Carbon Trading: Unethical, Unjust and Ineffective?

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 35

Carbon trading: unethical, unjust and

ineffective?
Simon Caney and Cameron Hepburn
June 2011
Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy
Working Paper No. 59
Grantham Research Institute on Climate Change and
the Environment
Working Paper No. 49

1
The Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy (CCCEP) was established
by the University of Leeds and the London School of Economics and Political
Science in 2008 to advance public and private action on climate change through
innovative, rigorous research. The Centre is funded by the UK Economic and Social
Research Council and has five inter-linked research programmes:
1. Developing climate science and economics
2. Climate change governance for a new global deal
3. Adaptation to climate change and human development
4. Governments, markets and climate change mitigation
5. The Munich Re Programme - Evaluating the economics of climate risks and
opportunities in the insurance sector

More information about the Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy can be
found at: http://www.cccep.ac.uk.

The Grantham Research Institute on Climate Change and the Environment was
established by the London School of Economics and Political Science in 2008 to
bring together international expertise on economics, finance, geography, the
environment, international development and political economy to create a world-
leading centre for policy-relevant research and training in climate change and the
environment. The Institute is funded by the Grantham Foundation for the Protection
of the Environment, and has five research programmes:
1. Use of climate science in decision-making
2. Mitigation of climate change (including the roles of carbon markets and low-
carbon technologies)
3. Impacts of, and adaptation to, climate change, and its effects on development
4. Governance of climate change
5. Management of forests and ecosystems

More information about the Grantham Research Institute on Climate Change and the
Environment can be found at: http://www.lse.ac.uk/grantham.

This working paper is intended to stimulate discussion within the research community
and among users of research, and its content may have been submitted for
publication in academic journals. It has been reviewed by at least one internal referee
before publication. The views expressed in this paper represent those of the
author(s) and do not necessarily represent those of the host institutions or funders.

2
CARBON TRADING: UNETHICAL, UNJUST AND INEFFECTIVE?

Simon Caney a and Cameron Hepburnb*


a
Department of Politics and International Relations, University of Oxford,
and Magdalen College, Oxford, UK
b
Grantham Research Institute and CCCEP, London School of Economics and Political Science,
New College and Smith School, Oxford, UK

21st April 2011

_____________________________________________________________________
Abstract

Cap-and-trade systems for greenhouse gas emissions are an important part of the climate
change policies of the EU, Japan, New Zealand, among others, as well as China (soon)
and Australia (potentially). However, concerns have been raised on a variety of ethical
grounds about the use of markets to reduce emissions. For example, some people worry
that emissions trading allows the wealthy to evade their responsibilities. Others are
concerned that it puts a price on the natural environment. Concerns have also been
raised about the distributional justice of emissions trading. Finally, some commentators
have questioned the actual effectiveness of emissions trading in reducing emissions. This
paper considers these three categories of objections — ethics, justice and effectiveness
— through the lens of moral philosophy and economics. It is concluded that only the
objections based on distributional justice can be sustained. This points to reform of the
carbon market system, rather than its elimination.

Keywords: carbon markets, emissions trading, ethics, justice, efficiency,


commodification, carbon pricing, climate change

_____________________________________________________________________
* Corresponding author. E-mail address: [email protected]
We are grateful to David Frame for helpful discussions and to Timmons Roberts and Henry Shue for their
very instructive comments on the paper presented by Caney at the ‘Commodifying Carbon’ Conference
(Oxford, 16 July 2007); to Dale Jamieson and participants the Environmental Studies Research Seminar at
New York University for comments on the paper presented by Hepburn on 21 April 2009; to members of
the Royal Institute of Philosophy for comments on the paper presented by Hepburn on 11 February 2010;
and to Luc Bovens, John Broome, and David Wiggins for their written comments. We are also grateful to
Wilfred Beckerman, Rufus Black, Simon Dietz, Mike Mason, Dieter Helm, Nicholas Stern and Ed Page for
useful discussions. Caney undertook research on this while holding an ESRC Climate Change Leadership
fellowship and is grateful to the ESRC for its support.

3
1. Introduction
The design of climate-change policy involves underappreciated ethical dimensions.
Greenhouse gas emissions might be reduced by several main approaches, each of which
raise different considerations of ethics and justice. For instance, governments might
provide information about the science and economics of climate change, price
greenhouse gas emissions through a ‘carbon tax’, subsidise clean technology, establish a
‘cap-and-trade scheme’ in which a limit is placed on total emissions which declines over
time (e.g. as per notions of ‘contraction and convergence’), and/or implement
‘command-and-control’ regulation requiring firms and individuals to take certain action,
such using specific cleaner technologies. These approaches have various levels of
effectiveness (that is, of successfully reducing emissions) and of efficiency (in terms of
reducing emissions at least cost). They also have distributional implications (in that there
will inevitably be losers and winners). Implementing climate-change policies is also likely
to, and indeed will need to, change our relationship with the natural environment.

This paper focuses on cap-and-trade systems, which are argued by some to be a vital
component of the attempt to prevent ‘dangerous anthropogenic forcing’1 and dangerous
temperature increases.2 Indeed, greenhouse gas emissions trading was provided for by
Article 17 of the Kyoto Protocol. 3 Many environmentalists support a cap-and-trade
system because it is the only policy that places an absolute limit on the level of emissions.
This allows emissions to fall over time consistent with the notion of “contraction and
convergence”, for instance. 4 Other policies such as carbon taxes might, with luck,
achieve the same effect of controlling and reducing emissions, but they do not provide
the level of guarantee provided by a cap-and-trade system. Unless emissions are reduced,
moreover, business-as-usual economic activity will increase the concentrations of
greenhouse gases in the atmosphere, leading to temperature increases of perhaps four
degrees Celsius by the end of the century, and serious risks of dangerous changes in
precipitation and climate.

1 United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC): 1992, Article 2, text available at

http://www.unfccc.int.
2 We focus on carbon dioxide emissions given their sheer volume and contribution to climate change but

we should note, of course, that carbon dioxide is not the only greenhouse gas.
3 Cameron Hepburn, ‘Carbon trading: a review of the Kyoto mechanisms', Annual Review of Environment and

Resources, 32 (2007), 375–393.


4 Aubrey Meyer, ‘Contraction and Convergence: The global solution to climate change’ Schumacher Briefing 5,

2000, Foxhole, UK: Green Books Ltd.

4
Several cap-and-trade systems for greenhouse gases have been implemented around the
world. The most notable is the EU Emissions Trading Scheme (EU ETS), which came
into effect on 1 January 2005 and is now in its second phase (2008-2012). 5 Other
countries are establishing emissions trading, and some countries such as Australia are
engaging in vigorous debates about the merits of emissions trading schemes compared
with other approaches. The USA passed legislation in the House of Representatives
which would cap emissions, with the cap reducing to 80% below 2005 levels by 2050, but
passage of the legislation through the Senate was blocked. China has recently announced
it will pilot carbon trading in five provinces and eight large cities in the coming years.6
Long before the implementation of cap-and-trade systems for reducing greenhouse gas
emissions, there were other kinds of environmental trading schemes. Perhaps the best
known is the trading scheme for sulphur dioxide (SO2) in the USA under Title IV of the
1990 amendments to the Clean Air Act, which has successfully reduced acid rain at low
cost.7

As cap-and-trade systems to limit carbon dioxide pollution have actually been


implemented, so too have criticisms emerged. The most aggressive criticisms of cap-and-
trade emerge from climate-change sceptics, who would prefer to see no government
response to climate change, and who consider cap-and-trade the most likely policy to
succeed in passing through the relevant legislatures. More sober criticisms include
arguments that emissions trading is inherently ethically objectionable. For instance,
Michael Sandel argued that:

“turning pollution into a commodity to be bought and sold removes the


moral stigma that is properly associated with it...[and] may undermine the
sense of shared responsibility that increased global cooperation requires”.8

The merit of such criticisms can depend upon the specific form of emissions trading
under consideration. Trading within a cap-and-trade system could occur between

5 For an overview of the EU ETS see the special issue of Climate Policy, vol.6 no.1 (2006).
6 Global Times, ‘Five provinces, eight cities selected for gas-emission cut off’, 11 August 2010.
http://business.globaltimes.cn/china-economy/2010-08/562368.html
7 Robert N Stavins, ‘What Can We Learn from the Grand Policy Experiment? Lessons from SO2

Allowance Trading’. Journal of Economic Perspectives 12:3 (1998), 69-88.


8 Michael Sandel ‘Should we Buy the Right to Pollute?’ in Public Philosophy: Essays on Morality in Politics

(Cambridge: Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2005), 94 & 95.

5
countries (e.g. as occurs under the Kyoto Protocol), between firms (e.g. as occurs in the
EU ETS), or potentially even between individuals. The implications for the sense of
shared responsibility vary in each case. Furthermore, policy choices about the allocation
of tradable allowances, whether given away to regulated entities for free or else sold,
affect the justice of an emissions trading scheme.

