Thought and Knowledge - An Introduction To Critical Thinking

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 480

Thought & Knowledge:

An Introduction to Critical Thinking


Fourth Edition
This page intentionally left blank
Thought & Knowledge:
An Introduction to Critical Thinking
Fourth Edition

Diane F. Halpern
Berger Institute for Work, Family, & Children
Claremont McKenna College

� LAWRENCE ERLBAUM ASSOCIATES, PUBLISHERS


2003 Mahwah, New Jersey London
Editor: Bill Webber
Textbook Marketing Manager: Marisol Kozlovski
Editorial Assistant: Erica Kica
Cover Design: Robert Perine
Textbook Production Manager: Paul Smolenski
Full-Service & Composition: DC / CCS Information Services, Inc.
Text and Cover Printer: Hamilton Printing Company

This book was typeset in 10/12 pt. Palatino, Bold, and Italic
The heads were typeset in Americana Extra Bold, and Palatino Bold.

Copyright © 2003 by Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.


All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form,
by photostat, microform, retrieval system, or any other means, without
the prior written permission of the publisher.

Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Publishers


10 Industrial Avenue
Mahwah, New Jersey 07430

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-PubIication Data


Halpern, Diane F.
Thought and knowledge: an introduction to critical thinking / Diane F. Halpern. -4th ed.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and indexes.
ISBN 0-8058-3965-8 talk. paper) -ISBN 0-8058-3966-6 talk. paper) 1. Critical thinking. l. Title.
BF441 . H25 2002
1 53-dc21
2002024594

Books published by Lawrence Erlbaum Associates are printed on acid-free


paper, and their bindings are chosen for strength and durability.

Printed in the United States of America


10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
This book is dedicated to the loving memory of
Dr. Katharine D. Newman-
author, professor, friend, aunt, and so much more.
She loved people and she loved learning.
What better tribute is there?
This page intentionally left blank
Contents

Preface xi

1 Thinking: An Introduction I
The Need for Critical Thinking Skills 2
Empirical Evidence That Thinking Can Be Improved 10
Learning to Think Critically: A Four Part Model 14
Intelligence and Thinking Skills 21
Learning to Be Intelligent 25
Becoming A Better Thinker: The Quick and Easy Way 26
Thinking about Thinking 27
Critical Thinking: Hollywood Style 32
A Framework for Thinking 34
Chapter Summary 37
Terms to Know 38

2 Memory: The Acquisition, Retention,


and Retrieval of Knowledge 39
Memory As the Mediator of Cognitive Processes 40
Acquisition 49
Retention 59
Retrieval 63
Working Memory 66
Metamemory 69
Mnemonics 71
Biases in Memory 79
Long-Term Accuracy Is Sometimes Excellent 80
Applying the Framework 81
Chapter Summary 83
Terms to Know 84

3 The Relationship Between Thought and Language 87


Thought and Language 88
Words and Their Meanings 100
Language: Tool or Master of Thought? 106
Comprehension: The Reason for Language 118
Applying the Framework 132
Chapter Summary 134
Terms to Know 134
viii CONTENTS

4 Reasoning: Drawing Deductively Valid Conclusions 1 37


Logical and Psychological 138
Linear Ordering 141
If, Then Statements 146
Combinatorial Reasoning 155
Syllogistic Reasoning 156
Probabilistic Reasoning 173
Reasoning in Everyday Contexts 174
Reasoning Gone Wrong 176
Applying the Framework 177
Chapter Summary 178
Terms to Know 179

5 Analyzing Arguments 1 82
The Anatomy of an Argument 183
Diagramming the Structure of an Argument 189
Actively Open-Minded Thinking 193
Evaluating the Strength of an Argument 195
How to Analyze an Argument 204
A Template for Writing Sound Arguments 205
Persuasion and Propaganda 207
Explaining as Knowing 209
Applying the Framework 226
Chapter Summary 227
Terms to Know 228

6 Thinking as Hypothesis Testing 23 1


Understanding Hypothesis Testing 232
Inductive and Deductive Methods 233
Populations and Samples 236
Science versus Science Fiction 241
Determining Cause 243
Thinking About Errors 253
Self-Fulfilling Prophecies 254
Occult Beliefs and the Paranormal 256
Thinking as an Intuitive Scientist 257
Applying the Framework 259
Chapter Summary 260
Terms to Know 261

7 Likelihood and Uncertainty:


understanding Probabilities 264
Probabilistic Nature of the World 265
Factors Affecting Judgments about
Likelihood and Uncertainty 270
Using Probability 272
Expected Values 282
CONTENTS ix

Subjective Probability 285


Making Probabilistic Decisions 288
Risk 296
Statistical Use and Abuse 300
Applying the Framework 303
Chapter Summary 305
Terms to Know 306

8 Decision Making 308


Making Sound Decisions 309
Pitfalls and Pratfalls in Decision Making 315
Evaluating Consequences 327
Elimination by Aspects 330
Preparing A Worksheet 331
Postdecision Commitment and Evaluation 339
Applying the Framework 343
Chapter Summary 345
Terms to Know 345

9 Development of problem-Solving Skills 348


What Is A Problem? 349
Anatomy of A Problem 350
Stages in Problem Solving 352
Well-Defined and Ill-Defined Problems 355
Problem Planning and Representation 356
Problem-Solving Strategies 372
Problem-Solving Problems 387
Applying the Framework 391
Chapter Summary 392
Terms to Know 393

10 Creative Thinking 396


Defining Creativity 397
Creativity as a Cognitive Process 404
Encouraging Creativity 412
Strategies for Creative Thinking 416
Applying the Framework 425
Chapter Summary 427
Terms to Know 428

1 1 The Last Word 430

References 432

Author Index 453

Subject Index 460


This page intentionally left blank
Preface to Fourth Edition

Based on the belief that it's good for kids to have married parents, some states in the
United States are paying a marriage bonus to couples receiving Temporary Aid to
Needy Families (TANF, formerly known as welfare). When I discussed this novel
approach to social engineering with the students in my college classes, many
thought it was a good idea. However, no one thought that unmarried couples who
receive TANF should have to pay an "unmarried penalty"; none of the students
thought that if couples decided NOT to marry that they should be "fined" or "pun­
ished" financially for their decision. The funny thing about this discussion was that
the students did not immediately understand that if the government provides more
money for couples who get married, it is also paying less money to couples who
don't get married. Whether we call it a "marriage bonus" or "unmarried penalty" is
just a matter of framing-the way we present the information. In one frame (mar­
riage bonus), it seems like a much better idea than the other frame (unmarried
penalty). There are countless similar examples where a change in the way informa­
tion is presented produces large changes in how people feel about the information.
But, with some training in critical thinking, we can learn to recognize framing and
thus not fall prey to attempts to influence what we think by manipulating the way
information is presented.
There are so many other examples where critical thinking skills are important­
ranging from decisions about politics and the environment to personal choices
about whom and when to marry and whether or when to have children. If I say that
only a stupid person would agree with a particular position or that everyone else
agrees with me, it is often easy to sway individual and public opinions against or
for the same position. I can even persuade many people that one brand of soap is
a "good buy" (buy two bars and get one free) or that crime is or isn't a major threat
to your safety by describing the same set of facts as "crime rates are up by 300%"
versus "only five crimes have been committed in a major metropolitan area this
year." Surely crime seems more menacing with the first statistical statement than the
second, even though both can be true.
With the deluge of information on the internet, especially unreliable and even
false information, the need to enhance one's ability to think critically is more critical
than ever before. I hope that you will find the information in the fourth edition of
Thought & Knowledge: An Introduction to Critical Thinking useful and informative.
Over the years, many readers have written to me with real-life examples of the ways
they have used the critical thinking skills that are presented in this book. Please
keep those e-mails coming ([email protected]), and have fun
with this book!

xi
xii PREFACE TO FOURTH EDlTIO�

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS FOR THE FOURTH EDITION

This is the best part-where I get to thank the wonderful people who have helped to
make the fourth edition the best one (so far). Sincere thanks to Dr. Bill Buskist at
Auburn University and Dr. Mark Haviland at the Loma Linda University School of
Medicine for their insightful comments on every chapter. The book has benefited
greatly from their insightful comments and very hard work. I also thank the many
students who have used this book (in earlier editions) over the last 20 years for their
helpful insights. I hope that the many new examples and clarifications will make it
more user-friendly than ever before. Finally, thanks to my wonderful family-my
husband, Sheldon; daughter, Jaye; son, Evan; and daughter-in-law, Karen. You make
it all worthwhile.
1

Thinking: An Introduction

Contents
The Need for Critical Thinking Skills Intelligence and Thinking Skills
Thought and Knowledge The Nature of Intelligence
A Working Definition of Critical The Measurement of Intelligence
Thinking Learning to be Intelligent
What's Critical About Critical Becoming a Better Thinker: The Quick
Thinking? and Easy Way
Changing How People Think: Should Thinking About Thinking
It Be Done? Thinking as a Biological Process
Empirical Evidence That Thinking Can Thinking as Imagery and Silent
Be Improved Speech
Transfer of Training Preferred Modes of Thought
Learning to Think Critically: A Four Critical Thinking: Hollywood Style
Part Model A Framework for Thinking
A Skills Approach to Critical Becoming a Better Thinker: A Skills
Thinking Approach
The Disposition for Effortful Chapter Summary
Thinking and Learning Terms to Know
Performance-Competence
Distinction
Transfer of Training
Metacognitive Monitoring
2 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

Many people would sooner die than think. In fact they do.
-Bertrand Russell (quoted in Macmillan, 1989)

"Think about it!" How many times have you heard this phrase or said it yourself?
Look around you. Watch a student solving a calculus problem, or a programmer
"debugging" a computer program, or a politician arguing that the Strategic Defense
Initiative will not work. Watch a child absorbed in a fairy tale, or an architect de­
signing a skyscraper, or a senior citizen planning to live on a fixed income. What are
they doing that makes their faces appear so serious, so quizzical-so much like
Rodin's famous statue, "The Thinker," which inspired the pose for the beautiful
woman thinker on the cover of this book? They are all "lost in thought," yet lost
seems like a strange word to describe the process of thinking-maybe "creating
knowledge in thought" would be a more appropriate phrase.

THE NEED FOR CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS

Although the ability to think critically has always been important, it is a vital neces­
sity for the citizens of the 21st century. Every generation needs more education than
the one that came before because the world is becoming increasingly technical and
complex. In his award-winning book, Earl Hunt (1995) examined the skills that will be
needed by our workforce in the early decades of this century and asks, ''Will we be
smart enough?" Our quality of life, perhaps even the future of our planet, depends on
how we answer this question. The workforce is one critical place where we can wit­
ness the dizzying pace of change. There is an increased demand for a new type of
worker-the "knowledge worker" or the "symbol analyst," a phrase that is used by
the United States secretary of labor to describe someone who can carry out multistep
operations, manipulate abstract and complex symbols and ideas, acquire new infor­
mation efficiently, and remain flexible enough to recognize the need for continuing
change and for new paradigms for lifelong learning. Workers in almost every job cate­
gory can expect to face novel problems in a workplace that is changing repeatedly. Fa­
miliar responses no longer work, and even newly acquired ones won't work for long.
The information explosion is yet another reason why we need to provide specific
instruction in thinking. It has been estimated that "The world's total yearly produc­
tion of print, film, optical, and magnetic content would require roughly 1.5 billion gi­
gabytes of storage. This is the equivalent of 250 megabytes per person for every man,
woman, and child on earth" (Regents of the University of California,
http:Uwww.sims.berkeley.edu/how-much-info/' January 30, 2001). The sheer mag­
nitude of the information glut is a good example of how much the world is changing
because quantities of knowledge are no longer measured in number of words or
pages, but in units that most people can only vaguely comprehend. (I suppose that
millions of gigabytes of magnetic content is larger than anything I can imagine.)
We now have an incredible wealth of information available, quite literally at our
fingertips, via the Internet and other remote services with only a few minutes of
"search time" on the computer and a few clicks of a mouse. The quantity of data that
is available is overwhelming, creating a "paralysis of analysis" as we make choices
about how to select information from this ever-expanding database (Davidson, 1996).
Relevant, credible information has to be selected, interpreted, digested, evaluated,
learned, and applied or it is of no more use on a computer screen than it is on a
THE NEED FOR CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS 3

distant library shelf. If we cannot think intelligently about the myriad of issues that
confront us, then we are in danger of having all of the answers, but still not knowing
what they mean. The twin abilities of knowing how to learn and knowing how to
think clearly about the rapidly proliferating information that we must select from
are the most important intellectual skills for the 21st century.
The information glut and the constantly changing workplace are not the only rea­
sons why critical thinking is more critical now than at any previous time in history.
For the first time in history, we have the ability to destroy all life on earth. The
decisions that we make as individuals and as a society regarding the economy, con­
servation of natural resources, and the development of nuclear weapons will affect
future generations of all people around the world.
We are called upon to make decisions on a wide range of important local and per­
sonal topics. For example, in a recent election, voters had to decide if they favored
or opposed an increase in property taxes, the construction of a canal that would di­
vert water from one part of the state to another, mandatory AIDS testing for crimi­
nals, and a rent control ordinance, in addition to deciding which candidate they
preferred for diverse political offices including governor, state treasurer, county
commissioner, and trustee of the local library system. Consumers need to decide if
irradiated foods pose a health risk, if the public school system is providing an ade­
quate education, and whether health plans that allow you to choose your physician
are preferable to plans that do not. Because every citizen is required to make count­
less important decisions, it may seem obvious that, as a society, we should be con­
cerned with the way these decisions are made. Surprisingly, it is only within the last
10 to 20 years that educators, politicians, and the general public have begun to ad­
dress this topic in a serious manner.

GRIN AND BEAR IT by Lichty & Wagner

u

<Ii
« .
z ,
"0
> ' .
..
..
t:

U

"Fifty cents tor my thoughts?"


4 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

In the United States, the topic of critical thinking gained widespread attention
when the (U.s.) National Education Goals Panel established educational goals that the
United States would strive to achieve by the year 2000 and beyond. Panel members
realized that our best hope for a strong global economy and for citizens who can par­
ticipate in the democratic process is to produce college graduates with a broad knowl­
edge base and strong critical thinking skills. An educated, thinking citizenry is the best
way, perhaps the only way, to ensure world peace and adequate resources. Accord­
ingly, one of the educational goals that they set for the year 2000 and beyond was that:

The proportion of college graduates who demonstrate an advanced ability to think


critically, communicate effectively, and solve problems will increase substantially.
(National Education Goals Panel, 1 991, p. 237)

Unfortunately, this goal was the only one of the national education goals that was
never funded, despite bipartisan support from both George Bush (the elder) and Bill
Clinton, a fact that led some to cynically suggest that politicians really do not want a
thinking public.
Numerous national reports over the last 25 years have shown that instruction de­
signed to improve the thinking process is desperately needed. In one of the earliest
reports on this problem, the United States was been described as a "nation at risk"
because we are failing to provide students with the most essential component of ed­
ucation-instruction that fosters the development of the ability to think (National
Commission of Excellence in Education, 1983). College faculty from a variety of aca­
demic disciplines list critical thinking (and problem solving) along with communi­
cating, interpersonal skills, and computer literacy as the "the basic competencies or
skills that every college graduate [should] have" (Diamond, 1997). Adult workers
agree, with 81% of the over 1,000 who responded to a national survey, reporting
that critical thinking, literacy, and communication skills are "very important" com­
pared to only 50% who rated computer skills as "very important" (The Chronicle of
Higher Education, 2000). Politicians of every persuasion, blue-ribbon panels, work­
ers, and students all recognize the critical importance of critical thinking as the pri­
mary objective of education.
International studies repeatedly paint a gloomy picture of the current status of
critical thinking. Izawa and Hayden (1993) summarized the results from an interna­
tional comparison in which the best students from the United States scored lower
than the worst Japanese students in mathematical problem solving; abysmal results
were also obtained for reading skills and knowledge of history. Neubert and Binko
(1992), using data from a different study, concluded that only 39% of 17-year-olds
can find, summarize, and explain information. And, in what may be the most horri­
fying tale ever told by the prolific science fiction writer, Isaac Asimov (1989) re­
ported on the true state of scientific understanding and knowledge by Americans. In
a telephone survey conducted by the Public Opinion Laboratory at Northern Illinois
University, Asimov noted that the researchers found that only 20% of the more than
200 adults surveyed believe that the sun revolves around the earth. Why, asks
Asimov, over 400 years since the scientific community agreed on the fundamental sci­
entific fact that the earth revolves around the sun, are the vast majority of adults still
unaware of a basic fact that is "taught" in grammar school science? The depressingly
long list of findings and reports by prestigious panels that conclude that many
adults do not have adequate thinking and learning skills shows that it is time to stop
issuing reports and time to start acting in ways that promote these skills.
THE NEED FOR CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS 5

Numerous other countries have recognized that the world community is growing
smaller and the need for a citizenry that can think critically is imperative in every
country. Such was the conclusion of a panel of experts on higher education that met
in Mexico. They agreed that "the job of the university today is to turn out students
who can think in a rapidly changing world" (De Lopez, 1992, p. B4). News reports
from Pakistan and many different countries in Eastern Europe and Asia also docu­
ment phenomenal growth in the number of college courses designed to help their
students become better thinkers (Bollag, 1997; Cohen, 2000; Collett, 1994).
If the conclusions of national and international study groups don't convince you
of the need for critical thinking instruction, consider this: Most people will finish
their formal education between the ages of 18 and 22. Today's young adults are ex­
pected to have the longest average life span in the history of the world, with most
living into their 70s and many living into their 80s and 90s. We can only guess what
life will be like in the years 2060 or 2070 or beyond, years that many of you who are
reading this book will live through. One likely guess is that many of today's young
adults will be working at jobs that currently don't exist and dealing with technolo­
gies that dwarf the imagination of present-day science fiction writers. What do they
need to learn during their first two decades of life that will prepare them for their re­
maining 50 + years?
It is difficult to imagine any area where the ability to think clearly is not needed.
Yet, few of us have ever received explicit instructions in how to improve the way
we think. Traditionally, our schools have required students to learn, remember,
make decisions, analyze arguments, and solve problems without ever teaching
them how to do so. There has been a tacit assumption that adult students already
know "how to think." Research has shown, however, this assumption is wrong. Psy­
chologists have found that only 25% of first-year college students possess the skills
needed for logical abstract thought-the type of thought needed to answer "what
would happen if. . ." questions and to comprehend abstract concepts (McKinnon &
Renner, 1971). The situation is succinctly summed up by Brock, formerly the Repub­
lican Party chairman and currently an international consultant, who, after reading a
recent report on the low level of learning and thinking skills of college graduates,
exclaimed, "It ought to terrify everybody" (quoted in Frammolino, 1993, p. A41).

Thought and Knowledge

Knowledge will forever govern ignorance: And a people who mean to be their
own Governours, must arm themselves with the power which knowledge gives.
-James Madison
(Texas Library Association, http://www.txla.org/groups/godort/kip-award.htmD

One of the elementary schools that I attended as a child had the words "Knowledge
Is Power" chiseled into a concrete block above its front door. If I were asked
to amend this maxim based on my experiences over the many years since I last
past through those doors, I would edit the concrete block to read "Thought and
Knowledge Are Power," because knowledge is powerful only when it is applied
appropriately, and thought is powerful only when it can utilize a large and accurate
base of knowledge.
This is a book about thought and knowledge and the relationship between these
two constructs. It is about thinking in ways that allow us to use previous knowledge
6 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

to create new knowledge. Everything we know, and everything everyone else


knows-that is, all existing knowledge-was created by someone. When we learn
Euclidean geometry, we are learning about knowledge created by the great mathe­
matician, Euclid. Similarly, other eminent inventions and insights such as the wheel,
shoes, video games, toilet paper, E = mc?, and the "discovery" of America all repre­
sent knowledge created by people. Knowledge is not something static that gets
transferred from one person to another like pouring water from one glass to another.
It is dynamic. Information becomes knowledge when we make our own meaning out
of it. Of course, it is silly to think that we should all start from "scratch" and re-create
the wheel. We build on the knowledge created by others to create new knowledge.
We also create knowledge every time we learn a new concept. The newly acquired
information is used to construct our own internal knowledge structures. ("Knowl­
edge structures" is a technical term used by cognitive psychologists to describe all of
the interrelated concepts that each of us has about different subjects.) Knowledge is a
"state of understanding" that exists only in the mind of the individual knower (King,
1994, p. 16). We use our existing knowledge when we receive new information in
order to make sense of the new information, thus the acquisition of knowledge is an
active mental process. Each individual builds "extensive knowledge structures" that
connect new ideas to what is known so that knowledge is always personal and some­
what idiosyncratic. These knowledge structures or schemata are our personal inter­
nal representations about the nature of the world. When we recombine them in new
ways with other schemata, we are creating new knowledge. This idea was expressed
more eloquently by Resnick (1985, p. 130) when she said: "Knowledge is no longer
viewed as a reflection of what has been given from the outside; it is a personal con­
struction in which the individual imposes meaning by relating bits of knowledge and
experience to some organizing schemata."

A working Definition of Critical Thinking

Ultimately, it is not we who define thinking, it is thinking that defines us.


-Carey, Foltz, & Allan (Newsweek, 1983, February 7)
Although many psychologists and others have proposed definitions for the term
"critical thinking," these definitions tend to be similar in content. In a recent review
of the critical thinking literature, Fischer and Spiker (2000) found that most defini­
tions for the term "critical thinking" include reasoning/logic, judgment, metacogni­
tion, reflection, questioning, and mental processes. Jones and his colleagues (Jones,
Dougherty, Fantaske, & Hoffman, 1995; Jones, Hoffman, Moore, Ratcliff, Tibbetts, &
Click, 1995) obtained consensus from among 500 policymakers, employers, and edu­
cators, who agree that critical thinking is a broad term that describes reasoning in an
open-ended manner and with an unlimited number of solutions. It involves con­
structing a situation and supporting the reasoning that went into a conclusion.
Here is a simple definition that captures the main concepts: Critical thinking
is the use of those cognitive skills or strategies that increase the probability of a
desirable outcome. It is used to describe thinking that is purposeful, reasoned, and
goal directed-the kind of thinking involved in solving problems, formulating in­
ferences, calculating likelihoods, and making decisions, when the thinker is using
skills that are thoughtful and effective for the particular context and type of think­
ing task. Critical thinking is more than merely thinking about your own thinking or
THE NEED FOR CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS 7

making judgments and solving problems-it is using skills and strategies that will
make "desirable outcomes" more likely. Decisions as to which outcomes should be
desirable are embedded in a system of values (Halpern, in press; Sternberg, in press).
One of my favorite definitions of critical thinking was published over 40 years
ago (1960) and comes very close to this contemporary notion of critical thinking as a
learnable skill: "Critical thinking then is the process of evaluation or categorization
in terms of some previously accepted standards . . . this seems to involve attitude
plus knowledge of facts plus some thinking skills" (Russell, cited in d'Angelo, 1971,
p. 6). In short, Russell's equation is:

Attitude + Knowledge + Thinking Skills = Intelligent Thinking

What's Critical About Critical Thinking'?

The "critical" part of critical thinking denotes an evaluation component. Sometimes


the word "critical" is used to convey something negative, as when we say, "She is a
critical person." However, evaluation can and should be a constructive reflection of
positive and negative attributes. When we think critically, we are evaluating the
outcomes of our thought processes-how good a decision is or how well a problem
has been solved. Critical thinking also involves evaluating the thinking process-the
reasoning that went into the conclusion we've arrived at or the kinds of factors con­
sidered in making a decision. Critical thinking is sometimes called directed think­
ing because it focuses on obtaining a desired outcome. Daydreams, night dreams,
and other sorts of thinking that are not engaged in for a specific purpose are not
subsumed under the critical thinking category. Neither is the type of thinking that
underlies our routine habits, which, although goal directed, involve very little con­
scious evaluation, such as getting up in the morning, brushing our teeth, or taking a
usual route to school and work. These are examples of nondirected or automatic
thinking. Other examples of noncritical thinking include the rote recall of informa­
tion (e.g., listing state capitals) or the failure to consider evidence that might support
a conclusion that you do not like.
In thinking about critical thinking, consider, for example, someone in need of
money who decides to remedy this problem with a trip to the racetrack where she
bets on a pretty filly named "Handsome Singer." There is some (small) chance that
she will "win big" if her horse comes in, but this is not an example of critical think­
ing, even if she reflected on her actions and "Handsome Singer" was the first to
cross the finish line. The most likely outcome is that she will lose the money she bet,
surely an undesirable outcome. On the other hand, suppose that she invested her
money in a "blue-chip" stock instead of betting it on "Handsome Singer." There is
some chance that she will lose her money with this strategy, but on average in the
long run, the likelihood of the desirable outcome of having more money is much
higher with the stock investment. The investment is a rational or reasoned course of
action, but it cannot guarantee a desirable outcome. The future is always unknown
and there can never be guarantees about the future, even for the best of thinkers. A
substantial increase in the likelihood of a desirable outcome is the best that critical
thinking can promise, and it is the best hope for the future that anyone can offer.
The focus of this book is on the development and improvement of those skills
that characterize clear, precise, purposeful thinking. It is a practical book, based
8 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

primarily on applications of cognitive psychology to memory, reasoning, problem


solving, creativity, language, and decision making. Despite the fact that some critics
have claimed that critical thinking is just a "fad" that will surely go out of style, it
has a very long history in psychology and education. John Dewey, the pioneering
American educator, identified "learning to think" as the primary purpose of educa­
tion in 1933. Besides, it is difficult for me to consider that the need to think well is a
"passing fancy" that will soon be out of style, much like the Rubik's cube, 'big
hair," and bell-bottom jeans.
Although psychology has been concerned with the way people think for much of its
100+ years of existence as an academic discipline, cognitive psychology, the branch of
psychology that is concerned with thought and knowledge, has virtually dominated
scientific psychology for the past 30 years. Cognitive psychologists are concerned with
learning about the skills and strategies used in problem solving, reasoning, and deci­
sion making and the way these abilities relate to intelligence. All of this interest in
human thinking processes has given birth to a new area of psychology that has come to
be known as cognitive process instruction. Its goal is to utilize the knowledge we have
accumulated about human thinking processes and mechanisms in ways that can help
people improve how they think. For example, by examining correct and incorrect
responses in a variety of situations, psychologists have found that most people's
spontaneous and intuitive approaches to solving problems are frequently wrong.
Furthermore, psychologists can often predict when an incorrect response will be made
either because of the nature of the problem or because of common biases that a prob­
lem solver may bring to the problem. This knowledge is already being put to use to
solve a host of applied problems that range from providing military personnel with
map-reading skills to designing "user-friendly" computer programs.

Changing How People Think: Should It Be Done?

We know that the average American, because of changes in the economy at home
and abroad, will change work seven or eight times in a lifetime . . . . If that is
true, it is clear that we need an agenda as a people for lifetime learning.
-U. S. President Bill Clinton ("Clinton's message," 1994, p. 6A)

The whole idea of influencing the way people think may seem scary. It suggests
terms like "mind control" and "propaganda," or perhaps even a "Big Brother,"
like the one in Orwell's chilling novel 1984, who knew what you were thinking.
In reality, though, critical thinking is an antidote to the kind of mind control that
worried Orwell. Learning the skills of clear thinking can help everyone recognize
propaganda and thus not fall prey to it, analyze unstated assumptions in arguments,
realize when there is deliberate deception, consider the credibility of an information
source, and think a problem or a decision through in the best way possible.
When I discuss the topic of critical thinking with students and other people with
whom I come in contact, I am sometimes told that there is no such thing as critical
thinking because different viewpoints are "all a matter of opinion" and that everyone
has a right to his or her own opinion. They argue that a 'better way to think" does not
exist. I certainly agree that we all have the "right" to our own opinion; however, some
"opinions" are better than others. 1£, for example, you believe that heavy alcohol con­
sumption is good for pregnant women, you had better be able to back up this belief
with sound reasoning. (There isn't any.) The opposite belief, that pregnant women
THE NEED FOR CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS 9

should drink very little, if at all, can be supported with carefully controlled laboratory
studies that document the deleterious effect of alcohol on a developing fetus.
Similarly, everyone has the right to believe in phenomena such as astrology and
extra-sensory perception, but there is no sound evidence to support the existence of
these phenomena. James Randi, a magician and escape artist who is now best
known for his work in debunking claims of psychics and others, has a certified $1
million fund that will be given to anyone who can legitimately demonstrate para­
normal ability under test conditions. The $1 Million Paranormal Challenge is still
unclaimed (James Randi Educational Foundation, http://www.randi.org/research/
index.htmD. All beliefs are not equally good.
Let's consider some examples of the need to think critically. A good place to start
is with commercials. Sponsors pay substantial sums for the opportunity to persuade
customers to purchase their products. An advertising campaign is rated as success­
ful if more of the product is sold after the advertisement, and the additional sales
more than cover the cost of the advertisement. One of my favorite examples is ciga­
rette advertisements. As you undoubtedly know, every cigarette advertisement in
the United States must carry a message like this one: "Warning: The U.s. Surgeon
General has determined that cigarette smoking is dangerous to your health." It
would seem that this message would conjure up visions of hacking coughs, stained
teeth, and lung cancer, and thus reduce the effectiveness of any cigarette advertise­
ment. To counter the surgeon general's warning, many cigarette advertisements
show smokers in natural outdoor surroundings with crystal lakes, clear blue skies,
and tall, green pine trees. One cigarette advertisement reads, "Come to where the
clean is." Another classic cigarette ad reads, "Alive with pleasure"-an attempt to
counteract the association of smoking with premature death.
Have you ever stopped to consider the association of cigarette smoking and the
beauty of an outdoor scene? Does cigarette smoking seem healthier when it is asso­
ciated with beautiful people in beautiful settings? One brand of cigarettes is called
"Malibu." The advertisements depict the soft white sand and foamy blue ocean at
Malibu Beach in California, which is probably the ultimate setting for ''beautiful
people." The beautiful setting that is brought to mind by the name of this brand of
cigarettes is designed to counteract images of sickly people gasping under oxygen
tents-a more probable associate of cigarette use.
Another example of the need for critical thinking comes from a conversation I
once had with a cab driver. Our conversation got around to the way laundry prod­
ucts are advertised. He told me that he never paid any attention to advertisements
and that they had no effect on his decision about which product to buy. He went on
to say that he always buys the blue liquid detergent that is good at getting out "ring
around the collar." Do you see the inconsistency in his statements? Although he be­
lieved that he was not allowing the advertising claims to influence him, in fact, they
were directly determining his buying habits. I doubt if many people worried about
"ring around the collar," "waxy-yellow build-up" on their kitchen floor, "fresh
smelling carpets," or "soft elbows" before commercials told us that we were remiss
and socially undesirable unless we attended to these details. The unstated assumption
in these commercials is that the "problems" they identify (dark lines on the inside
neck portion of shirts, or floors that aren't as clear as new ones) are important ones
that can be remedied if you purchase the advertised products. The cab driver, for
example, accepted the problem of ring around the collar as a valid concern and then
purchased the advertised product without any conscious awareness of the ways his
thoughts and behaviors had been influenced.
10 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

In every political campaign, candidates tell voters that they are opposed to waste,
fraud, pollution, crime, and overpaid bureaucrats. These speeches are inevitably fol­
lowed with loud cheering and applause. (Pay attention to this when you watch the
next political convention-regardless of the party.) What's wrong with these
speeches? The candidates never really say anything. I've never heard any candidate
claim to be for waste, fraud, pollution, crime, or overpaid bureaucrats. Voters should
ask them to be more explicit about their goals, how they would accomplish them,
and where the money would come from to finance political plans.
Here's another example. The following problem was posed to 9-year-olds in the
United States: "Jason bought three boxes of pencils. What else do you need to know
to find out how many pencils he bought?" (Solorzano, 1985). Only 35% of the
youngsters realized that the missing information was how many pencils were in
each box. Here is a problem that was presented to a large sample of 13-year-olds:
"An army bus holds 36 soldiers. If 1,128 soldiers are being bussed to their training
site, how many busses are needed?" (Chance, 1986, p. 26). Most of the students
tested had no trouble carrying out the computations. The problem came in using the
answer in a meaningful way. Many rounded the answer they received to the nearest
whole number and concluded that 31 busses were needed. Others gave a decimal
answer (31.33) or showed the remainder from their long division. The problem was
not one of basic computational skills, but of thinking about the kind of answer that
the problem required and using a strategy that was different from one that was
taught in school, namely rounding "up" to the next highest whole number rather
than rounding to the nearest whole number. Perhaps, simple examples like this one
provide the most convincing answer to the question of whether critical thinking
should be taught. America's most precious commodity is thinking, educated people.
We must make this the goal of education.

EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE THAT THINKING


CAN BE IMPROVED

Everyone agrees that students learn in college, but whether they learn to think
is more controversial.
-Wilbert J. McKeachie (1992, p. 3)
If you've been thinking critically about the idea of improving how you think,
then you've probably begun to wonder if there is any evidence that thinking can be
improved. Although there has been some debate about whether it is possible to
produce long-lasting enhancements in the ability to think effectively (Block, 1985;
Bruer, 1993; Facione, Facione, & Giancarlo, 2000; Glaser, 1984; Halpern &
Nummedal, 1995; Norris, 1992), we now have a considerable body of evidence that
thinking skills courses and thinking skills instruction that is embedded in other
courses can have positive effects that are transferable to many situations. Numerous
qualitatively different forms of outcome evaluations for thinking courses provide
substantial evidence for the conclusion that it is possible to use education to im­
prove the ability to think critically, especially when instruction is specifically de­
signed to encourage the transfer of these skills to different situations and different
domains of knowledge. In fact, it is difficult to identify any aspect of critical think­
ing that could not be taught and learned. We learn mathematics in the belief that
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE THAT THINKING CAN BE IMPROVED 11

mathematical skills can be used in real-world contexts in which they are needed;
similarly, we learn writing and speaking skills in the belief that learners will use
these skills when they write or speak in any context. When students take courses
designed to improve their ability to work with numbers, write, or speak, most
students show improvements. There is no reason why we should believe that
instruction in critical thinking would not show the same positive effects.
Here is a brief summary of some of the findings that support the conclusion that
critical thinking skills can be learned in educational settings and later used in other
contexts:

1. A formal evaluation of a nationwide thinking skills program in Venezuela


showed that students who had participated in classes designed for instruction in
thinking skills showed greater gains in orally presented arguments and in answer­
ing open-ended essay questions than a comparable control group (Herrnstein,
Nickerson, de Sanchez, & Swets, 1986). This study is particularly notable because
the researchers used an experimental design that allowed them to conclude that it
was the instruction and not some extraneous factor that caused students in the ex­
perimental group to improve in their ability to think critically. Students were
assigned at random either to receive the thinking skills instruction or some other
"control" instruction. Additionally, the oral arguments and writing samples were
graded blind; that is, the graders did not know if the students they were assessing
had received the thinking skills instruction or were in the control group. The results
showed that the targeted thinking skills were transferred and used appropriately
with novel topics. Students who received the thinking skills instruction showed
greater gains than the control group students on tests of general aptitude (some­
times called intelligence tests), problem solving, decision making, reasoning,
creative thinking, and language. This experiment provides strong support for the
conclusion that improvements in thinking are possible when instruction is designed
for this purpose. Unfortunately, because of a change in government support for this
program, there are no long-term follow-up data from the Venezuela project, but at
least in the short-term, it does seem that better thinking can be learned.
2. Self-reports by college students show that the overwhelming majority believe
that they have made substantial gains in their ability to think critically after com­
pleting a thinking skills course (e.g., Block, 1985). Students rate themselves higher
on numerous self-report scales including the willingness to suspend judgment, abil­
ity to evaluate conflicting claims, use of likelihood and uncertainty, and utilization
of numerous problem-solving heuristics such as working backward from the goal,
eliminating useless information, and evaluating the credibility of an information
source. Of course, believing that you have improved in the ability to think critically
is not the same as actually demonstrating improvements in critical thinking, but at
least student self-assessments are in agreement with other sorts of data. Taken to­
gether with the other data presented later, self-reports add to our confidence in con­
cluding that long-lasting enhancements in the ability to improve how we think can
result from instruction in critical thinking.
3. Other researchers have used a Piagetian cognitive developmental approach to
determine if critical thinking instruction was associated with greater developmental
gains when compared to a control group. They found that adult students who
received the critical thinking instruction showed greater gains in their level of cogni­
tive development than a matched group that received standard college-level course­
work (Fox, Marsh, & Crandall, 1983). This is an impressive improvement in light of
12 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

the finding that only 25% to 50% of first-year college students possess the skills
needed for abstract logical thought when this ability is assessed with Piagetian mea­
sures (McKinnon & Renner, 1971).
In another study that used a cognitive developmental approach to determine the
effectiveness of critical thinking instruction, Leming (1998) and Kronholm (1993)
taught college students how to think critically about controversial public policy is­
sues. They used the Reflective Judgment Interview that was developed by King and
Kitchener (1994) to measure gains in critical thinking. The Reflective Judgment Inter­
view is a standardized instrument in which students are presented with situations
that call for the evaluation of evidence, expert opinion, and the adequacy of the argu­
ment. Leming and Kronholm found that the students who participated in the year­
long project designed to develop their thinking skills showed significantly greater
gains on the Reflective Judgment Interview than the students who had standard in­
struction. The authors believe that advancement in cognitive developmental stages is
a better way to measure improvements in critical thinking because it can index incre­
mental growth based on each student's starting point prior to instruction.
4. A theoretically advanced means of assessing changes in thinking ability is to
study how a body of knowledge undergoes changes in mental representation. Al­
though the theoretical rationale for this technique is beyond the scope of this book,
the findings of these sorts of studies are easily comprehended. Schoenfeld and
Herrmann (1982), for example, found that when college students were taught gen­
eral thinking skills, they demonstrated substantial improvement in problem solving
relative to students who received more traditional instruction. In addition, these
students organized their mental representation of the content matter in ways that
were more similar to an expert's mental representation than a control group did.
5. Using a skills approach, Facione (1991; Facione, Facione, & Giancarlo, 2000)
found that college students who received coursework in critical thinking scored
significantly higher on a multiple-choice test of thinking skills than comparable
students who had not taken such a course. Other studies have also documented
improvements on multiple-choice tests of critical thinking. For example, Lehman,
Lempert, and Nisbett (1988) found that graduate-level college students improved
significantly on a critical thinking test that included short scenarios about realistic
situations. They concluded that training with general "rules" of thinking is general­
ized to other contexts.
6. The strongest support for beneficial outcomes from critical thinking instruction
comes from a collection of studies by Nisbett and his colleagues (Nisbett, 1993). For
example, in one study, Nisbett and his coauthors phoned students at their home after
the coursework was completed, under the guise of conducting a survey. They found
that students spontaneously applied the thinking skills that they had been taught in
school when they encountered novel problems, even when the school-related context
cues were absent (Fong, Krantz, & Nisbett, 1986). In a different study, inductive rea­
soning tasks were taught to college students using realistic scenarios from many dif­
ferent domains. Students were able to use these skills on a later test. The authors
concluded that critical thinking is "a skill" and that "it is transferable" (Jepson,
Krantz, & Nisbett, 1993, p. 82). Nisbett's (1993) edited book contains 16 chapters that
show that rules of logic, statistics, causal deduction, and cost-benefit analysis can be
taught in ways that will generalize to a variety of settings. A similar conclusion about
the positive effects of courses designed to promote critical thinking was reached in
another independent review of the literature (Bruer, 1993; Chance, 1986).
7. Additional support was reported by Kosonen and Winne (1995), who studied
the transfer of critical thinking skills to a novel domain in a study that used college
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE THAT THINKING CAN BE IMPROVED 13

students, secondary school students, and middle-school students as participants.


Like Nisbett, they found that when students learned general rules about reasoning
and practiced these skills with everyday "ill-structured" problems, the thinking
skills transferred to new contexts and different domains. Most recently, Lovett and
Greenhouse (2000) (building on the work of Paas, 1992, and others) reported similar
results. Lovett and Greenhouse found that when students learned to solve multiple
problems using "varied" problem sets during learning, the initial learning took sig­
nificantly longer, but the students who learned with a variety of examples per­
formed better on transfer problem sets than students who practiced only on similar
problems. Thus, it seems that critical thinking skills are learned best and are most
likely to transfer to novel situations when they are taught using a variety of different
examples. Principles derived from empirical studies like these (and others) that
show the successful transfer of critical thinking skills can serve as a model for in­
structional design. Many important principles from cognitive psychology are ap­
plied in this text to encourage effective learning that lasts.

All of the diverse findings (and many others that are not reviewed here because the
relevant research literature is huge) point to the same conclusion: Adult students can
learn to think more critically when they receive instruction that is designed for this pur­
pose. The assessment studies that used comparison groups suggest that gains are most
pronounced when instruction is specifically designed for the promotion of critical think­
ing. Critical thinking does not automatically result as a by-product of standard instruc­
tion in a content area. A systematic educational effort to improve thinking is needed to
obtain these positive effects (Baron, 1990). Critical thinking instruction needs to focus
overtly and self-consciously on the improvement of thinking, and the learning experi­
ence needs to include multiple examples across domains in order to maximize transfer.

Transfer of Training

Why Johnny can't read was one of the central questions raised about American
education in the 1970s. Why Johnny can't think replaced it in the 1980s.
-A. L. Brown and J. c. Campione (1990, p. 108)

All of these studies that attest to the effectiveness of critical thinking instruction are
studies of the generalizability or transfer of critical thinking skills. The real goal of
any instruction to improve thinking is transfer of training. What I mean by transfer
is the use of critical thinking skills in a wide variety of contexts. The whole enter­
prise of learning how to improve thinking would be of little value if these skills
were used only in the classroom or only on problems that are very similar to those
presented in class. Ideally, critical thinking skills should be used to recognize
and resist unrealistic campaign promises, circular reasoning, faulty probability
estimates, weak arguments by analogy, or language designed to mislead whenever
and wherever it is encountered. Critical thinkers should be better able to solve or
offer reasonable solutions to real-world problems, whether it is the problem of nu­
clear war or how to set up a new video recorder. These skills should also be long
lasting and useful for the many decades of critical thinking that most of us will face.
Admittedly, these are lofty goals, but they are important ones. The best way to pro­
mote the kind of transfer I'm advocating is with the conscious and deliberate use of
the skills that you learn in a wide variety of contexts. Students can actively enhance
transfer by looking for instances that call for critical thinking skills and using them.
14 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

The problems and review exercises that are provided in the exercise book that ac­
companies this text, Thinking Critically About Critical Thinking, are designed to maxi­
mize transfer. A variety of different types of problems are presented about different
topics. By working through these problems, you will increase the likelihood that
you will recall and use the thinking skills that are presented in the text and in real
life when you really need them. There are many variables that affect how likely you
are to transfer a thinking skill from one area of study to another, but we do know
that transfer can and does occur (Klaczynski, 1993). Be sure to be on the lookout for
other instances when these thinking skills are needed, and be sure to use them!

LEARNING TO THINK CRITICALLY:


A FOUR PART MODEL

The model that I have proposed for critical thinking instruction consists of four
parts (Halpern, 1998, in press):

1. Explicitly learn the skills of critical thinking


2. Develop the disposition for effortful thinking and learning
3. Direct learning activities in ways that increase the probability of transcontex­
tual transfer (structure training)
4. Make metacognitive monitoring explicit and overt

Let's consider each of these parts.

A Skills Approach to Critical Thinking

As you work your way through the chapters in this book, you will come across
many different thinking skills, with each chapter containing those skills that are es­
pecially useful in thinking about the chapter topic. For example, the thinking skills
used in understanding likelihood and uncertainty are presented in that chapter. You
may be wondering what a "thinking skill" is. Some examples should help. Here is a
list of generic skills that are important in many situations.
A critical thinker can

• Recognize semantic slanting and guilt by association.


• Seek out contradictory evidence.
• Use the metacognitive knowledge that allows novices to monitor their own
performance and to decide when additional help is needed.
• Make risk: benefit assessments.
• Generate a reasoned method for selecting among several possible courses of
actions.
• Give reasons for choices as well as varying the style and amount of detail in ex­
planations depending on who is receiving the information.
• Recall relevant information when it is needed.

• Use skills for learning new techniques efficiently and relating new knowledge
to information that was previously learned.
• Use numerical information including the ability to think probabilistically and

express thoughts numerically.


LEARNING TO THINK CRITICALLY: A FOUR PART MODEL 15

• Understand basic research principles.


• Demonstrate an advanced ability to read and write complex prose.
• Present a coherent and persuasive argument on a controversial, contemporary
topic.
• Provide complex instructions in language that is appropriate for the audience.
• Use matrices and other diagrams for communication.
• Synthesize information from a variety of sources.
• Determine credibility and use this information in formulating and communi­
cating decisions.

Critical thinking instruction is predicated on two assumptions: (a) that there are
clearly identifiable and definable thinking skills that students can be taught to rec­
ognize and apply appropriately, and (b) if recognized and applied, the students will
be more effective thinkers. Thus, one part of the model for learning to become a bet­
ter thinker is learning how to use the skills of critical thinking and how to recognize
when a particular skill or skills are needed.

The Disposition for Effortful Thinking and Learning

All our dignity lies in thought.


-Blaise Pascal (1623-1662)
No one can become a better thinker just by reading a book or even by just learning a
set of thinking skills that would be useful, if they were used. An essential compo­
nent of critical thinking is developing the attitude or disposition of a critical thinker.
Good thinkers are motivated and willing to exert the conscious effort needed to
work in a planful manner, to check for accuracy, to gather information, and to per­
sist when the solution isn't obvious or requires several steps.

Performance-Competence Distinction
Very often there is an important distinction between what people can do and what
they actually do. This is called the perfonnance-competence distinction. It is of no
value to learn a variety of critical thinking skills if you never use them. Developing a
critical thinking attitude is at least as important as developing thinking skills. Sears
and Parsons (1991) described critical thinking as an "ethic" in order to emphasize the
importance of attitude to good thinking. Facione, Facione, and Giancarlo (2000) found
that students who had positive attitudes toward critical thinking showed the greatest
gains from critical thinking instruction. Many errors occur not because people can't
think critically, but because they don't. One of the major differences between good
and poor thinkers, and correspondingly between good and poor students, is their atti­
tude. A critical thinker will exhibit the following dispositions or attitudes:

1. Willingness to Plan

If everybody thought before they spoke, the silence would be deafening.


-George Barzan
(Cybernation International; http:Uwww.cyber­
nation.com I victoryIquotesI thoughtsandthinking.html)
16 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

I've watched thousands of students (literally) take exams. There are always some
students who begin to write as soon as the exam hits their desk. They just plow
ahead and begin writing before they begin thinking. Not surprisingly, the results
are a disoriented jumble that often bears little relation to the questions being asked.
When asked a question in class, they will often answer with the first idea that comes
to mind. These students need to learn to check their impulsivity and plan their re­
sponse. They should be outlining or diagramming the structure of a response before
they begin to write. Planning, the invisible first step in critical thinking, is essential.
With repeated practice, anyone can develop the habit of planning.

2. Flexibility

In a classic old book, Rokeach (1960) talks about rigidity and dogmatism as the
characteristics of a "closed mind." A person with a closed mind responds negatively
to new ideas by stating, "That's the way I've always done it." Another common re­
tort that shows the unwillingness to consider new ideas is the well-worn phrase, "If
it ain't broke, don't fix it." This sort of close-minded response cuts off consideration
of new ideas. By contrast, an attitude of flexibility is marked by a willingness to con­
sider new options, try things a new way, reconsider old problems. An open-minded
person is willing to suspend judgment, gather more information, and attempt to
clarify difficult issues. This does not mean that all opinions are equally good or that
judgment should take a backseat to openness. It does mean, though, that a critical
thinker is willing to think in new ways, review evidence, and stick with a task until
all reasonable options have been considered.

3. Persistence

"You may be disappointed if you fail, but you are doomed if you don't try."
-Beverly Sills (quoted in James Rogan, Bits & Pieces, 1993, p. 7)

Baron (1987), in an excellent essay on the significance of attitudes, emphasized


the importance of persistence to academic success. Closely related to persistence
is the willingness to start or engage in a thoughtful task. Some people look at a
seemingly difficult task and opt not to even begin the thinking process. They're de­
feated at the start. Others will start working on a task and stop before it is com­
pleted. Good thinking is hard work that requires diligent persistence. Critical think­
ing is usually effortful: It can make you as tired as any physical labor, but can
be much more rewarding. In a comparison of students who were unsuccessful in
mathematics with those who were successful, researchers found that much of the
difference in success rates was directly attributable to differences in attitudes. The
unsuccessful students believed that if a problem could not be solved in less than 10
minutes, then they would not be able to solve it. By contrast, the successful students
persisted in working on difficult problems (Schoenfeld, 1985).

4. Willingness to Self-Correct, Admit Errors, and Change Your Mind When the
Evidence Changes

In science it often happens that scientists say, "You know that's a really good
argument; my position is mistaken," and then they would actually change their
minds and you never hear that old view from them again. They really do it. It
LEARNING TO THINK CRITICALLY: A FOUR PART MODEL 17

doesn't happen as often as it should, because scientists are human and change is
sometimes painful.
-Carl Sagan
(The Review: Science and Pseudoscience Review in Mental Health;
http: / / www.pseudoscience.org! definitions-pseudo.htmD
We all make mistakes. In fact, creative thoughts and actions would not be possi­
ble if we were unwilling to make mistakes, at least some of the time. Instead of be­
coming defensive about errors, good thinkers can acknowledge them and learn
from them. People with good critical thinking attitudes utilize feedback, try to fig­
ure out what went wrong, and try to recognize the factors that led to the error. They
recognize ineffective strategies and abandon them in order to improve the thinking
process. Critical thinkers are also able to change their mind or the conclusion that
they reached, when new information warrants such a change. They do not need to
hold onto an old idea that is no longer justified.
It is interesting to note that the general public usually does not like it when a pub­
lic figure changes his or her mind, especially when the change is away from a con­
clusion that was popular. However, if a person is open to a fair evaluation of new
information, sometimes that information will lead to a different conclusion. It
would be foolish to hold to an old conclusion or belief when it is no longer war­
ranted. The ability to change one's conclusion when new or better information be­
comes known is not "waffling" or some other negative term that is used to describe
someone whose views change as readily as the shifting direction of the wind. What
is needed is a new term that has positive connotations to be used for critical thinkers
who are willing to change conclusions when sound evidence warrants a change. The
progress of science depends on such people, although unfortunately this is one
attitude of critical thinking that is still all too rare.

5. Being Mindful

In order to develop basic thinking skills, it is necessary to direct your attention to


the processes and products of your own thoughts. Langer (2000) defines mindful­
ness as "the simple act of drawing novel distinctions" (p. 220). It is the opposite of
the "automatic pilot" that we use for routine tasks like setting the dinner table, get­
ting to school or work every day, or watching television in the evening. According
to Langer, learning requires a mindful engagement with the task and materials. She
told a humorous personal story about a case of mindlessness that makes this point
well (Langer, 1989). When shopping one day, the clerk told her that she had not
signed the back of the credit card she was using. Langer signed the card, then
handed it back to the clerk. The clerk then processed the sale and had Langer sign
the credit slip. Then, dutifully, as she had no doubt been instructed, the clerk
checked the signature on the back of the newly signed credit card with the signature
on the credit slip. She never realized that she had just seen Langer sign both!
As long as we respond in a mindless or routinized way, problems worth solving
will never be recognized, and creative solutions will be missed.

6. Consensus Seeking

Committee and group organizational structures are most often the norm in the
world of work. Critical thinkers need to be predisposed to seek ways in which
18 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

consensus among group members can be achieved. They maintain an awareness of


the social realities that need to be overcome so that thoughts can become actions.
Consensus seekers need high-level communication skills, but they also need to find
ways to compromise and to achieve agreement. Without this disposition and related
interpersonal skills, even the most brilliant thinkers will find that they cannot
convert thoughts to actions.

Transfer of Training

In becoming a better thinker, it is important to have a large repertoire of critical


thinking skills and to be willing to engage in the effortful process of using them. The
third component of this model involves recognizing when critical thinking is
needed, so that you can select the most appropriate skills for the situation. This is
the Achilles' heel of transfer. The problem in learning thinking skills that are needed
in multiple contexts is that there are no obvious cues in the context to trigger the re­
call of the thinking skill. Critical thinkers need to create the recall cues from the
structural aspects of the problem or argument, so that when the structural aspects
are present, they can serve as cues for retrieval. A similar point was made by Hum­
mel and Holyoak (1997), who said, "First, thinking is structure sensitive. Reasoning,
problem solving, and learning . . . depend on a capacity to code and manipulate re­
lational knowledge."
When critical thinking skills are learned so that they transfer appropriately and
spontaneously, critical thinkers can focus on the structure so the underlying charac­
teristics become salient instead of the domain-specific surface characteristics. An ex­
ample should help here because the idea of transferring skills to novel areas is
highly abstract.
Suppose that you understand the way contrast effects can influence one's judg­
ment. For this example, suppose that you know that if you are offered several part­
time jobs that pay $6 an hour, $8.50 an hour will seem like more money than if you
had been offered several part-time jobs that pay $10 an hour. Even if you know that
contrast effects can influence judgments, will you be able to recognize the power of
contrast effects on your judgment in a totally different situation, such as when your
friend begins a story about his "brush with the law" by telling you about all of the
people from your old high school class who are now in jail? His "brush with the
law" will seem much less serious when it is told after stories about people you know
who committed serious crimes than it would if he had told it after stories about peo­
ple you know who are successful and have not committed any crimes. In this exam­
ple, your hypothetical friend is making his own crime seem less bad by contrasting
it with more serious ones. How can you recognize that the same principle of con­
trast is affecting your judgment in both situations (judgments about pay per hour
and seriousness of a crime)? If you can recognize that the same principle is at work,
you could use the same critical thinking skills to prevent the effect of contrast from
influencing how you think. In other words, how can you learn to apply your knowl­
edge about contrast effects in different sorts of situations?
There is an old saying in psychology that "the head remembers what it does." It
is important to direct your own learning so that the skills of critical thinking are
learned (encoded) in a way that will facilitate their recall in novel situations. It is
what learners do that determines what gets learned. Here are some examples of
thinking tasks that are designed to help with the transfer of critical thinking skills.
LEARNING TO THINK CRITICALLY: A FOUR PART MODEL 19

They require readers to perform certain tasks or answer carefully crafted questions
that draw attention to structural aspects of the problem or argument: If you com­
plete the exercises in the workbook that accompanies this text (Thinking Critically
About Critical Thinking), you will

• Draw a diagram or other graphic display that organizes the information.


• List additional information you would want before answering a question.
• Explain why a particular multiple-choice alternative was selected. Which is
second best? Why?
• State the problem in at least two ways.
• Identify which information is most important. Which information is least
important? Why?
• Categorize the findings in a meaningful way.
• List two solutions for problems.
• Identify what is wrong with an assertion that was made in the question.
• Present two reasons that support the conclusion and two reasons that do not
support the conclusion.
• Identify the type of persuasive technique being used.
• Present two actions you would take to improve the design of a study that was
described.

Tasks like these require learners to focus on structural aspects of the problems so
that the learner can identify and use an appropriate critical thinking skill.

Metacognitive Monitoring

Metacognition refers to our knowledge of what we know (or what we know about
what we know) and the use of this knowledge to direct further learning activities.
When engaging in critical thinking, you will need to monitor your thinking process,
check whether progress is being made toward an appropriate goal, ensure accuracy,
and make decisions about the use of time and mental effort. There is good evidence
that you can become a better thinker and learner by developing the habit of monitoring
your understanding and by judging the quality of your learning (Cohen, Freeman, &
Wolf, 1996). Metacognition is the executive or "boss" function that guides how
adults use different learning strategies and make decisions about the allocation of
limited cognitive resources. Numerous studies have found that good learners and
thinkers engage in more metacognitive activities than poor learners and thinkers,
and that the skills and attitudes of metacognitive activities can be taught and
learned so that students can direct their own learning strategies and make judg­
ments about how much effort to allocate to a cognitive task.
For example, when learners are required to provide reasons and evidence to
support a conclusion and counterreasons and conflicting evidence that refutes
the conclusion, they must focus on the quality of their thinking. The giving of
reasons forces thinkers to "tickle their memory." By this I mean they have to access
information stored in memory. They also have to consider both positive and negative
evidence. It is well documented that we tend to weigh evidence much more heavily
when it favors a belief that we hold over evidence that disconfirms a personal belief
(Stanovich & West, 1997). Numerous studies have found that good learners and
thinkers engage in more metacognitive activities than poor learners and thinkers,
Individual Variables
Situational ( education,
Variables experience)

Initiating Stimulus
(e.g., gasoline gauge
on empty,
an algebra problem,
a crying baby,
a career decision)

Dispositionsl
Attitudes
(motivation,
persistence,
concern for
accuracy)

Survey Broad Categories of Available Critical Thinking Skills

Select and apply skills

�------==------+I
� Metacognitive Monitoring
Are the skills that are being applied making
a desirable outcome more probable?

FIG. 1 . 1 A schematic model of the critical thinking process. Notice how dispositions,
individual background variables, and situational variables all influence the way a situation is
interpreted and the decision as to whether or not it requires the effortful process of critical
thinking. If critical thinking is needed, then individuals select the critical thinking skills that
are most likely to be appropriate for the situation. Five categories of skills are shown in this
diagram. Good critical thinkers have a large repertoire of critical thinking skills to choose
from and are skilled at making selections that are appropriate for the situation. (Critical
thinking skills and the selection of the appropriate skill are learned.) Metacognitive
monitoring is repeatedly cycled as individuals determine if the skills they are using are
increasing the likelihood of a desirable outcome or if other skills are needed. When a "good
enough" outcome is achieved, the process is stopped.

20
INTELLIGENCE AND THINKING SKILLS 21

and that the skills and attitudes of metacognitive activities can be taught and learned
so that students can direct their own learning strategies and make judgments about
how much effort to allocate to a cognitive task (Nelson, 1996; Swanson, 1990).
A schematic diagram of the critical thinking process, including individual differ­
ences and situation variables is shown in Figure 1.1. Notice how dispositions and at­
titudes influence the process at multiple points, beginning with recognizing patterns
in the environment that may require critical thinking (e.g., a gas gauge pointing to
empty or a career decision that needs to be made) and ending with the decision
when to end the thinking process. The skills of critical thinking are selected and
applied as individuals monitor their progress toward a desirable outcome. Good
instruction with structure training will make all of the stages of the process more
efficient and more likely to be successful.
One of the most frequently asked questions concerning thinking skills instruction
is whether learning to be a critical thinker can make someone more intelligent. As
noted earlier (and in numerous other reviews, see for example, Perkins & Grotzer,
1997), substantial evidence exists that instruction in critical thinking really can help
people think better and that improved thinking will transfer to novel contexts. Can
critical thinking improve intelligence? The answer to this important question de­
pends upon how intelligence is defined.

Before you read further, stop for a minute to think about your own definition
of intelligence. If a program of instruction can help learners to think better,
have they become more intelligent?

INTELLIGENCE AND THINKING SKILLS

If we want to improve America's schools, we will have to apply in the classroom


what we know about humans as intelligent, learning, thinking cultures.
--Bruer (1993, p. 1)
One of the most frequently asked questions concerning thinking skills instruction is
whether learning to be a critical thinker will make someone more intelligent The
answer to this important question depends on how intelligence is defined.

The Nature of Intelligence

Solving problems is the specific achievement of intelligence.


--George Polya (1957)
Intelligence is one of the most controversial topics in psychology. It is a basic topic
in thinking because intelligence is the "stuff" of which thought is made. It is difficult
to imagine a context in which intelligence is not manifested or needed. The term in­
telligence is used commonly in everyday language. Most people believe that they
are at least about average or above average in intelligence (Brim, 1966). (Despite
Garrison Keillor's assurances to the contrary, you should realize that this is mathe­
matically absurd because most people can't be above average.)
22 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

Psychologists continue to debate exactly what the term "intelligence" should mean
(Ceci, 1996; Herrnstein & Murray, 1994; Neisser et al., 1996). Think for a minute about
your own definition of intelligence. A dictionary won't be much help, because dictio­
naries define difficult multifaceted concepts like intelligence with a few simple words
that reflect some expert's opinion of what a word means. What should we mean when
we refer to intelligence? This question leads to another and even more important
question, "Who is the appropriate authority to decide what it means to be intelli­
gent?" (The importance of thinking about definitions is a critical thinking skill that is
presented in more detail in Chapter 3, "The Relationship Between Thought and Lan­
guage.") When Robert Sternberg (1982), a psychologist known for his research on
understanding the concept of intelligence, asked people to list the characteristics
of an intelligent person, the following answers were frequently given: "reasons
logically and well," "reads widely," "keeps an open mind," and "reads with high
comprehension." Most people share these intuitive notions of intelligence. These
everyday notions of intelligence are consistent with the definition of critical thinking.
Thus, for most people, intelligent thinking is very similar to the idea of critical
thinking.
Sternberg'S (1999) own definition of intelligence is concerned with the way peo­
ple "achieve success in life, given one's personal standards, within one's sociocul­
tural context" (http:Uspider.apa.org:80/ftdocs/gpr/1999/december/gpr34292.htmD.
Sternberg'S theory of Successful Intelligence is composed of analytic, practical, and
creative intelligences. Each of these three components of Successful Intelligence can
be measured separately, and most tasks involve some combination of two or three
of these intelligences. Sternberg and his colleagues developed a program for teach­
ing successful intelligence to middle-school students (Williams, Blythe, White, Li,
Sternberg, & Gardner, 1996) that they evaluated in many different settings (Gardner,
Krechevsky, Sternberg, & Okaguki, 1994). They reported that students taught with
their three-part intelligence program outperformed control groups that did not re­
ceive this instruction. Thus, they concluded that they successfully taught the chil­
dren to be more intelligent.
Sternberg is not alone in his belief that intelligence can be enhanced with pro­
grams specifically designed for this purpose, although the various researchers do
disagree about the appropriate content for programs designed to enhance intelli­
gence and about the components that make up intelligence. Perkins and Grotzer
(1997) describe a program of instruction that is similar to the approach being used in
this text, with specific instruction in thinking skills, dispositions, meta cognition, and
transfer of training. They concluded that "intelligence can be taught to at least a lim­
ited extent, with more research required to determine the extent to which intelli­
gence can be increased. Instruction can help people to enhance reflective intelligence
with significant generality and persistence" (p. 1125).
The idea that intelligence can be taught is not new. The notion of intelligence as
learning and thinking was articulated early in this century by the famous Russian
psychologist, Lev Vygotsky (1978). He offered an alternative to the static view of
human learning and intelligence as a "fixed quantity" that could be observed and as­
sessed in laboratory settings. According to Vygotsky, intelligence is best indexed by
the way in which people learn, especially when they receive feedback about their
learning, rather than in the level of learning they have achieved at some point in
time. This emphasis is not surprising in light of Vygotsky's work with disadvantaged
populations in the aftermath of the Russian Revolutionary war, in which many
children never had the opportunity to develop their intelligence because of the
INTELLIGENCE AND THINKING SKILLS 23

severe privations of war. These same children often learned new skills and knowl­
edge very quickly when they were given the opportunity to learn, demonstrating
a level of intelligence that could not have been predicted by any standardized mea­
sure that might have been used to test them. Thus, it was their ability to learn from
their experiences that Vygotsky used to define and measure intelligence, not a score
on a test or similar other measure.
Several contemporary psychologists have suggested that conceptualizations of
intelligence need to include emotional aspects of life's success, such as having reward­
ing relationships, empathy, good self-esteem, and optimism (Goleman, 1995; Mehra­
bian, 2000; Salovey & Sluyter, 1997). One way of linking the literature on emotional
intelligence to critical thinking is to consider interpersonal situations as contexts that
call on critical thinking skills. For example, an interpersonal problem at work is no dif­
ferent from any other problem in that it requires good problem statements, generation
of many possible solutions, and selection of a solution that maximizes a desired out­
come-steps that are used to solve any problem, regardless of contexts.
Perhaps the most famous definition of intelligence was offered by E. G. Boring
many years ago in response to the question, "What is intelligence?" He replied:
"intelligence is what the tests test" (1932, p. 35). The "tests" he was referring to
are, of course, standardized intelligence tests. The way psychologists have mea­
sured intelligence has had a direct effect on the way they have come to think about
intelligence.

The Measurement of Intelligence

As you can imagine, the measurement of intelligence has proven to be a difficult


task. The underlying idea is that intelligence exists, and because it exists, it exists in
some quantity (in each individuaD, and because it exists in some quantity, it can be
measured. The only difficulty with this line of reasoning is: "How?"
There is an obvious need to be able to quantify or measure intelligence. Histori­
cally, intelligence tests were designed for a very practical reason. In the early part of
this century, the French government realized the need to know which children
should receive regular classroom instruction and which should receive remedial or
accelerated instruction. Alfred Binet and Theodore Simon were given the job of
designing a test that could be used to place children in the appropriate educational
setting. Modern intelligence tests are still used for this purpose.
Binet and Simon recognized that the type of question that an intelligent 4-year­
old can answer correctly is very different from the type of question that an intelli­
gent 8-year-old can answer correctly. Thus, they devised a test with items that
varied in difficulty for each age level. The tests designed in France by Binet and
Simon have been revised many times. The most popular revision was undertaken
by Lewis Terman, a psychologist at Stanford University. Terman's revision of the
earlier intelligence test is commonly referred to as the Stanford-Binet. Another pop­
ular battery of intelligence tests was written by David Wechsler. He authored two
separate tests, the Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children (WISC) and Wechsler
Adult Intelligence Scale (WAIS) designed for adults over 15 years of age. Wechsler's
intelligence tests yield three IQ scores--one based on verbal test items, one based on
performance test items, and one based on all of the test items, called full-scale IQ.
Following are some test items written to be similar to the ones found in the WAIS
(Jensen, 1980, pp. 144-145).
24 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

Verbal Test Items


1. At what temperature does water freeze?
2. Who wrote The Republic?
3. Why is gold worth more than copper?
4. How many inches are there in 3 1/2 feet?
5. If six men can finish a job in 3 days, how many men would be needed to fin­
ish it in 1 day?
6. In what way are sperm and ovum alike?
7. Repeat a series of digits after the test administrator recites them. (For exam­
ple, a test taker would hear "8175621" and then repeat the digits either in the
same order they were given or in reverse order.)
8. Explain the meaning of strange.
9. Explain the meaning of adumbrate.

Performance Test Items


Test takers are asked to:
10. Translate the numerals 1 to 9 into code symbols (e.g., 1 [, 2
= ), 3 #, etc.).
= =

11. Tell what is missing from familiar objects or scenes (e.g., a clock without
hands).
12. Use wooden cubes painted red and white to duplicate a design shown on
cards.
13. Arrange a series of cartoons into a logical sequence.
14. Assemble jigsaw puzzles.

The actual test items vary in difficulty and are presented in increasing difficulty
within each type of test. The IQ score that an individual receives is determined by
calculating how many questions she or he answered correctly relative to the average
person in the standardization group.
As you can see from these items, intelligence is measured with a variety of
questions. The general knowledge verbal questions tap information that most people
would be expected to learn as a member of our society. For most of us, answering
questions about the temperature at which water freezes involves only memory
retrieval, but it assumes that we had the opportunity to learn this information. Some of
the more difficult ones, like 'Who wrote The Republic?" would obviously favor those
with a good academic background. Abstract reasoning about the nature of supply­
and-demand is needed to answer the question "Why is gold worth more than cop­
per?" The ability to use numbers as well as the knowledge that there are 12 inches in
one foot is needed to answer the fourth question. The answer to question number 6 is
difficult because the differences between sperm and ovum may be more salient than
their similarities. Of course, you also need to know what these terms mean, again fa­
voring anyone with a good (and standard) academic background. Repeating a series of
digits forward or backward requires good memory skills. If you practice the memory
aids (mnemonics) discussed in the memory chapter, you can go off the top of the scale
on this question. The eighth and ninth questions are standard vocabulary questions.
The performance items are more difficult to categorize. Because most of the tests
are timed, speed is an important factor in determining performance IQ. Changing
numerals to code symbols involves a careful balance of speed and accuracy in order
to finish as many numerals to code transformations as possible with few errors.
Question 11 tests your knowledge of common objects. The ability to duplicate
designs is a spatial ability. Arranging a series of cartoons in a logical sequence
LEARNING TO BE INTELLIGENT 25

requires the test taker to generate hypotheses about the actions depicted. It is
necessary to be able to see a whole object from its parts, a spatial ability, to put jig­
saw puzzles together. Intelligence tests assume that the test taker is motivated to
perform well (which is often not true) and that the test taker has had the sorts of ex­
periences that are assumed to be "normative," another assumption that is often un­
warranted. The notion of intelligence that is embedded in standardized tests is that
intelligence is a fixed quantity.
Not surprisingly, intelligence testing yields lower scores for minority groups and
any low-income population because these groups have not had the same learning
experiences that are assumed by the writers of the IQ tests. Readers are probably
aware of the recent, acrimonious controversies surrounding some of these issues,
many of them generated by the publication of a massive book entitled The Bell Curve
(Herrnstein & Murray, 1994). The authors argue that intelligence is largely inher­
ited, that it is measured fairly by standard intelligence tests, that it remains fairly
constant from childhood into old age, and that it is affected only marginally by edu­
cation. I disagree with all of these points (Halpern, 1995).

LEARNING TO BE INTELLIGENT

Cognitive science enables us to go beyond intelligence tests and understand how


the human mind solves problems.
-Robert Sternberg (1992, p. 53)

Thus far, we have considered several different notions of what it means to be intelli­
gent and some of the problems in determining how intelligent someone is. Because
this text is concerned with thinking and helping you to learn how to improve
your thinking, it seems reasonable to return to the question posed at the beginning
of this section: "Will learning to be a critical thinker make you more intelligent?"
For those psychologists who view intelligence as a fixed quantity that can measured
with test items that depend, in part, on the opportunities that are afforded to
individuals (e.g., the rich have more and better educational opportunities than
the poor), then their answer will be "no." However, along with an increasing
number of psychologists, I believe that the static notion of intelligence is wrong
and damaging. If any individual can learn to be a better thinker and subsequently
can use newly acquired thinking skills across a wide variety of contexts, then I
believe that, by definition, that person has learned to be more intelligent. There will
always be some people who are more intelligent than others. There are individual
differences and limits on how well each of us can think and reason, and certainly in­
telligence is also determined, in part, by genetics. However, we all have some
amount of undeveloped potential; everyone can make substantial gains in his or her
intellectual abilities. Even though we can't all be geniuses, we can all learn to think
more intelligently.
Many contemporary psychologists agree that intelligence is comprised of skills
that can be enhanced with training (deGroot, 1983; Nickerson, 1986; Perkins &
Grotzer, 1997). Sadler and Whimbey (1985), pioneers in the area of thinking skills im­
provement, echoed these sentiments when they defined intelligence as "a complex of
skills" (p. 44). The same basic idea can be seen in deGroot's (1983) definition of intel­
ligence as a mental program consisting of heuristics and in Nickerson's (1987) advice
26 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

to teachers that they teach for tactics. Skills, strategies, heuristics, and tactics are all
different words for the same idea-learnable components of intelligent thought.

