The Case Study Method in Social Inquiry (Robert Stake, 1978)
The Case Study Method in Social Inquiry (Robert Stake, 1978)
The Case Study Method in Social Inquiry (Robert Stake, 1978)
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Sage Publications, Inc. and American Educational Research Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to Educational Researcher.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 189.125.96.10 on Sun, 06 Dec 2015 20:18:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
The
Case
Study
Method
in
Social
Inquiry,
ROBERTE. STAKE
Universityof Illinois, Urbana-Champaign
It iswidelybelievedthatcasestudies
are useful in the studyof humanaffairs
because they are down-to-earth and
attention-holdingbut thatthey arenot a
suitablebasis for generalization.In this
paper, I claim that case studies will
often be the preferredmethod of research because they may be epistemologically in harmonywith the reader's
experience and thus to that person a
naturalbasis for generalization.
amendedthroughpersonalexperience.
I believe that it is reasonable to conclude that one of the more effective
means of adding to understandingfor
all readers will be by approximating
throughthe words and illustrationsof
our reports, the naturalexperience acquired in ordinary personal involvement.
At the turn of the century, German
philosopher Wilhelm Dilthey (1910)
claimed that more objective and "scientific" studiesdid not do the best job
of acquaintingman with himself.
Onlyfromhis actions,his fixed utterances,hiseffectsuponothers,can
man learn abouthimself;thus he
learnsto knowhimselfonly by the
round-about
way of understanding.
Whatwe once were, how we developedandbecamewhatwe are,we
learn from the way in which we
acted, the plans which we once
adopted,thewayin whichwe made
ourselvesfelt in ourvocation,from
old deadletters,fromjudgmentson
which were spokenlong ago. .
we
ourselvesandothersonly
understand
whenwe transferourown livedexperienceinto everykindof expression of ourown andotherpeople's
lives.
He distinguished between the human
studies and other kinds of studies.
Thehumanstudiesarethusfounded
on thisrelationbetweenlivedexperience, expression,and understanding. Hereforthefirsttimewereacha
quiteclearcriterion
by whichthedelimitationof the humanstudiescan
be definitivelycarriedout. A study
belongsto thehumanstudiesonlyif
its objectbecomesaccessibleto us
theattitude
whichis founded
through
on therelationbetweenlife, expression, andunderstanding.
Dilthey was not urgingus merely to
pay moreattentionto humanisticvalues
or to put more affective variablesinto
our equations. He was saying that our
methods of studying human affairs
need to capitalize upon the natural
powers of people to experienceandunderstand.
Knowledge. In statements fundamental to the epistemology of social
inquiry, Polanyi3 distinguished between propositional and tacit knowledge. Propositionalknowledge - the
knowledge of both reason and gossip
- was seen to be composed of all interpersonallysharablestatements,most
of which for most people are observations of objects and events. Tacit
knowledge may also dwell on objects
and events, but it is knowledge gained
from experiencewith them, experience
with propositions about them, and
rumination.
5
February1978
This content downloaded from 189.125.96.10 on Sun, 06 Dec 2015 20:18:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
naryunderstandings,bothnew andold,
are merely the pieces from which
mighty explanations are made. And
that explanationis the grandestof understandings.But explanationand understanding are perhaps not so intimately interwoven.
Practicallyeveryexplanation,be it
causal or teleologicalor of some
otherkind,canbe saidto furtherour
of things. But "ununderstanding
alsohas a psychologiderstanding"
cal ring which "explanation"has
not. Thispsychologicalfeaturewas
emphasized by several of the
nineteenth-centuryantipositivist
perhapsmostforcemethodologists,
fully by Simmelwho thoughtthat
as a methodcharacunderstanding
is a formof
teristicof thehumanities
in themindof
empathyorre-creation
thescholarof thementalatmosphere,
thethoughtsandfeelingsandmotivations,of the objectsof his study.
is alsoconnected
... Understanding
in a way thatexwithintentionality
the
is not.Oneunderstands
planation
aims andpurposesof an agent,the
meaningof a signorsymbol,andthe
or
significanceof a socialinstitution
religiousrite. This intentionalistic
. . dimensionof understanding
has
come to play a prominentrole in
morerecentmethodological
discussion. (VonWright,1971)
Generalizationmay not be all that despicable, but particularizationdoes deserve praise. To know particularsfleetingly of course is to know next to nothing. What becomes useful understanding is a full andthoroughknowledge of
the particular, recognizing it also in
new and foreign contexts.
