Orlando now saw spoilt his rhyme and split his metre. Moreover, nature has tricks of her own” ([44],
p. 5). It must have been for this reason that Geoffrey H. Hartmann wrote in his article “Virginia’s Web”: “Nature
[…] is one in which the artist participates” ([45], p. 27).
16
Note that the insertion of neo-Kantian philosopher Cassirer pertains to another diffraction offered by this article.
I will argue elsewhere that just like Cassirer’s philosophy of technology fits process-philosophies of technicity
(cf. [47]), his “logic of the cultural sciences” fits the philosophy of the humanities such as it is developed in this
article [48]. The important point being that this is in spite of the neo-Kantianism according to which his work is
usually classified.
194
This “performative correspondence” [47] allows for underlining how the beautiful is ultimately
about, in Kantian terms,
[…] a judgment of taste [that] involves an uncoerced response, on the part of the
subject, to the object that is being judged beautiful. Aesthetic judgment is a kind of
recognition: it’s an appreciation of how the object “adapts itself to the way we
apprehend it”, even though, at the same time, it remains indifferent to us ([5], p. 2;
emphasis in original).
Shaviro continues by stating that this “adaptation” must be read as a Darwinian notion exemplified
by the “response-ability” 17 of the orchid and the wasp, an example that has been made famous by
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari and stems from the work of evolutionary biologist Rémy Chauvin,
who was, as a matter of fact, highly critical of the work of Charles Darwin [51]. During a process of
adaptation, “the object lures the subject while remaining indifferent to it; and the subject feels the
object, without knowing it or possessing it or even caring about it” ([5], p. 5; emphasis in original) 18.
The active role of the non-human in the so-called “judgment of taste” has now been secured: both
humans and non-humans are response-able and this relationality can be both inter- and intra-species
(cf. [49]). Shaviro makes the role of beauty in the break-through of dualisms on the level of concepts,
methodology, and schools of thought precise. Putting an end to Cartesianism, positivism, and
linguistic constructivism alike, Shaviro’s work on the Immanuel Kant of the Third Critique19, on
Whitehead, and on Deleuze is all about the intertwinement of how and what we know. That what we
know is intertwined with the world makes all of the thinkers just listed into “secular and naturalistic
[thinkers according to whom] empiricism is ultimately correct: all our knowledge comes from
experience, and there is nothing outside experience, or beyond it” ([5], pp. 23–24).
17
This concept is Derridean, Harawayian, and Baradian [8,49,50].
18
Throughout his book Shaviro is keen on highlighting that he is not on the side of the speculative realists/materialists
or object-oriented ontologists, for that matter. For instance, he affirms that “[t]he aesthetic subject does not impose
its forms upon an otherwise chaotic outside world. Rather, this subject is itself informed by the world outside, a
world that (in the words of Wallace Stevens) ‘fills the being before the mind can think’” ([5], p. 13; emphasis in
original). The point here is that the speculative realists/materialists would label this a “correlationist” argument (a
label that is negatively evaluated) based on Shaviro’s inclusion of the aesthetic subject. Shaviro explicitly reads
Whitehead as a theorist of “subjectivity as embedded in the world. The subject is an irreducible part of the universe,
of the way things happen” ([5], p. xii).
19
Cassirer talks about value and Kant too, but his Kant is a wholly different Kant ([48], p. 104). This demonstrates
that a diffractive reading does not entail the smoothing out of important differences or tensions.
195
environment. Second, in Becoming Undone, Elizabeth Grosz comes to the study of beauty by way
of her fascination for the work of Darwin as diffracted with Luce Irigaray’s feminist philosophy.
Irigaray is “with perhaps Deleuze alone” said to push to “the terms by which we understand our
existence as beings in a world larger than ourselves, a world not entirely of our making, whose limits
and constraints provide the very limits and constraints of thought itself” ([52], p. 99). In line with
Whitehead again, Grosz argues that the push to such a world in humanities scholarship “is not alien
to a Darwinian understanding of natural and sexual selection and is actively confirmed by [Darwin’s]
claims more than perhaps those of any other theorist of the nineteenth and twentieth century” ([52],
p. 104). If nineteenth-century Darwin actively confirms the twentieth-century Irigarayian insight that
“nature itself is sexed, made up of (at least) two types of being, two forms of incarnation, two types
of sexuality and morphology, two types of activity and interpretation” ([52], p. 104), the oeuvre of
Darwin extends beyond itself. It is no longer just to be considered along the progressively linear lines
of Darwin leading to socio-biology and sociobiology leading to evolutionary psychology (EP), on
the one hand, and twentieth-century and contemporary feminists reconfirming socio-biology and EP
by negation, on the other. Grosz makes clear that whereas socio-biology and EP thrive on crude
materialism and feminist theory on idealism (cf. [53], p. 58), both are grafted upon a(n exclusion of a)
Darwinism that, together with Irigaray and Deleuze, affirms that
[n]ature itself is dynamized, historical, and subject to dramatic change. Sexual
difference remains the most creative and powerful means by which this transformation
is brought about. It is the means by which the natural cultivates culture, rather than
culture cultivating nature ([52], p. 168).
Dynamic nature, in other words, is originary and sexual differing moves the ever-changing
marking exercise that is the motor of nature as always/already dynamic. Sexual bifurcation is not,
once again, naturalized.
Grosz’s work hinges on the insight that Darwin’s “[s]exual selection may be understood as the
queering of natural selection, that is, the rendering of any biological norms, ideals of fitness, strange,
incalculable, excessive” ([52], p. 132). The process of “queering” in this fragment does not uncover
presentism on the side of Grosz. Whereas queer theory as a conceptual field is localized in the here
and now, its actualized form references not at all a thorough excessiveness in the biological,
the cultural, let alone the biocultural sense. “Queer” can signify a sexual selection that goes beyond
“gene maximization, of the selfish gene’s interest in its own perpetuation” ([52], p. 129) as well as
beyond identity politics, which is a selection that demonstrates how biology and culture are
predicated upon one another:
Homosexuality, like racial diversity or difference, […] is one of the many excesses that
sexual selection introduces to life, like music, art, and language, excesses that make life
more enjoyable, more intense, more noticeable and pleasurable than it would otherwise
be. ([52], p. 131)
196
Nature explains itself: sexual selection introduces “aesthetic value in the sheer relationality and
facticity before one’s eyes”. Of course, a well-known example pertains to the peacock’s feathers, “an
impressive display of beauty” ([52], p. 128)20.
And indeed, Becoming Undone closes with an analysis of art, albeit not in the incarnation of
“Darwinian lit crit”. Grosz brings in aboriginal art as it is anti-representationalist, yet fully situated
and visionary; it asks of its viewers to become with the work and, as such, this “[a]rt denaturalizes
life” ([52], p. 189) as much as it deculturalizes culture, we could add (cf. [55]), as we are not
supposed to be reverted back to idealism. Aboriginal art is the art that endures and opens up to the
total environment of the Australian land. Grosz claims that “[i]n the work of Aboriginal artists, art
becomes ontology” ([52], p. 190; cf. [56]). What is particularly striking about Grosz’s analyses of the
artworks of Doreen Reid Nakamarra and Martu women is how the lines, the paint, and the pictorial
elements; sand dunes, hills, lakes, and waves function precisely like those elements that Dean
mentioned in his Whiteheadian poetry analysis. The so-called elements are not the relata, but what
happens is that the art works express sheer relating in such a way that what happens on the canvas or
the paper is “not in opposition to science, however one may understand this term, but as its
underside, as its intuitive complement” ([52], p. 190). It is once again one nature that is originary as it
is from here that the colored lines and patches gather together.
In The Art of Evolution—a book illustrating the intricate interwovenness of science and art around
1890—Phillip Prodger cites Darwin’s take on the matter. The following sentences were published in
the fifth edition of The Origin of Species from 1869, but had been cooked up in 1838–1839 when
Darwin was about to finish the first edition of his world-famous book:
[…] the sense of beauty obviously depends on the nature of the mind, irrespective of
any real quality in the admired object; and […] the idea of what is beautiful, [is] not
innate or unalterable. […] If beautiful objects had been created solely for man’s
gratification, it ought to be shown that before man appeared, there was less beauty on
the face of the earth than since he came on stage. (quoted in: [57], p. 51)
Darwin’s first sentence appears to be an anthropocentrism; however, Darwin’s entire work
centered on “the animal origins of the most complex human mental functions” instead of “ascribing
human values to animals” ([57], p. 55). Therefore, it is just like the second sentence a meditation on
the indifference of the object according to which it is only in the encounter happening in the total
environment that a judgment of taste makes for something that stays. When we are confronted with
an object from a time before man (“archefossils”, to speak with Quentin Meillassoux in [58]) and
judge it as beautiful, this is proof of the non-linear spatiotemporality of the total environment that we
find in art. The endurance of the object is precisely that which is inexpressible in a purely scientific
formula—pace EP—because such formulae are based on culture as an outside or Other, and on
language as deceptively static. (The question is of course to what extent such formulae are scientific
and who provides them with that status as histories of science univocally showcase the messiness of
scientific practices.)
20
Grosz alludes at times to the sublime, for instance when she describes her response to aboriginal art “[l]ike when
before huge natural wonders, we are perceptually dwarfed” ([52], p. 200). See also [54].
197
6. Conclusions
For one thing, the attempt to avoid both idealism (the resulting man-made representations come
to stand for the thing) and crude materialism (consequentially materials are merely mute objects
or resources) suits the contemporary humanities well. The disciplined humanities have always
distinguished themselves from a scientistic crude materialism, but this argument got them caught up
in Snow’s “two cultures”. In other words, the dualist rendering of the matter and message of art in
interpretative work that privileged the “message” over the “ matter” reveals that this separation has
not allowed humanities scholars to go to the bottom of things (cf. [59,60]). In an attempt not to give
way to anything crudely material, the Culture-centered humanities have become susceptible to
idealism by privileging the linguistic process, because the message of an artwork is supposed to
come and to be decoded from a humanist mastermind upon which matter remains mute (here, too).
Humanities scholarship that embraces inclusive nature, i.e., that starts from what is before the eyes
of the humanities scholar in an attempt to follow Whitehead’s take on empiricism instead of a take
on empiricism (positivism) that follows the logic of the two cultures is scholarship that affirms
the originary entanglement of matter and meaning, whether conceptualized as “humanicity” [9],
“technicity” [61], “feminicity” [62], “alphabeticity” [63], or, simply and along the lines of this article,
nature. It is this kind of scholarship that evokes an inclusive genealogy of the humanities that is no
longer (in the words of C.P. Snow) “bewitched by the power of dialectics”.
Acknowledgments
The author wishes to thank Alex Hebing for his generous engagement with a previous draft of this
article and the three anonymous reviewers as well as the external editor for their encouraging
comments. The research for this article has been sponsored by the Innovational Research Incentives
Scheme Veni (275-20-029) of the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO).
Conflicts of Interest
1. Michel Foucault. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of Human Sciences. New York: Vintage
Books, 1994. Originally published in 1966.
2. Wilhelm Dilthey. Introduction to the Human Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1989. Originally published in 1883.
3. Karen Barad. Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter
and Meaning. Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2007.
4. Donna Haraway. Modest_Witness@Second_Millennium. FemaleMan©_Meets_
OncoMouse™: Feminism and Technoscience. London and New York: Routledge, 1997.
5. Steven Shaviro. Without Criteria: Kant, Whitehead, Deleuze, and Aesthetics. Cambridge and
London: The MIT Press, 2009.
198
25. Steven Shapin. Never Pure: Historical Studies of Science as if It Was Produced by People with
Bodies, Situated in Time, Space, Culture, and Society, and Struggling for Credibility and
Authority. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010.
26. James W. McAllister. Beauty & Revolution in Science. Ithaca and London: Cornell University
Press, 1996.
27. Félix Guattari. The Three Ecologies. Translated by Ian Pindar and Paul Sutton. London and
New York: Continuum, 2008. Originally published in 1989.
28. Alfred North Whitehead. “Theories of the Bifurcation of Nature.” In The Concept of Nature:
The Tarner Lectures Delivered in Trinity College November 1919. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1920, pp. 26–48.
29. Donna Haraway. The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Significant Otherness.
Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press, 2003.
30. Karen Barad. “Re(con)figuring Space, Time, and Matter.” In Feminist Locations: Global and
Local, Theory and Practice. Edited by Marianne DeKoven. New Brunswick: Rutgers
University Press, 2001, pp. 75–109.
31. Thomas S. Kuhn. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1996. Originally published in 1962/1969.
32. Gilbert Simondon. On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects. Translated by
Ninian Mellamphy. University of Western Ontario, 1980. Available online:
http://dephasage.ocular-witness.com/pdf/SimondonGilbert.OnTheModeOfExistence.pdf
(accessed on 13 March 2011). Originally published in 1958.
33. Bruno Latour. We Have Never Been Modern. Translated by Catherine Porter. London: Prentice
Hall, 1993. Originally published in 1991.
34. Susanne K. Langer. Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art developed from Philosophy in a New
Key. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1953.
35. Renée C. Hoogland. A Violent Embrace: Art and Aesthetics after Representation. Hanover:
Dartmouth College Press, 2014.
36. Félix Ravaisson. Of Habit. Translated from the French by Clare Carlisle and Mark Sinclair.
New York and London: Continuum, 2008. Originally published in 1838.
37. Henri Bergson. “The Life and Work of Ravaisson.” In The Creative Mind: An Introduction to
Metaphysics. Translated by Mabelle L. Andison. Mineola: Dover Publications, 2007, pp. 187–216.
Originally published in 1904.
38. Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari. What is Philosophy? New York: Columbia University Press,
1994. Originally published in 1991.
39. Gregg Lambert. “How to Create a Territory with the Work of Art?” Paper presented at the
seminar Materialism without Territory—Art and the Environment, CAAD—Chair for
Computer Aided Architectural Design, Zürich, Switzerland, May 2014.
