On Not Loving Everyone

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

ON THE LOVE OF COMMENTARY

ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE: COMMENTS ON


JEAN-LUC NANCYS LAMOUR EN CLATS
[SHATTERED LOVE]
Mathew Abbott

And for what, except for you, do I feel love?

The essay begins with a warning and a series of questions:


The thinking of love, so ancient, so abundant and diverse
in its forms and in its modulations, asks for an extreme
reticence [retenue] as soon as it is solicited. It is a question of
modesty, perhaps, but it is also a question of exhaustion:
has not everything been said on the subject of love? Every
excess and every exactitude? Has not the impossibility of
speaking about love been as violently recognized as has
been the experience of love itself as the true source of the
possibility of speaking in general? We know the words of
love to be inexhaustible, but as to speaking about love,
2
could we perhaps be exhausted?
Much depends on the first sentence of the next paragraph, which
functions as a potential rejoinder and answer to this warning and
these questions: It might well be appropriate that a discourse on love
supposing that it still has something to say be at the same time a
communication of love, a letter, a missive (82; 225f). The possibility
of speaking about love has been placed in question by the sheer
volume of texts that purport to do just that (it is a paradox worth
reflecting on: the fact that something appears to be everywhere means
1

Stevens, Notes Toward a Supreme Fiction, 380.


Nancy, Shattered Love, 82; Lamour en clats, 225 (citations henceforth
given in the text; translations are from Garbus and Sawhney unless a footnote indicates otherwise).
2

139

GLOSSATOR 5
it might be nowhere). Yet exhaustion can be alleviated with a change
in trajectory: if one cannot speak about love, then one can still speak
in it (for [w]e know the words of love to be inexhaustible). That
Nancys essay presents as a treatise on love therefore shows there is
reflexivity here. This may be more than an essay on love. It may also
be a declaration of it. Indeed, if it is what it presents itself as, then it
has to be.
The claims are being made in the conditional (It might well be
appropriate . . . [Et sans doute il conviendrait . . . ]), but this is not
because of modesty (rhetorical or otherwise). As Nancy writes:
[T]he words of love, as is well known, sparsely, miserably repeat
their one declaration, which is always the same, always already
suspected of lacking love because it declares it (82; 226f). A
declaration of love has a very particular and ambiguous
epistemological status. It is perhaps more problematic even than the
kinds of reports more usually associated with the skeptical threats of
the problem of other minds: if it is true that when I see someone
writhing in pain with evident cause I do not think: all the same, his
3
feelings are hidden from me, then in love things are complicated.
Here one can be mistaken in attributing the predicate in love to
oneself (Romeo and Rosaline); here it is not meaningless to say, I
know I am in love (How? I just know); here the intensity of an
affective display can itself cast doubt on what we might presume (or
hope) it is intended to convey (sometimes the louder you shout it, the
hollower you sound). Wittgenstein again: Love is not a feeling. Love
is put to the test, pain not. One does not say: that was not true pain,
4
or it would not have faded so quickly. It is not that love cannot be
proven save through exceptional actions (gifts, sonnets, extravagant
marriage proposals, etc.), but rather that this being put to the test is
crucial to it, and persists with it at all times; there is no way of
proving it once and for all, and so the task it sets is continual. As a
thought experiment, imagine it were possible to use neuroimaging to
determine the intensity of feeling a subject has for a certain person.
Even if one could prove scientifically that a particular man or
woman arouses extreme desire and/or affection in the subject, then
would this be sufficient to prove love? Are such feelings even
necessary to love? Could we not, in certain circumstances,
legitimately speak of it in their absence? Nancys essay will try to
3
4

Wittgenstein, Investigations, 223.


Wittgenstein, Zettel, 504 (translation modified).

140

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


show that this problem the fact that love cannot be proven or
guaranteed is actually a condition of its possibility. As Catherine
Kellogg puts it in a piece on Nancys thought: [I]t is the very
inability to guarantee love the very ephemerality of the experience
5
of loving that calls forth the promise of love in the first place.
Nancys essay turns on this epistemological particularity, which
makes it rather singular. For the text does not just make a claim about
love. It makes a claim about being in the light of love. The argument
is transcendental. To get ahead of ourselves, it says: if there is love
(and there is: I have declared it), then being is finite. Nancys essay
declares love in order to comment on it, and demonstrates that,
because there is love, being is in a certain way. Yet that declaration is
epistemologically ambiguous, because love is not the kind of thing
that can be definitively proven or achieved (demonstrating it
showing it, sustaining it is an ongoing task). As such, Nancys is a
singular kind of transcendental argument. It is a transcendental
argument in which one of the lemmas is a promise. We will come back
to this, for it is arguably the heart of the essay. It shows us something
important about Nancys ontology.
Lets return to the text as it develops. In the next paragraphs,
Nancy invokes once again the reticence required for thinking love,
but cautions against the idea that it stems the fact that it would be
indiscreet to deflower love (83; 226f). It is not that to write or speak
of love entails crudeness or a lack of propriety; it does not mean
debasing something that should really be treated with respectful or
sacred silence. For love has already been marked in art and literature
by an unrestrained and brazen exploitation [exploitation dbride ou
honte] (83; 226f); and this shamelessness, along with the resultant
difficulty of moralising about or sermonising on love, are inherent to
what it is: charity and pleasure, emotion and pornography, the
neighbor and the infant, the love of lovers and the love of God,
fraternal love and the love of art, the kiss, passion, friendship (83;
226 7f). There is no use pretending otherwise: love gets around.
Nancy: To think love would thus demand a boundless generosity
toward all these possibilities, and it is this generosity that would
command reticence: the generosity not to choose between loves, not
to privilege, not to hierarchize, not to exclude (83; 227f). The last
thing love needs is to be arranged taxonomically and valued
accordingly, such that certain of its manifestations are taken to be
5

Kellogg, Love and Communism, 345.