BECOMING A BETTER THINKER:


THE QUICK AND EASY WAY

"A sucker is born every minute."


-Po T. Barnum (cited in Bartlett, 1980, p. 460)

As I raced through the supermarket after work one day, I was surprised to see a
candy bar called "Think!" Just what I needed, a candy bar with "mind-enhancing in­
gredients." And to think (oops, pardon the pun) that I was working hard to learn bet­
ter thinking skills when all I had to do was eat a candy bar. Apparently, I am not the
only one to wonder about "Think!" candy bars. The Center for Science in the Public
Interest, a nonprofit organization of health and science professionals, investigated
this candy bar in a recent issue of Nutrition Action HealthLetter (Science in the Public
Interest, 2000). They contacted the candy bar company for evidence to back up the
claim that the ingredients in "Think!" can help you "stay sharp." Here's the com­
pany's response: "We're not claiming that it helps you think,' insists Garret Jennings,
the inventor of Think!, the 'Food for Thought' bar. . . . But, if somebody feels great
after a Think! Bar,' asks Jennings, 'who cares if that is just a placebo effect?'" (p. 12).
I hope that your response to the question posed at the end of the last paragraph
is, "I do." A placebo is used as a control or comparison whenever drugs are tested­
it is the condition that contains no active drugs-you may know it as a "sugar pill."
Sometimes just the belief that we are taking a "drug" that will improve the ability to
think can lead us to believe that we really are thinking better, even when we are not.
But then, I guess this thinking-candy is targeted at consumers who are not good
thinkers in the first place. Of course, it is possible that there are some ingredients
that could enhance the ability to think. The question for thoughtful consumers is
"What is the evidence that this product does what the manufacturer claims?"
According to Science in the Public Interest, the answer is "none."
Unfortunately, there are no quick and easy programs that will make you a better
thinker, despite some unscrupulous claims that you can think better instantly, with­
out really trying. One article in a supermarket-checkout-line "newspaper" claimed
that pregnant women could make their as yet unborn children more intelligent by
listening to fine music and reading classical literature during their pregnancy. Other
ludicrous schemes for better thinking include breathing into paper bags and listen­
ing to subliminal tapes. A large-scale study by The National Academy of Sciences
concluded that there is no scientific evidence to support the claim that biofeed­
back, "neurolinguistic programming," subliminal learning, or other commercial
"super learning" techniques can improve your thinking (Gillette, 1987; Greenwald,
Spangenberg, Pratkanis, & Eskenazi, 1991; Hostetler, 1988). In a second major study,
the National Research Council (1994) found that there is no evidence to support
claims that sleep-learning is possible, even though most of us believe that it sure
would be nice. A trip through most so-called "health food stores" will reveal a wide
variety of products and pseudo-medicines that claim or suggest that they can im­
prove your memory, enhance your thinking, or do whatever else is desirable (e.g.,
make you thin, sexy, strong, and smart). However, there is usually little or no valid
evidence that any of these products can bring about their promised effects.
THINKING ABOUT THINKING 27

THINKING ABOUT THINKING

You are today where your thoughts have brought you; you will be tomorrow
where your thoughts take you.
-James Allen (Cybernation International,
http: //www.cybernation.com/victory / quotes.. subjects/
quotes thoughtsandthinking.html)
_

There are many different ways to conceptualize the thinking process. From the per­
spective of a neuropsychologist or biologist, thinking is the activation of groups of
neurons. Other researchers study the medium of thought, that is, the conscious and
unconscious use of symbols, images, and words. Another approach is to conceptual­
ize thinking as the flow and transformation of information through a series of
stages. As I think about using the brain to think about the way the brain works, I am
reminded about a joke I once heard: A comedian commented that he never eats
tongue, a common food in many cultures, because he wonders if the tongue he is
eating is tasting him while he is tasting it. Similarly, I wonder if we can use our
brain to reveal its own mysteries?

Thinking as a Biological Process

The brain exists in order to construct representations of the world.


-Philip Johnson-Laird (quoted in Restak, 1988, p. 235)
Researchers from many fields have spent their lifetimes trying to understand what
people do when they think. Brain researchers are interested in understanding how
the brain and other parts of the nervous system work. Every time you have a
thought, feel an emotion, or receive information through your senses, your nervous
system is involved. If you could examine your own brain, you would no doubt
be surprised to find that it looks like a giant mushy walnut with the consistency of
a soft-boiled egg. There is nothing in its appearance to even suggest that it is the
foundation of human thought.
The capacity of the human brain is awesome. "If each of the brain's 10 to 15 billion
neurons is capable of only two states, on or off, the capacity of the brain would be 2 10
billionth power. To write out this number at the rate of one digit per second would
take ninety years" (The Chronicle of Higher Education, 1987, p. A2). Even if these fig­
ures are off by a few billion or so, it is clear that we each have some undeveloped po­
tential. The human brain has remained essentially unchanged since the dawn of
modern history, yet during that time humans have used this amazing mass to de­
velop advanced technologies that include the ability to visit distant planets and have
more than doubled the average expected life span. What has changed is "the infor­
mation that is going into the brain and the processing it receives" (Machado, cited in
Walsh, 1981, p. 640.) It is the ability to learn and to think that has changed the world.
Although brain researchers have discovered fascinating links between the physiol­
ogy and anatomy of the brain and intellectual skills, there is still much to learn.
Everything that we are or ever will be can, at least on one level, be attributed to pat­
terns of neurons that communicate via chemical messengers. The connections among
neurons change as a function of experience (and genetically coded information). Ex­
perience is the major architect of the brain (Gazzaniga, Ivry, & Magnun, 1998). We
28 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

can change our brains by selecting different sorts of experiences. Every time you
learn something new, you have changed your brain. If you have learned anything
new since you started reading this book, you are already a changed person-I have
"messed with" your brain. I hope you will agree that I left it better than it was before
you started reading. As a discipline, brain research is still in its infancy.
Thus far, biologists have discovered that factors like malnutrition, lead poisoning,
and some drugs can impair the capacity for higher level thought. Current science fic­
tion notions about brain transplants, pills to make us smarter, or miracle foods that
prolong neural life remain in the realm of late-night movies, Saturday afternoon
matinees, and research laboratories. Learning is the best way to rewire the brain.

Thinking as Imagery and Silent Speech

Thinking is the talking of the soul with itself.


-Author Unknown
Found in a Fortune Cookie
Psychologists at the beginning of the century believed that thinking was composed
of mental images. Later, other psychologists hypothesized that thinking was simply
a form of "silent speech," much like talking to yourself without vocalization. In
order to test these hypotheses, psychologists would ask subjects to describe what
they did when responding to certain questions. Let's try some examples. As you an­
swer each question posed below, try to be aware of what you did as you "thought
about it."

1 . How many windows are in your living room?


2. What does your mother look like?
3. What letter comes after N in the alphabet?

TH E FA:\l I L" eI RCl S , By Bil Keane

"Thinking is when the picture is in your head


with the sound turned off."
THINKING ABOUT THINKING 29

4. Name a word that rhymes with "shoe."


5. How much is 2 + 3?
6. Can you define "critical thinking"?

As you answered these questions, were you aware of the use of images and/or
words? Most people find that when they are asked to describe some concrete object,
like the number of windows in their living room or their mother, they are aware of
picture-like images. In fact, it seems almost impossible to answer these questions
without generating an internal representation or utilizing imagery in some way.
Can you describe your mother or anyone else without creating an image? Questions
like 3 or 4, which involve the order of letters in the alphabet and the sounds
of words, usually require an individual to recite the items silently. (Did you sing "1-
m-n-o-p" to yourself in order to answer Question 3?) When answering questions
like 5 and 6, people are often unable to say how they arrived at an answer. (By the
way, if your answer to Question 6 was "no," you should go back and reread the
beginning sections in this chapter.) Most people feel that the answers just seemed
to "pop into their heads" without their being conscious of the "medium" or "stuff"
of thought.
Currently, research psychologists are debating whether the "true" medium of
thought involves imagery, or sentence-like propositions, or both. For most people,
the question is moot, as almost everyone reports that, at least under some circum­
stances, they are aware of both mental images and "silent speech" during the
thought process. Most of the time, however, we have little or no conscious aware­
ness of what happens when we think.
Sometimes, thinking can be improved if we "work at" generating an image or using
speech-like thought. Albert Einstein often credited his ability to solve difficult
problems to his extensive use of imagery. The most famous use of imagery
was recorded by the chemist Kekule. He knew that if he could understand the
structure of a benzene molecule he would have hit on one of the most important
discoveries in organic chemistry. Kekule knew that most chemical molecules are long
strands of atoms, and that the structure of a benzene molecule had to be different. In
order to solve this problem, Kekule practiced generating visual images that might help
him to find the right one. His hard work was rewarded when the historic answer came
to him this way:

Again the atoms were gamboling before my eyes . . . My mental eye . . . could now dis­
tinguish larger structures . . . all twining and twisting in a snakelike motion. But look!
What was that! One of the snakes had seized hold of its own tail, and the form whirled
mockingly before my eyes. As if by a sudden flash of lightning I awoke (Kekule, quoted
in Rothenberg, 1979, pp. 395-396).

The image of a snake biting its own tail led Kekule to the discovery that the
benzene molecule was structured as a closed ring and not like strands of the other
molecules. Thus, he was able to use visual imagery to direct his thoughts about a
complex topic.
Words also serve to direct and stimulate thought. Although it may be obvious
that thoughts are usually communicated with language, it is also true that language
helps to generate thoughts. The generative role of language can be seen in an experi­
ment by Glucksberg and Weisberg (1966). They used a classic problem in the psy­
chology literature that was originally devised by Duncker (1945). In this problem,
30 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

subjects are required to attach a candle to a wall so that it could be lit. They are
given a candle, a box of matches, and some thumbtacks. Stop now and think how
you would go about solving this problem if you were given only these materials
(Fig 1.2). Don't go on until you've thought about it.
The best solution is to dump the matches from their box, tack the box to the wall,
and set the candle in the box. Most subjects have difficulty with this task because
they fail to think of the box as part of the solution-they see it only as a "box of
matches." Glucksberg and Weisberg had people solve this problem under one of
two conditions. The items were either labeled ("box," "tacks," "candle," and
"matches") or they were not labeled. Subjects in the labeled condition solved the
problem in about 1 minute, while those in the unlabeled condition took an average
of 9 minutes. The labels directed attention to the relevant items and changed how
the subjects in the first group solved this problem.
Let's consider a different example of the way language directs thought. There is a
popular riddle that goes something like this:

A young boy and his father went for a Sunday drive. A drunken driver swerved in
front of their car, killing the father on impact. The young boy was rushed to the nearest
hospital where the chief of neurosurgery was summoned to perform an operation.
Upon seeing the boy, the chief of neurosurgery cried out, "I can't operate on him, he's
my son!" How is this possible?

When I've posed this riddle to students, they have sometimes replied: "The
chief of neurosurgery is the boy's stepfather"; "The real father didn't die"; or "It's
impossible." Have you guessed the correct answer? The answer is that the chief of
neurosurgery is the boy's mother. The reason for the difficulty is that, in our society,
when we hear terms like "chief of neurosurgery" we tend to consider only males.
The words we use can determine the kinds of thoughts we think. (This concept is
developed more fully in Chapter 3.)
Have you ever listened to two professionals in the same field discussing their
work? Most professionals have highly developed specialized terms to communicate
their thoughts. Often, these specialized terms also serve to guide the way the profes­
sionals think:

FIG. 1 . 2 Using only the materials shown in this figure, how would you attach the candle
to the wall so that it can be burned?
THINKING ABOUT THINKING 31

How did the surgeon acquire his knowledge of the structure of the human body? . . . It
has taken hundreds of dissections to build up the detailed and accurate picture of the
structure of the human body that enables the surgeon to know where to cut. A highly
specialized sublanguage has evolved for the sole purpose of describing this structure.
The surgeon had to learn this jargon of anatomy before the anatomical facts could be ef­
fectively transmitted to him. Thus, underlying the "effective action" of the surgeon is
an "effective language." Learning this anatomical language was a prerequisite to the
transmission of the factual information that is needed here for effective action. (Bross,
1 973, p. 217)

As this author points out, technical jargon not only facilitates communication
among professionals, it is an inherent part of the development of ideas in a specialized
discipline. As you will see, I stress the learning of specialized terms in every chapter in
this book because the terms carry much of the meaning that is being conveyed.
The use of jargon can serve as an efficient shorthand for communication among
professionals. Specialized terms, however, can also serve as a barrier that keeps
laypersons from understanding. Have you ever gone to a physician and found
you were unable to communicate with her because you didn't understand the techni­
cal terms she used? A physician with a clear understanding of the problem
should be able to communicate the nature of your problem in plain language.
Beware of anyone who scatters terms indiscriminately or uses them as labels for
simple phenomena.
A friend of mine once went to an allergy specialist who, after extensive tests,
announced that my friend had "chronic rhinitis." Although my friend found this di­
agnosis alarming, with further questioning, she learned this means "runny nose," a
diagnosis she could have made by herself.

Preferred Modes of Thought

Even though most people report that they are aware of the use of imagery and silent
speech, at least some of the time there is good evidence that individuals have pre­
ferred modes of thought. That is, some people seem to think more fluently or easily
with one of these types of internal representation than the other. Suppose that I was
giving you directions to a building on a college campus. Consider the two types of
directions shown in Figure 1 .3. Do you prefer the map that conveys information in a
spatial array or the verbal directions (e.g., "Take the second left after you pass Lake
Avenue")? There also seems to be individual differences in preferred sensory
modes. Some students report that they comprehend difficult material best when
they read it; others prefer to listen to difficult material.
There is more than just anecdotal evidence in support of the notion that people
have preferred modes of thought. Gardner (1983) provided considerable evidence
for the concept of "multiple intelligences." There is abundant evidence that some
people prefer to think "spatially" while others prefer to think verbally (Halpern,
2000; Halpern & Collaer, in press). For example, college students with low verbal
ability performed much higher on their tests when they were instructed with
a knowledge map, which is a spatial representation of information, than when
they were instructed in the usual manner that relies more heavily on verbal skills
(Patterson, Dansereau, & Wiegmann, 1 993). There are also some tasks that are
particularly well suited for a particular thinking mode. Imagery, for example, is
usually a better strategy when dealing with spatial problems like those commonly
32 I. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

campus area map

.
,

�,!:::::::.�....--t---+-_.t:

*
_ .... ...
NORTH V---",--_ '. ...."'0 ••
'"

Driving Directions:
1. Take Embarcadero Road exit from the Bayshore Freeway.
2. Make a right at the exit (South) and continue straight for approximately 2 miles.
3. When you cross El Camino Real the street name changes to Galvez Street. Continue on Galvez to the next
large street, which is Campus Drive.
4. Make a left on Campus Drive. (This is a curvy street. Follow it around as it curves to the right.)
5. Make a right onto Mayfield Avenue.
6. Take the first right, which is Lagunita Drive.
7. Park in the second lot on the left.

FIG. 1 . 3 Consider the map and accompanying verbal directions. Which would you prefer
if you had to find your way?

encountered in geometry, the building trades, and architecture. Deliberately switch­


ing from one mode to another is often a critical thinking strategy. I'll be returning to
this notion several times throughout this book. I will suggest that you write out in
words the procedures and solutions to mathematics and science problems and use
imagery and spatial techniques when comprehending complex prose. Comprehen­
sion and problem solving can often be enhanced with the deliberate use of different
thinking modes. Even if you are particularly proficient with one mode, it is good to
develop less-preferred modes as well.

CRITICAL THINKING: HOLL ¥WOOD STYLE

Unfortunately, critical thinking sometimes has a pejorative connotation. This is es­


pecially true in common media depictions of the good thinker as someone who is
CRITICAL THINKING: HOLLYWOOD STYLE 33

cold and calculating. The quintessential example of stereotype is the pointy-eared


Mr. Spock of Star Trek fame. As you probably know, Mr. Spock is a fictitious charac­
ter from the popular television series and movies about space travel in the distant
future. Spock, as he is most commonly called, is only half-human, a fact that is re­
vealed by his pointy-ears. The other half of his bi-species heritage is Vulcan, a
species of being whose thinking is totally rational. In fact, he is so reasoned that he is
unable to understand the mushy and sentimental emotions that seem to plague
mere humans-emotions like love and hate, which have no rational counterpart.
The media depiction of this popular fictitious character presents the message that
rational thought is cold and incompatible with human feelings.
Other times, the media depicts the "good thinker" or good student as the "nerd."
The good thinker is rarely the attractive beauty queen or the athletic stud. More typ­
ically, this character is ridiculed for wearing thick glasses (often held together with
tape), wiping at or sniffing with chronic rhinitis, and expressing a predilection for
plaid clothing. This negative message about good thinking is a common theme in
movies made for the huge teen market. In many ways, the idea that thinking reflec­
tively or following a reasoned plan of action instead of an emotional one is made to
appear "uncool." The impulsive and dashing bubbleheads who are portrayed as the
heroes in this genre of immensely profitable movies are as ludicrous a stereotype as
the nerdy good thinker. Perhaps if the movies showed the lives of these stereotyped
teens a few years later, when the impulsive bubblehead is working at a low-paying
job (or in jail) and the nerdy thinker is doing interesting work for a better salary,
critical thinking would suddenly look very "cool." As long as these stereotyped
movie images make money, it will be difficult to correct these negative stereotypes
and make critical thinking a desirable goal.
The negative image of thinking is not just restricted to teen movies. After every
televised presidential debate, a small army of "spin masters" come on the air to
tell the American public what the candidates just said. Their task is to put a positive
"spin" on their preferred candidate (e.g., He provided a clear vision for America . . .
blah, blah, blah) and a negative spin on the opponent (e.g., He was perspiring
and did not smile enough . . . blah, blah, blah). In one retelling of what the candi­
dates just said, a prominent spin master faulted the opposition candidate for provid­
ing too much information and for hesitating before answering complex questions!
It seems to be the expected format that candidates will provide quotable snippets
that are completely unrelated to reasoned responses about immensely important
issues (e.g., I knew John Kennedy and you're no John Kennedy; Read my lips!)
and short answers that reduce complex issues to one liners. The general public often
responds negatively when candidates give thoughtful, intelligent responses to
complex questions, perhaps because we have been conditioned to associate this
sort of response with the "loser" image that Hollywood and the other media seem
to enjoy.
Critical thinking has been unfairly portrayed as cold and unemotional. The desir­
able goal of a problem or decision is often based on values, feelings, and predilections.
In addition, one frequently recommended skill in improving an outcome is to try to
"see" the issue from the perspective of other individuals. This sort of perspective tak­
ing should increase empathy rather than decrease it. In addition, critical thinking, be­
cause of its roots in psychology, takes into account the intimate connection between
thinking and feeling. Most psychotherapies involve the use of cognitive processes­
thinking, communicating, and understanding-as a way to alter emotional responses.
Empathy, imagination, and value setting are all part of critical thinking.
34 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION


\II1\.1!t
.E'( 'f/II2ITCIOtI'io.UlII< 00Sf.1Of1l'C Ni'6II. -. ...- �

NON SEQUITUR © Wiley Miller. Dist. By UNIVERSAL PRESS SYNDICATE. Reprinted with
permission. All rights reserved.

A FRAMEWORK FOR THINKING

Thinking . . . is continuous, a series of informed improvisations more like those


of a jazz musician than the playing of a classical musician performing a set piece
of music from a score.
-Restak (1988, p. 233)
Unfortunately, there is no simple "how to" formula that can be used in every
situation that calls for critical thought. You already know about the importance
of planning as one of the attitudes or predispositions for critical thinking, but
knowing that it's important to plan is of little value if you don't know how to
plan. Consider the following advice about wilderness survival that appeared in a
phone directory:

Wilderness Survival
Things you must NOT do:

• Wear brand new boots.


• Leave an open fire unattended.
• Panic. If you meet trouble, stop and think.

I'm sure that the first two recommendations are excellent, but I'm less sure about
the value of telling someone to think without any instructions about how to go
A FRAMEWORK FOR THINKING 35

about it. The following is a general, all-purpose framework or guide that can be
used to direct the thinking process. It's not a sure-fire guarantee to good thinking
(there are none), but it is a way of getting started and ensuring that the executive
processes needed in thinking-planning, monitoring, and evaluating-are being
used in a reflective manner. You can probably guess why these are called executive
processes. They function like the ''boss'' in a busy office by directing the flow of
work and deciding where to put the available resources. The framework is a series
of questions, some of which may be repeated several times during the thinking
process, which are general enough to be useful in a wide variety of applications, in­
cluding reasoning from premises, analyzing arguments, testing hypotheses, solving
problems, estimating probabilities, making decisions, and thinking creatively. These
questions follow from the flow diagram in Figure 1 .1 . Although the framework will
remain the same for all of these thinking tasks, the actual skills used will vary some­
what with the nature of the task. The proposed framework is an adaptation of the
problem-solving procedures originally proposed by the brilliant mathematician and
scholar George Polya in 1945. Polya's model is presented in Chapter 9, "Develop­
ment of Problem-Solving Skills."
As you progress through each of the following chapters in this book, you will
gain experience in applying this framework in different contexts and different
knowledge domains. The thinking skills you acquire as you work through this
book will transfer to other contexts if you acquire the habit of using the framework.
The purpose of presenting the framework now is to provide an introduction and
overview of what's to come. It's an easy-to-use guide that, through repeated practice,
should become automatic. The following questions will be used to guide the thought
process:

1 . What Is the Goal?

Critical thinking was defined earlier in this chapter as the use of those cognitive
skills or strategies that increase the probability of a desirable outcome. This term is
used to describe thinking that is purposeful, reasoned, and goal directed. The first
step in improving thinking is to be clear about the goal or goals. What is it that you
want to do? Real-life problems are messy. Sometimes there are multiple goals, and
sometimes we'll return to this question several times, as our understanding of the
goal will often change after we've worked on it for a while. A clearly articulated
goal will provide direction to the thinking process and allow you to make better de­
cisions about the skills you will need to use. In the course of thinking about real­
world problems, you may need to change direction and redefine the problem and
the desired outcome several times, but it's still important to have an outcome in
mind to provide some focus. After all, if you don't know where you're going, you
can never be sure if you've arrived.
There are a large variety of possible goals. Goals can include deciding among
a set of possible alternative solutions, generating a novel solution, synthesizing
information, evaluating the validity of evidence, determining the probable cause of
some event, considering the credibility of an information source, and quantifying
uncertainty.
Are you making a decision about whether to have a heart transplant or what
flavor ice cream to select from the corner store? Impulsive thinking about ice cream
flavors is not a bad thing and does not require critical thinking; impulsive thinking
about life-and-death decisions does. Not everything we do in life requires critical
36 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

thought. The way you identify the goal should help you plan the time and effort
required by the situation.

2 . What Is Known'?

This is the starting point for directed thinking. While this may seem fairly
straightforward now, when we actually use this framework on real problems, you'll
find that you may have to return to the "knowns" several times as you interpret and
reinterpret the situation. Some information will be known with certainty, other in­
formation may be only probably true or partially known. This step will also include
recognizing gaps in what's known and the need for further information gathering.

3 . Which Thinking Skill or Skills Will Get


You to Your Goal'?
Once you have some idea of where you are (the knowns or givens) and where
you're going (the goal or purpose), you're better able to plan goal-directed thinking
processes. Knowing how to get from where you are to where you want to be is the
power of critical thinking. These are the thinking skills or strategies that have been al­
luded to throughout this chapter. Just as there are many different possible goals, there
are many different strategies for attaining them. Let's consider the "thinking is like a
map" analogy a little further because it can help to clarify some abstract concepts by
making them more concrete. Suppose you are about to go on a trip to visit two old
friends. One has become a Buddhist monk and lives high on a mountaintop in the
Himalayas. The other has become a surfing champion and is living on the beautiful is­
land of Hawaii. You'd have to use a different method of travel to reach each destina­
tion, one time scaling a mountain, the other deciding between a plane or boat. Similarly,
you'll have to use different thinking skills with different types of thought problems.
This step will involve generating and selecting the appropriate strategy to reach
the goal. If you've given any thought to how you will reach a Himalayan mountain­
top (I'm assuming that this is a novel thought for most of you), you'll start to gener­
ate several options. You'll probably have to cross an ocean, which means deciding
between a plane or boat of some sort, and then travel by train and/or car, and then
travel by foot and/or animal (which one?). Of course, you'll probably need a guide.
What are the vaccination requirements for someone traveling to Tibet? Oh yes, will
you need a visa? I think you've gotten the idea by now that traveling to a Hi­
malayan mountaintop is a lot like other quests for knowledge. It will take time and
careful planning. By contrast, your trip to visit your surfer friend will be easier and
cheaper. Some problems are like that.

4. Have You Reached Your Goal'?

I've taught statistics for more than 20 years now. I must have asked students if
they've checked their work as often as I've said my name. A concern with accuracy
is probably the biggest predictor of success. Does your solution make sense? Did
you get to your mountaintop in Tibet or are you on an anthill in Iowa? Was your
goal the right one or should it really have been "where shall I travel this summer?"
If it really should have been the latter goal, then you can forget Tibet and consider
Paris or Japan or the rugged beauty of Newfoundland. What have you learned on
the way that you can use again?
CHAPTER SUMMARY 37

Becoming a Better Thinker: A Skills Approach

Critical thinking skills are those strategies for finding ways to reach a goal. Of
course, dividing the thinking process, which is fluid and continuous, into discrete
skills is artificial, but it is necessary to break the massive topic of critical thinking
into manageable pieces. Although I have divided the topic of critical thinking into
several chapters, each of which focuses on a different type of problem (e.g., reason­
ing, analyzing arguments, testing hypotheses, making decisions, estimating likeli­
hoods), these problems are not easily separable in real life. You will often need to
estimate likelihoods when making a decision or generate possible solutions in a
reasoning task. The division is necessary for teaching and learning and is not meant
to imply that critical thinking can be cut into neat packages.
The development of critical thinking skills requires specific instruction, practice
in a variety of contexts, feedback, and time to develop. I hope that working your
way through this book will be mostly enjoyable and well worth all of the effort. An
important part of learning is applying the skills of critical thinking to the many dif­
ferent examples that appear throughout the book. I hope that you will be using the
workbook that accompanies this text, Thinking Critically About Critical Thinking, so
that you can practice, practice, practice. As the old joke goes, it is the only way to get
to Carnegie Hall. So, please get comfortable, prepare for some interesting work, and
enjoy this book.

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . The rapidly accelerating pace of change that marks the opening of the 21st cen­
tury has made the ability to think critically more important than at any other time in
history.
2. Critical thinking can be defined as the use of those cognitive skills or strategies
that increase the probability of a desirable outcome. It is used to describe thinking
that is purposeful, reasoned, and goal-directed.
3. There is considerable empirical evidence from a variety of sources that cogni­
tive skills can be learned from instruction specifically designed to teach these skills
and that these skills transfer to real-world settings when they are practiced in multi­
ple contexts.
4. Developing a critical thinking attitude and disposition is at least as important
as developing the skills of critical thinking. The skills are useless if they are not
used. The attitude of a critical thinker must be cultivated and valued.
5. Metacognition refers to people's knowledge of their own thought processes.
We often have little conscious awareness of how we think. Self-monitoring your
own thought processes is one way to improve how you think.
6. Many contemporary psychologists conceptualize intelligence as made up of
component parts, which include acquiring and using knowledge, executive
processes that guide the thinking and learning process. These components can all be
improved and developed with instruction and practice. We all have some undevel­
oped potential and can learn to think more intelligently.
7. People report that thinking sometimes seems to rely on visual imagery and
sentence-like propositions. There are individual differences and task differences in
the use of these modes of thought.
38 1. THINKING: AN INTRODUCTION

8. A general, all-purpose framework for thinking was presented. It consists of


four questions that should be asked whenever you're faced with a critical thinking
task. It will serve as a guide for the thinking process.
9. Remember, you are what (and how) you think! Have fun with this book.

TERMS TO KNOW

You should be able to define the following terms and concepts. A good way to re­
view and check your comprehension is to cover up the definition, then try to define
each term, then uncover the definition and compare your answer with the brief one
that is provided. (Your answer is expected to be more complete than the one pre­
sented in this review.) The goal is not to memorize the terms; instead you should be
sure that your definition captures the meaning of the term. Be sure to cover the defi­
nition because it is easy to believe you know it when the answer is in front of you,
but hard to fool yourself when you have to generate your own answer. If you find
that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to reread the section in which it
is discussed.

Schemata. Internal representations of knowledge. The way we organize our knowl­


edge about the world.
Critical Thinking. The use of those cognitive skills or strategies that increase the
probability of a desirable outcome. It is purposeful, reasonable, and goal directed.
Also known as directed thinking. Compare with nondirected thinking.
Directed Thinking. Critical thinking or thinking that is goal directed.
Nondirected Thinking. Daydreams, night dreams, and rote memorization. Com­
pare with directed (or critical) thinking.
Cognitive Process Instruction. Instruction based on cognitive theories and research
that is designed to help people improve how they think.
Transfer of Training. The spontaneous use of skills that are learned in one context
in a different context.
Performance-Competence Distinction. The difference between what a person does
(performance) and what that person is able to do (competence).
Critical Thinking Attitude. The willingness to plan, flexibility in thinking, persis­
tence, willingness to self-correct, mindful attention to the thought process, and the
seeking of consensus. It is not possible to be a critical thinker without this sort of
attitude.
Habit of Planning. The repeated and automatic use of plans.
Mindfulness. The act of drawing novel distinctions. Mindful engagement with ma­
terial is needed for good learning.
Metacognition. Our knowledge about our memory and thought process. Colloqui­
ally, what we know about what we know.
Imagery. The use of an internal picture-like representation while thinking.
Preferred Modes of Thought. Individual preferences for different types of internal
representations.
Executive Processes. The oversight or planning and monitoring processes in thinking.
2

MeIllory: The Acquisition,


Retention , and Retrieval
of Knowledge

Contents
Memory as the Mediator of Cognitive Mnemonics
Processes Keywords and Images
The Time Line Rhymes
Varieties of Memory Methods of Places
Memory Without Awareness First Letters
Acquisition Mnemonic Principles
Strategies That Promote Learning External Memory Aids
Retention Remembering Events
The Constructive Nature of Memory Biases in Memory
Stereotypes and Prejudice Confirmation Bias
Retrieval Pollyanna Effect in Memory
Forgetting Vivid, Dramatic, Personal, and
Retrieval Cues Familiar
Working Memory Long-Term Accuracy Is Sometimes
Chunking Excellent
Working Memory and Problem Applying the Framework
Solving Chapter Summary
Metamemory Terms to Know
Confidence

39
40 2. MEMORY

Many years ago I read a story about a beautiful young woman who, because of a terri­
ble fear of growing old, made an interesting deal with the Devil. She agreed to sell her
soul to him. In return, he promised that she would spend her old age in complete hap­
piness. The Devil kept his promise. When the woman grew old, she became totally se­
nile. Her old age was spent in the memories of her youth, visiting with friends who had
long since died, totally oblivious of life around her. The memory of this story has
stayed with me for a long time. I wonder if she would have made this deal if she had
known that her happiness would be bought with senility and would consist of a life
among her memories. I would like to be able to tell you who wrote this story and give
you the title, so that you can read it for yourself, but I can't. I've forgotten where I read
it. Although I believe that I can remember accurately many of the details of the story, I
can't remember where I read it or who wrote it.

MEMORY AS THE MEDIATOR


OF COGNITIVE PROCESSES

How wonderful, how very wonderful the operations of time, and the changes of
the human mind! . . . If any one faculty of our nature may be called more
wonderful than the rest, I do think it is memory.
-Austen (quoted in Powell, 1985, p. 403)
Ulric Neisser (1982), a cognitive psychologist, once asked, "What do we use the past
for?" (p. 13). This may seem like a strange question, but a good way to begin our
quest to understand memory is by examining its function. According to Neisser, we
use the past to define ourselves. If you are a fan of the soap operas, you'll recognize
this as one of the favorite themes. Soap opera plots often involve memory loss (am­
nesia) in one of the protagonists. The usual sequence of events consists of a sudden
blow to the head of a leading man or woman followed by a peculiar loss of memory
in which the identity of family members is forgotten. While this is rare in real life, it
does point out the essential role of memory. It tells you who you are, where you're
from, and where you're going.
Try to imagine what life would be like if you had no memory. For most of us, this
is a frightening thought. A loss of memory is a kind of death. If we had no memory
for our past, the people we are would no longer exist, even if our bodies continued
to function. Our memories are our most valuable possession. I don't know anyone
who would sell the memories he or she has accumulated over a lifetime, no matter
how much money was offered. Life without memory is unfathomable.
All intelligent systems (e.g., humans, computers, dogs, cockroaches) have the
ability to learn and remember. These abilities play a crucial role in all of our lives.
Most important, they are inevitable consequences of living. For humans, the ability
to learn and remember well often determines the quality of life, economic status,
and sometimes even survival. Because the ability to think clearly depends, in large
part, on how well we can utilize past experiences, memory is a central topic in de­
veloping thinking skills. Thinking is a cognitive process-what and how we think
depends on what we know-on the contents of our memories. In this chapter, we
consider current views of how memory works, why forgetting occurs, when mem­
ory can be misleading, and ways to improve memory.
All thinking skills are inextricably tied to the ability to remember. As you proceed
through the chapters in this book, you will repeatedly find evidence of the pervasive
MEMORY AS THE MEDIATOR OF COGNITIVE PROCESSES 41

influences of memory on how and what we think. Consider, for example, the per­
ception of risk. Psychologists have found that hazards that are unusually memo­
rable such as a recent disaster or a sensationalized depiction in a film or televised
newscasts (e.g., stories about teenagers who kill their parents and knife-wielding
wives who mutilate their husbands) distort people's perception of risk. Most people
rate dramatic causes of death such as earthquake or shark attack as many times
more likely than they actually are, and less memorable causes of death are routinely
underestimated (Lichtenstein et al., 1978).
The distortion in perceived risk is due to the sorts of events that people can think
of when they make judgments about risk. Public opinion polls show that crime is a
major concern for most Americans. But, is there really a crime wave, or just the per­
ception of a rapid increase in the rate of crime? The Center for Media and Public Af­
fairs reviewed 573 television shows, movies, and music videos that were released
from 1998 to 1999. They found an average of 31 acts of violence were depicted per
hour of viewing time, which is approximately one act of violence every two min­
utes; the three major television networks in the United States showed more crimes
per show every year for the last several years-even though the crime rate had not
changed (Center for Media and Public Affairs, http: //www.cmpa.com/archive/
vioI98.htm). Why are television news shows increasing their coverage of crime? In
part, a few violent crimes dominated the news, but it is also possible that the major
networks are trying to compete with the tabloid-type shows that feature violent
crime. It is not surprising that a recent poll taken in the city of Milwaukee found that
80% of the people surveyed believe that crime had increased or stayed the same,
when in fact, crime in Milwaukee has been steadily declining (Fletcher, March 25,
2000). The point being is that many people think about crime when they are asked
their concerns. Why crime? To answer this question, we need to understand why
crime is what "comes to mind" and not something else like poverty, the envi­
ronment, or education, when people search through their memory stores and re­
trieve "crime" as their primary concern. The perception that crime is rising, which is
at odds with the actual data, would be expected to influence how people think
about crime-related issues like mandatory sentences for offenders, willingness to
fund the construction of new prisons, and whether to buy burglar alarms or own
hand guns.
A related media-made impression of a crime wave can arise from reporting in­
creases without ever stating the actual number of crimes. For example, although it
was true that the killing of tourists in Florida went up 300% in a two-year period, it
helps to mention the actual number that have been killed: The number increased
from three deaths to eight deaths-hardly a crime wave, even though many people
now believe that it is not safe to travel to Florida! It is not surprising then that peo­
ple would conclude that there has been a rapid rise in the rate of crime-after all,
this is what is shown and reported on news shows, and what we are likely to recall
when deciding about the risk of crime. In Chapter 7 on likelihood and probability, I
will describe the confusion between percentages and frequencies in the context of
thinking with numbers, but the point I want to make here is that it is the huge in­
crease in the percentage of crimes that most people will remember and use when
making judgments about crime. Few people will ever think to ask about the number
of tourists who were killed, so frequency information will not be "available" in
memory for use in helping them decide if a place is safe or unsafe.
Another example of the centrality of memory to the thinking process can be seen
in decision making by juries. The jury process is at the heart of the u.s. legal system.
42 2. MEMORY

It is one of our most cherished rights as citizens. A group of strangers is cloistered in


a small room for the sole purpose of evaluating evidence pertaining to the guilt or
innocence of an accused. The synthesis, analysis, and weighing of evidence that is
often contradictory is a complex cognitive process, which, like all cognitive
processes, depends on what is remembered. In a simulated study of how juries reach
decisions, Reyes, Thompson, and Bower (1980) varied the vividness (and, therefore
the memorability) of the evidence provided during a mock trial. In half of the cases,
the prosecution presented the more vivid information; in the other half, the defense
presented the more vivid information. Judgments of guilt paralleled the differential
recall of the prosecution and defense arguments. When the information favoring the
defendant was more vivid, he was more likely to be acquitted (found not guilty),
and when the information favoring the plaintiff was more vivid, the defendant was
more likely to be found guilty. The "jurors" based their decision about guilt or inno­
cence on the information available to them from their memories of the trial.
The vivid information was more memorable, more available, and therefore more
likely to be utilized in the jury deliberations. The influence of the availability of
information in decision making will be considered again in Chapter 8.

