Empirical Cross-Sectional Asset Pricing
Empirical Cross-Sectional Asset Pricing
Empirical Cross-Sectional Asset Pricing
Stefan Nagel
Stanford University, NBER and CEPR
Abstract
I review recent research efforts in the area of empirical cross-sectional asset pricing. I
start by summarizing the evidence on cross-sectional return predictability and the failure
of standard (consumption) CAPM models and their conditional versions to explain these
predictability patterns. One response in part of the recent literature is to focus on ad-
hoc factor models, which summarize the cross-section of expected returns in parsimonious
form, or on production-based approaches, which suggest links between firm characteristics
and expected returns. Without imposing restrictions on investor preferences and beliefs,
neither one of these two approaches can answer the question why investors price assets the
way they do. Within the rational expectations paradigm, recent research that imposes
such restrictions has focused on the ICAPM, long-run risks models, as well as frictions and
liquidity risk. Approaches based on investor sentiment have focused on the development
of empirical proxies for sentiment and for the limits to arbitrage that allow sentiment
to affect prices. Empirical work that considers learning and adaptation of investors has
worked with out-of-sample tests of cross-sectional predictability.
I am grateful for comments to Frederico Belo, John Campbell, Marco Giacoletti, Sebastian Infante, Bob
Hodrick, Arthur Korteweg, Ian Martin, Dimitris Papanikolaou, Lasse Pedersen, Jeff Pontiff, Mike Schwert,
and Jeff Wurgler.
1
1 Introduction
It is a fundamental question of financial economics whether assets with different risk exposures
and characteristics are priced to earn different rates of return. I survey studies in empirical
cross-sectional asset pricing that provide evidence on this question and relate the evidence
to models of investor preferences and beliefs. I begin by laying out a framework that will be
vector of parameters pins down the law of motion of Xt . Assume that Xt is observable
to investors, and let Jt denote the sigma algebra generated by Xt . The economy features
N assets that produce a vector of payoffs Dt (Xt ). Let Mt (Xt , ) be the stochastic discount
factor (SDF) that reflects preferences of a representative investor with preference parameters
Most empirical studies in cross-sectional asset pricing rely on rational expectations asset-
pricing theory in the tradition of Lucas (1978) to derive model predictions and a null hypoth-
esis. Under rational expectations (Muth (1961)), investors are endowed with knowledge of
the parameters . Defining (gross) returns as Rt+1 (Pt+1 + Dt+1 )/Pt , investors price assets
according to
where the conditional expectation E[.|Jt ] is taken under the density f (Xt+1 |Jt , ) with knowl-
edge of . Now define Ht+1 Rt+1 Mt+1 1. Continuing to assume knowledge of , we can
apply the law of iterated expectations and condition down to the econometricians information
conditions
for any At -measurable instruments Zt . Studies in cross-sectional asset pricing often focus on
2
the special case
of (2), where Zt is a vector of portfolio weights that combines the N assets into a portfolio.
Evaluating (3) is akin to asking whether the elements Zit of Zt can predict differences in
discounted returns Hit+1 of the N assets. The cross-sectional asset pricing literature has
produced a large body of evidence of such cross-sectional return predictability. I start the
survey with a review of this evidence in Section 2. The economic interpretation of these
Stochastic discount factor. The law of one price implies that a stochastic discount factor
(SDF) exists such that (1) holds, and it can be constructed as a linear combination of the asset
payoffs (Hansen and Richard (1987)). The economic content of pricing models is therefore in
the restrictions that they impose on the SDF. Restrictions can be motivated by theory (e.g.,
the CAPM) or have an ad-hoc nature (e.g., restricting a factor model to a small number of
ad-hoc factors). Researchers often look to enrich the specification of investors preferences or
the dynamics of risks to enhance the pricing performance of models. I review these issues in
Sections 3 and 4.
based on the rational expectations paradigm, where it is presumed that investors know the
realistically, an investor would have to learn by observing data. A Bayesian investor learning
R
would form expectations based on the predictive density f (Xt+1 |Jt ) = f (Xt+1 , |Jt )d,
where the B superscript of the expectations operator indicates that the expectation is now
taken under the Bayesian predictive density f (Xt+1 |Jt ). For the econometrician, this has the
3
unpleasant consequence that the usual approach of evaluating a sample version of (2) to test
the pricing model is not valid: return predictability that is evident to an econometrician ex-
post may not exist under the predictive distribution that investors perceive at the time they
make decisions. There is only a small empirical literature so far that looks at empirical cross-
sectional asset pricing from the perspective of learning. Out-of-sample tests are onealbeit
imperfectway to study learning effects, and I cover this line of work in Section 6.
holds with E S [.|Jt ] evaluated under the subjective density perceived by investors. I use
Section 5 covers empirical studies that take this perspective. Since the boundary between
rational theories and sentiment-approaches is fuzzy,1 I refrain from using the somewhat sim-
or behavioral, approaches.
Frictions. Frictions can affect the SDF in several ways. Frictions may prevent participa-
tion of some classes of investors in the market. Frictions can also give rise to risks that are
of concern to investors, such as liquidity risk. I cover work on these issues in parts of Section
Data snooping. One problem that plagues cross-sectional asset pricing is that much of
1
For example, macroeconomists have worked with models of boundedly rational learning (Bray (1982),
Marcet and Sargent (1989)) in which agents use simplified forecasting rules rather than a full Bayesian ap-
proach. Sims (2003) argues that agents with limited information-processing capacity may find it rational to
be inattentive to some types of information.
4
the empirical work in this area is inherently a search for anomalies. When researchers search
over a large number of candidate predictors for predictability that is unexplained by standard
models of the SDF, it is inevitable that some turn up as significant just by pure chance.
Conventional procedures of statistical inference do not account for this search over many
candidate predictors. The out-of-sample tests reviewed in Section 6 can help shed light on
this problem.
cussed as the study of market efficiency, but the meaning of this concept is not clearly defined,
which limits its usefulness as an organizing principle. Fama (1970) defines a (semi-strongly)
efficient market as one that always fully reflects all available (public) information, but it is
not clear whether fully reflect refers to the demanding notion of rational expectations (this
is the view taken in Jensen (1978)), or whether the notion of market efficiency should allow for
learning and adaptation (Schwert (2003) and Timmermann and Granger (2004) propose this
interpretation). Frictions and risks further obscure the precise meaning of market efficiency.
ing that market efficiency should be defined as the absence of profit opportunities from
investors trade, it is possible that sentiment affects prices, yet sophisticated investors do not
perceive any abnormal profit opportunities given the frictions and risks that they face.2 If one
defines such a market as efficient, efficiency becomes a largely empty concept because it does
sentiment) of how investors price assets. For these reasons, I prefer to explicitly spell out the
belief-formation hypothesis that researchers work with, rather than relying on the imprecise
While I aim to cover the main conceptual issues in empirical cross-sectional asset pricing,
the survey is necessarily selective in its scope. I focus on recent work, mostly on equity
2
See, for example, Dumas, Kurshev, and Uppal (2009) for an illustration of this point in a general equilib-
rium model.
5
markets. On the econometric side, I emphasize the importance of the choice of moment
conditions when estimating and evaluating asset-pricing models, but I mostly skip a discussion
In this section, I provide a brief survey of the vast literature on cross-sectional return pre-
dictability. I focus on the most common categories of return predictors. Most studies in this
literature assess predictability relative to standard linear factor models of the SDF, such as
the CAPM, consumption CAPM, or ad-hoc factor models as benchmark models. I discuss
The history of returns and trading volume of a stock is a natural place to look for return
predictors, and the data are easily accessible. In the practice of investment management,
One of the most studied predictability patterns in this area is the momentum effect
that entered the academic literature with Jegadeesh and Titman (1993). Jegadeesh and
Titman show that stocks with high returns over the past three to twelve months (winners)
outperform stocks with low recent returns (losers) over the next three to twelve months.
good earnings outperform those with unexpectedly bad earnings over the next six months
(Bernard and Thomas (1989)). Chan, Jegadeesh, and Lakonishok (1996) show that this
earnings momentum is related to, but partly distinct from, the price momentum effect. Lee
and Swaminathan (2000) show that stocks with high trading volume have low future returns
6
Over longer horizons, in contrast, returns have a tendency to mean-revert, as shown in
DeBondt and Thaler (1985) and DeBondt and Thaler (1987): Winners over the past three to
five years underperform losers. Jegadeesh and Titman (2001) find that the momentum effect
dies out after a holding period of about 12 months, and returns then start to revert at longer
holding periods.
Vuolteenaho (2000) and Cohen, Polk, and Vuolteenaho (2003) build on the log-linear present
value model of Campbell and Shiller (1988) to formulate a present-value relationship in terms
of the book-to-market (B/M ) ratio. They start with the clean-surplus accounting relation
where rt denotes the log stock return, and yt log(1 + Yt /Bt1 ) is the log return on equity
Thus, holding fixed expectations of future ROE, expected returns must be low if bm is
low. Holding fixed current bm, high expected ROE implies high expected returns. This
motivates the use of bm and expected profitability, preferably jointly, as return predictors.
Of course, expected returns do not necessarily have to vary across stocks. If they do not,
variation across stocks in bm reflects either future profitability or the approximation error
in (6). But if they do vary, bm and/or expected ROE should be correlated with expected
returns.
As (6) is simply an approximate accounting identity, it does not shed light on the struc-
4
If the firm also engages in equity issues or repurchases, yt must be modified to include growth in per-share
book value of equity due to the issuance or repurchase activity (Ohlson (2005)). Equity issues at B/M < 1
or repurchases at B/M > 1 both raise the per-share book value of equity.
7
tural drivers of cross-sectional variation in expected returns. It does not matter whether
priced risk under rational expectations, learning effects, or sentiment drive the variation in
expected returns. The conclusion that bm and expected profitability should predict returns
The use of valuation ratios like B/M in return prediction has a long history in finance.
Fama and French (1992) reexamine the evidence and confirm that stocks with low market
capitalization (small firm premium) and high B/M (value premium) earn higher expected
returns. They find that firm size and B/M absorb the predictive role of the earnings-to-price
ratio. Other researchers examine B/M jointly with current profitability measures as proxies
for expected future profitability. Haugen and Baker (1996) document that ROE positively
predicts returns controlling for B/M and various other return predictors. Vuolteenaho (2002)
shows that recent returns, ROE, and B/M jointly predict returns. Given the approximate
accounting identity, it is not all that surprising that valuation ratios like B/M and profitabil-
ity variables are positively related to future returns. The more interesting bit is the failure
of standard models of risk and return to explain this cross-sectional variation in returns.