141

GLOSSATOR 5
higher or truer instantiations of its essential principle: if we want to
understand love, then it would be a mistake to attempt to distinguish
between loves on the grounds of how authentic, ethical, painful,
dangerous, healthy, passionate, trite, spiritual, erotic, fidelitous,
sentimental, possessive, romantic, exploitative, narcissistic, or happy
they are. Rather, the extreme multiplicity and indefinite abundance
6
(83; 227f) that marks love is its essential principle. The reticence love
calls for, then, is demanded by the boundless generosity (83; 227f)
one needs in order to think it:
Love in its singularity, when grasped absolutely, is itself
perhaps nothing but the indefinite abundance of all
possible loves, and an abandonment to their dissemination,
indeed to the disorder of these bursts. The thinking of love
should learn to yield to this abandon: to receive the
prodigality, the collisions, and the contradictions of love,
without submitting them to an order that they essentially
7
defy (83; 227f).
At this point, the reflexivity that is so crucial to this essay is pushed
further. Nancy indicates that the generous reticence required here
would be no different from the exercise of thought itself (83; 227f):
thought, insofar as it rejects abstraction and conceptualization,
insofar as it refuses to produce the operators of a knowledge (83
4; 227f), is a practice of openness to something that exceeds it. For
Nancy, as for the later Heidegger, thought does not master its object;
rather, it undergoes an experience, and lets the experience inscribe
itself (84; 227f). This letting [laisse] is important: like Heideggers
Gelassenheit, it links the practice of thought with acceptance and
6

Nancy writes: [Love] is not in any one of its shatters, or it is always on the
way to not being there. Its unity, or its truth as love, consists only in this
proliferation, in this indefinite luxuriance of its essence and this essence
itself at once gives itself and flees itself in the crossing of this profusion. Pure
love refuses orgasm, the seducer laughs at adoration blind to the fact that
they each pass through the other, even though neither stops in the other...
[L]ove is not polymorphous, and it does not take on a series of disguises. It
does not withhold its identity behind its shatters: it is itself the eruption of
their multiplicity, it is itself their multiplication in one single act of love, it is
the trembling of emotion in a brothel, and the distress of a desire within fraternity (102; 256f).
7
Translation slightly modified.

142

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


receptivity. Yet Nancy goes perhaps further than Heidegger in
asserting that thought, which does not lay claim to a particular
register of thinking but rather invites us to thinking as such (84;
227f), is love. As he writes: It is the love for that which reaches
experience; that is to say, for that aspect of being that gives itself to be
welcomed (84; 227f). Thinking love requires generosity, receptivity,
and openness to something in excess of the thinker which is to say
it requires love.
So there is a double reflexivity at work in this essay. Not only
does it have to declare love in order to think it, but this thinking must
itself be carried out as love. This heady confluence of practice and
theory can help explain some of the formal characteristics of the piece
which, if we are to believe its claims, will actually need to
performatively enact them. Given its repeated insistence on the
multiplicitous nature of love, then, it is appropriate that it achieves
this through a variety of means: its refusal to find in any of the
8
various figures of love that it traces a paradigmatic image of it; its
collapse in its postscript into a strange Blanchotian dialogue (which
indicates once again that a text on love might also have to be a
9
communication of it) ; its insistence, and this is inherent in the
contradictory movements of the text as its argument develops, that
the nature of its object is such that any full possession of it would
10
actually represent its loss; its reliance on quotations from and
references to an eclectic range of philosophical and literary sources (a
formal technique that recalls Benjamins Passagenwerk). The text is not
8

Nancy writes: . . . loves ultimate paradox, untenable and nevertheless


inevitable, is that its law lets itself be represented simultaneously by figures
like Tristan and Isolde, Don Juan, or Baucis and Philemon and that these
figures are neither the types of a genre nor the metaphors of a unique reality,
but rather so many bursts [clats] of love, which reflect love in its entirety each
time without ever imprisoning it or holding it back (101; 254f).
9
See 108 9; 267-8f.
10
Nancy writes: There is not one philosophy that has escaped this double
constraint. In each, love occupies place that is at once evident and dissimulated (as, in Descartes, between the theory of union and that of admiration), or
embarrassed and decisive (as, in Kant, in the theory of sublime reason), or
essential and subordinate (as, in Hegel, in the theory of the State). At the cost
of these contradictions and evasions, love consistently finds the place that it
cannot not have, but it only finds it at this cost. What we would have to understand is why this place is essential for it, and why it is essential to pay this
price (86; 230f).

143

GLOSSATOR 5
only a philosophical treatise on love, but also an attempt at a kind of
multiplicitous exposure of it; like love itself, Nancys essay offers
finitude in its truth; it is finitudes dazzling presentation (99; 251f).
This ultra-reflexivity which requires of the essay this intertwining of
content and form, of philosophical claims and their enactment is
part of what makes it beguiling.
None of this entails that the affects we associate with love are
necessarily appropriate to thought. It is not that to think in Nancys
sense of the term requires any particular feeling(s) of the thinker,
whether they are taken either as a condition for, or simple
epiphenomenon of, thinking. Love is not a feeling. Rather it is a
simultaneous opening and obliging of the self: an opening of the self
to something that exceeds it and an obliging of the self to that excess.
To say that thinking is love, then, is not to expound any kind of
irrationalism (such that, for instance, thinking would necessarily
mean being intoxicated, giddy, exalted, etc.). As Nancy puts it: To
say that thinking is love does not mean that love can be understood
as a response to the question of thinking and certainly not in the
manner of a sentimental response, in the direction of a unifying,
effusive, or orgiastic doctrine of thinking (84; 228f). Instead, the
obligation appropriate to love is also appropriate to thought. It is not
exactly an ethical obligation, at least in the mainstream philosophical
sense of the term (after all, it is possible to be in love and to be
unethical; indeed it is possible to be in love and to be evil and
11
sometimes love provokes it). It is an obligation in the etymological
sense of the word, which derives from the Latin ligre, meaning to
bind (think of our ligature, or the speculative etymology of the term
religion as that which binds the human to the divine). Love/thought
ties one to what one loves/thinks. As Nancy writes: [I]t is necessary
to say that thinking is love is a difficult, severe thought that promises
rigor rather than effusion (84; 228f). Love/thought asks something of
the lover/thinker; to engage in it is to be tested. Nancys is not a
sentimental or flabbily relativistic thinking.
11

Nancy writes: (It is perhaps that a hypothesis that I leave open here in
love and in hate, but according to a regime other than that of Freudian ambivalence, there would not be a reversal from hate to love, but in hate I
would be traversed by the love of another whom I deny in his alterity. Ultimately, I would be traversed by this negation. This would be the limit of
love, but still its black glimmer. Perverse acts of violence, or the cold rage to
annihilate, are not hate) (102; 255 6f).