40. Bruno Latour. Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1999.
200
41. Bruno Latour. “Reflections on Etienne Souriau’s Les différents modes d’existence.” In The
Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. Edited by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek
and Graham Harman. Melbourne: re.press, 2011, pp. 304–33.
42. William Dean. “Whitehead’s Other Aesthetic.” Process Studies 13 (1983): 104–12.
43. Gregg Lambert. Who’s Afraid of Deleuze and Guattari? London and New York: Continuum, 2006.
44. Virginia Woolf. Orlando: A Biography. London: Vintage Books, 2004. Originally published
in 1928.
45. Geoffrey H. Hartmann. “Virginia’s Web.” Chicago Review 14 (1961): 20–32.
46. Ernst Cassirer. “Form and Technology.” In Ernst Cassirer on Form and Technology:
Contemporary Readings. Edited by Aud Sissel Hoel and Ingvild Folkvord. Translated by
Wilson McClelland Dunlavey and John Michael Krois. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan,
2012, pp. 15–53. Originally published in 1930.
47. Aud Sissel Hoel, and Iris van der Tuin. “The Ontological Force of Technicity: Reading Cassirer
and Simondon Diffractively.” Philosophy and Technology 26 (2013): 187–202.
48. Ernst Cassirer. The Logic of the Cultural Sciences. Translated by S.G. Lofts. New Haven and
London: Yale University Press, 2000. Originally published in 1942.
49. Jacques Derrida. “The Animal that Therefore I Am (More to Follow).” Translated from the
French by David Wills. Critical Inquiry 28 (2002): 369–418.
50. Donna Haraway. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press, 2008.
51. Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia.
Translated by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987. Originally
published in 1980.
52. Elizabeth Grosz. Becoming Undone: Darwinian Reflections on Life, Politics, and Art. Durham
and London: Duke University Press, 2011.
53. Jonathan Culler. On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism after Structuralism, 25th
anniversary ed. London and New York: Routledge, 2008. Originally published in 1982.
54. Sara Barns, and Andrew Patrizio. “Darwin on the Threshold of the Visible: Contemporary Art
and Evolution.” In The Art of Evolution: Darwin, Darwinisms and Visual Cultures. Edited
by Barbara Larson and Fae Brauer. Dartmouth: University Press of New England, 2009,
pp. 288–309.
55. Samantha Frost. “The Implications of the New Materialisms for Feminist Epistemology.”
In Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science: Power in Knowledge. Edited by Heidi E.
Grasswick. Dordrecht: Springer, 2011, pp. 69–83.
56. Brian Martin. “Immaterial Land.” In Carnal Knowledge: Towards a New Materialism Through
the Arts. Edited by Estelle Barrett and Barbara Bolt. London: I.B. Tauris, 2013, pp. 185–204.
57. Phillip Prodger. “Ugly Disagreements: Darwin and Ruskin Discuss Sex and Beauty.” In The Art
of Evolution: Darwin, Darwinisms and Visual Cultures. Edited by Barbara Larson and Fae
Brauer. Dartmouth: University Press of New England, 2009, pp. 40–58.
58. Quentin Meillassoux. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Translated by
Ray Brassier. New York: Continuum, 2008. Originally published in 2006.
201
59. Estelle Barrett, and Barbara Bolt, eds. Carnal Knowledge: Towards a New Materialism through
the Arts. London and New York: I.B. Tauris, 2013.
60. Bettina Papenburg, and Marta Zarzycka, eds. Carnal Aesthetics: Transgressive Imaginary and
Feminist Politics. London and New York: I.B. Tauris, 2013.
61. Federica Frabetti. “Rethinking the Digital Humanities in the Context of Originary Technicity.”
Culture Machine 12 (2011): 1–22.
62. Felicity Colman. “Affective Feminicity.” Paper presented at the 8th European Feminist
Research Conference, Budapest, Hungary, May 2012.
63. Vera Bühlmann. “The Body of the Cypher (An Atomist View on Computational Entities that are
Generic in their Kind).” Paper presented at the seminar Materialism without Territory—Art and
the Environment, CAAD—Chair for Computer Aided Architectural Design, Zürich,
Switzerland, May 2014.
202
Abstract: This paper explores the ways that critics writing in the early nineteenth century developed
arguments in favor of what we think of today as the humanities in the face of utilitarian pressures that
dismissed the arts as self-indulgent pursuits incapable of addressing real-world problems. Its focus
reflects the extent to which the financial crisis in our own day has manifested itself in a jarring shift
in research priorities towards applied knowledge: a retrenchment which has foregrounded all over
again the question of how to make the case for the value of the humanities. These problems, however,
also constitute an important opportunity: a chance to re-imagine our answers to questions about
the nature and role of the humanities, their potential benefits to contemporary life, and how we might
channel these benefits back into the larger society. The good news is that in many ways, this
self-reflexive challenge is precisely what the humanities have always done best: highlight the nature
and the force of the narratives that have helped to define how we understand our society—its various
pasts and its possible futures—and to suggest the larger contexts within which these issues must
ultimately be situated. History repeats itself, but never in quite the same way: knowing more about
past debates will provide a crucial basis for moving forward as we position themselves to respond to
new social, economic, technological, and cultural challenges during an age of radical change.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Keen, P. “Imagining What We Know”: The Humanities in a
Utilitarian Age. Humanities 2014, 3, 73–87.
For those of us working in the humanities it is, as Charles Dickens famously said, the best of times
and the worst of times. The digital revolution has manifested itself in a range of cultural changes that
are in many ways far more radical than the ones unleashed by the invention of the printing press over
five hundred years ago, and they have made their presence felt far more swiftly. Where those earlier
changes took centuries before their impact was fully realized, the digital revolution has redefined our
communicative world in decades. And whereas the invention of moveable type preserved the basic
form of the codex, the digital revolution has altered the most fundamental ways that it is possible to
think about the materiality of writing, and about the relation between books and texts. Its interactive
possibilities have also forced us to reimagine our ideas about the relationship between authors and
readers, and between the individual reader and the reading public (or publics) to which he or she may
feel they belong. Never before has a generation lived through such extraordinary technological and
cultural changes.
Nor are these changes limited to those emerging creative and critical forms that have become
known as digital humanities. The advent of new technologies and the new forms of textual community
they enable have cast those earlier technologies of writing associated with manuscript and print
203
culture in an exciting new light by helping to expose many of the assumptions that had, until the last
couple of decades, been so thoroughly naturalized that they resisted critical analysis. As critics such
as Adrien Johns and Andrew Piper have argued, becoming more attuned to the historical arbitrariness
of these technological achievements (the fact that their history did not unfold in any preordained
way) has made us newly aware of the kinds of ideological work that were required in order not to
think about the many forms of mediation (cultural, political, technological, educational, economic)
that had naturalized these earlier forms of textual production [1,2]. As a result of these changes in our
own day, we have very rapidly grown used to thinking in far broader terms about the kinds of
infrastructure that lurk just beneath the surface of the production, circulation, and reception of the
books whose material reality earlier critics tended to dismiss in order to concentrate on the literary
richness of the ideas they contained. Predictions of “the death of the book” (a media favorite for the
past several years, though it seems to have diminished recently) may have been premature, but we
can never take the idea of “the book” for granted again.
That is the upside. But if the extraordinarily rapid and wide-ranging changes unleashed by the
digital revolution have shaken up our most entrenched assumptions about important forms of cultural
production and reception in critically exciting ways, it is equally true that it is hard to think of a time
when the humanities were so badly besieged on any number of levels, the most serious of which has
been a jarring shift in research priorities towards market-driven applied knowledge: a retrenchment
that has foregrounded all over again the question of how to make the case for the value of the
humanities. As Martha Nussbaum has recently argued, “we are in the midst of a crisis of massive
proportions and grave global significance”: not “the global economic crisis that began in 2008”
(though that context is definitely part of the issue), but the widespread erosion of support for the
humanities in terms of both pedagogical and research priorities within universities ([3], pp. 1–2).
Nussbaum’s book—Not For Profit: Why Democracy Needs the Humanities—has become a widely
cited element of this debate, but the urgency of the topic has generated numerous books and articles,
many of them by distinguished scholars in a range of venues, from academic journals to leading
magazines and newspapers. As Marjorie Perloff put it in an article entitled “Crisis in the Humanities”,
“[o]ne of our most common genres today is the epitaph for the humanities” [4]. The phrase
itself—crisis in the humanities—has become so familiar that it has begun to appear in scare quotes,
along with warnings that just because everyone is saying it, doesn’t mean it isn’t true. “You’ve
probably heard several times already that the humanities are in ‘crisis’”, Gordon Hunter and Feisal G.
Mohammed wrote in a New Republic article entitled “The Real Humanities Crisis Is Happening at
Public Universities”, but as their title implies, this doesn’t mean that we should doubt it. “The crisis
is real”, they assure us [5]. Few would contradict them. In a column in the New York Times that was
prompted by the threat of SUNY Albany to close their French, Italian, Classics, Russian and theater
programs, Stanley Fish responded to a letter from one of his readers that it “will be a sad, sad day if
and when we allow the humanities to collapse” by insisting “that it had already happened”. Fish’s
tone of world-weary resignation struck many people as misguided (“I have always had trouble
believing in the high-minded case for a core curriculum—that it preserves and transmits the best that
has been thought and said—but I believe fully in the core curriculum as a device of employment for
me and my fellow humanists”), but his pessimism is widely shared [6]. Robert Weisbuch is on safe
204
ground in his insistence that “today’s consensus about the state of the humanities—it’s bad, it’s
getting worse, and no one is doing much about it—is supported by dismal facts” ([7], p. B4). However
illustrious their past, the humanities have no future at all, so these epitaphs suggest, and that
recognition has put its stamp on our present discussions like few other topics today, the digital
revolution not excepted.
The signs of this crisis are everywhere around us. In England, the government’s 2010 decision to
cancel funding for the teaching of humanities programs has been doubled by the spirit of intellectual
recoil that characterizes its new Research Excellence Framework, which was recently established
as the official basis for determining research funding allocations amongst English universities. As
Stefan Collini has pointed out, part of this formula for funding allocation depends on what the
Research Excellence Framework calls the “impact” of research, a somewhat nebulous concept which
the Framework breaks down into thirty-seven categories, each of which is in turn measured by a
series of “indicators” such as (to quote the Framework) “creating new businesses”, “commercializing
new products or processes”, and “attracting R & D investment from global business” (quoted in [8],
p. 18). As Collini points out, the final category, the only one where the work of most humanities
scholars might easily be slotted, which is headed “other quality of life benefits”, is unique amongst
the thirty-seven in having no examples provided. In place of the sorts of concrete indicators
suggested in the other thirty-six examples of research impact, this final one contains a one-line note
that merely says: “please suggest what might also be included in this list” (quoted in [8], p. 18).
Admittedly, the “impact” score accounts for only 20% of the overall assessment (likely to rise to 25%
in the next REF cycle); publications in scholarly journals of “high quality” still weigh far more heavily.
But this inability to imagine the “impact” or usefulness of the humanities is a chilling index of a
broader failure of the same kind. These institutional pressures are also taking more insidious forms,
such as the current shift within the U.K. to an emphasis on “open access” publishing. Few would
disagree with the intrinsic worth of this idea in the abstract, but the fact that publishing costs will be
downloaded to researchers has opened the door to further problems by enabling universities to target
which areas of research will receive support to offset these costs.
Evidence of these problems is just as hard to miss in Canada, where I live and work, from the
federal government’s $7 million cut to SSHRC1 funding in 2012 (all of which was replaced by
targeted funding emphasizing collaboration with industry, or more broadly, non-academic partners);
to the cancellation of the Ontario Research Fund, including the special round for the Social Sciences,
Arts, and Humanities; to the growing sway of a narrow cluster of research priorities (health,
environment, and digital technologies) and a rhetorical emphasis on addressing “real-life problems”
within universities’ strategic plans. It is borne out, over and over again, in the closure of university
departments and programs, the budget cuts, and the general climate of suspicion that have become
part of our day-to-day experience. In 2013, the University of Alberta announced that it had suspended
admission to twenty humanities programs. An editorial entitled “Liberal Arts and Commercial
Utility” in the Globe and Mail (Canada’s leading national newspaper) epitomized this reactionary
climate in its warning that “the liberal arts are necessary and good, but not sufficient in the modern
1
SSHRC, or the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council, is the main source of research funding for
academics working in the humanities and social sciences.
205
age” ([9], p. F8). If, as Percy Shelley once famously complained, poets had been challenged “to
resign the civic crown to reasoners and mechanists”, this same tension has reemerged today in the
face of a new utilitarianism ([10], p. 131).
But as serious as these problems are, it is important to recognize that they are not reducible to a
growing antagonism to the humanities alone. Scientists within and outside of universities have been
equally outraged by what they regard as an unprecedented attack on the idea of curiosity-driven
abstract research: the pursuit of knowledge as an end in itself. In December 2012, hundreds of
leading scientists in lab coats marched in front of Parliament Hill to protest being muzzled by a
government that is mistrustful of any sort of research that is not in step with their business agenda.
Five months later, John McDougall, the Calgary businessman who serves as President of Canada’s
National Research Council (once a highly respected body of scientific researchers) made headlines
by insisting that “innovation is not valuable unless it has commercial value”. McDougall’s comments
were part of an announcement of a broader shift in the NRC's focus towards research the government
deems “commercially viable” [11]. As an editorial about the fate of the NRC in the Toronto Star put
it, “once a bastion of pure research—exploratory science no business would pay for but which is
essential to eventual innovation—the agency has been redesigned to respond to industry requests, its
$900-million budget effectively transformed into a business subsidy” [12]. Within universities, this
attack on pure research is part of an underlying tendency to thinking about the role of the university
in more narrowly vocational terms as an institution whose primary role is to ensure that graduates
secure well-paying jobs. Months after McDougall’s announcement, the ACCUTE2 president, Stephen
Slemon, warned that as sharply as the humanities have felt the burden of financial cuts, it is crucial to
recognize this wider context: “we are all under attack. I don’t know anyone now working in any of
the postsecondary human or natural sciences who does not feel institutionally threatened” [13].
As Slemon suggests, it is important to recognize the extent to which the crisis in the humanities
today is intensified by this double threat: a shift away from the humanities towards STEM disciplines
(Science, Technology, Engineering, Mathematics) that is compounded by a broader resistance to
curiosity-driven research in both the arts and the sciences. Worse, as critics such as Collini and
Thomas Docherty have recently argued, this double problem is further intensified by a growing
suspicion of universities generally [14,15]. “At a moment when the number of students currently
enrolled in these institutions across the globe is several times larger than was the case only a generation
ago, there is unprecedented skepticism about the benefits (both intellectual and material) of a university
education” ([14], p. 3). Based within institutions that are increasingly underfunded, besieged by a
growing insistence on the exclusive worth of “commercially viable” research, and rooted in the most
vulnerable side of the disciplinary divide within universities, support for the humanities has been
weakened by a growing skepticism about any sort of research that cannot be converted into short
term market-based applications, and any sort of education that is unlikely to lead to good jobs. (It
seems to do little good to cite studies that indicate that humanities graduates fare equally well in their
subsequent careers, even if it the transition from university to a good job takes slightly longer.) “The
2
The Association of Canadian College and University Teachers in English is in many ways the Canadian equivalent
of the MLA.
206
liberal arts are necessary and good”, the saying goes, but clearly “not sufficient in the modern age”.
The best of times and the worst of times, for sure.
2. Past Debates
the tendency of “the thinking and studious, and scientific and philosophical part of the community”
to draw on “the materials of useful knowledge” in order to prepare one’s self for “the real business of
life” ([18], pp. 578–79). These sorts of views are crucial for two reasons. Utilitarians’ hostility to
poetry (and to imaginative expression generally) represented a challenge that would help to define
the struggle to articulate a role for the humanities at the precise historical moment when the idea
of culture was crystallizing into its modern form. But just as importantly, the utilitarians were
themselves reformers eager to effect social change, which made the challenge of responding to their
hostile ideas about the social worth of poetry especially urgent. As with today, it was never a debate
between reformers and reactionaries, but about what forms of knowledge production mattered
amongst those people who shared a commitment to social and political improvement.
The crisis that forces us to make the case for the humanities today in the face of similar pressures
to focus on “useful knowledge” that is suited to “the real business of life” can best be answered with
a clearer understanding of the ways that ideas about the humanities were forged in the crucible of this
spirit of intellectual reaction which defined itself in terms of the unique importance of more “serious”
forms of knowledge. For early nineteenth-century advocates such as Shelley, William Hazlitt, and
Leigh Hunt, the arts constituted a central aspect of a larger struggle for social progress, but like today,
these arguments were themselves sharpened by the need to challenge a utilitarian emphasis on
the primacy of applied knowledge. These writers anticipated Albert Einstein’s famous comment that
“imagination is more important than knowledge. For knowledge is limited to all we now know
and understand, while imagination embraces the entire world, and all there ever will be to know and
understand” ([19], p. 97). But they did so in a polemical spirit that was animated by the need to
make a case for the importance of the humanities in the face of a backlash against the value of
imaginative expression.
Those writers who sought to make a case for the arts responded in a range of ways, from Hazlitt’s
and Thomas Carlyle’s vehement opposition to utilitarianism’s reductive moral calculus, to Hunt’s
and John Stuart Mill’s efforts to forge some degree of common ground, to Francis Jeffrey’s struggle
to adapt the legacy of Scottish Enlightenment accounts of sympathy to the demands of an industrial
society. Shelley’s response, which was in many ways the most radical and the most theoretically
sophisticated of his age, and which it has become crucial to make again, if in slightly different terms,
was that poetry—or today, the humanities—must be understood, not as the opposite but at the limits
of applied knowledge: a larger perspective that enables us “to imagine that which we know”, in
part by highlighting the “unapprehended relations” within which particular innovations must be
situated ([10], pp. 111, 134). Poetry, he argued, offers a potential for insight into the nature and limits
of applied knowledge capable of extending the transformative power of reason by setting reason
against itself in a self-reflexive turn which belongs to the province of the imagination. The implication
of Shelley’s argument was that poetry was the more important or “useful” form of knowledge, even
in Peacock’s rigidly utilitarian terms, but if Shelley’s insistence on the importance of fostering larger
critical contexts within which to think about these issues (“imagin[ing] that which we know”) is just
as relevant today as it was two hundred years ago, his intervention is equally instructive in another
way as well.
208
Our sense of crisis has helped to foster an energetic and sophisticated debate about the nature and
value of the humanities but it is worth emphasizing that a crisis mentality has risks of its own.
Besieged on all sides, it can be hard to resist a set of sometimes counterproductive consolatory
narratives about why the humanities matter, many of which either view our neglect as an ironic
badge of honor—the fact that we remain proudly out of step with the larger vocational and
commercial spirit of our age—or which simply reverse the kinds of intellectual prejudices that we are
protesting against. W. H. Auden’s claim that “poetry makes nothing happen: it survives/In the valley
of its making where executives/Would never want to tamper” is understandably tempting, especially
given many corporate executives’ evident lack of concern for poetry, but this sort of special pleading
for some rarified position sheltered from the corrupting influence of the world will not ultimately
help us to develop an adequate response to the crisis in the humanities today [20].
Posing the question, “What, then, can be done?” Fish warns “it won’t do to invoke the pieties” that
have become familiar elements of this debate: “the humanities enhance our culture; the humanities
make our society better—because those pieties have a 19th century air about them and are not even
believed in by some who rehearse them” [6]. Alex Usher, the author of a popular on-line column
offered by the Higher Education Strategy Associates, puts it even more bluntly. Taking issue with
the kinds of positions espoused by Rosanna Warren in her New Republic article, “The Decline of
the Humanities—and Civilization”, which imply that the humanities have some sort of monopoly on
teaching people “what it is to be fully human”, Usher warns against the reaction that this kind of
self-aggrandizing claim produces: “Honestly, how self-absorbed, smug, self-righteous and arrogant
does one have to be to believe that one’s own work is solely responsible for the maintenance of all
human progress since the Renaissance? After reading it, I actively wanted to go around, eliminating
random humanities departments out of sheer spite” [21]. It is worth adding that Usher has nothing
against humanities programs, but his response is both understandable and illuminating: arguments
which imply that the humanities are somehow inherently superior to other intellectual fields, or that
those people who have not benefited from a humanities education are not “fully human” (even if they
mistakenly think they are) are inevitably going to rub people the wrong way.
Which brings us back to Shelley’s Defense of Poetry, a polemic that, read superficially, seems
to epitomize the self-righteous strain that Usher objects to in Warner’s argument. Stung by Peacock’s
diatribe against poetry, Shelley fought back by insisting on the paramount importance of those
committed to the task of “enlarg[ing] our imagination” or, as critics might put it today, helping us “to
be fully human” ([10], p. 132). Had “reasoners” such as Locke, Hume, Gibbon, Voltaire, Rousseau
and their disciples never struggled on behalf of “oppressed and deluded humanity”, Shelley allowed,
“a little more nonsense would have been talked for a century or two; and perhaps a few more men,
women and children, burnt as heretics. We might not at this moment have been congratulating each
other on the abolition of the Inquisition in Spain” ([10], p. 132). These reforms were all good things,
Shelley acknowledged, but in comparison with their limited impact, “it exceeds all imagination to
conceive what would have been the moral condition of the world if neither Dante, Petrarch,
Boccaccio, Chaucer, Shakespeare, Calderon, Lord Bacon, nor Milton, had ever existed; if Raphael
and Michael Angelo had never been born; if the Hebrew poetry had never been translated; if a revival
209
of the study of Greek literature had never taken place; if no monuments of ancient sculpture had been
handed down to us” ([10], p. 132).
It sounds awful, of course, a high-water mark in “self-absorbed, smug, self-righteous and
arrogant” responses to anyone who would dare to criticize the importance of the arts or humanities.
Who cares if a few more or less “oppressed and deluded” people die cruel and unnecessary deaths
compared with the horror of living in a world without Shakespeare and Milton. Except that Shelley is
a step ahead of us. His real point, as he quickly makes clear, is not that the “higher truths” offered by
those individuals blessed with artistic genius trumps social reform but that this latter group—the
“promoters of utility”—are in danger of intervening in ways that are ultimately counterproductive
because they have been blinded by their uncritical faith in the force of reason and the sufficiency of
applied knowledge. Having neglected the task of “enlarg[ing] their imagination”, they have failed to
ask the more serious questions about both the unexamined assumptions and unintended consequences
of their efforts. Their uncritical commitment to an eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century form
of technological determinism left them exposed to the danger of what Shelley denounced as “the
abuse of all invention for abridging and combining labor, to the exasperation of the inequality of
mankind” ([10], p. 134). His reference, of course, was to the disastrous effects of that best and worst
innovation of the industrial age known as the assembly line, which works precisely through
abridging and combining labor. The opening pages of Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations featured a
reverential depiction of the almost magical force of a proper division of labor in something as
“trifling” as a pin factory, in which the work is “divided into about eighteen distinct operations” ([22],
pp. 14–15). All that was needed was that the workers be “collected”, where the scale of the operation
allowed, “into the same workhouse” ([22], p. 14), an arrangement that was central to what Smith
lauded as the task of “reducing every man’s business to some one simple operation, and … making
this operation the sole employment of his life” ([22], p. 18). Lest we should be in danger of missing
the fact that this is what he too has in mind, Shelley repeats himself in an almost identical description
four paragraphs later:
Whilst the mechanist abridges, and the political economist combines, labor, let them
beware that their speculations, for want of correspondence with those first principles
which belong to the imagination, do not tend, as they have in modern England, to
exasperate at once the extremes of luxury and want ([10], p. 132).
Shelley’s argument was not ultimately with social activists’ struggle to achieve political reform
(his polemic, A Philosophical View of Reform, tended to regard them in more generous terms as
important allies in the struggle for social progress) but with the dangerous lack of perspective that
uncritical ideas about reason as an engine of progress and technology as an inherently beneficial
force implied: the unintended “abuse” of new forms of instrumentalist knowledge.
Shelley’s concern here is about fundamental social realities rather than higher spiritual truths,
about economics rather than aesthetics: about the sorts of issues which ought to have been more
forcefully championed by Enlightenment reformers, had they thought imaginatively enough about
the impact of their own struggles. The reformist dream of rational progress had collapsed into a
utilitarianism which, despite its triumphalist rhetoric, only reinforced existing inequalities. Knowledge
210
had fallen prisoner to the very historical forces that it had presumed to challenge; history remained
the nightmare that reformers were struggling to wake up from. Or as Shelley rather unpoetically put
it, “the rich have become richer, and the poor have become poorer” ([10], p. 132). His point was not
that Enlightenment reformers’ efforts had not mattered but rather that they had been undermined
by the tendency of their very success to overshadow the larger sorts of questions that would help to
ensure their ongoing social good. Poetry (or the arts) offered a radical extension of the critical
impulse associated with reason, an amplification rather than a negation of its transformative power
(or “impact”) which insists on the primacy of a much broader sense of the “unapprehended relations”
within which particular developments must be situated ([10], p. 111).
Nor, for Shelley, was this merely a historical coincidence. On the contrary, it was precisely the
breathtaking pace of change that had fostered this faith in technology as an end in itself. People had
lost perspective, which is the real danger in times of rapid and fundamental change: “We have more
moral, political and historical wisdom, than we know how to reduce into practice; we have more
scientific and economical knowledge than can be accommodated to the just distribution of the
produce which it multiplies. The poetry in these systems of thought, is concealed by the accumulation
of facts and calculating processes” ([10], p. 134). The problem lay in an imbalance between applied
and self-reflexive knowledge: “a cultivation of the mechanical arts in a degree disproportioned to the
presence of the creative faculty... From what other cause has it arisen that these inventions which
should have lightened, have added a weight to the curse imposed on Adam?” ([10], p. 134).
Shelley’s critique amounts to an early version of the argument that Max Horkheimer and Theodor
Adorno would offer in Dialectic of Enlightenment, that the progress of enlightened thought tended,
by its very nature, to undermine itself because its very successes weakened the all-important tension
between these two very different kinds of knowledge: the technological field of applied expertise and
a critical self-reflexiveness (Shelley’s “poetic faculty”) that ought to pose questions about the larger
context within which instrumentalist advances ought to be situated [23]. Horkheimer and Adorno
were ultimately pessimistic about the possibility of reversing this process, but for Shelley, the poetic
imagination was also a form of praxis, simultaneously a set of critical insights and a force that would
generate the impulse to put these into action: “We want the creative faculty to imagine that which we
know; we want the generous impulse to act that which we imagine” ([10], p. 134). Nor was this task
altogether difficult, had people the will to do so: “There is no want of knowledge respecting what is
wisest and best in morals, government, and political economy, or at least, what is wiser and better
than what men now practice and endure. But we let ‘I dare not wait upon I would, like the poor cat in
the adage’” ([10], p. 134).
