MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Virtues in Foot and Geach PDF
MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Virtues in Foot and Geach PDF
MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Virtues in Foot and Geach PDF
October
ISSN
CRITICAL STUDY
B A MI
Both Philippa Foot and Peter Geach have put us in their philosophical debt to an
unusual extent over an unusual length of time. From their first published articles
Geachs on designation and truth in Analysis in , Foots on whether morality
needs or can have a philosophical justification in Philosophy in both made their
mark as among the few whose work is always not just worth reading, but necessary
reading. Foots contributions have been almost exclusively within moral philosophy,
while Geachs have ranged more widely: on multifarious issues in logic and the
philosophy of logic, on McTaggart, Aquinas, Hobbes and Frege, on mental acts, on
the virtues, and on providence and evil, not to speak of his excellent translations.
Their new books reflect this difference. The question that Foot addresses returns
to long-standing concerns with the moral evaluation of human actions: what kind of
evaluation is that? In the course of arriving at and defending her answer to this
question against alternative views, she engages with various issues about which she
had written earlier. But these discussions are subordinated to a single central pur-
pose. Geach by contrast has a more varied subject-matter. Six of his seven essays are
revised versions of the Frst Franz Joseph and Frstin Gina Lectures delivered at
the International Academy of Philosophy in Liechtenstein, while the seventh was a
talk on Prophecy to the boys of Shrewsbury School. Every one is impressive, both
as argument and as writing. All of them make one ask for more; but what is
remarkable is how much Geach succeeds in saying within so brief a compass.
Because so much has been compressed into so short a space, and because therefore
Geach has on occasion left it to his readers to spell out his argument further and to
consider further objections, those who want to quarrel with his conclusions (and they
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly, . Published by Blackwell Publishers, Cowley Road, Oxford , UK, and
Main Street, Malden, , USA.
ALASDAIR MACINTYRE
will be many) may be deceived into thinking their task easier than it is. These are
essays that point beyond themselves, provoking continuing thought at many points.
The first essay, on Truth, Love and Immortality, has the same title as Geachs
admirable book on McTaggart, but whereas Geachs principal concern in the book
was to make the best case that could fairly be made for McTaggarts arguments and
positions, here his aim is to separate out what is true in McTaggarts teaching from
what is false. Of the other essays, three are about truth and cognate matters, one has
the title What is Man?, and the final essay is on the goodness of God. But it would
be wrong to conclude that, while Foots book has a genuine unity, Geachs does not.
It is rather that the unity of Geachs book is of a different kind.
What Geach presents is an account of our common human nature and its
prospects, and each of his treatments of particular questions brings out some feature
of that account. He is most of all concerned with the place of truth in human life,
and time and again he returns to the importance of hope. Over twenty years ago in
his Stanton Lectures (The Virtues, Cambridge UP, ), Geach argued both that
human beings need hope and that there is no hope for them, either individually or
corporately, except from Gods promise of new life after this life in the kingdom that
is to come. And the same theological view is taken in these present lectures. Here as
elsewhere Geach draws insightfully upon resources provided by his Catholic faith,
but he is always scrupulous in distinguishing conclusions that depend upon some
article of faith from those that are matter for reason alone.
He begins his discussion of the harm of inconsistency by noting that, just as
minor vices may save us from major harms (the lazy servant of a tyrant may engage
in much less wickedness than one who is assiduous), so inconsistency may save the
inconsistent from going the full length in drawing conclusions from false premises
(p. ). But inconsistency is none the less a serious threat: inconsistent history will
somewhere be factually false (p. ), inconsistent instructions cannot all be im-
plemented, and an inconsistent moral code will prescribe morally objectionable
conduct. So we need to form mental habits that will make us less liable to this kind
of error. What is most important about inconsistency is that it condemns us to false
judgement. It matters, because truth matters.
The essay on Truth, Truthfulness and Trust begins by identifying the indis-
pensable part that testimony plays as a foundation for the house of knowledge
(p. ). We generally have to rely on the truthfulness of others, and lying and fraud
tend to unravel the fabric of our relationships and of our lives. But there are, of
course, particular lies that do no harm. What attitude should we take to them?
Geach contrasts promise-breaking with lying. There are types of circumstance in
which promise-breaking is unqualifiedly justifiable. But lying is always something to
feel some shame and sorrow for. Even someone who lies in an emergency for his
neighbours necessity ought to reflect that, if he had not accustomed himself to
telling little lies under no pressure at all, he would very likely have had it given
to him ... to devise a way of escape without lying (p. ), perhaps by equivocation,
something that Geach rightly regards as justified in some circumstances.