This paper examines various ethical and moral objections to emissions trading. We
examine these considerations in relation to a simple emissions trading scheme (ETS),
rather than with respect to ‘add-on’ policies like carbon offsetting. While carbon offsets
are beyond the ambit of this paper, we simply note here that offsets have two important
moral virtues, — namely minimising waste and transferring climate finance to poorer
countries to help them reduce emissions — but they also face challenges of “asymmetric
information” which opens the way to potential gaming and fraud. By considering its
moral virtues, Section 2 examines why emissions trading might be thought to be a
suitable policy response to climate change. Section 3 reviews and elaborates on a general
taxonomy of ethical reasons for caution in the use of markets, engaging with the
literature on the moral limits to markets. Section 4 employs this taxonomy to assess the
view that carbon trading is unethical. Section 5 examines the notion that carbon trading
may lead to unjust outcomes, and section 6 reviews arguments that carbon trading has
not so far been effective at reducing emissions. Policy implications are suggested in the
conclusion (section 7).

2. The moral virtues of cap-and-trade

2.1 Ensuring environmental protection


Cap-and-trade systems for pollution control can guarantee that pollution will be limited
to the quantity specified by the ‘cap’, if it is suitably enforced.9 The pollution cap is
reduced from one period (often several years) to the next, thereby reducing total
emissions over time. In the EU, for instance, the cap in the 2008-2012 period was set so
that emissions would be reduced by 5% compared with 1990 levels, and the cap for the
next period (2012-2020) has been set to reduce emissions by at least 20% compared with
1990 levels, although the EU commission is currently contemplating tightening the cap

9 Enforcement requires independently verified measurements of emissions (with sensors or flowmeters) or

independent calculations of those emissions based on the measured output produced and its emissions
intensity, coupled with spot checks by verification agencies.

6
to a 30% reduction by 2020, a position which has the support of the United Kingdom,
France and Germany, among others.

In this way, cap-and-trade systems provide policymakers and environmentalists with the
certainty that a given emissions target will be met. Other policies, such as carbon taxes,
subsidies or specific regulations, can make good progress towards reducing emissions,
provided they are designed and enforced appropriately, but do not provide the same
confidence as cap-and-trade systems. Cap-and-trade systems, like taxes, also provide a
price signal. When the total level of emissions (and thus permits allocated) is fixed below
business-as-usual levels, the permits become ‘scarce’ and trade with a positive price.
Regulated entities can trade permits amongst themselves, establishing a ‘carbon price’.
This price fluctuates with time, providing information about whether it is cheaper for
companies to reduce emissions internally, or whether it is cheaper to purchase allowances
from another firm which has reduced its emissions below its allocation.

2.2 Minimising waste


Cap-and-trade schemes therefore ensure that the cheapest short-run sources of
abatement are undertaken first, because firms have an incentive to reduce their emissions
whenever they can do this for less than the market price. There will be many different
ways firms can economise on their emissions. The market price ensures that firms are
rewarded if they do make reductions and penalised if they don’t. Just as the ‘cap’
supports environmental integrity, the ‘trade’ supports minimum cost. This is true too of
carbon taxes, which provides a similar economic incentive for firms to seek out
abatement opportunities in a manner which minimises waste.

In contrast, government will rarely know where the cheapest sources of abatement are to
be found, because opportunities to reduce emissions are often at the operational level of
individual firms. Even if government had access to data on individual operational
decisions (which it generally does not), it would be a mammoth task to attempt to specify
the ‘optimal’ actions for each firm. If government does attempt to do this, it will
doubtless make mistakes. If it doesn’t, and instead applies a uniform regulatory standard,
this is likely to be wasteful, because one firm can often comply more cheaply than
another.

7
To take an example, suppose that firm A and B are both required to reduce emissions by
1 million tonnes of CO2. If firm A can reduce emissions for £10/tonne, while for Firm
B it costs £20/tonne, then £10 million is wasted if trade between Firm A and Firm B is
prevented. These wasted funds might have been used to develop new low-carbon
technologies and products, increased staff wages, been passed onto shareholders or
simply given to charity. Trade creates these benefits by minimising waste.

2.3 Maintaining liberty


A final moral virtue of economic instruments, including both carbon trading and taxes, is
that these policies allow regulated entities (whether countries, firms or individuals) the
liberty to reduce their emissions using the methods they see fit. In the (relatively
unlikely) event that government actually knew more cost-effective ways to reduce
emissions than individuals, there would still be value in allowing individuals to make their
own choices, and indeed to make (and learn from) their own mistakes. Regulatory
approaches which stipulate the specific actions to be taken deny people this liberty and
deny them the creativity to arrive at different and original ways of cutting back on
emissions or other ways which, even if they are more expensive, may be preferred by the
individuals concerned.

There is a further benefit from allowing this liberty. If environmental groups take the
view that the cap is not tight enough, they can purchase allowances and then retire them,
thus preventing firms from using them to pollute. In this way, non-governmental
organisations can voluntarily choose to tighten the cap. Indeed, in the EU ETS this is
precisely what occurs, and there are various non-profit and indeed for-profit
organisations that offer individuals the opportunity to force companies to reduce
emissions by more than the government limits.

3. A general taxonomy
We have seen that moral virtues attach to carbon trading. This is one of the reasons why
legislatures around the world have introduced such systems as a means of controlling
emissions. Yet there are important moral arguments against emissions trading, and in
order to give a comprehensive account of such arguments, we present in this section a
taxonomy of the kinds of reasons that one might have for thinking that certain goods or
services should not be traded. In section 4, we draw on this taxonomy to examine
several different arguments against emissions trading. By doing so we hope to provide as

8
systematic an account as possible of the different reasons one might have for rejecting
emissions trading.

Our taxonomy draws on an account developed by Judith Andre in her instructive analysis

of Michael Walzer’s well known but rather unsystematic discussion of goods that should

not be transferred for money.10 Andre seeks to provide a more rigorous categorisation of

the different kinds of reasons that can be given for thinking that certain burdens or

benefits should not be bought and sold.11 Drawing on her work, we distinguish between

five types of case where trading a benefit or a burden is morally problematic.

First, there are goods which ‘by their nature cannot be owned’.12 Well-known examples

might include love, friendship, respect and admiration.

Second, there are some things that it is possible to own but which we think it would be

wrong to own.13 Again there are well-known examples. It is possible to own human

beings but, of course, we now think that this is an indefensible practice, as this fails to

respect the dignity and moral standing we attach to other human beings.

A third case where a trade in goods or services is problematic arises when it is impossible

to alienate a good or a responsibility.14 First, consider goods. There are goods which a

person can possess but which he or she conceptually cannot transfer to others. An

example would be an honour (such as the Nobel prize).15 This honour belongs to the

person awarded it and she cannot bestow it on someone else. It is not possible to

alienate it. The same can be said of academic qualifications. People can only acquire

these in a certain kind of way. For example, they must have been admitted onto the

10 Michael Walzer Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983), 100-

103.
11 Judith Andre 'Blocked Exchanges: A Taxonomy' in Pluralism, Justice, and Equality (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 1995) edited by David Miller and Michael Walzer, 171-196.
12 Andre 'Blocked Exchanges’, 175: cf 175-176.
13 Andre 'Blocked Exchanges’, 176: cf 176-178
14 Andre 'Blocked Exchanges’, 178-179.
15 Andre 'Blocked Exchanges’, 179.

9
course in question, complied with the regulations, and passed the relevant examinations.

The pedigree matters and this entails that it is not possible simply to transfer the good to

others. Consider now responsibilities: there are some responsibilities which only the

original duty bearer can honour and which it is not possible for others to honour. For a

clear example of this kind of responsibility, suppose that a spouse has a duty of sexual

fidelity to their partner. In such a case, this is a responsibility that they alone can honour.

Compliance with that duty requires that particular person to personally discharge the

duty. They cannot outsource that obligation to others in some way (though others can,

of course, assist them in their performance of the duty).

In addition to the first three categories, there are also cases where it is possible to alienate

a good or a responsibility but we might think that it is wrong to alienate such a benefit or

a burden to other people.16 Again we can distinguish between two cases here. The first is

when someone alienates a responsibility to someone else but we think it is wrong for him

or to do so. Machiavelli, for example, argued that it would be wrong for citizens to

delegate the responsibility to protect their state or fight their wars to others, notably

mercenaries. In his view, citizens should defend the state themselves. 17 Another

example would be someone who seeks to alienate a civic responsibility (like doing jury

service) to someone else. One might think that this is their job: they should do it and

should not pass it on to others. We shall refer to these as ‘non-delegable duties’. These

are duties one can alienate but should not. A second kind of case involves alienating a

‘benefit’. To take one example, some like John Stuart Mill, hold that people should not

be allowed to alienate their own liberty.18 They have inalienable rights. Another case is

voting rights. It is widely held that it is wrong to transfer this benefit to others.19

16 Andre ‘Blocked Exchanges’, 179-180.


17 Machiavelli The Discourses (Middlesex: Penguin, [1531] 1970) edited with an introduction by Bernard
Crick, Book 1, Discourse 43, 218.
18 John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Middlesex: Penguin, (1859) 1974, 173.
19 The case of voting rights has an extra complication for one might think that although it is a benefit to

the citizen it also comes with a duty too (for example, to cast it in the public interest) and that this duty in
part explains why it should not be transferred.