3. Future Roles
This emphasis on poetry as a critical perspective from which to reconsider inherited ideas and as a
spur to act on the conclusions this reconsideration suggested may ultimately have been a bit
romantic. Poetry may never have possessed the revolutionary power that Shelley suggests. But
having said so, it is worth emphasizing the timeliness of Shelley’s argument about the dangers of the
scramble to embrace applied knowledge at the expense of any adequate recognition of larger social
and political contexts: the “unapprehended relations” within which these solutions to so-called
211
real-world problems must be situated. And this is where he might well have found an ally in critics
such as Usher. Having been challenged by his readers to answer the question of what sort of
arguments we might want to make, in place of the self-serving claims for the unique power of the
humanities that he had denounced, Usher cites Paul Wells’ argument in his 2010 article, “In Praise of
the Squishy Subjects”, that “societal problems are incredibly complex and can’t be explained by simple
cause-and-effect, what the humanities do is get people used to the idea of complexity” [24,25].
Especially, one might add, in times when rapid change heightens both the appeal and the dangers of
an unexamined faith in innovation. As Stanley Fish rightly warns us, making our case by appealing to
values that sound like they belong to another era won’t be much help in our efforts to persuade the
broader public of our worth, but ironically, knowing more about the long history of the struggle to
make this case may itself be instructive in forging the kinds of arguments that will help as we try to
position ourselves in a rapidly changing present.
All of this highlights both the urgency and the complexity of what seem to me to be the most
important points that have emerged out of the debates that this crisis in support for the humanities
has triggered:
The first and most important is the question of how we make the case for the humanities to people
outside of our own academic community. How do we avoid the trap of simply preaching to the
converted? We are bedevilled by the paradox that the positions that will likely be the most popular
amongst us, even when we get these arguments right, may be hardest to convey to the broader public
in any really convincing way. Wells is absolutely right that what may seem like the most necessary
strategy—clambering onto the rhetorical bandwagons of the day—won’t get us very far. Citing
arguments made by Noreen Golfman (then president of the Canadian Federation for the Humanities
and Social Science) “about the contribution of social sciences and humanities research to innovation,
and to our nation’s ability to compete globally and be an effective partner in the international
community”, in part “by stimulating the need for economic recovery in the short term and by shaping
the broader prospects for Canada’s future”, Wells rightly dismisses these arguments as unconvincing
gestures to short-term thinking (quoted in [25]). They sound both opportunistic and, what may be
worse, tedious. But they do clarify the importance of forging arguments that we can believe in in
ways that will resonate with people outside of our own academic community. A bit of history, which
is one of the things that we can bring to the discussion, can help a lot. The other side of this question
is the issue of how far can we push the argument that the self-reflexive space of critical thinking
fostered by the humanities offers a more useful form of knowledge than other “commercially viable”
forms without surrendering to the utilitarian or vocational logic that this argument is intended to
resist. But do we have a choice?
My other points emerge from this initial one. The first is that we need to be wary of the intellectual
cost of the arguments that we have been forced into making, over and over and over again, in favour
of the humanities. It’s not that these arguments aren’t legitimate (I think they are). And it is definitely
not the case that we don’t have to make them. But in being forced to make them so repeatedly and so
defensively, we can travel down an intellectual dead-end that does as much harm as it does good.
Here’s a simple if anecdotal way of explaining what I mean: I became Chair of an English
department a little over six years ago in a Faculty that includes both the arts and social sciences. At
212
the time, the mood was expansive and intellectually generous: the real emphasis was on the common
ground between those two groups. That never really changed, but by the time I stepped down as
Chair this past year, our talk had been hijacked by an embattled sense of how to make the case for the
humanities in the face of a climate, both within and outside of the university, that does not seem to
place much value in what we do. It’s not that we fell out with our colleagues on the social sciences
side of the fence—the opposite was true, much to their credit—but in defending the humanities, we
had been forced into focusing on a set of far less interesting conversations.
The trickiest question may lie in the unexamined tension between the humanities as a field of
critical analysis and humanism as an inherited set of cultural values. How we can make a case for the
humanities in ways that do not depend on what many of us now regard as the outmoded assumptions
that were central to traditional models of humanism? This is the most fundamental question that
confronts us: do we know what we mean by “the humanities” in an age when most of us who work in
the area no longer align ourselves with the humanist ideals that provided our disciplines’ rationale as
they emerged in their modern form in the nineteenth century. It is not simply that, as Fish points out,
these “pieties”—“the humanities enhance our culture; the humanities make our society better”—no
longer strike us convincing; they seem to be bound up with a highly conservative deference to authority
and resistance to activist intervention that has the potential to be deeply reactionary [6]. We avoid
them, not because we’re embarrassed by their dated feel, but because we’re suspicious of their
political implications. We may no longer need to explain the problems that an Arnoldian humanist
rhetoric about the disinterested contemplation of universal truths entailed, but our rejection of it does
raise the thorny question of what we actually mean by the humanities today, in an age that is
increasingly uncomfortable with inherited definitions of the term “humanism”. It raises the question
of how we can make that case to the broader public, if not to our senior administrators, without
appearing to be either self-contradictory or just intellectually dishonest. To put this more constructively,
how might we begin to theorize a new “new humanism”—not the highly conservative school of thought
which became known as the new humanism in the first half of the twentieth century, but one that takes an
honest engagement with these tensions as its starting point without abandoning the political impulse that
helped to fuel critiques of humanism in the name of a historically grounded politics of difference in
recent decades?
Rather than confronting this dilemma as a problem, it may be more accurate and more productive
to recognize it as a valuable starting-point as we position ourselves to answer the question of the
future role of the humanities. If we rid ourselves of the baggage of the sorts of outmoded “pieties”
that Fish cautions us against, which include the idea that the humanities have a singular ability to
make us “fully human”, we can concentrate on Paul Wells’ point, which Usher rightly endorses and
which has become a central aspect of the many discussions that this crisis has prompted, that the
humanities train us to be more fully engaged with the issues of our day. This emphasis on fostering
engaged forms of citizenship, which epitomizes what has become known as the ethical turn in the
work of theorists such as Jacques Derrida and Emmanuel Levinas, has been especially true of recent
debates about globalization, which have highlighted the ways that the relentless traffic of ideas and
bodies, goods and wealth, pipelines and pollutants, across borders and oceans has produced both new
cultural formations and reinvigorated hegemonic orders. An insistence on the importance of
213
recognizing the simultaneity of both of these aspects of our modernity—the growing possibilities of
collaboration on the one hand and the persistent forms of economic exploitation and the cultural
dissonance between incommensurable traditions and value systems on the other—has been a
hallmark of these debates. But this emphasis on encouraging a comfort with complexity as a basis of
new forms of engagement has been equally central to a range of other questions, from the efforts of
posthumanist critics such as Cary Wolfe to complicate debates about animal rights, to the ways that
the concept of “geological agency” proposed by Dipesh Chakrabarty have enabled us to reframe
environmental issues, to Marxist critiques of neoliberalism. Running through all of these has been an
emphasis on the importance of embracing those forms of complexity that flourish in times of
fundamental change when it is no longer possible to deal with emerging problems using inherited
methodologies3.
Offering “a reminder that you can never know what you’ll need to know”, and that it can therefore
never be enough to work hard to “figure out the answers to important questions” without adequately
considering if they are the right questions, or if they have been formulated in the most helpful ways,
Wells points out that what really matters is the challenge of fostering a climate where irreducible
complexity is welcome:
Very few of the problems our society faces admit to narrow technical solutions. There
is no genome for crime or poverty or the listless emptiness that comes from punching a
time clock. There is no subatomic particle which, once discovered and mapped, will
coax a song into giving up its secrets or make the subjunctive verb tense easier to
conjugate. These things are mysteries and they will remain mysteries right to the heart
of them. It is helpful, then, to have people around who are used to mystery [25].
For Wells (and Usher) this is where the humanities have an important role to play:
If you spend a few years wrestling with the idea of society as propounded by Hobbes,
Locke, Mill, Rousseau and Marx, you come away with a better understanding of all the
alternative ways our own society might choose to configure itself, with their attendant
risks. If you study the fur trade in British North America, you learn something lasting
about the contribution of aboriginal Canadians to our politics and economics, and you
begin to understand the behaviour of today’s Canadian businesses a little better. Read
Goethe or Cervantes in the original and you understand things about Germany and
Spain today that Goethe and Cervantes cannot have imagined [25].
It may not even be the case that a humanities education will be useful because it offers a kind of
soft version of applied knowledge: a training in all of those things that you didn’t know would help
you to address particular problems but did—a history of the fur trade as an illuminating perspective
3
For arguments about globalization, see for instance, Timothy Brennan, At Home in the World: Cosmopolitanism
Now [26], Bruce Robbins, Perpetual War: Cosmopolitanism From The Viewpoint Of Violence [27], and Robbins
and Pheng Cheah, Cosmopolitics: Thinking And Feeling Beyond The Nation [28]. For posthumanist interventions in
animal rights debates, see for instance, Cary Wolfe, Zoontologies: The Question Of The Animal [29]. For the
concept of “geological agency”, see Dipesh Chakrabarty, “The Climate of History: Four Theses” [30].
214
on Canadian business, or of political theory on questions about public policy. It can do that, for sure.
Even more fundamentally, and maybe more importantly, by teaching us to be comfortable with
complexity, and by encouraging us to realize that complexity is a central characteristic of our world
rather than something that needs to be reduced out of existence, it can train us to be more genuinely
engaged citizens in a world that is going through extraordinary changes. In doing so, the humanities
will indeed play a vital role in helping us to “come away with a better understanding of all the
alternative ways our own society might choose to configure itself, with their attendant risks”, not just
by exposing us to particular historical theories, options, and experiments, but by enlarging our
imaginations in ways that incline us to think about the sorts of “unapprehended relations” that can
have a more important influence—both positive and negative—than some of the more obvious but
limited aspects of our debates.
Will this knowledge come in handy? Will it have direct application in some lucrative
enterprise? It might well. Stranger things have happened. In the meantime, this sort of
study instills in the student an appreciation for the richness of our human enterprise.
It shows that the way we live is not the way we have always lived, nor is it the way
everyone lives. It demonstrates the role of ideas and the possibility of massive change.
It is harder, having contemplated such things, to go back to a rote existence. Not
impossible, but harder [25].
As we struggle with the challenge of facing up to the problems and possibilities of the future,
this may be the greatest advantage that the humanities have to offer. They can help us to become
intolerant of reductive thinking (though this adds to the importance of resisting unconvincing clichés
about stimulus and innovation in the arguments that we pose on our own behalf). They can encourage
us to think about new innovations in the context of larger questions about their “utility” or “impact”:
who will they help? What might the consequences be? How can these best be addressed? What have
we missed when we fixate on the ideas that do seem important to us? The humanities are very
definitely not the only place on the disciplinary map where this kind of training goes on, but when it
is done well, it plays a vital and in many ways unique role in cultivating this atmosphere of engaged
citizenship in which insisting on the stubborn importance of questions may be as profitable as a
struggle to come up with the sorts of answers that can too easily descend into technical fine-tuning.
Their ability to make us more comfortable with complexity and more focused on the “unapprehended”
implications of the kinds of research that we are prioritizing may even lessen the danger of
“exasperat[ing]...the extremes of luxury and want” that remain stubbornly in place two centuries
after Shelley’s Defense. In a utilitarian age marked by the scramble to embrace “commercially
viable” forms of knowledge, that is a point worth making.
Acknowledgments
I would like to acknowledge the support of the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council
of Canada.
215
Conflicts of Interest
References
1. Adrian Johns. The Nature of the Book: Print and Knowledge in the Making. Chicago, IL: The
University of Chicago Press, 1998.
2. Andrew Piper. Dreaming in Books: The Making of the Bibliographic Imagination in the
Romantic Age. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 2009.
3. Martha Nussbaum. Not For Profit: Why Democracy Needs the Humanities. Princeton, NJ, and
Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2010.
4. Marjorie Perloff. “Crisis in the Humanities.” Electronic Poetry Centre. Available online:
http://epc.buffalo.edu/authors/perloff/articles/crisis.html (accessed on 17 December 2013).
5. Gordon Hunter, and Feisal G. Mohammed. “The Real Humanities Crisis Is Happening at Public
Universities.” New Republic, 6 September 2013. http://www.newrepublic.com/article/114616/
public-universities-hurt-humanities-crisis.
6. Stanley Fish. “The Crisis of the Humanities Officially Arrives.” New York Times,
11 October 2010. Available online: http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/10/11/
the-crisis-of-the-humanities-officially-arrives/?_r=0.
7. Robert Weisbuch. “Six Proposals to Revive the Humanities.” Chronicle of Higher Education,
26 March 1999. https://chronicle.com/article/Six-Proposals-to-Revive-the/34597/.
8. Stefan Collini. “Commentary.” Times Literary Supplement, no. 5563 (2009): 18–19.
9. Anonymous. “Liberal arts and commercial Utility: Editorial.” The Globe and Mail,
6 October 2012.
10. Percy Bysshe Shelley. The Complete Works of Percy Bysshe Shelley. Edited by Roger Ingpen
and Walter E. Peck. London: Ernest Benn; New York, NY: Gordian Press, 1965, vol. 7.
11. Jessica Hume. “NRC to only pursue ‘commercially viable’ science.” Toronto Sun, 7 May 2013.
http://www.torontosun.com/2013/05/07/nrc-to-only-pursue-commercially-viable-science.
12. Anonymous. “Attack on Science Shows Need for New Parliamentary Watchdog: Editorial.”
Toronto Star, 3 December 2013.
13. Stephen Slemon. “President’s Message.” ACCUTE Newsletter, 2013. http://accutecanada.files.
wordpress.com/2013/07/2013-summer-newsletter.pdf.
14. Stefan Collini. What Are Universities For? London: Penguin, 2012.
15. Thomas Docherty. For the University: Democracy and the Future of the Institution. London:
Bloomsbury, 2011.
16. Jonathan Bate. “Introduction.” In The Public Value of the Humanities. Edited by Jonathan Bate.
London: Bloomsbury, 2011.
17. Francis O’Gorman. “Making Meaning: Literary Research in the Twenty-First Century.” In The
Public Value of the Humanities. Edited by Jonathan Bate. London: Bloomsbury, 2011,
pp. 272–82.
