DFM STARUS On Metaphores
DFM STARUS On Metaphores
DFM STARUS On Metaphores
and language
D.F.M. Strauss
Department of Philosophy
University of the Free State
BLOEMFONTEIN
E-mail: [email protected]
Abstract
Metaphor: the intertwinement of thought and language
The analysis of this article aims at reflecting on the nature of
metaphoricity within the context of thought and language –
inspired by the contributions of Elaine Botha in this regard
commencing about three decades ago. This paved the way for
those who were working within the tradition of reformational
philosophy to take a new look at the nature of metaphor.
Since thinking and talking are concrete activities in principle
functioning in all aspects of reality, they cannot as such provide
criteria to decide on the order relationship between the logical-
analytical and lingual aspects of reality. It turns out that, without
a proper view of the differences between concept and word, an
account of the nature of metaphor remains inconsistent. Uni-
versal traits, logical objectification, and the conceptual unknow-
ability of what is individual, surfaces in the article. The founda-
tional role of spatial relationships appears to be linked to imag-
ing and imagining, informing the proposal to differentiate be-
tween modally and entitary directed knowing.
The linguistic turn in particular inspired a renewed interest in
language and the central place of metaphorical language use.
After considering the connections between analogy and meta-
phor a new approach to the distinction between modal analo-
gies and metaphors is proposed – one that is geared towards
the interconnections between the different dimensions of our
experiential world. The last part is dedicated to Lakoff and
Johnson (1999) who have developed a peculiar view of the
“embodied mind”, “conceptual metaphor”, and “cross-domain
mappings”, while the article concludes with an argument about
1. Introduction
Within the circles of reformational philosophy, Elaine Botha certainly
deserves credit for being the first one who thoroughly entered the
field of philosophical reflection on the nature of metaphor – culminat-
1 This excellent work by Botha (2007) explores a theme indirectly related to our
current discussion on metaphor in the context of thought and language –
although what is later introduced in our discussion, regarding the conditioning
role of interdimensional connections for different kinds of metaphor, may prompt
Botha to consider the expansion of the scope of metaphors and the strict
distinction between modal analogies and metaphors.
2 Parmenides only adds language, as an utterance, after thought and being has
been identified: “Thinking and the thought that it is are the same; for you will not
find thought apart from what is, in relation to which it is uttered.” (Diels & Krantz,
B.8.34-36.) The legacy of Parmenides is mainly observed in that the meta-
physics of being is actually a space metaphysics, supplemented by the idea of
an analogy of being. See the text below.
6 Suppose we consider the category of “flying entities”, then one may encounter a
metaphor in which reference is made to the “wing” of the aeroplane. It seems as
if we have a higher level similarity and a lower level difference – “flying”
encompasses both natural and artificial flying entities.
It does not help to argue that thinking and speaking function in all
aspects of reality, because this insight does not elucidate the order
relation between the logical and the lingual. However, we are getting
closer to an understanding of this problem when we consider the
fact that the logical sense of children appears to develop more ra-
pidly than their linguistic abilities and competence. Consider the
following striking example. A little girl, who first notices a pigeon and
learns its name, can abstract “concretely”, for instance when she
shortly thereafter refers to a shrike as a pigeon. The child actually
designates the concept “bird” with the name (verbal sign) “pigeon”.
This is only possible, because from the concrete sensorially per-
ceived image of a pigeon, the girl has lifted out certain bird-cha-
racteristics, e.g. a beak, wings, feathers, while simultaneously relin-
quishing the specific characteristics that distinguish a pigeon from a
shrike.
9 See his Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik die als Wissenschaft
wird auftreten können (Kant, 1969 [1783]:341; § 52b).
12 “Kunst ist Intuition, Intuition ist Individualität, und Individualität wiederholt sich
nicht.”
5. Cross-domain mappings
Lakoff and Johnson (1999) started to explore a scheme analogous
to what is found in the mathematical function concept, manifested in
their idea of source domains and target domains. As their starting
point, they look at the scope and richness of our subjective mental
life, where “subjective judgements” are made about “such abstract
things as importance, similarity, difficulty, and morality” and where
we meet “subjective experiences of desire, affection, intimacy, and
achievement”.
15 De Saussure (1966:67) says that the “bond between the signifier and the
signified is arbitrary”.
7. Expanded conditions
If we specify that the term metaphor does not apply to modal ana-
logies, we still have to contemplate what can be included in the
realm of metaphors. In fact, we have to expand our argument that
aspectual analogies (similarities and differences between aspects of
reality) ought to be distinguished from metaphors, because there are
actually more possibilities (cf. Strauss, 2009:155 ff.).
8. Conceptual metaphor
Strictly speaking, the expression “conceptual metaphor”, although
described in an intelligible way, conflates the sign mode with its
foundational logical-analytical aspect. Concepts are not words and
for that reason they cannot be metaphors. Furthermore, in the ab-
sence of an articulated theory of modal functions, the nature of
intermodal, interaspectual or interfunctional connections are distor-
ted by the theory of conceptual metaphor. Ontic interconnections are
presented as if they were, in fact, interconnections between con-
ceptual domains. It also explains why the discussions of conceptual
metaphor avoid an analysis of the ontic meaning of an aspect.
When one enters into an analysis of what is given in reality (in a pre-
conceptualised ontic sense), then one realises that spatial pheno-
mena – such as vertical lines or verticality and horisontality – are
founded in the meaning of number. Within space we can discern
dimentionality as an order of extension in one, two, or three dimen-
sions. Without the foundational quantitative meaning of one, two and
three, the entire notion of spatial dimensions collapses into nothing-
ness. Likewise, the spatial awareness of magnitude also factually
presupposes number, because when we speak of different dimen-
sions it is also possible to speak of length (one-dimensional exten-
sion), surface (two-dimensional extension), volume (three-dimen-
sional extension), and so on. Therefore, verticality is embedded in
dimensionality and the latter also collapses into nothingness when
separated from its coherence with the quantitative meaning of the
numbers employed in designating different kinds of magnitudes.
9. Concluding remark
Metaphors indeed transcend the logical-analytical mode – without
being able to cut their ties with the conceptual basis found in the
logical aspect. Without the foundational role of (analytical) concept
formation (thinking), the entire distinction between a source domain
and a target domain, as well as the distinction between literal and
metaphorical language, becomes meaningless. Precisely because a
metaphor is not a concept, it can employ words metaphorically
List of references
ARISTOTLE. 2001 [1941]. The basic works of Aristotle. Ed. by R. McKeon with
an introduction by C.D.C. Reeve. New York: The Modern Library.
BIRTWISTLE, G.M 1996. Filosofie van de kunst en de aesthetica. (In Van
Woudenberg, R., ed. Kennis en werkelijkheid. Amsterdam: Buijten &
Schipperhijn. p. 342-370.)
BLACK, M. 1979. More about metaphor. (In Ortony, A., ed. Metaphor and
thought. New York: Cambridge University Press. p. 1-24.)
BOTHA, M.E. 2006. Metaphor, embodiment and fiduciary beliefs in science. (In
Lategan, L.O.K. & Smith, J.H. Time and context relevant philosophy.
Festschrift dedicated to D.F.M. Strauss. Bloemfontein: Association for
Christian Higher Education. p. 17-36.)
BOTHA, M.E. 2007. Metaphor and its moorings, studies in the grounding of
metaphorical meaning. Bern: Peter Lang.
BRANDT, P.A. 2000. The architecture of semantic domains – a grounding
hypothesis in cognitive semiotics. Revista portuguesa der humanidades,
4(1 & 2):11-51.
CROCE, B. 1953. Aesthetic as science of expression and general linguistic. 3rd
ed. Trans. from the definitive Italian edition from 1920. New York:
Noonday.
DE SAUSSURE, F. 1966. Course in general linguistics. Ed. by C. Bally & A.
Sechehaye. London: McGraw-Hill.
DE VLEESCHAUWER, H.J. 1952. Handleiding by die studie van die logika en
die kennisleer. Pretoria: Moerau.
DIELS, H. & KRANZ, W. 1959-1960. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Vol. 1-3.
Berlin: Weidmannsche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
DOOYEWEERD, H. 1938. Recht en historie. Paper presented at the 23rd
Scientific Gathering of the Free University of Amsterdam, 13 July 1938.
EIBL-EIBESFELDT, I. 2004. Grundriß der vergleichenden Verhaltensforschung:
Ethologie. Hrsg. Vierkirchen-Pasenach: Buch Vertrieb Blank GmbH.
ENCYCLOPEDIA BRITANNICA. 1975. Vol. 15. London: Hemingway Benton.
GADAMER, H.-G. 1991. Die Hermeneutik und der Diltheyschule. Philoso-
phische Rundschau, 38(3):161-177.
KANT, I. 1969 [1783]. Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik die als
Wissenschaft wird auftreten können. Hamburg: Felix Meiner edition.
KÖLLER, W. 1975. Semiotik und Metapher. Stuttgart: Metzier.
LAKOFF, G. & JOHNSON, M. 1999. Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind
and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.
LAKOFF, G. & NÚÑEZ, R.E. 2000. Where mathematics comes from: how the
embodied mind brings mathematics into being. New York: Basic Books.
MÄCKLER, A., Hrsg. 2000. 1 460 Antworten auf die Frage: Was ist Kunst?
Köln: DuMont.
NARR, K.J. 1976. Cultural achievements of early man. (In Altner, G. & Hofer, H.
Die Sonderstellung des Menschen. Stuttgart: Fischer. p. 98-152.)
SEERVELD, C.G. 1968. A Christian critique of art and literature. Toronto: The
Association for Reformed Scientific Studies.
Key concepts:
analogies
concept
conceptual metaphor
language
metaphor
thought
Kernbegrippe:
analogieë
begrip
begripsmetafoor
denke
metafoor
taal