Current ROE may not be the best predictor of future ROE. For example, some sub-
components of current profitability may help predict future profitability better than others.
Sloan (1996) decomposes earnings into cash earnings and accruals. He finds that firms with
a high accruals have low future profits and abnormally low future returns. Hirshleifer, Hou,
Teoh, and Zhang (2004) argue that net operating assets summarize the cumulative history
of non-cash earnings and provide a better predictor of future earnings than single-period ac-
cruals. They find that net operating assets strongly predict future returns. Fama and French
(2006) employ a variety of accounting variables, past stock returns, and analyst earnings
forecasts that help forecast future earnings and they show that these variables also predict
returns. Novy-Marx (2012a) argues that gross profits (revenues minus cost of goods sold) are
a good predictor of future earnings, and he finds that gross profitability is strongly positively
8
Some researchers have used valuation ratios, profitability measures, and other accounting
variables to construct a summary measure of financial distress and find that distressed stocks
have abnormally low returns (Dichev (1998) and Griffin and Lemmon (2002)). Campbell,
Hilscher, and Szilagyi (2008) report a similar finding within a distress-prediction framework
that also employs price-based variables such as lagged returns and volatility.
Theories of firms investment and financing can provide further insights about potential pre-
related to expected profitability and negatively related to discount rates and hence future
stock returns. Li, Livdan, and Zhang (2009) provide a recent exposition of this mechanism.
Titman, Wei, and Xie (2004), Fama and French (2006), Anderson and Garcia-Feijoo (2006),
and Li, Livdan, and Zhang (2009) find evidence consistent with this prediction.
High-investment firms are also likely to raise external financing, while firms with low
investment rates distribute capital to investors. As a result, discount rates are also negatively
related to external financing (see, e.g., Li, Livdan, and Zhang (2009)). Consistent with this
prediction, Daniel and Titman (2006), Fama and French (2008), and Pontiff and Woodgate
(2008) construct measures of net equity issuance activity and find a negative relationship to
High levels of investment and external financing also translate into higher growth. There-
fore, one would expect a negative association between growth and future returns. Lakonishok,
Shleifer, and Vishny (1994) document a negative relation between past sales growth and re-
turns. Cooper, Gulen, and Schill (2008) look at growth in total assets and find a negative
Investment and growth are also related to accruals. Fairfield, Whisenant, and Yohn (2003)
argue that high-growth firms tend to be high-accrual firms, suggesting that the relationship
between accruals and expected returns of Sloan (1996) may be a growth effect. Lewellen
9
and Resutek (2012) however show that investment, external financing, and accruals all have
While q-theory is useful for identifying potential cross-sectional predictors of returns, the
theory is silent about the reasons why investors price stocks to have different expected rates
of return. The evidence that investment- and financing-related variables predict returns does
not reveal whether priced risk under rational expectations, investor learning, or sentiment are
the drivers of the discount rates that firms face in financial markets and that they respond
Theories in which idiosyncratic volatility plays a role in pricing typically predict a positive
relation between idiosyncratic volatility and expected returns. For example, in Merton (1987)
a positive relationship arises because investors are imperfectly diversified and demand com-
pensation for bearing idiosyncratic volatility. Empirically, Ang, Hodrick, Xing, and Zhang
(2006) find the opposite result: stocks with high idiosyncratic volatility have extremely low
returns. Huang, Liu, Rhee, and Zhang (2010) caution that this idiosyncratic volatility effect
seems to be driven by the return reversals known to exist in one-month returns (Jegadeesh
(1990)). Idiosyncratic volatility is also one of the variables used in the distress-prediction
model of Campbell, Hilscher, and Szilagyi (2008) and the sign of the effect in their frame-
2.5 Seasonality
One puzzling feature of cross-sectional return predicability is that it is subject to strong sea-
sonality. Novy-Marx (2012b) offers an updated view based on recent data. He documents that
many of the cross-sectional return predictors reviewed in this section have a strong January
seasonal: size and value effects, for example, are concentrated in January, while momentum
10
survey is silent about the source of this seasonality.
Most empirical studies in cross-sectional asset pricing employ (log-)linear factor representa-
tions of the SDF. In this section, I review the canonical models that appear in most empirical
work, while Section 4 looks at recent efforts to improve these models. The work reviewed
Typically, the SDF specifications in cross-sectional asset pricing studies are special cases of
the SDF that arises in a representative-agent framework in which the representative investor
has the preferences proposed by Epstein and Zin (1989), Epstein and Zin (1991), and Weil
mt+1 = log ct+1 + ( 1)rw,t+1 , (7)
where rw,t+1 log(Wt+1 /(Wt Ct )) is the log return on wealth, ct+1 log(Ct+1 /Ct ) is
intertemporal substitution, and is a relative risk aversion parameter. With power utility,
As Giovannini and Weil (1989) show, if the state vector is identically and independently
11
Conditional CAPMs. In (8) and (9), the price of risk, controlled by the parameter , is
constant over time, which is why these models are often referred to as an unconditional
coefficients,
This is a conditional consumption CAPM. For example, in the external habit model of Camp-
bell and Cochrane (1999), xt is the surplus-consumption ratio and 0t and ct are nonlinear
is also frequently applied in empirical work, but the theoretical motivation is less clear in this
case. One possibility is that investors myopically maximize, period by period, their expected
utility of next-period wealth. In this case, 0 (xt ) = 0 and w (xt ) = (xt ), where (xt ) is a
variance. If we combine a log-linear factor model mt+1 = 0t ft 0 ft+1 with the assumption
that rit+1 and ft+1 are conditionally jointly normal, evaluation of the log of the conditional
1 2
Et [rit+1 ] + it = 0t + it0 t , (12)
2
where 0t 0t + ft 0 ft 12 ft 0 t ft , it 1 f
t Covt (rit+1 , ft+1 ), t Et [ft+1 ], t is the
conditional covariance matrix of ft+1 with a vector t2 of factor variances on the diagonal, and
t t ft are the factor risk premia. If a conditionally risk-free asset exists with time t + 1
log return rtf , and ft represents log returns on traded assets, we can apply the conditional
12
pricing relation to the risk-free asset and the factors themselves and solve for 0t and ft :
1
0t = rtf + ft 0 ft ft 0 t ft , (13)
2
f 1 f f 1
t = t (t rt + t2 ), (14)
2
1 2 1
Et [rit+1 ] + it = rtf + it0 (ft rtf + t2 ). (15)
2 2
The relations (13) and (14) highlight that 0t and ft have important implications for the
time-series dynamics of returns: they control the conditional risk-free rate and conditional
risk premia. While estimation of linear factor models in cross-sectional asset pricing studies
often focuses on cross-sectional pricing implications, it is important to keep in mind that the
(11), carry out a (conditional) first-order Taylor approximation, and normalize the SDF by
Applying this SDF to the pricing restriction for excess returns, Et [Mt+1 (Rt+1 Rtf )] = 0, we
which is approximately identical to (15), especially for returns measured over short horizons.
13
framework, even though some of the original studies use the linearized SDF (16) applied to
simple returns.
Mimicking portfolios. The pricing implications of the SDF remain unchanged if we replace
non-traded factors by their (conditional) projection on the test asset returns. More precisely,
in the log-normal setting the projection is on the log returns of test assets, and on simple
The failure of the (consumption) CAPM to explain cross-sectional return predictability has
prompted some researchers to resort to ad-hoc factor models. The motivation for this ap-
proach is the insight that risk factors in the SDF can be replaced by their mimicking portfolios.
The most prominent example is the Fama and French (1993) three-factor model, in which the
SDF is specified as a linear function of a market index return, RM , the difference in returns
between portfolios of small and large stocks, SM B, and the difference in returns between
portfolios of high and low B/M stocks, HM L. Fama and French (1993) show that this model
SM B and HM L are constructed from portfolios that span the very same expected return
spreads along the size and B/M dimensions that the model is trying to explain. Is the model
therefore tautological? Not entirely. The economic content in Fama and French (1993) is in
the finding that the three factors explain not only cross-sectional, but also most of the time-
series variation in the size and B/M portfolios, with time-series R2 in excess of 90%. This
shows that small firms returns, for example, correlate a lot more strongly with almost-small
firms returns than with large firms returns. However, given this strong co-movement, it is
not surprising that expected returns of small firms are similar to those of almost-small firms
and value stocks expected returns are similar to those of almost-value stocks in the way
captured by the factor model; otherwise a near-arbitrage opportunity would arise. Absence
14
of near-arbitrage opportunities arises in any model under minimal restrictions on preferences
and beliefs (e.g., as in Ross (1976) and Cochrane and Saa-Requejo (2000)), and these weak
restrictions hold in (plausible) models of sentiment and models of learning just as well as in
rational expectations models. Therefore, the fact that the Fama-French model explains size
and B/M returns does not discriminate between these competing explanations.
Fama and French (1993) suggest that SM B and HM L could mimick pervasive priced
macroeconomic risk factors. If so, then SM B and HM L should explain other features of the
cross-section of expected returns, too, not just size and B/M effects. Fama and French (1996)
argue that this is the case because the three-factor model also explains the expected return
However, all of these variables are closely related to B/M . The one anomaly in their tests
The empirical evidence accumulated since Fama and French (1996) suggests that there
are other important sources of cross-sectional variation in expected returns unrelated to the
have predictive power after adjusting for exposure to the Fama-French factors. To name a
few, the idiosyncratic volatility anomaly (Ang, Hodrick, Xing, and Zhang (2006)), the net
equity issuance effect (Daniel and Titman (2006)), and the predictability associated with
gross-profitability (Novy-Marx (2012a)) are all present after risk-adjusting returns with the
of expected returns that combines many known predictors and his portfolios exhibit large
Judging from this evidence, the Fama-French factors seem to be a convenient way of
summarizing the size and value effects, but not more than that. To capture other dimensions
(1997) adds a momentum factor to the Fama-French model. Novy-Marx (2012a) proposes a
gross-profitability factor. Hou, Xue, and Zhang (2012) construct a four-factor model with a
15
market factor, a size factor, an investment factor, and an ROE factor. The use of profitability-
models discussed above in Sections 2.2 and 2.3. Of course, one must keep in mind that present-
value relationships and q-theory do not answer the question why investors price stocks to have
Much of the early empirical work on size and value premia had been carried out with one-
factor models,
in which the price of risk is constant. This raises the question whether the unexplained size
and value premia could simply reflect the fact that researchers ignored time-varying prices of
To implement tests of conditional factor models, we need to specify the relevant state
variables xt and their functional relationship with the SDF coefficients 0t and ft . Jagan-
nathan and Wang (1996), Cochrane (1996), and Lettau and Ludvigson (2001), and a large
number of subsequent papers (see the references in Lewellen and Nagel (2006)) (LN) examine
models in which the coefficients are linear in the state variables. Applied to our log-linear
Thus, the conditional one-factor model has been turned into an unconditional multi-factor
model.6 Although intuitively appealing, this route turned out to be less fruitful than it
initially seemed.
To see why, suppose that a conditional one-factor model mt+1 = 0t ft ft+1 is the true
6
The xt term should not be regarded as a risk factor, though, because it is pre-determined. As a conse-
quence, under the restrictions of the model, it plays no role in generating cross-sectional variation in expected
returns.
16
model, but a researcher applies a constant-price-of-risk model like (18). How big is the pricing
error that results from this misspecification? Lewellen and Nagel (2006) (LN) perform these
calculations for a linearized SDF applied to simple returns. Here I show similar calculations
1 2
Et [rit+1 ] rtf + it = Covt (rit+1 , ft+1 )ft . (20)
2
Taking unconditional expectations and noting that the expected conditional covariance equals
1
E[rit+1 ] E[rtf ] + E[it
2
] = Cov(rit+1 , ft+1 ft )E[ft ] + Cov{Covt (rit+1 , ft+1 ), ft } (21)
2
The first term on the RHS is the result that one would obtain with the constant-price-of-risk
model (18). Even if conditional betas and the factor risk premium t = f t2 are time-
varying, an unconditional beta representation holds as long as the price of risk is constant.
Only if the price of risk varies over time and is correlated with the conditional covariance of
returns and the factor, the second term on the RHS introduces a wedge between the pricing
implications for unconditional expected returns of the true conditional factor model and the
How big could Cov{Covt (rit+1 , ft+1 ), ft } be for a value minus growth portfolio? Con-
sider the case of the conditional CAPM where f is a market index log return. To maxi-
mize time-variation in the price of risk, consider the case in which all time-variation in the
Cov{Covt (rit+1 , ft+1 ), ft } = Cov(it , t ). To get an upper bound, consider the case in which
it and t are perfectly correlated. As LN point out, plausible values for the standard de-
7
Evidence from ICAPM and long-run risks models reviewed below in Section 4 suggest that conditional
factor volatility drives at least part of time-variation in factor risk premia. This would imply lower time-
variation in ft and smaller Cov{Covt (rit+1 , ft+1 ), ft }.
17
viation of it for a value-growth spread portfolio are around 0.30. Predictive regressions or
calibrated models of time-varying risk premia like Campbell and Cochrane (1999) suggest
a standard deviation of t of at most 0.5% monthly. Thus, an upper bound for the wedge
amounts to 0.15% monthly, or less than 2% in annualized termsmuch less than the empir-
ically observed value-growth spread of 0.50% monthly. If the correlation of it and t takes
a more realistic value substantially closer to zero, the gap to the observed value premium
becomes even bigger. Therefore, if the constant-price-of-risk version of the CAPM of the
form (18) fails to explain the value premium, it is not plausible that the conditional CAPM
can explain it. A similar logic applies in the case with a non-traded factor, as in the con-
sumption CAPM, but there it is the covariance between conditional consumption betas and
This reasoning leadsseeminglyto a puzzle. Studies like Jagannathan and Wang (1996)
and Lettau and Ludvigson (2001) use an SDF of the form (19) and find a dramatic improve-
ment in explanatory power for the cross-section of stock returns compared with an uncon-
ditional one-factor model. The key to reconciling these findings is to note that LNs anal-
ysis takes into account the models implications for the time-series dynamics of conditional
moments: according to theory, for a significant wedge to exist between the unconditional
expected return predictions of the conditional factor model and its constant-price-of-risk ver-
sion, Cov(it , t ) must be big. In contrast, if the model is fit to a cross-section of expected
returns, without taking into account conditional moment restrictions, this restriction is ig-
of conditional moments, via (13) and (14), that are completely out of line with the data.
Nagel and Singleton (2011) illustrate this gap between implied and empirical dynamics of
conditional moments in the case of the conditional consumption CAPM. They show that the
cross-sectional estimates of ft can be more than an order of magnitude too volatile compared
with models that feature strong, but plausible, time-variation in risk premia, like Campbell
8
In a finite sample, by estimating E[Mt+1 Rt+1 ] = 1 via GMM, or in a two-pass regression where, in the
second stage, average returns of the test portfolios are regressed on their factor betas.
18
and Cochrane (1999).
There is a further rather mechanical reason why fitting the unconditional versions (19) of
conditional factor modelsor in fact any multi-factor modelto the cross-section of expected
returns yields small pricing errors for certain types of test portfolios. Most studies that test
models of the form (19) use size and B/M portfolios as test assets. For these portfolios,
three factors explain almost all the time-series and cross-sectional variation in returns: the
market factor, SMB, and HML (Fama and French (1993)). Thus, within the log-normal
e
framework here, we can write the log excess returns, rt+1 rt+1 rtf + 12 E[it
2 ], on N test
assets approximately as
where B is a N K factor loading matrix, pet is a K-dimensional vector of log excess returns
on the factors underlying the test asset returns (the Fama-French factors, with K = 3, in the
case of the size- and B/M -sorted test portfolios ), and the residual et is uncorrelated with pet .
Now consider the application of a model like (19), which we can write as mt+1 = 0 0 ft+1 ,
where ft is uncorrelated with et and has dimension J = 3. The N J matrix of betas with
0
= BCov(pet+1 , ft+1 )1 (23)
where is the covariance matrix of f. Note that the betas on the proposed factors are
section of E[rte ] = BE[pet ] as well as B, namely perfectly, irrespective of the nature of the
proposed factors pe .9 That explains the cross-section of expected returns therefore has
little economic content. It just re-discovers the fact that the test asset returns have a low-
9
As long as the correlation between the elements of pet and ft is not exactly zero. Lewellen, Nagel, and
Shanken (2010) also analyze more general settings in which J < K and in which ft can be correlated with et .
19
dimensional factor structure and that the proposed factors f are uncorrelated with residuals
e. This is the point made in Lewellen, Nagel, and Shanken (2010) (LNS) (see also Daniel and
Titman (2012)). In many existing tests of models of the type (19), the number of proposed
factors is J = 3 and so the small pricing errors and high cross-sectional R2 emphasized in
Shanken (1985), and Hansen and Jagannathan (1997), adjust for the low-dimensional fac-
tor structure in test asset returns. These tests are correctly sized under the null hypoth-
esis that the model is correctly specified. However, a low-dimensional factor structure can
create a power problem. When the magnitude of the pricing errors is small due to the
low-dimensionality problem, these tests have little power to reject a false model. Moreover,
researchers often intentionally focus on R2 -type measures of model performance rather than
these specification tests to highlight the magnitude of pricing errors on economically inter-
esting portfolios, rather than linear combinations of portfolios formed based on statistical
considerations (Cochrane (1996)). Alas, if the test asset portfolios have a low-dimensional
factor structure, R2 -type measures are not economically informative. To make the tests more
moment conditions that are used to estimate and evaluate the model.
LNS discuss several avenues to enhance the informativeness of the tests. For example, one
can expand the set of test portfolios to include assets that do not share the low-dimensional
factor structure of size and B/M portfolios. LNS add industry portfolios and find a dramatic
deterioration in the cross-sectional fit of several previously proposed models of the type (19)
If factors of a proposed model are traded, a second possibility is to exploit the fact that
theory links the prices of risk, via (13) and (14), to expected excess returns of the factors.
20
This implies additional moment conditions for the factors themselves. Within our log-normal
e
E[rt+1 ] = (24)
e
E[ft+1 ] = . (25)
To what extent estimation pays attention to the additional restriction (25) depends on the
estimator that is employed. A two-pass regression estimator where the second stage regresses
e
the sample average of rt+1 e
and ft+1 on first-stage estimates of betas with OLS may pay little
attention to (25). In contrast, maximum likelihood (ML), as in Shanken (1992), enforces (25)
with a GMM estimator of a linearized SDF as in (16) and moment conditions for excess
returns E[Mt+1 (Rt+1 Rtf )] = 0. A GMM estimator with an identity weighting matrix may
put very little weight on the moment condition for the factor excess return, while an efficient
estimator with the optimal weighting matrix of Hansen (1982) enforces perfect pricing of the
factor asymptotically.11 Thus, inclusion of (25) among the moment conditions combined with
the use of efficient estimation methods is likely to enhance the informativeness of the tests.12
Empirical work in cross-sectional asset pricing typically works with unconditional moment
restrictions for estimation and evaluation, but conditional moment restrictions can enhance
the informativeness of tests. This enhancement is especially relevant for conditional factor
models. The time-varying prices of risk in these models imply strong predictions about the
time-variation of conditional risk premia. It seems useful to ask whether these time-series
10
ML is Pasymptotically equivalent to a time-series regression of rte on fte , which automatically imposes
= (1/T ) Tt=1 ft+1
e
(Gibbons, Ross, and Shanken (1989)), or a GLS cross-sectional regression which does
the same (Shanken (1992)).
11
This can be seen by noting that the asymptotic weighting matrix S 1 is proportional to the inverse of the
covariance matrix of the residuals in a regression of returns on factors (see, e.g., the appendix of Jagannathan
and Wang (2002)). If the factor is included among the test asset returns, the corresponding element of the
residual vector has zero variance, and hence S 1 1 puts infinite weight on pricing the factor perfectly.
12
For non-traded factors, this approach is not available. One might think that replacing non-traded factors
with mimicking portfolios might help, but this does not address the problem. One can show that if test asset
returns follow (22), K = J, and ft is uncorrelated with et , the mimicking portfolio always price the test assets
perfectly even if the mimicking factor risk premia are restricted to be equal to their expected excess returns.