216
18. Thomas Love Peacock. “The Four Ages of Poetry.” In Prose of the Romantic Period. Edited by
Carl R. Woodring. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1961.
19. Albert Einstein. Cosmic Religion: With Other Opinions and Aphorisms. New York, NY:
Covici-Friede, 1931.
20. W. H. Auden. “In Memory of W.B. Yeats.” In The Collected Poetry of W.H. Auden. New York,
NY: Random House, 1945.
21. Alex Usher. “Sh*t Humanities Professors Shouldn’t Say.” Higher Education Strategy
Associates, 27 November 2013. http://higheredstrategy.com/sht-humanities-
professors-shouldnt-say/.
22. Max Horkheimer, and Theodore Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment. Translated by John
Cumming. New York, NY: Continuum, 1999.
23. Adam Smith. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Indianapolis, IN:
Liberty Fund, 1981.
24. Alex Usher. “OK, So How Should the Humanities Present Themselves?” Higher Education
Strategy Associates, 2 December 2013. http://higheredstrategy.com/ok-so-how-should-the-
humanities-present-themselves/.
25. Paul Wells. “In Praise of the Squishy Subjects.” Macleans, 2 May 2010.
http://www2.macleans.ca/2010/05/02/in-praise-of-the-squishy-subjects-advocating-for-the-soc
ial-sciences-and-humanities/.
26. Timothy Brennan. At Home in the World: Cosmopolitanism Now. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1970.
27. Bruce Robbins. Perpetual War: Cosmopolitanism from The Viewpoint Of Violence. Durham:
Duke University Press, 2012.
28. Bruce Robbins, and Pheng Cheah. Cosmopolitics: Thinking and Feeling Beyond The Nation.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1998.
29. Cary Wolfe. Zoontologies: The Question of The Animal. Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press, 2003.
30. Dipesh Chakrabarty. “The Climate of History: Four Theses.” Critical Inquiry 35 (2009): 197–
222.
217
Abstract: Every generation faces the same challenge, to engage with the past and to cope with the
present, while building its future. However, the questions and problems inherent in human life remain
the same. It is a given that our society can only progress if we work toward handling ever newly rising
demands in appropriate ways based on what we know and understand in practical and theoretical
terms; but the drumming toward the future cannot be a one-way street. Instead, we have to operate
with a Janus-faced strategy, with one eye kept toward tomorrow, and the other eye toward yesterday.
Culture is, however we want to define it, always a composite of many different elements. Here I
argue that if one takes out the past as the foundation of culture, one endangers the further development
of culture at large and becomes victim of an overarching and controlling master narrative. This
article does not insist on the past being the absolute conditio sine qua non in all our activities, but it
suggests that the metaphorical ship of our cultural existence will not operate successfully without an
anchor, the past. I will illustrate this claim with reference to some examples from medieval literature,
philosophy, and religion as they potentially impact our present in multiple fashions.
Reprinted from Humanities. Cite as: Classen, A. The Challenges of the Humanities, Past, Present,
and Future: Why the Middle Ages Mean So Much for Us Today and Tomorrow. Humanities 2014,
3, 1–18.
One of the critical questions which medievalists face above all pertains to the foundation of their
own discipline and its relevance in the modern world. By the same token, of course, many other
cultural historians, to cast the net as widely as possible, find themselves in the same boat because as
time moves on, each new generation turns away from the past in order to find its own path toward the
future. When I studied history in the late 1970s and 1980s, I met many peers for whom 1789, or the
French Revolution, was the absolutely earliest starting point of anything having any relevance for
us today. I am afraid that this time limit has moved by now up to 1945, or to the end of the Second
World War. And we will have to wait only a few years until the next generation might use 1989, the
fall of the Berlin Wall, or the Iraq War since 2003 (until 2011) as the exclusively relevant marker for
their own historical time frame. In other words, the issue is highly relative and fluent, yet the basic
concern never changes and needs to be addressed constantly again because the importance of past
ideas for the present does not go away, except that the attention and interest by the present generation
is fading. Literature departments at North American universities tend not to shy away from cutting
positions located in the premodern world, and replacing them with new ones dealing with film,
minority literature, immigration issues, or business and marketing strategies. The situation,
unfortunately, might be even worse in the U.K., in the southern European countries, and probably
218
also in the northern countries. I cannot address the case of Asian, African, South-American, or
Australian countries.
It is, however, fully understandable and logical in a certain sense that the past, a very broad and
nebulous term by itself, does not necessarily carry relevance for the future generations at first sight.
There must be some direct connections, some intercultural significance, otherwise we might compare
apples with oranges and throw in anything smacking of history without explaining why we need to
learn about previous periods, literature, philosophy, or art works in order to cope with our lives in a
well-informed, efficient, and comprehensive manner.
Granted, any history can be of interest, and the more exotic it is, the better for some people who
pursue it as a hobby, but not as an epistemological instrument to understand oneself or the society we
live in. Yet then we run into the typically postmodern problem that we increasingly will be at a loss
how to justify the teaching of history at a time of shrinking resources, and soon enough history as a
school subject, at least a history extending prior to 1989 or 1945, might no longer be offered, becoming
another victim of the ever-growing corporatization of our education system that seems to prefer
future customers as its “end-products” instead of cultured and informed individuals. With history here
I mean to include all aspects of historical culture, such as literature, religion, art history, philosophy,
and the like.
Moreover, history in itself is a vast and complex field, and the more one enters into details,
the more the study of a specific period grows and expands, almost to an infinitude. For example,
Europeans still tend to mock at the short time span of the U.S. history of a little more than two
hundred years by now, considering that they themselves can look back to at least two thousand years
and more. However, the U.S. history has been vital for the entire western world, and it has been
highly complex, so there is no shortage of valuable, relevant, and significant aspects pertaining to
that subject matter which continues to have a deep impact on our daily lives, as we discuss, for
instance, the proper interpretation of the Constitution or the Bill of Rights. U.S. students might have
to study U.S. history just as long as they would need, for instance, with respect to the entire European
Middle Ages (ca. 500 to ca. 1500), depending on the approach pursued.
Actually, the North American culture must be divided into a pre- and a post-colonial period,
which immediately takes us back to 1492. In other words, both the European and the American
continent are directly linked in historical terms, insofar as the fundamental changes of the European
economy and the political system from the sixteenth century onward strongly depended on the
impact of the Americas, and the arrival of the European settlers changed the political landscape of the
New World for good.
One could even argue, and this with good justification, that the U.S. history is actually deeply
grounded in the enormously rich history of the native people of North America, extending as far back
as at least four thousand years [1,2]. Considering the Southwest (Arizona, New Mexico, and Southern
California), for example, we would have to include first the history of the missionary activities by the
Jesuits [3], then the truly medieval history of the ancient people in that region who have left
numerous ruins behind, especially all over Arizona and New Mexico, and finally the history of their
predecessors, especially the Cochise, Hohokam, Anasazi, Sinaguas, and Mogollon, some of whom
219
had built, as we have learned only recently, huge irrigation channels and had developed an elaborate
culture a very long time before the first white settlers appeared in that region [4,5].
All those aspects might seem far-fetched and irrelevant for European readers today, but they
demonstrate that the latter cannot simply pride themselves of being heirs of the most important culture
in the world, an observation which no longer needs to be commented on since postmodernity.
Moreover, the Jesuits, above all, maintained since the late seventeenth century an intensive
communication network between both continents and delivered extensive information about the
so-called Pimería Alta to their superiors, friends, and families. We know, for instance, of the Swiss
Jesuit missionary Philipp Segesser (1689–1762), who left behind an extensive correspondence, and
also shipped a considerable quantity of objects he had collected in the New World back home [6].
The founding father of the Jesuit mission was, of course, Padre Eusebio Kino (1645–1711), but I do
not want to trace the entire history of Jesuit missionary activities in the Sonoran Desert here. All
these remarks only serve to stress how much our approach to history can be relativized, and that the
importance of specific aspects of this or that history can be debated from many different perspectives,
depending on the vested interests by the targeted audience and the scholars involved. In other words,
(post)modernity is not necessarily the only criteria when we want to investigate human culture.
All this boils down to the fundamental concern, once again, how much the past matters for the
present and our future. Only a historical perspective can appropriately alert us to the presence of a
master narrative that might dominate, or manipulate, our thinking and mentality until today, not
allowing minority voices and alternative ideas come to the fore [7]. Of course, for many scholars
in the Humanities this would be tantamount to carrying coals to Newcastle since we have been
struggling with this concern for a long time, but this does not exempt us from studying as carefully as
possible the implications and corollaries of past cultures for us today once again. History matters,
and without an awareness of the past the foundation upon which we will build the future might be
rather shaky. I will exemplify my approach to this question below with examples selected from
medieval literature, philosophy, and religion.
It is very possible, of course, that the public would not simply accept our claims and refer us
quickly to the huge problems which our world faces today: the need for more or renewable energy,
sufficient food supply for an ever growing world population, the dangers of global climate change,
gender equality, or rather, the lack thereof, immigration issues, medical health care issues, world
conflicts among the Muslim populations and the war between Eastern terrorist groups and the
Western world, etc. The study of the past has apparently not much to do with those huge concerns.
Or does it, after all? We live today by what our predecessors created for us, and the value system
of the past continues to shape our thinking and frame of mind. The battle cries of the medieval
crusades are, tragically, not forgotten in certain quarters, and hatred and revenge for past injustices
and violence continue to incite radicals all over the world. Fortunately, the most fundamental
question that immediately arises does not have to be addressed here since otherwise we would
re-invent the wheel at a time when we might be close to abandon the metaphorical vehicle altogether
and discover futuristic modes of transportation without wheels. This pertains to the role and function
of the Humanities at large, which do not, of course, answer any of those questions and do not work
toward the goal, for instance, of discovering new ways how to produce more and better food [8]. Yet,
220
our world would not be what it is without literature, history, religion, art history, philosophy, etc.
Undoubtedly, we cannot live without food, but an existence perhaps protected in material terms but
void of ideas would not be worth the term we call it by [9]. Oddly, Robert G. Bednarik polemically
argues that the humanities “have no utility; they exist purely for their own sake” ([10], p. 70). He
suggests that the humanities should learn from the science and submit under the refutability concept,
but he seems to dream of a return of nineteenth-century positivism, and this at a time of postmodernity
when even the foundations of sciences have become unstable. After all, the Humanities do not
necessarily deal with so-called “facts,” but with human issues which can be conditioned by facts, or
interact with facts, but really address non-material aspects. There are facts, of course, in the history
of literature, arts, religion, and philosophy, but the critical issues in the Humanities pertain to the
discourse about ideas, concepts, and, above all, values. These are established not through inheritance
or logical deductions, but through the engagement with the past and the present in a constructive
conversation.
A sleuth of excellent studies has taken up the question recently what the Humanities really mean
and how they fit into our society, because it addresses also the very core of the school and university
system all over the world. In brief, Humanities scholars (perhaps, of course, because they might have
vested interests) have argued, virtually in unison, that human society consists of more than material
possessions and requires the Humanities as an academic discipline to deal with everything else in
human life beyond the physical dimension [11–15].
Already Tacitus had emphasized that the ultimate purpose of history is to learn about virtuous
individuals, and hence about virtues, that is, as we would call it today, ethics and morality, two aspects
that we can never inherit from our parents and must learn anew in each individual’s life [16]. Even
though Friedrich Nietzsche had warned us of too much history, that is, of an excessive absolutization
of past events and people to the detriment of our understanding of the present and the future, he also
reached the insight, in Georg Simmel’s terms, of life being both past and future. Martin Heidegger
developed this further and claimed that human life is really part of an ever forward marching
temporality at one and the same time [17,18]. In other words, we live in a time-space continuum that
thrives because of its double perspectives, looking backward and forward at the same time, and in
order to maintain the harmonious balance, we just cannot afford to neglect the historical dimension
which could be compared, so to speak, with the genetic code of all living existence. Life then
represents the evolution of that genetic material, even if that does not happen necessarily in a
progressive fashion.
One of the more critical areas in the Humanities that are under attack today, at least within the
universities, though not so much in the public, proves to be the study of the Middle Ages, whereas the
Classics seem to continue enjoying, even politically, a high degree of respect, perhaps because all the
founding fathers of the U.S., among many others, were thoroughly trained in that field. In fact, with
regard to the Middle Ages we observe a curious divergence because the interest in things medieval,
as manifested in medieval fares, medieval movies, medieval tournaments (see the Society for
Creative Anachronism or Medieval Fairs), medieval castles, medieval weapons, and so forth, is growing
in leaps and bounds, and this already for several decades now. In many ways American popular
culture, for instance, is deeply grounded in the glorification and idealization of the mythical King
221
Arthur, the famous Round Table, the sword Excalibur, and many other aspects and objects pertaining
to courtly society [19,20]. In many ways, the Middle Ages appear as a world in which aura and
charisma, but then also the ideal of honor were still more or less intact, thus providing material for
modern dreams about true human values lost in the capitalistic humdrum of modern life [21].
By contrast, the interest in studying the Middle Ages in a serious, scholarly fashion, which
would imply acquiring the necessary linguistic competence (Latin, medieval vernaculars), learning
the historical and religious background, then also studying the philosophical treatises and scientific
tracts, or exploring the history of medieval art, is shrinking quite rapidly, and the laments by medieval
scholars about this decline all over the world are loud and clear [22–24]. But such problems are
challenges to be tackled in a constructive way, and the subsequent part of this paper will outline some
strategies and concepts allowing us to confirm, once again, how much the critical study of the past in
general terms can only buttress the analysis of the present, and hence lay the foundation for the
future. As a side note, students of Classics have to work hard as well to acquire the necessary tools,
but within the academia this field seems to enjoy a higher respect than the Middle Ages, which might
seem to be more like a play thing for the decision makers than a serious subject matter.