The Time Line

The relationship among learning, retaining, and recalling involves the passage of
time. Let's clarify this with an example. It is reasonable to expect that during a col­
lege career, students will take many, many exams. When you finish reading this sec­
tion of the book, you should be able to answer a question like: "What is the relation­
ship among learning, retaining, and recalling?" If you write the correct answer on
an exam, your professor will infer that sometime before the exam you learned the
relevant material, you retained it (kept it in memory), and you were able to recall it
(retrieve it from memory) when it was needed (on the exam). Learning and retain­
ing are not observable behaviors. They must be inferred from the activity of recall,
which is inferred from some other behavior, such as writing the correct answer on a
test. A friend can watch you while you move your eyes across the lines of print that
appear in a book propped up in front of you, but she can't see you learn. In the ex­
ample presented here, writing the correct answer on an exam is the behavior that al­
lows the inference that learning and retention have occurred. Learning and retention
are hypothetical constructs, terms that have been made up to help psychologists
study and understand the mind and, thus, they have been called "convenient fic­
tions." Learning and retention are like perception, motivation, thirst, sex drives, hal­
lucinations, and many other terms in that they have no external physical reality.
They are only known by inference, and they are helpful in understanding the
processes of the mind.
Learning and retention are usually inferred together. If I asked you what notable
event occurred in Australia in 2000, and you answered correctly, then I would infer
that you learned, retained, and recalled that Australia was the site of the 2000
Olympic Games. If you are unable to answer this question, then either: (a) you never
learned the fact in question; or (b) you learned it, but forgot it; or (c) you could recall
it in some other situation, maybe with some recall cues.
The relationship between learning and memory is a temporal one (time-based)
and is depicted on the time line in Fig. 2.1 . Something happens at Time 1 that we call
learning or the acquisition of information. Following Time 1 is an interval, which
MEMORY AS THE MEDIATOR OF COGNITIVE PROCESSES 43

Learning -----. Memory -----. Retrieval


� �
, ?
V
Time 1 Retention Interval Time 2

FIG. 2. I . A time line depicting the relationship among learning, memory, and retrieval.

can be as short as a few thousandths of a second or as long as a lifetime. Retention of


information during this time interval is attributed to memory, but indexed by re­
trieval. At Time 2 (some time after Time 1), the individual exhibits some behavior,
like correctly answering an exam question that allows us to infer that the material
was both learned and remembered.

Varieties of Memory

Thought and memory are closely related, for thought relies heavily on the
experiences of life.
-Norman (1988, p. 1 15)
The goal of good remembering is to learn information that may be useful in the fu­
ture and to learn it in a way that makes it easy and likely to be recalled when it is
needed. By gaining some insight into the way memory works, you should be able to
use this knowledge to improve your ability to remember.
In the first chapter, I provided a working definition for "critical thinking" and the
more general term "thinking." A key idea is that thinking is the manipulation or
transformation of some internal representation (Hunt, 1989; Reisberg, 2001). Our in­
ternal representations are manipulated or transformed in symbolic ways, so that the
knowledge we have can be used to solve problems and make decisions. Notice that I
use the term "knowledge" whenever I refer to an internal representation. Informa­
tion exists in the world. When we learn information-that is, acquisition or the
incorporation---of information into our existing mental structures, it becomes mean­
ingful-it becomes knowledge. When we think, we use our knowledge to accom­
plish some goal. When we think in deliberate ways that increase the probability of
obtaining that goal, we are engaging in critical thinking.
Memory is not a single process. It is a series of processes or systems, each of
which has its own operating principles. Psychologists do not agree about the num­
ber of separate processes that comprise memory because there are many dimensions
to memory and many different ways to conceptualize the remembering processes. I
like to think of it as different ways to cut the "memory pizza." (I was a pizza wait­
ress when I was in college, and I frequently tried to cut the pizza in novel ways. I'm
not sure why I recalled this experience as I searched for an analogy for memory, but
this is what I remembered. I hope that this is a useful way to understand this discus­
sion. At least, the pizza analogy should provide food for thought.)
For example, memory operates differently when you learn a motor skill like ski­
ing than it does when you study for a history test. Therefore, you would not use the
same methods to learn to ski as you would to learn about an event in history. Simi­
larly, what you do during the retention interval, the time interval between the ac­
quisition of new information and its retrieval. Retrieval is the act of remembering
44 2. MEMORY

information at recall. The length of the retention interval also governs what and
how you learn and recall. If you had to remember the date of the Civil War for only
5 seconds, you would engage in different remembering activities during the reten­
tion interval than if you had to remember it for 5 months. What you already know
about skiing or history is also an important determinant of the way in which you go
about adding to that knowledge. Similarly, the complexity of the information and
the context in which you learn and remember also play a role in the selection of the
best strategies for learning and remembering. Intuitively, we all know about some
of these differences, but an improved understanding of the operating principles of
memory should help to use it more efficiently.
Perhaps another analogy would be useful at this point because the concept of
memory systems is so abstract. Think about the many interrelated components in an
automobile engine. If you understand that pumping too much gas into a stalled car
can "flood" the engine, then you can avoid this problem. Similarly, if you under­
stand that the battery can lose its charge if you run the heater, lights, and radio for a
long time when the motor is off, you can also use this knowledge to avoid the prob­
lem of a dead battery. The many systems of memory also have operating rules, and
if you acquire, retain, and recall information with these rules in mind, you should be
a better driver of your own memory system.
Here are some of the distinctions that have been made to differentiate among
memory systems: Episodic memory is the memory we have for events in which we
can recall our own participation-when and where we learned them (Tulving,
1972). Examples of episodic memory include remembering where you spent your
1 7th birthday, recalling the plot from a movie you saw last week, and remembering
the day you graduated from high school. This sort of memory is fairly easy to ac­
quire because it seems to happen without much effort on your part. Semantic mem­
ory is the memory that we have for facts like the multiplication table and word
meanings. You probably cannot remember where and when you learned that 7 X 9 =

63 or the definition of "chauvinist pig," but these are parts of your memory system.
You probably can recall all of the trouble you had learning the multiplication tables.
It is easy to talk about the knowledge contained in episodic and semantic memory.
For this reason, these two systems are part of a larger grouping in memory that is
called declarative memory.
Motor memory, as you might expect, pertains to remembering motor skills. Let's
suppose that you are an excellent outfielder in baseball. You can get your glove to
the place where the ball is going and throw it in the right direction within fractions
of a second. This is certainly an impressive skill, but it is very difficult to verbalize
exactly how you do it. You are able to call on your knowledge when it is needed, but
can't exactly say what it is that you do. If you wanted to teach me to be a great out­
fielder (lots of luck), you could not just tell me what you do. It would be of little use
for you to describe your activities, "I catch the ball instead of missing it, then throw
it where it is most needed, instead of somewhere else." On the other hand, if you
wanted to teach me the multiplication tables, you could do that in words.
Procedural memory, or remembering how to do something, shares some features
with motor memory. The difference is that the procedure does not necessarily have
to involve motor skills. For example, if you are as old as I am (unlikely), then you
once learned how to use a slide rule. (For those of you who grew up in the age of
cheap and efficient calculators, a slide rule is a device that looks like a ruler and can
be used to perform mathematical calculations.) This is a kind of "knowing how"
that is often differentiated from declarative tasks that involve "knowing that."
MEMORY AS THE MEDIATOR OF COGNITIVE PROCESSES 45

Another way of dividing memory depends on how hard you have to "work" in
order to remember. This distinction is between automatic and effortful memory.
How many movies have you seen in the last two months? Even avid movie-goers
can almost always answer this question (Hasher & Zacks, 1984). Frequency informa­
tion is one type of learning and remembering that occurs fairly automatically; that
is, with little conscious awareness or practice. For this reason, it is often called auto­
matic memory. By contrast, suppose that you need to remember a series of dates for
a history exam. Unfortunately, this sort of information will require that you work at
remembering-most probably you would repeat the dates until you could recite
them without looking. This is an example of effortful memory. Some types of mem­
ory will require hard work, others will be easy, but with repeated practice and the
acquisition of additional information, effortful processing will become more auto­
matic. Perhaps one way of thinking about education is that it makes hard "things"
easy. Experts in any area-history buffs, computer programmers, skilled athletes­
have all done the hard work of learning and now make "it look so easy," so auto­
matic. Now they have more attentional and memory resources for the more
advanced aspects of their work.
Other, totally different ways of "slicing the memory pizza" depend on the length
of the retention interval. If the retention interval is up to one or two minutes, then
the best ways to ensure recall will be different than when the interval is longer (up
to an entire lifetime). Simple rehearsal, such as repeating a phone number that needs
to be remembered long enough to dial it, will work well for short retention intervals.
If you needed to learn your new phone number so that you can recall it months
or years from now, you could not spend the retention interval repeating your
phone number. You need to engage in activities that are appropriate for long-term
retention.
Memory can also be categorized by the type of recall task that will be performed.
If you only have to recognize the correct response, you will need less effort at acquisi­
tion than if you actually have to generate the response with few cues. Students fre­
quently tell me that they study differently when they are expecting a multiple-choice
test (recognition) than an essay test, (recall with few cues). There is experimental ev­
idence that when students expect a multiple-choice test, they perform better on this
type of test than on a recall test and when students expect an essay test, they per­
form better on essay tests than multiple-choice tests (Tversky, 1973). When prepar­
ing for a test, students engage in intentional learning activities and do something to
help them remember the material. Learning that occurs without deliberate effort is
called incidental, for example, your memory for the plot of a television sitcom that
you saw last night. I often hear from students who come to my office for academic
advising that they "can't do math" or "can't do science" or "can't write well." I
think that what they really mean is that the learning of math (or science or writing­
we all have different skills and abilities) is effortful. Of course, with hard work, they
can. I think that if they understood that some kinds of learning are effortful and
some are easy, then they would not be so quick to conclude that they "can't do it,"
when in fact what they need to do is exert conscious effort and do the hard cognitive
work of intentional learning.
Like learning, recall can be effortful or easy, and sometimes, automatic. I don't
know why I remembered my years as a pizza waitress when I was thinking about
ways to explain the abstract concept of memory. It came to me spontaneously. Sev­
eral different ways of conceptualizing the multiple processes of memory, or, as I
have been calling it, cutting the memory pizza, are shown in Fig. 2.2.
46 2. MEMORY

Varieties of Memory
Task Variables

Declarative
Length of
Retention Interval
Semantic

Short- Long-
Term Term
Memory
1 second
to ", 1
Types of Recall minute lifetime

Recognition

FIG. 2 . 2 . Varieties of memory. There are many different ways to conceptualize the types of
memory processes. I suggested that you think of it as ways to cut up a pizza-in this case, a
memory pizza. Each of these "pieces" or categories of memory has its own set of operating
principles.

As you can see, there are many ways to categorize the multiple processes of
memory. What you need to remember from this discussion is that you will have to
consider what you need to remember and when and why you will need it, and what
you already know about the topic when you engage in activities that promote re­
membering. But, whatever the nature of the memory task, a consistent theme
throughout this book is that the knowledge we retain in that amazing organ that
perches on top of our spines, directs the mental processes that we call thinking. A
strong base of knowledge and good thinking skills operate together in the critical
thinker (Champagne, 1992; Lawson, 1999). However, it is important to bear in mind
that although an excellent memory may direct and influence thinking, a head full of
good facts does not make someone a good thinker. One of the saddest sights in col­
lege is the student whose memory is an encyclopedic compendium of unintegrated
factoids. Just as great thinking skills with a head that contains no knowledge is
worthless, so is a head full of information without the thinking skills, unless you as­
pire to be a game-show contestant! Thought and knowledge-sounds to me like a
great title for a book.
MEMORY AS THE MEDIATOR OF COGNITIVE PROCESSES 47

Memory Without Awareness

Few judges are psychologists, or they would realize that nothing can be stricken
out of a human consciousness after being let in. Judges seem to be quite unaware
that it is a hard task to put anything into the average mind and, once in, an
impossible one to take it out.
-Clarence Darrow (1932, p. 145)
One kind of memory that has fascinated many psychologists during the last decade
is memory for information that we do not know we know. It's hard to understand
how something that we do not know we know could be called memory, so an exam­
ple should help. Suppose that I write a two-word phrase in such small type that you
couldn't read it. If I asked you to recall the phrase, you would say that you never
saw it or it was so small you could not read it. Additionally, suppose that I devised
a task that demonstrated that, in fact, you did have some memory for that two-word
phrase, even though you had no conscious knowledge of ever reading it. The mem­
ory test for unconscious memory could be a word fragment task, where you fill in
the blanks to form a two-word phrase, for example, _ _ s s pp
_ _ e. If you filled
_ _

in the blanks to read "just suppose," and I found that none or very few people who
had not been exposed to this two-word phrase in small print could fill in the blanks,
then I would have evidence for memory without conscious knowledge. In fact, there
is good evidence for just such a memory system. Because it is a memory that we
cannot access by the usual methods of responding, it is called implicit memory
(Graf & Komatsu, 1994; Greenwald, 1992; Roediger, 1990). By contrast, explicit
memory is memory for information that can be discussed or described.
Here is another example-suppose that your family always spoke Italian in the
home when you were a small child, and now that you are an adult, you cannot seem
to remember a single word of Italian. Yet, if you took a class in Italian, you would
find that the words that you thought you didn't know come back to you so that you
are speaking Italian with less effort than other students who did not grow up in a
home where Italian was spoken. This is a kind of implicit memory because you had
no conscious awareness of the fact that you knew some Italian, yet you found that
you did.
If we can show that we "remember" information that we did not know that we
know, can this unconscious information influence how we think without our being
consciously aware of their effect? It seems that these memories that we do not know
about consciously can have an effect on how we feel about the objects of these mem­
ories. The effect of unconscious memories are seen when people are asked about
preferences. For example, imagine that you are participating in an experiment
where a word is repeated a few times, but you do not really know what the word is
because it may have been spoken too softly for you to hear, or it was spoken in a
noisy room, or it was a word or picture that was shown so badly out of focus that
you cannot say what was shown. Suppose also that some time later, you hear the
word or see the picture. It is probable that you will indicate that you prefer the stim­
ulus that you never knew was heard or said. Similarly, if you see the name of some
unknown person but you have no conscious memory of seeing that name, you are
more likely to judge that it is the name of a famous person when you encounter it
some time later than if you had not previously been exposed to the name (Seamon
et al., 1995). It seems that these stimuli that reside in a memory system that you have
no conscious knowledge of "feel familiar" even though you do not know why.
48 2. MEMORY

Memories "feel" different from new information, and we use these feelings about
memory as a basis for judgments, without knowing that familiarity is causing us to
make the judgments that we do.

The Illusion of Truth. What would happen if I told you a lie, and you have no
conscious memory that I told you this lie? Here's one possibility: Did you know that
the president of your college was caught shoplifting at Sears? Sure, this is a lie; I
don't know anything about the president of your college; in fact, I don't really know
you, and you may never have attended college. Let's further suppose that you for­
got that I told you this lie, and some time later you hear that there was a crime on
campus and the president of your university is a possible suspect. It seems that the
information linking the president and crime will "feel familiar," even though you
don't recall where you heard it before, and you are more likely to judge the state­
ment that your president committed a crime as the truth than if I had not previously
told you the lie that she was caught shoplifting at Sears. Can you see why this phe­
nomenon is called the "illusion of truth"? Information that was encountered previ­
ously, even if at the time you knew it might be a lie, makes it more likely that you
will believe the information when it is encountered a second time than if you had
not been told the original lie (Wegner, Wenzlaff, Kerker, & Beattie, 1981).
So what should I do if I want to influence how you evaluate information-if I
want you to believe my lie? I could repeat the information that I want you to believe
several times, then allow some time to pass so that you don't recall where you heard
it. When you hear the information at some time in the future, it will seem familiar,
so you will assume it is true. (It would have a "familiar ring" to it.) Based on the illu­
sion of truth, can you understand why rumors are effective, even when they are
known to be lies? Have you ever heard the expression, "there is no such thing as
bad publicity"? It seems that people often forget exactly what they heard, but when
they encounter a person's name for a second (or more) time, the name seems famil­
iar. We tend to interpret this feeling of familiarity in a way that gives it meaning. So,
an actor or politician who is not well known, but was involved in some scandal or
was in the news for some other reason, will be judged as more famous than one
whose name does not have the same "familiar feel."

Classical Conditioning. Another kind of memory without awareness is the re­


sult of classical conditioning. If you have had an introductory class in psychology,
then you probably learned about the pioneering work of Ivan Pavlov. He was able
to get dogs to salivate to the sound of a bell by repeatedly pairing the sound of a bell
with the presentation of food. In human terms, that is like getting you to respond to
the sound of a bell in much the same way that you would respond to the sight and
smell of a thick, juicy steak sizzling on a grill. (If you are a vegetarian, then think of
a juicy veggieburger or whatever the appropriate mouth-watering meal is for you.)
Classical conditioning can occur without conscious awareness, and clever propa­
gandists have used this technique to influence how people think.
There is a striking example of the use of classical conditioning to influence
thoughts and actions on display at the Museum of Tolerance in Los Angeles,
California, which is a museum that is dedicated to documenting and explaining the
origins and consequences of prejudice and intolerance. In one display, old movies
that were shown in Nazi Germany depict the repeated pairing of revolting scenes of
rats streaming out of sewers and running over garbage and other waste. Virtually
everyone responds with disgust to these repulsive scenes. Exaggerated pictures of
ACQUISITION 49

Jews were flashed onto the screen so that the long noses of the disgusting rats are
superimposed over the exaggerated facial features of Jews. It does not take long be­
fore the facial features evoke feelings of disgust, which were learned through the re­
peated pairing of the repulsive rat scenes and the faces. For people who viewed
these movies, the feeling of disgust can be elicited at some time later when similar
facial features are encountered, without the viewer ever being aware of where or
how this association was learned. This is a powerful and frightening example of the
way memory without awareness can support a conscious program of prejudice and
discrimination. As the learner (viewer of the films), you would attribute the feeling
of disgust to some other reason or source, a fact that makes its effect so pernicious.
In one of the controversies that erupted during the presidential match between Al
Gore and George W. Bush, two candidates for president of the United States in 2000,
a controversial television advertisement criticized Gore's health plan as a plan that
would be run by "bureaucrats." There is nothing unusual in this because name­
calling is a common political technique used to persuade voters not to vote for the
other candidate. What was unusual in this advertisement was that the word
"RATS" was briefly flashed on the television screen as the announcer said the word
"bureaucrats." This advertisement can be seen on the Internet at a site that is main­
tained by "Political Ad Critic" (http://political.adcritic.com). The television screen is
reproduced in Fig. 2.3. In thinking about the effect of this advertisement, remember
that the word "RATS" was flashed very quickly. I do not know what the intent of
the advertising agency was, although I can guess at their intent. George W. Bush
claimed that he had no knowledge of the advertisement.
Look closely at Fig. 2.4. This picture is taken from a picture book of Mother Goose
Tales. It was published in 1942, during World War II. This is a series of pictures
about what may be the world's most famous egg, Humpty Dumpty. Does Humpty
Dumpty look vaguely familiar to you? It will, if you are a history buff. He bears
an uncanny resemblance to Adolf Hitler, leader of the Nazi forces during World
War II. Does his fall and his inability ever to rise again (be put together again) sug­
gest that a message is being sent that the reader might learn without conscious
awareness?

ACQUISITION

In 1935, Time Magazine featured the predictions of Ralph S. Willard, a Hollywood


chemist who claimed to be able to freeze monkeys and resuscitate them. Willard sug­
gested that this process could be used with prisoners because it was cheaper than jail,
the unemployed, who could be kept frozen until the economy produced more jobs, and
even the depressed, who could remain in the freezer until a cure was found. By the
way, it is clear that "Willard was a humbug" who disappeared into science fiction his­
tory. (Harris, 1993, p. 55)

Unless you already knew this, you have just acquired new information. You can an­
swer questions that you couldn't answer a few moments ago. You are a changed
person, and you will never be the same again. The knowledge you have embedded
in memory pertaining to Time Magazine, cryogenics (freezing people), and strange
ideas from the 1930s is altered. So it is with all new information that causes you to
change what you know and how you think.
50 2. MEMORY

FIG. 2 . 3 .A reproduction of the television screen that was used during an anti-Gore
commercial during the presidential campaign in 2000. (From http:Upolitical.adcritic.com.)

You may have heard the term "information explosion," which refers to the
tremendous increase in the amount of information we have to deal with in contem­
porary society-information that has to be acquired, retained, and retrieved if we
are to function in an increasingly complex world. Consider, for example, the docu­
mentation that soldiers have to master in order to learn and perform maintenance
on military tanks. There are more than 40,000 pages of instructions, and the tools re­
quired for maintenance could fill a large truck (Brooks, Simutis, & O'Neil, 1985). The
soldiers who are responsible for the tanks need to know how to learn and recall
large amounts of technical information in order to perform well at this highly com­
plex task. As more of us log on to electronic networks, we are privy to staggering
quantities of information. We need to know how to search selectively and how to
navigate through a sea of databases, bulletin boards, discussion groups, and "buy­
ing opportunities."
We are surrounded every moment by more information than we could possibly
acquire. Stop some friends some time during the day and ask them to close their
eyes. Ask them questions about the room they're in (for example, which pots are on
the stove, if they're in the kitchen), or the book they're reading (like whether there
are headings on the page they're reading or what is shown on the book cover), or
the person they're with (like whether a friend parts her hair on the side or down the
middle). You'll be surprised how much of this potentially available information is
not known. We are selective about the nature of the information we acquire.

Strategies That Promote Learning

There is no substitute for the serene pleasure that learning can bring.
-Izawa (1993, p. 43)
Although there are many different kinds of memory processes and contexts, several
general rules have emerged that can promote the learning of new information.
There is an old saying that goes something like this, "the head remembers what it
Humpty Dumpty

Humpty Dumpry sac on a wall,


H umpty Du mpty had a greac fall;

All [he K ing" h orses


and all che K i ng's men

Cannot p u c Humpty Dumpty


cogecher aga in.

FIG. 2 . 4. An illustration taken from The Tall Book of Mother Goose. Pictures by Feodor
Rojankovsky. (1942). New York: Harper & Row. Look closely at Humpty Dumpty. He looks
too much like Adolph Hitler for the message of his sudden downfall and inability to rise
again to be a coincidence.
51
52 2. MEMORY

does." (I really like this saying and use it a few times in this book.) Embarrassingly, I
once again have to admit that I don't remember where I first heard it, but I do recall
the message: What you do at acquisition (when you are learning something) is an
important determinant of what you will remember. Simply put, if you engage in ac­
tivities that promote learning, you will improve your memory.

Pay Attention. One of the primary determinants of what we know is what we


attend to. Think back to the last time you were at a large, noisy party with people
standing around in small groups talking to each other. Imagine that you're standing
with two acquaintances discussing the weather. There are several small groups of
people standing nearby who are also carrying on conversations. If someone near
you, but not talking to you, mentions your name or something of interest (e.g., "Did
you hear the latest news about Debbie and Stanley?"), this will attract your atten­
tion. If, however, the same person standing at the same distance from you, speaking
in the same voice, is discussing tree blight, you probably would never notice, unless
you have a special interest in tree blight. Think about what will happen to the con­
versation you've been having about the weather. If your answer is "Not much,"
you're correct. When you switched your attention to the more interesting conversa­
tion, you lost most of the meaning of the original conversation. If, at this point, the
person who has been talking to you suddenly stops and asks, "What do you think
about it?" you'd become embarrassed, because you would have no knowledge of
what she had been saying.
The phenomenon described here is called the Cocktail Party Effect. Most people
can think of an episode where they've experienced this effect. It demonstrates sev­
eral basic properties of attention.

1 . If you don't pay attention, you won't acquire information. Let's consider the
scenario a little more closely. When you were attending to the weather conver­
sation, you knew very little or nothing about the other conversations around
you. When you switched your attention to the more interesting conversation,
you could not say what was happening in the weather conversation. Thus, at­
tention will be a major factor in what gets remembered, because it determines
what gets into the human information system.
2. There are limitations on your ability to process information. All of the conver­
sations going on around you are not processed equally well.
3. There are individual differences in what is attended to. If you had no interest
in "the latest news about Debbie and Stanley," but found the weather fascinat­
ing, then you would not have switched your attention and could have re­
sponded with more than a sheepish grin to the question, "What do you think
about it?"

If you're interested in knowing more about memory so that you can improve
your own, then you'll have to pay attention to attention. Many people complain that
they forget the names of people soon after they've been introduced. It is likely that
they never paid attention to the name at the time of introduction. If information is
not acquired, then it can never be remembered. When meeting someone, it is a good
idea to repeat the person's name aloud to be certain that you've heard it correctly
and to be certain that you've paid attention. Saying the name, rather than just hear­
ing it, is an important aid for remembering. If you cannot say the name soon after
hearing it, you can be sure that you won't remember it some time later. You need to
ACQUISITION 53

develop the habit of monitoring your attention. If your eyes are moving across a
text, but your mind is somewhere else, you need consciously to be aware of the fact
that you're not attending, so that you can redirect your effort to the material to be
learned. It's been said that a good politician remembers names. This is also true of
successful salespeople, teachers, waiters, and waitresses. Even if you'll never be a
politician, salesperson, teacher, or waiter or waitress, it is a good social skill that is
well worth the effort.
When learning a name (for a person, a concept, or object) immediately repeat and
then "do" something to help you fix it in your memory-say it out loud a second
time, spell it, associate it with something that can help you remember the name such
as a person's features, or just explain what it means in your own words. The effect of
generating the name (saying it from your own memory) will help with recall. I tried
to explain this principle to the manager at a sandwich shop where I frequently stop.
Often the order is wrong, which costs money and hurts business. I suggested that he
have the people taking the order repeat it back to the customer to ensure its accu­
racy and to help the order-taker or sandwich-maker remember the order as he or
she works on it. The manager looked unimpressed with this sage advice. It's unfor­
tunate because this simple generative task would significantly reduce the number of
wrong orders and unhappy customers.
In case you're unimpressed with the rule that unless you attend to something you
won't know it, let's try a demonstration. Most people will admit that they like
money and have worked hard to earn it. In Fig. 2.5 there are several drawings of a
U.s. penny.
Only one is correct. If you're like most people, you won't be able to recognize the
correct penny because you never attended to its details. Although you've dealt with
pennies numerous times (if you are a resident of the United States), you learned
only enough of the details to tell it apart from other coins. You probably never ac­
quired a detailed memory of pennies. To find the "correct" answer, check it with a
real penny, but be certain that you attend to all of the details carefully. If you're still
dubious, try drawing a telephone keypad from memory or name the letters on the
second row of your computer keyboard. Few people find that they know which
numbers and letters go together, yet we have all dialed telephones thousands of

1\ II ()

K M N o

FIG. 2.5. Fifteen drawings of a U.S. penny. Which one is correct? (From Nickerson and
Adams, 1979).
54 2. MEMORY

times, and few can name the letters, yet we can use them, often without looking.
These actions have become so automatic that we no longer pay conscious attention
to them and without attention, they cannot be recalled.
The need to pay attention in school should be obvious. John Holt (1964), a re­
spected educator and author of the book How Children Fail, believes that many chil­
dren fail in school because they don't pay attention. Think about how your mind
sometimes seems to wander when reading textbooks or during lectures. Most
students are not even aware when they're not paying attention. It should be obvious
by now that in order to develop better memory skills, you will also have to develop
attentional skills.

Monitor Meaning. Comprehension and memory are closely related concepts


because memory is enhanced when the material is meaningful, and meaningful in­
formation is retained more easily than material that is low in meaning. If you are
learning in a classroom setting, from a textbook, or some similar setting in which the
information is complex prose and you need to be able to recall it some time later, you
need to monitor how much and what you are understanding. Stop at the end of each
section, and state or write in your own words, without looking at the text, what you
just read. This is important because it provides practice at remembering, but you still
need to practice your remembering after some time has passed since reading the text.
If you cannot meaningfully summarize each section just after reading it, then you
will not be able to summarize it at some later date. You need to be aware of what
you are learning, and take action if you have "lost it." This is a concrete way to
check on your attention. If you finished a section in a text and have no idea what
you just read, you need to go back and attend to the content. Additional suggestions
for monitoring meaning are given later in this chapter in the section on metamem­
ory and in Chapter 3 where questioning strategies are presented.
Stop now, cover this section of your book and say aloud or write out in two or
three sentences about what this section on memory is conveying.
To demonstrate the powerful influence of meaning on memory, look at A, B, and
C in Fig. 2.6 for a few seconds, then cover the figures and reproduce them from
memory. Try this now.
You probably remembered some parts of the figures shown in Fig. 2.6, but didn't
remember them perfectly. Suppose I now tell you that Fig. 2.6A is a soldier walking
his dog behind a picket fence (Do you see the dog's tail and the end of the soldier's
rifle?), and that Fig. 2.6B is a washerwoman scrubbing the floor (Do you see her
water bucket and the bottoms of her shoes?). If you recognized Fig. 2.6C as a bear be­
hind a tree, then you drew it more accurately than if it seemed more like abstract art.
Making the figures meaningful will enhance how well they are remembered. You can
test this with friends by telling them what the figures are, uncovering them briefly,
and then comparing how much your friends remembered to your own drawings.
Your elementary school teachers recognized the role that meaning plays in mem­
ory when they told you to "read for meaning." We can add meaning to information
by elaborating on it. For example, when you are learning something, try to relate it
to something that you already know (Connor-Greene, 2000). Put the topic in context
or make your own summary of the information (Davis & Hult, 1997). The idea is to
exert the effort and spend the time needed to relate new material to something that
is already known so that you won't remember it as an isolated bit of information.
In a clever demonstration of the principle that anything that improves compre­
hension will improve memory, two psychologists (Bransford & Johnson, 1 972)
ACQUISITION 55

FIG. 2.6. A demonstration of the effect of meaningfulness on memory. Look at these


figures for a few seconds, then cover them and reproduce them from memory. (Figures A and
B are adapted from Osgood, 1953. Figure C is adapted from Hanson, 1 958).

presented college students with the following passage to read. Read it for yourself
and then see how much you can remember.

The procedure is actually quite simple. First you arrange things into different groups
depending on their makeup. Of course, one pile may be sufficient depending on how
much there is to do. If you have to go somewhere else due to lack of facilities that is the
next step, otherwise you are pretty well set. It is important not to overdo any particular
endeavor. That is, it is better to do too few things at once than too many. In the short
run this may not seem important, but complications from doing too many can easily
arise. A mistake can be expensive as well. The manipulation of the appropriate mecha­
nisms should be self-explanatory, and we need not dwell on it here. At first the whole
procedure will seem complicated. Soon, however, it will become just another facet of
life. It is difficult to foresee any end to the necessity for this task in the immediate fu­
ture, but then one never can tell. (p. 722)

You probably did not remember very much of this passage. I also doubt that you
found it very understandable.
I'd like you to read the passage again, this time keeping the title "Washing
Clothes" in mind. It should seem much more memorable because the title provided
56 2. MEMORY

a context or a framework for understanding the passage. When information is pro­


vided before a person reads a text or learns about a topic, the reader is better able to
assimilate the incoming information. The advance organizers-the preliminary in­
formation-act as a guide or framework that helps the learner to anticipate informa­
tion and to relate it to other topics. This is the rationale behind the outlines that
appear at the beginning of each chapter in this book and the reason why each chap­
ter in the accompanying exercise book begins with a series of questions that requires
you to think about the topics in the chapter you are about to read.

Distribute Learning. In plain English, this strategy means, "Don't cram." You
will learn material in a way that is more resistant to forgetting if you space out the
learning sessions. This seems to hold true whether you are learning a motor skill,
like how to return the ball with a strong back hand in tennis, the derivation of chem­
istry formulas, or how to use a new piece of equipment. Spread out the study ses­
sions for maximal benefit (Cull, 2000; Donovan & Radosevich, 1998). If you can
allocate only 5 hours to studying for an exam, spread it out over 3 or 4 days, instead
of spending the entire time at one sitting. Of course, study periods also need to be
long enough to allow for integration of the information you're reading. The ideal
study period depends on many factors including the difficulty of the material, your
own attentional capacities, and how much has to be learned. In fact, it seems that the
more variability you use when learning, the better able you are to recall information
in a wide variety of settings, so study for different lengths of time with different in­
tervals between study sessions for the longest lasting memories.

Get Organized. "Clean up your room!" I don't think that there is a person alive
who hasn't heard (or spoken) these words. The idea that "you'll never be able to
find anything in this mess" may also apply to how you store information in mem­
ory. Although the similarity between memory and a messy room is obviously a
gross oversimplification, organization does make it easier both to find a pair of
socks that match and retrieve information from memory.
I'd like to demonstrate this point with two lists of words. Read one list, at a rate
of approximately one word per second, cover the list, and write down as many of
the words as you can remember, then repeat this process with the second list.

Girl
Heart
Robin
Purple
Finger
Flute
Blue
Organ
Man
Hawk
Green
Lung
Eagle
Child
Piano
ACQUISITION 57

Stop now, cover the above list, and write down as many words from this list as
you can remember.
Now read the next list, cover it, and then write down as many of the words that
you can remember from this list.

