Response To What Is Comparative Politic PDF
Response To What Is Comparative Politic PDF
Response To What Is Comparative Politic PDF
1
Andrew F. March, “What Is Comparative Political Theory?” Review of Politics 71,
no. 4: xx–xx]
2
Ibid., xx.
3
Ibid., xx.
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 569
namely, those who are interested in exactly how the overall field should be
restructured and who might, therefore, take issue with the narrow focus on
comparison. This is, in fact, a rather important question. We need to think
about whether and why March’s approach to the way political theory
ought to treat otherness—namely, ensuring that an engaged comparative pol-
itical theory focuses on those thinkers and texts who represent systematic
doctrinal conflict and speak to normative disputes, while leaving all other
treatments of non-Western thought to be incorporated into the existing disci-
plinary conventions and modes of inquiry—is the appropriate one.
Some of March’s own comments implicitly suggest that the demands and
imperatives of what we currently consider comparative political theory—
namely, the impetus to study thinkers and texts beyond the West—cannot
be confined to an internal discussion because they are inextricably connected
to the overall field of political theory. Why be concerned with pitching the
imperative of comparative political theory to the entire field, or with com-
manding the respect of other political theorists, if the goal is simply to
refine the internal methodological requirements of a subfield, most of
which are ultimately self-sufficient and self-contained? March himself
rightly reminds us of the centrifugal nature of political theory: adherents of
subfields as methodologically diverse as feminist theory, pragmatism,
Rawlsian pluralism, or hermeneutic theory often have nothing to say to
each other, and thus little interest in—or need for—justifying their existence
either to one another or to the field as a whole. However, in indicating that
it has to command the respect of those not interested in non-Western thinkers,
March’s proposal implies that discussions about comparative political
theory cannot continue to be internal ones. Meanwhile, the results of
the restructuring that March proposes also clearly have implications for the
field as a whole. This suggests, then, a need to examine the presuppositions
underlying political theory’s overall relationship to the otherness of
non-Western texts and ideas. March alludes to this larger question, but
chooses ultimately to bracket it entirely. I intend to argue, however, that the
particulars of his proposal have implications for this larger question that
cannot be ignored.
development for the field of political theory.4 Yet his essay strikes many a note
of pessimism about the possibility of a strictly comparative political theory as
he defines it, precisely because of what he acknowledges to be the irreducible
internal plurality of traditions and the porosity of boundaries between them.5
This uncertainty is further underscored by a lack of clarity about the central-
ity of doctrinal orthodoxy that March suggests should be the centerpiece of an
engaged political theory. On the one hand, March seems to be quite serious
about the focus on doctrinal orthodoxy, which he argues for most clearly
and in an impassioned fashion in theses 7 and 8. Reading what sounds like a
strong advocacy of the criterion of doctrinal orthodoxy in these sections, one
is easily led to worry that the focus on traditions of thought with conflicting
substantive moral commitments, mutually incompatible sources of authority,
and the insistence on deep moral distinction between traditions with stable
boundaries will have reifying, alienating, and radicalizing effects. That such
an approach will make it tempting to deny hybridity and reify non-Western
traditions by reducing them to a caricature of their most orthodox figures
and texts is only the most obvious objection. One starts to worry that the
sort of political theorizing March seeks to characterize as comparative
would bring into relief only the most orthodox representatives of a given reli-
gious tradition or doctrinal view, further alienating or perhaps radicalizing the
responses of their interlocutors from other traditions.