21
predictions are in line with the data. With traded factors, Lewellen and Nagel (2006) show
that this can be done by utilizing higher frequency data (e.g., daily returns), and estimating
a factor model as a time-series regression within short time windows (e.g., quarters). The
idea is that conditional betas and the conditional market risk premium (co-)vary very little
within a short time window, so a time-series regression within a short window produces ap-
proximately unbiased estimates of conditional betas and conditional alphas. The conditional
factor model can then be tested by examining whether the average of the (noisy) short-
window alpha estimates is significantly different from zero. Based on this method, LN find
that the conditional CAPM fails to explain the size and value premia. Ang and Kristensen
(2012) refine this approach by using a more general non-parametric estimation methodology
(LNs estimator is a special case of theirs) and they find similar results.
instruments and working with the moment conditions (2). But which instruments should
we use? Even if we fix the set of random variables that we want to condition on, there is
still an infinite number of ways to construct the instruments and to choose the number of
moment conditions, as any function of At -measurable random variables is a valid and feasible
instrument. Some instruments may enhance the informativeness of the moment conditions,
while others may add little information over and above the unconditional moment restrictions.
Nagel and Singleton (2011) build on Hansen (1985) and Chamberlain (1987) to implement
Nagel and Singleton examine several scaled consumption CAPMs of the form (19) and find
that these models are unable to fit the cross-sectional and time-series dimension of the data
In summary, the conditional factor models that seem to do so well in explaining the cross-
section of unconditional expected returns on size and B/M portfolios struggle to explain the
data when additional moment conditions are brought inas one would expect, given the
discussion in Section 3.3. More generally, these results highlight that researchers must be
22
careful to choose moment conditions that can be informative about the economic explanatory
power of a model.
As the conditional factor model route proved to be less fruitful than it initially seemed, other
approaches to enhance standard specifications of the SDF have recently received more atten-
tion. A number of recent papers work with the general version of the Epstein-Zin-Weil SDF
(7). They obtain empirically implementable models by making additional assumptions about
the observability of wealth portfolio returns (ICAPM) or about the dynamics of consumption
(long-run risks). I also review work that links asset prices to the first-order conditions of
The Epstein-Zin-Weil SDF (7) features a consumption growth factor. As consumption is no-
could perhaps improve the empirical performance of the model. Campbell (1993) shows that
the intertemporal budget constraint can be used to substitute out consumption. Recent work
by Campbell, Giglio, Polk, and Turley (2012) extends this approach to a setting with con-
ditional heteroskedasticity. The intertemporal budget constraint implies that the log return
on wealth follows
w
rt+1 = at + ct+1 + vt+1 , (26)
where at log((Wt Ct )/Ct ) and vt+1 log(Wt+1 /Ct+1 ). Campbell et al. further approxi-
mate vt+1 + at+1 , where takes a value close to one. Using this approximation in (26)
23
and substituting into the log Epstein-Zin-Weil SDF (7) yields
w
mt+1 = log + at + at+1 rt+1 . (27)
Assuming that asset returns and consumption growth are conditionally jointly log-normal
and applying the conditional pricing restriction Et [Mt+1 Rt+1 ] = 1 with the SDF (27) to the
return on wealth allows solving forward for at . Substituting this result for at+1 in (27) and
cf dr 1 risk
mt+1 = gt Nt+1 + Nt+1 + Nt+1 (28)
2
where
X
dr
Nt+1 (Et+1 Et ) j rt+1+j
w
, (29)
j=1
cf w w dr
Nt+1 rt+1 Et [rt+1 ] + Nt+1 , (30)
X
risk
Nt+1 (Et+1 Et ) j Vart+j (mt+1+j + rt+1+j
w
). (31)
j=1
Thus, one obtains a conditional three-factor model that represents a discrete-time version
of the intertemporal CAPM (ICAPM) of Merton (1973). The N dr and N risk factors reflect
the exposure of the SDF to changes in investment opportunities in the form of news about
expected returns and news about risk, respectively. N cf represents news about expected cash
Campbell and Vuolteenaho (2004) (CV) investigate the homoskedastic version of (28)
risk is zero, as in Campbell (1993). Empirical implementation of the model requires
where Nt+1
forecasts. They find that the high market beta of growth stocks in the post-1963 period arises
largely from a strong negative loading on discount-rate shocks, while value stocks have higher
24
cash-flow betas (see, also, Bansal, Dittmar, and Lundblad (2005)). With > 1, cash-flow
risks carry a higher risk premium than discount-rate risks, resulting in a value premium.
When evaluating the fit of their model, CV take into account the fact that the ICAPM
restricts the risk prices in (28) to be a function of only one parameter (). Incorporating
this restriction in the empirical estimation helps to avoid the problems associated with a
low-dimensional factor structure in test asset returns that I reviewed in Section 3.4.
Campbell, Giglio, Polk, and Turley (2012) investigate the full heteroskedastic version of
(28) (Brennan, Wang, and Xia (2004) empirically analyze a related model). Campbell et
al. assume a one-factor structure of volatility shocks. In this case the conditional variances
that enter N risk are proportional to the common volatility factor. In the post-1963 sample,
they find that value stocks have small positive exposure to these volatility shocks, but the
exposure of growth stocks is much bigger. The positive correlation of equity returns with
volatility shocks is counter-intuitive, but since volatility shocks have a negative price of risk,
Overall, the ICAPM shows some promise for explaining the cross-section of expected
returns, but some challenges remain. VAR dynamics are subject to substantial estimation
uncertainty, and empirical results differ to some extent across plausible specifications of in-
vestment opportunity dynamics (see Chen and Zhao (2009) and Bansal, Kiku, Shaliastovich,
and Yaron (2012)). A second challenge is that the dynamics of investment opportunities es-
timated by the VAR may not be internally consistent with the model. The Epstein-Zin-Weil
SDF implies equilibrium restrictions on the joint time-series dynamics of risk premia and
volatility that are ignored in an unrestricted VAR. Taking these unrestricted VAR dynamics
as exogenously given, an Epstein-Zin-Weil investor would want to time the market, while
the ICAPM implementation of Campbell et al. assumes that the investor holds 100% of
wealth in the market portfolio of risky assets. Holding a market-timing portfolio would in
turn change the investors view about the riskiness of value and growth stocks. Bansal, Kiku,
Shaliastovich, and Yaron (2012) explore a specification in which the market risk premium is
25
linear in the conditional variance of the market return, which is a step (albeit not a complete
one) towards reconciling the dynamics of investment opportunities with the model.
While the ICAPM approach is motivated by the notion that returns on wealth may be easier
to observe than consumption, one can also make the argument that the wealth portfolio
return may be difficult to observe because many important components of wealth are traded
in markets subject to severe frictions (e.g., housing), or not traded at all (e.g., human capital).
If one follows this argument, then substituting out the wealth return rather than consumption
Using (26) to substitute out the wealth return from the log Epstein-Zin-Weil SDF (7)
yields
Applying this SDF to the conditional pricing restriction Et [Mt+1 Rt+1 ] = 1 for the wealth
return and substituting for the wealth return in the conditional expectation (but not the
variance) using (26), one can solve forward for at . Substituting the result into (32) for at+1
1
sc 1 lc 1 risk
mt+1 = gt Nt+1 ( )Nt+1 + N , (33)
2 1 t+1
where
sc
Nt+1 ct+1 Et [ct+1 ], (34)
X
lc
Nt+1 (Et+1 Et ) j ct+1+j , (35)
j=1
and N risk is defined as before in (31). Restoy and Weil (2011) derive the homoskedastic
26
version of (33) without N risk . If > 1/, assets earn a positive risk premium for positive
lc . Bansal and Yaron (2004)
correlation with shocks to long-run consumption growth, Nt+1
label this risk as long-run risk and they propose that consumption growth contains a small
highly persistent component that makes this risk relevant for asset pricing.
Consistent with a premium for long-run risk, Parker and Julliard (2005) find that the
covariance of stock returns with future consumption growth several years ahead is positively
related to B/M and negatively related to size, which helps explain the cross-section of average
returns on size and B/M portfolios. Liew and Vassalou (2000) find that the Fama-French
size and B/M factors help predict GDP growth at an annual horizon, which also points in
this direction. Hansen, Heaton, and Li (2008) find similar results with a different approach
to measuring long-run risk. Bansal, Kiku, and Yaron (2007) assume a parametric model
for consumption growth with a small highly persistent component and stochastic volatility.
They show that N lc and N risk can be constructed empirically by projecting consumption
growth and squared consumption innovations on the markets price-dividend ratio and the
risk-free rate. Their model has a somewhat harder task than the ICAPM, because it links
consumption dynamics and asset returns in an internally consistent fashion. The model
explains part of the value and size premia during the 1930 to 2002 period, but it leaves a
substantial portion unexplained. Standard errors are big because the long-run consumption
These problems in estimating long-run consumption dynamics raise some doubts about
the merit of the rational expectations assumption in these models. Similar concerns arise
in the ICAPM, where the long-run dynamics of discount rates are difficult to pin down. As
Hansen, Heaton, and Li (2008) emphasize, if econometricians struggle to pin down these
long-run dynamics, it is a leap of faith to endow agents with knowledge of the parameters of
ing, parameter uncertainty, and model uncertainty seems particularly relevant for models
27
Johannes, and Lochstoer (2012) show that learning could be the source of long-run risk: a
Bayesian agent learning about a constant consumption growth rate is aware that her subjec-
tive beliefs about the mean growth rate evolve as a martingale, and thus perceives long-run
risk.
While the consumption-based asset-pricing model links the SDF to consumers marginal rate
of substitution state by state, production-based models link the SDF to producers marginal
rate of transformation (Cochrane (1991)). This raises the prospect that one could recover the
SDF from (possibly better measured) macroeconomic data on the production side without
not allow the marginal rate of transformation to vary across states, which makes recovery of
The model of Belo (2010) is an exception. Belo specifies a production function that allows
producers to move productivity across states, and he works out how to empirically recover
the SDF as a function of industry-level production variables from the producer first-order
conditions, without any assumptions about consumer preferences. He finds that this SDF
technology, access to financial markets, and they trade to remove arbitrage opportunities be-
I ]=1
tween physical investment and financial markets, then the pricing equation Et [Mt+1 Rt+1
holds for physical investment returns RI in the same way it holds for stock returns. Just as
one can construct a pricing kernel by projecting M on securities returns (Hansen and Jagan-
nathan (1991)), one can construct one by projecting M on investment returns. Restricting
the number of physical investment returns to a few common factors, Cochrane arrives at an
ad-hoc factor model where the SDF is linear in two investment returns, approximated by
investment growth rates (private residential and non-residential investment). Li, Vassalou,
28
and Xing (2006) use a similar approach with a more disaggregated set of investment growth
rates. These ad-hoc factor models have some success in fitting the cross-section of stock
returns, but their economic content is limited. A test of these models really just tests the law
of one price under the inclusion of physical investment returns, combined with the ad-hoc
A third approach, pioneered by Berk, Green, and Naik (1999), is to exogenously fix an
SDF as a function of some aggregate shocks, and proceed to model the evolution of firms
asset composition and systematic risk. Berk et al. use a dynamic real options model in which
value firms consist of assets in place and growth options, while growth stocks are pure growth
1
mt+1 = rtf z2 z t+1 , (36)
2
where t+1 is also the only aggregate shock that affects firms assets-in-place cash flows,
while the value of growth options is additionally exposed to interest-rate shocks that have a
with the SDF, i.e., a higher systematic risk and expected return, than growth stocks. Carlson,
Fisher, and Giammarino (2004) work with a related model with a single source of aggregate
uncertainty. Zhang (2005) endogenizes firms cash flows and systematic risk in a competitive
industry equilibrium. Zhang also uses an SDF like (36), but with a time-varying loading on .
In his model, is the only source of aggregate uncertainty. Novy-Marx (2011) finds support
for the prediction implied by these models that operating leverage should be positively related
to expected returns.
Berk et al., Carlson et al., and Zhang argue that their models provide a rational ex-
planation for the value premium. This conclusion is not warranted. These models surely
produce interesting insights into the origins of firms systematic risk exposures, but these
models cannot shed light on the question whether the empirically observed cross-sectional
variation in expected returns reflects priced risk under rational expectations, the effects of
29
learning, or the effects of sentiment. The exogenous specification of an SDF like (36) does
not embody any economic assumptions other than no arbitrage combined with ad-hoc re-
strictions on the types of shocks that do and do not enter the SDF. That the no-arbitrage
restriction holds does not imply that the SDF reflects rational pricing. For example, in an
economy in which there is a single source of aggregate uncertainty, as in Zhang (2005), any
systematic effects of investor sentiment would also be driven by this single aggregate shock.
Consequently, under the econometricians objective probability measure, the SDF would also
take the form (36). Berk, Green, and Naik (1999) impose the ad-hoc restriction that the part
of the interest-rate shock uncorrelated with does not show up as a shock in the SDF. But
why dont investors care about that part of the shock? Are there rational reasons for them
not to care about it, or are they imperfectly rational in attaching a zero price of risk to this
shock?13 Without a structural model of consumer preferences and beliefs, the model cannot
A natural fourth approach is therefore to jointly model consumer preferences and the
production side in general equilibrium. In many cases, though, models that take this ap-
proach also imply that a conditional consumption CAPM or even a conditional CAPM holds,
which brings the models into conflict with the empirical evidence in section 3.5. For example,
Gomes, Kogan, and Zhang (2003) have a single aggregate shock in their model, and the mar-
ket portfolio is conditionally a perfectly correlated mimicking portfolio for consumption, and
hence the conditional CAPM holds (the same happens in Zhang (2005) and Carlson, Fisher,
and Giammarino (2004)). To get around these undesirable predictions, some researchers
have added additional sources of uncertainty to the model. For example, Papanikolaou
(2011) works with Epstein-Zin-Weil preferences and a production technology that is sub-
factor portfolio that mimicks the technological innovation shocks and which helps explain the
13
A similar assumption is made in Lettau and Wachter (2007). As Lettau and Wachter and Santos and
Veronesi (2010) point out, with external habit preferences like in Campbell and Cochrane (1999), the interest-
rate shock would appear in the SDF and lead to a growth premium rather than a value premium.
30
cross-section of average returns in the data.
The vast majority of empirical studies in cross-sectional asset pricing work within a log-
normal framework, either explicitly, by combining a log-linear SDF with the assumption of
joint log-normality of returns and the SDF, or implicitly, by applying a first-order Taylor
approximation to a non-linear SDF. This approach may fail to account for higher moments
and tail risks that investors care about. Recent work by Barro (2006) revived interest in the
Empirical work on the cross-sectional pricing implications of disaster risks is still in its
infancy. In principle, one can account for these in empirical work by applying non-linear esti-
mation methods (e.g., GMM) to Et [Mt+1 Rt+1 ] = 1 without linearizing the SDF or assuming
log-normality. Alternatively, one can include higher-order polynomial terms in the approxi-
mation. This is the approach taken by Harvey and Siddique (2000) and Dittmar (2002). To
the extent that tail risks are important, sample selection and the finite-sample distribution
the (per-capita) aggregate consumption of all consumers in the economy. In reality, not all
consumers participate in financial markets. Asset prices might reflect the consumption risks
of financial market participants, but not necessarily the consumption risk of non-participants.
To explore this idea, Mankiw and Zeldes (1991) construct a series of per-capita stockholder
consumption, and they show that with this series it is easier to explain the equity premium in
a consumption-based asset pricing model than with overall per-capita consumption because
stockholder consumption has a higher covariance with stock returns. Malloy, Moskowitz,
and Vissing-Jrgensen (2009) apply this idea to the cross-section of stock returns within a
31
long-run risks model in which the log SDF follows a homoskedastic version of (28). They
construct a stockholder consumption growth series from Consumer Expenditure Survey data
from 1982 to 2004. They are able to explain cross-sectional variation across size and B/M
portfolios with a much lower coefficient of relative risk aversion than with standard measures
not households. The idealized notion that agents optimally, frequently, and timely make
decisions according to their first-order conditions seems more likely to hold for financial
institutions than for households. Transaction costs, information costs, limited attention, and
behavioral biases on the part of households may reduce the informativeness of aggregate
consumption data about priced risks in financial markets. It therefore seems worthwhile to
From a financial institutions viewpoint, the definition of good and bad states of the world
likely depends on factors that are not well captured by aggregate consumption. One important
concern for financial institutions seems to be liquidity. This reasoning motivated Holmstrom
and Tirole (2001), Acharya and Pedersen (2005), and Brunnermeier and Pedersen (2009) to
propose models in which the SDF is liquidity-state-dependent. The notions of liquidity are
different in each of these models (the marginal value of liquidity services of tradeable assets in
c t
Mt+1 = Mt+1 . (37)
t+1
Augmenting the standard Epstein-Zin-Weil SDF (7) in this way yields, in logs,
mt+1 = log ct+1 + ( 1)rw,t+1 t+1 , (38)
32
where t+1 log(t+1 /t ). In this model, assets that pay off well in states in which
liquidity is scarce (low t+1 ) trade at a price premium and have a low expected return.
Pastor and Stambaugh (2003) construct an empirical liquidity factor by measuring the
(illiquidity-driven) tendency of individual stock returns to revert at daily frequency. They find
a substantial spread in average returns between stocks that load differently on their liquidity
factor and a liquidity-factor-mimicking portfolio helps explain the momentum effect (see,
also, Sadka (2006)). Acharya and Pedersen (2005) construct a liquidity factor by aggregating
individual stocks Amihud (2002) illiquidity ratios. Adrian, Etula, and Muir (2012) propose
broker-dealer leverage as a proxy for t+1 . Their rationale is that de-leveraging indicates
deteriorating funding conditions and high marginal utility for financial intermediaries. A
single-factor SDF with this variable as the only factor does remarkably well in explaining the
joint cross-section of average returns on size, B/M , momentum, and bond portfolios.
Frazzini and Pedersen (2011) consider an economy in which some investors are leverage-
constrained (see, also, Baker, Bradley, and Wurgler (2011)). In this model, t reflects
the weighted-average Lagrange multiplier on the leverage constraints. In their model, all
securities have the same covariance with t+1 . Applied to the CAPM special case of (38)
1 2 1 2
Et [rit+1 ] + it = rtf + t + it (Et [rt+1
w
] rtf t + it ) (39)
2 2
Thus, the zero-beta rate rtf + t is higher than rtf and the slope Et [rt+1
w ] r f + 1 2 of
t t 2 it
the risk-return tradeoff is flattened by t , as in Black (1972).14 Frazzini and Pedersen find
support for this prediction in a variety of international markets and asset classes.
With regards to leverage constraints, it is also worthwhile recalling the discussion of the
ICAPM in section 4.1. One unresolved problem in this literature is the assumption that the
investor whose Euler equation is used to price assets is assumed to be always fully invested
14
There is a wedge between the zero-beta rate and the risk-free rate in this model, because leverage-
constrained investors refrain from holding the risk-free asset and it is priced by unconstrained investors.
33
in the market portfolio, without timing the market, even though (exogenously specified)
investment opportunities are time-varying. Campbell, Giglio, Polk, and Turley (2012) point
out that one potential resolution could be to interpret the Euler equation as the first-order
condition of a leverage-constrained investor. The discussion here shows that this would likely
entail an additional factor in the SDF driven by the Lagrange multiplier on the constraint.
5 Sentiment
I now turn to empirical work on cross-sectional asset pricing that departs from the rational
tion of growth, underreaction, limited attention are examples of such departures. Common
to these approaches is that the SDF Mt+1 that reflects sentiment-driven investors marginal
utilities prices assets under subjective beliefs, i.e., EtS [Mt+1 Rt+1 ] = 1. Under objective beliefs,
t+1
Mt+1 = Mt+1 , (40)
t
where t is the Radon-Nikodym derivative of the subjective probability measure with respect
to the objective one. Thus, for the econometricianwho works with data generated under
the objective measurethe challenge is still the same as in rational expectations theories:
specify and test specifications of the SDF. The only difference is that with sentiment effects
present, the econometrician has to entertain the possibility that subjective beliefs enter Mt+1
through t+1 /t . These relationships between pricing under the subjective and objective
Part of the empirical literature has focused on ad-hoc factor models (as in the debate
between Daniel and Titman (1997) and Davis, Fama, and French (2000) about charac-
teristics versus covariances) or on theoretical models with reduced-form SDFs (see the
15
Differences in opinion could also arise under Bayesian learning with non-common priors
34
discussion in Section 4.3) to discriminate between risk-based and sentiment explanations
of cross-sectional return predictability. Yet, without taking a stand on some theoretical re-
strictions on M , these approaches cannot shed light on this question. For example, suppose
that mt+1 log(Mt+1 ) follows a linear one-factor model, and log(t+1 /t ) has one-factor
representation where the single factor reflects aggregate sentiment fluctuations. In this case
ad-hoc factor model perfectly explains expected returns, even though pricing is influenced by
sentiment.
sider an economy with two investors. Investor A holds subjective beliefs. As first-order con-
the risk exposures taken on by A (e.g., high exposure to assets that A is optimistic about).
B R
Investor B is a sophisticated arbitrageur with rational expectations, and Et [Mt+1 t+1 ] = 1
contrast, would reveal that it prices assets correctly under the objective measure, consistent
with a risk-based explanation. Of course, both the sentiment and risk-based explanations are
For sentiment to have price impact, some limits to arbitrage must exist that prevent so-
asset class in the same direction, there is a natural explanation: trading against sentiment
16
Gromb and Vayanos (2010) survey the theoretical literature on limits to arbitrage.
35
requires taking risky positions with undiversifiable risk. Sophisticated investors want to
be compensated for taking on such risk, which limits their willingness to trade aggressively
against sentiment. Many cross-sectional return predictability patterns offer fairly high Sharpe
Frictions could constitute an additional impediment. Pontiff (1996) shows that the market
values of closed-end fund shares are more likely to deviate from their net asset value if an
arbitrage strategy is subject to greater residual risk and to greater costs for initiating and
holding the position. In a similar vein, a number of recent papers find that various cross-
sectional return predictability patterns are stronger among stocks subject to such frictions.
Short-sale constraints are one example. They are most likely to be relevant among stocks
with low institutional ownership, because institutional investors, and especially passive ones,
are the most active lenders of stocks to short sellers. Based on this idea, Nagel (2005)
shows that cross-sectional return predictability based on several predictors, including B/M ,
is stronger among stocks with low institutional ownership (controlling for size).
Small stocks and stocks without analyst coverage are typically not attractive investments
for professional investors with big portfolios. Griffin and Lemmon (2002) find that the value
premium is bigger among these stocks, and Hong, Lim, and Stein (2000) report stronger
momentum effects. Campbell, Hilscher, and Szilagyi (2008) find that the distress anomaly is
stronger for stocks with low analyst coverage, institutional ownership, and liquidity.
volatility; see for example Ali, Hwang, and Trombley (2003) for B/M , Lipson, Mortal, and
Schill (2011) and Lam and Wei (2011) for the asset growth anomaly, Mendenhall (2004) for
the post-earnings announcement drift, and Mashruwala, Rajgopal, and Shevlin (2006) for
the accrual anomaly. These results could indicate that idiosyncratic risk acts as a deterrent
(2006)), but it is not clear whether this theory is quantitatively plausible. After all, strategies
36
5.2 Predicting Returns with Cross-Sectional Sentiment Proxies
Some researchers have developed proxy measures for investors subjective beliefs, with the
Diether, Malloy, and Scherbina (2011) and Chen, Hong, and Stein (2002) build on the idea
in Miller (1977) that if investors with divergent beliefs face short-sale constraints, prices are
set by optimists, while pessimists sit on the sidelines with zero positions. Greater divergence
of beliefs then implies greater overpricing and lower future returns. Diether et al. proxy for
investors belief dispersion with analyst forecast dispersion, while Chen et al. proxy for it
with the (lack of) breadth of mutual fund ownership of a stock. Both find support for the
La Porta (1996) uses analyst forecasts as a sentiment proxy and finds that stocks with
high forecasted growth perform poorly subsequently, especially around future earnings an-
nouncements, supporting the hypothesis of Lakonishok, Shleifer, and Vishny (1994) that the
value premium could arise from excessive extrapolation of firms past performance.
Teo and Woo (2004) proxy for investor sentiment with the returns of mutual funds in
small/large and growth/value styles. They find that high style returns in the past years pre-
dict low returns for stocks associated with these styles, consistent with the model of Barberis
and Shleifer (2003). Frazzini and Lamont (2008) identify stocks with positive sentiment as
those that are held by mutual funds that have recently received a lot of inflows. They show
that these stocks perform poorly in the future. Furthermore, positive-sentiment stocks tend
Lemmon and Portniaguina (2006) find that expected returns of small stocks and stocks
with low institutional ownership are low when the University of Michigan consumer senti-
37
ment index is high. Baker and Wurgler (2006) construct an index from several aggregate
sentiment proxies from the prior literature. They find that expected returns of stocks that
high volatility stocks) are most sensitive to sentiment. Stambaugh, Yu, and Yuan (2012) use
predictability patterns (most of those discussed in sections 2.2 and 2.3). They find that long-
short strategies constructed from these predictors have low returns following high aggregate
sentiment, and most of this time-variation comes from the short component of the portfolio,
consistent with a short-sale constraints explanation. It is noteworthy that none of these pa-
pers finds that the value premium can be predicted with aggregate sentiment proxies. An
exception is Ben-Rephael, Kandel, and Wohl (2012). They construct an aggregate sentiment
index from a measure of investor reallocation between equity and bond funds and find that
high sentiment predicts low returns most strongly among small stocks and growth stocks.
The above studies focus on directional measures of sentiment, but some researchers have
belief dispersion for individual stocks is highly sensitive to fluctuations in aggregate belief
dispersion for some stocks, and less for others, or if some stocks are more likely to be affected
dispersion from individual stock analyst forecasts and finds that high dispersion forecasts a
strong value premium. Hong and Sraer (2012) argue that high-beta stocks have the highest
(beta) and return arises only in times of low belief dispersion. In times of high dispersion, this
relationship follows an inverted U-shape. They find empirical support for these predictions.
This theory is an alternative (based on heterogeneity in beliefs) to the theory of Frazzini and
Pedersen (2011) (based on heterogeneity in risk aversion and leverage constraints) to explain
the low average returns of high beta stocks discussed in section 4.5.
38
5.4 Limited Attention
A different line of work examines whether cross-sectional return predictability could arise
from investors failure to pay timely attention to valuation-relevant pieces of information. Sims
and Peng and Xiong (2006) and Hirshleifer, Lim, and Teoh (2011) apply these ideas in models
of cross-sectional asset pricing. Sloan (1996) and Hirshleifer, Hou, Teoh, and Zhang (2004))
suggest limited attention as an explanation of the accrual anomaly: investors seem to pay
components.
attention to relatively complex information. DellaVigna and Pollet (2007) show that de-
mographic information can predict industry profitability far in the future, but the market
ity. Cohen and Frazzini (2008) examine economically linked firms and find that the market
does not fully incorporate these economic links when responding to news. Following a simi-
lar logic, Menzly and Ozbas (2010) find cross-industry return predictability for economically
linked industries. Cohen and Lou (2011) empirically categorize firms into complicated and
easy-to-analyze ones and find that the returns of easy-to-analyze firms predict the returns of
their more complicated peers. Belo, Gala, and Li (2012) document predictable variation in
Hou, Peng, and Xiong (2009) look at aggregate proxies of investor attention. They argue
that high trading volume and being in an up-market proxies for high investor attention,
and they find that earnings momentum (interpreted as underreaction) weakens with investor
39
6 Out-of-Sample Tests
The asset-pricing approaches that I have discussed so far may be too stark in their treatment
of beliefs. Rational expectations theories assume that investors act in equilibrium as if they
knew the specification and parameters of the equilibrium law of motion that generates the
data. This may be a useful benchmark, but real-world investors have to learn the data-
generating process. To the extent regimes change, parameters drift, and memory may get
lost, it is not clear how fast, if at all, this eventual convergence to rational expectations
happens. Sentiment theories on the other hand rest on the notion that investors have some
fixed biases and attention deficits. Real-world investors may indeed have biases and attention
deficits, but they are probably not be completely immune to learning either.
If investors learn and adapt, this has implications for cross-sectional return predictability
(see Lo (2004) for an exposition of this view). There are still many open questions about how
learning affects asset prices, and the body of empirical literature that deals with these issues
is still quite small. Nevertheless, some progress has been made. Much of this work employs
Out-of-sample tests can also help address data-snooping concerns. I review empirical
work that speaks to the data-snooping issue after the discussion of learning.
Intuitively, one might think that if learning is driving return predictability, this predictability
should not exist out of sample (where out of sample here is meant to be forward in time,
problem, consider the model of Lewellen and Shanken (2002) (LS). LS set up a model in which
a risk-neutral Bayesian investor observes dividends drawn from an IID normal distribution
with mean . The investor initially starts with a diffuse prior. The gross risk-free rate is
40
Combining this definition with the valuation relation Pt = Dt /(Rf 1) yields
e 1
Rt+1 = 1+ (Dt+1 Dt ). (41)
(t + 1)(Rf 1)
strategy that buys Dt units of the stock at t, financed at Rf , finds that it has an expected
return of
2
e 1
E[Rt+1 Dt ] = 1+ <0 (42)
(t + 1)(Rf 1) t
This trading strategy uses only information available in real time, and hence it is imple-
mentable out of sample, yet it earns non-zero expected returns. The reason is that the
econometricians evaluation of the population moment in (42) (or its large sample approx-
imation) uses information about that the investor does not have in real time (at time t
generally a suitable null hypothesis for testing whether return predictability is generated by
learning.
As the expression (42) shows, the magnitude of the trading strategys expected excess
return declines with the number of periods that the investor has learned the dividend process.
This time-decay could potentially provide a signature of learning that one could look for in
the data. The form of the time-decay will typically depend on the specifics of the process that
the investors are learning about, but the prediction that return predictability in out-of-sample
The learning problem faced by real-world investors may be of a somewhat different nature,
though. In Bayesian learning models, the agent can costlessly pay attention to any number
of variables that might be relevant (within the set of models entertained by the agent).
In practice, even sophisticated investors and their computer algorithms can pay attention
only selectively to a limited set of variables. Over time they may discover new ones, and they
41
form an opinion about their relevance. Schwartzstein (2012) provides a model that formalizes
this type of learning under selective attention. In his model, an agent pays attention to a
predictor z only with a certain probability that depends on the agents belief that z is an
important predictor. Eventually, as the agent updates the belief on the importance of z,
the agent will learn to pay attention to z, but the learning process may take a long time.
Applied to cross-sectional asset-pricing, learning under selective attention would mean that
(abnormal) return predictability associated with a predictor z can exist as long as investors
pay insufficient attention to z. Once attention picks up (for example, when an academic
study publicizes the predictive power of z), investors quickly incorporate z into their return-
forecasting models and the predictability associated with z disappears. Out-of-sample tests
that check for post-publication predictability can shed light on this type of learning.