10
Let us turn finally to a fifth category. This fifth type of argument maintains that certain

goods (or responsibilities) should not be alienated for money.20 It does not object to

someone exchanging a good or service but it does object to someone exchanging it for

financial gain. Consider, for example, prostitution. Some, for example, would argue that

whilst there is nothing wrong with having sex per se, and indeed sex as part of a loving

relationship is normally considered to be good, it would be wrong to exchange sexual

favours for money. Some argue along similar lines against commercial surrogate

motherhood.

We can sum up the preceding discussion with the following table.21

Table 1: Arguments against trading certain burdens and benefits


Type Description Illustrative Examples
1 Goods which cannot be owned Love, friendship
2 Goods which should not be owned Persons
3 Goods and responsibilities that cannot be alienated Honours
4 Goods and responsibilities that should not be alienated Civic responsibilities, votes
5 Goods and responsibilities that should not be alienated for money Sex

4. Five ethical arguments against emissions trading


Having presented this taxonomy of the kinds of objections one might make to trading in
general, we now turn to examine the case against trading allowances to emit greenhouse
gases.22 Not all of the categories outlined in the previous section lend themselves to a
critique of emissions trading. In particular, we set aside the first and third type of
argument. There do not seem to be any reasons why one cannot own an emissions
allowance (so the first kind of argument does not apply) and one can easily transfer this
good to others (so the third kind of argument does not apply).

20 Andre ‘Blocked Exchanges’, 180-187.


21 This table captures, we hope, the logical possibilities but it obviously does not describe all the kinds of
issues that might arise under the various headings. For excellent discussion of the kinds of issues that arise
and the relevant normative consideration see Debra Satz, Why Some Things Should Not Be for Sale: The Moral
Limits of Markets (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010).
22 For an excellent discussion of arguments against markets in permits ‘to pollute’ see Robert Goodin

‘Selling Environmental Indulgences’, Kyklos 47:4 (1994 573-596. For a contrary view and response see
Wilfred Beckerman and Joanna Pasek ‘The Morality of Market Mechanisms to Control Pollution’, World
Economy 4:3 (2003), 191-207.

11
We shall therefore focus on arguments 2, 4 and 5. More precisely, we shall consider one
type 2 argument, two type 4 arguments, and two type 5 arguments.

Before beginning the normative analysis it is worth distinguishing between two separate
questions. The first question is whether it is permissible for states and other political
institutions to set up emissions trading schemes. Let us call this the institutional question.
The second question is whether it is ethically appropriate for individuals to buy or sell
emissions permits. Let us call this the individual question. These two questions are
importantly different. One might, for example, argue that it is appropriate for the state
to allow this kind of trading even if one thinks that such trading is immoral. On a liberal
conception of the role of the state, the duty of the state is to treat people justly and
respect their rights. This can include granting persons rights to do things which one
believes to be immoral. For example, one might think – at the institutional level – that
persons should be allowed to sell sexual services for money and yet also think – at the
individual level – that persons ought not do so.

Our concern is primarily with the first type of question. The arguments from
environmental outcomes, waste minimization and liberty give us prima facie reasons to
endorse such a scheme. Our view is quite compatible with the view that persons are
under a moral obligation to reduce their emissions, not to use energy wastefully and
unnecessarily and, more generally to adopt an ethic of frugality of the sort advanced by
David Wiggins in his paper.23 Let us now consider five anti-market arguments to see
whether the reasons in favour of emissions trading can be outweighed.

Argument A: Owning what should not be owned

One argument that might be made against emissions trading is that it involves owning a
kind of good that, while it is possible to own it, should not be owned. 24 Emissions
trading assumes that humans have property rights in the natural world. It might be
argued that this is undesirable. The natural world (or perhaps, more plausibly, particular
features of the natural world like the Earth’s atmosphere) should not be treated as
people’s private property. Anti-commodification arguments are familiar, and in many
cases, have force. For example, as noted above, we surely think that humans should not

23 Wiggins ‘A Reasonable Frugality’ this volume.


24 For this line of reasoning see also Goodin ‘Selling Environmental Indulgences’, 578-579.

12
be owned. However, these types of arguments are unpersuasive in the context of
emissions trading.

One central problem with the argument is that emissions trading does not rely on the
assumption that persons own the atmosphere.25 Emissions trading involves a right to use
up some natural resource but a ‘use right’ is not the same as a ‘property right’.26 An
example might bring out the point. Consider someone who purchases a permit to camp
on a certain plot of land. He or she does not, thereby, gain a private property right in the
land. Rather they have a ‘use right’ – a right to use that piece of land for a fixed period
of time. Emissions permits can be understood in a similar way. They entail a right to
use, for a period of time, a certain proportion of the absorptive capacity of the
atmosphere. After some time (maybe several hundred years in the case of greenhouse
gases) the impact of the emission of greenhouse gases, like the impact of the camper, will
effectively disappear.

Further evidence for the claim that emissions trading does not assume that persons own
the atmosphere can be found once we note that emissions trading is quite compatible
with the idea of stewardship. It is often said that humanity should act as ‘stewards’ or
‘trustees’ of the natural world rather than as private owners of it. 27 The concept of
stewardship or trusteeship (we use the two interchangeably) might be said to include
three components. First, those who are trustees of some particular designated natural
resources may have a right to use that resource (use rights). Second, however, those who
hold the natural resources in trust are not entitled to destroy the natural resources (no
right to destroy). As Tony Honoré notes in his seminal analysis of ownership,28 the right to
destroy is one of the key eleven ‘incidents’ of private property, so this second feature

25 For further discussion see Caney ‘Markets, Morality and Climate Change: What, if anything, is Wrong

with Emissions Trading?', New Political Economy 15:2 (2010), 204-205. See also Caney 'Justice, Morality and
Carbon Trading’, Ragion Pratica 32 (2009) for a discussion of this and other anti-market arguments.
26 Hermann E. Ott and Wolfgang Sachs 'The Ethics of International Emissions Trading' in Ethics, Equity

and International Negotiations on Climate Change (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2002) edited by Luiz Pinguelli-
Rosa and Mohan Munasinghe, 171.
27 For example, Brian Barry writes that “those alive at any time are custodians rather than owners of the

planet, and ought to pass it on in at least no worse shape than they found it in”, ‘Justice Between
Generations’ in Liberty and Justice: Essays in Political Theory Volume 2 (Oxford: Clarendon, 1991), 258. For
discussion of the concepts of ‘stewardship’ and ‘trusteeship’ see Robin Attfield Environmental Ethics
(Cambridge: Polity, 2003) chapter 2 and Attfield The Ethics of the Global Environment (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 1999) chapter 3.
28 Tony Honoré ‘Ownership’ in Making Law Bind: Essays Legal and Philosophical (Oxford: Clarendon Press,

1987), pp.161-192 at 170.

13
distinguishes trusteeship from ownership. A third, and related, component can best be
explicated by using a distinction coined by John Passmore in his seminal Man’s
Responsibility for Nature. Passmore distinguishes between ‘conservation’, which he defines
as “the saving of natural resources for later consumption”29, and ‘preservation’, which he
defines as “the attempt to maintain in their present condition such areas of the earth’s
surface as do not yet bear the obvious marks of man’s handiwork and to protect from
the risk of extinction those species of living beings which man has not yet destroyed”.30
Utilising this distinction one might say that a third aspect of stewardship includes duties
to conserve and/or preserve certain resources and features of the natural world for those
who follow them (duty to conserve or preserve).

Now emissions trading is compatible with this ideal. Someone committed to the ideal of
stewardship may think that we are stewards of Earth’s climate and, therefore, may not
destroy it and indeed must conserve or preserve it for future generations (thereby
complying with the second and third features of ‘stewardship’). However, she may also
quite consistently think that, within limits specified by the duty not to destroy, humans
and non-human animals may use the absorptive capacity of the atmosphere (thereby
conforming to the first feature of stewardship). This requires setting a budget specifying
a safe level of emissions. With this in mind the proponent of a stewardship approach
must then consider what policy instruments – including carbon taxes or emissions
markets or regulations – would best protect this atmosphere. She might then quite
consistently propose an emissions trading scheme for those permissible emissions.
Emissions trading is, thus, not reliant on the private ownership of Earth’s atmosphere
and is fully compatible with a commitment to global stewardship.

Before we turn to consider a second argument against emissions trading we should,


however, note an objection that might be levelled against our response to the first
argument.31 A critic might reply that though we are correct that emissions trading does
not require the ‘ownership rights’ over the natural world, our appeal to ‘use rights’ over
the natural world is not sufficient to exonerate emissions trading, for use rights can be
morally problematic too. Consider, for example, a form of slavery in which persons do

29 John Passmore Man’s Responsibility for Nature: Ecological Problems and Western Traditions (London:
Duckworth, 1974), 73.
30
Passmore Man’s Responsibility for Nature, 101.
31 We are grateful to Luc Bovens for raising this objection.