Curiously, despite huge difficulties everywhere, perhaps mostly coming from the administrative
side where enrollment figures matter the most, medieval research is booming, and the output of new
critical studies on the Middle Ages is truly astounding. Scholars flock to the major medieval
conferences, and journals focused on the medieval past are thriving [25]. Increasingly scholars have
energetically argued that many aspects determining the Middle Ages can easily prove to be model
cases for the exploration of our present and future, such as the concept of the nation, or rather, the
absence thereof, the engagement with representatives of foreign cultures and religions, the approach
to nature (ecocriticism) [26], and the understanding of Europe in the past as a model for the Europe of
the future, without real borders and grounded in a shared Latinate or oral-vernacular culture [27].
When medievalists discuss the phenomena of identity formation, difference as cultural practice,
transgressing of borders as a creative process, and of cosmopolitanism, they draw from medieval
situations, but really probe universal issues pertaining to all people, thus bring together past and
present in a most productive manner [28,29]. Multilingualism and the exchange of cultures are not
exclusively modern aspects, but were already intensively negotiated throughout the entire premodern
world. The current discourse on immigration, amazingly perhaps for modernists, proves to be nothing
but the continuation of a long tradition, even if some of the social and religious parameters have
changed requiring a modulation and adaptation of the instruments dealing with those issues [30,31].
This is not to deny the strong alterity of the Middle Ages, but every stage of our past falls into that
category, including the Classics. In the Western world, for instance, there is a very strong trend to
concentrate on medieval Europe, instead of medieval Japan or China, simply because of direct lines
connecting that world with us. We certainly need to demonstrate, as Marcus Bull has called it,
“respect for the extraordinary diversity of human experience” ([32], p. 5), and the Middle Ages
represent, simply put, one of many significant facets of human life in the past. We need many of
those facets to understand who we really are today and where we have come from. After all, to follow
Bull to the very end of his argument, alterity is an essential component of all human cultures, both
222
past and present, and to study the Middle Ages alerts us to the very nature of ourselves, but seen
through a historical lens ([32], p. 141).
Although the Greek philosopher Heraclit had formulated that no one can ever step into the same
river twice since everything keeps flowing and nothing stays the same, neither the river itself with its
riverbed and water nor the person trying to cross the river. This applies to us as well, being the avatars
of the past. Considering how much scholars are examining and studying the history of everyday life, of
gender relationships, the history of generational conflicts, of racism and homophobia, for instance,
and taking into account such critical issues such as the relationship between orality and literacy,
the exploration of the senses and desires, we can fathom how much the past altogether, at least the
European Middle Ages, has become much closer to us than ever before. We still notice clearly
marked differences in social, economic, religious, and philosophical terms (e.g., feudalism versus
democracy, a manuscript culture versus a print and a computerized culture), but we recognize, as the
result of ongoing research, more strongly than perhaps ever before how much we as modern people
have been shaped and influenced by our medieval past, and hence have evolved on the basis of our
predecessors, sometimes hundreds of years or almost a millennium ago [33].
Simon Gikandi recently made the excellent observation that some, if not many, of the most
important literary and social critics of the twentieth century had been exiles, and that their exile had,
perhaps not so unexpectedly, provided them with an important platform from which they were much
more empowered to view their world back home than those who had stayed without being completely
integrated into their new country or culture. “It is in the works of the exiles of the twentieth century
that one can discover literary criticism functioning as a project of the human subject outside nation,
outside the imperium of humanism, in the place of the other, in the language of the other. Confronted
with the abyss presented by slavery, genocide, or the violence of empire, writers and critics would
seek refuge in the house of criticism” ([34], p. 522).
In a curious but far-reaching analogy, we can identify the past also as an exile, even if a temporary
and voluntary one only for the scholar and reader turned critic. By studying literary and historical
texts from the Middle Ages, for instance, we transplant ourselves for a short time into a different
mind-set, a different culture, language, religion, and social context and thus gain an outside perspective
from the past to the present. However, just as in the case of a modern exile, the observable difference
is not so huge as to destroy all bridges to the own self and the home culture. As much as the exiles
wrote about their own identity and the culture of the world left behind (see already Ovid, or the
medieval heroic figure of Dietrich) [35], as much the cultural historian can transpose him/herself
into the past and thus gain a new vantage point through which the modern world can be viewed in a
new light.
Referring to the South African writer and author Es’kia Mphahlele, Gikandi insightfully notes,
which certainly applies to our current reflections in a metaphorical sense: “exile, which would appear
to many people to be the name and logic of homelessness, was the instrument of one’s self-alienation.
And this self-alienation was connected to a powerful ideal of freedom” ([34], p. 525). Turning to
Medieval Studies, we would certainly not need to search for political freedom, but it proves to be
refreshing and illuminating to build a distance to the paradigm of our modern world in order to grasp
truly what is going on today, now seen through the lens of the past. Or, in Gikandi’s words, the
223
historical ‘exile’ facilitates criticism as “a conduit outside systems of domination” ([34], p. 526).
Critics of the modern world are best qualified if they have a thorough understanding of the past and
can pinpoint the roots of specific phenomena determining the present world.
Of course, we in the West live in democracies, but the emergence of this type of government
happened not too long ago and there are still many countries in the world where democracy either does
not exist or is even adamantly opposed. Moreover, there is no absolute guarantee that we can maintain
the democratic system in the future; hence it remains absolutely mandatory to remember how the entire
process and intellectual discourse was set in motion in the past to reach us today. Intriguingly, the
entire issue of the power relationship between a king/ruler and the people was already of central
concern for such medieval thinkers as John of Salisbury (ca. 1120–1180), William of Ockham
(ca. 1285–1347), or Marsiglio da Padua (ca 1275–ca. 1342) ([36,37]; [38], pp. 296–308). We would
not necessarily have to rely on their insights to gain an understanding of the theoretical implications
of a ruler assuming too much power to the detriment of the people, but if we want to comprehend the
historical discourse about the proper relationship between God and a ruler, and then the people,
which takes us directly to our own western-style democracies, the voices of these two medieval
philosophers certainly deserve to be listened to, and this still in 2013 and well beyond [39].
Both in practical and theoretical terms I have over the years investigated how to innovate Medieval
Studies for the modern student generation and how to bring medieval texts to life again [40,41]. To
meet my own needs, I have recently created a new textbook, which is now available already in its
second revised edition [42]. Beginning with Boethius’s Consolation of Philosophy (ca. 525), this
book provides a large selection of relevant texts which all hail from the Middle Ages and invite
critical readings and epistemological challenges insofar as they contain, as I would contend,
profound, timeless messages about human problems, concerns, ideals, fears, aggressions, and other
notions and hence prove to be of greatest significance for the modern discourse about those very
same issues.
Following, I will briefly touch on some of the most fascinating texts and outline in shortest terms
possible what kind of message can be found contained in them in order to illustrate how texts from
the late antiquity through the entire Middle Ages, for instance, can serve to provide important material
for our discourse on universal concerns and problems. Boethius, for instance, probes the question
what constitutes mis/fortune and surprisingly reaches the insight that there is no real misfortune
because humans do not own anything really, not even their own bodies and health. Everything is on a
loan, so to speak, from fortune, which can take that health away any time. True happiness rests much
more deeply in the natural instinct toward the good, which explains why so-called evil people in
reality are not fully evil, but rather blind and weak and cannot even move on their own toward the
natural goal of merging with Goodness or the Godhead; hence the more evil things they commit, the
more they eliminate themselves and actually deserve pity and commiseration.
In the Old High German “Song of Hildebrand” (ca. 820), we encounter a warrior father in direct
confrontation with his son who assumes that Hildebrand died already a long time ago. Lack of
communication and a bitter adherence to traditional feudal values ultimately terminate their feeble
attempts at establishing a communication; finally weapons replace their words, and although this
short epic poem ends in a fragment, we can safely assume that tragedy strikes both men, either the
224
father killing his son, or the other way around, or both murdering the other. Here, as in so many other
cases, we can recognize how much literary texts prove to be platforms for the exploration of
communication, a fundamental concern for people of all times [43].
In Gautier de Coinci’s “Our Lady’s Tumbler” (ca. 1220–1230) a very simple man, who had been
allowed to join a monastery, desperately tries to find his own way of worshiping God. Being illiterate
and unlearned, he cannot participate in any of the monks’ rituals and ceremonies, but he eventually
discovers the quiet crypt where he can resort to his own skills, tumbling, and thus he establishes an
intensive though highly idiosyncratic service in honor of the Virgin Mary who graces him, in a vision
which only the abbot and another monk secretly observe, with her appearance. Leaving the strongly
Catholic aspect aside, what matters for us the most here is the realization that the humble tumbler,
deeply filled with his idealism and belief, does not allow the other monks, in their learnedness and
cultivation, to sidetrack him, although he is very afraid of their criticism. Although he does not know
how to venerate the Virgin Mary according to the monastic norms and conventions, he proves to be
more devout than the entire community, obviously being more passionate and pious than them,
clearly demonstrated by the vision, even though he himself is not aware of it. As Gautier clearly
signals, transcending all cultural barriers, true idealism and passion cannot be stifled or suppressed,
while learning and cultural rituals carry the danger of turning into rote and empty ceremonies.
The timeless value and importance of the Lais by Marie de France (ca. 1170–ca. 1200) and of the
theoretical writings by Christine de Pizan (ca. 1364–ca. 1429), especially about her struggle to
defend women and to argue for their independence, are so well known by now that we do not need
to discuss these two authors. However, it is still worth pointing out how much both created texts
that deeply appeal to modern-day readers for a variety of reasons. As Sharon Kinoshita and Peggy
McCracken emphasize in the conclusion of their monograph on Marie, “in our time she is
remembered as one of the most important authors of the Middle Ages” ([44], p. 218). As to Christine
de Pizan, Nadia Margolis concludes how much this amazing and highly prolific writer continues
to appeal to a wide range of audience, especially today, serving now even as a “feminist-cultural
icon” ([45], p. 156).
Even with regard to the question of possible toleration and tolerance medieval writers had much
to contribute, as recent research has uncovered, although we might want to reserve the emergence
of the latter notion more for the eighteenth century [46,47]. Famous theologians and philosophers,
poets and historians could be mentioned here who all contributed, in one way or the other, to the
development of this arduous and thorny path, such as Peter Abelard, Ramon Llull, Marsilio Ficino,
or Giovanni Pico della Mirandola. Tolerance by itself proves to be a complex issue and represents the
results of an ongoing discourse over the centuries, representing an ideal that we today in the West
would like to uphold, though it is more than self-evident how fragile this ideal can be. Insofar as we
are part of and contributors to that discourse, which deeply impacts us on a daily basis, it certainly
behooves us, in order to further and accentuate that discourse, to listen to the past voices and pay
attention to their concerns, troubles, and struggles in that regard.
As the current Dalai Lama has insightfully formulated, our world can only progress and reach
a constructive future if we embrace compassion, tolerance, justice, inner values, i.e., spirituality, and
ethical and moral ideals [48]. All these elements identify a highly developed and civilized society,
225
but they are very hard to achieve and then to maintain; so the struggle for them goes on.
Understanding, however, how they at first emerged and then gradually developed throughout the
Middle Ages and beyond, strongly contributes to continued promotion of such values. Humanity is
covered by only a very thin veneer of positive ideals, aimed at collaboration, support, empathy, and
love, so just a tiny spark can rip off that veneer and throw a whole society into the abyss of chaos and
violence, whether we think of the conditions in Kosovo from 1998 to 1999 or in Egypt in 2013.
This also applies to the probably most important aspect of human existence, the experience of
love. But love is not simply a passion, deeply driven by hormones and other chemicals; instead it
reflects on the spiritual side of our lives and also needs to be informed by ethical values (love is
commitment, communication, compromise, collaboration, compassion, and community). This finds
an excellent expression in the courtly verse narrative “Der arme Heinrich” (Poor Henry) by the
Middle High German poet Hartmann von Aue (fl. ca. 1170–ca. 1200) [49]. The protagonist contracts
leprosy and faces certain death, since there was no medical treatment of this sickness. A medical
doctor in Salerno (near Naples) tells him, however, that if he could find a young, nubile woman
willing to die for him, her blood would help him to recover—clearly a narrative motif borrowed from
miracle stories and fairy tales, hence completely unrealistic, as the protagonist realizes himself since
he despairs when he has learned of that advice and retires to a farm to await his certain death.
Years pass, when he finally reveals to the farmer and his family what the doctor had told him. In
the meantime, one of the daughters had obviously fallen in love with Heinrich, and now decides to
sacrifice herself for him. Her arguments defending her determination to give her heart blood for the
young nobleman prove to be so convincing that everyone believes that the Holy Spirit must have
spoken through her. The sick prince and the girl travel to Salerno and the doctor then prepares the
operation, when Heinrich hears the sound of the sharpening of the knife. Curious and concerned, he
gazes through a hole in the wall and suddenly recognizes who that girl really is. He virtually faces an
apparition within the operation room, recognizing the absolute beauty of the naked female body,
while he realizes his own physical and spiritual ugliness. Thereupon Heinrich immediately changes
his heart and suddenly accepts God’s will, now being ready to die and to spare the girl’s life.
Although the latter bitterly fights against the changing of the plans, since she had hoped to gain
fast access to heaven and thuys to avoid all the problems of adult life here on earth, the male
protagonist remains firm and returns home with her. In that moment God acknowledges Heinrich’s
transformation into a humble person and a good Christian and so lets him become well again. At the
end the prince marries the farmer’s daughter, which makes a good happy end. We must, of course,
apply an allegorical, if not anagogical, reading to this story to make sense of it, otherwise it would
have to be regarded as a naive and sentimental religious tale of little relevance. If we understand the
girl to represent Heinrich’s soul, and his leprosy as an expression of the turn away from his spiritual
self, then the healing and ultimate marriage constitute the reunification of body and soul and the
recovery of human life in spiritual terms [50].