Why ought we always to feel some shame and sorrow even for small and
harmless lies? Partly because those who allow themselves to tell small lies will under
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
VIRTUES IN FOOT AND GEACH
pressure find themselves telling big lies, but partly because small lies are themselves
bad. Geach follows Aquinas view that lying consists in speaking contrary to ones
own mind. Although ones mind is not a measure of truth, everyone (Geach adds
unless he is exceptionally corrupt) desires to orient his mind to truth (p. ).
This natural desire for truth is expressed in the high value that many who reject
the Christian revelation or any other religious view of things set upon the pursuit of
truth; but the natural desire for truth may be perverted, and among the influences
that may assist in perverting it are false philosophical theories of truth. How then
should we think about truth? Geach rejects both pragmatist and correspondence
theories. He develops briefly, but illuminatingly, an account of indicative sentences
according to which A free-standing sentence is dual to its logical contradictory and
sentences that occur as integral parts of longer ones are dual to their contra-
dictories (pp. ). All sentences capable of truth or falsity are dual to their
negations, and just because this is so, we do not need to follow Frege in thinking that
false sentences have to be understood as relating to the False, a counterpart to the
True. All indicative sentences purport to be orientated to the True. True sentences
are in fact orientated to the True, while false sentences fail to be orientated as they
purport to be. The view that indicative sentences are orientated to the True, that
they are, as it were, signposts pointing to the True, is to be distinguished
from Freges thesis that such sentences designate the True (or, in Freges view, the
False). Frege failed to recognize that The semantic role of an indicative sentence is
utterly different from that of a name or again of a complex designation (p. ).
Geach then suggests, and it is a compelling suggestion, that the difference between
designating and being orientated towards is implicitly acknowledged by anyone who recog-
nizes what makes a logos, in Aristotles word, apophantikos, and that he is able to use
the metaphor of orientation to make explicit what they recognize. This claim, like
some others in this book, badly needs expanding, both in order for us to understand
it better and because it is central to an account of truth which has this unusual
merit: it not only proposes solutions to some of the central philosophical problems
about truth, but does so in a way that enables us to understand better the place that
truth has in human life.
Geachs greatest debt in developing his account of truth is to Anselms De Veritate,
and he notes that if we can show that there is a God, then we can hardly conceive
of his needing to orient his thought to a Truth distinct from himself.... Rather God
must be conceived as constituting all truth; and, as knowing it in constituting it,
Only so could God be worthy of our total worship (p. ). Therefore we must reject
any view of God that is incompatible with the identity of God and Truth.
In focusing attention on what Geach says about truth I do not want to suggest
that this is the only valuable part of his book. On the contrary, there are some
equally splendid discussions of other topics. But the discussion of truth has a peculiar
importance for philosophy now. And aspects of that importance can be brought out
by considering its relevance to Philippa Foots new book. Yet since that ambitious
book has its own distinctive importance, attempting, as it does, to give a new
direction to the enquiries of moral philosophy, I need first to consider at adequate
length how Foots overall argument proceeds.
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
ALASDAIR MACINTYRE
Foot begins by insisting that we should not tie moral judgement too closely to
action (p. ). Someone may indeed have a good reason to perform some action in
virtue of the truth of some moral judgement, but may fail to perform it from
ignorance or weakness of will or shamelessness. Moreover, when a moral judgement
has provided an agent with a motivating reason to act, this need not be because his
feelings, passions or desires have provided him with a goal. What moves that agent
may be simply his recognition of a reason for action, a recognition which itself gives
a rational agent a goal. By these two denials Foot separates herself from any neo-
Humean account of moral judgement. What then are moral judgements? To say of
an act that it is vicious is to say of its agent that he suffers from some form of natural
defect. What does Foot mean by natural defect?
It is the kind of defect which a plant or a non-human animal exhibits when it fails
to be what as a member of its particular species it needs to be. The way an indi-
vidual should be is determined by what is needed for development, self-maintenance
and reproduction: in most species involving defence, and in some the rearing of the
young (p. ). Foot draws on Michael Thompsons work in order to argue that an
understanding of the life-form of any species must be in terms of the norms that
specify what is required for such needs to be met. When we evaluate individuals by
reference to those norms, we use the expressions good and bad, and we do so in a
way that has nothing to do with their relationship to us or our attitudes to them.