14
not have full ownership relations over others (and so may not destroy them) but they can
‘use’ those others as they see fit and without their consent. Suppose, for example, that
they can (i) require them to work for no pay and control what they do and when they do
it, and that they can (ii) sell or lend these persons to others for their use. (Let us term
this slavery*.) Consider, similarly, a system of marriage in which men have ‘use rights’
over their wives (and so may have sex with their wives without their consent), and may
(like Michael Henchard in Thomas Hardy’s The Mayor of Casterbridge) sell their wife at an
auction, but may not destroy them (and so strictly speaking does not own them in
Honoré’s sense). (Let us term this marriage*.) It follows from these examples that a
system of ‘use rights’ can be deeply morally unacceptable too.32

In reply: we agree that some kinds of use right are morally indefensible. Clearly slavery*
and marriage* are objectionable. Two points, however, can be made. First, the problem
with both of these institutions is that the ‘use rights’ involved in both slavery* and
marriage* directly violate the fundamental and basic rights that all persons have over
themselves. This explains why these kinds of use rights are morally unacceptable. By
contrast, we see no reason to think that the natural world possesses an analogous right
that would preclude human beings from having use rights over it. To challenge our
position the critic would have to provide an argument that establishes both (i) that
Nature can be a right-holder, and, moreover, (ii) that the rights that it possesses disallow
persons from using it in anyway whatsoever without its consent (whatever that would
mean). This seems to us a tall order and we are unaware of any argument that could
establish this. Second, not only do we lack any reason to deny humans some use rights
over the natural world, we also have positive reason to ascribe such use rights to persons.
To withhold from persons any use rights over the natural world (unlike denying people
use rights over other human beings without the latter’s consent) would have catastrophic
effects. It would deny people the land they need to live on, food to eat, water to drink,
energy for heat and so on. It is, in effect, to call for the end of human life on earth. We,
of course, place a limit on how much persons can use the natural world but see no
reason to withhold from them any use rights at all, and plenty of reason to affirm such
restricted use rights (including use rights over the atmosphere).

32
Note, incidentally, that this argument does not object solely or even primarily to the ‘trading’ of permits.
Rather its concern seems to be with a system which distributes ‘rights to use the atmosphere’ whether or
not they are tradeable.

15
Argument B: Alienating responsibilities that one should perform oneself

Having considered a type 2 argument, and having argued that type 1 and type 3
arguments do not apply to the trading of permits to emit greenhouse gases, let us
consider a type 4 argument. These, recall, maintain that certain goods (such as one’s
liberty or voting rights) and certain responsibilities (such as one’s civic responsibilities)
should not be alienated.

This kind of argument has been applied in a number of different ways to emissions
trading. One common variant of this approach argues that creating a system with
emissions trading is objectionable because it allows people to alienate responsibilities that
it is inappropriate for them to alienate. This argument – what might be termed the
Collective Sacrifice Argument – appeals to what we earlier termed ‘non-delegable duties’. If
we focus on the distribution of emissions within a state, the claim is that each citizen
should ‘do their bit’ and should not delegate their tasks to others. They themselves
should constrain their own emissions and not pay for someone else to lower their
emissions. At the international level, this argument would hold that each state should
shoulder ‘its’ burden and that high-emitting countries should not pay others to discharge
‘their’ duty.33

Note that this argument does not claim that those who purchase permits to emit
greenhouse gases are not making a sacrifice. Clearly they are. The complaint is that they
are not making the right kind of sacrifice. Paying a financial burden is not the way to
discharge one’s duty. One must discharge one’s duty by keeping one’s emissions within a
pre-specified limit.

The idea of a shared sacrifice is a powerful one. However, this argument only has force
against certain kinds of systems of emissions trading.34 For example, if the government

33 Michael Sandel has given this kind of argument. See ‘Should we Buy the Right to Pollute?’, 95. Sandel’s
argument against emissions trading is a part of a more general civic republican concern about the role of
markets and the way they encroach into many domains in human life. See Michael J. Sandel Justice: What’s
the Right Thing to do? (London: Penguin Books, 2009), 84-91 and his discussion of “republican citizenship”
in Sandel ‘What Money Can’t Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets’, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
delivered at Brasenose College, Oxford, May 11 and 12, 1998, 107ff. This is available at:
http://www.tannerlectures.utah.edu/lectures/documents/sandel00.pdf (last accessed on 8 September
2010). See also his first Reith Lecture (‘Markets and Morals’) at
http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/b00kt7rg (last accessed on 8 September 2010).
34 For further discussion see Caney ‘Markets, Morality and Climate Change’, 208.

16
were to allocate permits to individuals and require them to control their own emissions as
a matter of public duty, it would then be problematic to allow some people to pay to be
exempted from this particular sacrifice. This would be akin to having a system of
national military service and then allowing some to pay for others to substitute for them
in discharging their public duty. However, it is crucial to note that emissions trading
schemes do not necessarily have this character. An emissions trading scheme which
allocates permits to firms, who either reduce their emissions or trade with other firms
who have done so, can protect the environment without creating an individual civic
responsibility to reduce emissions. Emissions trading need not involve the creation of
civic duties, only to then allow individuals to escape their own duty by paying a sum of
money. They can instead be a system which does not directly ascribe responsibilities to
reduce emissions to its citizens, but which nevertheless achieves the collective
environmental objective.

At this point a proponent of the Collective Sacrifice Argument may, of course, reply that we
ought to address the challenge of reducing greenhouse gas emissions by creating a system
of civic responsibilities. They might argue that we should adopt the same kind of
approach that is normally adopted during in wartime – one in which there is rationing
and a ban on trading. However, it is far from clear why this is the best way to deal with
emissions reductions. In very many cases we allocate responsibilities to the state rather
than to each individual citizen. For example, we often require government to remove
household waste (rather than call for a system in which everyone takes their own waste
to the rubbish tip) and we expect governments to provide an army to defend us (rather
than have a military force entirely constituted by compulsory national service) and we
then pay for the state to perform these tasks. Furthermore, in other cases, we might rely
on other individuals to perform various tasks (e.g. look after our children). We discharge
our responsibilities by paying the money that is required, rather than personally
performing those responsibilities. But if we accept that kind of reasoning in these other
cases, why should we insist that the task of emissions reduction must not be done in this
kind of way? As Jeremy Waldron writes, “[w]artime conscription – together perhaps
with jury service – is virtually the only example of the state’s discharging its functions by

17
exacting service rather than money from its citizens. Since the dawn of the modern era,
states have relied for the most part on cash rather than in-kind contributions.”35

At this point one final point might be made: a proponent of the Collective Sacrifice
Argument might argue that our analysis of the Collective Sacrifice Argument overlooks an
important distinction between two kinds of case. 36 They might reason as follows.
Consider, first, a case where, say, two agents (A and B) are emitting greenhouse gases and
it is much more expensive for A to reduce emissions than B. In such a case it seems
reasonable to allow A to perform her duty by paying B to reduce emissions on A’s
behalf. Consider, however, a case where A and B both have exactly the same costs of
reducing emissions. Suppose, however, that A does not feel like reducing her emissions
and so would like to pay B instead. This, it might be argued, brings out the moral appeal
of the Collective Sacrifice Argument. When applied to emissions trading, the thought might
be that it is acceptable for a rich western country to pay China to reduce its emissions
more cheaply by switching to more efficient technologies already in use in the west, but
that it would be wrong for a rich western country, because it can’t really be bothered, to
pay the Chinese to reduce emissions by, for instance, not using a technology that
westerners still continue to use.

Two points can be made in reply. First, it is not clear why it would be wrong for
countries to express different attitudes to the way in which they bear their burden of
reducing emissions, provided that all countries do indeed bear this burden. To give an
analogy: consider two neighbours. Why would it be wrong for one to pay the other for
the use of the other’s front drive if the other consents to it and thinks the sum is a
reasonable one? One neighbour no longer has the use of their front drive, and perhaps
would find this inconvenient, but by foregoing the use of one resource (the front drive)
but they simultaneously gain the use of another one (the money) in its stead.

35 Jeremy Waldron, 'Money and Complex Equality' in Pluralism, Justice, and Equality (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1995) edited by David Miller and Michael Walzer, 152. Waldron’s statement may
overstate the exceptional nature of in-kind contributions. The challenge, nonetheless, remains: we need an
argument for the claim that we must discharge our environmental duty in an in-kind form when there are
other possibilities.
36 We are grateful to Luc Bovens for raising the objection presented in this paragraph and the example we

use to illustrate it.

18
Second, it is arguable that this kind of argument, and, moreover, the ‘West v China’
example given above, gains whatever intuitive appeal it has because it invokes separate
extraneous factors – namely the respective wealth of the contracting parties and the
fairness of the distribution of emission permits. That is, it might seem problematic for
the wealthy to pay the poor to forego a good that the wealthy continue to enjoy. It is
noticeable, for example, that the example that Sandel employs to illustrate the Collective
Sacrifice Argument involves a rich family (“[t]he family in the mansion on the hill”) paying
its poorer neighbours to do some work for them.37 This, however, cannot give us reason
to reject emissions trading tout court. Rather it draws our attention rather to ensuring that
there is a fair distribution of resources, including a fair share of emissions permits (an
issue we discuss below in section 5).

Argument C: Emissions trading and the vulnerable

Consider now a third argument. Like the preceding argument it maintains that emissions
trading involves alienating what should not be alienated (a type 4 argument). However,
unlike the previous argument it focuses not on the person buying extra permits but on
those who sell the permits. It maintains that to create a system in which permits to emit
greenhouse gases were traded would allow trades which are disadvantageous to the most
vulnerable and, as such, should not be allowed.