Our reading, which solves a profound crux in Hartmann research, illustrates how much a literary
text, from the past or the present, is empowered, to use Paul Ricoeur’s words, “to transcend its own
psycho-sociological conditions of production and thereby to open itself to an unlimited series of
readings, themselves situated in socio-cultural contexts which are always different” ([51], p. 91). In
226
other words, medieval texts might certainly carry more meaning for us today than modern literature,
which is not to reject the latter as a centrally important medium of the cultural ideals and values of
our own times. We can use Hartmann’s narrative exceedingly well to explore the body-mind relationship
and to fathom strategies how to overcome the blindness which the physical existence tends to impose
on us in epistemological terms.
After all, the protagonist resorts to gazing and discovers a way for him to look inside, an
extraordinarily useful metaphor for our attempts to gain spirituality or to connect with our inner self,
truly a significant epiphany [52]. Not surprisingly, Dante’s Divina Commedia has proven to be
as meaningful today as the poems by Walther von der Vogelweide or the plays by William
Shakespeare. They all represent powerful and meaningful voices about the soul’s quest, not the only
ones to the exclusion of their modern counterparts, but strong voices in the same huge choir called
Humanities.
The world would be different today if St. Francis of Assisi (ca. 1181–1226) had not stepped forward
and had preached to his audiences, developing innovative ideas about true spirituality in practical
terms. Undoubtedly, his messages of humbleness, peacefulness, and love transcend all cultures and
periods until today, irrespective of his complete submission under the Catholic Church [53,54]. Most
uniquely, he went so far as to advocated for a “species equality as opposed to speciesism; that is, the
equality of all beings as part of God’s creation, instead of a strictly anthropomorphic and hierarchical
worldview of inherent human superiority” ([55], p. 43). In a way, we might call him an ecocritic
avant la lettre, pursuing a “theistic, ecocentric environmental ethic, or more commonly creation
spirituality” ([55], p. 44). Even though Francis was not a biologist or environmentalist in the modern
sense of the term, he certainly created the principles of spiritual ecology and biophilism, perceiving
the natural world as the closest we can get to experience God [56]. His soft voice from the early
thirteenth century powerfully resonates with us until today and promises to stay with us because
of his profound messages that continue to serve us exceedingly well to transcend the material
confinements of our existence.
I would like to conclude with some remarks on the profound and universally relevant sermons and
treatises by the German philosopher and mystic (?) Meister Eckhart (ca. 1260–1327/1238), who has
fascinated religious scholars, philosophers, and literary researchers ever since [57]. As Dermot
Moran urges us to consider, “Eckhart has to be read as both belonging to and radically renewing the
tradition of negative theological writers that runs from Proclus and Dionysius through Johannes
Scottus Eriugena, Maimonides, Albertus Magnus, and subsequently goes on to Nicholas of Cusa. At
the same time, as a Parisian academic and a Dominican theologian, Eckhart absorbed and in many
ways reinterpreted the central tenets of the new Aristotelian philosophy of being promulgated by
Thomas Aquinas and other neo-Aristotelians in the Paris Arts Faculty” ([58], pp. 675–76).
In fact, postmodern literary theory would not be completely understandable without recognizing
the influence which Eckhart exerted, for instance, on Georges Batailles, Jacques Derrida, and
others [59], and this particularly because of his teachings on apophaticism, the human inability to
speak about God ([60], pp. 35, 38–39, 116).
There are many debates as to whether Meister Eckhart was a mystic [61], or simply a theologian
and philosopher ([62], pp. 465–84). For our context it only matters that his thoughts excited both his
227
contemporaries and his posterity until today, here disregarding his vehement critics. In his Talks of
Instruction (ca. 1300), for instance, we come across a host of amazing thoughts and ideas that
naturally provoked the traditional Church and ultimately caused the Pope John XXII to condemn this
teacher as a heretic on March 27, 1329 [63].
Considering how much Eckhart insists on pursuing a free mind, but this in a religious sense, we
can easily recognize why representatives of Eastern religions have recognized a kindred spirit in him.
He defines the free mind as “one which is untroubled and unfettered by anything, which has not
bound its best part to any particular manner of being or devotion and which does not seek its own
interest in anything but is always immersed in God’s most precious will” ([64], p. 5). The individual
ought to strive toward the unification with the Godhead by way of abandoning the self as much as
possible. Relying on the own self-will removes the hope for peace, hence the only possible first step
to achieve illumination would consist of taking leave of oneself and also of the material existence;
this then would pave the way toward the encounter with God ([63], p. 6).
Most critically, the individual must detach from him/herself ([63], p. 8) in order to allow God to
enter the soul. Quite similarly to St. Francis, Eckhart also emphasizes that God is to be found in all
things since He consists of the entire material existence as His external manifestation ([63], p. 9). The
true believer needs to turn inside and neglect the outside wherever s/he goes because God is to be
found “in the heart, in an inner motion of the spirit towards him and striving for him, and not just in
thinking about him always and in the same way” ([63], p. 10). Looking for external solitude would
not help unless the individual has found inner solitude: “We must learn to break through things and to
grasp God in them, allowing him to take form in us powerfully and essentially” ([63], p. 11).
With a good will, virtually everything can be achieved, and those things one wants are closer to
the individual than objects that might be lying in the lap but are not wanted ([63], p. 15). That will,
however, must not have selfhood and must have gone out of itself. Nevertheless, even the greatest
ecstasy and experience of the Godhead in one self would be only secondary compared to a
demonstration of true love toward another person, poor and suffering ([63], p. 17). After all, as
Eckhart emphasizes, “whenever we give up what we desire for God’s sake, be it something physical
or spiritual, we will find it again in God just as if we had actually possessed it and had given it up for
God” ([63], p. 18; [64]). In a way, Heinrich in Hartmann’s narrative had already demonstrated the
meaning of Eckhart’s teachings because only when he had given up on his own will, that is, his desire
to get well, and submitted himself completely under God, did he get well. In Eckhart’s words:
“nothing makes us true so much as the giving up of our will” ([63], p. 19). Selfhood blinds the
individual and makes it impossible for the Godhead to enter the soul ([63], p. 21). He admonishes his
audience not to try to imitate Christ in concrete terms, but spirituality a. because it would be impossible
for him to do so, and b. because God wants our love more than our works ([63], p. 30). We might
recognize here a kind of anticipation of Martin Luther’s teachings, but then we could also perceive in
Eckhart’s teachings universal insights deeply shared by Hinduists and Buddhists [65,66].
Virtue emerges as one of the central principles which the devout individual ought to strive
for “ceaselessly until we attain the essence and ground of virtue” ([63], p. 41). In practice this means:
“We must train ourselves in self-abandonment until we retain nothing of our own. All turbulence and
unrest comes from self-will, whether we realize it or not. We should establish ourselves, together
228
with all that is ours and all that we might wish or desire in all things, in the best and most precious
will of God through pure ceasing-to-be of our will and desire” ([63], p. 42). Surprisingly, we can
discover strong similarities in the comments even by modern representatives of Buddhism, so when
the current Dalai Lama remarks: “the inner motivational dimension is the most important aspect of
ethics. For when our motivation is pure, genuinely directed toward the benefit of others, our actions
will naturally tend to be ethically sound” ([48], p. 71). What ultimately matters, as he underscores, is
that we have a shared value system and deeply care about the world altogether, not just about the own
self, community, or country ([48], pp. 84–85).
This paper, however, is not just about Meister Eckhart, Christine de Pizan, or the Dalai Lama, so it
must suffice what we have plucked from the major treatise by this Franciscan teacher in order to
reach our conclusion as to the meaning and relevance of the past for the present and future. It would
be hard, if not impossible, to contradict the messages provided by any one of them, after all, since
they addressed the human condition in a most intriguing and far-reaching manner that matters for us
as well. For instance, Boethius’s teachings about mis/fortune and goodness carry as much meaning
and relevance as those by Gautier de Coinci and Marie de France, each in his/her own terms and respects.
Human existence in the Middle Ages already faced all the fundamental concerns and problems
as we do, but the framework was different, especially with a much stronger belief system and trust
in spirituality. Insofar as we can detect toleration, but not quite tolerance, some acceptance of
foreigners or representatives of other religions, but not integration, we can recognize significant
connection between them and us.
The warnings about the disastrous consequences of interminable blood feud and revenge, as
formulated in the anonymous Nibelungenlied (ca. 1200), might have a direct bearing on the conflict
between the various Islamic groups in the Middle East, between Protestants and Catholics in
Northern Ireland, and Muslims and Hindus in Pakistan and India respectively, although I honestly
question whether any of those involved in the terrible bloodshed in the name of his or her God might
have heard of this heroic epic or would even care about its messages. However, the distance should
not concern us here, and the lack of interest by the moderns in the past should not frustrate us,
because human existence is subject to a continuous flow from the past to the present and beyond, and
the task of the Humanities is to work toward the goal to keep the voices from the past present and
alive, irrespective of all the senseless killings all over the world.
The most painful analogy would be the eternal flame burning at Hiroshima as a reminder of the
nuclear attack on August 6, 1945. Tragically, the nuclear arm race fully developed only afterwards,
and the hope for a dismantling of these nuclear bombs seems rather dim even now; yet, the flame
keeps burning, and there has not been any other nuclear attack ever since. We might even say that the
Humanities are all about hope, which is anchored in the past and reaches out to the future. As human
beings we are entitled to succeed and to suffer, as Sir Gawain does in the alliterative romance Sir
Gawain and the Green Knight (ca. 1350–1380), but we cannot give up hope and must rather go
through a period of despair and frustration than to abandon our goal, as many medieval poets were
able to teach us ([67], pp. 144–46).
This flow of history—and I deliberately do not use the term “progress”—is deeply determined by
past individual voices that raised their concerns and offered ideas, probing the relationship between
229
body and mind, spirit and God, self and nature, and the individual versus society. The Humanities are
not looking for truths in material terms, as Bednarik assumes, and their purpose cannot, in fact,
should not, be the search for truth as the sciences probably do correctly because they do not deal with
the same kind of facts but with values, ideals, dreams, hopes, anxieties, desires, and imagination ([10],
p. 71). Those who call for making the Humanities more credible according to the criteria determining
the sciences [10] pursue a utilitarian approach, which would certainly be acceptable for the sciences,
but completely misses the essential task of the Humanities.
In the Humanities, by contrast, we are on a quest, probing what the many different voices from
past and present have to say and how they resonate with our own ideals and needs. Of course, there is
never a simple formula to translate medieval observations, for instance, into concrete recommendations
or recipes for our lives today. Instead, we encounter a world of metaphors, allegories, symbols,
images, and allusions that invite us to go on our own quest, but now armed and strengthened with the
insights by those before us who have already learned how to handle situations, how to think about
conditions, or how to draw from experiences in order to cope successfully in spiritual, ethical, moral,
and religious terms. Moreover, the failures of the past are equally important lessons, and literary
texts, for instance, regularly reflect on disasters, miscommunication, aggression, and hostility. We
need those as sample cases how to work through such difficulties and to recover our spiritual and
social self.
The present could be compared with a children’s choir, while the past resonates with us like an
adults’ choir (with no values attached to those terms). As we know from practical experiences, if both
choirs join forces, the musical sensation proves to be phenomenal. Past voices are not simply passé,
they just sound differently. In this regard Meister Eckhart’s comments only need to be rendered into
a language that we can understand today better in order to become highly meaningful and relevant for
us to reach the future. Dante’s deep concern at the beginning of his Divina Commedia about where to
go in this life and his sense of being at a loss in the middle of a metaphorical forest lends a voice to
our own need to forge our path through the wilderness, which is a profoundly epistemological task of
which literature reports systematically [68].
We also might want to use the metaphor of the past as a distant land with many treasures. We can
no longer live there, but just like exiles, we must travel there from time to time to regain our
objectivity, to rebuild the own self, to learn anew about ourselves, God, and the world. We cannot
stay in the past, of course, as the Romantics liked to do or as fantasy/history novel writers prefer, but
drawing from past insights proves to be tantamount to having the essential key to the storehouse of
the collective human experiences predicated on values and ideals. We need those altogether for the
establishment and maintenance of our existence, today and tomorrow, otherwise we undermine our
traditional claim on being members of the human community which is determined by the Janus-face,
as mentioned above.
Presentism is a short-sightedness both toward the past and the future, but fortunately the current
situation at schools and universities globally still affirms that we are not yet trapped in such an
epistemological prison, although we can notice worrisome trends as a result of constantly reduced
budgets and intellectual battles aimed against the study of the past [69]. Some years ago Louise
Cowan made the very valid claim regarding “The Necessity of the Classics,” postulating most
230
passionately: “What is needed is to recapture their spirit of high nobility and magnanimity, of order
and excellence, but to recapture that spirit in a framework of democracy engendered by a Biblical
culture of radical openness. The things worth preserving, the things we ought to be passing down, far
transcend any single heritage: they partake of the fundamental structures of being itself” ([70], p. 11).
By analogy, we can claim the same for the Middle Ages as a time in which heroic values and
ideals, religious spirituality, the experience of physical love, and the quest for the Arthurian dream
were intensively pursued and experimented with. That quest, significantly, has not ended yet, and
actually constitutes part of what makes us human, both then and today (and we do not have to limit
ourselves at all to the world of King Arthur and the courts). As primitive and simple-minded the
tumbler in Gautier de Coinci’s Marian miracle tale appears to be at first sight, he truly demonstrates
what it means to pursue one’s deepest dreams and to throw the weight of one’s whole existence
behind it in order to realize what at first seems impossible.
Today, when virtually everything can be bought, everything has a price tag, and no profound
struggles await the modern individual, as it still was in the case of Beowulf, Siegfried (Nibelungenlied)
or El Cid, banality and triviality set in, and the mundane dominates everything, and this although
there is no shortage of tremendous tasks, heroic deeds, and model behavior [71].
The past is going to stay with us, but it is up to us to decide how to approach and utilize it in the
best way possible. We can, for example, simply dismiss it as irrelevant and unimportant in face of all
the tasks and problems facing the modern world. But we can also accept it as a dimension of the
universal human experience from which we never should divorce ourselves; otherwise we would cut
off one of our own legs, that is, our intellectual, spiritual, philosophical, literary, and artistic home.
The whispering from Boethius to Sebastian Brant (1494, The Ship of Fools), from the Merovingian
Queen Dhuoda to fifteenth-century Christine de Pizan continues to reverberate in our ears and minds
and help us to figure out the labyrinthine passage through this life: Lucky an individual or a society
that can draw from the past as the storehouse of everything that came before us and created the
framework in which our present existence evolves and aims for the future. Cutting ourselves off from
the past, however delimited, would constitute an act of intellectual suicide.
Conflicts of Interest
References
1. Jake Page. In the Hands of the Great Spirit: The 20,000-Year History of American Indians.
New York: Free Press, 2003.
2. Susan A. Miller, and James Riding In, eds. Native Historians Write Back: Decolonizing
American Indian History. Lubbock, TX: Texas Tech University Press, 2011; the number of
related studies is legion.
3. Albrecht Classen. Early History of the Southwest through the Eyes of German-Speaking Jesuit
Missionaries: A Transcultural Experience in the Eighteenth Century. Lanham, MD, Boulder,
CO, et al.: Lexington Books, 2013.
231
4. Laurie D. Webster, and Maxine McBrinn, eds. Handbook of North American Indians:
Southwest. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution, 1979, vol. 9. Available online:
http://www.frommers.com/destinations/arizona/0211020044.html (accessed on 18 August 2013).
5. Maxine E. Mcbrinn, and Laurie D. Webster, eds. Archaeology without Borders: Contact,
Commerce, and Change in the U.S. Southwest and Northwestern Mexico. Boulder, CO:
University Press of Colorado; Chihuahua [Mexico]: Conaculta/INAH, 2008.
6. The Letters of the Swiss Jesuit Missionary Philipp Segesser (1689–1762): An Eyewitness to the
Settlement of Eighteenth-Century Sonora (Pimería Alta). Edited and translated by Albrecht
Classen. Arizona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies, Occasional Series, 5. Tempe:
Arizona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies, 2012.
7. Judith M. Bennett. History Matters: Patriarchy and the Challenge of Feminism. Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 2006, p. 53.
8. Ted Underwood. Why Literary Periods Mattered: Historical Contrast and the Prestige of
English Studies. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2013.
9. Albrecht Classen. “Humanities—To Be Or Not To Be, That Is the Question.” Humanities 1
(2012): 54–61. http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/1/1/54.
10. Robert G. Bednarik. “Rendering Humanities Sustainable.” Humanities 1 (2012): 64–71.
http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/1/1/64.
11. Stefan Collini. What Are Universities For? London: Penguin, 2012.
12. Thorstein Veblen. The Higher Learning in America: A Memorandum on the Conduct of
Universities by Businessmen. New York: Huebsch, 1918.
13. Martha Nussbaum. Not for Profit: Why Democracy Needs the Humanities. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2010.
14. Past, Present and Future: The Public Value of Humanities and Social Sciences. London: British
Academy, 2010.
15. Frederick Luis Aldama. Why the Humanities Matter: A Commonsense Approach. Austin:
University of Texas Press, 2008.
16. Gordon Wright. “History as a moral science.” American Historical Review 81, no. 1 (1976): 1–
11. http://www.historians.org/info/AHA_History/gwright.htm.
17. Mark Sinclair. “Nietzsche and the problem of history.” Richmond Journal of Philosophy 8
(2004): 18–23.
18. John Zilcosky. “Modern monuments: T. S. Eliot, Nietzsche, and the problem of history.”
Journal of Modern Literature 29, no. 1 (2005): 21–33.
19. Andrew E. Mathis. The King Arthur Myth in Modern American Literature. Jefferson, NC;
London: McFarland, 2002.
20. Michael N. Salda. Arthurian Animation: A Study of Cartoon Camelots on Film and Television.
Jefferson, NC; London: McFarland, 2013.
21. C. Stephen Jaeger. Enchantment: On Charisma and the Sublime in the Arts of the West.
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2012.
22. Profession. New York: The Modern Language Association of America, 2012.
232
23. William D. Paden, ed. The Future of the Middle Ages: Medieval Literature in the 1990s.
Gainesville, Tallahassee, et al.: University Press of Florida, 1994.
24. Roger Dahood, ed. The Future of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance: Problems, Trends, and
Opportunities for Research. Arizona Studies in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance, 2.
Turnhout: Brepols, 1998.
25. Albrecht Classen, ed. Handbook of Medieval Studies: Terms—Methods—Trends. Berlin and
New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2010, vol. 3.
26. Connie Scarborough. Inscribing the Environment: Ecocritical Approaches to Medieval Spanish
Literature. Fundamentals of Medieval and Early Modern Culture 13. Berlin and Boston:
De Gruyter, 2013.
27. Ernst Robert Curtius. European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages. Translated from the
German by Willard R. Trask. Bollingen Series, XXXVI. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1990. Originally published in 1948.
28. Michael Borgolte, Julia Dücker, Marcel Müllerburg, and Bernd Schneidmüller, eds. Integration
und Desintegration der Kulturen im europäischen Mittelalter. Europa im Mittelalter, 18. Berlin:
Akademie Verlag, 2011.
29. John M. Ganim, and Shayne Aaron Legassie, eds. Cosmopolitanism and the Middle Ages. The
New Middle Ages. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013.
30. Albrecht Classen, eds. East Meets West in the Middle Ages and the Early Modern Time:
Transcultural Experiences in the Premodern World. Fundamentals of Medieval and Early
Modern Culture, 14. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter, 2013.
31. Mark Amsler. Affective Literacies: Writing and Multilingualism in the Late Middle Ages. Late
Medieval and Early Modern Studies, 19. Turnhout: Brepols, 2011.
32. Marcus Bull. Thinking Medieval: An Introduction to the Study of the Middle Ages. Houndmills,
Basingstoke, Hampshire, and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005.
33. Johannes Fried. “Geschichte als historische Anthropologie.” In Geschichte des Mittelalters für
unsere Zeit: Erträge des Kongresses des Verbandes der Geschichtslehrer Deutschlands
“Geschichte des Mittelalters im Geschichtsunterricht” Quedlinburg 20.-23. Oktober 1999.
Edited by Rolf Ballof. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 2003, pp. 63–85.
34. Simon Gikandi. “In the house of criticism.” PMLA 128, no. 3 (2013): 521–29.
35. Albrecht Classen. “The experience of exile in medieval German heroic poetry.” Medieval
German Textrelations: Translations, Editions, and Studies (Kalamazoo Paper 2010–2011).
Edited by Sibylle Jefferis. Göppinger Arbeiten zur Germanistik, 765. Göppingen: Kümmerle,
2012, pp. 83–110.
36. G.R. Evans. Fifty Key Medieval Thinkers. London and New York: Routledge, 2002.
37. Cary J. Nederman. John of Salisbury. Medieval and Renaissance Texts and Studies, 288.
Tempe, AZ: Arizona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies, 2005.
38. John Marenbon. Medieval Philosophy: An Historical and Philosophical Introduction. London
and New York: Routledge, 2007.
233
39. Albrecht Classen. “The People Rise Up against the Tyrants in the Courtly World: John of
Salisbury’s Policraticus, the Fables by Marie de France and the anonymous Mai und Beaflor.”
Neohelicon 35, no. 1 (2008): 17–29.
40. Medieval German Voices in the 21st Century. The Paradigmatic Function of Medieval German
Studies for German Studies. A Collection of Essays, Edited by Albrecht Classen. Internationale
Forschungen zur Allgemeinen und Vergleichenden Literaturwissenschaft, 46. Amsterdam-Atlanta:
Rodopi, 2000.
41. Albrecht Classen. “The quest for knowledge within medieval literary discourse: The
metaphysical and philosophical meaning of love.” Words of Love and Love of Words in the
Middle Ages and the Renaissance. Edited by Albrecht Classen. Medieval and Renaissance Texts
and Studies, 347. Tempe: Arizona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies, 2008,
pp. 1–51.
42. Albrecht Classen, ed. Medieval Answers to Modern Problems. San Diego: Cognella, 2013.
Originally published in 2012.
43. Albrecht Classen. Verzweiflung und Hoffnung. Die Suche nach der kommunikativen
Gemeinschaft in der deutschen Literatur des Mittelalters. Beihefte zur Mediaevistik,
1. Frankfurt am Main, Berlin, et al.: Peter Lang, 2002.
44. Sharon Kinoshita, and Peggy McCracken. Marie de France: A Critical Companion. Gallica,
24. Cambridge: D. S. Brewer, 2013.
45. Nadia Margolis. An Introduction to Christine de Pizan. Gainesville, Tallahassee, et al.:
University Press of Florida, 2011.
46. Cary J. Nederman. Worlds of Difference: European Discourses of Toleration c. 1100–c. 1550.
University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2000.
47. Wege zur Toleranz: Geschichte einer europäischen Idee in Quellen. Edited, introduced and
commented by Heinrich Schmidinger. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 2002.
48. His Holiness the Dalai Lama. Beyond Religion: Ethics for a Whole World. Boston: Houghton
Mifflin Harcourt, 2011.
49. A Companion to the Works of Hartmann von Aue. Edited by Francis G. Gentry. Studies in
German Literature, Linguistics, and Culture. Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2005.
50. Albrecht Classen. “Utopian Space in the Countryside: Love and Marriage Between a Knight and
a Peasant Girl in Medieval German Literature. Hartmann von Aue’s Der arme Heinrich,
Anonymous, ‘Dis ist von dem Heselin,’ Walther von der Vogelweide, Oswald von Wolkenstein,
and Late-Medieval Popular Poetry.” In Rural Space in the Middle Ages and Early Modern Age:
The Spatial Turn in Premodern Studies. Edited by Albrecht Classen, with the collaboration of
Christopher R. Clason. Fundamentals of Medieval and Early Modern Culture, 9. Berlin and
New York: De Gruyter, 2012, pp. 251–79.
51. Paul Ricoeur. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences. Translated by John B. Thompson.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
52. Dana E. Stewart. The Arrow of Love: Optics, Gender, and Subjectivity in Medieval Love Poetry.
Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press; London: Associated University Presses, 2010.
234
53. André Vauchez. Francis of Assisi: The Life and Afterlife of a Medieval Saint. Translated by
Michael F. Cusato. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2012.
54. Michael J. P. Robson, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Francis of Assisi. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2012.
55. Leslie E. Sponsel. Spiritual Ecology: A Quiet Revolution. Santa Barbara, CA, Denver, CO, and
Oxford, England: Praeger, 2012.
56. Leonardo Boff. “All the Cardinal Ecological Virtus: St. Francis of Assisi.” In Cry of the Earth,
Cry of the Poor. Translated by Philip Berryman. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1997,
pp. 203–20.
57. Jeremiah M. Hackett, ed. A Companion to Meister Eckhart. Brill’s Companions to the Christian
Tradition, 36. Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2013.
58. Dermot Moran. “Meister Eckhart in 20th-Century Philosophy.” In A Companion to Meister
Eckhart. Edited by Jeremiah M. Hackett. Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2013, pp. 669–98.
59. Ilse N. Bulhof, and Laurens Ten Kate, eds. Flight of the Gods: Philosophical Perspectives on
Negative Theology. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy, 11. New York: Fordham University
Press, 2000.
60. Bruce Holsinger. The Premodern Condition: Medievalism and the Making of Theory. Chicago
and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2005.
61. Richard J. Woods. Meister Eckhart: Master of Mystics. New York: Continuum, 2011.
62. Kurt Flasch. Das philosophische Denken im Mittelalter: Von Augustin zu Machiavelli, 3rd ed.
Stuttgart: Reclam, 2013. Originally published in 1986.
63. Albrecht Classen. “Meister Eckhart’s Philosophy in the Twenty-First Century.” Mystical
Quarterly XXIX, no. 1–2 (2003): 6–23.
64. Meister Eckhart. Selected Writings. Selected and Translated by Oliver Davies. London:
Penguin, 1994.
65. Louis Roy. Mystical Consciousness: Western Perspectives and Dialogue with Japanese
Thinkers. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2003.
66. Reiner Schürmann. Wandering Joy: Meister Eckhart’s Mystical Philosophy. Translated from
the German by Reiner Schürmann. Great Barrington, MA: Lindisfarne Books, 2001.
67. Flo Keyes. The Literature of Hope in the Middle Ages and Today: Connections in Medieval
Romance, Modern Fantasy, and Science Fiction. Jefferson, NC, and London: McFarland, 2006.
68. Umberto Eco. Six Walks in the Fictional Woods. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994.
69. John A. McCarthy, and Katrin Schneider, eds. The Future of Germanistik in the USA: Changing
Our Prospects. Vanderbilt: Department of Germanic and Slavic Languages, 1996.
70. Louise Cowan. “The necessity of the classics.” The Intercollegiate Review 37, no. 1 (2001): 3–
11.
71. Albrecht Classen. “Friends and friendship in heroic epics: With a focus on Beowulf, Chanson de
Roland, the Nibelungenlied, and Njal’s Saga.” Neohelicon 38, no. 1 (2011): 121–39.
MDPI AG
Klybeckstrasse 64
4057 Basel, Switzerland
Tel. +41 61 683 77 34
Fax +41 61 302 89 18
http://www.mdpi.com/