Green
Blue
Purple
Man
Girl
Child
Piano
Flute
Organ
Heart
Lung
Finger
Eagle
Hawk
Robin

Stop now, cover the above list, and write down as many words from this list as
you can remember.
Undoubtedly, you recalled correctly more words from the second list than from
the first. You may not have realized that the lists were identical except for the order
in which the words were presented. You might expect that you did better the sec­
ond time because you already had a chance to practice the words once. This is true.
The additional time spent studying the words can partially account for the improve­
ment in recall. However, most of the improvement on the second list came from the
organization provided by presenting words in categories. Research has shown that
when lists of words are presented in categories, recall of material is two to three
times better than when the same list of words is randomly presented (Bower &
Clark, 1969). When words are presented in random order, as in the first list, recall
is improved when subjects have enough time to generate their own categories
(Bousfield, 1953).
You can apply this memory principle by organizing material that you need to
learn. If you are learning a classification system for a biology course or the proper­
ties of metals for a course in science, study one group or category at a time. See how
the groups relate and note similarities and differences within and between cate­
gories. Impose a structure or organization on the material to be learned. Interrelate
the items so that they become coherent. I'll be presenting several strategies for orga­
nizing complex prose passages in Chapter 3. Organizational strategies are as impor­
tant in the recall of prose passages as they are in the recall of lists.

Generate Multiple Cues for Retrieval. I've seen it happen many times. A good
student, who works hard, finds that he can't remember an answer on an exam, and
then soon after turning in his paper, the answer seems to pop into his head. Or, sim­
ilarly, as soon as he hears the answer, he realizes that he "knew" it, but couldn't
remember it when it was needed. These are frustrating experiences that can have
dire consequences if you can't recall, for example, the CPR (cardio pulmonary
58 2. MEMORY

resuscitation) you learned in high school or the emergency procedures for those
times when you run low on air in the middle of a deep sea dive. Knowledge that
you can't recall when it is needed is called inert knowledge. Later, in Chapter 10 on
creative thinking, we will consider ways to help you think of new solutions for new
problems. 'Think of" is really the same as activating inert knowledge. Memory is
central to all thinking. Psychologists know a great deal about remembering and for­
getting, including some ways to make information that you "know" available when
you need it. We know that what you do when you are learning something will have
a strong effect on whether you are able to recall it when it is needed.
When you recall something, it is in response to some cue. For example, "name
some strategies that promote recall." In this example, the terms "strategies to pro­
mote recall" are the cues for what is to be remembered. You would not answer with
a statement like "AI Pacino is a great actor," although this might be your answer to
the question, "Name a great actor." When you learn something, you need to learn it
along with the cues that are likely to be present at recall. Ask questions about causes
and consequences of the material you are learning. How does the newly acquired
information relate to other concepts? What I am describing is the principle of encod­
ing specificity, the idea that material is most likely to be recalled when you are pre­
sented with the same cues that were available when you learned it.
You can use the principle of encoding specificity to improve your memory by
generating a rich variety of cues whenever you learn. A "deep" understanding will
help to prevent the problem of inert knowledge. By asking why, when, and how
questions and developing interconnected knowledge structures in which you relate
what is learned to what you already know, you will be able to respond to a greater
variety of retrieval cues (The Cognition and Technology Group at Vanderbilt, 1993).
Learning that encourages a "deep" or extensive knowledge will help to make the in­
formation spontaneously available in those situations when you need it (Van
Haneghan et al., 1992). Be sure to concentrate on cues that you are most likely to en­
counter when you have to remember something. You can also use external memory
aids as cues to recall, a topic I will discuss later in this chapter.

Overlearn. When can you stop studying? Well, if this question is applied to a
specific example, like studying for a literature exam, then the best answer is when
you know the material perfectly over several different sessions. Consider what hap­
pens when a child learns her multiplication tables. At some point, she gets through
the entire pack of dreaded "flash cards" (remember them?) without an error. If she
stopped learning there, you would find that the next time she went through the
deck of flash cards, a few errors would "creep" in. She needs to overlearn, that is, go
through the pack of cards without errors many times, with sessions spaced out over
time, to ensure accurate recall when these arithmetic facts are needed.

Be Aware of Noncognitive Factors. There are many factors that can affect your
ability to learn that has little to do with cognition but you do need to be able to rec­
ognize them so that you can find ways to eliminate them. Suppose that you are
trying to learn something (anything), but are exhausted from lack of sleep or from
excessive exercise (say, the marathon you just ran); your ability to attend, encode,
and retain information will suffer. Your ability to learn can also be adversely af­
fected by drugs (prescription and nonprescription varieties), an extremely anxious
or depressed emotional state ("I'll never learn this, then I will flunk out, then every­
one will know I am dumb, then I will have to sell hamburgers for the rest of my
RETENTION 59

life," etc.), a lack of time for learning, a poor background in the subject area, and
many more factors. Did you know that lack of sleep can be as detrimental to your
ability to think and respond as being drunk? Sleep deprivation is a major cause of
accidents. The scary part of sleep deprivation is that the sleep-deprived person has
little knowledge of how poorly he or she is thinking. You will probably not allow
friends to drive drunk, but will think nothing of allowing them to drive when they
are overtired, a condition that can be just as dangerous. These are just a few of many
possible behaviors that depress your ability to learn. I hate to sound like your
mother, but take care of yourself, eat right, exercise, get enough sleep, and get help
with physical and emotional problems. There is little point in working on the think­
ing skills that are presented throughout this book if you are going to be spending
much of your life strung out on drugs, half-asleep, or too anxious to learn.

RETENTION

The art of remembering is the art of thinking . . . our conscious effort should not
be so much to impress or retain (knowledge) as to connect it with something
already there.
-William James (1890)
The term "retention" is sometimes used synonymously with memory. Unfortu­
nately, this term suggests that memory is like a vast storage tank or library where
memories are stored and something like miniature pictures of events are retrieved
when we need to recall an event. This notion of memory is wrong.

The Constructive Nature of Memory

Many of the popular notions people hold about memory are wrong. For example, in a
story by the famous mystery writer Agatha Christie, the witness to a crime had her
memory of it "covered over" by a series of events that followed the crime so that she
was unable to remember what happened. As the years passed and the witness grew
old, the distracting and confusing information was forgotten until only the "true"
memory remained. The notion of how our memory works makes for great fiction, but
is a wrong account of what psychologists have learned about memory. In fact, the re­
verse of this account of memory is more accurate. If we encounter new information
after an event takes place, we are likely to confuse the new information with our orig­
inal memory; the original memory does not become "clearer" or better with time.
In a study of memory for the O. J. Simpson trial, college students were asked
about their memory for the verdict in this famous murder trial 3 days after it was
announced and then again 15 and 32 months later CSchmolck, Buffalo, & Squire,
2000). It is surprising that at 32 months after the verdict was announced, few of the
students even remembered filling out a questionnaire about their memory of the
O. J. Simpson trial soon after it happened. At 32 months, many major errors in mem­
ory occurred, with many students answering questions to which they had earlier re­
sponded that they didn't know. They filled in the missing pieces in their memory
after the fact, and had high confidence in their memory for the event, even when
their memory was wrong.
60 2. MEMORY

Several important facts about memory are demonstrated in this study: (a) memo­
ries are frequently inaccurate and sometimes completely wrong; (b) we tend to fill in
missing information in memory with information that "fits" with our belief system
or was acquired after the event occurred; (c) there is very little relationship between
memory accuracy and confidence-we are often highly confident that we are re­
membering an event exactly as it happened, when, in fact, the memory is partly or
wholly wrong. These are important points to remember about memory because we
all rely on information stored in memory to make decisions and understand events,
and we mostly believe that our own memory is highly accurate.

Prior Knowledge. Your ability to learn and remember new material depends
on what you already know. You certainly wouldn't take an advanced course in nu­
clear physics if you never had a basic course in physics. However, you probably
never realized that prior knowledge, the information you already know, influences
how you think and how you remember new information in almost any context. You
can read a passage about a familiar topic more quickly than you can read a passage
of (objectively) comparable difficulty regarding an unfamiliar topic because your
prior knowledge about a known topic facilitates comprehension. Later in this book,
I consider the differences between novices and experts in how they solve problems.
The expert is better able to comprehend a problem and to remember important as­
pects of the problem because of her prior knowledge of the field.

Stereotypes and prejudice

Stereotyping is a category based cognitive response to another person.


-Fiske (1993, p. 623)
An interesting experimental demonstration of the idea that prior knowledge influ­
ences what people will remember was conducted by two psychologists, Snyder and
Uranowitz (1978). Two groups of college students served as subjects. Students in
both groups read the same story about a woman named Betty. The story contained
information about her life. Among the information presented was the fact that she
occasionally dated men. Up to this point, everything was the same for the students
in both groups. After reading the story, one group of students was told that Betty
had become a lesbian, while the other group of students was told that she was lead­
ing a heterosexual lifestyle. The question of interest was whether this would influ­
ence what they remembered about Betty's life story. One week later, all of the
students returned to the laboratory to answer questions about the story they had
read. They were asked many questions, but the critical question was;

In high school, Betty:


(a) occasionally dated men
(b) never went out with men
(c) went steady
(d) no information provided

Can you guess the results of this experiment? The group of students who were told
that Betty is now a lesbian were much more likely to "remember" (b) as the correct
answer than the group of students who were told that Betty is a heterosexual. The
students who had been told that Betty is a lesbian believed that they remembered
RETENTION 61

something that hadn't occurred. Their prejudices and beliefs about lesbians caused
them to remember events that never transpired.
In an experiment designed to determine how sex role stereotypes influence mem­
ory (Halpern, 1985), high school students were given dull, boring stories to read
about the life of a main character who was either a male ("David") or a female
("Linda"). The events described in the story were those commonly engaged in by
both women and men. Female high school students who read stories with Linda as
the protagonist remembered the story better than other female students who read
the same story with David as the protagonist; whereas, male high school students
remembered the story better when David was the protagonist. It seems that the high
school students were able to identify with the main character when his or her sex
was the same as their own, and this resulted in better memory for the details of the
story. In addition, errors in memory were biased toward conformity with sex role
stereotypes.
Our beliefs about lesbians, women, men, and other groups, especially racial and
ethnic groups, exert strong influences on what we will remember about members of
these groups. People may honestly believe that they are recalling something that, in
fact, never occurred because their beliefs about what must have happened bias how
they recall the events.
Experiments like the ones just described have important implications for under­
standing the nature of prejudice. Let's return to the earlier example and suppose
that Betty was a real person whom you knew while growing up. There may be
many things that you can remember about Betty. You now learn that she is a les­
bian. Suppose further that you have a stereotype of lesbians as women who drive
trucks, crush beer cans with one hand, and hate men. Because this stereotype, like
most, contains very little truth about any hypothetical "average" lesbian, you would
be forced either to change your stereotype or to change what you remember about
Betty. It seems that it is our specific memories that change, not the more abstract
memory information underlying our stereotypes. You might selectively remember
information like the fact that she always liked to play basketball and forget other in­
formation about Betty that is inconsistent with your stereotype, like the fact that she
also liked to cook and plant flowers. Allport (1954), in a classic book on prejudice
wrote, "It is possible for a stereotype to grow in defiance of all evidence . . . "
(pp. 189-190). This is an important point that I want to reiterate. Our beliefs are not
easily changed; instead, we tend to change our memory for what we saw and heard
so that the memory is made consistent with the beliefs. Most often, memory is al­
tered without conscious awareness that the information is being recalled in a way
that does not match the event. This is why stereotypes are so resistant to change,
and the need to understand how we think and remember is so important. The criti­
cal need to understand and reduce stereotyping and prejudice was concisely sum­
marized by Fiske (1993, p. 621 ), "Without stereotypes there would be less need to
hate, exclude, exterminate."
Stereotypes act as maps that simplify the world for all of us. They allow us to
make predictions about people, and they also lead us to often exaggerate group dif­
ferences (Klauer & Meiser, 2000). In general, most people recall more positive and
fewer negative characteristics for their own group with the reverse for memory
about other groups.

Inference and Distortion. Memory is malleable. Our memory depends on how


we encoded or interpreted events, not the events themselves. What we remember
62 2. MEMORY

changes over time (Schacter, 1999). When our knowledge and experience change,
our memories also change (Bartlett, 1932). There are additions made to memories so
that we remember events that never occurred and deletions made so that we forget
other events that did. Often, people cannot distinguish between their own thoughts
and their perceptions (Johnson & Raye, 1981 ). Have you ever wondered," Did she
really say that or did I think she said that?" At your next high school or college re­
union get together with friends to remember old times. You may be surprised to
find that the same events are remembered differently by each of you, and each will
have memories that others don't have. Furthermore, each of several people who
shared a common event and remembered it differently will be highly confident that
his or her memory is highly accurate. Overconfidence about our ability to remember
is another pervasive psychological trait that bears almost no relationship to how ac­
curate the memory really is.

Eyewitness Testimony. Seeing is believing, or so they say. Nowhere is this


adage held as strongly as in our legal system. Very often eyewitness testimony is the
determining factor between a conviction and an acquittal. Defendants with credible,
plausible alibis have been convicted by an eyewitness's identification. Should we be
placing so much faith in the accounts given by eyewitnesses?
If we use the theoretical framework provided earlier, then recall of the event de­
pends on acquisition, retention, and retrieval. Information can never be recalled cor­
rectly unless it was attended to at the time it occurred. This would not seem to be a
problem if we're interested in memory for a crime, because it would seem to de­
mand our attention. In fact, witnesses and victims fail to notice many important de­
tails because of a narrowing of attention that occurs under stress. If there is a gun or
other weapon used during the crime, then the victim focuses on the weapon. Other
details that are needed for correct identification, like whether the assailant had a
moustache, may go unnoticed (Loftus, 1979).
There are many alterations of the memory of the event that occur during the re­
tention interval, which in this case is the time between the crime and the recollection
of it at trial. Discussions of the crime after it occurred can be incorporated into mem­
ory so that the individual may honestly believe that she is recalling the crime, while
what is really being recalled is a discussion of the crime.
A notorious example of the fallibility of human memory was seen in a highly
publicized case involving a Catholic priest who was positively identified as an
armed robber by several different witnesses. The trial ended abruptly when a much
younger and taller man confessed, offering details of the crime that could only have
been known by the real robber, because they were never publicized. The witnesses
had not lied. Each honestly believed that he or she remembered seeing the priest as
the robber. It is important to realize that although memory can sometimes be aston­
ishingly accurate, it can also be astonishingly wrong.

Real and False Memories. An explosive controversy involving memory has


shaken public confidence in many accounts of memories that were not recalled for
long periods of time and then suddenly emerged, often during psychotherapy ses­
sions. These memories usually involve traumatic events such as witnessing a mur­
der or experiencing sexual or other physical abuse. Some psychologists believe that
these memories are quite accurate and that they were not available for recall be­
cause they were repressed as a protective mechanism for the individual who could
not deal with the trauma. Other psychologists believe that even though some of
RETRIEVAL 63

these memories may be accurate accounts of real events, many are likely to be
"false" memories for events that either did not occur or were very different from the
way they were remembered (Loftus, 1993; Roediger & Bergman, 1998).
Memories can be accurate or inaccurate and there is no way to distinguish
between the two. In some cases, there is corroborating evidence showing that the
memory is "true" (e.g., physical evidence of abuse), and in other instances, there is
evidence that these "memories" were "suggested" by therapists and others, and
thus, never occurred. But, in many cases, there is no scientific or other way to detect
the differences among a highly accurate memory, an altered memory that is partly
accurate and partly inaccurate, and a completely false memory. There have been
many highly publicized cases involving prominent figures in which some horrible
deed was alleged to have happened. Unfortunately, some innocent people have been
accused of horrible crimes. One such case involved Cardinal Bernardin, a respected
Catholic leader, who was accused of abusing a young man. The young man remem­
bered the abuse for the first time many years after it allegedly occurred. The young
man later decided that he didn't really remember such abuse. On the other hand,
memories of abuse and other tragic events are sometimes accurate. The evidence
must be considered on a case-by-case basis, which is how our legal system works.

RETRIEVAL

What is your mother's maiden name? Unless you happened to be sitting here think­
ing about your mother's name, the name seemed to "pop" into your mind. The
answer must have been stored in some way that allowed it to be retrieved with a
simple question. In fact, it seems almost impossible not to remember your mother's
maiden name, when you are asked this question. Now try this one: What are the
names of the Seven Dwarfs in Snow White and the Seven Dwarfs? If you did not grow
up in America or another Western culture, then you may have responded to this
question with, "Huh?" Of course, you cannot remember something that you never
learned. If you grew up in North America or another Western culture, then you
probably saw the movie and read this old fairy tale, and now you are having trouble
with this question, even though you probably heard their names and read them sev­
eral times. Forgetting can be a frustrating experience for everyone. How can we un­
derstand the retrieval process when it works so well sometimes and so poorly other
times? (P.5. Are you ready to give up? Their names are Bashful, Sneezy, Sleepy,
Grumpy, Happy, Doc, and Dopey.)

Forgetting

Happiness lies in good health and a bad memory.


-Ingrid Bergman (quoted in Smith, 1992, p. AI)

One of the major theories of forgetting is that events interfere with each other in
memory. This is called the interference theory of forgetting. Suppose that you are
studying French and Spanish in college. You'd probably find that you sometimes
get them confused because what you've learned about one language "interferes"
with what you've learned about the other. In general, the more similar two events
64 2. MEMORY

are (or in this case languages), the more interference there will be. Knowing this, can
you think of a way to reduce interference and improve memory? In the example just
given, one way would be to take the courses in different semesters to minimize the
interference, or at least one course early in the morning and the other in the evening.
By keeping the French and Spanish courses as separate as possible, you can reduce
some of the interference.

Thinking and Forgetting. By definition, we can't recall what we have forgotten.


Often, we will have partial information about the forgotten information, such as the
frustrating, "I know that I know the answer, but I can't remember it now." Psychol­
ogists call this experience the "tip of the tongue" phenomena because of the mad­
dening way the information seems to be right on the tip of the tongue, but can't
quite be recalled. Other times, we simply do not know what we have forgotten. Re­
searchers have found that most often people treat the absence of information as
though it is evidence that there is none. Let me explain with an example. Should you
marry your significant other? Suppose that you can think of ("thinking of" is the
same as recalling) two reasons why you should and none why you shouldn't. Be­
cause you cannot recall any reasons that run counter to this decision, you rely on
what can be recalled to guide your decision. The problem, of course, is that we can­
not know what we have forgotten. However, it is possible to spend some time and
effort considering what sort of evidence might have been forgotten and overlooked.
Did you forget to consider that she picks her nose and this really bothers you, or
that he is a sloppy housekeeper, a trait that drives you "crazy"? The need to gener­
ate information so that it can be evaluated is discussed in several places throughout
this book. For now, think of it as a forgetting problem that can be lessened, but not
eliminated, with conscious effort to consider what might have been forgotten. Be­
cause we cannot recall any reasons why we may be making the wrong decision,
people tend to be overconfident about the quality of their decisions. A second rea­
son for the overconfidence that we have in our thinking and remembering processes
is that we can only act on one decision (e.g., marry or not), and we can never know
if another decision would have been better.

Recall Errors. It is clear that we store knowledge (or generate it) in highly orga­
nized ways. Sometimes, the errors we make can provide clues to how it is orga­
nized. Has your father or mother ever called you by your sibling's name? Most
people respond, "Yes." But, few people report that their father or mother called
them by the name of the family dog. Intuitively, this would be insulting (unless they
really love the dog) because it suggests some underlying facts about how your par­
ent thinks about you. Similarly, if your boyfriend or girlfriend called you by the
name of a former significant other, this is also perceived as insulting because it sug­
gests that he or she was thinking about the former boyfriend or girlfriend or that in­
formation about you and the former love are stored together in memory.
I can think of several examples where these "slips of the tongue" have revealed
some telltale signs about the way people store information in memory. In one em­
barrassing example, a university administrator kept mixing up the names of two
African-American deans. This painful mix-up showed how he had stored informa­
tion about them in memory and tended to think about them as "African-American
deans" instead of some other grouping or as individuals.
Stop now, and answer the two questions in the following box. After you write in
the answer for each question, rate how confident you are that your answer is
RETRIEVAL 65

correct. Use the numbers 1 to 7 to rate your confidence with 1 = not at all confident,
=
7 completely confident, and 4 middle level of confidence.
=

1 . How many animals of each kind did Moses take on the ark?
____ Confidence rating (1-7)

2. In the biblical story, what was Joshua swallowed by?


____ Confidence rating (1-7)

Look over your confidence ratings and compare with them with the ratings of
other students. If you responded like most people, you were very confident and
very wrong. Did you respond with the 1/2" to the first question? If you did, you were
wrong because Moses didn't have an ark; you were thinking about Noah. What
about the second question? Were you confident that the answer is a "whale?" If so,
you were wrong again because it wasn't Joshua who was swallowed by a whale.
Demonstrations like this one show how memory works. When you read about ani­
mals on an ark, you activated your knowledge for the biblical ark story and never
noticed that Moses was named in the question. The same thing happened with your
knowledge of the biblical whale story. Reflect on what this shows us about human
memory-the way it is organized and used and the way we can be completely confi­
dent and completely wrong. Try this demonstration with your family and friends
and then explain to them what you have learned about remembering.

Retrieval Cues

As you recall (I hope, I hope) a strategy for good learning is to generate multiple
cues when you are learning new information that should be useful at recall. Let's
consider how these cues operate at recall. Have you ever heard a song on the radio
and then thought about the time you first heard it? ("They're playing our song.")
Where did these memories come from? Something in the environment acted as a re­
trieval cue so that the memory was brought into conscious awareness.
Let's try a demonstration of the powerful effect retrieval cues can have on mem­
ory. Below is a list of words I'd like you to read. Go through the list once at a rate of
approximately one word per second, or have someone read them aloud to you. See
how many words you can remember.

Winter
Green
Foot
Pencil
Sweater
Jupiter
Chicago
Bible
French
Violin
Lunch
Russia
Collie
66 2. MEMORY

Spaghetti
Melrose Place
Newsweek

Stop now, cover the above list, and see how many of the list items you can recall
in any order. Be sure to try this exercise before you go on. Don't look back at the
list when you are finished.

If you didn't remember all 16 words, what happened to the words you forgot? Are
they permanently lost or could you remember them with the proper retrieval cues?
Here is a list of cues. See how many of the "forgotten" words you can recall.

A season of the year


A color
A part of the body
A writing instrument
An article of clothing
A planet
A name of a city
A type of book
A language
A musical instrument
A meal
A country
A breed of dog
A food
A television show
A magazine

Certainly you can remember many more of the items on the list with the appropri­
ate retrieval cues, and this improvement can't be attributed simply to guessing. Gen­
erating your own cues while you are trying to learn something in order to facilitate
recall is one good way to improve memory when the cues that you use at learning
are those that are likely to be available at recall. The cues act like "hooks" in memory
so that information is more accessible and can be more readily remembered.
Many of the strategies to improve memory "work" by providing retrieval cues.
Have you ever had the frustrating experience of struggling to recall the name of your
best friend or your favorite author and then remembered it after you embarrassed
yourself by forgetting such obvious information? As discussed in the section on gener­
ating multiple cues at the time of learning (encoding cues), the fact that you may have
the knowledge needed in a situation does not guarantee that access to that knowledge
will occur. Retrieval cues help us to locate relevant information that is stored in mem­
ory; they allow us to use what we know. The ability to access stored knowledge is an
"important hallmark of intelligence" (Bransford, Sherwood, Vye, & Rieser, 1986).

WORKING MEMORY

A common theme among researchers who study memory is that memory has a lim­
ited capacity; that is, we cannot remember everything that we would like. Nor can
WORKING MEMORY 67

we keep too many different "pieces" of information in an active form in memory so


that we can use them all simultaneously. If I asked you to recite the alphabet back­
wards while solving calculus problems, you would object because there is simply
not enough "space" or "effort" or whatever term you want to use to execute these
two tasks simultaneously, although either one alone can be performed. The cogni­
tive resources that are used to execute mental operations and to remember the out­
comes of these processes are available only in a limited supply. The "place" where
conscious thought occurs is called working memory because it is the hypothetical
space where we perform the work of thinking. One goal of an efficient cognitive sys­
tem is to make the work of thinking easier, or, metaphorically to reduce the amount
of space or effort needed in working memory.
Baddeley (1986, 1992) has proposed a view of working memory that includes a
"central executive" or "boss" that directs the activities we engage in while thinking,
and other systems that involve visual and verbal modes of thought. Often without
awareness, we make decisions about how to spend the limited resources of working
memory. One of these decisions is to use external aids. For example, instead of try­
ing to remember my shopping list, I write it down. I know that it is not worth the
mental effort of committing this list to memory. We also categorize information to
reduce the load on memory. I could remember to buy "stuff" for the dog (dog food,
biscuits, flea powder) and "stuff" for the kids' lunches (sandwich makings, apples,
lunch bags), etc. This strategy would reduce the number of items that I would have
to recall and make forgetting less likely.
Another way we manage our memory is by making decisions about what infor­
mation we need to use and how much mental effort to "spend" on a particular task.
For example, suppose that you had to make a decision concerning a complex issue.
You could decide to omit technical information that is difficult to understand, and
therefore uses a great deal of working memory. If you had to decide if there is dan­
ger from the nuclear waste dump that is next to your house, you might decide to
deal with only a subset of the information to simplify the difficult task of under­
standing nuclear risk. Unfortunately, you could also reduce the mental workload by
seeking simple explanations for complex issues such as crime (it's caused by unem­
ployment), truancy (it's caused by bad parents), or economic downturns (it's caused
by some minority group that is different from you). These simple purported causes
for difficult problems help to reduce the amount of information that is used to reach
a conclusion, but they are also a detriment to good thinking because complex prob­
lems do not have simple, single causes.

Chunking

As you can see, the strategies that we use to reduce the effort of thinking and re­
membering can lead to biases and errors. What is needed is an efficient way to re­
duce the demands on working memory that will not have a negative effect on what
and how we think. Multiple studies of the ways that experts think have shown that
one of the major differences between people with expertise in some field and those
without the expertise is in the efficient way that the experts organize and recall in­
formation that is specific to their specialty. The experts are able to perceive large,
meaningful patterns of information, which reflects the highly organized nature of
the information in their memories. They also know how to search for answers to
problems using information available in the environment and knowledge that they
68 2. MEMORY

have stored in memory. Experts keep the goal clearly in mind, and regulate their
thinking process (Glaser, 1992). These highly compact memory "units" and efficient
search strategies place fewer demands on working memory. Interestingly, these ad­
vantages are specific to the expert's specialization. They approach cognitive tasks in
other domains much like the rest of us, a fact that suggests that the real advantage is
not in a generally superior mind or memory, but in the highly developed knowl­
edge structures and search procedures that correspond to one's area of expertise
(Chi, Glaser, & Farr, 1988).
Meaningfulness and familiarity can account for some individual differences in
the ability to utilize highly compact memory units. Have you ever wondered how a
good poker or pinochle or chess player is able to remember which cards have been
played or which moves have been made? In a classic study of chess players' memo­
ries for the positions of chess pieces on a board, deGroot (1966) found that chess
masters could remember chess positions that actually occurred in a game after look­
ing at the board for only 5 seconds. Novice chess players had much more difficulty
in remembering where the chess pieces had been. Does this mean that really good
chess players have extraordinary memories? To answer this question, deGroot
placed the pieces randomly on the board and asked master and novice players to
view the board for 5 seconds and then recall the positions of the pieces. In the ran­
dom placement condition, both groups performed about the same. It seems that the
master players remembered more than the novices only when the board positions
were highly meaningful.
It seems likely that good card players remember which cards have already been
played because each hand is highly meaningful to them. For example, John Moss
(1950, a pseudonym for the author of How to Win at Poker) describes a series of possi­
ble hands that a player can be dealt along with several possible cards that could be
drawn. It would be easy for him or another poker shark to remember a "four of dia­
monds in the hole with a four of hearts, six of diamonds and ace of spades ex­
posed." He could remember this as a single familiar hand, while a novice player
would have to remember four separate cards. For the good players, this hand would
represent a single chunk in memory. Reducing a large number of items to a single
item to be remembered is called chunking. (No, it is not a brand of Chinese food.) It
is a subtle and ubiquitous memory process that allows us to recall whole sentences
instead of words and whole words instead of letters. As material becomes increas­
ingly meaningful, we can reduce the number of items that need to be remembered.
Master chess players and card players seem to have this memory advantage.
Look quickly at the row of letters and numbers presented below, and then cover
them and try to remember as many as you can:

IB MF BI TW AJ FK
816 44 93 62 51 69 41

If you had difficulty with this task, the reason may be that the information was
not chunked or grouped into meaningful units. Suppose I reorganize the letters by
changing the spacing but not their order. They now become IBM, FBI, TWA, JFK.
You should have no difficulty remembering all of the letters now. The amount of in­
formation hasn't changed, but the cognitive demand has. It is much easier to recall
information that is chunked into meaningful units. Consider the row of numbers.
Suppose I tell you that this series, if regrouped, is the sequence 92, 82, 72, etc. Again,
by relating the input to what's known to make it meaningful, a difficult memory task
METAMEMORY 69

can be made trivial. The notion that meaning is important in memory will be raised
again, later in this chapter, when we consider strategies for improving memory.

working Memory and problem Solving

Working memory is the "place" where we manipulate information so that we can


use the information to perform some task. When solving a problem or making a de­
cision, many different strategies or alternatives need to be considered simultane­
ously. One bottleneck in these processes is the limited capacity of working memory.
After all, we cannot consider 20 different options at the same time or apply several
different strategies in our mind to decide which will work. We will return to the lim­
ited capacity of working memory in several of the following chapters because it is
easier to solve problems or make decisions when we can reduce the load on work­
ing memory (Reber & Kotovsky, 1997).

METAMEMORY

If one has poor insights into the inner workings of their cognitive system, this
should inhibit their performance on virtually all tasks, because it is hard to
imagine a single cognitive task that does not require some level of metacognitive
awareness for its successful completion.
-Ceci and Ruiz (1993, p. 1 75)

The term metamemory refers to one's personal knowledge of his or her own mem­
ory system. It seems that much of the difference between good and poor learners
can be attributed to metamemory. Bransford (1979) has summarized this:

. . . (E)ffective learners know themselves what they need to know and do in order to
perform effectively; they are able to monitor their own levels of understanding and
mastery. These active learners are therefore likely to ask questions of clarification and
more efficiently plan their study activities. Such activities are quite different from pas­
sively accepting (yet momentarily actively processing) the particular information that a
person or text presents. (p. 248)

In Chapter 3, I will build on this theme and emphasize the importance of asking
questions as a metamemory strategy.
This quote from Bransford brings up the important concept of active learning.
Very little, if anything, can be learned passively (American Psychological Associa­
tion, 1992; Bransford, Brown, & Cocking, 1999). You need to deal actively with ma­
terial if you want to remember it. Good learners know when they understand the
material and when they do not understand it; poor learners don't seem to notice the
difference. Good learners know what they have to do to facilitate learning. These are
the executive processes that keep the learner mindful of what and how much is
being learned. For example, good learners may spontaneously link new information
to information previously learned or think of possible applications for the new ma­
terials they are learning. As you read this paragraph, you may be applying this
learning "device" by noting the similarity of this concept with one you learned in
the section entitled organization, that imposing additional organization on material
by activities like these will result in improved comprehension.
70 2. MEMORY

An interesting study has shown that students who are having academic problems
in college approach their text assignments differently from good students (Whimbey,
1976). The less successful college students read difficult material straight through
without seeming to notice when they didn't understand the material and without
rereading the difficult sections. Good students know these strategies. Whimbey
found that he could improve performance for the poorer students by teaching them
how to organize the material and how to become aware of what they were under­
standing and what they weren't. Too often college students and others believe
that they know some material because they've read or heard it. They're surprised
to find that they can't answer basic questions about the material they thought
they knew.
Nelson and Narens (1990) provided a list of tasks that are used in experimental
settings to assess metamemory. This list can easily be adapted as a way to enhance
metamemory. For example, before you begin a learning task, carefully assess the
ease with which you expect to achieve the learning, called ease of learning judg­
ments. If you are a senior in college who has majored in sociology, you might de­
cide that the material presented in an introductory psychology text would be easy
for you to learn. Alternatively, you could decide that a course in Asian philosophy
would be relatively difficult to learn. The reason for making ease of learning judg­
ments is that they require you think about the to-be-Iearned material, considering
what you already know about the topic, your ability in the area, and the learning
context. These reflections will prepare you to allocate the necessary time and mental
resources to accomplish the task.
While you are learning, consider how well you know the material-that is, make
judgments of how well you are learning quality of learning judgments. If you can
-

determine that it is not going well, then you can redirect your learning activities and
seek help. After learning, think about how well you know and understand what has
just been learned-feelings of knowing judgments. Finally, when you are using the
material in a response, make degree of confidence judgments about your answers.
Taken together, these four tasks will provide an ongoing monitor of learning and
memory, and they can help with the selection of control procedures such as allocating
more time and effort, trying another study mode, and stopping the learning session.
These four metamemory tasks are summarized in Table 2.1.

Confidence

The idea that we can be highly confident about the accuracy of our memories and
completely wrong has already been mentioned in several places in this chapter. It is
clear that, in some ways, we can be misled by our own assessments of how well we
can remember. For example, if students are asked to judge how likely they are to re­
call information about a topic right after they studied it, they tend to overestimate
the likelihood that they will recall the information correctly at some later time
(Benjamin, Bjork, & Schwartz, 1998). It seems that immediately after learning, the in­
formation is easily recalled, so we assume that it will be easy to recall at some later
time. A more accurate estimate of how likely students are to recall information
would come from judgments that are not made while the newly learned information
is so "fresh. " It seems that we should be less confident about the accuracy of our
memories and the likelihood of recalling something in the future, even when the
memory "feels" accurate and recall seems easy.
MNEMONICS 71

TABLE 2. 1 .
Self· Reflective Tasks That Can Serve as a Guide for Monitoring
the Process of Remembering

When What How


Before learning Ease of learning judgments Look over the material that is
to be learned and judge the
ease with which you will
learn it. Consider what you
already know about the
topic, the reason why you
are learning it, and your own
abilities.
While learning Quality of learning As you learn, monitor how
judgments well you are understanding
the information or performing
a motor skill. Can you
summarize in your own
words what is being
learned? Are you generating
multiple cues and using
techniques that foster deep
learning?
After learning Feeling of knowing When the learning task is
judgments completed, reflect on how
well you learned the
material. Have you
overlearned for maximal
retention and used
distributed practice? Will
you be able to recall the
material some time in the
future?
At recall Degree of confidence When you are recalling the
judgments information, consider how
confident you are in your
recall.

MNEMONICS

In an episode of the popular children's television show, Sesame Street, Bert and
Ernie, two lovable Muppets, discussed an intriguing memory phenomenon. Bert no­
ticed that Ernie had tied a piece of string around his finger to help him remember
something. In fact, Ernie tied string around each of his eight fingers (apparently
Muppets have eight fingers) to be really sure that he didn't forget. After some
prompting from Bert, Ernie recalled that the string was supposed to help him re­
member he should buy more string, because they had run out of string.
Although this story is humorous, it illustrates some fundamental assumptions
and problems encountered by humans (and Muppets) in dealing with their memory.
The wide range of activities from tying a string around one's finger to the more elab­
orate procedures presented later are called mnemonic devices. They are techniques
72 2. MEMORY

for orgamzmg and elaborating information so that it can be more easily


remembered. Many students use mnemonic devices to prepare for exams and some
of the techniques are so common that we usually don't think of them as mnemonics.
During the summers when I was in college, I worked as a waitress at a resort in
the Catskill Mountains of New York. The resort had a nightclub with the usual array
of singers, dancers, jugglers, and animal acts. (The kitchen help were not allowed to
attend the nightclub, so, of course, we would sneak in as often as we could.) One
particular act that amazed me was a memory act by Harry Lorayne. He went
around the audience recalling people's names. His memory seemed limitless. I was
also surprised at how much the audience enjoyed his performance and that an
amazing memory would qualify as a nightclub act. After all, no one ever asked me
to demonstrate the amazing powers of critical thinking as a nightclub act! (Perhaps
there is a reader who books nightclub acts, who is just looking for this sort of late­
night crowd-pleasing entertainment.) Harry Lorayne later wrote two books on this
topic (Lorayne, 1975; Lorayne & Lucas, 1974). The mnemonic principles he used are
presented here along with several others.
Most mnemonics are based on a few simple memory principles. They all force
you to pay attention to the items to be remembered, and they provide either an or­
ganization scheme or a meaningful context for unrelated items. The user is often re­
quired to organize the material and to use the mnemonic as an efficient retrieval
cue. The use of mnemonics also requires metacognitive monitoring-keeping track
of what you know. They are intentional strategies, ones that you can use when you
decide that you want to remember something. Thus, from what you've already
learned about memory earlier in this chapter, you can see that mnemonics are not
mere theatrical tricks. They work because they represent applications of basic prin­
ciples of memory.
We all employ memory aids everyday. The most common aids are external mem­
ory aids, such as the sticky notes that are popular, calendars in which we write ap­
pointments and other activities that we want to remember, timers to remind us to
turn off the stove, and shopping lists. Mnemonics that are designed to help us retrieve
information from memory are called internal memory aids. In this chapter, I present
four basic types of internal memory aids-keywords and images, rhymes, method of
places, and first letters. Each will be discussed in turn followed by some guidelines
for selecting the appropriate mnemonic for the type of material to be learned.

