Finalfinalpaper
Finalfinalpaper
Finalfinalpaper
Madeline Libbey
Dr. Russell Poldrack
Reading the Brain
1 March 2017
Brief Overview of First Draft Revisions:
explanatory sentence.
b) I removed Cephos from my examples of commercialized fMRI after it was brought to my
those paragraphs: indistinguishable finger movements and head movements that can create
imaging artifacts.
d) In the Rule 702 section and US v Semrau section of the essay (pages 7 and 8), I added points and
analysis about the Daubert Standard to further discuss the judiciarys interaction with scientific
evidence in the past and how that might affect the future.
e) On page 9 I changed the wording ruin lives to something a little less dramatic, and hopefully
more accurate
f) The biggest change I made was on page 10 with the discussion of the regulation committee to
clarify just what policy I want to implement and how. I added a few sentences about the specifics
of the committee, what it might look like and what the regulations might look like.
a) Grammatical/Wording Changes: For the majority of grammar and wording changes throughout
the paper, I made the fixes. Most of them had to do with clarity and specificity which I wouldnt
have noticed, so I really appreciated those. However, I intentionally kept the we throughout the
style and varied the syntax for some. I did keep a few though, because, along with the we I feel
c) Show dont tell: I removed all of the language similar to This paper will show etc. but I
usually kept the rest of those passages other than that specific phrase because I see them as more
brackets. I did keep the block quotes for Rule 403 and 702 because I think the logical
progression from the rule followed by my analysis is as clear as I can make it.
Libbey 3
The Futile Quest for Truth: A Policy Proposal for the Regulation of fMRI Lie Detection
Its generally understood that a memoir is not a complete and accurate account of ones
life. Instead, it is the recollections of ones past, a record of memories and thoughts about
experiences preceding the now. Unlike an autobiography, not every fact has been checked for
objectivity. In fact, a memoir often relates in prose what cannot be fact-checked. But, sometimes
it does. Many a memoir has been found to contain complete falsehoods, even when they are
unbeknownst to the writer. An authors truthful recounting of their story, the way they remember
it, may in fact be entirely different from the real, objective, truth. How reliable are our personal
truths? And, maybe more importantly, our lies? While this phenomena of false remembrance in
memoirs may have some consequences, these pale in comparison to when this ambiguous truth
arises in court. This is the work that we have laid out for the triers of fact: discern the truth from
the lies, the false remembrances, and the noise. To investigate these truths, we gather evidence,
we cross-examine, we call upon experts, and then finally, we decide. Its a system that at its best,
However, today this balance is being tipped. With the introduction of neuroscience-based
lie detection into a court of law an fMRI becomes our trier of fact, and false remembrances and
scanning image noise can be mistaken for truths. The issues with fMRI-based lie detection
today are two-fold: First, we must address the preliminary question of efficacy; and only after we
do, can we address the secondary question of ethicality. To date, the scientific community is
divided on the causes and effects of lies, the neural markers of lies, and the scientific definition
of a lie itself. fMRI lie detection cannot be reliable until the nature of a lie (versus a false belief,
or omission) is defined, and cannot be replicable until the neural markers of deceit are known
Libbey 4
and consistent. Therefore, as it is now, fMRI lie detection is not replicable, nor reliable. Some
critics argue that it never can be. There is much work to be done before this method will be
accepted in the scientific community as effective, and arguably even more work to be done
Not only is fMRI lie detection technologically flawed, un-replicated, and limited, it is
also fundamentally incompatible with the judiciary. Even if all of these technological obstacles
were surmounted the issue of introducing fMRI lie detection data as evidence into court poses
additional challenges to be resolved. The Federal Rules of Evidence, Fifth Amendment and right
to privacy, along with past judicial opinions, all suggest that fMRI lie detection would be
considered more prejudicial than probative in a court of law. To understand this we must delve
deeper into the limits and challenges of an effective fMRI and its implications on the rights of the
accused, due process, and the integrity of our courts. Ultimately this evidence reveals an urgent
need for legislation creating a regulatory system for pre-market approval of lie detection
techniques, which would play a crucial role in preserving the authenticity of the judiciary.
To evaluate the legitimacy of using fMRI lie detection, it is critical to first understand the
basic mechanisms behind the technology. Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging has been
utilized in the scientific and medical community for more than a decade (Wagner et al.). In
analyzing this data we can isolate the changes in the brain correlated to specific presented stimuli
or the performance of a task. This is done by subtracting the noise brain activity from the
image, which is found by comparing a control image to the experimental image and subtracting
the difference. Considering the complexity of brain function and cooperation among systems, the
key to obtaining significant results is choosing an adequate control image. For example, if a
researcher is looking for what areas of the brain are triggered by reading aloud, the control might
Libbey 5
be viewing words without speaking (Bizzi et al.). With this method it is possible to isolate and
correlate brain activity with behavior. fMRI-based lie detection is attempting to correlate brain
The preliminary issue is fMRI technology, as it is now, is simply not advanced enough to
detect lies in real world situations. The inability to identify an accurate control image, the
inability to mimic a real-world lie in a laboratory, the misinterpretation of data, and the
unchecked potential for countermeasures all contribute to the unreliability of this method. All of
these issues ultimately beg the question: how do we keep this unreliable technology out of the
Establishing a sufficient control image is the most basic challenge that fMRI lie detection
faces. The primary nature of deceit within the brain is still mysterious to researchers.
Considering this, it is nearly impossible to find a control from which to make inference. For
instance, a control used in a laboratory setting may intrinsically leave out crucial convoluting
brain activity that would be present in a real world situation. Dr. Elizabeth Phelps, explains that
in her findings, the neural signatures of lying may be heavily intertwined with emotion and
imagery(Bizzi et al.). The imagery and emotion that would likely be present when a lie is
personally relevant and important might interfere with the use of fMRI signals to detect
familiarity(Bizzi et al.). In other words, in the laboratory researchers find an isolation of activity
when a subject tells what would be considered a lie. However, there are significant differences in
brain activity from a subject telling an instructed untruth, to a suspect or witness of a crime
answering highly emotional and anxiety inducing interrogations. Therefore, correctly identifying
Phelps).
Provided that a lab setting differs drastically from real-world application, laboratory
studies are testing a different set of brain functions than those that would be ignited by a true lie.
This not only poses problems with identifying a control image, but also causes issue in the way a
stimulus is presented. In a meta-analysis by Martha J. Farah, she found that the types of
instructed lies utilized by fMRI lie detection studies are cognitively complex: the subject must
remember the stimuli, suppress the truth, decide to lie, and choose a response (Bizzi). Dr.
Phelpss research tells us that while it is quite likely that a real lie may follow a similar sequence
of processes, the involvement of emotion and personal attachment would alter the brain activity
drastically. Real-world versus laboratory applications aside, according to Bizzi et al., for any
process that is cognitively complex it is impossible to jump from observing brain activity to
inferring mental processes due to the sheer complexity and interaction between regions of the
brain. It is for this reason that fMRI is widely understood as a purely correlative tool. If we
cannot establish neither a baseline for a controlled brain image from which to present a stimulus,
nor an acceptable stimulus to present; it is obvious why fMRI lie detection has been met by so
much skepticism.
Obtaining a reliable control image and stimulus is just the first of many issues
surrounding the research into fMRI lie detection. Companies like No Lie MRI, an investigative
services that offers fMRI lie detection, claims their current accuracy is over 90% and is
estimated to be 99% once product development is complete (Greely). Dr. Nancy Kanwisher
explains in her essay, The Use of fMRI Lie Detection: What Has Been Shown and What Has
Not, that the statistics included on these sites come from an analysis of averaging group data as
Libbey 7
opposed to analyzing individual subject data. On a fundamental level, group studies are not
useful for determining whether a particular subject is lying, rendering the rationale behind these
companies groundless(Wagner et al.). Yet even when we examine the research analyzing
individual subject data, the results, while scientifically probative, are inconclusive and unreliable
for real-world application. For example, in a study conducted by Kozel and colleagues, the
research question posed was not Can you tell if the subject is telling a lie or a truth? but
instead, it investigated the question Which of these responses are lies?(Kozel). In fact, most
studies of fMRI lie detection are investigating this secondary question instead of true lie
detection. It is misleading to equate these laboratory conditions and group data generalizations
with a real-world application, especially when they have the potential to be applied in a context
Supposing we do take this context out of the lab and use it within a real world situation;
research subject getting paid to perform a fMRI study is much more likely to cooperate than a
criminal being tried for murder. And still, even when we have cooperative subjects trying their
best to help us and give us good data, we still throw out one of every five, maybe ten, subjects
because they move too much (Wagner et al.). Head movement that causes artifacts and ruins
scan data can be detected by a researched, but other movements, for example the movement of a
finger, are indistinguishable by the fMRI and cause interference with the tested task for cognitive
reasons. The accuracy rate of lie prediction drops nearly 70 percent when we introduce these
indistinguishable movements (Wagner et al.). Additionally, Dr. Phelps hypothesizes that studies
on the repetition of the Stroop Task indicate that the lying neural signatures could be suppressed
with practice and repetition. Furthermore, Dr. Kanwisher also conjectures that many of the same
Libbey 8
Certainly, these findings are concerning when considering their possible implications within a
court of law.
It is clear that these basic technological obstacles impose serious credibility issues on
fMRI lie detection data. But even if we do apply these faulty techniques to real world situations
and present them as evidence in court, the introduction of fMRI lie detection into a trial as
evidence would most certainly fail. The judiciary imposes safeguards against such misleading
data as this, first and foremost with the Federal Rules of Evidence (Greely). Rule 702 is the
original rule of evidence concerning admissibility of expert witness testimony and scientific
methodology. Established in 1976 this rule was later expounded upon and specified with the
Daubert Standard set forth in the Daubert v Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals Case. The most recent
The Daubert Standard further specifies these requirements with the following: the method must
be testable and tested, peer reviewed, the rate of error must be known and controlled, and the
method must be generally accepted into the scientific community. If it were brought into court
today, lie detection evidence provided by fMRI would never pass these stipulations, nor should
it. To address the first requirement, the evidence given earlier in this brief explains the gross
insufficiency of data surrounding this technology. Nearly no two studies can agree on even the
basic biological mechanisms behind lying. If we are to understand sufficient to mean that
Libbey 9
many data agree, fMRI would not come close. It has also been made clear that the methods of
obtaining lies and truths through fMRI are themselves unreliable until we understand much more
about how the processes of deceit within the brain work. Until then, not only are the methods
know (and the scientific community corroborates) we may never be able to disentangle the
cognitive processes to the extent that is demanded by the law. But even if the confounds present
suddenly disappeared, Rule 403 in the Federal Rules of Evidence would likely bar the data from
Certainly, the prejudicial value of unreliable lie detection evidence would radically outweigh the
benefits. In fact, there arent any. Introducing this data in trial, even if it were accurate, would
surely incite prejudice and bias among a jury. Our system requires that if presented with any
incriminating evidence, the jury must still remain impartial, assume the innocence of the
defendant, and weigh all facts together for their verdict. This type of cumulative evidence would
mislead the jury, essentially replacing a trial of peers run by fact and circumstance with statistics
and weighing probabilities of error. Which, as found in People v. Collins, threatens the very
purpose of the jury itself. While assisting the trier of fact in the search of truth, [evidence] must
This argument is corroborated by the decision in the case of US. v. Semrau, where the
court held to exclude fMRI lie detection evidence presented to bolster defendant testimony
credibility. The scans done on Dr. Semrau were kept out of court because the technology had
Libbey 10
not been fully examined in real world settings [and] was not consistent with tests done in
research studies(Greely). This finding is consistent with what we would expect when analyzing
the data from previous studies: when applied to a real-world setting, this form of lie detection
will not provide predictable results. Additionally, it was found that this evidence violated Rule
403 of evidence, because the data were found to be essentially inconclusive, as well as the scans
All of this raises the issue: the law understands an effective scientific technology as
nearly always an effective judicial technique, but the evidence presented here would support an
argument against this assumption. If most researchers agree that fMRI lie detection is flawed and
for now should stay in the laboratory, and if four U.S. Supreme Court justices have preemptively
argued that the introduction of this type of evidence--reliable or not--would unduly infringe the
province of the jury, who is arguing for fMRI lie detection use in the judiciary? The obvious
Companies like No Lie MRI that market fMRI lie detection services to attorneys have
motive to lobby for fMRI-based lie detection in the courts. The typical fMRI lie test, run just
once, would cost a customer over $5,000. That is about twice the amount it usually costs to
compensate an expert witness to testify on DNA findings, and five times the amount for a DNA
test. But of course, the marketed motive behind this technology isnt just the money, it is the
ability to make something as messy as truth and criminal justice into something as simple as a
yes or a no. In a court system where individuals are given advantage for what they look like and
where they come from, this idea is enticing. If we strip the courts of subjectivity, we strip them
of bias and prejudice. It isnt that simple. The bottom line is that unreliable fMRI lie detection is
a liability. False, ineffective, and uncorroborated science such as this being marketed as fact has
Libbey 11
the potential to affect momentous change in our judiciary. While research is one sphere, the legal