One can distinguish between two versions of this argument, what might be called the
Paternalist Argument and the Unreliable Trustees Argument. The Paternalist Argument maintains
that allowing persons to trade emissions may be undesirable because people will make
poor judgements about their own interests and so they should be protected from
themselves.38 This argument is hard to sustain. Though there may be cases where a
degree of paternalism is justified, it is not at all clear why: (a) we should assume that
adults will make dire choices about their energy needs, and (b) even if they do it is not at
all clear why the value of self-determination would be outweighed here. Furthermore, (c)
the argument has no force against emissions trading between companies, as in the EU
ETS. For paternalism to be justified there must be a case for protecting an actor (in this

37 Sandel ‘Should we Buy the Right to Pollute’, 95. See also Goodin’s discussion of the related, but distinct,
argument that it is wrong to have a scheme that allows “some but not all” to be exempt from some burden
or to enjoy some benefit, ‘Selling Environmental Indulgences’, 584-585. How objectionable we find such
schemes will depend heavily on whether the allocation of the scarce good is fair.
38 James Tobin defends restrictions on trade for this reason: ‘On Limiting the Domain of Inequality’,

Journal of Law and Economics, 13:2 (1970), 266.

19
case, a company) from its own decisions. This can be plausible – in restrictive conditions
– when that actor has an independent moral value and when protecting their well-being
is of great importance and when they are likely to make errors in judgement. However,
companies – unlike persons – do not have fundamental moral status; their importance
stems from their contribution to consumers, owners, shareholders and employees. It is
thus it is hard to see why we should prevent a company from making poor decisions
about how many emissions permits to purchase or sell.39

A more plausible argument is what we have termed the Unreliable Trustees Argument. This
argument runs as follows: there are cases where it is either impossible or undesirable to
allocate permits to emit greenhouse gases to certain groups of people, and we therefore
have reason to create trustees to care for their interests. However, these trustees are
sometimes unreliable (either because they are not motivated to care for those in their
trust or because they are sometimes incompetent). Given this, rather than distribute
money to these unreliable trustees to care for those in their charge (which they might
spend inappropriately) there is a case for placing limits on how the trustees can use the
resources allocated to them.

It may be helpful to give some concrete illustrations of this kind of reasoning. One
example is provided by James Tobin who makes an Unreliable Trustees Argument when he
defends allocating educational vouchers (rather than money) to parents.40 This is a form
of non-tradable good; it can only be used for one purpose and cannot be sold for profit.
The case for vouchers is that these are the best way to ensure that children receive the
goods we want them to receive. Now someone may argue on similar grounds that
emissions trading may be morally problematic in cases where one has to use trustees, but
cannot be sufficiently confident that they will use any permits allocated to them for the
benefit of their charges. Henry Shue appears to endorse this kind of reasoning and
argues that states should not be allowed to sell all of their emission rights because that
would risk harming their citizens. Some emissions, he claims, should be regarded as
“inalienable”.41

39 We are grateful to Luc Bovens for pressing us on this point.


40 James Tobin ‘On Limiting the Domain of Inequality’, p.271. He makes the same point in a discussion of

food vouchers (p.268).


41 See Henry Shue ‘Subsistence Emissions and Luxury Emissions’, Law and Policy 15:1 (1993), 58, and Shue

‘Climate’ in A Companion to Environmental Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001) edited by Dale Jamieson, 455-

20
Note, however, that Shue does not claim that this rules out all emissions trading.42 At
most, it would entail that emissions trading be impermissible where that would jeopardise
vital energy and other needs. It thus does not give us any reason to condemn an
emissions trading scheme in the European community or within states that one can
assume will take a responsible approach to the emissions needs of their own population.
It comes into play only in countries which distribute the emission rights (or the proceeds
of selling emissions rights) in such an egregiously unjust way that interfering with
sovereignty is unwarranted. 43 Thus it might, for example, apply in a regime that
withholds emissions necessary for a decent standard of living from its citizens.44

Argument D: Putting a price on the natural world?

Having considered two type-4 arguments, let us turn now to a type-5 argument. Some
may object to emissions trading on the grounds that it puts a price on carbon dioxide
emissions. They may argue that what is objectionable about emissions trading is not that
it allows people to alienate their responsibilities or exchange benefits, but rather that
emissions trading puts a monetary value on carbon dioxide (and other greenhouse gases).
This, they may object, is an inappropriate attitude to take to the natural world, because its
value simply cannot be captured in monetary terms.

456. This kind of argument is also endorsed by Hyams ‘A Just Response to Climate Change: Personal
Carbon Allowances and the Normal-Functioning Approach’, Journal of Social Philosophy 40:2 (2009), p.244.
See also pp.243-244 for further discussion where Hyams discusses what we term the Paternalism and the
Unreliable Trustee Arguments. Hyams appears to think that Shue’s claims are a paternalistic claim about
whether to prevent individuals from selling their own emission rights. Shue, however, is not discussing
individual carbon permits and rejecting them for being paternalistic. His point rather is about the dangers
of letting states sell all ‘their’ emissions permits, thereby jeopardising the needs of their citizens. See also
Shue ‘Equity and Social Considerations related to Climate Change’, Papers presented at the IPCC Working
Group III Workshop on Equity and Social Considerations Related to Climate Change, Nairobi, Kenya 18-
22 July (1994) especially 389.
42 Shue ‘Subsistence Emissions and Luxury Emissions’, p.58 and ‘Climate’ 455.
43 On the moral limits of state sovereignty see Simon Caney Justice Beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory

(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), chapters 5.


44 What about states that do not deny their subjects the emissions needed for a decent standard of living

but which nonetheless distribute them unjustly? This raises a number of complex issues that we cannot
hope to resolve here. Much depends on factors such as (i) whether emissions trading with this unjust state
improves or worsens the condition of the unjustly treated within that state at all, (ii) whether withholding
trade incentivises the unjust government to engage in reform or whether, by contrast, engaging in trade is a
more effective way of encouraging improvements, and (iii) how much weight we accord to self-
determination as compared with securing an internally just distributions. See, further, Caney Justice Beyond
Borders, chapter 5 and 7.

21
A defender of emissions trading can, however, reply that emissions trading does not
necessarily involve any expression of the value of the natural world. One might, for
example, quite consistently adhere to both of the following tenets:
(a) the natural world is of intrinsic value and its value cannot be captured by
monetary estimates, and
(b) the most efficacious way of protecting the natural world involves setting strict
limits on the extent to which humans emit greenhouse gases and then allocating
the remaining legitimate emissions through the operation of an emissions trading
scheme.

To hold that market mechanisms are an effective way of protecting the natural world
does not entail anything about why the natural world has value. Emissions trading here
is simply a means to an end and is not in any way a statement about why the natural
world has value.45

This point might be put in another way: it is often said (and we endorse the claim) that
political actors should ‘put a price on carbon’. Cap and Trade schemes are obviously one
way (though not the only one) of putting a price on carbon. It is, however, crucially
important to be clear on what this does and does not entail. On the one hand it clearly
entails that to emit a certain quantity of greenhouse gases will cost a certain amount of
money and hence these emissions permits have a price tag. However, putting a price on
(a) emissions permits does not entail putting a price on (b) the protection of the earth’s
atmosphere. Emissions trading schemes, thus, put a price on the use of a certain amount
of the absorptive capacity of the atmosphere; they do not thereby put a price on the
maintenance of a climate that is hospitable to human and non-human life. To give an
analogy one might think that some ancient ruins are of great intrinsic value and therefore
must be protected. And one might think that the best and fairest way of achieving this is
to regulate access to these vulnerable ruins and to charge people if they wish to visit
them. In doing so the scheme will put a price on ‘visiting the ruins’. But by doing so it
does not thereby put a price on ‘the protection of the ruins’. The same is true of
emissions trading schemes. To put a price on one thing (the right to use the atmosphere)
is not to put a price on another thing (the preservation of our climate system).