144

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


Implicit in this Heideggerian turn toward the category of
thought is a claim about philosophy. It is not quite that philosophy is
opposed to thought. It is that it is possible to carry on something that
resembles philosophy in the absence of thought; that philosophy can
be (and has been) tempted to forgo thinking. It does so to the extent
that it is an expression of the will to mastery. Philosophy doesnt
think when it refuses the receptivity and risk inherent in thought,
when it fails to maintain itself in relation to an excess, when it tries to
12
reduce everything to knowledge. Yet philosophy is not always or
essentially the will to mastery. Indeed philosophys name points to
this ambiguity: if it is the love of wisdom, it is not the arrival at
wisdom, nor is it the knowledge of it. Nancy: The intimate
connivance between love and thinking is present in our very origins:
the word philosophy betrays it. Whatever its legendary inventor
might have meant by it, philosophy, in spite of everything and
perhaps in spite of all philosophies means this: love of thinking,
since thinking is love (84; 227-8f). The double aspect of philosophy
invoked here is crucial: philosophy is love, but only perhaps in spite
of philosophies. If the practice of philosophy results in a worldview,
or a reasoned commitment to a set of theses (about mind, meaning,
metaphysics, morals, or whatever), then philosophy doesnt think; if
however philosophy admits its obligation toward what exceeds
knowledge, then perhaps it can be worthy of what we call it.
Love/thought is foundational for, yet always in danger of being
denied by, philosophy.
The Symposium is paradigmatic here. On the one hand, the work
signifies first that for Plato the exposition of philosophy . . . is not
possible without the presentation of philosophic love (85; 229f).
Generously welcoming all the different kinds of love, the work
presents the Eros proper to philosophy not with the mastery of a
triumphant doctrine but rather in a state of deprivation and
12

Descartes provides an image of this: [O]pening the thorax of a young live


rabbit and displacing the ribs so that the heart and trunk of the aorta are
exposed, I then tied the aorta with a thread at a certain distance from the
heart, and separated it from everything adhering to it, so that there could be
no suspicion that any blood or spirit could flow into it from anywhere but the
heart; then with a scalpel I made an incision between the heart and the ligature, and I saw with the greatest clarity [manifestissime] blood leaving in a spurt
through the incision when the heart was extending, while, when it was contracted, the blood did not flow (quoted in Grene, The Heart and Blood,
328).

145

GLOSSATOR 5
weakness, which allows the experience of the limit, where thought
takes place, to be recognized (85; 229-30f); in this text, Plato
touches the limits and presents his thought with a reticence
13
[retenue] not always present elsewhere (85; 230f). On the other
hand, however, the Symposium also exercises a mastery over love
(85; 229f): it introduces choices of philosophical knowledge and a
truth regarding love that assigns its experience and hierarchizes its
moments (85; 230f). So the work takes away with one hand what it
gives with the other; it deigns to open its discourse to the multiplicity
of love, but recoils from that multiplicity, substituting the impatience
and conatus of desire for its joyous abandon (85-6; 230f): [I]n Plato,
thinking will have said and will have failed to say that it is love or
to explain what this means (86; 230f). This ambivalence, here
displayed in one of philosophys foundational texts, marks the
traditions inheritance of love. Philosophy needs it, but fails again and
again to display the generous reticence it demands. As Nancy writes:
If thinking is love, that would mean (insofar as thinking is confused
with philosophy) that thinking misses its own essence that it misses
by essence its own essence (91; 237f).
This immanent critique of the tradition of philosophy, in which
the discourse appears as engaged in a flirtation with mastery and
security that would, if consummated, represent the denial of its own
condition of possibility, places Nancys essay firmly in the postHeideggerian tradition of the critique of metaphysics. Nancy, we
might say, here reads the Heideggerian history of (the forgetting of)
being in terms of a missed rendezvous (91; 238f) between
philosophy and love. As Linnell Secomb points out, it reminds in
particular of Levinas, whose own work can be understood as an
attempt at opening philosophy to an experience of difference and
exposure that had been haunting it all along. Nancys loving
philosophy, Secomb writes, is indebted in part, and perhaps most of
all, to Levinas a debt, a gift, a legacy that Nancy lovingly announces
through an exposition of Levinas and an exposure of his own thought
14
to that of Levinas. But of course, Levinass own relation to
Heidegger was nothing if not ambivalent, and Nancys own postHeideggerian reception of Levinas returns the ambivalent favour.
First we should note that Nancys evocation of Levinas in this essay
(which takes place in an extended parenthetical remark) itself begins
13
14

Translations modified.
Secomb, Amorous Politics, 452.

146

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


with a sort of warning: I will be even less explicit with Levinas than
with Heidegger (104; 260f). Secomb takes this as a kind of discretion
(in a Derridean ethical manner he does not return the gift through
eulogy, or dutiful discipleship, for example and instead disseminates
15
the gift of Levinasian ethics) , arguing that Nancys engagement
16
with Levinas is both a critique and a further elaboration. Yet the
critique runs deeper than Secomb seems to acknowledge and the
elaboration, if it is that, is one that calls into question a crucial aspect
of Levinass philosophy. As Secomb recognises, what Nancy finds
problematic in Levinas is the tendency toward teleology on display in
his works in relation to love, which allows him to hierarchise loves
according to the kind of taxonomic procedure Nancy wants to
criticise (Nancy speaks of the the oriented sequence that Levinas,
in a rather classical manner, sets up between fecundity, filiation,
and fraternity (105; 260f)). What we need to recognise, however, is
that the teleology at work in Levinas (or at least, in the Levinas of the
early works, up to and including Totality and Infinity), is the flipside to
his sequential phenomenology, which traces the experience of the self
as it moves from the clutches of the pure fact of being, understood as
17
a totality without content (the anonymous il y a), toward the other.
For Levinas, subjectivity begins in the impersonal and moves toward
ethical experience. As he says at the outset of Time and the Other, it is
toward a pluralism that does not merge into unity that I should like to
18
make my way and, if this can be dared, break with Parmenides. Or
15

Secomb, Amorous Politics, 452.