Keywords and Images

The following demonstration was presented as an anecdote by Donald Norman


(1976, p. 134). I have used it as a class demonstration many times, and students are
always surprised at how well it works. The use of this mnemonic depends on first
learning keywords, which serve as "hooks" for information that is learned later. In
this case, the keywords are in the form of a simple poem to learn. Spend a minute or
two learning this poem:

One is a bun,
Two is a shoe,
Three is a tree,
Four is a door,
Five is a hive,
MNEMONICS 73

Six are sticks,


Seven is heaven,
Eight is a gate,
Nine is a line, and
Ten is a hen.

Do you have this memorized? If not, go over the poem again.


Now, I'm going to present a list of words to be remembered. You have to form an
image or association between the listed items and the items in the poem you just
learned. For example, the first item on the list is ashtray. Image an ashtray with a
bun in it, since the bun was the first item in the poem. You could imagine something
like a large hamburger bun sitting in a dirty ashtray. Read the items on the list one
at a time, allowing enough time to form an image.

1 . ashtray
2. firewood
3. picture
4. cigarette
5. table
6. matchbook
7. glass
8. lamp
9. shoe
10. phonograph

Now, cover the list of words and answer the following questions:

What is number eight?


What number is cigarette?

If your experience was like the one Norman described or the ones my students
report, then you've been surprised to find that the answers were easily available. In
this case you learned a list of rhyming keywords and then used imagery to relate the
words to be learned to the keywords. Research has shown that images are best
when they're interacting (e.g., the bun is in the ashtray and not just next to it) and
when they are vivid and detailed (the bun that I was imaging was a hamburger bun
and the ashtray was glass) (Baddeley & Andrade, 2000; Bower, 1972). The deliberate
use of both verbal and imagery modes of thought was introduced in Chapter 1 .
We'll use this strategy again in Chapters 9 and 1 0 on creativity and problem solving.
Of course, you're probably thinking, "Why not just write the list down on paper?" If
paper and pencil are allowable and available, this is certainly the best and cheapest
mnemonic that you can find, but often we need to commit lists to memory. If you
are an anatomy student, you have to learn long lists of the names of nerves, bones,
and other organs. Chemists need to learn complex formulas, and it would not instill
confidence in me if I found that my surgeon kept a written list of body parts above
the operating table (but, it might not be a bad idea). There are many real-life in­
stances when we need to learn long lists of material in as efficient a way as possible.
In a recent survey, college students were asked about the strategies that they used
to help them remember material for exams (Soler & Ruiz, 2000). Most of the college
students, like the 10th graders who were also surveyed, responded that they used
74 2. MEMORY

low-level strategies like repetition, a strategy that is very inefficient if the goal is
long-term remembering. Few reported that they used more effective strategies like
deliberately forming vivid images of the material they were learning.
Images can also be used alone (without keywords). They are especially advanta­
geous when you want to remember names and faces. This is the technique that
Harry Lorayne (1975) uses. Change the names you want to remember to a concrete
noun; pick out a distinctive feature of the face and image the two as interacting. He
suggests that you pay special attention to cheeks, lips, facial lines, forehead, nose,
eyebrows, and eyes. For example, if you meet Ms. Silverstein and you notice that
she has wide-set eyes, you could image a silver beer mug (stein) between her eyes.
Mr. Dinter could be changed to dinner and an entire dinner could be imaged on his
large forehead. Try this at the next party you attend. You'll find it fun, and you may
surprise yourself with your new abilities.
A keyword mnemonic system has been developed especially for learning a sec­
ond language (Atkinson, 1975). Suppose you are learning French and are faced with
the following three vocabulary words with their English translations to learn:

French English
homme man
etoile star
legume vegetable

Students begin by generating their own keywords. The keyword should sound
like the foreign vocabulary word. Thus, for the word homme, I'd generate "home,"
for etoile, I'd use "a towel," and for legume, I'd use "lagoon."
The second step makes use of imagery by linking an image of the keyword with
the correct translation of the foreign word. I'd visualize a man entering a large
home, a towel with a star painted on it, and vegetables floating in a lagoon. (It's best
when the items are interacting.) When the foreign words homme, etoile, and legume
are encountered, students would then automatically recall the images and retrieve
the correct translations.
Atkinson claims that as facility with the foreign language develops the need to re­
member the images diminishes and students can extract the intended meaning
without the use of imagery. Students who are taught to use this method consistently
recall more correct English translations (72% compared with 46%) than students
who use the usual rote rehearsal method of repeating the words until they "stick."
Furthermore, this method seems to work best when students generate their own
keywords and images. The need for active participation in learning and the payoff
from the effortful work of learning are general rules for improving memory. This is
a mnemonic that is well worth using if you are studying a foreign language.

Rhymes

We also use rhymes to help us remember. For example, there are few people who
haven't heard:

I before E, except after C.


or
Thirty days hath September, April, June, and November.
MNEMONICS 75

Answer this question quickly. What letter comes after N? Most people find that
they need to sing that portion of the alphabet (1, m, n, 0, p) to answer this question.
Like rhymes, the rhythm established in songs help to deter forgetting.
Rhymes are useful when order is important because mistakes in order will usu­
ally destroy the rhyme. Notice that the first keyword poem I presented relied on
keywords, images, and rhymes (one is a bun, etc.). This is an especially easy
mnemonic to use, probably because several mnemonic devices are employed in the
same poem to guard against forgetting.

Methods of Places
Before I describe how "places" work as a mnemonic device, I'd like you to re­
member my back-to-school shopping list. Read the list through slowly once, then
see how many items you can recall.

Pencils
Ruler
Notebook
Marking pens
Compass
Tape
Paper
Scissors
Sharpener
Reinforcements
Tablet
Glue

How many items on this list did you remember?


Now I'll show you how the method of places (or method of loci) could improve
your recall for this list. Pick a familiar route, like the one from your house to school.
Now imagine each of the items on this list placed somewhere along this route. The
pencils could be very tall and form a fence around your front lawn, the ruler could
be sitting across your car, the notebook could be the stop sign at your corner, etc.
Try this now with the back-to-school shopping list just presented. Once the images
are formed, you should be able to remember every item by "mentally walking
through" your route and noticing the items you've imagined along the way.
I once went to an introductory lesson for a very expensive memory improvement
course. The method of places was the demonstration they used to convince potential
students that the course was valuable. For months afterward, I received letters in
the mail asking me if I "forgot" to send my money and to register for their course.
The expensive (there are no cheap ones) memory improvement courses teach the
same methods presented in this chapter. They have no magic secrets that are un­
available in the psychology literature.
The Greeks, who were famous for giving long speeches from memory, have left
us with many tips on how to best use this method. For example, the same route can
be used repeatedly for different lists, but we should be careful not to put more than
one item at the same place (Ross & Laurence, 1968). They also suggested that the
places should not be too much alike (e.g., don't use only stop signs along your
route) and that they should not be too brightly lit (or there will be glare) nor too
76 2. MEMORY

dimly lit (or the objects will be difficult to see). This is a good method to use when
events need to be remembered in a particular order, since the route can be mentally
traversed forward or backward.
Research with the elderly has shown that they can perform as well as much
younger college students when they are taught and use this mnemonic. This is im­
portant because America is an aging society, and many elderly fear a loss of mem­
ory. If you are elderly, or if you know someone who is, many of the simple
mnemonics presented in this chapter such as the method of places and use of visual
imagery can be used as an aid to memory and thus, postpone or reduce cognitive
aging effects. It is also particularly useful to assist the elderly with the use of exter­
nal memory aids such as medication boxes that have an alarm to signal the time for
the medication, calendars, and timers (Park, 1 992). External aids have the advantage
of helping those with failing (or poor) memory recall the tasks that are important.
The internal mnemonics offer the benefit of helping the elderly retain their own cog­
nitive abilities.

First Letters

First letter mnemonics are probably most commonly used in preparing for tests. To
use this technique, take the first letter of each term to be learned, insert vowels and
other letters if necessary, and make a word. When you need to remember the list,
you recall the word you formed and then use each letter as a retrieval cue for each
item on the list. Many of us learned to remember the names of the Great Lakes as
HOMES (Huron, Ontario, Michigan, Erie, and Superior). If you never learned this
before, you'll never forget it again.
The first letter mnemonic organizes unrelated terms into a single word. You al­
ready know how important good organization is for memory. I can remember using
this technique when I was a college student. The class had been told to be prepared
to answer a long essay question that was to be written during an in-class exam.
There were six points that I wanted to make in the essay, and I wanted to be sure
that I included all of them in order. I took the first letter of each of the points, made
up a word using these letters and used this word to help me remember all of the
points for the exam. (It worked well.) This technique is also especially useful when
you have to speak in front of people without notes. Select one word that can stand
for each point you want to make and use the first letter of each word to form a single
retrievable word. Even though good speeches may appear unrehearsed, good
speakers practice with techniques like this one. It helps them to present their speech
in a confident and professional manner.
A related mnemonic that doesn't fit clearly into any of the categories is the one
used to recall the value of pi. I'm presenting it in this section because even though it
doesn't involve first letters, it is a letter-based technique. Read the following sen­
tence:

May I have a drink, alcoholic, of course.

By counting the letters in each word, you can read off the digits for pi, which are
3.1415926. It is easier to remember a single meaningful sentence than it is to recall
eight digits.
MNEMONICS 77

Mnemonic principles

Mnemonic devices can be powerful aids for memory. They are also paradoxical be­
cause it seems that to remember better you need to remember more. The first letter
mnemonic requires that you remember the new word you created with the first let­
ters as well as each of the words. The keyword systems require that you learn a key­
word system, and the rhymes present you with a song or poem to be learned. They
each necessitate work. Acquiring a good memory means working at it, but it is work
that pays off in lifelong dividends. There are hundreds of studies that demonstrate
that the deliberate use of mnemonics improves recall (McCormick & Levin, 1987).
There is probably no field that requires more rote memory, in addition to other
sorts of remembering, as medicine. There are thousands of mnemonics to help stu­
dents in the medical fields recall the names of anatomical parts and their connec­
tions. Here is one that I learned in biology class many years ago: "On Old Olympus
Towering Tops, A Finn And German Viewed Some Hops." Some readers will recog­
nize this mnemonic as a way to recall the 12 cranial nerves in order: Olfactory,
Optic, Occulomotor, Trochlear, Trigeminal, Abducens, Facial, Auditory [or Vestibu­
locochlear], Glossopharyngeal, Vagus, Accessory [or Spinal root of the accessory],
Hypoglossal. As you can probably guess, there is a Web site dedicated to medical
mnemonics (http: / /www.medicalmnemonics.com) .
Let's try to develop a mnemonic that could help you to remember the types of
mnemonics. First, let's review what they are: keywords and images, rhymes,
method of places, and (first) letters. Although you could use the method of places
and image each of these terms along a route, or associate them with a keyword, or
make up a poem, my choice for a list like this one is the first letter mnemonic. Start
by listing the first letter of each term: K, R, MP, 1. You can modify the first letter
technique by using each letter to begin a word in a sentence, since incorporating
these letters in a single word may be difficult. Try it. The sentence one of my stu­
dents came up with is "Kind Round Men, Please Listen." Use imagery also to aid re­
call. Imagine a round (fat) man with a kind face and very big ears (for listening).
Make your images detailed and vivid. (Can you see his round tummy and elephant­
size ears?) If you're asked to recall the mnemonic devices, you can list each one, and
by remembering the name of each, all of the information you've learned about them
should also be easily retrieved.
Many people find it difficult to remember how to spell the word "mnemonics."
Another student suggested this one: Memory Never Explains MONey and Ice
Cream Sandwiches. Be sure to think about this mnemonic. Can you generate an
image to go along with this sentence? You should never have difficulty spelling this
word correctly again.

External Memory Aids

External memory aids, which are sometimes called "cognitive prostheses," are also
valuable in helping with the multitude of remembering tasks that we all encounter.
If you have to remember to do something, use a kind of remembering called
prospective memory because it is memory for a future event-setting an
alarm, posting a note, tying a string on your finger, or leaving something in an obvi­
ous and unavoidable place (e.g., the waste basket in front of the door; Herrmann &
Gruneberg, 1 999).
78 2. MEMORY

Some people have acquired specialized and specific external memory aids. I was
impressed with such a system when I was attending a ballet at the grand Bolshoi
Theatre in Moscow. Like many cities with very cold weather, it is customary to
check your coat when you arrive at the theater. In addition, many people also check
bags, boots, and large hats. The workers at the wardrobe have to be able to dispense
hundreds of possessions very quickly when the ballet is over. In addition, the check­
ers also rent binoculars and need to remember who rented the binoculars so as to be
certain that the binoculars are returned. I found that the checkers had devised a sim­
ple external mnemonic system. The coat hooks are numbered (into the hundreds at
each station). When someone checks a bag with the coat, the checker uses a number
that ends in 4 (14, 24, 34, etc.). Then, when the claim ticket is presented at the end of
the show, a 4 in the last digit means that the checker should look below for a pack­
age. If a person rents binoculars, then a chalk line is marked above the coat hook
number. Then, if a coat is retrieved and there is a chalk mark above the number, the
checker knows that binoculars are to be returned. This simple system, which has
probably developed over many years, helps to get a large number of people out of
the wardrobe area and reduces the time spent in line. This last point is critical to
Russians who often have to wait in long lines. If only such a system could be used to
reduce the other lines as well.

Remembering Events

Most often we need to remember events rather than lists or related concepts. Much
of the work done in the area of event memory has been conducted by psychologists
trying to assist victims and witnesses of crime with recall of the criminal activity.
We can borrow the mnemonic techniques that they use to improve memory.

The Cognitive Interview. "Information is the lifeblood of a criminal investiga­


tion" (Stewart, 1 985). How can eyewitnesses to an event be helped to remember
what happened so that they can provide law enforcement officers with the needed
information? One way to improve the quantity and quality of what gets remem­
bered is with the use of a memory aid for events known as the cognitive interview
(Fisher, 1995). The cognitive interview is based on principles derived from cognitive
psychology about how information is organized and the types of retrieval cues that
can work to prime recall. It seems that the unflappable Sergeant Friday from the old
television show Dragnet was wrong when he asked for, "just the facts, ma'am." The
accuracy and completeness of recall is improved by elaboration, especially about ob­
jects and activities that occurred near the crime in time or space. Geiselman and
Fisher (1985) have found that recall for events can be enhanced by using the follow­
ing strategies:

1 . Start by recalling ordinary events that occurred before the target event (i.e.,
the crime). Visualize the circumstances. Think about the layout of the room,
weather, traffic flow, or any other aspect of the scene. Think about your mood
at the time.
2. Be as complete as possible in your recall. Don't edit your report or exclude
something because you think that it might not be important.
3. Recall the event in both forward and backward order, or start from the middle
and recall both forward and backward in time from some central incident.
BIASES IN MEMORY 79

4. Change your perspective. Try to recall the event as though you were some
other person such as a spectator (real or imaginary) or you were the perpetra­
tor of a crime.

There are additional techniques that can be useful for recall of specific types of in­
formation. If you are trying to remember the physical appearance of someone, does
someone else whom you know come to mind? Why? In what ways are they similar?
If you can't recall a name, recite the alphabet to see if a particular letter can "jog"
your memory. Sometimes partial information like the number of syllables in a name
can be recalled. If numbers are involved (e.g., a license plate), try to recall the num­
ber of digits or some physical characteristic of the digits like their size or color.
The techniques of the cognitive interview can be used anytime you need to re­
member an event. There are several studies showing that it can help children and
adults remember events. Imagine, for example, that there has been a recent rash of
burglaries in your neighborhood. Suppose further that you hid a valuable piece of
jewelry as a deterrent to theft, but later realize that you can't remember where you
hid it. Or, more commonly, suppose you can't remember where you left your car
keys. This can be a very frustrating type of forgetting. In this case you would try to
retrace your steps and try to recall the last time you used them. Systematic and de­
liberate use of these techniques should be helpful in recall.

BIASES IN MEMORY

All of the mnemonics or strategies for remembering presented thus far in this chap­
ter have been concerned with the deliberate use of memory strategies. Much of what
we remember was acquired incidentally, that is, without the use of a conscious, de­
liberate scheme. If you go to the movies, you can later recall the plot and actors
as well as the name of the theater you were sitting in, without deliberately creat­
ing images or using rhymes. It's fortunate that we don't always have to work at
remembering.
Unfortunately, our memories are subject to certain biases. All items stored in
memory are not equally likely to be recalled, and when memory errors occur, they
are not random. Because all thinking relies on memory, it is important to recognize
the ways in which memory can be biased.

Confirmation Bias

One type of bias that was already discussed is the effect of stereotypes. Stereotypes
alter memory in predictable ways. The influence of stereotypes is just one instance
of a more general bias to remember more easily information that confirms our hy­
potheses than information that contradicts them (Beyth-Marom, Dekel, Gombo, &
Shaked, 1 985). In an interesting study of this effect, college students were told that
their dreams would be interpreted by a clinical psychologist (Mazzoni, Loftus, Seitz, &
Lynn, 1 999). The psychologist, who was a collaborator in the study, gave the stu­
dents false information about the meaning of their dreams, telling, for example, that
their dreams revealed that they had been bullied before the age of 3. A large propor­
tion of the students came to "remember" this incident, which never happened.
80 2. MEMORY

Additionally, students who believed in the validity of dream interpretation before


the experiment were more likely to remember the incident suggested by the clinical
psychologist than those who did not. Thus, prior beliefs about what we believe to be
true influence memory, so that we tend to remember events that are consistent with
our beliefs.

Pollyanna Effect in Memory

Recall is also biased in that we tend to remember events in ways that reflect posi­
tively on us. If you want to try this out, stop now and list the grades you received in
high school (or if you are in high school now, list the grades you received in middle
schooD. It seems that most people remember getting very good grades (Bahrick,
Hall, & Berger, 1996). Like previous studies, it also seems that there is little relation­
ship between how confident someone is about the memory for one's grades and the
accuracy of that memory.

Vivid, Dramatic, Personal, and Familiar

We also know that there is a recall advantage to information that is well known, fa­
miliar, prominent (generally important or personaD, recent, vivid, and dramatic.
Having said this, we also know that, over time, memory for even these sorts of
events will become inaccurate, even though it continues to "feel" like an accurate
memory (Schacter, 1999). There is also the frustrating problem of inert knowledge,
which occurs when we do not recall information at a time when it is needed. In ad­
dition, general knowledge about events is sometimes mistaken as memory for a
specific event because people cannot tell the difference between events as they were
experienced and events that they constructed from general knowledge (Jacoby,
Kelley, & Dywan, 1 989). These biases in memory have profound effects on how peo­
ple think. For this reason, I'll be returning to biases in memory several times
throughout this book.

LONG-TERM ACCURACY IS SOMETIMES EXCELLENT

Before you despair completely, you will be happy to know that memory can also be
fairly good. For example, if you were wondering, "Why bother learning this, if I will
soon forget it and not even know that I forgot," there are several good reasons to
keep studying. It seems that memory for information learned in a cognitive psychol­
ogy class was still fairly good for main concepts and important ideas, even 12 years
after learning, although memory for many of the names of the theorists tended to be
forgotten in about three years (Conway, Cohen, & Stanhope, 1991) and memory for
high school math was almost perfect decades later for students who continued
learning and took math in college (Bahrick & Hall, 1 991). In a study of memory for
Spanish that was learned in high school or college (students for whom Spanish was
not their native language), researchers found that rapid forgetting occurred during
the first six years from the date the formal language learning was completed, but ap­
proximately 60% of what was learned was remembered through the adult years and
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 81

up until the 60s and 70s when age-related forgetting began to occur (Schmidt, Peeck,
Paas, & van Breukelen, 2000). The original level of learning is important in deter­
mining how well something will be remembered over time, with higher levels of
learning associated with better long-term memory. Similarly, memory for the neigh­
borhood in which adults grew up was also marked with a short period of forgetting
followed by good memory (for what was not forgotten) for 40 or more years
(Schmidt, Peeck, Paas, & van Breukelen, 2000). As in the other studies, good remem­
bering was associated with overlearning and spacing of learning episodes. Thus,
the more you learn, the better you remember information related to the topic of
your learning, with broad principles and concepts generally well remembered for a
lifetime.
You can take advantage of these operating principles of memory in two ways.
First, you could use them to improve memory by considering information that you
want to remember by overlearning and spacing learning sessions over time. In addi­
tion, make the material to-be-learned familiar and prominent, generate encoding
cues, use organizational strategies, and elaborate by connecting the new information
to knowledge you have already acquired. Perhaps, even more importantly, you can
be aware of the ways your memory is likely to be biased and engage in deliberate at­
tempts to debias your recollections.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

A general framework for thinking was presented in Chapter 1 . Let's see how we can
apply it to the topic of memory.

I . What Is the Goal?

At least three different types of thinking goals involve memory. The first is how to
acquire (learn) something so that it can be more readily recalled at a later time. This
is an encoding (or acquisition) goal. A second type is a retrieval goal in which the
desired outcome is recall of some item that was previously stored. Finally, there is a
debiasing goal. This involves examining your recall for evidence of bias so that you
can recognize the possibility that a memory may not be veridical and correct for it.
The first step in applying the framework is to determine what the appropriate
goal is for a given situation. Are you learning new material, trying to recall some­
thing accurately, or examining your recollections for possible bias?

2 . What Is Known?

This is a question about where to start. Is there a list of foreign vocabulary words
sitting in front of you that you have to learn? Can you remember seeing your wallet
this morning, but can't remember what you did with it after that? Can you remem­
ber most of the battles fought in Europe during the 1 9th century, but can't get the
order straight? Are you considering your own thinking about a contemporary issue
like gays in the military or "three strikes and you're out?" If so, then you will need
to consider where your beliefs and attitudes came from and the ways in which they
may be biased or even completely wrong, even when they "feel" right. Different
skills would be used in each of these situations. By paying careful attention to what
82 2. MEMORY

is known or given, you can use this information as a guide for selecting the appro­
priate skill for each situation.

3. Which Thinking Skill or Skills Will Get


You to Your Goal?
Several different strategies to improve memory were presented in this chapter.
You have to select among them for ones that are most likely to help you attain your
goal. The selection is based on the nature of the goal, what is known, and how much
effort you are willing to put into goal attainment. For example, if your goal is to re­
member the names of the people you meet during a business meeting or during the
course of interviewing with many different people, you would select Harry
Lorayne's imaging technique for associating names and faces. Similarly, if you were
able to take notes during the interviews, you would review your notes. You could
use the method of places for subject areas like history and social sciences for which
knowing the correct sequence of events is crucial to understanding them. Similarly,
if you are thinking through your beliefs and attitudes about complex issues, you
need to select skills that will help you evaluate them for bias, distortion, and error.
The following memory skills were presented in this chapter. Review each skill
and be sure that you understand how to use each one.

• Monitoring your attention


• Developing an awareness of the influence of stereotypes and other beliefs on
what we remember
• Making abstract information meaningful as an aid to comprehension and recall
• Using advance organizers to anticipate new information and to prepare for
reading
• Organizing information so that it can be recalled more easily
• Overlearning because you know that it will increase the probability and accu­
racy of recall
• Recognizing that although you may be very confident that you are recalling an
event accurately, there is also a high probability that your memory is not as ac­
curate as it feels
• Generating retrieval cues at both acquisition and retrieval
• Practicing recall for information that you are intentionally trying to learn
• Monitoring how well you are learning
• Using external memory aids
• Employing keywords and images, rhymes, places, and first letters as internal
memory aids
• Applying cognitive interview techniques
• Developing an awareness of biases in memory so that you can consider the
way your own beliefs, attitudes, and background knowledge could be influ­
encing what and how you remember

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?


Suppose that you selected the keyword mnemonic for foreign language learning
to learn a list of technical terms in a course in physics. You go through the list, gen­
erate familiar English words that sound like the ones you're trying to learn, etc.
(You cleverly adapted the technique for use with words that may as well be from a
CHAPTER SUMMARY 83

foreign language as far as you're concerned.) The effort doesn't stop there. Go over
the list "cold" (without your notes and with their definitions covered). Distribute
your learning and overlearn. Do you know the words? If not, go through the tech­
nique as many times as needed to pass this quality assurance test. As mentioned in
Chapter 1 , parts of this framework may have to be reiterated. You may need to se­
lect a different mnemonic if the first one isn't getting you to your goal. Try singing
the words and their definitions. (Sure, your roommate will think you're strange. So
what?) These steps call for careful monitoring of progress, persistence, and flexibil­
ity until you find a strategy that works.
If the goal is to examine your own memories for bias, then you would need to
think about your personal beliefs about the situation or person being recalled, any
information that you may have learned after the event occurred that could influence
your memory, and other biasing factors. You can never know how accurate your
memory is unless there is some external record, like a videotape that was taken at
the time of the to-be-remembered incident. But, you can develop a healthy dose of
humility about the accuracy of your own memories and understand the way in
which the memories, and consequently the thoughts, of others can also be biased.

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Memory was described as the mediator of cognitive processes because all of


our thoughts depend upon the ability to use what we have stored in memory.
2. There are many different varieties of memory, and what and how you learn
and remember will depend on the type of information to-be-remembered, what you
already know, the length of the retention interval, and noncognitive factors like
health and motivation.
3. By engaging in the hard work of effortful learning, you can make whatever is
being learned easier and more automatic, so there is a real payoff in effort for those
who are willing to work at their learning.
4. There are many learning strategies that reflect the fact that all learning is not
the same. Good learners will know what they have to do to learn and remember,
and they will do it.
5. It is important to attend to information that you want to learn and to monitor
how well you are learning.
6. The "illusion of truth" refers to the memory phenomenon in which we forget
the source and sometimes even the content of a message, but when we encounter
the name of a person who was part of the forgotten message, the "feeling of famil­
iarity" is interpreted as "the new message must be true." Of course, this occurs
without conscious awareness, so all we can do is be aware of the possibility that it is
happening and be less willing to believe rumors or innuendos.
7. Our memories are not perfect true "copies" of events that have occurred. Prior
knowledge, subsequent knowledge, stereotypes, and meaningfulness of the mater­
ial all influence what will be remembered. These distortions and biases occur with­
out conscious awareness, so we need to be vigilant for the ways in which personal
beliefs and experiences could be influencing memory.
8. Memory can be improved with appropriate retrieval cues and good organiza­
tion. Generation of to-be-remembered information (with minimal or varied cues)
spaced over time will result in enhanced recall relative to passive or massed rehearsal.
84 2. MEMORY

9. Working memory is the term used for the "place" in which we consciously
think. It has a seriously limited capacity that we can control by deciding which in­
formation to attend to and how much effort a particular task is worth. When learn­
ing is difficult, we need to reduce the load on working memory. This can be done by
writing information on paper, making it more automatic, or attending to the infor­
mation to-be-Iearned.
10. Mnemonics improve recall because they utilize the basic memory principles
of attention, organization, meaningfulness, and chunking. The mnemonics
presented were keywords and images, rhymes, method of places, and first letters.
(Remember: Kind Round Men, Please Listen.)
1 1 . Memory for events can be improved with the cognitive interview technique,
which uses elaboration at recall to improve memory.
12. Although it is difficult to believe, even those memories in which we are very
confident can be completely wrong. This is difficult for most people to accept be­
cause our phenomenological sense is that our own memories are "true."
13. Our memories are biased in predictable ways. Examine your own recall for
the possible influence of biases related to stereotypes, general knowledge, positive
reflections on oneself, or for information characteristics such as being well known,
familiar, prominent, recent, vivid, and/ or dramatic.

TERMS TO KNOW

You should be able to define or describe the following terms and concepts. If you
find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to reread the section in
which it is discussed.

Hypothetical Constructs. Terms like learning, memory, and perception that are used
as labels for the theoretical processes that underlie human thought and behavior.
Thinking. The manipulation or transformation of some internal representation.
Acquisition. Used to describe learning. Also known as encoding, or putting infor­
mation into memory.
Retention Interval. The time interval between the acquisition of new information
(learning) and its retrieval.
Retrieval. The act of recalling or remembering information that had been previ­
ously acquired (learned).
Episodic Memory. Memory for events in which we can remember our own partici­
pation.
Semantic Memory. Memory for facts like word meanings and the multiplication
tables.
Declarative Memory. Knowledge that can be verbalized easily.
Motor Memory. Memory for the performance of motor skills like swimming or rid­
ing a bicycle.
Procedural Memory. Memory for accomplishing some task such as using a slide
rule or operating equipment.
Automatic Memory. Remembering that seems effortless such as the memory for
the frequency of events.
Effortful Memory. Remembering that requires the deliberate and conscious use of
strategies such as memory for a series of dates.
TERMS TO KNOW 85

Intentional Learning. Used to describe learning efforts and activities that are en­
gaged in when a learner is deliberately trying to learn something so that it can be re­
called later.
Incidental Learning. Learning that occurs without any deliberate effort, such as
learning the plot of a television show or the habits of family members.
Implicit Memory. Memory about which we have little conscious knowledge.
Explicit Memory. Memory for information that can be discussed and described.
Compare with implicit memory.
Illusion of Truth. When a message is forgotten and the name of a person (or an
event) that was in the forgotten message is encountered at some time in the future,
this person (or event) feels familiar. People look for reasons why it would feel famil­
iar and decide that the new message must be true. This illusion operates without
conscious awareness.
Cocktail Party Effect. Information that is being attended to will be remembered,
while information that is not being attended to will be forgotten or never learned.
Phenomenon is named for the way people switch their attention among different
simultaneous conversations at large parties.
Advance Organizers. Outlines or other summaries that are used before learning to
assist with the process of acquisition.
Inert Knowledge. Knowledge that isn't recalled when it is needed.
Encoding Specificity. The cues that are available at learning (or encoding) will be
useful if they are also available at retrieval.
Interference Theory of Forgetting. A theory of how we forget that attributes for­
getting to "interference" or displacement of the to-be-remembered items by other
material that has been previously or subsequently learned.
Working Memory. The "place" where knowledge is consciously manipulated
or transformed. Thinking is constrained because working memory has a limited
capacity.
Chunking. A memory process in which a number of related items are stored and
retrieved as a unit in order to facilitate memory.
Metamemory. A person's knowledge about his or her own memory system; for ex­
ample, knowing that you have to repeat a series of digits in order to maintain them
in memory.
Ease of Learning Judgments. Individual estimates of how easy or difficult it will be
to learn a skill or information. This type of judgment is made before the learning
process.
Quality of Learning Judgments. Individual estimates of how well material is being
learned. This type of judgment is made during the learning process.
Feelings of Knowing Judgments. Individual estimates of how well something is
known. This type of judgment is made after the learning process.
Degree of Confidence Judgments. Individual estimates of whether a particular re­
sponse is correct. This type of judgment is made at the time of retrieval.
Mnemonic Devices. Memory aids or techniques that are utilized to improve
memory.
External Memory Aids. The deliberate use of lists, timers, calendars, and similar
devices to remind an individual to do something.
Internal Memory Aids. Mnemonic devices or memory aids that rely on plans or
strategies to make retrieval easier and more likely.
Keywords. A mnemonic device or memory aid in which a previously learned list of
words or rhymes serve as associates or "hooks" for the to-be-remembered items.
86 2. MEMORY

Method of Places. (Also known as method of loci.) A mnemonic device or memory


aid in which a familiar route is selected and the to-be-remembered items are imaged
at intervals along the route. At recall, the individual "mentally traverses" the route
to retrieve the items.
First Letter Mnemonics. A mnemonic device or memory aid in which the first let­
ters of each word to be learned are combined into a single word.
Prospective Memory. Remembering to do something at some time in the future.
Cognitive Interview. A technique for recalling events that uses principles of cogni­
tive psychology to guide the retrieval process.
Encoding Goal. Recognizing that you want to learn something-use the strategies
for promoting learning.
Retrieval Goal. Recognizing that you want to recall something-use the strategies
for improving recall.
Debiasing Goal. A conscious attempt to recognize the ways in which memory can
be biased and engaging in activities that are designed to minimize the bias such as
continuing to search for additional information and reflecting on stereotypes.
3

The Relationship Between


Thought and Language

Contents
Thought and Language Ambiguity, Vagueness, and
Psycholinguistics Equivocation
Underlying Representation and Etymology and Reification
Surface Structure Bureaucratese and Euphemism
Implications and Inference Framing with Leading Questions,
The Role of Inference in Negation, and Marked Words
Advertisements Contrast and Context
Rules for Clear Communication Anchoring
Analogy and Metaphor Barometers of Thought
Using Analogies as an Aid to Comprehension: The Reason for
Understanding Language
U sing Analogies as Problem­ Strategies for Comprehension
Solving Aids Re-representation
Using Analogies to Persuade Questioning and Explaining
Words and Their Meanings Concept Maps
Definitions and the Control of Hierarchies
Thought Networks
The Power of Labels and Categories Matrices
Prototypical Thinking General Guidelines and Principles
Language: Tool or Master of Thought? Applying The Framework
The Direction and Misdirection of Chapter Summary
Thought Terms to Know
Emotional Language and Name
Calling

87
88 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

There is an old story about three umpires that goes something like this:

Three umpires were unwinding at a local pub after a very tough day. All three had en­
dured abusive shouts like, "Kill the Umpire" and had numerous offers for new pairs of eye­
glasses. After a few mugs of brew, they began discussing how they would decide to call balls
and strikes. The first umpire, Jim, explained that it was really quite simple. "I simply call
them as I see them."
Donnie, the second umpire, disagreed when he said, "1 see them as I call them."
Neil, the third umpire emphatically shook his head in disagreement with the other two.
"You're both wrong," he said, slurring his words somewhat. "They don't even exist until
I call them."

Neil had a good point. Whether a ball whizzing past home plate is a ball or strike
depends on what the umpire labels it. The words he uses both interpret and define
reality.

THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

The development of mind, thought, and language is simply a nexus in which it


is impossible to separate one from the other.
-Michael Studdert-Kennedy (quoted in Restak, 1 988, p. 231 )

How d o you express your thoughts i n words and sentences? How influenced are
you by your particular language? You will have difficulty answering these ques­
tions because you use both so automatically and because you have no conscious
awareness of the way your thoughts give rise to the words you use to express them.
In fact, if you try to monitor your speaking process, you'll find yourself stuttering
and interfering with the fluid speech that you normally create so easily. It's as
though speech emerges automatically and preformed. Conscious attention directed
at the process tends to interfere with it.