45 For further discussion see Caney ‘Markets, Morality and Climate Change’, 206.

22
Argument E: Does emissions trading convert what ought to be a fine into a fee?

Let us turn now to a fifth argument against emissions trading. Like the preceding
argument, this argument also makes a type 5 objection. It runs as follows: emissions
trading grants people permission to pollute so long as they pay a financial fee but, so the
argument runs, this is profoundly mistaken. Emitting greenhouse gases is a wrong that
should be fined: it is not something that one should be allowed to do if one pays a fee.
The core idea is nicely captured by Sandel in a short critique of emissions trading. Sandel
writes:
“The distinction between a fine and a fee for despoiling the environment is not
one we should give up too easily. Suppose there were a $100 fine for throwing a
beer can into the Grand Canyon, and a wealthy hiker decided to pay $100 for the
convenience. Would there be nothing wrong in his treating the fine as if it were
simply an expensive dumping charge?” 46

Sandel’s answer is ‘no’. It would be wrong in this case to treat the “fine” as if it were a
“fee”. Similarly it would be wrong for an able bodied person to park in a disabled car
parking space with a view simply to paying the ensuing fine and treating the latter as a
reasonable price to pay for the privilege.47 Sandel then applies this kind of thinking to
greenhouse gas emissions.48 Persons should restrict themselves to a fixed quota and for
any of them to exceed their individual quota is a crime that should be punished with a
fine, not an option which they can pay for (as would be the case with a fee). Let us term
this the Fines/Fee Argument.49

Sandel’s argument is, however, unpersuasive. It applies to cases where an individual act
brings about a wrong (as it does in the hiker case and the car parking case), but it does
not apply to cases where a wrong is only caused by a large number of individual actions
when they hit a certain threshold. Sandel’s claim that it would be wrong for the hiker to
treat the $100 as a fee rather than a fine is plausible. But one cannot move from this
example to conclude that emissions trading is similarly inappropriate. If one individual
throws a single beer can, then she despoils the environment. However, if one individual

46 Sandel ‘Should we Buy the Right to Pollute?’, 94.


47 Sandel ‘Should we Buy the Right to Pollute?’, 95.
48 Sandel ‘Should we Buy the Right to Pollute?’, 94-95. See also Goodin ‘Selling Environmental
Indulgences’, 581-583.
49 For an interesting study of how people may treat what are intended as fines as if they were fees see Uri

Gneezy and Aldo Rustichini’s well-known paper ‘A Fine is a Price’, Journal of Legal Studies 29:1 (2000), 1-17.

23
purchases allowances so that she can emit more than her quota (however that is defined)
then that in itself does not necessarily constitute a wrong if others, in line with the terms
of the transaction, emit correspondingly less than their quota. A system of fees is not
necessarily inappropriate.50 Allowing people to exchange emissions permits for money is
not therefore a case of wrongfully alienating responsibilities for money.

In sum, none of the five ethical arguments against climate change are seen to be
compelling. First, emissions trading does not rely upon the private ownership of Earth’s
atmosphere and is compatible with a commitment to global stewardship. Second, the
Collective Sacrifice Argument is unpersuasive because trading between firms and/or states
can protect the environmental without creating civic duties; environmental goals and
stewardship can be achieved by allocating the responsibility to states, rather than to
individual citizens. The Paternalistic Argument is not applicable to emissions trading
between firms, and there is no particular reason to think it would be persuasive even if
trading took place between individuals. Third, the Unreliable Trustees Argument might
entail that emissions trading be impermissible with corrupt states where this might
jeopardize vital energy and other needs. However, it is not an argument against
emissions trading per se and does not rule out emissions trading such as the EU ETS or
systems in other well-governed countries. Fourth, while emissions trading puts a price
on carbon dioxide emissions, this is not an expression of the value of the natural
environment. Fifth, Sandels’ Fines/Fee Argument is unpersuasive because each individual
tonne of carbon dioxide emitted does not constitute a moral wrong — it is the aggregate
damage that is problematic. An emissions trading or a system of taxes is able to prevent
this damage, without the need to criminalise the activity of emitting and impose a system
of fines.

5. The (distributive) justice of emissions trading


Section 4 considered the five strongest arguments for the claim that it would be
intrinsically objectionable to create a system of emissions trading, and found them to be
relatively weak. However, even if there is nothing intrinsically unethical about trading
emissions permits, this does not necessarily imply that emissions trading will lead to just
outcomes. In this section, we consider the impacts of emissions trading on distributive

50On this point see Caney 'Justice, Morality and Carbon Trading’, 210. This point is also made by Hyams
‘A Just Response to Climate Change’, 243.

24
justice and the distribution of wealth. In focussing on this issue we are not assuming that
distributive justice is the only relevant consideration in determining whether a policy is
just. It is, however, an important consideration and it is the focus of this section.

We start from the assumption that, other things being equal, a more equal distribution of
wealth is preferable to a less equal distribution. In general, market systems have a
tendency at best to perpetuate existing distributions of wealth, and at worst to exacerbate
wealth differences between rich and poor. Market economies involve greater uncertainty
than planned economies, and the skilled and the fortunate are the beneficiaries, while the
unskilled and the unlucky tend to suffer bad outcomes. While market economies tend to
generate aggregate wealth and promote liberty, they can and do lead to highly unequal
outcomes.

As with markets generally, environmental markets should not necessarily be expected to


promote distributive justice or reduce inequality. Other things being equal, one might
therefore expect the move to emissions trading to generate more unequal outcomes.
However, the distributional consequences of an individual ETS are a function of the
specific rules for allocating permits. Indeed, there is no reason in principle for an ETS to
lead to more unequal distribution of wealth. It will depend on how the scheme is
designed. The key point is this: whatever account of distributive justice one favours, the
ETS can be designed to deliver a just outcome, either by specifying the allocation of
permits in line with this favoured principle or by auctioning the permits and then
distributing the revenues in line with this favoured principle.

In practice, two considerations will determine whether an ETS exacerbates or reduces


inequality: first, the impact of increasing the cost of emitting pollution on different
segments of the population and second, the transfers of wealth involved in the sale or
free allocation of emissions allowances.

Controlling pollution directly or indirectly leads to an increase in the cost of pollution so


that individuals and firms produce less of it. The evidence available strongly suggests
that controlling carbon dioxide emissions is regressive, which is to say that the impacts
are worse for low-income households (as a proportion of their income) than high-
income households. This effect can be neutralised or reversed if the policy (whether

25
emissions trading or taxes or otherwise) raises government revenue which is recycled to
compensate poorer households.51 In Australia, for instance, the Garnaut Review notes
that roughly 10 per cent of income is spent on transport fuel, gas and electricity by low-
income households, while high-income households spend only 5 per cent on these
goods. 52 Pricing pollution thus hits poorer people relatively harder. Further, poorer
households often rent, rather than own, their accommodation, which further constrains
their ability to respond by adopting low-emissions substitutes, such as insulation, efficient
space heating, hot water systems and cooking appliances. Similar effects are found in
other countries.

For emissions trading to avoid regressive impacts, allowances must be sold to firms with
a portion of the revenues directed to provide compensation to poorer households. This
compensation could be a function of the costs required to adjust to a low-carbon
economy, or could simply be given to low-income households through the tax system.

In addition to the fact that pollution control increases the price of pollution, a second
consideration is that pollution policies transfer wealth from some individuals to other
individuals, depending upon the particular policy and how it is implemented. For
instance, carbon taxes on industrial firms normally transfer wealth from their
shareholders back to the government. Carbon taxes need not have a regressive effect,
provided the government doesn’t give the funds back to the same firms, or earmark the
funds for particular pet programmes (which often occurs in practice for political
reasons). If funds are used to reform and reduce the burden of taxation on the poor, the
impact of carbon taxes could be progressive. Similarly, auctioned permits under a cap-
and-trade scheme transfer wealth from firms to governments, and again provided these
funds are used sensibly, the effect need not be regressive and could be progressive.

51 On the regressivity of carbon taxes, see James M. Poterba ‘Tax Policy to Combat Global Warming: On

Designing a Carbon Tax’ in Rudiger Dornbusch and James M. Poterba (eds.) Global Warming: Economic
Policy Responses. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1991 and Gilbert E. Metcalf, ‘A Distributional Analysis of
Green Tax Reforms’, National Tax Journal 52 (1999), 665-681. But for the opposite conclusion see Thomas
Sterner, ‘Fuel taxes: An important instrument for climate policy’, Energy Policy 35 (2007), 3194–3202. On
the distributional consequences of command and control policies, see Leonard P. Gianessi, Henry M.
Peskin and Edward N. Wolff ‘The Distributional Effects of Uniform Air Pollution Policy in the United
States’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 93 (1979), 281-301 and David H. Robison, ‘Who Pays for Industrial
Pollution Abatement?’ Review of Economics and Statistics 67 (1985), 702-706.
52 Ross Garnaut, The Garnaut Climate Change Review, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008, ch 16.

26
However, for the most part – for the political reasons discussed above – governments
have not auctioned off permits or used tax revenues for progressive reforms of the tax
system. Rather, as in the EU ETS, the vast majority of “European allowances”, or
EUAs, have been given to firms for free, rather than auctioned. 53 This has created
windfall profits for firms, because (a) the emissions trading scheme creates a price which
increases marginal costs of all units of production, which is often largely passed on to
consumers in the form of higher goods prices, depending on the market structure; but
(b) the firms are given most of the EUAs for free. In other words, marginal costs of
production on all units increase, because firms need to retire a permit for every unit of
production. However, firms (a) pass the cost increase onto consumers in the form of
higher prices, and (b) they are compensated by government for the cost increase by being
granted permits — which are a substantial financial asset — for free. 54 Thus, the EU
ETS has created large-scale wealth transfers from taxpayers to firms, who have reaped
substantial windfall profits. Rather than support suppliers, customers, or employees,
these windfalls have largely been retained by shareholders, who are wealthier than the
average taxpayer. The consequence is that it seems almost certain that the EU ETS has
been significantly regressive. Similarly, in the USA, Parry argues that the free allocation
of permits to industry would be regressive, redistributing income from poorer to richer
households.55

The conclusion is that climate-change policies are likely to create regressive impacts
without other compensatory measures, and the EU ETS is certainly no exception so far.
However, the design of the EU ETS has been improving as policymakers have learned
from their mistakes. For instance, in the third phase of the system (2013-2020), the cap
is much tighter (at least 20% and possibly 30% reductions from 1990 levels), and the
proportion of EUAs sold at auction will increase substantially. However, even with these
effects, it would seem that the EU ETS is likely to remain a regressive way of reducing
emissions, at least until 2020. A policy that puts a price on emissions will only be
progressive if it also raises significant amounts of government revenue to compensate

53 Cameron Hepburn, Michael Grubb,Karsten Neuhoff,Felix Matthes, and Max Tse., ‘Auctioning of EU
ETS Phase II allowances: how and why?’ Climate Policy, 6:1 (2006), 135-158.
54 See Robin Smale, Murray Hartley, Cameron Hepburn, John Ward, and Michael Grubb, ‘The impact of

CO2 emissions trading on firm profits and market prices’, Climate Policy, 6:1 (2006), 31-48 and Cameron
Hepburn, John K.-H. Quah, Robert A. Ritz. ‘Emissions trading and profit-neutral grandfathering’,
Economics Papers 2008-W12, Economics Group, Nuffield College, University of Oxford.
55 Ian W H Parry, 2004. Are emission permits regressive? Journal of Environmental Economics and Management,

47:2, 364-387.