Secomb, Amorous Politics, 452.
17
Toward the beginning of Time and the Other, Levinas provides a useful
thought experiment to explain the concept of the il y a [there is]: Let us imagine all things, beings and persons, returning to nothingness. What remains
after this imaginary destruction of everything is not something, but the fact
that there is [il y a]. The absence of everything returns as a presence, as the
place where the bottom has dropped out of everything, an atmospheric density, a plenitude of the void, or the murmur of silence. There is, after this destruction of things and beings, the impersonal field of forces of existing.
There is something that is neither subject nor substantive. The fact of existing
imposes itself when there is no longer anything. And it is anonymous: there
is neither anyone nor anything that takes this existence upon itself. It is impersonal like it is raining or it is hot. Existing returns no matter with what
negation one dismisses it. There is, as the irremissibility of pure existing
(Levinas, Time and the Other, 46-47).
18
Levinas, Time and the Other, 42 (my emphasis).
16

147

GLOSSATOR 5
as he puts it in Totality and Infinity: [W]e can proceed from the
experience of totality back to a situation where totality breaks up, a
19
situation that conditions the totality itself. Crucially, the whole
analysis is predicated upon an equation between being as such and an
impersonal, anonymous force that must be evaded for the sake of the
other. And this is precisely what Nancy will challenge in Levinas,
both in his rather subtle parenthetical note, and implicitly but
consistently in the essay at large:
[I]n the es gibt (it gives [itself]) of Being, one can see
everything except generality. There is the each time, anarchic . . . occurrence of a singular existing. There is no
existing without existents, and there is no existing by itself,
no concept it does not give itself but there is always
being, precise and hard, the theft of generality. Being is at
stake there, it is in shatters [en clats], offered dazzling,
multiplied, shrill and singular, hard and cut across: its
being is there . . . This takes place before the face and
signification. Or rather, this takes place on another level: at
20
the heart of being (105; 261f).
Nancy is alluding here to Levinass essay Existence and Existents; the
argument is intended to call its foundational concept that of the il y
a, or the pure fact of being without beings into question. Nancys
ontology is geared from the outset toward a thinking (loving?) of
being in which this image of a radically impersonal being-in-general is
undermined in its very ground. Levinass teleology of love is
problematic not just because it misses the essentially multiplicitous
nature of its object, then, but also because missing this multiplicity
means missing what love has to show about being. Love shows us
that what takes place before the face and signification is not the
brute totality of a there is (which Levinas will figure in terms of a
21
condemnation to being), but rather a there is that is always already
plural: [B]eing-with takes place only according to the occurrence of
being, or its posing into shatters [clats]. And the crossing the
coming-and-going, the comings-and-goings of love is constitutive of
that occurrence (105; 261f). The multiplicity proper to love is
19

Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 24.


Translation modified.
21
Levinas, Existence and Existents, 24.
20

148

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


nothing other than the multiplicity of being itself. As it is exposed,
love exposes being as shattered.
It would be wrong to take this talk of shattering (a necessarily
imperfect rendering of the French clater, which possesses further
connotations of bursting, brilliance, shining, and sparking) to imply
that being is whole before being broken in the experience of love, that
loves shattering shatters a totality. Rather, this shattering has to be
understood as originary: being is always already shattered; to put it a
little awkwardly, we might say that the shard precedes the break. This
is how Nancy avoids the Levinasian problematic of
phenomenologically demonstrating how multiplicity enters into a selfcontained, irremissibly monolithic being (and thus also the basic
problem associated with this: that the multiplicity he establishes
22
remains haunted by that monolith). In another work, Nancy writes:
That which, for itself, depends on nothing is an absolute. That which
nothing completes in itself is a fragment. Being or existence is an
23
absolute fragment. The fragments or shards in play here are not
pieces of some larger puzzle; rather they are absolutely fragmentary,
and do not refer back to some prior whole. Beings multiplicity is not
the result of its lacking unity; it is absolute in its plurality, completely
24
incomplete. Existence is infinitely finite.
Nancy wants to
undermine the idea of pure presence that runs through the early
Levinas; he invokes love in order to show (or rather, to promise) that
being is never a brute totality.
He argues something similar of the self. In love, the self finds
itself to be broken, shattered, and intruded into. If I return to myself
in the experience of love (and importantly, Nancy does not deny that
25
love involves a kind of self-return or self-appropriation), then I
return broken: I come back to myself, or I come out of it, broken
[bris] (96; 247f). If I am in love, then I lose my self (I lose my self
possession); if I am in love, then I find myself, but I find myself to be
mortal, finite, and exposed to something that exceeds me. In love I
22

See Critchley, Very Little... Almost Nothing, 89 93.


Nancy, The Sense of the World, 152.
24
See Nancy, The Sense of the World, 29 33.
25
Nancy writes: Love frustrates the simple opposition between economy
and noneconomy. Love is precisely when it is, when it is the act of a singular being, of a body, of a heart, of a thinking that which brings an end to
the dichotomy between the love in which I lose myself without reserve and
the love in which I recuperate myself, to the opposition between gift and
property (96; 246f).
23

149

GLOSSATOR 5
find myself to have lost myself. As Kellogg puts it, What the other
(who we love) presents to us, Nancy argues, is the fact of her
existence, which is to say, a being whose mortality and finiteness,
26
calls us to know our own. Love is only possible (if it is possible
this is only a promise, after all) between finite, mortal creatures. This
is to say that immortals could not love each other (this is perhaps part of
what our literary, cinematic, and popular cultural traditions evoke
with their images of the vampire: all desire, no love and condemned
27
to the continual torture of that). We could say that lovers share
their finitude, as long as this sharing in understood in an
appropriately rigorous way: not as the sharing of feelings or
experiences, as certain debased contemporary discourses would have
it, but the sharing of an exposure to something excessive, absolutely
inappropriable (and of course, as lovers know, there is pain in this).
Some of the most beautiful passages of Nancys essay are dedicated to
a description of how love exposes the selfs finitude to itself, and to
the other:
[T]he break is a break in his self-possession as subject; it is,
essentially, an interruption of the process of relating oneself
to oneself outside of oneself. From then on, I is constituted
broken. As soon as there is love, the slightest act of love, the
slightest spark, there is this ontological fissure that cuts

26

Kellogg, Love and Communism, 344.