Soon, however, the reader is not quite sure whether—or how much—she
has to worry about this reification of orthodoxies. March is sophisticated
enough not only to acknowledge that examples of hybridity and nonideal-
types abound in all traditions, but to suggest that he is, in fact, quite deeply
concerned with the implications of this hybridity and pluralism. But what
March gives with one hand, he takes away with the other, for it becomes
less clear what sort of role March really does intend for the criterion of doc-
trinal orthodoxy to play in his argument. He now puts forth simultaneous
requirements for two different things that seem to be in conflict with one
another: namely, on the one hand, an engaged comparative political theory
that focuses on the first-order implications of normative disputes and has
the capacity to reveal important implications of such normative disputes
to the adherents of multiple traditions, and on the other, an engaged compara-
tive political theory that focuses on systematic conflict among deeply distinct
entities, each representing the orthodox center of a moral doctrine. In thesis 9,
4
See, for instance, March, page xx: “[A] patient, thorough and responsible exca-
vation of the contours of moral conflict itself is a creative and engaged way of genu-
inely comparing distinct ethical traditions”; as well as page xx: “[C]omparative
political theory will be richer and more interesting by moving further into the realm
of normative justification within multiple traditions.”
5
“It may of course be that the distinction I am drawing is incoherent or unsustain-
able. But then so might the idea of an engaged comparative political theory if it is to be
more than non-Western political theory” (xx –xx).
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 571
6
For more details on the origins of the caste system, Vedic philosophy, and other
classical Hindu texts, see U. N. Ghoshal, A History of Indian Political Ideas (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1959); Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan and Charles A. Moore,
eds., A Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957);
and John B. Chethimattam, Patterns of Indian Thought: Indian Religions and
Philosophies (Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1971).
572 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
very same reason, it is unclear whether this value-conflict alone could provide
any insights pertaining to the terms of cooperation between the adherents of
respective doctrines. After all, the stratification and regulation of social and
political life through the caste system could only be said to be the deepest of
internal concerns within a tradition, and in its most orthodox form, has little
ability to speak beyond those concerns and contexts.
Another version of this problem could be the following: If hybridity, plur-
ality, and dissent from ideal-types are, in fact, the conditions that tend more
commonly to characterize adherence to traditions, then is the choice of ortho-
dox or ideal-type figures and texts faced with the potential problem of irrele-
vance or disjuncture from the range of available existential realities within a
tradition and thus from any real insight on the terms of social cooperation?
“I myself doubt very much,” March acknowledges, “that any person thinks
and acts solely in terms of what their authoritative doctrine or ideology pre-
scribes. Certainly, in the postcolonial world it is difficult to find non-Western
thinkers who have been utterly unaffected (unpolluted?) by Western ideas,
norms, and expectations” (xx). This suggests that it is often equally difficult
to find actual practices—the realities of lived lives and practices by those
who adhere existentially to the doctrinal truths being investigated—that cor-
respond to the most doctrinally orthodox or central positions within that
tradition. To revert to my previous example, one is less and less likely to
find among Hindu believers a concern for adherence to caste-based hierarchy
in its most orthodox doctrinal form. While many modern-day Hindus are
content loosely to follow caste-based prescriptions for endogamy, the most
orthodox doctrinal prescriptions of texts, such as the Laws of Manu pertaining
to social interactions, employment status, and political rule, are increasingly
irrelevant. If an engaged comparative political theory is to focus on genuinely
knotty moral questions about public life on which only the most orthodox
figures or texts can be consulted, then these problems may often not have
much connection to the existential realities of lived lives within that doctrinal
tradition. The purchase of orthodoxy or doctrinal centrality may have to come
at the cost of relevance to public discourse about social cooperation.
Finally, could it also be the case that the most interesting and relevant gui-
dance on matters of public life involving multiple traditions comes not from
the orthodox doctrinal center of any given tradition but rather from thinkers
and texts that dissent from orthodoxy, formulating hybrid and synthetic doc-
trines that lie at the blurry intersections of boundaries between traditions? For
instance, March makes repeated reference to Gandhi—including, most
kindly, to my own work on Gandhi. But Gandhi was neither orthodox nor
ideal-typical as a representative of the Hindu tradition of political thought,
as March himself acknowledges.7 And Gandhi’s capacity to provide
7
On p. xx, March recognizes that Gandhi’s thought was never distinct or radically
alien enough from Western thought as to form a distinct community of moral
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 573
11
See footnote no. 47 on p. xx.