27
low-income households. As this has apparently been too difficult for politicians to
achieve so far, we conclude that emissions trading as currently implemented has had
negative consequences for distributive justice.

6. The effectiveness of cap-and-trade


The effectiveness of any climate-change policy is also an ethical matter. If climate
policies are not able to reduce emissions at the appropriate rate and scale, the risks
imposed upon future generations would likely be considered to contravene
intergenerational justice. Previous experience with cap-and-trade systems has shown that
such systems can make significant contributions to environmental protection, provided
that they are designed and implemented correctly.

6.1 Is cap-and-trade politically feasible?


One critically important question to ask of any proposed climate policy is whether it is
actually politically feasible. Over the last 40 years, climate-change policies have proven
extremely difficult to put in place. Because these policies provide a global public good,
every country, particularly smaller countries, have an incentive to free-ride on others’
efforts. Furthermore, achieving domestic political agreement on tackling climate change
is challenging because there are many powerful losers and relatively few winners (unless
other nations take similar action). Furthermore, the science continues to have important
uncertainties, and the costs are incurred now while the benefits accrue decades and
centuries into the future. Given these perspectives, instead of asking “why has so little
been achieved?”56 some sceptical economists often find it remarkable that any action has
occurred at all, and consider the real puzzle to be why anything at all has been achieved.57

Cap-and-trade systems have the virtue that they are almost the only deliberate climate-
change policy to actually reduce emissions to any significant degree so far.58 Half of the
European economy is subject to the EU ETS, with a revealed price of around €10-
20/tCO2, significantly higher than any other serious direct price signal elsewhere in the
world. Other cap-and-trade schemes include the Regional Greenhouse Gas Initiative in
the north-eastern USA, the Western Climate Initiative in several western USA states and

56 Dieter Helm, 2010. “Climate-change policy: why has so little been achieved?“ in Dieter Helm and
Cameron Hepburn. (eds) The Economics and Politics of Climate Change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
57 Scott Barrett. 2003. Environment and Statecraft, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
58 Greenhouse gas emissions have been reduced by non-deliberate events or policies, such as the recent

recession and the Montreal Protocol on Substances That Deplete the Ozone Layer (1989) to the Vienna
Convention for the Protection of the Ozone Layer (1985).

28
Canadian provinces, and those adopted in the Australian state of New South Wales,
Switzerland, Norway, Japan, New Zealand. As noted above, both China and India have
also recently announced that they will be implementing cap-and-trade systems to reduce
their absolute level of emissions.

The reason why some states and regions have been able to put a price on greenhouse gas
emissions with emissions trading, whereas efforts to date with carbon taxes have not
been as successful, is that cap-and-trade systems are able to garner political support from
a wide spectrum of relevant actors. Environmentalists have supported cap-and-trade
systems because the cap on emissions, which gets tighter over time, is the best method of
securing a good environmental outcome. Industry has supported cap-and-trade ahead of
direct regulation because it is cheaper and minimises the costs of compliance, and
industry prefers cap-and-trade to taxes because, as discussed above, cap-and-trade allows
a proportion of allowances to be given to firms for free. Finally, cap-and-trade systems
have a natural constituency once they are up and running. The industrial firms which
own the permits will see the value of that asset increase as the cap is tightened. Financial
firms who trade the asset also have an interest in rising carbon prices. Unlike a carbon
tax, where there is no strong constituent to support them, cap-and-trade systems have,
rightly or wrongly, found support across a cross-section of environmentalists and
business that make them more politically feasible.

6.2 Defining effectiveness


Only once a system has been implemented can its effectiveness be assessed. The
effectiveness of emissions trading depends on the question which it is intended to
answer. Is emissions trading intended to deliver global emission reductions of over 50%
by 2050, without other policy interventions? Or is emissions trading intended to be part
of a package of climate policies, so that its effectiveness is measured by whether it has
made a sufficiently substantial contribution to reducing emissions?

In addition to measuring effectiveness of emissions trading according to the appropriate


objective, effectiveness must also be measured by reference to a ‘counterfactual’, namely
a baseline scenario describing what would have happened if the emissions trading scheme
had not been introduced. Emissions trading can guarantee a specific limit on emissions,
but it cannot guarantee a specific reduction in emissions compared to business-as-usual,
because business-as-usual emissions are uncertain. For instance, a given emissions target

29
might be achieved not because of emissions trading, but because of a severe economic
recession which caused a fall in business-as-usual emissions. In a recession, economic
activity falls and emissions fall, so the demand for permits could fall to the extent that the
permit price could end up at zero. In such circumstances, it would be difficult to
conclude that the ETS is working to reduce emissions. In contrast, if the price of
emissions allowances is positive, then it follows that emissions trading is probably
reducing emissions. The higher the allowance price, the greater the relative impact of the
emissions trading scheme, and the lower the relative contribution of business-as-usual
changes to reducing emissions.

6.3 Has cap-and-trade reduced emissions?


Cap-and-trade systems have been successfully used in the United States to phase out
leaded gasoline in the 1980s,59 reduce sulphur dioxide (SO2) and nitrogen oxides (NOx)
emissions from power plants from 1995 onwards, 60
and the phase-out of
chlorofluorocarbons (CFCs).61 The leaded gasoline programme achieved environmental
targets with an estimated cost saving of $250 million per annum.62 The SO2 programme
also achieved environmental targets, saving $1 billion per annum compared with the
estimated costs of other regulatory approaches.63

The fact that a particular policy intervention has worked for one environmental problem
does not imply that it will necessarily work for others. Climate change is a particularly
vexing environmental challenge because it is international, intergenerational, based on
complex and uncertain science, and involves almost every aspect of production and
consumption around the world. Many economists express the view that emissions
trading (or some other form of emissions pricing, such as international carbon taxes) is a
necessary but not sufficient component of overall climate-change policy. Other policies
are needed because of the presence of multiple ‘market failures’.

59 Suzi Kerr, and David Maré ‘Efficient Regulation Through Tradeable Permit Markets: The United States

Lead Phasedown’, Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics, University of Maryland. Working
Paper 96-06 (January); Albert L. Nichols, ‘Lead in Gasoline’, in Richard D. Morgenstern, ed., Economic
Analyses at EPA: Assessing Regulatory Impact Resources for the Future, Washington, D.C. 1997, 49-86.
60 A. Denny Ellerman, Paul L. Joskow, Richard Schmalensee Juan-Pablo Montero, and Elizabeth M. Bailey.

(2000), Markets for Clean Air: The US Acid Rain Program, New York, Cambridge University Press.
61 Robert N Stavins, ‘Addressing climate change with a comprehensive US cap-and-trade system’, Oxford

Review of Economic Policy 24:2 (2008), 298-321.


62 Albert L. Nichols, ‘Lead in Gasoline’, 49-86.
63 Carlson, Curtis, Dallas Burtraw, Maureen Cropper, and Karen Palmer. 2000. ‘SO2 Control by

Electric Utilities: What are the Gains from Trade?’ Journal of Political Economy, 108:6 (2000), 1272-1326.

30
The most significant experiment with cap-and-trade systems for greenhouse gases to date
began with the launch of the EU ETS in 2005. In the first phase of the scheme, from
2005-2007, carbon prices rose to highs of above €30/tCO2 and then crashed to near zero
for most of 2007. Zero prices arose when it became clear in the third and final year of
the phase that that aggregate emissions were well below the number of allowances issued.
This surplus of allowances implied that they were worthless. The period of zero prices in
2007 was problematic for several reasons; most importantly the incentive to continue
reducing emissions was dramatically weakened.