This pits Nancy against Alain Badiou, who analyses love in terms of the
Subjects (or rather Subjects) fidelity to the event of love; a move that, as he
makes clear in his Ethics, renders the loving Subject immortal in a certain important sense. As Badiou writes: The fact that in the end we all die, that
only dust remains, in no way alters Mans identity as immortal at the instant
in which he affirms himself as someone who runs counter to the temptation
of wanting-to-be-an-animal to which circumstances may expose him. And we
know that every human being is capable of being this immortal - unpredictably, be it in circumstances great or small, for truths important or secondary.
In each case, subjectivation is immortal, and makes Man. Beyond this there is
only a biological species, a biped without feathers, whose charms are not
obvious (Badiou, Ethics, 12). While the ethic of fidelity that Badiou constructs displays certain similarities with Nancys idea of love as kind of ongoing promise without guarantee, the distinction here is clear: Badious Subject
is marked by its having been able to rise above the everyday, ordinary, finite
world of mortals. For Nancy, on the other hand, love can only happen to a
finite self, and only exists because being as such is finite.
27

150

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


across and that disconnects the elements of the subjectproper the fibers of its heart. One hour of love is enough,
one kiss alone, provided that it is out of love and can
there, in truth, be any other kind? Can one do it without
love, without being broken into, even if only slightly? (96;
247f)
The temporal progression implied here, however, is something of an
analytical fiction. Just as with being, it is not that love breaks the
unity of the self, or shatters it, or intrudes upon it: rather, it reveals
the self as always already broken, multiplicitious, shattered. As Nancy
acknowledges (a few paragraphs later, in parentheses): [T]he heart is
not broken, in the sense that it does not exist before the break . . . it
is the break itself that makes the heart (99; 250f). What I love is the
others impropriety, the fact that it does not have a hold on itself. But
it is not as though my love renders the other finite in this way.
Rather, it reveals it as such. Or still more accurately, it reveals me as
such as it reveals the other as such, and one for the other in a kind of
mutual astonishment.
Nancy unifies these two claims the claim about being, and the
claim about the heart of the self via a striking image/metaphor, the
precise status of which is rather enigmatic:
Again it is necessary that being have a heart, or still more
rigorously, that being be a heart. The heart of being
means nothing but the being of being, that by virtue of
which it is being. To suppose that the being of being, or
the essence of being, is an expression endowed with
meaning, it would be necessary to suppose that the essence
of being is something like a heart that is to say: that
28
which alone is capable of love (88; 234f).
How are we to take the claim that it is necessary that being be a heart?
It would be uncharitable to simply regard this as a poetic flourish on
Nancys part, as a literary device, affectation, or simple attempt at
28

How striking that this comes from a philosopher who, five years after the
publication of the essay, would have his own heart transplanted. What an
uncanny confirmation of the lack of self-possession that Nancy posits as essential to (the heart of) being!

151

GLOSSATOR 5
ornamentation: if this is a metaphor, then it should be more than
just a metaphor. We need to take it seriously; but how? Here it is
worth acknowledging that Nancys statement here is made in the
subjunctive [que l'tre soit un coeur his emphasis]. It indicates that we
are returning to the theme of the promise.
For Nancy, I love you is the most authentic name for love
itself. It is not simply a constative statement, in that it doesnt just pick
out a fact about the world (say the presence in me of certain strong
feelings). Rather it also does something: it is itself an event, not just a
description of one. But neither (to continue in this Austinian register)
is it a standard performative. While saying I pronounce you man
and wife is clearly an action namely, the act of pronouncing the
status of I love you is more ambiguous. Does saying it mean doing it
in this case? What, besides sincerity, are the felicity conditions of this
performative? At issue is the nature of the act in question is it
really something that happens once, like the pronouncement of
marriage? If I say I pronounce you man and wife, and the power
really is invested in me, then you become man and wife; if I say I
love you, then do I really love you? Even if I am sincere, I can still
be wrong. There are other ways of loving besides saying I love you,
yet one cannot pronounce except by pronouncing. I love you, then,
is a singular kind of statement, one that seems to exist in a zone of
indistinction between the constative and the performative. For Nancy,
it is a sort of promise, and one of a particular sort. It is a promise on
which I am, in a certain fundamental sense, unable to fully make
good (for what would constitute its having been kept?). The
promise, Nancy writes, neither describes nor prescribes nor
performs. It does nothing and thus is always in vain. But it lets a law
appear, the law of the given word: that this must be (100; 253f). A
lack of guarantee thus marks the promise of love: The promise must
be kept, and nonetheless love is not the promise plus the keeping of
the promise. It cannot be subjected in this way to verification, to
justification, and to accumulation . . . Perhaps unlike all other
promises, one must keep only the promise itself: not its contents
29
(love), but its utterance (I love you) (100; 253f).
29

Nancy has returned to this in Dis-Enclosure: The Deconstruction of Christianity,


where he reads the promise without guarantee essential to love in terms of
the Christian category of faith (152): What I am saying here would be
perfectly suitable to our modern definition of faithfulness in love. It is precisely that, for us faithfulness in love, if we conceive of faithfulness as distinct