12
Indeed, March makes fleeting references to Islamic thinkers such as Ibn Taymiyya,
Al-Ghazali, and Al-Qardawi as orthodox representatives of Islamic doctrine, as well as
to the possibility of a problem-driven investigation of the Danish cartoon controversy.
But absent a more detailed example, one is left wondering what distinguishes these
particular cases as good examples of systematic value conflict based on doctrinal
orthodoxy or distinction, with no way to judge what other cases from traditions
outside Islam might fulfill similar requirements.
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 575
Absent further clarification, one is left wondering how seriously to take the
pessimistic remarks March makes about the possibility of a truly engaged
comparative political theory and how—if at all—to reconcile these with his
keen advocacy of the project and of the centrality of doctrinal orthodoxy
therein. As a result, which of the alternatives he truly endorses also
remains unclear throughout March’s article. Should we have a comparative
political theory focused purely on value-conflict among autonomous moral
doctrines as a subfield of a global umbrella of political theory in which
Gandhi and Qutb are taught alongside Plato and Hobbes? Or are the require-
ments for an engaged comparative political theory, if we understand them
properly, so unrealistic—given the preponderance of hybridity, plurality,
and synthesis—that it seems implausible that we could ever fulfill them
and still have something interesting to say about value conflict, as, in fact,
the very last words of the essay tell us?13 We are left wondering, then,
whether March endorses the project of a distinct subdiscipline of comparative
political theory organized around the pursuit of problem-driven value con-
flict, or whether his argument is intended to demonstrate the implausibility
of such reform, and to endorse the alternative he implies, namely, that all
non-Western texts are subsumed into the existing canons and methods of pol-
itical theory proper, both scholarly and engaged. The reader is left puzzling
over the goal of March’s project: Does he simply intend to pose the question
of the viability of an engaged comparative political theory as an unanswer-
able one? Or does he intend to answer it? If the latter, one does not know
which of March’s possible conclusions most accurately describes his position.
13
His final paragraph suggests that hybridity and synthesis, rather than orthodoxy
or authoritative doctrinal centrality, are the conditions that tend more commonly to
characterize relationships between traditions, and that the project of building a sub-
field focused on problem-driven value-conflicts between autonomous, moral doctrines
is, therefore, a tenuous one because the distinction of entities and sharpness of bound-
aries defining those distinctions is rather more blurred in the case of political theory
than in other fields. “As it turns out, it might not be so easy for any form of
‘engaged’ political theory to follow political science, law, and other disciplines in inau-
gurating comparative methods. For unlike fields where the object of study is a well-
contained entity . . . political theory has a special burden. In dealing with the realm
of thoughts, ideas, and truth-claims, it is not always clear when the boundary
between ‘ours’ and ‘theirs’ obtains and when that boundary per se is generative of
compelling questions” (xx).
576 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
14
“Of course, there is no denying that non-Western traditions are rich and have other
interesting things to say besides those which bear on justification or value conflict.
However . . . there would be nothing particularly comparative about the study of
non-Western traditions that focus purely on the internal concerns of those traditions.
There is no reason not to have a scholarship devoted to the noncomparative study of
non-Western political thought (as, of course, we do)” (xx).
15
See March’s elaboration of thesis 2 on pp. xx –xx. See also p. x: “Comparative
methods are thus already assumed to be part of the wide, variable, and diverse
forms of activity which for disciplinary-organization purposes go under the name
political theory.”
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 577
tradition.16 But the particular way in which March makes this argument relies
heavily on the idea that the practice of political theory has always been com-
parative in some senses, which in turn leaves intact the existing structures and
methods of political theory, implying that there is no need to reorganize its
disciplinary practices or its methods of inquiry.17 Suggesting that the treat-
ment of most non-Western thinkers, texts, and ideas can unproblematically
be assimilated into the existing and available practices of political theory
may unwittingly end up reaffirming the hegemony of Western categories if
it implies (as March’s argument currently does) that Gandhi can simply be
studied and taught alongside Plato and Machiavelli without any rethinking
of the very categories of inquiry that structure our treatment of these texts.