The goodness that we ascribe in this way Foot calls natural goodness. And
natural goodness is a concept that has application not only to plants and to non-
human animals, but also to human beings. The diversity of human goods does not
make it impossible that the concept of good human life plays the same part in
determining goodness of human characteristics and operations that the concept of
flourishing plays in the determination of goodness in plants and animals (p. ).
Foot goes on to argue that human beings are defective as human beings unless they
do what is needed for human good, including such things as refraining from murder
and keeping promises (p. ). This raises two questions.
The first is: what reason has any individual human being for caring about
whether or not he is defective as a human being? Foot answers that we all have good
reason to care about this. She begins from Davidsons distinction between what
someone should do relative to a certain consideration and what one should do all
things considered, developing a view of practical reasoning in support of the con-
clusion that to act badly is to act against reason. She follows Warren Quinn in
holding that the concept of practical rationality has to be spelt out in terms of some
prior notion of good. It is just because some action is a good thing to do, or achieves
some good, that we have a reason to perform it. So the sceptic who asks whether we
as individuals have reason to act as good human beings makes a mistake about
reasons. Foot recognizes that the sceptic may have in mind someone with dangerous
desires who is not motivated to act as reason requires. But the fact that we might
hunt around for something that has a chance of affecting his actions (p. ) does not
in the least undermine this account of practical reasoning.
Everything for Foots overall argument turns, then, on her claims about the
nature of human goodness, and this in two related respects. First, in speaking of
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
VIRTUES IN FOOT AND GEACH
human actions as good, we are, on her view, speaking of natural goodness. So it has
to be shown that in taking some types of action to be incontrovertibly good we are
ascribing this kind of goodness to them. Secondly, we have to ask what it is about
good actions that makes them good. In addressing both these questions Foot rejects
as irrelevant any distinction between other-regarding and self-regarding actions.
The goodness or badness of an action may be as much a matter of self-regarding
prudence as of other-regarding justice. But it always has to do with what is in some
way voluntary, a matter of the will. Someone may, of course, act badly on the basis
of inadequate information or misinformation. But if the agents ignorance concerns
facts that he could and should have known, then ignorance may be imputed to his
will (p. ).
What then makes an act good? It is good by not being in any respect bad. Foot
follows Aquinas in holding that while any one defect is sufficient to make an action
bad, freedom from all defect is required to make it good. What are the types of
defect which may deprive an action of goodness? They are threefold. First, there are
kinds of action that are bad just because they are of that kind. Secondly, the end for
which an action is done may make an action bad, even if it is otherwise good, as
when a blackmailer saves the life of his victim only in order to continue deriving an
income from him. Thirdly, to act in a way other than as one believes to be right is to
act badly. It does not of course follow that to believe that one acts rightly is to act
well. Foot again follows Aquinas in holding both that an erroneous conscience does
not excuse and that to act against ones conscience is always wrong.
Foot completes her argument by considering how human good is related to
human happiness. What she calls deep happiness has as its objects things that are
basic in human life, such as home, and family, and work, and friendship (p. ), and
for some, the search for truth or artistic creation or the achievement of an explorers
goals. The connection between deep happiness and virtue is complex. Someone very
bad can certainly be contented with his life, but perhaps there is that in happiness
that he cannot attain. And very good people may find that by acting as they should
they will make it impossible for themselves to achieve the deep happiness that they
had hoped for, as did those who sacrificed their lives by opposing the Nazi evil. But
such happiness could not have been achieved by co-operating with the Nazis. For
this co-operation too would have deprived them of happiness. The suggestion is,
then, that humanitys good can be thought of as happiness, and yet in such a way
that combining it with wickedness is a priori ruled out (p. ).
Foots overall argument is now complete. She has a final chapter on Nietzsches
challenge to her central thesis, about which I shall say something later. But she has
laid out her grounds for her conclusion, that moral evaluation concerns the
goodness or badness of agents and of their voluntary actions, and that what makes
agents and actions good or bad is the presence or absence of natural defect. Human
goodness is natural goodness, natural just as the goodness of non-human species is
natural. How should we respond to this thesis and to the arguments with which she
supports this claim? I begin with her account of why we need the virtues.
Foot quotes from the first of Geachs Stanton lectures: Men need virtues as bees
need stings (The Virtues, p. ). For what do men need the virtues? On Geachs view,
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
ALASDAIR MACINTYRE
they need them in order to achieve the ends proper to a man; but in order to show
that the virtues are needed, we do not first have to determine what those ends are.