The price collapse was caused by a combination of two things. First, firms actually
reduced their emissions in the first two years of the phase, motivated by high prices in
the 2005 and 2006 period, so that they didn’t need as many allowances in 2007. Second,
regulators handed out too many EUAs in the first place, as a result of uncertainty about
business-as-usual emissions and sustained lobbying by individual firms and EU Member
States for additional allowances. What is the overall balance between these two
considerations? Ellerman and Buchner review the EU ETS over 2005 and 2006, when
emissions were 60 million tonnes (or 3 per cent) below the allocation levels.64 After a
careful econometric analysis, they conclude that, although there is considerable
uncertainty, emissions were probably reduced compared to business-as-usual by 50 to
100 million tCO2 in each of those two years by the EU ETS, amounting to several
percent of total emissions in the scheme. This is a considerable achievement; by
comparison, the entire UK economy (which is partially covered by the EU ETS) emits
around 500 million tCO2 in any given year. This suggests that, even with the manifest
design flaws in the first phase of the EU ETS, and in a system that had zero prices for a
considerable period, significant reductions in emissions compared were achieved
compared to business-as-usual.

More recent analysis supports this view. Anderson and di Maria (2010) find that over the
three trading years of the pilot phase from 2005-2007, total abatement was 247 million
tonnes, or just over 80 million tonnes per year. 65 Consistently, a separate study by

64 Denny Ellerman, and Barbara Buchner. ‘Over-Allocation or Abatement? A Preliminary Analysis of the

EU ETS Based on the 2005–06 Emissions Data’, Environmental and Resource Economics, 41 (2008), 267-287.
65 Barry Anderson and Corrado di Maria. ‘Abatement and allocation in the pilot phase’, Environmental and

Resource Economics, 2010. DOI: 10.1007/s10640-010-9399-9.

31
Delarue et al. (2008) found reductions in the power sector alone of 30-60 million tonnes
in 2005 and 20-35 million tonnes in 2006.66

Indeed, even though the price in the first Phase (from 2005-2007) ultimately did fall to
zero, Ellerman and Buchner (2008) point out that it is unsurprising that emissions were
reduced given the following three observations:67

1. The price of EUAs was positive and significant during the 2005-2006 period,
providing firms with an incentive to reduce emissions;
2. Real output in the EU rose over those two years, and improvements in CO2
intensity had been declining which implies a baseline of increasing CO2 emissions
prior to 2005; and
3. Historical emissions data indicate a reduction in absolute emissions over the
relevant period, allowing for plausible bias.

6.4 Will cap-and-trade reduce emissions in future?


Even if the EU ETS has been successful at reducing emissions to date, it must do so at
much greater scale in the future if it is to provide a policy response commensurate with
the scale of the challenge. There have been several changes in the design of the EU ETS
between Phase 1 and the current Phase 2 (from 2008-2012), with further improvements
in place for Phase 3 (from 2013-2020). Current allowance prices are around €10-
20/tCO2, significantly higher than any economy-wide carbon tax, and market participants
who publish forecasts of future prices expect prices to increase substantially over the
coming years. To some extent, companies take these future prices into account when
making their investment decisions.

Some of the more significant changes since Phase 1 have been as follows:

- The EU commission has been more resistant to lobbying by firms, and has
insisted on greater cuts in emissions than requested by EU Member States and
their firms;

66 Erik Delarue, Kris Voorspools, William D, D’haeseleer. ‘Fuel switching in the electricity sector under the
EU ETS: review and prospective’. Journal of Energy Engineering, 134:2 (2008), 40–46.
67 Denny Ellerman, and Barbara Buchner. ‘Over-Allocation or Abatement? A Preliminary Analysis of the

EU ETS Based on the 2005–06 Emissions Data’,.

32
- A higher proportion of EU allowances (EUAs) are being auctioned to firms
rather than given away for free;
- Banking of allowances is possible from Phase 2 to Phase 3. This promotes
confidence that carbon market prices will not fall to zero. Indeed, prices were
positive even during the recent financial crises and recession, which reduced
output and baseline emissions. This is because the market price reflects the effort
required by market participants to achieve the agreed emission reductions
through to 2020.

These changes suggest that emission reductions created through the 2008-2012 phase are
likely to be significantly greater than those in the so-called ‘learning’ phase from 2005-
2007. Furthermore, emissions reductions in the 2013-2020 phase will take the European
economy substantially below business-as-usual, and indeed 20-30% below emissions in
1990.

7. Conclusion
Cap-and-trade systems for greenhouse gas emissions have been put in place in several
countries over the last decade. While the evidence so far suggests that they have been
successful in reducing emissions, they have been subject to increasing criticism by
climate-change sceptics. Over the course of 2010, they were also tarred with the same
brush of dissatisfaction addressed towards the United Nations negotiations, which failed
to deliver a binding agreement at the international conference in Copenhagen in
December 2009, but which appears to have achieved greater progress at Cancún in
December 2010. In this paper we hope to have identified key ethical criteria by which
one can evaluate such schemes. More specifically, we have defended four conclusions.

First, we have noted in their favour that emissions trading schemes may minimize waste
and recognize person’ interest in liberty.

Second, we have provided a taxonomy of ethical objections to the market. Drawing on


this we have examined five different attempts to show that emissions trading schemes are
inherently unethical and have found each of these attempts wanting. Emissions trading
schemes, so we have argued, are not committed to either ‘ownership’ rights or
unacceptable ‘use rights’ over the atmosphere as a whole and are compatible with an

33
ideal of environmental stewardship (Argument A). In addition to this, while the Collective
Sacrifice Argument has force in some contexts, we have no reason to apply it to this
particular context (Argument B). A third argument – that one may restrict emissions
trading in order to protect the vulnerable – can take two forms, but neither rule out
emissions trading entirely (Argument C). Such arguments (in particular what we termed
the Unreliable Trustees Argument) draw our attention to the important issues of who should
possess the legal rights to emit greenhouse gases and how one can best ensure that the
permits (or the revenues of auctions) should reach the people entitled to them. Such
concerns do not, however, undermine many emissions trading schemes (Argument D).
Finally, we have argued that emissions trading schemes do not elide the distinction
between a ‘fee’ and ‘fine’ (Argument E). Emissions trading schemes are, thus, not in
principle objectionable.

Having considered these five root-and-branch critiques of emissions trading we then


turned to two other criteria relevant to the evaluation of emissions trading schemes. The
first critical issue is the effect of emissions trading schemes on the distribution of wealth.
This takes us to our third conclusion which is that while cap-and-trade systems are not
intrinsically unethical, they (like other policies that put a price on greenhouse gas
emissions) are likely to hit poorer households harder than richer households, with
unwelcome implications for distributional justice. The current EU ETS puts a price on
pollution without providing adequate compensation for poor households and, as a result,
it has had a greater impact on the poor relative to the rich. This is not a necessary
outcome,68 and in principle it is possible to design an ETS so that the revenues from
auctioning permits are used to produce a progressive result. Indeed, companies in the
EU ETS will have to pay for a greater proportion of their allowances over time, so there
is some possibility that this problem will be resolved as the ETS matures. That said, it is
unlikely that the EU ETS will be progressive for at least another decade.

This leaves the final crucial consideration, namely ‘are emissions trading schemes an
effective means of mitigating climate change?’. Our conclusion here is that a careful
analysis of cap-and-trade systems shows that they are more effective at reducing
emissions than many of their critics appear to believe. As noted above, even in the 2005-

68 Indeed, research suggests that fuel taxes might not be regressive in developing countries: Thomas Sterner,

‘Fuel taxes: An important instrument for climate policy’, Energy Policy 35 (2007), 3194–3202.

34
2007 learning phase of the EU ETS, discredited as having “failed” by some critics, it is
estimated that 50-100 million tonnes of CO2 a year were reduced compared to business-
as-usual. The current phase (2008-2012) of the EU ETS will deliver greater reductions,
notwithstanding the recession, and the reductions delivered in the next phase (2013-
2020) depend upon whether the EU commits to a 20% or a 30% target in the course of
the next year or so.

Given the moral virtues of cap-and-trade systems and the absence of compelling moral
objections relative to other policy possibilities, we conclude that emissions trading
remains a valuable policy tool with which to address climate change. Carbon taxes have
some advantages over cap-and-trade,69 but in other ways are worse, not least in the fact
that they provide no guarantee of environmental outcomes, and are significantly more
difficult to establish politically. Indeed, carbon taxes are likely to continue to be
politically difficult, especially in the USA, to implement and maintain at a level that will
achieve reductions in emissions at the necessary rate to provide a just outcome for future
generations. Direct regulation is inferior to an ETS or a carbon tax because it increases
costs of compliance, increases wastage and reduces liberty of individuals and companies
to adapt to a low-carbon economy in the manner most suitable to them. In an ETS, the
possibility of trade minimises waste, the cap ensures environmental integrity over time,
potentially according to a gradual “contraction and convergence” pathway, 70 and the
allocation of the permits determines the distributive justice (and political success). None
of this is to suggest that a single cap-and-trade system would alone be an adequate
response to climate change. Nevertheless, it is a morally valuable, rather than a morally
suspect, contribution to moving at speed and at scale to the low-carbon economy
required for humans to continue to flourish on Earth into the next century and beyond.

69
Cameron Hepburn, ‘Regulation by prices, quantities or both: A review of instrument choice’, Oxford
Review of Economic Policy 22:2 (2006), 226-247.
70 Aubrey Meyer, Contraction and Convergence: The global solution to climate change’.

35

You might also like