Psycholinguistics

Communication is primarily an exercise in thinking.


-Pitt and Leavenworth (1968, p. viii)

Psycholinguistics is the field of psychology concerned with how we acquire and use
language. Language is a complex cognitive activity that all normal humans perform
with apparent skill and ease. As speakers, we select the words we want to use and pro­
duce them in a (mostly) grammatically correct form. As listeners, we use the informa­
tion in another's utterance to share the expressed thoughts. What do we know about
the way speakers and listeners share thoughts through the medium of language?

Underlying Representation and Surface Structure

Language appears to be simply the clothing of naked thought.


-Miller (1 972, p. 43)
The comprehension of language is a process in which the message is used to con­
struct a representation of the information referred to in the message (Resnick, 1 985).
THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE 89

The sequence of sounds that we produce must correspond to our intended meaning
if we are to communicate successfully. The "sender" and the "receiver" also must
share a common knowledge of word meanings and grammar. Because language is
always incomplete, the receiver must rely on prior knowledge, context, and other
cues to comprehension to construct a correct representation.
Psychologists who are concerned with the way people use and understand lan­
guage divide language into two structures or types of representations. The underly­
ing representation of language refers to the meaning component of language-it's
the thought you want to convey. Surface structure refers to the sounds of the verbal
expression that you use or its written form on paper, a computer monitor, or some
other writing surface. Look carefully at Fig. 3.1, which depicts this process. As you
can see, the thought in the mind of the "sender" is the underlying or deep structure.
The thought is private and known only to the sender. The problem in producing lan­
guage is deriving surface structure from the underlying representation in the
sender's mind, and the problem in comprehending language is getting from the sur­
face structure back to the speaker's (or writer's) underlying representation. Language
is integral in these processes because it is the medium with which thoughts and emo­
tions are most often expressed and interpreted (although other media such as dance,
mime, and visual arts are sometimes used to express thoughts and emotions).
A communication is "successful" when the underlying representation constructed
by the receiver matches the underlying representation of the sender. The receiver's
representation of the meaning is constructed over time because using language is a
sequential process with words uttered or read one after the other. All strategies for
improving comprehension involve ways of building representations so that they
will most nearly match the one intended by the sender. It is the representation of
knowledge about the world, the "architecture of the cognitive system," that medi­
ates comprehension (Bower & Cirilo, 1985).

The Thought in the Mind


of the Sender
(Deep Structure)
(J)
Cl
(J) Cl as
Cl c :J
as Cl
:J :i: c
Cl as as
c (J) Words, Phrases, ...J
as 0- Cl
...J CI) Sentences to Express c
Cl 0 '6
c c
·0 Cl the Thought (J)
:J -E
.s::.
"C
·c �
e 0-
0.. 3: E
0
Speech Sounds 0

Shapes of Letters on Paper


or Computer Terminal
(Surface Structures)

FIG. 3. I . The problem of comprehension. The sender has a thought that she wants to
communicate to a receiver. The thought (deep structure) is private and known only to the
sender. It is transformed by speech sounds or the shapes of letters (surface structure), which
are used by the receiver to reconstruct the meaning expressed by the sender's words.
90 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

When language is ambiguous, the surface structure can have more than one
meaning or underlying representation. Some examples of ambiguous sentences are:

• Visiting professors can be boring. (This can be interpreted to mean either that it
is boring to visit the offices of professors or that it is boring when professors
visit campus.)
• They are kissing fish. (This can be interpreted to mean either that they are a va­
riety of fish called "kissing fish," or that they are a variety of fish who kiss, or
that at least two people have their mouths in the fish bowl and are engaging in
the somewhat kinky behavior of kissing fish.)
• He cooks carrots and peas in the same pot. (I won't explain the two possible in­
terpretations, but you will need to read this one aloud.)
• Each sentence is ambiguous because there is a single surface structure (the
sound of the sentence) and at least two possible underlying representations or
interpretations. Clear communications are unambiguous. With only a little ef­
fort, an ambiguous statement can be made clear so that it corresponds to only
one underlying representation. For example, the first sentence can be made un­
ambiguous with simple changes:
It is boring to visit professors.
or
Professors who visit campus are boring.

When there is a problem in the communication process, it is often difficult to


know if the problem stems from the sender's thinking, the sender's use of language,
the receiver's use of language, or the receiver's thinking. For example, consider a
conversation that I had with a 5-year-old girl with whom I spent a very long after­
noon. She asked me to buy her a hamburger, which I was glad to do. While standing
in line to order her food, she let me know in a very loud voice that she wanted her
hamburger "with no meat." Obviously puzzled, I thought perhaps she didn't un­
derstand that the brown patty on the roll, the "hamburger," was meat. I patiently
tried to explain this concept to her. Adamantly, and even louder, she screamed that
she wanted her hamburger without meat. Aha, I thought, she must want plain
cheese on a bun-sort of a cheeseburger without the burger. But no, she rejected this
possibility and began a full-scale tantrum at this point. What was the problem? Was
the problem with language-did she not know the meaning of the words "ham­
burger" or "meat"? Was the problem in her thinking, which was illogical? Was I the
problem? Perhaps my background knowledge of what constitutes a hamburger did
not match hers. In other words, did the problem stem from faulty thinking or faulty
use of language, or, possibly both? I never did find out she had wanted. We beat a
hasty exit from the restaurant as the other customers and the servers gave us very
disapproving looks. By the way, I took a regular hamburger with us, which she hap­
pily ate in the car as I drove her home.

Implications and Inference

Communication depends as much on information that is implied as it does on the


words that are explicitly stated. Comprehension of meaningful material will always
require the listener or reader to make inferences by going beyond the words uttered.
THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE 91

Consider this very simple three-sentence story:

Matt inherited a great deal of money.


Bertha loves diamonds and furs.
Bertha married Matt.

Although very little factual information was provided, it is a meaningful story.


Readers infer that Bertha married Matt for his money and that she will use his
money to buy diamonds and furs, although this interpretation may not be correct.
All communication requires the receiver to fill in gaps between given bits of infor­
mation to understand the intended meaning. Much of the meaning people convey
goes beyond the meaning of the words they utter (Dews & Winner, 1999). Has any­
one ever said to you, "You're a big help!" when they mean exactly the opposite?
Sarcasm, as in this example, can only be interpreted by NOT using the words as
spoken to determine their meaning. To know when "You're a big help!" means the
exact opposite, we rely on context and the tone and expression used. The fact that
we often assume a meaning that does not correspond to the definition of the words
used is why psychologists conceptualize the acquisition of knowledge as a process
of construction that is built by integrating new information with what is already
known by both receiver and sender. Many decades ago, Bruner (1957) succinctly de­
fined thinking as "going beyond the information given." Understanding language
by making inferences is a prime example of this definition of thinking.

The Role of Inference in Advertisements

When you produce speech, the intended meaning is implied or suggested by the
words you use, the context in which it is embedded, and verbal and nonverbal ex­
pressions. It is possible to say one thing and to communicate something quite differ­
ent. This technique is often used by advertisers who want to persuade you to buy
their products, yet have legal restrictions on the kinds of statements they can make.
A television commercial for American Express Travelers Cheques goes some­
thing like this:

"Oh, no, we've lost our travelers cheques! What will we do?" (Couple wrings their respec-
tive hands at this point, obviously looking distressed.)
The voice of a distinguished actor comes on, "What kind were they?"
Distressed couple responds, "American Express."
The distinguished actor calmly reassures them, "Good thing you have American Express
Travelers Cheques. You can get a refund at their conveniently located office across the street."
The now-smiling couple walk off the screen to the tune of "Don't leave horne without
them."

Other traveler check companies have complained about this advertisement be­
cause it implies that people who lose other brands of travelers' checks may not get a
refund. Notice that although this is never stated, the advertiser assumes that it is a
reasonable inference from the information offered.
Perhaps you're familiar with a popular advertisement for Listerine, a brand of
mouthwash. An apparently middle-class mother bundles her children in warm
clothing while discussing colds and flu. She earnestly states how much she dislikes
"scratchy sore throats" and "runny noses." To keep her family healthy, she sees that
92 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

they eat right, get plenty of rest and exercise, and "gargle with Listerine." Of course,
she never says that Listerine will prevent or cure colds. This would be a false claim
because there is no evidence that it does. Yet, this information is implied. Studies
with fictitious commercials have shown that viewers do infer from advertisements
like this one that mouthwash will protect against colds (Harris, 1 977).
Carefully selected words in advertisements are used to create an inference that
something is true when it is not. Airlines and other businesses often boast:

"Nobody beats our fares."

They expect that readers will infer that this means that they have the lowest fares.
Of course, they never state that they have the lowest fares because that would be
false. Nobody beats their fares because nearly all of the fares are the same. They
could have said, "Our fares are the same as our competitors." But, if they said it that
way, it would not mislead readers into believing that they have the lowest fares, and
consumers would correctly conclude that it doesn't matter which airline they book
with if cost is the sole determining factor. Always consider the distinction between
the linguistic content of the message and the inference you draw from it.
When you start reading and listening critically to advertisements, you may be
surprised to find appalling attempts to create impressions that can change beliefs. It
is instructive to read the advertisements for supposed weight loss products (e.g.,
cellulite creams, sauna suits, herbal wraps, vitamins, magic formula pills). Even the
ubiquitous "before and after" photos are designed to create the inference that you
will lose "30 or more pounds in two weeks" while eating anything you want and
without "tedious" exercise.
Harris (1977) found that people remember the implied meaning of a message,
and not the actual statements that were made. If you have already read the chapter
on the development of memory skills, this shouldn't be surprising to you. Meaning­
ful information is more easily remembered than nonmeaningful information. We
rarely remember statements verbatim. Thus, our memory of events depends on the
interpretations we give them when they occur.

Rules for Clear Communication

" When I use a word," Humpty Dumpty said, in a rather scornful tone, "it
means just what I choose it to mean-neither more or less. "
"The question is," said Alice, "whether you can make words mean so many
different things. "
"The question is," said Humpty Dumpty, "which is to be master-that's all."
-Lewis Carroll (Through the Looking Glass, 1872, p. 1 90)

To communicate effectively, you need to know a great many things in addition to


the thought being communicated and the words being used as the vehicle for the
communication: What is the purpose of the communication? What are your lis­
tener's characteristics-what is your listener's age and social status? How much
does the listener know or want to know about the topic? The answers to all of these
questions shape the nature of communications. We implicitly change the way we
speak or write, depending on how we answer these questions, and we make these
changes without realizing the extent to which the listener shapes our use of
THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE 93

language. Communication is governed by rules that we all obey, although you may
never have consciously considered them.

Rule I : Tell listeners what you believe


they want to know
Consider how you would answer a simple question like, "Where do you live?" If
I met you in Europe and asked you this question, you would probably respond, "in
the United States." If I asked you this question in New York, you would respond
with the name of a state, "in Pennsylvania." If I asked you the same question on
your college campus, you might respond, "in the dorms." If I asked you this ques­
tion while we were in the dorms, you might respond, "in Wing D, Room 331 ." And,
if I asked you this question in your dorm room, you would probably reply by giving
the name of your hometown. The same question could be asked each time, yet you
would give a different answer that depended on the context in which the question is
asked and what you thought I wanted to know. The level of information you choose
to convey depends on the purpose of the communication.

Rule 2 : Don't tell listeners what they already know


In Chapter I, I began by introducing the topic of thinking and the need for the de­
velopment of critical thinking skills. You probably did not think that this was un­
usual. Suppose I started every chapter in this book the same way. You would not
only think that this was unusual, you may also question my mental status.
When you present information to an audience, you balance the amount of new
information that you present with the old or already known information. If you pre­
sent too much new information at once, listeners will be lost and will not be able to
extract the intended meaning; if you present too much old or known information,
listeners will be bored. The relative proportion of old information to new informa­
tion is known as the given/new distinction (Clark & Haviland, 1977).
The ratio of given or known information to new information is a determinant
of the difficulty of a communication. If a passage (spoken or written) contains too
much new material for a listener or reader, it will be difficult to comprehend. No
one would take an advanced course in biochemistry without first obtaining the req­
uisite background in biology and chemistry. The educational process, if successful,
fosters the transformation of new information into the students' systems of known
information.

Rule 3: Vary the style of your communication,


depending upon the knowledge, age, and status
of the listeners
Suppose you are an expert computer programmer given the task of describing
the operations of a computer center to a group of visitors. You would vary the way
you convey the necessary information for each of the following: a group of politi­
cians; a group of children from an elementary school; your history professor; a close
friend; or an expert programmer from another university.
Your communication would be more or less technical depending on what you be­
lieve your listener knows about the topic. You might tell the politicians about the
high costs of maintaining a computer center; the elementary school children might
94 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

simply be told about the general use of computers; you might explain to your his­
tory professor how computers can be used in research; your close friend might be
told that you feel you're being underpaid; and the visiting programmer might be
told about the capacity of the computers and the steps you've taken to prevent the
spread of computer viruses.
The readability of text or ease with which spoken language is understood de­
pends, in large part, on the match between the text and the reader. The reason so
many of us find income tax and legal documents so difficult is that they are written
by and for accountants and lawyers-people with highly differentiated underlying
representations of the topics referred to in these documents. The rest of us have to
make many more inferences and more memory searches to understand the concepts
because our underlying representations of these concepts are relatively sparse. This
is why whenever we're engaged in communication; it is important to consider the
characteristics of the reader or listener. This is a more formal way of saying that the
beliefs, knowledge, and expectations of the intended audience for a communication
should determine how much detail goes into a communication and which words are
used. The difficulty of a text does not reside in the text itself, but in the reader-text
interaction.
The idea that what people understand depends on what they already know was
beautifully made in a book aptly titled, "How People Learn" (Bransford, Brown, &
Cocking, 1 999). They tell about a fish who gets to learn about the world above the
sea as it is explained to him by a friendly bird. When the bird tells of humans who
walk upright, we see the fish's mental image of walking fish. The story goes on
to show how each description of the dry world would be interpreted by a learner
who only knew of the water world. No matter how accurate the description, the
fish's understanding was limited strictly by his own life experiences and knowledge
of the world.

Rule 4: Tell the truth


When we communicate with each other, it is assumed that the information being
conveyed is truthful. This is an imperative for meaningful communication. Of
course, sometimes people lie. How do you process information when you believe
that the speaker is lying? All components of the communication are scrutinized. In
general, the communication process breaks down when the listener suspects that
the speaker is violating this rule. This loss of communication is eloquently described
by Chang (1 993) in her description of life during Mao's reign over communist
China, a time when no one dared to speak the truth: "The whole nation slid into
doublespeak. Words became divorced from reality, responsibility, and people's real
thoughts. Lies were told with ease because words had lost their meaning" (p. 298).

Rule 5: Use a simple straightforward style


Mark Twain said this best when he said, "Eschew surplusage." Information is
transmitted best when simple and precise language is used. Some people think that
use of multisyllabic words and intricate sentence structures is a sign of intelligence.
This is not true. It is a far more difficult task to express complex thoughts in simple
language than to express simple thoughts in complex language. The transformation of
our private thoughts into easily understood language is the benchmark of human cog­
nition. Sloppy thinking can never be made good even with the most flowery language.
THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE 95

Rule 6: Use manner and context to clarify meaning


Meaning depends not only on the words that we use, but also on the context and
the manner we use to convey it. Have you ever had the experience of having some­
one say, "I'll be happy to do that for you" in a manner that clearly showed that she
was most unhappy?
Context is a critical aid for comprehension. "The food is on the table" can be an
invitation to eat or a simple descriptive statement, depending on the context. Con­
text is also used to decide which of two possible meanings is the intended meaning
for ambiguous sentences. The intended meaning of "They are kissing fish" is usu­
ally straightforward when spoken in context. One way that context directs compre­
hension is by influencing the way we process incoming language.
Ekman (1992) speaks of "lying truthfully," that is, literally telling the truth while
leaving the listener with the opposite impression. For example, he tells about a man
who had been unfaithful to his wife for years without getting caught! He had, on
several occasions, taken money from her purse to buy flowers for other women.
Each time he did this, she noticed the missing money and innocently commented to
him: "I could have sworn I had an extra $50 in my purse; I must have lost it." Fi­
nally, one day she suspects that her partner has been unfaithful to her because she
finds matches from a local hotel in his coat when she takes it to the cleaners. When
she confronts him about this, he "honestly lies," by retorting: "Right. I've been hav­
ing a torrid affair during my lunch breaks; and do you remember those times you
thought you had lost money? Well, you didn't. I've been stealing your money to
buy my noon-time lovers gifts. And, let me see, what other ignominities have I omit­
ted?" This man just made a complete confession, yet the intent was to mislead his
wife by casting it in irony. Intonation matters!
Figure 3.2 is a visual demonstration of the context effect. You'll find that you have
no difficulty reading any of the words in Fig. 3.2. Now look carefully at the letters
that make up the words. The "H" in "the" is the same form as the "A" in "cat," yet
you may not have noticed this unless I pointed it out to you. Similarly, the way we
perceive the other "inky" letters depends on the rest of the letters that make up the

TAE CAT
F\�8
S f10T
�I SH
DE8T
FIG. 3 . 2 . Examples of the ways context influences meaning.
Notice, for example, that the "D" in "RED" is identical to the "B" in "DEBT." (Adapted from
Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., and the PDP Research Group. (1986). Parallel distributed
processing. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, p. 8.)
96 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

word context. Context provides strong cues that guide the way we construct knowl­
edge about the nature of the world.

Analogy and Metaphor

Midway between the unintelligible and the commonplace, it is metaphor which


most produces knowledge.
-Aristotle (Rhetoric III, 1410b)

One exception to the rule that the words used to convey a message should corre­
spond to their intended meaning is the use of analogy and metaphor. (The English
grammatical distinction among analogy, metaphor, and simile is not being consid­
ered here because it is irrelevant in this context.) If I tell you that "Myrtle is a hard­
headed woman," the literal translation is not the one intended. In this case, the
receiver must use his knowledge about the referent topic (hard surfaces) and "map"
the relevant knowledge onto his knowledge of Myrtle. Although you certainly have
never met Myrtle, and you may never have heard the expression "a hard-headed
woman," you can probably tell me that she is a stubborn, strong-willed person. You
came to this understanding by taking your knowledge of hard surfaces, selecting
characteristics of hard surfaces that might be relevant to a description of a person,
and transferring that knowledge to what you already know about Myrtle.

Using Analogies as an Aid to Understanding


Analogies are pervasive in human thought. Whenever we are faced with a novel
situation, we seek to understand it by reference to a known familiar one. When we
think by analogy, we map the underlying structure of a known topic onto the target
or unknown topic. This mental process is known as "structure mapping" (Halpern,
Hansen, & Riefer, 1 990; Gentner & Gentner, 1983). Structure mapping assumes
network-like representations of concepts in memory in which underlying structural
relationships and surface attributes (physical characteristics) are coded along with
each concept. For example, when we read that an atom is like a miniature solar sys­
tem, the implication is that the solar system and the atom have similar relationships
among their component parts-smaller bodies revolving around a larger one in
fixed path patterns. Other aspects, such as surface similarity (e.g., the sun is hot and
large and contains burning gases) is not implied. Analogies can be a useful tool
in the comprehension and recall of scientific passages (Halpern, 1987; Halpern,
Hansen, & Riefer, 1990). When students read technical passages that contained ap­
propriate analogies to familiar topics, they scored higher on tests of comprehension
and recall than a control group of students who read the same passage without the
analogy.
All analogies and metaphors state that two concepts are alike in some way. Good
analogies have similar underlying structures even when the topics are highly dis­
similar. They maintain much of their underlying structure in the transfer from base
(known) to target (unknown) domains while surface features are of minimal impor­
tance. Poor analogies are ones in which only surface or superficial characteristics are
similar. If I said that Myrtle is like milk because they both start with the letter m,
I would be using a very poor analogy. Whenever you encounter an analogy, you
need to consider the nature of the similarity relationship. Are the two concepts simi­
lar in their underlying structure so that relevant information about one concept can
THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE 97

be used to understand the other concept, or is the similarity trivial? The paradox in
thinking with analogies is that the best analogies usually differ in their surface fea­
tures. Blasko (1999) described analogical thinking as the "interaction of two dissimi­
lar concepts" (p. 1676).

Using Analogies as Problem-Solving Aids


What do you do when you are faced with a problem that has no obvious solution?
I address this question in more detail in Chapter 9 on problem solving, but one strat­
egy that is appropriate to consider here is the use of a solution that is borrowed from
a problem with a similar structure, often from a very different domain of knowledge.
The conditions under which people do and don't recognize and use analogous solu­
tions for problems from very distant domains of knowledge has been the subject
of much research (e.g., Vosniadou & Orotony, 1989). In order for this strategy to
"work," the problem solver must recognize that the essential characteristics of the
two problems are similar, despite the fact that the topics may be very different.
Consider, for example, the problem of bonding (gluing) two surfaces during den­
tal surgery. All bonding substances require a dry surface for bonding, and the
mouth is a wet environment. How can this problem be solved? The use of the small
towels or "teeth driers" do not work well during oral surgery, which can involve
profusive bleeding and the production of much saliva. Some creative dental sur­
geon looked for similar problems in other domains. He or she (I don't know the
identity of this unsung critical thinker) studied the way barnacles attach themselves
to piers and other surfaces in the ocean. The adaptive barnacle displaces the water
(sort of moves it aside) from the small area to which it is attaching. This displace­
ment of fluids has been modified for use in dentistry. If you're like most people, you
will agree that any discovery that makes dental surgery quicker and more success­
ful is a welcome advance. In this example, the problem solver considered the simi­
larities in the two problems of bonding in wet environments and then adapted a
solution from one domain (barnacles in the ocean) to a very different one (dental
bonding). In this way, an analogy was used to solve a problem.
When cognitive psychologists study the use of analogies to solve problems, they
are usually disappointed to find that most of the analogies are only superficially
similar to the problem people are given to work on (Tweney & Chitwood, 1995).
Laboratory studies of the use of analogies to solve problems are not encouraging.
Recently, Dunbar (2001) investigated the use of analogies in real-life settings where
experts in a field solve real problems, not the artificial ones that cognitive psycholo­
gists create. He found very different results. Real experts involved in solving prob­
lems that are important to them use analogies that share "deep structural features"
(p. 126). Scientists generate anywhere from between 3 to 15 analogies in a one-hour
laboratory meeting, with the majority coming from the domain in which they are
working. Dunbar concluded that analogies focusing on relational features are fre­
quently used to help solve problems.

Using Analogies to Persuade


In the popular movie, Dead Poets Society, the unlikely hero, Robin Williams, who
plays a high school teacher of English, asks his class of young men, "What is the
purpose of language?" After a short period of silence, a student yells out the obvi­
ous answer, "to communicate." Of course, this is not the correct answer in the
98 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

movie. The hero-English-teacher-character responds that the purpose of language is


to "woo women." An important point is made in this fictional exchange between
student and teacher. The purpose of language is to persuade-to change how and
what people think. We use language to persuade others to like or date us (as ex­
pressed in this movie), to alter or maintain political beliefs (e.g., capitalism is good),
or to convince someone to make a purchase (e.g., a particular brand of jeans).
We frequently use analogies to persuade someone that X is analogous to Y, there­
fore what is true for X is also true for Y. A good example of this sort of "reasoning by
analogy" was presented by Bransford, Arbitman-Smith, Stein, and Vye (1985). They
described a legal trial in the book, Till Death Us Do Part (Bugliosi, 1978). Much of the
evidence presented at the trial was circumstantial. The attorney for the defense ar­
gued that the evidence was like a chain, and like a chain, it was only as strong as its
weakest link. He went on to argue that there were several weak links in the evidence;
therefore, the jurors should not convict the accused. The prosecutor also used an
analogy to make his point. He argued that the evidence was like a rope made of
many independent strands. Several strands can be weak and break, and you will still
have a strong rope. Similarly, even though some of the evidence was weak, there was
still enough strong evidence to convict the accused. (The prosecutor won the case.)
Can you see how the use of analogies can guide how we think? In the trial exam­
ple, different sorts of outcomes depend on which of the analogies you found more
compelling. Let's consider another example. At a meeting of county administrators,
several people who were receiving welfare argued that there should be welfare re­
cipients on the county board. They argued that welfare recipients were in the best
position to understand the problems of life on welfare and therefore should be part
of the group that makes decisions about welfare. One of the board members said
that was an absurd proposition. He argued that having welfare recipients on the
county board was like putting residents of an "insane asylum" on the committee
that makes the rules for the asylum. What do you think of this analogy? In what
ways are people on welfare like the residents of an insane asylum? How are they
different? Are they different in ways that makes the board member's conclusions in­
valid? The insane are unable to think rationally, by definition. This is not true for the
poor. I don't believe that this was a good analogy and would not have been per­
suaded by it. (In fact, I find it insulting.)
Several different sorts of analogies were used in an attempt to persuade the judge
and the public during an antitrust lawsuit against Microsoft (Time, 1998, June 1 ) . Bill
Gates, who argued that it was not a monopoly to bundle only Microsoft products
(e.g., Internet Explorer and not Netscape) with its Windows Operating System,
made this analogy-"Forcing Microsoft to include Netscape's competing software
in our operating system is like requiring Coca-Cola to include three cans of Pepsi in
every six-pack it sells" (p. 25). The response from Time magazine to this analogy
was, " . . . . Coke doesn't control the system that distributes all drinks" (p. 25). Analo­
gies flowed from both sides of the case. Roberta A. Katz, lawyer for Netscape re­
sponded, "It's as if one of the networks was also producing the inner workings of
the TV set, and every TV was wired so that network was the one you saw" (p. 25).
Time responded to these anti-Microsoft analogies as well, ". . . at least the Windows
user can stick the Microsoft browser in the trash and download Netscape" (p. 25) .
One thing i s clear: Both sides o f this heated, high stakes case believed that they
could alter the outcome of the case by the use of judicious analogies that would
make their point. In case you are wondering about the outcome of this contentious
THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE 99

court case, Microsoft was ordered to break into at least two main divisions. As I am
writing this, the case is wending its way through a maze of appeals. (Additional
analogies from this court case are presented in Thinking Critically About Critical
Thinking, the workbook that accompanies this text.)
Some analogies are just plain bad-sometimes hilariously funny. I have an unat­
tributed e-mail that claims to contain the winners of a high school contest for the
"worst analogy." I don't know if there ever was such a contest, or if these are win­
ning entries, but they are certainly worthy of that dubious honor. Here are two at­
tributed to "unknown": "Her vocabulary was as bad as, like, whatever" and "The
red brick wall was the color of a brick-red Crayola crayon."
Here is another bad analogy taken from a magazine advertisement: The adver­
tisement states that "new research" suggests that we have two brains-the one in
our head and a second one, "which can override" the one in our head. The second
one is our intestines. I hope your initial response to this analogy is to ask questions
like, "What recent research? Who did it? Where was it published?" The picture in
the ad shows the convoluted outer portion of a brain and intestines drawn to sort of
look like the brain. The analogy continues to point out that both have nerve cells (so
do sea slugs-is this a critical similarity?). Like the brain in your head, your in­
testines "is wise"; therefore, you should buy (you knew the ad was to convince you
to buy something) healthy bacteria. Whenever you see an attempt to persuade you
to buy something or to think a certain way based on analogy, consider the nature of
the analogy. Is the analogy sound? How does that analogy relate to its purpose?
Even if the "healthy bacteria" are a good idea to purchase and consume, how do
they relate to the brain analogy? Just because it is possible to draw the intestines in a
way that "looks like" a brain does not mean that they are similar in ways that
should be selling the advertised product.
Analogies are used to sell more than "healthy bacteria" for a "brain-like
intestines./I They are used to sell political candidates and even wars. The 1 991 Per­
sian Gulf Crisis offers numerous examples. Was the situation (from the perspective
of the United States) like the beginning stages of World War II with Hussein emerg­
ing as Hitler (as the hawks would have us believe) or was it like the beginning
stages of Vietnam trapping us into an unpopular and protracted war (as the doves
would have us believe; Gentner & Holyoak, 1997; Spellman & Holyoak, 1992)? ''It
would not be an exaggeration to say that the United States went to war over an anal­
ogy" (Spellman & Holyoak, 1992, p. 913). These competing analogies were used to
persuade the general public about the best response for the situation.
As a final example of the power of analogies to persuade, consider the following
speech by Bishop Desmond Tutu ( 1 986), an eloquent leader in the political move­
ment that ended apartheid in South Africa:

Sometimes you get the notion that people try to inject into your heart that what you do
is insignificant; it cannot make a difference. Let me disabuse you of that notion. When
people see a colossal problem, they wonder whether they could do anything that makes
a difference. They need to keep remembering what they are told about how you eat an
elephant-one piece at a time. (p. 216)

Analogies are useful thinking strategies in many different contexts. The deliber­
ate use of analogies as an aid to solving problems and enhancing creativity is dis­
cussed in greater detail in later chapters.
1 00 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

WORDS AND THEIR MEANINGS

Eight years after resigning as president, Richard Nixon denied lying but
acknowledged that he, like other politicians, had dissembled.
-Paul Ekman (1992, p. 25)

Is alcoholism an illness or is it the lack of willpower by weak people who could stop
drinking if they really wanted to? Is drunkenness a crime that requires punishment
or a mental health condition that needs treatment? I have frequently been asked
questions like these, especially by students who are worried about or disgusted with
a loved one who has a drinking problem. There are many important aspects to this
question. First, the answer to the question of whether alcoholism is an illness de­
pends on how the term "illness" is defined, and more importantly, who gets to do
the defining. Second, it is possible that alcoholism would fit a definition of illness
and be controllable by the individual. The way this question is posed reveals many
unstated assumptions by the person asking the question regarding the nature of
illness and alcoholism. The ramifications of the way we classify alcoholism are im­
portant. If we decide that it is a disease, then it is destigmatized and treatment
would be paid for medical insurance plans. If it is a criminal offense, then alcoholics
can expect to "do" jail time, or at least fall under the criminal justice system. Medical
insurance does not cover crimes. The answer to this vexing question has varied over
different geographical locations and throughout history.
Words often have both cognitive and emotional meanings. If I name my brand of
cookies, "Mother's Cookies," then presumably I am activating some of the emo­
tional attachment you feel toward your mother when you think about my cookies.
Furthermore, if I believe that most people will have positive emotions toward their
own mothers (at least when mentioned in the context of cookies), then "Mother's
Cookies" would be a good name for my cookies. Of course, you probably know that
most store-bought cookies are baked in huge factories by people who may or may
not be mothers. I suppose most people like to think that a mother-like figure or per­
haps a group of playful elves are baking something tasty for them. The popularity of
these marketing strategies suggests that it is good business to arouse positive emo­
tional reactions toward a product.
Here are some new corporate names, which have no cognitive meaning, but sug­
gest positive emotions. According to Juge (2000, March 9), here is the suggested
meaning of some of the nearly 3000 American companies who changed names in
2000:

• Verizon "Are they trying to court fans of the band Vertical Horizon (whose
name itself is an oxymoron)-maybe to show that with Verizon, anything is
possible?" (p. B4)
• Cingular "evokes singular, a sign of the company's attempt to sell itself as
promoters of individuality. Cingular is about you and your individual needs
and the celebration of your own self expression." (p. B4)
• Accenture "plays on the belief that parts of the word mean something." (p. B4)

Like all marketing, these names were devised to sell an identity, in this case with
made-up words. It's funny that the name designed to make you think about your in­
dividuality (Cingular) is really asking you to be one of their 19 million clients! (Juge,
2000, March 9).
WORDS AND THEIR MEANINGS 101

Definitions and the Control of Thought

An amazing event occurred in 1973-millions of mentally ill people were suddenly


cured! Well, not exactly suddenly cured. What happened in 1973 was that the
American Psychiatric Association removed "homosexuality" from its list of official
mental disorders, with the result that the millions of homosexuals were no longer
considered by the psychiatric establishment as mentally ill. The American Psychi­
atric Association maintains the powerful position of deciding which categories of
human behavior and emotion should be defined as mental illnesses. This is an
immense power because the human behaviors and emotions that are listed in the of­
ficial "handbook" of mental disorders, the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (Amer­
ican Psychiatric Association, 1994), determine whether an individual will receive
medical funding for treatment, whether a judge will decide to commit an individual
to a mental facility or to a prison, and whether people label themselves and others
as "normal."
For most of everyday transactions, definitions do not pose a problem. We do not
normally have to decide what is meant by terms like desk, book, house, etc., unless the
particular desk, book, or house is so unusual that there might be doubt about how
well it fits our notions of what these terms mean. Of course, we cannot define every
term that we use-this would be a tedious and pointless exercise. However, the
problem of definition can be critical when words are used as a means of persuasion.
Consider the disastrous situation that occurred when Americans were held
against their will in Iran during Jimmy Carter's term (1976-1980) as president of the
United States. At first, the Americans were described as detainees, but the term
quickly changed to interees. Soon, the Americans were being referred to as prisoners
and then hostages. Each time, the word used to describe their status escalated in its
emotional impact. The label detainees suggests that there is nothing to worry about;
hostage is a "fighting term" that will cost lives and means armed conflict is likely.
Americans can be convinced that military action is need to free hostages, but people
are unlikely to be willing to kill or die for detainees. It is of little value to try to decide
which of these terms is the most correct; more importantly, who gets to decide
which term is used?
This is an important point because the words used to describe a situation become
more warlike as a prelude to armed conflict. For example, in 1985, Philadelphia po­
lice dropped a bomb on the home and headquarters of a black militant group called
"MOVE." It destroyed two city blocks and left over 200 people homeless. How
could this happen? According to Wagner-Pacifici, a professor at Swarthmore Col­
lege, as the confrontation heated up, the words used to describe this group changed
from more neutral terms like "zealots" to more inflammatory terms like "terrorists."
The language used to frame the problem was a major factor in the action taken by
the police. She concluded that, "If you end up talking about an action you're going
to take against a group in military terms, you begin to think and operate as if you
are in a war" (quoted in The Chronicle of Higher Education, April 20, 1994, p. A8).
Let's take a simple concept, like death. When is a person dead? It is now possible
to maintain an individual on machines that breathe for her and tubes that carry nu­
trients into the body and wastes out. Is such an individual dead? How do you
know? We think very differently about an individual who is dead than one who is
not. We bury the dead and not the living, but how can we know what to do if we
cannot decide whether an individual is living or dead? New technologies and med­
ical advances have made even simple concepts like death more complex.
1 02 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

Terms that are heavily laden with emotional impact often elicit strong images. If
you have already read Chapter 2 on memory, then you recall (I hope) that imagery
helps to maintain a concept in memory, a factor that is related to its ability to elicit
strong emotions. This fact is well known by propagandists who want to convince
the masses to act in extreme ways. In Mein Kampf, Adolph Hitler used expressions
like "racial brew," "purity of the blood," "poisoning of the blood," and "bastardiza­
tion" in his successful attempt to convince millions of people to participate in the
killing of millions of other people who differed from them in their religious beliefs.
Hitler even offered the "final solution," which means that he found a way to solve a
problem: His solution was to massacre an entire religious group. Hitler and his com­
patriots also used actual visual images to reinforce these emotions. Pictures of Jews
were alternated with revolting pictures of sewer rats and roaches crawling over filth
so that the images of Jewish faces and the vermin would become associated in peo­
ple's minds. It is interesting to note that the Nazis studied American advertising in
the 1920s to develop their persuasive techniques. If you are thinking that no contem­
porary person would fall prey to such blatant tactics designed to increase racism,
you have not read the papers lately.
Stop now and consider the way in which you would define the term crime, if you
had the power to write the definitions.
(Did you really stop and try to define what you think the word crime should
mean?) Don't go on until you try this simple exercise.
According to Peck, there was a famous inmate in a federal jail, a gangster named
Louis Lepke. In the cell next to his was a young conscientious objector from Iowa,
named Lowell Naeve. Mr. Naeve tried to explain what a conscientious objector was to
Mr. Lepke. Lepke replied incredulously, "You mean they put you in here for not
killing?" (quoted in Peck, 1986, p. 146). Lepke then laughed and laughed. Did your de­
finition of crime include the crime of refusing to go to war? Is Mr. Naeve a criminal?
Definitions are not static "truths." Meanings change over time as a function of
technological development, changing social mores, and a drift in the way words are
used. However, it is not true that a word can mean anything that anyone wants it to.
There is an advertisement in a large city newspaper for a plastic surgeon who "spe­
cializes in nose reduction, breast enlargement and reduction, liposuction, baggy
eyes, weak chins, face lifts, and saddlebag thighs." Putting aside the obnoxious idea
that every body part needs "fixing," this surgeon claims to be able to do it all. How
then, can he claim to be a "specialist"? The word is being misused to convey the idea
that he has great depth of knowledge and experience in all aspects of plastic
surgery. If he can perform many types of plastic surgery, he is a generalist. By defin­
ition, he can't specialize in everything.
Similarly, I bristle at offers for "free gifts with purchase." This is a marketing
scheme based on the idea that we all love gifts and bargains. A gift is free, or it is not
a gift. Consider the great deal that I saw advertised for soap.