A number of studies have examined whether the evidence for cross-sectional return pre-
dictability is weaker out of sample, subsequent to the publication of academic studies. Dimson
and Marsh (1999) find that the small-firm premium in the UK was not evident from 1989-
1997 after studies publicized the UK small firm premium. Schwert (2003) finds that the size
and value effects in the US disappeared during the 1994-2002 period. Green, Hand, and
Soliman (2011) find that the accrual anomaly has disappeared post publication. In contrast,
Jegadeesh and Titman (2001) find that momentum profits continued to exist in the years
One problem with these analyses is that the out-of-sample period is short, so it is difficult
ble remedy is to consider many return predictors simultaneously. McLean and Pontiff (2012)
study the post-publication return predictability associated with 82 characteristics that aca-
demic studies had identified. They estimate that the average decay in return predictability
is about 35%.
The studies above are true out-of-sample studies. They use data samples that were not
yet available to the researchers that published the original research. Decay in predictability
42
can also be studied with pseudo out-of-sample tests in which the researcher splits a data
sample into a training sample (used to estimate a predictive relationship) and a forecasting
sample (used to evaluate the predictive performance of the forecasting model). Haugen and
Baker (1996) use this approach and find substantial pseudo out-of-sample predictability for
a variety of predictors. Lewellen (2011) constructs a summary measure for expected returns
from 15 predictors. Using recursively expanding windows as training samples and a one-
month ahead horizon for forecasting samples, he finds a decay in predictive ability of about
20-30% compared with in-sample estimates. Cooper, Gutierrez, and Marcum (2005) find only
small out-of-sample predictability with a strategy that picks the best performing size, B/M ,
Qing (2011) find that momentum and turnover-related predictability is weaker among liquid
Overall, the evidence indicates that predictability tends to be somewhat weaker out of
sample, but, for most cross-sectional predictors, the predictability is still substantial, even
out of sample. To what extent the magnitude of the decay is consistent with learning is still
an open question.
problems in the original studies. Correlations between a predictor z found in sample could
reflect an in-sample correlation between z and noise rather than correlation of z with the
looking for predictors with significant predictive power, conventional procedures of statisti-
cal inference do not account for this specification search and hence overstate the statistical
significance. One approach to this problem is to adjust critical values of test statistics for
the specification search, as proposed in Lo and MacKinlay (1990) and White (2000), but im-
plementing these methods may be difficult when specification searches occur in an informal
43
manner or through sequential investigations by different researchers.
True out-of-sample tests can help address data-snooping concerns. If researchers found an
z and noise, there is no reason for the predictive relationship to exist in a data sample that
was not available to the researchers that published the initial results. In contrast, pseudo
out-of-sample tests are not a solution to the data-snooping problem, because researchers can
mine the data for significant pseudo out-of-sample predictability in the same way as it can
evidence exists for a number of cross-sectional predictors. Davis, Fama, and French (2000)
collect new accounting data and to construct B/M sorted portfolios prior to the 1960s and
they find a robust value premium. Dimson, Nagel, and Quigley (2003) do a similar exercise
to extend UK data back into the 1950s and they find a strong value premium. Other studies
have examined data from non-U.S. stock markets and confirmed the existence of a value
premium (Fama and French (1998)), momentum (Rouwenhorst (1998)), the idiosyncratic
volatility effect (Ang, Hodrick, Xing, and Zhang (2009)), the equity issuance effect (McLean,
Pontiff, and Watanabe (2009)), the asset growth anomaly (Watanabe, Yu, and Xu (2011))
and value and momentum effects in various asset classes internationally (Asness, Moskowitz,
and Pedersen (2012)). In contrast, Leippold and Lohre (2012) find that the accrual anomaly
is not a globally robust feature of stock returns. Thus, with few exceptions, the evidence
7 Concluding Remarks
1. A substantial body of evidence has now moved us beyond Fama and French (1996).
44
Empirical studies have found a number of robust cross-sectional return predictability
patterns that are not subsumed by size and B/M and by the Fama-French three-
factor model. For researchers using ad-hoc factor models as benchmarks in abnormal
return calculations, there is now little empirical justification for relying on the Fama-
French factors, rather than a factor model that incorporates these other sources of
2. Ad-hoc factor models are useful tools for summarizing the main dimensions of cross-
sectional return predictability, but they cannot be used to test risk-based rational ex-
restrictions on investor preferences, and hence on the risks that are relevant to investors,
empirical tests cannot discriminate between these competing explanations. The same
form SDF. Recent work on the ICAPM and long-run risk models that employs such
restrictions shows more promise to make progress on this question than the ad-hoc
begin with. First, in a market in which sentiment-driven investors trade with rational
investors, systematic sentiment can affect prices, yet rational investors first-order con-
recent empirical successes of the ICAPM could perhaps be interpreted in this way.
Second, theories of learning and adaptation fall neither into the rational expectations
nor the sentiment category. As real-world investors learn from data in similar ways
as econometricians do, these theories may deserve greater attention in the study of
45
about the performance of a model. In particular, fitting SDFs with time-varying prices
References
Acharya, V., and L. H. Pedersen. 2005. Asset Pricing with Liquidity Risk. Journal of
Adrian, T., E. Etula, and T. Muir. 2012. Financial Intermediaries and the Cross-Section
of Asset Returns. Working Paper, Northwestern University and Federal Reserve Bank
of New York.
Ali, A., L. S. Hwang, and M. A. Trombley. 2003. Arbitrage Risk and the Book-to Market
Amihud, Y. 2002. Illiquidity and Stock Returns: Cross-Section and Time-Series Effects.
Ang, A., R. J. Hodrick, Y. Xing, and X. Zhang. 2006. The Cross-Section of Volatility and
Ang, A., R. J. Hodrick, Y. Xing, and X. Zhang. 2009. High Idiosyncratic Volatility and Low
23.
Ang, A., and D. Kristensen. 2012. Testing conditional factor modelsJournal of Financial
Asness, C., T. Moskowitz, and L. H. Pedersen. 2012. Value and Momentum Everywhere.
46
Journal of Finance:forthcoming.
Baker, M., B. Bradley, and J. Wurgler. 2011. Benchmarks as Limits to Arbitrage: Under-
Baker, M., and J. Wurgler. 2006. Investor Sentiment and the Cross-Section of Stock Re-
Bansal, R., R. Dittmar, and C. Lundblad. 2005. Consumption, Dividends, and the Cross
Bansal, R., D. Kiku, I. Shaliastovich, and A. Yaron. 2012. Volatility, the Macro- economy
and Asset Prices. Working Paper, Duke University and University of Pennsylvania.
Bansal, R., D. Kiku, and A. Yaron. 2007. Risks for the Long Run: Estimation and Inference.
Bansal, R., and A. Yaron. 2004. Risks for the Long Run: A Potential Resolution of Asset
Barberis, N., and A. Shleifer. 2003. Style InvestingJournal of Financial Economics 68:161
199.
Barro, R. J. 2006. Rare Disasters and Asset Markets in the Twentieth CenturyQuarterly
Belo, F. 2010. Production-Based Measures of Risk for Asset Pricing. Journal of Monetary
Economics 57:146163.
Belo, F., V. D. Gala, and J. Li. 2012. Government Spending, Political Cycles and the
Ben-Rephael, A., S. Kandel, and A. Wohl. 2012. Measuring Investor Sentiment with Mutual
Berk, J. B., R. C. Green, and V. Naik. 1999. Optimal Investment, Growth Options and
47
Bernard, V. L., and J. K. Thomas. 1989. Post-Earnings-Announcement Drift: Delayed
Black, F. 1972. Capital Market Equilibrium with Restricted Borrowing. Journal of Busi-
ness 45:444455.
Bray, M. 1982. Learning, Estimation and the Stability of Rational Expectations Equilibria.
Brennan, M. J., A. W. Wang, and Y. Xia. 2004. Estimation and Test of a Simple Model
Brunnermeier, M. K., and L. H. Pedersen. 2009. Market Liquidity and Funding Liquidity.
251.
Campbell, J. Y., S. Giglio, C. Polk, and R. Turley. 2012. An Intertemporal CAPM with
Campbell, J. Y., J. Hilscher, and J. Szilagyi. 2008. In Search of Distress Risk. Journal of
Finance 63:28992939.
Campbell, J. Y., and R. J. Shiller. 1988. The Dividend-Price Ratio and Expectations of
Campbell, J. Y., and T. Vuolteenaho. 2004. Bad Beta, Good Beta. American Economic
Review 94:12491275.
nance 52:5782.
48
Carlson, M., A. Fisher, and R. Giammarino. 2004. Corporate Investment and Asset
nance 59:25772603.
Finance 51:16811713.
Chen, J., H. Hong, and J. C. Stein. 2002. Breadth of Ownership and Stock Returns. Journal
Chen, L., and X. Zhao. 2009. Return Decomposition. Review of Financial Studies 22:5213
5249.
Chordia, T., A. Subrahmanyam, and T. Qing. 2011. Trends in the Cross-Section of Ex-
Cochrane, J. H. 1991. Production-Based Asset Pricing and the Link Between Stock Returns
Cochrane, J. H., and J. Saa-Requejo. 2000. Beyond Arbitrage: Good-Deal Asset Price
Cohen, L., and A. Frazzini. 2008. Economic Links and Predictable Returns. Journal of
Finance 63:19772011.
Cohen, L., and D. Lou. 2011. Complicated Firms. Journal of Financial Eco-
nomics:forthcoming.
Cohen, R. B., C. Polk, and T. Vuolteenaho. 2003. The Value Spread. Journal of Fi-
nance 58:609641.
49
Collin-Dufresne, P., M. Johannes, and L. A. Lochstoer. 2012. Parameter Learning in Gen-
eral Equilibrium: The Asset Pricing Implications. Working Paper, Columbia Business
School.
Cooper, M., H. Gulen, and M. Schill. 2008. Asset Growth and the Cross-Section of Stock
Cooper, M., R. C. Gutierrez, and B. Marcum. 2005. On the Predictability of Stock Returns
Daniel, K., and S. Titman. 1997. Evidence on the Characteristics of Cross Sectional Vari-
Daniel, K., and S. Titman. 2006. Market Reactions to Tangible and Intangible Information.
Daniel, K., and S. Titman. 2012. Testing Factor-Model Explanations of Market Anomalies.
Davis, J., E. Fama, and K. French. 2000. Characteristics, Covariances, and Average Re-
DeBondt, W. F., and R. Thaler. 1985. Does the Stock Market Overreact? Journal of
Finance 40:793805.
DeBondt, W. F., and R. Thaler. 1987. Further Evidence on Investor Overreaction and
DellaVigna, S., and J. M. Pollet. 2007. Demographics and Industry Returns. American
nance 53:11311147.