For the four cardinal virtues are needed for any large-scale worthy enterprise, just
as health and sanity are needed. Foot slightly rewords Geachs thesis: virtues play a
necessary part in the life of a human being as do stings in the life of bees (p. ). Yet
later she asks And given the diversity of human lives can we really think of a species-
wide notion of human good at all?, and she expresses doubts about a possibility
which she seemed earlier to be entertaining seriously, that of using the word
flourishing of human beings as we use it of plants and animals (pp. ). Her
subsequent discussion of benefit does not seem to respond to these doubts.
We are therefore left with only one clear central claim: human beings need the
virtues if they are not to suffer from some natural defect, something that renders
them defective with reference to the norms for their species, as bees without stings
would be defective. What are specific to human beings are their natural powers,
especially the power to reason both speculatively and practically. Foots brief re-
marks about these powers seem to me to leave open too many questions about the
place of language and rationality in specifically human life. In so doing, they
contribute to an indefiniteness in her conception of natural goodness and natural
defect that leaves it unclear just how this notion is to be applied in the case of
human beings.
I shall consider in this light one of Foots examples, that of why it is bad to break
a promise on those occasions when it is bad. (There are of course some occasions in
which it is right to break some particular promise, and a shared understanding of
when this is right is part of our shared understanding of promising. This is a
qualification that I shall take for granted from now on.) Foot follows Elizabeth
Anscombe, who argued in her essay On Promising and its Justice that because the
procedure of promise-making and promise-keeping has the role of an instrument in
peoples attainment of so many of the goods of common life, someone who does not
give undertakings and act in conformity with them acts badly (Ethics, Religion and
Politics, Univ. of Minnesota Press, , pp. ). Anscombe spoke here of a nec-
essity: it is the necessity that Aristotle spoke of, by which something is called
necessary if without it good cannot be attained.
Anscombes argument is sound. But what it shows is that promise-making and
promise-keeping are required for achieving a great many goods, not that those
goods are judged good by the standard of natural goodness, as Foot understands it.
And of course human beings can survive and even flourish to some extent without
the institution of promise-making, as the example of the traditional indigenous
culture of the Tonga Islands seems to show (see F. Korn and S.R.D. Korn, Where
People Dont Promise, Ethics, (), pp. ). So what then would we have
to add, in order to exhibit promise-breaking as an example of natural defect?
Promise-breaking would indeed be such, if goods that are specifically human,
goods without which the specific end or ends of human life, whatever they are, could
not be achieved in the absence of promise-keeping. What goods might these be?
Foot has a useful catalogue of specifically human needs and of corresponding
deprivations. Human beings and human societies need the physical and mental
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
VIRTUES IN FOOT AND GEACH
capacities required for language-learning, the powers of imagination that enable us
to tell and to understand stories, the ability to join in songs and dances and to make
and laugh at jokes, the capacity in mothers for maternal affection, and the ability in
some individuals at least to explore, to create works of art, and to give leadership
(pp. ). And it is not difficult to understand why the lack of some of these in an
individual and of others of these in a society is a deprivation of a good specific to our
human nature. So the absence from a society of any widely practised system of
promise-making and promise-keeping would also be just such a deprivation. It
might plausibly be argued that the limitations of the older culture of the Tonga
Islands are evidence for this.
Yet what a society needs is a widely, not a universally, practised system of
promise-making and promise-keeping. This is compatible with at least some
individuals refusing to make promises, and others making promises but breaking
them, provided promise-breaking does not occur too often. Of those individuals we
may ask: of what, if anything, are they as individuals deprived, so that we may speak
justly of their suffering from some natural defect? They are of course, as Anscombe
showed, acting badly, but the question is: is their badness natural badness? It is in
asking and trying to answer this question that the indefiniteness of Foots account of
natural goodness becomes important.
For it may well seem that what makes it bad for a society not to have an adequate
system of promise-making and promise-keeping is one thing, while what makes it
bad for an individual to break a promise is another. The former badness is indeed a
defect in any human society, on Foots account a natural defect. The latter badness
is the badness of someone who does not act for the sake of the common good. But
does Foot give us adequate grounds for holding that this too is a natural defect?
Imagine a society of some sufficiently complex species, whose members are
systematically differentiated into a large class of those who do whatever is required
for the survival and flourishing of the society and more generally of the species, and
a much smaller class of free-riders. Such a society would suffer from natural defect if
there were too many free-riders, but the existence of some free-riders would not be a
defect, and the free-riders themselves are not necessarily defective members of the
species. For their existence might have the important function of making other
members of their society and species more vigilant in sustaining the practices
necessary for the societys and the species survival and functioning. So it might
perhaps be for human beings with promise-breakers. So long as there is a relatively
small number of them, their existence might be beneficial in that it makes the other
members of their society and species more vigilant in upholding the practice of
promise-making and promise-keeping than they would otherwise be. And if this
higher degree of vigilance is necessary to sustain promise-making and promise-
keeping, then the existence of some promise-breakers in such a society would not be
a natural defect, and the promise-breakers themselves, although acting badly in not
acting for the common good, would not have the badness of those who are naturally
defective.
If this is a possible scenario, it seems to put Foots central claim in question. For
not all moral evaluation would be a matter of natural goodness or badness. But this
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
ALASDAIR MACINTYRE
opinion morally out (p. ). She cites two reasons for her view in a footnote,
quoting Ronald Dworkins judgement: He sees the ban on torture as a barrier to
the power of a tyrannical ruler. Foot then adds One might also see torture as the
ultimate negation of the impulse humans have to come to each others aid (I am not
sure what to make of might in that sentence).
Suppose a group of Resistance fighters can only frustrate a Nazi intention to
torture and massacre their comrades by themselves torturing a suspect whom they
know to possess vital information. Foot sees no objection to their performing the
normally bad act of lying in this type of situation. But why then is it wrong for them
to perform the normally bad act of torture? On such an occasion this particular act
of torture will after all prevent tyrants from imposing their will, and in so far as it
negates what Foot calls the instinct to come to each others aid, it resembles the lie
which negates everything that makes us value truth. So we need to hear more from
Foot about the differences between torture and lying.
Moreover, Foot, as I remarked earlier, agrees with Aquinas that an act is good by
not being in any way bad, and she catalogues three ways in which an act can be
bad. So on occasions when it is right, on her view, to lie, that lie presumably cannot
be bad in any way. It follows that lying as such, lying as the kind of action that it is,
is not bad, and it follows from this, together with Foots catalogue of the ways in
which an act can be bad, that a lie told from benevolent motives with no harmful
consequences by an agent whose conscience approved his acts would never be bad.
But is this really Foots view?
If it is, then we need arguments to show that Geachs view of the good of truth
and of its place in human discourse and life is mistaken. If it is not, then we once
again need further clarification. What is lacking in Foots overall argument is an
adequate characterization of the precise relationship between saying of agents that
they are or are not naturally good, and saying of them that they told the truth or
lied, that they kept or broke promises, that they engaged in or refused to engage in
torture. Geach has told us clearly and trenchantly why he takes it that in wilfully
departing from the truth we are violating norms required of us by our nature as
rational animals. Foot does not make it similarly clear why the goodness or badness
she ascribes to certain types of act is natural goodness or badness. This unclarity
makes her response to Nietzsche less compelling than it might otherwise be.
Foot concentrates attention on two Nietzschean theses: that pity is bad for those
who feel it, by enervating and weakening them; and that actions are not to be
judged as good or bad in themselves, but only as they strengthen or weaken the
agents who perform them. Pitiless acts of plunder, murder and rape are not to be
condemned from the standpoint of those whose strength is exhibited in and
reinforced by them. And, we may add, since the strong human being is a predator
by nature, such acts are, on Nietzsches view, expressions of the natural goodness of
the strong.
Foot has two rejoinders to Nietzsche. The first is that we have no reason to
accept the underlying psychology of the will to power. About this I take her to be
incontrovertibly right. Her second response is to assert (p. ) that there is nothing
human beings need more than protection from those who would harm and oppress
The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,
VIRTUES IN FOOT AND GEACH
them. What she does not notice is how little Nietzsche would have disagreed. He
would have inserted the words the vast majority of before human beings, and
remarked that the weak do indeed need such protection in order to remain weak
and to disguise their weakness from themselves. But the needs of the strong are quite
different. What Foot has to show against Nietzsche, and what her argument does
not yet sufficiently show, is that there are natural needs of human beings as such,
providing a standard by which claims about the needs of the strong and the needs of
the weak can be evaluated. It has been my claim that here as elsewhere Geachs
essays point in the direction she needs to take.
Natural Goodness is an exciting and provoking book, more interesting than most
books in moral philosophy. If I have been largely critical, it is only because so much
hangs on whether Foot can provide the grounds that her central claims require.
What she has given us both in this book and elsewhere deserves nothing but
intellectual and moral gratitude.