That knowledge is a form of
generalizationtoo, not scientific induction but naturalistic generalization,
arrived at by recognizing the
similaritiesof objects and issues in and
out of context and by sensing the
naturalcovariationsof happenings.To
generalize this way is to be both intuitive and empirical, and not idiotic.
Naturalisticgeneralizationsdevelop
within a person as a productof experience. They derivefromthe tacitknowledge of how things are, why they are,
how people feel about them, and how
these things are likely to be lateror in
other places with which this person is
familiar.They seldom take the form of
predictionsbut lead regularlyto expectation. They guide action, in fact they
are inseparablefrom action (Kemmis,
1974). These generalizationsmay become verbalized, passing of course
from tacit knowledge to propositional;
butthey have not yet passedthe empirical and logical tests that characterize
formal (scholarly, scientific) generalizations.
Sociologist Howard Becker5 spoke
of an irreducible conflict between
sociological perspective and the perspective of everyday life. Which is
superior? It depends on the circumstance, of course. For publishingin the
sociological journals, the scientific
perspective is better;but for reporting
to lay audiences and for studying lay
problems,the lay perspectivewill often
be superior. And frequently that
everyday-life perspective will be
superiorfor discourse among scholars
for they too often share among themselves more of ordinary experience
than of special conceptualization.The
special is often too special. It is foolish
to presumethata more scholarlyreport
will be the more effective.
The other generalizations, i.e.,
rationalistic, propositional, law-like
generalizations,can be useful for understandinga particularsituation.And
they can be hurtful. Obviously, bad
laws foster misunderstandings. And
abstractstatementsof law distractattention from direct experience. Good
generalizations aid the understanding
ER
This content downloaded from 189.125.96.10 on Sun, 06 Dec 2015 20:18:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
February1978
This content downloaded from 189.125.96.10 on Sun, 06 Dec 2015 20:18:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
presumed,I fear,thatsomerespondents,
having
heardobjectionsto the case studymethodfrom
such authoritiesas JulianStanleyand Donald
Campbellandthinkingmoreof politicalvalue
thaninformational
their
value,wouldunderrate
andgeneralization.
utilityfor understanding
References
Bacon,SirFrances.NovumOrganum.1620.
Becker,HowardS. Problemsin the publication field studies.In ArthurJ. Vidich,Joseph
Bensman, and Maurice R. Stein (Eds.)
Studies.New York:
Reflectionson Community
JohnWiley, 1964, p. 273.
of inferenceand
Becker,HowardS. Problems
proof in participantobservation.American
SociologicalReview,1958,59, 652-660.
Blake, William.Annotationsto Sir Joshua
Reynold's"Disclosures"1808.
- comBohm,David.Scienceas perception
In F. Suppe(Ed.),TheStructure
munication.
of
ScientificTheories.Urbana:Univ. Ill. Press,
1974.
IX, 1972.
Research
for
Action'
GERARD PIEL
Publisher, ScientificAmerican
search into education must fall, therefore, intothe secondor lowerclass. Not
a disciplinein its own right- I hope, at
least, it does not pretendto such status
- education researchis the object of
the attentionsof the establisheddisciplines: psychology in all its varieties,
sociology, anthropology,demography,
statistics and, nowadays, economics.
Because our universities are departmentalized by discipline and the
scholar's career in each department
turns on contributionto its parochial
interests, it is not surprisingthat much
educationresearchis addressedto the
archivesof the disciplinesandnot to the
improvementof education.
The notionthattherearetwo ways to
do science, andthe unequaldistribution
of rewardsbetweenthem, thustogether
work a disservice to education and,
tion will also, by definition, pass muster in the discipline that has been
brought to bear upon the illumination
and improvementof education.
It is difficult to do social science
well, whetherpureor applied, in a culture as dominated as ours is by the
pragmaticsuccesses of the naturalsciences. The social sciences did not retain for long the innocent confidence
with which they were launchedin the
19th Centuryby Auguste Comte. The
Founderplacedthem at the pinnacleof
the scientificendeavor.In our country,
social scientists began to be elected to
the NationalAcademyof Sciences only
a little morethana decade ago; they are
still defendingtheirstatusas scientists.
The second class citizenship of social scientists causes them to try to
make social researchlook as much as
possible like the work of the physical
and biological sciences. The extreme
case is given by the distinguished
ER
This content downloaded from 189.125.96.10 on Sun, 06 Dec 2015 20:18:01 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions