Jay Moore Behaviorism
Jay Moore Behaviorism
Jay Moore Behaviorism
Sketch
Behaviorism
J. Moore
University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee
Early forms of psychology assumed that mental life was the appropriate subject matter for psychology, and introspection was an appropriate
method to engage that subject matter. In 1913, John B. Watson proposed
an alternative: classical SR behaviorism. According to Watson, behavior was a subject matter in its own right, to be studied by the observational methods common to all sciences. Unfortunately, by around
1930, Watsons behaviorism had proved inadequate. Many researchers
and theorists then adopted a view in which various organismic entities
were inferred to mediate the relation between S and R: mediational
SOR neobehaviorism. This general view has remained influential,
although the details of the various versions have differed over the
years. The behavior analysis of B. F. Skinner took an entirely different approach. Particularly important was the study of verbal behavior.
Although behaviorism is often conventionally defined as an approach
that seeks to explain behavior without directly appealing to mental
or cognitive processes, this definition needs considerable clarification,
especially as it pertains to Skinners behavior analysis and his view of
behaviorism as a philosophy of science.
Key words: behaviorism, cognitive psychology, mentalism, methodological
behaviorism, operationism, hypothetico-deductive method
450
Moore
BEHAVIORISM
451
452
Moore
BEHAVIORISM
453
learning theory of C. L. Hull, referring to the observed number of reinforcements that had taken place in the presence of the stimulus of interest. It
was wholly defined by the observable terms in an equation. Hence, habit
strength was exhaustively defined.
In contrast, consider the term super-ego, from psychoanalytic theory. It
was not the result of computations in the same way that habit strength was.
Rather, it pertained to something that existed in some sense, and it functioned by expressing cultural rules across a wide range of situations, from
sexually tinged childhood episodes to later forms of adult moral conduct. It
was only partially defined by any particular observation.
Early on, both logical positivism and operationism had exhaustively
defined their terms. Perhaps this strategy was useful at the time because
it guarded against unwarranted speculation or extension of analytical concepts when rigor and clarity of thought were at a premium. However, in logical positivism Carnap (1936, 1937) eventually came to de-emphasize exhaustive definitions in favor of partial definitions. Worth noting is that he did so
on the basis of technical considerations in formal logic, analyses of which
are beyond the scope of the present sketch, rather than practical concerns
about the actual derivation and application of the terms.
Important to note at this point is that operationism prompted similar
discussions in psychology. However, these discussions did involve practical concerns, rather than technical considerations involving formal logic:
Theorists objected that with exhaustive definitions, no general systems
could be built that applied concepts across different situations. One example
was mentioned above: super-ego. As another example, consider something
called a negative attitude. Theorists reasoned that a negative attitude
might influence several forms of behavior, not just one. The construct of
a negative attitude therefore needed to have a broad range of application,
across many different situations. Hence, many researchers and theorists
came to emphasize partial definitions because they believed exhaustive
definitions were far too restrictive in the actual conduct of science.
The psychologists MacCorquodale and Meehl (1948) sought to calm the
epistemologically troubled waters by formally proposing a distinction between two interpretations of theoretical terms. They called one interpretation the intervening variable interpretation. According to this interpretation,
terms were exhaustively defined, without remainder, by their relation to
observable measures. As mentioned above, this interpretation was consistent with the original definition of terms under logical positivism and operationism. MacCorquodale and Meehl called the other interpretation the hypothetical construct interpretation. According to this interpretation, terms
were only partially defined by their relation to observable measures. In their
words, hypothetical constructs admitted surplus meaning. This interpretation was consistent with the liberalized definition in logical positivism mentioned above (e.g., Carnap, 1936, 1937). Either usage was acceptable; it was
just a matter of clarifying and being consistent in that usage.
The variables and inferred constructs in the learning theories of
C.L.Hull and K. W. Spence were then analyzed extensively, and numerous
articles debated whether the terms were defined exhaustively or partially,
and were in fact being used consistently. In light of the distinction, Tolman
(1949), who was one of the first researchers or theorists to introduce the
notion of theoretical terms to psychology, quite explicitly abandoned his
454
Moore
BEHAVIORISM
455
456
Moore
common reasoning, brain recordings were taken to indicate some localization of function. That localization of function was, in turn, taken to indicate
that some inner controlling entity or agent, perhaps in the form of a theoretical homunculus, resided in that location. This whole approach simply represented the return to a long-standing dualistic concern with an all-controlling
mind or soul, and it was of concern to many (e.g., Kantor, 1938; Skinner,
1945). In addition, it implied that the construction and testing of hypotheses
involved mysterious mental activities on the part of scientists, not understandable in naturalistic terms. In short, the hypothetico-deductive method
represents a form of epistemological dualism as it concerns the processes
by which scientists are presumed to acquire knowledge.
BEHAVIORISM
457
variables are those that have become significant during the lifetime of the
species, or have been experienced during the lifetime of the organism, including its social-cultural environment. Part of the environment is enclosed
within the skin. We determine functional relations by varying environmental conditions and seeing if behavior varies accordingly, through the experimental method. In special situations it is appropriate to consider doing
nothing or standing still as instances of behavior. Thus, not all instances
of movement are behavior, and not all instances of behavior entail movement. Some instances of behavior occur because an eliciting stimulus has
been presented to the organism, either unconditioned or conditioned. Other
instances occur because in the past, the behavior has produced a particular
consequence in the presence of a particular set of antecedent circumstances,
and those antecedent circumstances are again present. This latter case is
described as a three-term contingency of reinforcement: In the presence of
(a) a discriminative stimulus, (b) a response characteristically produces (c) a
reinforcing consequence. To be sure, a theoretically oriented behavioral neuroscience is clearly a legitimate discipline. There is a sense in which a behavioral account of an event has two gaps. One gap is within the event, from the
time an organism encounters some environmental circumstance to the time
it responds. A second gap is between events, from the time the subject has
a given experience to the time the effects of that experience are reflected in
its behavior. There are physiological phenomena associated with these gaps
that neuroscience can know about and that will increase our ability to predict and control behavior, for example, if information about an organisms
behavioral history is lacking. In any case, behavior is not studied because it
provides evidence that validates theoretical or explanatory inferences about
causes of behavior (e.g., acts, states, mechanisms, processes, entities) from
another dimension (e.g., neural, mental, cognitive, psychic, conceptual). The
bulk of traditional psychology embraces the second perspective, however
implicitly.
2. Analytic concepts: Functional, relational, and generic. Definitions of
concepts are functional and relational. For example, a reinforcer is defined
in terms of its function. It is a consequence of a response that increases
the probability of the response. Furthermore, it is defined by its relation to
the response in question. Readers may note that something with sugar in it
may well function as a reinforcer when it is presented as a consequence of
a response. However, we define it as a reinforcer because of its effect on behavior, not by how much sugar it has in it. Finally, stimuli and responses are
generic conceptsthey belong to classes, and the functional relations (such
as reinforcement) obtain between classes. Class boundaries are sometimes
determined by experience, and sometimes they are innate.
3. Behavior: Public and private. Although many behavioral events are
publicly observable, not all are. Some behavioral events are private, in the
sense that they are accessible to only the person who is behaving. Private
behavioral events are determined by the tools or characteristics of an observer, rather than by anything pertaining to the nature of the event itself
(Donahoe & Palmer, 1994). Typically, these private behavioral events gain
their functional significance through public relations. Consequently, there
is no appeal to autonomous private entities from another dimensional system as causes of behavior. Behavioral principles are developed through the
analysis of public behavior and then used in interpretations of private forms.
458
Moore
BEHAVIORISM
459
460
Moore
BEHAVIORISM
461
For example, a common position in Western culture is that a mental dimension exists that differs qualitatively from a behavioral dimension and that
phenomena in this mental dimension cause behavior. However, this position
goes, explanations cannot appeal directly to the causal mental phenomena
because they are not publicly observable. As a result, another mode of inquiry,
different from one based on direct observation, is necessary to engage the
mental phenomena. The other mode of inquiry may involve something like
rational philosophical analysis, or it may involve engaging the mental indirectly, by using publicly observable phenomena like behavior or physiological
recordings as theoretical proxies for the mental phenomena. The operative
term here is indirectly. According to this position, behaviorism may indeed be
defined as a science of a publicly observable subject matter like behavior, but
the study of behavior is useful only because it provides evidence for conclusions about the unobservable mental phenomena that really cause behavior,
which are then rendered as theoretical and operationally defined in terms
of observables to meet epistemological assumptions about science. So interpreted, this position is consistent with the statements that behaviorism deals
with behavior rather than the mind, and that behavior should be explained
without directly referring to mental events or processes.
However common this position is, behavior analysis rejects it. To repeat,
behavior analysis holds that behavior is a subject matter in its own right.
The study of behavior is not a proxy for concerns with inferred causal factors in another dimension. Behavior is functionally related to environmental
variables at the level of phylogeny, ontogeny, or culture. Both behavior and
environment reflect factors inside or outside of the skin. A mental dimension that differs from a behavioral dimension has never existed for anybody.
Persons talk about the mental because of spurious social influences, not
because mental phenomena literally exist in another dimension and cause
people to talk about them.
The implications are as follows. Suppose we spend our time searching
for causal acts, states, mechanisms, processes, structures, or entities that we
assume are in another dimension. If neither those phenomena nor the other
dimension exist, then we will miss the relevant phenomena in the one dimension that do cause behavior. For example, suppose some traditional form
of psychology attributes an instance of behavior to the presence or absence
of an inferred, inner causal entity called self-esteem. This causal entity is
further assumed to be part of another dimension, which may be variously
characterized as hypothetical, conceptual, or theoretical. Certainly self-
esteem is not itself an entity that is directly observable. Traditional forms
of psychology may then fail to note whether responses have had characteristic consequences in the lives of persons said to possess or lack self-esteem.
Presumably, it is desirable to provide consequences that will result in persons (a) being described as having greater self-esteem and (b) engaging in
more productive, adaptive behavior. We can debate how well it is defined,
whether it is an intervening variable or hypothetical construct, and so on.
But all these debates are simply irrelevant at best. At worst, they damage the
potential of a science of behavior. The important consideration is that when
we appeal to causal phenomena like self-esteem from another dimension,
we do not pay attention to the persons interaction with the environment in
the relevant behavioral dimension, and whether responses in the persons
life have had the necessary characteristic consequences. We therefore miss
Moore
462
References
Boring, E. G. (1950). A history of experimental psychology. New York, NY:
Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Carnap, R. (1936). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419471.
Carnap, R. (1937). Testability and meaningcontinued. Philosophy of
Science, 4, 140.
Catania, A. C., & Harnad, S. (Eds.). (1988). The selection of behavior: The
BEHAVIORISM
463
Study Questions
1. Briefly describe the characteristics of structuralism, according to
the article. Use the terms introspection and contents of consciousness
knowledgeably in your answer.
2. Briefly describe the characteristics of functionalism, according to
the article.
3. Briefly describe the characteristics of Watsons SR classical behaviorism, according to the article. Use the terms objective and molecular knowledgeably in your answer.
4. Briefly describe the characteristics of mediational SOR neo
behaviorism, according to the article. Use the term mediational,
organismic variable knowledgeably in your answer.
5. Briefly describe the distinction between observational and theoretical terms. According to the article, what is the importance of operationism regarding the understanding of theoretical terms?
6. Briefly describe the distinction between the intervening variable
and hypothetical construct interpretation of theoretical terms.
7. Briefly describe the characteristics of the hypothetico-deductive
methodology. Use the term covering law knowledgeably in your
answer.
8. Summarize the following principles of radical behaviorism: (a)
behavior as a subject matter in its own right, (b) private behavior,
(c) selection by consequences at three levels, (d) verbal behavior as
operant behavior, and (e) pragmatism.
9. What is the articles definition of mentalism? Summarize why radical behaviorists object to mentalism.
10. According to the article, what are three reasons why cognitive psychologists appeal to mentalism in their explanations of behavior.
11. Briefly describe the relation between radical behaviorism and behavioral neuroscience, according to the article.
12. Briefly describe the practices known as methodological
behaviorism.
13. Summarize the radical behaviorist argument about why it is not
helpful to explain behavior by referring to mental processes.
464