To suggest that political theory as it now exists is and always has been com-
parative is quite right in one sense. But this focus on comparison as an
inherent feature of all political theory obscures important nuances. It obscures
the fact that the dominance of Western political theory arises not only from its
substantive foci but also from the dominance of its structures of inquiry,
its practices, and methods. It also ends up denying the parochial specificity
of those structures, practices, and methods by leaving them intact, rather
than problematizing them. It suggests that the existing substantive and meth-
odological canons of political theory require no reform or rethinking, and that
the very ways in which political theory has thus far conducted its compara-
tive inquiries are satisfactory to the task at hand, well-structured enough to
subsume the category of a whole new kind of distinction that confronts its
practitioners in new ways.
This in turn reveals another assumption embedded within the claim,
namely that what is required to do good scholarly work on Gandhi or
Confucius is, in the end, not any different from what is required to do
good scholarly work on Aristotle, Machiavelli, or Kant. The claim that the
alienness that separates us from our own ancients is no more or less mystify-
ing than the alienness that confronts us when we read Gandhi, Kautilya, or
Ibn Khaldun also lends implicit support to the hegemony and subsumptive
zeal of Western categories of inquiry, and to its propensity cheerfully to
engulf all other kinds of knowledge into its own tent. It suggests that most
kinds of otherness can be studied as though they were, in the end, no different
from the internal othernesses cleaving the category of West itself, and that
political theory is comparative enough to absorb the cultural difference of
16
See Godrej, “Toward a Cosmopolitan Political Thought: The Hermeneutics of
Interpreting the Other,” Polity 41, no. 2 (April 2009): 135–65. I do not claim that
March explicitly embraces the agenda of a global or cosmopolitan political thought,
but rather that some global or cosmopolitan structure is implied in his argument.
17
I am deeply indebted to Leigh Jenco for pushing me to think about the most radical
implications of decentering the parochialism of Western political theory. See also Leigh
Jenco, “What Does Heaven Ever Say?: A Methods-Centered Approach to
Cross-Cultural Engagement,” American Political Science Review 101, no. 4 (2007).
578 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
18
See Godrej, “Toward a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 139.
19
Ibid., 153.
20
Jenco, “What Does Heaven Ever Say?”
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 579
21
Godrej, “Toward a Cosmopolitan Political Thought.”
22
See Godrej, “Nonviolence and Gandhi’s Truth,” as well as “Gandhi’s Civic Ahimsa:
A Standard for Public Justification in Multicultural Democracies,” International Journal
of Gandhian Studies (forthcoming).
23
Ashis Nandy uses the term critical traditionalist to refer to Gandhi’s unique relation-
ship to the Indian tradition. Ashis Nandy, The Intimate Enemy: The Loss and Recovery of
Self under Colonialism (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1988).
580 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
24
See, for instance, Andrew March, “Islamic Foundations for a Social Contract in
Non-Muslim Liberal Democracies,” American Political Science Review 101, no. 2
(2007); “Sources of Moral Obligation to Non-Muslims in the ‘Jurisprudence of
Muslim Minorities’ (Fiqh al-aqalliyyat) Discourse,” Islamic Law and Society 16, no. 1
(2009).
RESPONSE TO “WHAT IS COMPARATIVE POLITICAL THEORY?” 581
required is to incorporate the study of these thinkers into the existing prac-
tices and methods of a political theory that is, as yet, inadequately structured
for the complexities of the task at hand.
Finally, March’s implicit support for the hegemony of Western categories of
inquiry is also reinforced by the subtle privileging of engaged over noncom-
parative or scholarly political theory as the ultimate warrant for addressing
non-Western texts and thinkers. March insists that he does not wish to down-
grade the status of scholarly political theory, and in many places, he acknowl-
edges that it may be a richer and more rewarding kind of scholarship
than purely engaged comparative political theory.25 But he also suggests
that purely scholarly work pertaining to non-Western thinkers or ideas has
little capacity to add value to existing political theory by exciting the imagin-
ation of political theorists working in and on the West, or convincing them to
care about ideas and texts from other traditions.26 Comparative political
theory, he claims, must aspire to be engaged rather than to be scholarly if it
is to add value to what is already inherently a sufficiently comparative endea-
vor. But this claim fails to recognize an important potential contribution of
what March would call “scholarly” or “noncomparative” political theory;
namely, that scholarly treatments of a thinker, a text, or a set of ideas may
have the potential not only to challenge our normative commitments but
also to change entirely the sorts of questions we even ask and the problems
we seek to focus on. Western political theory’s dominance arises from more
than simply its focus on certain texts and methods of inquiry; it also involves
asking certain kinds of questions motivated by certain presuppositions and
preoccupations. Leigh Jenco has reminded us splendidly that thinking
within the categories of Western experience limits our ability to engage in
modes of knowing and being that are removed from these categories, and
that thinking within another tradition—immersing oneself in its categories
of experience and practices of inquiry—may be a more effective methodologi-
cal antidote to this problem of Eurocentrism.27 Deep immersion in the sorts of
things March might consider scholarly activity—immersing oneself in
another tradition, its practices of inquiry, its ways of knowing and under-
standing the political world, its modes of questioning, and the kinds of pro-
blems it seeks to focus on—has a potentially groundbreaking contribution
to make by bringing to light entirely new kinds of questions arising from
25
See March, “What Is Comparative Political Theory?”: “A scholarship devoted to
the noncomparative study of non-Western political thought . . . may indeed be richer
and more sophisticated than various forms of comparative political theory” (xx).
26
On p. xx, he calls it the “weaker” form of political theory. He also states that “the
interest in non-Western political thought . . . merely to decenter the canon or to frame
‘cross-cultural dialogue’ . . . without rigorous epistemic or normative standards . . .
would be nothing . . . for the broader disciplines of political science and political
theory to get too excited about” (xx).
27
Jenco, “What Does Heaven Ever Say?”
582 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS
new preoccupations and new frames of inquiry. March suggests that texts
from outside the Western tradition should be able to excite the imagination
of political theorists trained and situated within the frameworks of the domi-
nant Western problematics and categories, making them care about
non-Western texts or ideas without having to dislodge their own frames of
thought. He thus implies that it is more important to make the treatment of
non-Western texts fit categories of Western inquiry and Western preoccupa-
tions than to shed critical light on or to problematize those categories and
preoccupations altogether.
March may respond (and, indeed, does suggest repeatedly) that he is less
interested in and/or committed to the political act of dismantling or troubling
the parochialism of settled Western understandings of political life and
methods of inquiry, as he is in the intellectual act of bringing rigor to the
project of comparative scholarship. But it is one thing to value rigorous scho-
larship over affirmative action, and quite another to provide a reforming
vision that implicitly contains the danger of reinforcing the intellectual and
methodological hegemony. This result seems especially awkward because
March suggests that the hegemony of Eurocentric categories is so obvious
that no one who chose to deny it would have a leg to stand on.28 My critiques
do not necessarily suggest that March should be more committed to the
project of dislocating the hegemony of Eurocentrism than he currently is,
but rather that he should be more attentive to the implications of his own
argument for acquiescing to—and perhaps reaffirming—that hegemony.
I have argued in this essay that Andrew March’s article, while presenting
an important contribution to the development of a crucial debate, leaves
the reader both somewhat puzzled about its actual goal and concerned
about its linkages to the dominant practices and methods of Western political
inquiry. In the end, of course, I am grateful to March for having started an
extremely important conversation, one that I hope to continue in spirited
fashion over time. I am also grateful to him for having done so in an interest-
ing and provocative way and for opening the door to a series of exchanges,
both with each other and with our other colleagues in the field. I believe
we are together in hoping for this to be the commencement, rather than the
finale, of such rich and challenging exchanges.
28
“Who today would assert with confidence that concepts and categories developed
in European and North American societies are necessarily applicable to other
societies? Who today would deny that European and North American societies
have defined for themselves and others the dominant normative understandings of
contemporary philosophical concepts?” (March, “What is Comparative Political
Theory?” xx).