152

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE

This can explain why Nancy turns to the subjunctive in his claim
about being: to say that it is necessary that being be a heart is not the
same as saying that it necessarily is a heart. Its not that being is a
heart, but that it has to be. To say that it is necessary that being be a
heart is to promise that being is singular and exposed, that it is not the
brute generality that horrifies Levinas, but rather a plurality that
exceeds our attempts at mastering it. If being is a heart, then it is
because of a groundlessness at its heart, the fact that it exposes itself
as depending on no law, no foundation. The lack of guarantee that
defines love is essential to being as such. Nancy:
What appears in [the light of love], at once excessive and
impeccable, what is offered like a belly, like a kissed
mouth, is the singular being insofar as it is this self that is
neither a subject nor an individual nor a communal being,
but that she or he which cuts across, that which arrives
and departs. The singular being affirms even better its
absolute singularity, which it offers only in passing, which
it brings about immediately in the crossing. What is offered
through the singular being through you or me, across
this relation that is only cut across is the singularity of
being, which is to say: that being itself, being taken
absolutely, is absolutely singular (108; 265f).
The claim that it is necessary that being be a heart folds Nancys claim
about being into his claim about the self. Both are thus posited as
simultaneously singular and plural, the that it is of each cutting across
the other. Astonishment at my lover, and astonishment with her;
astonishment at being, and astonishment with it and all these
astonishments bound up together, impossible to tell apart. This
positing of the self/being as a heart is a promising, and its lack of

from the simple observation of conjugal law or of a moral or ethical law outside the conjugal institution. This is even, perhaps, what we mean more profoundly by love, if love is primarily related to faithfulness, and if it is not that
which overcomes its own failings but rather that which entrusts itself to what
appears to it as insufficiency... This is why the true correlate of Christian
faith is not an object but a word... our amorous faith is entirely Christian,
since, as faithfulness, it entrusts itself to the word of other, to the word that
says I love you, or doesnt event say it (153).

153

GLOSSATOR 5
guarantee is essential (one cant be astonished by the appearance of a
link a causal chain).
What love shows if it exists is that there is something in
being that is more than being. It exposes excess at and as the heart of
it. And there is no demonstrating it outside of a love/thought whose
condition of possibility is this very lack of epistemic assurance, this
impossibility of definitive demonstration. If love exists, then it is
because being is (infinitely) finite, but we cannot show or be finally
justified in our (true) belief that it exists. To love/think is to testify to
the existence of something withdrawn from knowledge, to maintain
oneself in relation to an excess that, from the perspective of certain
discourses, is properly invisible. Indeed to Nancys list sexology,
marriage counseling, newsstand novels, and moral edification (102;
257f) we might add evolutionary psychology, and perhaps
romance reality television: the first unsentimentally refusing the
distinction between love and desire, reading love as the simple
expression of desires inherited as the result of adaptive processes; the
second sentimentalising them both, reading them as the expression of
some private, unique, confessing, entertaining self. Both miss love,
because both reduce it to the existence or non-existence of a certain
state of affairs. They miss the groundlessness that is essential to it,
and because of it.
Missing love in this way, these discourses miss the only possible
site of community. This is not because love is the principle or ground
of community (such that our being-together would necessarily be a
kind of loving). It is because love and community share a condition of
possibility in the groundlessness of being. In The Inoperative
Community, which is the title essay from the collection of English
translations in which Shattered Love also appears, Nancy uses the
concept of dsoeuvrement [inoperativity] to get at this groundlessness. It
is useful to understand it as a response to Bataille, who is Nancys key
interlocutor in this essay because of his lifelong obsession with tracing
a mode of exposure that would be irreducible to intersubjectivity,
relations of exchange, and every form of sociality; Nancy finds in
Bataille an ally in the struggle to locate a place of community at once
beyond social divisions and beyond subordination to technopolitical
dominion, and thereby beyond such wasting away of liberty, of
speech, or of simple happiness as comes about whenever these
30
become subjugated to the exclusive order of privatization. At the
30

The Inoperative Community, 1.

154

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


same time, however, Nancy discovers a certain limit to Batailles
thinking here, a certain tendency to oppose to society an immanentist
figure of communal fusion thought in terms of the attainment or
production of common being. For Nancy, Bataille was tempted by a
nostalgic image of community understood according to an image of
ecstatic union, an orgiastic being-together as something that we
have lost in modernity (thus he remains stuck opposing Gesellschaft
with Gemeinschaft something that Nancy, despite his commitment to
31
thinking community, obstinately refuses). This would be the source
of his fascination with fascism (which is itself a grotesque or abject
32
resurgence of an obsession with communion). And because of the
link between the project of communal fusion and death (political or
collective enterprises dominated by a will to absolute immanence,
33
writes Nancy, have as their truth the truth of death), it would also
be the source of his being haunted . . . by the idea that a human
sacrifice should seal the destiny of the secret community of
34
Acphale. The difference between community and communion is
fundamental here; for Nancy, the latter is a violent and dangerous
parody of the former. But of course Bataille, the thinker who for a
long time . . . had represented archaic societies, their sacred
structures, the glory of military and royal societies, the nobility of
feudalism, as bygone and fascinating forms of a successful intimacy of
being-in-common with itself, eventually came to understand the

31

For Nancy, it is not that in capitalist modernity relations of exchange and


domination uprooted and destroyed a previously existing community. What
existed before the rise of capital was something else entirely, something for
which have no name or concept (11). Nancy writes: Community has not taken
place, or rather, if it is indeed certain that humanity has known (or still knows,
outside of the industrial world) social ties quite different from those familiar
to us, community has never taken place along the lines of our projects of it
according to these different social forms. It did not take place for the
Guayaqui Indians, it did not take place in an age of huts; nor did it take place
in the Hegelian spirit of a people or in the Christian agape. No Gesellschaft
has come along to help the State, industry, and capital dissolve a prior Gemeinschaft... community, far from being what society has crushed or lost, is
what happens to us question, waiting, event, imperative in the wake of society
(11).
32
The Inoperative Community, 16-17.
33
The Inoperative Community, 12.
34
The Inoperative Community, 16-17.

155

GLOSSATOR 5
35

ridiculous nature of all nostalgia for communion.