Diether, K. B., C. J. Malloy, and A. Scherbina. 2011. Differences in Opinion and the Cross
50
Dimson, E., and P. Marsh. 1999. Winter. Murphys Law and Market Anomalies. Journal
Dimson, E., S. Nagel, and G. Quigley. 2003. November/December. Capturing the Value
Dittmar, R. F. 2002. Nonlinear Pricing Kernels, Kurtosis Preference, and Evidence from
Dumas, B., A. Kurshev, and R. Uppal. 2009. Equilibrium Portfolio Strategies in the Pres-
Epstein, L., and S. Zin. 1989. Substitution, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Behavior of
969.
Epstein, L., and S. Zin. 1991. Substitution, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Behavior
Economy 99:263286.
Fairfield, P., J. S. Whisenant, and T. Yohn. 2003. Accrued Earnings and Growth: Implica-
tions for Future Profitability and Market Mispricing. Accounting Review 78:353371.
Fama, E. 1970. Efficient Capital Markets: A Review of Theory and Empirical Work. Jour-
Fama, E. F., and K. R. French. 1992. The Cross-Section of Expected Stock Returns. Journal
of Finance 47:427465.
Fama, E. F., and K. R. French. 1993. Common Risk Factors in the Returns on Stocks and
Fama, E. F., and K. R. French. 1996. Mulitifactor Explanations of Asset Pricing Anomalies.
Fama, E. F., and K. R. French. 1998. Value versus Growth: The International Evidence.
51
Journal of Finance 53:19751999.
Fama, E. F., and K. R. French. 2006. Profitability, Investment and Average Returns.
Fama, E. F., and K. R. French. 2008. Average Returns, B/M and Share Issues. Journal of
Finance 63:29712995.
Frazzini, A., and O. A. Lamont. 2008. Dumb Money: Mutual Fund Flows and the Cross-
Frazzini, A., and L. H. Pedersen. 2011. Betting Against Beta. Working Paper, NYU.
Gibbons, M., S. Ross, and J. Shanken. 1989. A Test of the Efficiency of a Given Portfolio.
Econometrica 57:11211152.
Giovannini, A., and P. Weil. 1989. Risk Aversion and Intertemporal Substitution. Working
Paper, NBER.
Gomes, J., L. Kogan, and L. Zhang. 2003. Equilibrium Cross-Section of Returns. Journal
Green, J., J. R. M. Hand, and M. T. Soliman. 2011. Going, Going, Gone? The Apparent
Griffin, J. M., and M. L. Lemmon. 2002. Book-to-Market Equity, Distress Risk and Stock
Gromb, D., and D. Vayanos. 2010. Limits to Arbitrage. Annual Review of Financial Eco-
nomics 2:251275.
52
Hansen, L. P. 1985. A Method for Calculating Bounds on the Asymptotic Covariance Ma-
238.
Hansen, L. P., J. C. Heaton, and N. Li. 2008. Consumption Strikes Back? Measuring
Hansen, L. P., and R. Jagannathan. 1991. Implications of Security Market Data for Models
Hansen, L. P., and S. F. Richard. 1987. The Role of Conditioning Information in Deducing
613.
Harvey, C. R., and A. Siddique. 2000. Conditional Skewness in Asset Pricing TestsJournal
of Finance 60:12631295.
Haugen, R. A., and L. Baker, Nardin. 1996. Commonality in the Determinants of Expected
Hirshleifer, D., K. Hou, S. H. Teoh, and Y. Zhang. 2004. Do Investors Overvalue Firms
Hirshleifer, D., S. S. Lim, and S. H. Teoh. 2011. Limited Investor Attention and Stock
73.
Holmstrom, B., and J. Tirole. 2001. LAPM: A Liquidity-Based Asset Pricing Model. Jour-
Hong, H., T. Lim, and J. C. Stein. 2000. Bad News Travels Slowly: Size, Analyst Coverage,
53
Hong, H., and D. A. Sraer. 2012. Speculative Betas. Working Paper, Princeton University.
Hou, K., L. Peng, and W. Xiong. 2009. A Tale of Two Anomalies: The Implications
of Investor Attention for Price and Earnings Momentum. Working Paper, Princeton
University.
Hou, K., C. Xue, and L. Zhang. 2012. Digesting Anomalies. Working Paper, The Ohio
State University.
Huang, W., Q. Liu, S. G. Rhee, and L. Zhang. 2010. Return Reversals, Idiosyncratic Risk
Jagannathan, R., G. Skoulakis, and Z. Wang. 2009. The Analysis of the Cross Section of
Jagannathan, R., and Z. Wang. 1996. The Conditional CAPM and the Cross-section of
Comparison of the SDF and Beta MethodsThe Journal of Finance 57:pp. 23372367.
Finance 45:881898.
Jegadeesh, N., and S. Titman. 1993. Returns to Buying Winners and Selling Losers: Im-
Kan, R., and C. Robotti. 2008. Specification Tests of Asset Pricing Models Using Ex-
cess Returnscation Tests of Asset Pricing Models Using Excess Returns. Journal of
54
Empirical Finance 15:816838.
Finance 51:17151742.
Lam, F. E. C., and K. J. Wei. 2011. Limits-to-Arbitrage, Investment Frictions, and the
Lee, C. M., and B. Swaminathan. 2000. Price Momentum and Trading Volume. Journal of
Finance 55:20172069.
Leippold, M., and H. Lohre. 2012. Data Snooping and the Global Accrual Anomaly. Applied
Lemmon, M., and E. Portniaguina. Winter 2006. Consumer Confidence and Asset Prices:
Lettau, M., and S. C. Ludvigson. 2001. Resurrecting the (C)CAPM: A Cross-Sectional Test
Lettau, M., and J. A. Wachter. 2007. Why Is Long-Horizon Equity Less Risky? A Duration-
Lewellen, J. 2011. The Cross Section of Expected Stock Returns. Working Paper, Dart-
mouth College.
Lewellen, J., and S. Nagel. 2006. The Conditional CAPM Does Not Explain Asset Pricing
Lewellen, J., S. Nagel, and J. Shanken. 2010. A Skeptical Appraisal of Asset-Pricing Tests.
Lewellen, J., and R. J. Resutek. 2012. The Predictive Power of Investments and Accruals.
55
Lewellen, J., and J. Shanken. 2002. Learning, Asset-Pricing Tests and Market Efficiency.
Li, E. X., D. Livdan, and L. Zhang. 2009. Anomalies. Review of Financial Studies 22:4301
4334.
Li, Q., M. Vassalou, and Y. Xing. 2006. Sector Investment Growth Rates and the Cross
Liew, J., and M. Vassalou. 2000. Can Book-to-Market, Size and Momentum be Risk Factors
Lipson, M. L., S. Mortal, and M. Schill. 2011. On the Scope and Drivers of the Asset
ment 30:1529.
Lo, A. W., and A. C. MacKinlay. 1990. Data-Snooping Biases in Tests of Financial Asset
Mankiw, N. G., and S. Zeldes. 1991. The Consumption of Stockholders and Nonstockhold-
Marcet, A., and J. Sargent, Thomas. 1989. Convergence of Least Squares Learning
ory 48:337368.
Mashruwala, C., S. Rajgopal, and T. Shevlin. 2006. Why is the accrual anomaly not arbi-
traged away? The role of idiosyncratic risk and transaction costs. Journal of Accounting
56
McLean, D. R., and J. Pontiff. 2012. Does Academic Research Destroy Stock Return Pre-
McLean, D. R., J. Pontiff, and A. Watanabe. 2009. Share Issuance and Cross-Sectional
Business 77:875894.
Menzly, L., and O. Ozbas. 2010. Market Segmentation and Cross-predictability of Re-
887.
nance 32:11511168.
Muth, J. F. 1961. Rational Expectations and the Theory of Price Movements. Economet-
rica 29:123.
Nagel, S. 2005. Short Sales, Institutional Investors and the Cross-Section of Stock Returns.
Nagel, S., and K. J. Singleton. 2011. Estimation and Evaluation of Conditional Asset
Novy-Marx, R. 2012a. The Other Side of Value: The Gross Profitability Premium. Journal
of Financial Economics:forthcoming.
ing Anomaly Performance with Politics, the Weather, Global Warming, Sunspots, and
57
the Stars. Working Paper, NBER.
ies 10:323347.
Papanikolaou, D. 2011. Investment Shocks and Asset Prices. Journal of Political Econ-
omy 119:639685.
Parker, J. A., and C. Julliard. 2005. Consumption Risk and the Cross Section of Expected
Pastor, L., and R. F. Stambaugh. 2003. Liquidity Risk and Expeced Stock Returns. Journal
Peng, L., and W. Xiong. 2006. Investor Attention, Overconfidence and Category Learn-
Economics 111:11351151.
Pontiff, J. 2006. Costly Arbitrage and the Myth of Idiosyncratic Risk. Journal of Accounting
Pontiff, J., and A. Woodgate. 2008. Share Issuance and Cross-Sectional Returns. Journal
of Finance 63:921945.
Restoy, F., and P. Weil. 2011. Approximate Equilibrium Asset PricesReview of Fi-
nance 15:128.
Ross, S. A. 1976. The Arbitrage Theory of Capital Asset Pricing. Journal of Economic
Theory 13:34160.
284.
58
Sadka, R. 2006. Momentum and Post-Earnings-Announcement Drift Anomalies: The Role
Santos, T., and P. Veronesi. 2010. Habit formation, the cross section of stock returns and
Schwartzstein, J. 2012. Selective Attention and Learning. Working Paper, Dartmouth Col-
lege.
Shanken, J. 1985. Multivariate Tests of the Zero-Beta CAPM. Journal of Financial Eco-
ies 5:133.
Sloan, R. 1996. Do Stock Prices Fully Reflect Information in Accruals and Cash Flows
Stambaugh, R. F., J. Yu, and Y. Yuan. 2012. The Short of It: Investor Sentiment and
Teo, M., and S.-J. Woo. 2004. Style effects in the cross-section of stock returnsJournal of
Timmermann, A., and C. W. Granger. 2004. Efficient Market Hypothesis and Forecasting.
Titman, S., K. J. Wei, and F. Xie. 2004. Capital Investments and Stock Returns. Journal
59
Vuolteenaho, T. 2000. Understanding the Aggregate Book-to-Market Ratio and Its Impli-
Vuolteenaho, T. 2002. What Drives Firm-Level Stock Returns? Journal of Finance 52:233
264.
Watanabe, A., T. Yu, and Y. Xu. 2011. The Asset Growth Effect and Market Efficiency:
nomics 105:2942.
60