sphere is quite another. It should be made clear that while we do have a precedent in place, our
constitution, which qualifies scientific methods in court when theyre reliable and effective, even
an effective scientific method can fail to be an effective technique of justice. The bottom line:
prejudicial science is clearly needed. The legislation proposed is not a radical measure by any
means. It is only imposing the same regulations we expect from medical research to
neuroimaging research. The FDA was established for many of the very same reasons that fMRI
is raising concern within the legal and scientific communities (Greely). Today, we require that
drugs be proven to be both safe and effective before they can legally leave the laboratory and
reach pharmacy shelves. This legislative change suggests a similar pre-market approval for
fMRI, with the establishment of a commission within the FDA dedicated to this issue and other
issues in the scientific sphere of neuroimaging. Though fMRI lie detection is currently too
unreliable to pose serious threats to the judicial system, the potential harms of this technology as
it stands now, and how it could evolve, are too great to wait. The framework of this regulation
commission is laid out as such: the subject of the regulation will include all neuro lie detection
techniques, including polygraph, EEG, fMRI etc. The committee actually doing the regulation
will accredit methods of lie detection following a similar structure to FDA drug approval, an
initial standardized set of rules dictating the regulations for trials, and research will be
established and revised as technology changes. This will certainly not be easy but with help from
committees from the Department of Defenses Academy for Credibility Assessment, MacArthur
Law and Neuroscience Foundation and others, it is possible to establish some sort of baseline
Libbey 12
from which to begin assessment. A regulatory structure would entirely resolve the current issues
facing fMRI lie detection credibility without stifling attempts to improve upon them. The future
of fMRI lie detection is uncertain. Many argue that it will never reach a level of sufficient
reliability and replicability to be accepted into the scientific community, let alone the legal one.
Nevertheless, this regulation system will establish the precedent that until it improves, whether
that day comes or not, fMRI lie detection cannot breach the barriers of theory or research while
Humans like patterns. We like black and white, simplicity. We like to think we are simple,
but we are not. It truly would be revolutionary if we could discern truth from falsehood by
identifying voxels of electrical impulse in our hippocampus. Unfortunately, telling a lie is much
more complicated than igniting a lying region of the brain. It is intertwined with cognitive
complexity: emotion, imagery, suppression, control. Neuroscience can begin to understand this,
fMRI can scratch the surface of deceit, but it cannot detect lies. At any relevant level of
sophistication or reliability. The research conducted on fMRI-based lie detection has revealed
worlds of complexity and possibility within the brain, but it has not revealed a reliable method of
lie detection. Even if it did prove itself as a reliable and replicable method in the real world, it
still is not compatible with the integrity and function of our judiciary. The possibility of fMRI
passing the standards of evidence set out by our constitution is close to none. Nevertheless, if the
day comes when fMRI-based lie detection passes the regulations in our rules of evidence, the
rules of evidence must adapt to better preserve the power of the jury, and the rights and privacy
of the accused. For now, regulation will do. The passing of this legislation will keep fMRI in the
laboratory, where it--for now--belongs, and in doing so preserve the authenticity and purpose of
Works Cited
Anthony Wagner, Richard J. Bonnie, BJ Casey, Andre Davis, David L. Faigman, Morris B.
Gideon Yaffe, fMRI and Lie Detection: A Knowledge Brief of the MacArthur Foundation
Emilio Bizzi, Steven E. Hyman, Marcus E. Raichle, Nancy Kanwisher, Elizabeth A. Phelps,
(2009). Using Imaging to Identify Deceit: Scientific and Ethical Questions. American
Farah, M. J., Hutchinson, J. B., Phelps, E. A., & Wagner, A. D. (2014) Functional MRI-based lie
detection: Scientific and societal challenges. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 15, 123-31.
Ganis, G., Rosenfeld, J. P., Meixner, J., Kievit, R. A., Schendan, H. E. (2011) Lying in the
Greely, H. (2009). Law and the Revolution in Neuroscience: An Early Look at the Field.
Symposium.
J. Peter Rosenfeld, Bradley Cantwell, Victoria Tepe Nasman, Valerie Wojdac, Suzana Ivanov &
10.3109/00207458808985770
Kozel, F. A., Johnson, K. A., Mu, Q., Grenesko, E. L., Laken, S. J., & George, M.S. (2005)
Libbey 14
58:8, 605613.
Langleben, Daniel. Using Brain Imaging for Lie Detection: Where Science, Law and Research
Policy Collide. Psychol Public Policy Law. 2013 May 1; 19(2): 222234.
doi:10.1037/a0028841.
Ronald J. Allen, M. Kristin Mace, The Self-Incrimination Clause Explained and Its Future
Stoller, S. E., & Wolpe, P. R. (2007). Emerging Neurotechnologies for Lie Detection and the