It is this
ambivalence that interests Nancy, the way Bataille wavered on the
edge of a concept of community that would resist both the
36
problematics of sociality or intersubjectivity and the image of
37
community as fusion, community understood as a work of death.
This is what Nancy means when he writes that what he thus had to
38
think at his limit is what he leaves for us to think in our turn.
Batailles thinking is crucial for Nancy because it splits on the very
distinction that he wants to clarify; despite its nostalgic tendencies, it
testifies to the dissolution, the dislocation . . . the unsurpassable
39
conflagration of community that marks our time. This, then, is the
significance of the concept of dsoeuvrement. The capitalist spectacle, we
might say, refuses the worklessness at the heart of community (and
indeed, sets us to work as it does so), privatising the experience of
finitude such that it simply collapses into senselessness. On the other
hand, the nostalgic, orgiastic reduction of community that tempted
Bataille is meant above all to make a work of death, to make death
the work of common life and grant it a total sense. Nancy goes on:
And it is this absurdity, which is at bottom an excess of meaning, an
absolute concentration of the will to meaning, that must have dictated
40
Batailles withdrawal from communitarian enterprises. Thus for
Nancy Batailles eventual renunciation of the nostalgia that marked
his obsession with community must have stemmed from the
acknowledgment that community is workless in an essential sense; that
community is precisely that which resists all our attempts at setting life
and death to work in the constitution of shared meaning. This follows
from Nancys decision to think from out of a proper confrontation
with the finitude of being: it is in the openness of being, its lack of
grounding in any substantial or metaphysical principle, that we
experience the mutual exposure that is community. If the spectacle is
blind to this openness, obscuring it behind the ideological
metaphysics of the private individual, then fascism rages to close it.

35

The Inoperative Community, 17.


The Inoperative Community, 14
37
The Inoperative Community, 17.
38
The Inoperative Community, 25.
39
The Inoperative Community, 1.
40
The Inoperative Community, 17.
36

156

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


Crucial for us is how the image of communion that haunted Bataille
was entwined with an image of love. And of course, Bataille thought
love in terms of absolute loss and expenditure, as a limit experience
that lacerates the self and exposes it to an outside that it cannot
accommodate. Thus community emerges in his thought as dependent
on the sharing of nocturnal terrors and the kind of ecstatic spasms
41
that are spread by death. As he put it in his final address to the
Collge de Sociologie in July 1939:
The sacrificial laceration that opens the festival is a
liberating laceration. The individual who participates in
loss is obscurely aware that this loss engenders the
community that supports him. But a desirable woman is
necessary to he who makes love, and it is not always easy
to know if he makes love in order to be united with her, or
if he uses her because of his need to make love. In the
same way, it is difficult to know to what extent the
community is but the favorable occasion for a festival and
a sacrifice, or to what extent the festival and the sacrifice
bear witness to the love individuals give to the
42
community.
Thinking community according to the image of lovers means
subjecting them both to a logic of sacrifice. Love becomes a work of
death, taking death as its very paradigm (love, Bataille writes,
expresses a need for sacrifice: each unity much lose itself in some
43
other, which exceeds it), and community appears as constituted on
the basis of a sacrificial laceration that bears more than a passing
44
resemblance to sexual laceration. Bataille effects a collapse of the
41

Bataille, Nietzschean Chronicle 208; Nancy quotes this passage without


comment in The Inoperative Community (34).
42
Bataille, The College of Sociology, 251.
43
Bataille, The College of Sociology, 250.
44
Bataille, The College of Sociology, 251. Nancy identifies a similar logic at
work in the figure of suiciding lovers: The joint suicide is one of the mythico-literary figures of this logic of communion in immanence. Faced with this
figure, one cannot tell which the communion or the love serves as a model for the other in death. In reality, with the immanence of the two lovers,
death accomplishes the infinite reciprocity of two agencies: impassioned love
conceived on the basis of Christian communion, and community thought
according to the principle of love (The Inoperative Community, 12).

157

GLOSSATOR 5
conceptual distinctions between love/community and death/sacrifice;
all are fused together in the orgiastic image of communion. Compare
this with the following from Nancy:
Properly speaking, there is no laceration of the singular
being: there is no open cut in which the inside would get
lost in the outside (which would presuppose an initial
inside, an interiority). The laceration that, for Bataille, is
exemplary, the womans breach, is ultimately not a
laceration to the outside. (While the obsession with the
breach in Batailles text indeed indicates something of the
unbearable extremity at which communication comes into
play, it also betrays an involuntarily metaphysical reference
to an order of interiority and immanence, and to a
condition involving the passage of one being into an other,
rather than the passage of one through the exposed limit of
45
the other.)
The difference is subtle but absolutely essential. For Nancy, Bataille
was (involuntarily) metaphysical to the extent that he was wedded to
the opposition between interiority and exteriority (such that, for
instance, lovers would be engaged in an absolute desire to sacrifice
the former for the latter). This is the significance of the breach, the
laceration, and the wound in Batailles thinking: for him, these are
points of entry and openness, points at which the integrity of the self is
threatened with the dissolution that fascinated him. For Nancy, on
46
the other hand, exteriority goes all the way down: as we saw, it is not
that love breaks into the self, violating its integrity; rather it reveals it
as always already broken. Nancys thought of love retains from
45

The Inoperative Community, 30.


As Nancy writes in an essay included in the artists book released with
Phillip Warnells film Outlandish: The body doesnt contain anything, neither
a spirit that couldnt be contained nor an interiority specific to the body, since
the body itself is nothing but the multiply folded surface of the ex-position or
ek-sistence that it is . . . All the way down to its guts, in its muscle fiber and
through its irrigation channels, the body exposes itself, it exposes to the outside the inside that keeps escaping always farther away, farther down the
abyss that it is (Nancys Strange Foreign Bodies, 18). Perhaps this is the
significance of the central image of Warnells film: a live octopus in a tank of
water positioned at the stern of a boat in choppy seas.
46

158

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


Bataille the sense that it exposes a certain unbearable extremity, but
jettisons his sacrificial metaphysics of the void. This is what he means
47
when he writes: [t]here is nothing behind singularity. Nancy thus
refuses the idea, still at work in Bataille, that lovers are lost in a
48
convulsion that binds them together, that in the act of love there is
a dissolution and reconstitution, an overcoming of a prior separation.
As he writes: In love, there is melee without assimilation or
laceration. There is body one in each other and one to each other
without incorporation or decorporation. Love is the melee of two
49
bodies that would avoid all the traps of one. Retrieving love from
the sacrificial register in this way, Nancy is able to extract it from the
paradigm of death. This, in turn, allows for a thought of community
that would not therefore be reducible to the metaphysics of
communion. Love is not the principle of community; it is another
modality of the exposure of the finitude that is shared in community.
And what is shared is not the void but groundlessness: the pure
gratuity of a world without principle.
Given Batailles fierce atheism, it is perhaps ironic that Nancy
links the project of communal fusion that tempted him with
Christianity, arguing that the fascist project represented a convulsion
50
of Christianity, and claiming that the true consciousness of the
loss of community is Christian . . . communion takes place, in its
51
principle as in its ends, at the heart of the mystical body of Christ.
But of course, this should not surprise us, because the Eucharist is
obviously the exemplary model for understanding community
according to a logic of love that would always already be a logic of
sacrifice: community as incorporation, as participation in a single
body. In that sense, Nancys project can be understood as intervening
into the metaphysics of Christianity so as to release something from it
(which is to say that he was engaged in the deconstruction of
Christianity well before Dis-Enclosure). This will underline the
significance of the thought of love available in Lamour en clats,
which turns more than once to the philosophical question raised by
the Christian equation between God and love (Nancy argues, for
47

The Inoperative Community, 27.


College of Sociology, 250.
49
Strange Foreign Bodies, 17-18 (translation modified).
50
The Inoperative Community, 17.
51
The Inoperative Community, 10.
48

159

GLOSSATOR 5
instance, that God is love provides the model for thinking is love
(86; 228f)). If it is true that I can only love that which is finite, then it
follows that the very idea of a universal love for everyone is
incoherent. If there is any sense in the command to love ones
neighbor, then, it will consist in the fact that the neighbor resists
52
becoming a representative of abstract humanity. Similarly, if there
is a love for being, it will be because there is no such thing as
53
everything, because being does not exist except here and here. In the
terms of Nancys essay, it will be because the essence of being is
something like a heart that is to say: that which alone is capable of
love (88; 234f).
Loves uncertain light shows being not as a brute totality, but
exposes it as singular and plural, completely incomplete. I cannot love
being in general, and I cannot love everyone. But perhaps there is
no guaranteeing it I can love this being, this one.

52

Slavoj iek argues that the realisation of universal love is plagued by exceptions for this very reason (see Neighbors and Other Monsters, 182-3).
53
This finitude arguably also forms the (erotic) condition of the possibility of
commentary. Commentary is a mode (or shard) of love because it exposes
the finitude of a text in exposing the real infinity of the task that it sets for
itself: the fact that one can never completely fill the margin. The text always,
as Zarathustra proclaims of all great loves, wants more. Of course, that there is
always more to say means not only that one can never say enough (as the
pseudo-poet proclaims when he bemoans the inadequacy of language in the
face of his beloved), but also that one cannot say everything: just as I can
only love because I cant love everyone, I can only write because I cant write
everything.

160

ABBOTT ON NOT LOVING EVERYONE


REFERENCES
Badiou, Alain. Ethics, trans. Peter Hallward (London: Verso, 2001).
Bataille, Georges. Nietzschean Chronicle, trans. Allan Stoekl et al,
in Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927-1939 (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1985, 202-212.
Bataille, Georges. The College of Sociology, trans. Allan Stoekl et
al, in Visions of Excess: Selected Writings, 1927-1939 (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1985, 246- 253.
Critchley, Simon. Very Little... Almost Nothing (London: Routledge,
2004).
Grene, Marjorie. The Heart and Blood: Descartes, Plemp, and
Harvey, in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of Rene Descartes, ed.
Voss, S. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 324-336.
Kellogg, Catherine. Love and Communism: Jean-Luc Nancys
Shattered Community, Law and Critique (16: 3, 2005), 339-355.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Existence and Existents, trans. Alphonso Lingis
(Pittsburgh: Duquense University Press), 1978.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Time and the Other, trans. Richard Cohen
(Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1987).
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity, trans. Alphonso Lingis
(Pittsburgh: Duquense University Press, 1969).
Nancy, Jean-Luc. Lamour en clats, in Une pense finie (Paris:
Galile, 1990), 225-267.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. Shattered Love, trans. Lisa Garbus and Simona
Sawhney in The Inoperative Community (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1991), 82-109.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Sense of the World, trans. Jeffrey Librett
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997).
Nancy, Jean-Luc. Dis-Enclosure: The Deconstruction of Christianity, trans.
Bergo, Malefant, and Smith (New York: Fordham University
Press, 2008).
Nancy, Jean-Luc. Strange Foreign Bodies in Outlandish: Strange
Foreign Bodies, trans. Daniela Hurezanu (London: Calverts,
2010), 17-24.
Secomb, Linnell. Amorous Politics: Between Derrida and Nancy, in
Social Semiotics (16: 3, 2006), 449-460.
Stevens, Wallace. Notes Toward a Supreme Fiction, in The Collected
Poems (New York: Vintage Books, 1990), 380-408.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M.
Anscombe (Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing, 2001).

161

GLOSSATOR 5
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Zettel, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1967).
iek, Slavoj Neighbors and Other Monsters: a Plea for Ethical
Violence, The Neighbor: Three Inquiries in Political Theology
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006), 134-190.

Mathew Abbott lives in Queanbeyan, Australia. He completed his


PhD in philosophy at the University of Sydney, where he wrote on
the question of political ontology, particularly in relation to Heidegger
and Agamben. He researches phenomenology, aesthetics, and
political theory; he teaches philosophy, poetry, film, and politics. His
first collection is forthcoming with Australian Poetry.

162

You might also like