Buy three bars, get one free.

The cost of the four bars of soap was $2.00. How does this differ from buying
soap at its regular price of $.50 a bar? Do I really believe that the soap manufacturer
has a "gift" for me? It is not "free" nor is it a "gift," if I have to pay money to receive
it. Every brand of vitamins in the store near my home offers 30 "free" vitamins with
the purchase of a bottle of 100 vitamins. (The free vitamins are packaged separately
in a small bottle, thus adding to production costs and increasing waste and the cost
WORDS AND THEIR MEANINGS 1 03

of the vitamins.) Wouldn't it be more honest to state instead that the price shown is
the cost for 1 30 vitamins? I promise to buy such a brand, if I ever find one that is
honest in advertising its cost. Also, if I ever meet up with the advertising giant who
devised this particular scheme to separate consumers from their money, I will have
a "free gift" for her or him.

The Power of Labels and Categories

As I sat with friends drinking coffee at my kitchen table, someone yelled, "Kill it, kill
it," as a very large bug darted across the floor. "Yuk, it's a cockroach." But on
further inspection, we found that it was not a cockroach, but a "cute little cricket."
A friend scooped up the cricket in a paper cup and gently released it outdoors,
while my daughter ran after it trying to feed it lettuce and grass. Why was it dis­
gusting and in need of immediate extermination when we believed it to be one type
of bug-a cockroach-and cute and in need of saving when it turned out to be
another-a cricket?
The process of categorization is essential in understanding the world and guiding
our responses. When we see a bug, or a baby, or an old person, or a professor, we
use our knowledge about the categories to which they belong to make inferences
about how they are likely to act. We know that a baby will share some essential fea­
tures with all babies. It will sometimes cry for reasons that we cannot understand; it
will need to have its diaper changed; it will slobber and coo. Of course, every baby
is unique, but, fortunately, we can use our knowledge of category membership to
know something about every baby. This is fortunate because it reduces the load on
memory and allows us to understand and predict what will happen when interact­
ing with any baby. The process of categorization is an example of cognitive econ­
omy, which means that it is a process that reduces the mental workload and makes
thinking less effortful. Instead of having to learn a set of new expectations for every
stimulus with which we come in contact, we can use category membership to re­
duce the uncertainty in the situation.
Although categories are necessary in dealing with the large variety of objects in the
world, they also can be the cause of serious errors. Not all members of a category are
the same, and often a stimulus is miscategorized. Stereotypes result from several cog­
nitive and noncognitive processes, but one clear reason that they persist is due to the
effect of categorical thinking. Think about a racial or religious group that is different
from your own. Describe the members of that group. You will find that general terms
emerge that clearly do not apply to all group members, and may not even apply to any
group members. When you think about members of your own race or religion, you
will tend think of them as much more individualized than members of other groups.
As long as we classify individuals into racial and religious groups and label the mem­
bers of these groups with certain attributes, stereotypical beliefs will be maintained.
Every year U.s. park rangers report that someone is seriously mauled by a bear in
one or more of our national parks. Often, the injured person was trying to feed or
even hug a large, wild bear. Why? Because many Americans have categorized bears
along with dogs as friendly animals with which we can play. After all, the only
bears that most of us know personally are Yogi Bear (a lovable and dim-witted car­
toon character), Smokey the Bear (the spokesbear for fire prevention, also a cartoon
character), teddy bears (popular stuffed animals), and possibly the highly trained,
human-like bears that we see riding bicycles and playing ball in zoo and circus acts.
1 04 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

l'� � \llc..1'\N>. of \�Rt-I\\NOux;,.'(. . .


W\.\�i I Cb..LL � "t«JM&.Nlfl-R,( L���
Or j\')\)GN\1C.1'li" I� v-Jl-\�i' \� c.oL)RTb
CP>..LL '&Rt>.NO L�RC.�N,{·

'"


�t«>,,-�.NI;1 <'\!iIf. EI'I � _ �. "tNNoJ .

Non Sequitur © Wiley Miller. Dist. By UNIVERSAL PRESS SYNDICATE. Reprinted with
permission. All rights reserved.

These artificial situations lead many people to miscategorize bears as cuddly ani­
mals instead of dangerous ones.
Similarly, people decide what is natural or right based on their categorical
systems. In Western countries, dead cows and chickens are acceptable foods. The
Vietnamese traditionally consider dogs and monkeys to be food, yet many Western­
ers cringe at this "unnatural" food choice. Many Japanese find raw seafood to be a
delicacy, and the French often enjoy eating snails and frog's legs. (I have often won­
dered what happens to frog arms. Yes, this is a feeble attempt at a joke. Do I get
points for just trying?) In times of severe famine, people have been known to eat old
shoes, the bark of trees, and even other humans. The point of this stomach-turning
paragraph is that what seems to be a natural category, like what is a food, often
turns out to be culturally bound and arbitrary, when it is inspected more closely. We
use the same processes of categorical thinking when we determine which behaviors
are natural for women and men and other groups, such as old people and the dis­
abled, based on experiences in our own culture. Most of us are completely unaware
of the extent to which culture influences our thinking by creating categories and de­
termining what belongs in each category.

Prototypical Thinking

At the local baseball game, the final score was 8-9, yet no man on either team
ever crossed home plate.
How is this possible?
WORDS AND THEIR MEANINGS 1 05

You should be able to solve this riddle fairly easily because it has the same structure
and answer as a riddle that I posed in Chapter 1 . I repeat it here to make a point. We
tend to think in terms of prototypes or best examples of a category. Not surprisingly
this is called prototypical thinking. Give up? The game was played in an all-women
league. For those of you who could not solve this problem, it is probably because
you automatically think of males when you think of baseball players, just as in the
first chapter, many people did not think of a woman when the physician was de­
scribed as a neurosurgeon. Even if you had heard the neurosurgeon puzzle before,
did you recognize that the same principle was affecting your thinking when I
changed the riddle so that it pertained to baseball players? Of course, you know that
women play baseball, but this does not readily lJcome to mind."
Although I have never met you, I already know a great deal about what and how
you think. Let me demonstrate this with an exercise devised by Decyk (994). For
each of the following categories, give a good example. In fact, give the first example
that comes to mind:

1. A bird
2. A color
3. A triangle (a picture is okay)
4. A motor vehicle
5. A sentence
6. A hero
7. A heroic action
8. A game
9. A philosopher
1 0. A writer

Are you finished? Here is a list of your most likely answers: (1) for a bird you
probably named robin or sparrow, or possibly eagle; (2) for a color you most likely
said red or blue; (3) for your triangle you either drew or named an equilateral trian­
gle; (4) for a motor vehicle you probably listed a car; (5) for an example of a sentence
you probably wrote a short declarative sentence (e.g., The girl ran home.); (6) the
hero you named is most likely one of the following males-Superman, Batman, or
possibly a fireman; (7) the heroic action you named probably involved a single act by
a male such as a rescue by a fireman; (8) most likely you listed Monopoly as an exam­
ple of a game, or some other board game; (9) for a philosopher you probably named
Socrates or Aristotle; (0) and finally, for a writer you probably named Stephen King,
but if you named someone else, it is very probably a white male author.
What is the point of this demonstration? People tend to think in terms of proto­
types or "best examples" of a category. Our prototypes vary from culture to culture,
but they are relatively standard within a culture. If you live in Australia, you might
name a "kiwi" as an example of a bird, a response that would be very unusual for
Americans or Chinese. Thinking in terms of prototypes biases how and what we
think. When we think about members of a category, only the most typical exemplars
(examples of a category) readily come to mind. Consider the implications of the
finding that most people name only living white males as an example of a writer. It
means that we carry a standardized lJpicture" or "definition" of those characteristics
that writers share and these characteristics are restricted with regard to time, race,
and sex. Of course, different answers would be expected from people from countries
other than the United States or, possibly, other cultural groups within the same
1 06 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

country. Most Russians would probably name Puskin, or less probably, Tolstoy or
Chekhov, if they were asked to give an example of a writer. But, regardless of what
the particular prototype is, the reliance on the most typical member of a category
limits thinking. Few people will name an older person or a child or a dog when
asked to think of a hero, yet old people and children and even dogs (e.g., Lassie) can
and do perform heroic acts. The most commonly named philosophers are dead,
Greek males. With prototypes like this, few people will "think of" philosophy as a
popular, contemporary profession that is open to all ages and races.
If you maintain a conscious awareness of the way prototypes restrict thinking, it
is possible to reduce their effect (Oecyk, 1994). Practice giving unusual answers to
the category questions asked above. With a little thought, you can think of ways to
subdivide the categories and expand the possibilities that you develop. For example,
Monopoly is a board game. Name some other types of games (e.g., ball games, card
games, jacks). Think about games played alone (e.g., solitaire) and games played
with others (e.g., hangman). What about games from other countries, games from
other times in history, and games played by children (e.g., pat-a-cake and peek-a­
boo)? With very little effort, you can generate a wide variety of games that differ
from your prototype. The deliberate use of giving unusual examples of categories is
one way of making a wider array of information that is stored in memory more ac­
cessible, so that you can use the knowledge that you already have acquired when
you need it.

LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT?

Learn a new language and get a new soul.


-Czech proverb

We use language not only to convey our thoughts, but also to mold and shape them.
Language and thought are inextricably related concepts that exert mutual influences
on each other. Some psychologists believe that language, at least in part, influences
thought. Examples of this concept were presented earlier in this chapter in the section
on labeling and the way labels affect how we think. The hypothesis that the language
we use affects how we think is called the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis of linguistic rela­
tivity, or more informally, the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis (Sapir, 1960; Whorf, 1956).
"How do I know what I mean until I see what I say?" (Miller, 1972, p. 43). In a
humorous way, this question examines the relationship between thought and lan­
guage. Although it seems clear to most people that our thoughts influence the lan­
guage that we use, it is sometimes more difficult to understand the reciprocal nature
of the relationship. Anthropologists and psychologists have studied whether people
who speak different languages also think differently. Perhaps you have had the ex­
perience of translating a passage from one language to another and had difficulty
conveying exactly the same meaning. Jokes are a good example of this. Ethnic jokes
that are told in their native language frequently lose their humor when they are told
in translation. Could this indicate that ways of thinking, as reflected in language,
differ across cultures?
Some chilling implications of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis appeared in George
Orwell's classic book written in 1 949, which he entitled 1984. In 1984, he wrote
about a repressive society that was able to control the thoughts of its citizenry by
LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT 1 07

redefining some words and removing others from the language. By gaining control
of the language, this futuristic society dictated which thoughts were possible and
which were not.
The Orwellian example is an extreme interpretation of the Sapir-Whorf hypothe­
sis that language absolutely determines thought. According to this view, if a term
does not exist within a language, speakers do not have the corresponding thought.
Do you believe that if the word love didn't exist in our language, then people would­
n't be able to feel the emotion represented by the word? Most people would disagree
with the strong form of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis. Cross-cultural research that has
examined the way different languages influence thought has not supported the
strong version of the Sapir-Wharf hypothesis (Berlin & Kay, 1969; Rosch, 1977). A
weaker version of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis is that language influences but does
not determine thinking. As an example of this, consider the following terms carefully
and decide if each elicits a different thought: senior citizen; old man; golden-ager.
Did each term connote a different thought? Did you think about a different type of
person with each word? Most people agree that they did. (See Fig. 3.3.)

The Direction and Misdirection of Thought

All words are pegs to hang ideas on.


-Henry Ward Beecher (1812-1887)

Proverbs from Plymouth Pulpit (cited in Drysdale 1887, p. 33)

Senior Citizen O l d Man Gol den Ager

FIG. 3.3. The words we use influence how we think. Compare the different thoughts that
are evoked by the terms "senior citizen," "old man," and "golden-ager."
1 08 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

Given that language will influence what we think, it is only a short leap to suggest
that language can be used in deliberate ways to shape thinking so that it conforms to
a particular ideology or point of view. It also seems likely that if we understand how
language is used to direct how we think, then an awareness of the ways in which
this occurs should help us to resist the automatic type of thinking that goes along
with an uncritical approach to communication.

Emotional Language and Name calling


As described in the earlier section on labeling, the same event can be described in
several different ways. Yet, the words we use to describe an event are not inter­
changeable in the meaning they convey. Language that is highly emotional has a dif­
ferent effect on readers and listeners than more mundane ways of conveying the
intended meaning. This is the weaker version of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis­
although language may not determine thought, it directs, and sometimes misdirects,
it. Consider the heated debate between those for and against abortion. The faction op­
posed to abortion realized that it is better to be for something than against something
and therefore decided to call their stance "pro-life" rather than "anti-choice." On the
other side, those who favored abortion certainly didn't want to be called "anti-life"
and decided to label their stance "pro-choice." They hoped that people would think
differently about a position that is "pro-choice" than they would about one that is
"anti-life." Of course, the position hasn't changed-only its label or name has
changed, but presumably the way the position is labeled influences how people think
about it. One "pro-lifer" told a colleague that the best way to win a debate on this
topic is to use frequently the words kill and baby in the same sentence (Kahane, 1992).
The juxtaposition of these two words is sure to bring about an emotional response.
Another example of the deliberate choice of words to create a carefully planned
impression concerns the "rewriting" of history. All history texts (indeed, every­
thing) were written by someone with a particular point of view. Recently, the word
aggression was taken out of Japanese history books that described World War II in­
vasions. Do the same descriptions of an act seem "better" in some sense when they
are not modified by the word aggressive? The contemporary Japanese historians who
asked for this deletion apparently think so. Similarly, Russian historians are now
using harsher terms to describe Stalin's role when he was the leader of the former
Soviet Union. They now know and are free to say that Stalin slaughtered millions of
innocent Russians whose "crime" was to disagree with his policies. Such people
were officially labeled "enemies of the state/' a label that was meant to instill fear in
the individual who received such a label and to convey to everyone else that
disagreement with Stalin's official policies would be considered an act of treason.
History is also being rewritten in nonverbal ways in the new capitalist Russia. A
massive number of statues of Lenin and Stalin are now being sold as scrap metal
with new statues of Peter the Great and other Romanovs (members of the former
ruling family) now standing on the pedestals that held the bronze busts of commu­
nist leaders for most of the 20th century. With the advent of advertising in the new
capitalist Russia, images of the "Marlboro Man" puffing away on imported ciga­
rettes are now more numerous than depictions of the formerly ubiquitous Lenin. It
is clear that emotionally laden words and inspiring visual displays both reflect and
influence how people think.
The lesson is clear: When you want to influence how people think, choose your
words and images carefully. You also need to be aware of the ways in which other
LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT 1 09

people attempt to manipulate your thoughts by the labels they use. The deliberate
use of words designed to create a particular attitude or foster certain beliefs is called
semantic slanting. The meaning or semantics is slanted so that the listener's
thoughts will be directed in some way. It's fairly easy to find examples of this
around election time when issues and groups label themselves with favorable terms
and others with negative terms (name calling). During a recent election, a group
called "Citizens for Sane Laws" opposed a proposition, and another group called
"Citizens for Better Government" favored it. The political advertisements continued
to broadcast these group names and the message to vote "No on 10" or "Yes on 10,"
depending on who financed the advertisement. Very little meaningful information
was ever given on the merits or problems of the proposition. Be wary of attempts to
influence your thinking through the use of positive and negative labels, especially
on the important issues that concern social and political policies. I received a politi­
cal solicitation that may be among the most blatantly slanted in the choice of words
that it used. The outside of the envelope read, "The bloated, blathering bottom­
feeders of big government hope that you'll never uncover these secrets." For some
reason, I didn't expect to find reasoned and impartial information inside the enve­
lope. Would you?

Ambiguity, Vagueness, and Equivocation


The thinking process can also be misled when words are imprecise or misused.
Words are ambiguous when they can have multiple meanings depending on con­
text, and the appropriate meaning is unclear in a given context. The problem here,
as in the sentences described earlier, is one of determining the intended meaning or
underlying representation. A good example of this was provided by von Oech
(1983). According to von Oech, J. Edgar Hoover, the former director of the FBI, was
reviewing a typed copy of a letter he had dictated to his secretary. He didn't like the
margin widths she had used for the letter and wrote, "Watch the borders" on the let­
ter and asked her to retype the letter and send copies to top FBI agents. For the next
two weeks, FBI agents were put on special alert along the Canadian and Mexican
borders.
Another humorous example of ambiguity was provided by Fogelin (1987). Com­
pare the following two sentences:

Mary had a little lamb; it followed her to school.


Mary had a little lamb; and then a little broccoli.

The word had is ambiguous. It is used to mean owned in the first sentence and ate
in the second sentence. Its meaning is not clarified until the second half of each sen­
tence. A clever example of ambiguity can be found in the title of a classic book by
Phyllis Chesler (1972), Women and Madness, in which she meant madness to mean
both anger and insanity. I also deliberately used ambiguity in the title of my edited
book Changing College Classrooms (Halpern, 1994). The word changing could refer to
the fact that college classrooms are changing or that we should engage in activities
to change them. I meant the word in both senses; hence I made deliberate use of am­
biguity. Often, a situation is ambiguous and you are not sure how to respond or
which of several definitions is appropriate. Although this sort of ambiguity can lead
to errors, not all ambiguity is negative. Sometimes, creative interpretations of the in­
tended meaning and creative responses are the result of ambiguous situations.
1 10 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

Although ambiguous words have multiple meanings, vague words have impre­
cise meanings. Vagueness refers to a lack of precision in a communication. If your
friend Martha told you to bake a cake in a hot oven, you'd probably ask her how hot
it should be. In this context, the word hot is too vague and needs to be specified fur­
ther. Consider the "clarification" provided by Justice Brennan of the u.s. Supreme
Court when he provided a working definition that would assist those in the legal
process of determining the sort of punishment that is cruel and unusual. As you
probably know, punishment that is cruel and unusual is prohibited by the U.s. Con­
stitution. But, we have little guidance for determining what makes a punishment
cruel and unusual. He offered, "a punishment is cruel and unusual . . . if it does not
comport with human dignity." Such a definition will not help a judge or jury decide
whether a particular punishment is cruel and unusual. Justice Brennan's comments
are much too vague to be useful. It is not easier to determine which actions do not
comport with human dignity than it is to decide if they are cruel and unusual. A com­
munication is vague if it does not specify enough details for its intended purpose.
There is legislation in California that requires warning notices to be posted in all
places where the public may come in contact with cancer-causing chemicals. The
sign designed for gas stations is shown in Fig. 3.4.
As you can see, the new signs are too vague to be of value. There is no informa­
tion about the level of risk, or the likelihood of developing cancer, or how long you
would have to be exposed to these chemicals to reach some level of risk. There is no
way to use this information to make a meaningful decision about whether the risk is
so high the area should be avoided. This is a clear example of a deliberately unclear
communication. The gasoline companies were opposed to this law and have regis­
tered their complaint by posting the required signs, but not providing the public
with interpretable information.
Vagueness is sometimes a socially polite way of handling an unpleasant situa­
tion. If you ask someone about her divorce, you may get a vague response like "We
were incompatible," rather than a more precise, but less acceptable, "The stinking
rat cheated every chance he could get."

Wa r n i n g
Detectable a m o u nts
of chemicals known to
the State of C a l ifo r n i a
t o cause cancer, birt h
defects, or o t h e r
repro d u ctive h a rm may
be fou n d in a n d
a r o u n d t h i s faci l ity.

FIG. 3 . 4. An example of vagueness. California law requires that warning signs be posted in
all places where consumers come in contact with cancer-causing chemicals. Signs like this one
are being used at all gas stations. The information they convey is too vague to be meaningful.
LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT 111

Equivocation occurs when the meaning of a word is changed in the course of the
same discussion, and thus is different from vagueness or ambiguity. Consider the
following "line of reasoning" (Reasoning will be considered more fully in the next
chapter.):

1 . Man is the only rational animal.


2. No woman is a man.
3. Therefore, no woman is rational. (Damer, 1987)

The meaning of the word man changed from the first to the second sentence. In
the first sentence, man stood for all of humanity-both female and male. In the sec­
ond sentence, it was used as a sex-specific term, with females conveniently omitted.

Etymology and Reification


These two terms both concern word meanings. Etymology is the study of word
origins. It's often interesting to learn how language evolved and developed. How­
ever, it is wrong to conclude that a word has a particular meaning or nuance based
on the word from which it was derived. Consider, for example, the use of the word
gay to refer to homosexual men. The word is commonly used today to denote pride
and other positive attributes of male homosexuals. The origin of the word was quite
different. The word gay was derived from a definition meaning "wanton and licen­
tious." It would be wrong to conclude that gays are therefore wanton and licentious.
Language is a living entity and word definitions evolve and change. Returning to a
word's origins to find its contemporary meaning is like studying the writings of
Karl Marx to understand how modern communism is practiced in Cuba.
Reification is a more difficult concept to explain. Reification occurs when some­
thing abstract is given a name and then treated as though it were a concrete object.
Consider the Freudian notion of the "ego." According to Freudian theory, the ego is
that portion of the personality that deals with reality. Sometimes, therapists forget
that it is an abstract concept and start treating it as though it were tangible. If a
physician suggested that you take vitamins or engage in exercise to strengthen your
ego, you should run quickly from his office. The ego is not something that can be
physically altered because it is an abstract concept, not a physical body part. Per­
haps the most obvious case of reification involves the concept of intelligence, where
intelligence tests yield "IQ" scores that are said to measure it, and then IQ is used as
though it were the physical embodiment of intelligence.

Bureaucratese and Euphemism


Two language barriers to comprehension are bureaucratese and euphemism.
Bureaucratese is the use of formal, stilted language that is unfamiliar to people who
lack special training. The same information can be expressed better with simpler
terms. Bureaucratese is different from the use of precise technical terms that may be
needed in specialized disciplines; in bureaucratese, the style and language hinders
our understanding instead of aiding it. The legal profession is often guilty of bu­
reaucratese. I once read a legal document that began with the term "Witnesseth." Of
course, I questioned what meaning was being conveyed with the use of this term,
which is standard on many legal forms. The answer was "very little." It could have
been deleted altogether or replaced with "Notice" or "Read this document," both of
1 12 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

which would have been more meaningful than the obscure "Witnesseth." Ditto
for other obscure terms like "party of the first part" and "party of the second part,"
not to mention the archaic Latinisms that riddle the law (e.g., "ex parte" and "cor­
pus delecti").
Euphemism is the substitution of a desirable term for a less desirable or offensive
one. Although there is nothing inherently wrong with polite conversation, the result
is often a loss of communication. Euphemism is common in hospital and medical fa­
cilities where bodily functions need to be discussed. Hospital personnel may ask a
patient if he has "voided his bladder." Many patients do not realize that this refers
to urination. In fact, it has been shown that a majority of patients do not understand
the language that is commonly used in their interactions with medical staff. Many
patients do not understand words like malignant, benign, terminal, and generic. You
can imagine a solemn physician telling a patient that she is "terminal," with the pa­
tient then brightly inquiring when she'll get better. It is easy to see how the use of
euphemisms can lead to misunderstandings.
Euphemisms abound in advertisements of all sorts. Do ''bathroom tissue" and
"feminine hygiene products" seem more desirable and glamorous than toilet paper
and menstrual pads? Euphemisms often obscure the intended meaning. Although
polite speech is a necessary rule of society, euphemistic terms that are not com­
monly used interfere with the communication of ideas, and thus should be avoided.
Euphemisms are designed to change the affect or emotion that we feel when we
confront topics that we may find repugnant. The idea is that feelings will be less
negative if a phenomenon is given a more acceptable name. For example, many peo­
ple have complained that ''beauty pageants," like the "Miss America Pageant," are
demeaning to its participants whose value is determined by their appearance­
much like a horse or cow at an auction. Officials and sponsors of these pageants dis­
agree. They argue that these pageants are opportunities for the contestants to
demonstrate their talents and to win money and other prizes that can be used to fi­
nance an education or to launch a career. Those who believe that such displays are
demeaning reply that the bathing suit competition, in which women march around
in skimpy bathing suits and high-heel shoes, should not be a requirement for schol­
arship money for a college education. This argument has continued heatedly for
years, mostly centering around the bathing suit competition. In recognition of the
fact that a contestant's appearance when clad in scanty clothing probably is unrelated
to her talent, academic potential, or scholarship, the officials of the Miss America
Pageant decided to remedy this situation. They renamed the competition. Women
still parade in scanty swimsuits and high heels, but now it is called "health and fit­
ness in a swimsuit" (Leive, 1 994). This is a strange euphemism for the portion of the
competition that leads the contestants to resort to starvation diets and plastic
surgery-neither of which promotes health and fitness.
Probably the biggest perpetuators of euphemisms are politicians. In response to
public protests over tax increases, we now have "revenue enhancement" bills. Abor­
tion is now sometimes called "pregnancy termination," and sex education classes are
often called "family education." One of my favorite examples is in the change of a
class title that was offered in a junior high school. Based on the idea that boys as well
as girls need to know about cooking, nutrition, and similar topics, a teacher offered
a course called "home economics for boys." It had zero enrollment. She then got wise
and retitled the course ''bachelor living." So many boys wanted to take the class with
this new name, there was a waiting list. With very little effort, you should be able to
find other examples where the change of a label changed how people think.
LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT 1 13

Framing with Leading Questions, Negation,


and Marked Words

Framing occurs when a question is asked in a way that suggests what the correct re­
sponse should be. The reader is "led" into assuming a particular perspective or
point of view.
Consider the following problem:

Imagine that the United States is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual disease, which
is expected to kill 600 people. Two alternative programs to combat the disease have been pro­
posed. Assume that the exact scientific estimate of the consequences of the programs are as
follows:
If Program A is adopted, 200 people will be saved.
If Program B is adopted, there is 1 /3 probability that 600 people will be saved, and 2/3
probability that no people will be saved.
Which of the two programs would you favor? (Tversky & Kahneman, 1981, p. 453)
Now consider the same problem, and select between the following two programs:
If Program C is adopted, 400 people will die.
If Program D is adopted there is 1 /3 probability that nobody will die, and 2/3 probability
that 600 people will die.
Which of these two programs would you favor?

When this problem was presented to college students, 72% of those given the first
set of choices selected Program A, and 78% of those given the second set of choices
selected Program D. Look closely at the choices. Program A and C are effectively
identical-they differ only in that A is described in terms of the numbers of lives
saved, but C is described in terms of the number who will die. Programs B and D
are also identical, differing only in the language used to describe the outcomes. It
seems that most people are risk adverse, which means that they prefer options that
do not involve loss. When an alternative makes a potentia1 10ss prominent (e.g., fo­
cuses on the number that die), people will reject that alternative. It is clear that when
an option is stated in terms of a loss, it is judged more negatively than a mathemati­
cally identical statement about gains. This is an important result, showing that
human judgments and preferences can be readily manipulated by changes in the
way questions are asked or framed. If I tell you that a new medical treatment has a
50% success rate, you will be more likely to endorse its use than if I tell you that it
has a 50% failure rate. The only difference is whether the information was presented
in a positive (success rate) frame or a negative (failure rate) frame (Halpern &
Blackman, 1985; Halpern, Blackman, & Salzman, 1989).
Framing is one of those topics that appears in several different chapters in this
text because it can be used to influence thinking in many different contexts. A frame
creates a particular perspective on a issue-"it manipulates salience in order to in­
fluence subsequent judgment" (Rhoads, http://www.influenceatwork.com/re­
trieved February 10, 2002). The underlying idea is that we can be made to think
about the same subject in different ways, depending on what it is about that subject
that we are focusing on. For example, if I asked you if you think that the president is
doing a good job, you might think about the state of the economy and come up with
one answer or think about international relations and come up with another. If I can
get you to focus on one of these variables (the economy or international relations) by
making it more salient in your thinking, then I could influence the way you assess
1 14 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

the president. Framing effects are ubiquitous-good salespeople use them to get us
to focus on positive aspects of their products and good lawyers and others use them
to persuade juries and the rest of us about the guilt or innocence of their client.
Framing effects can be powerful. If you understand how they work, you can use
framing to your advantage and recognize when others are using it to their advantage.
Suppose you are interviewing for a job and you have gotten to the "sticky" issue of
negotiating salary. If you said to the prospective employer that you really wanted
$50,000 a year, but you are willing to take $45,000, the employer begins to see this
offer as a gain of $5000. Similarly, if the prospective employer were to say that she was
ready to offer $40,000 but is willing to go as high as $45,000 (after all you studied criti­
cal thinking and should be worth more salary), then you would have the "feeling" of
having gained $5000. The first figure mentioned set a frame (or anchor-a topic con­
sidered later in this chapter) for interpreting the salary (Pinkley & Northcraft, 2000).
Another example of the influence of language on thought comes from a study by
Loftus (1975, p. 561). Forty people were asked questions about their headaches.
A key question was posed in one of two ways:

"Do you get headaches frequently, and, if so, how often?"


or
"Do you get headaches occasionally, and, if so, how often?"

Can you anticipate the results of this study? The respondents who answered the
first question reported an average of 2.2 headaches per week, whereas those who
answered the second question reported an average of .7 headaches per week. It
seems that if people are asked questions with the word frequently, they will believe
they have experienced more headaches than if they are asked the same question
with the word occasionally. Note that although this example does not seem to contain
any deliberate attempts to mislead or direct respondents' answers, the changes in
wording have accomplished exactly that end. Pay careful attention to the way that
questions are posed. Always consider if slight changes in the language used would
result in different responses. Try rephrasing a question or information for yourself
and remain alert for ways in which slight changes in phrasing could be producing
large differences in responses.
Salespeople know that leading questions can be good for business. If I am show­
ing you some household items, a good sales technique is to ask "How many will
you take?" The assumption here is that the sale is made, and it is only a matter of
how many you will buy, not whether you will buy. Similarly, a car salesperson who
is ready to "close the deal" will ask "What color do you want?" This question makes
it clear that you have already decided that you will buy the car and the only deci­
sion left is that of color.
Advertisers and merchants like to price their wares in uneven amounts, like
$19.99 and $24.95. Have you ever wondered why they don't simplify matters and
price garments to the nearest dollar so that $19.99 would be labeled $20.00 and
$24.95 would become $25.00? The frame or perspective being induced here is one of
considering the price as "less than $20.00." Of course, the one-cent difference is neg­
ligible, but it does seem to change how people think about the price.
Listeners can also be framed or misled with negation. Suppose you read that a
prominent politician is not a drunk. Suppose further that this is absolutely true; she
is not a drunk. Most people would infer that there was some question about her
sobriety and the truth of the assertion. The pragmatic function of negation is to deny
LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT 1 15

something that is plausible (Carroll, 1986). Thus, listeners will infer the plausibility of
that which was denied. President Richard Nixon hadn't considered this psycholinguis­
tic principle when he uttered the now-famous words in response to his Watergate de­
bacle-"I am not a crook." Most people took this to mean that it is plausible that he is a
crook. Thus, the denial of some act often has the paradoxical result that people now
believe it is more likely to be true than they would have if no denial had been made.

Contrast and Context


Are you making a good salary? How is your health? Is the new love in your life
intelligent and kind? Do you approve of the current president? The way you are
likely to answer all of these questions depends on what you are comparing them to
and the context in which the comparison is being made. Contrast and context pro­
vide meaning to cognitive activities like judging and evaluating. In a classic study,
Parducci (1968) asked subjects to decide how bad it is to "pocket the tip that the pre­
vious customers left for the waitress." Half the subjects were asked to judge this
event along with the following mild infractions: stealing a loaf of bread from a store
when you are starving; playing poker on Sunday; cheating at solitaire. The other
half of the subjects were asked to judge the same event (pocketing the tip that the
previous customers left for the waitress) along with the following infractions:
spreading rumors that an acquaintance is a sexual pervert; putting your deformed
child in the circus; murdering your mother without justification or provocation.
Taking a waitress' tip was judged to be a more serious offense when it was pre­
sented along with milder infractions than when it was presented among a list of
serious infractions. The event (pocketing a tip) was exactly the same in each case,
and the wording was identical. Changes in the context in which it was presented
created changes in the way it was evaluated. Context is an important determinant of
the meaning we assign to events.
Judgments and evaluations are always made relative to some frame of reference.
Suppose that your friend has just moved into a small one-room apartment near
campus. This apartment will seem like heaven, if he has moved from an even
smaller one-room apartment that he shared with four people he did not like, and it
will seem awful if he moved from a large swanky penthouse in the best part of the
city. The object being evaluated (the apartment) and the evaluator are the same in
both scenarios. The only change is the frame of reference that is being used. Contrast
is a powerful determinant of the way in which we evaluate an alternative.
I recall reading a book when I was a child entitled Cheaper by the Dozen (Gilbreth,
1963). It was a (mostly) true story about a family with 12 children, hence the title,
and their parents, who were psychologists. The father knew very well about the
power of contrast effects. After he purchased a new home for his family, he took
them out to see it for the first time. He drove around the city, stopping at various
run-down houses in bad neighborhoods, while he pretended to be lost. Finally, he
pulled up to the home he had purchased, which looked like a palace in comparison
to the decaying shacks he had stopped at earlier. The family was delighted with
their luxurious new home, which certainly seemed even better when compared to
the others that they had just seen. This principle is used quite well in the letter that
is reprinted from a delightful book by Cialdini (1993) and shown in Fig. 3.5.
Contrast can be used effectively in a wide range of situations. For example,
Zimbardo and Leippe (1991) offer this advice when you want to borrow money from
a friend or parent. They suggest that you first ask for a large sum that you are fairly
1 16 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

Dear Mother and Dad:

Since I left for college I have been remiss in writing and I am sorry for my thoughtlessness
in not having written before. I will bring you up to date now, but before you read on, please
sit down. You are not to read any further unless you are sitting down, okay?

Well, then, I am getting along pretty well now. The skull fracture and the concussion I got
when I jumped out the window of my dormitory when it caught on fire shortly after my
arrival here is pretty well healed now. I only spent two weeks in the hospital and now I can
see almost normally and only get those sick headaches once a day. Fortunately; the fire in
the dormitory; and my jump, was witnessed by an attendant at the gas station near the
dorm, and he was the one who called the Fire Department and the ambulance. He also
visited me in the hospital and since I had nowhere to live because of the burntout dormitory,
he was kind enough to invite me to share his apartment with him. It's really a basement
room, but it's kind of cute. He is a very fine boy and we have fallen deeply in love and are
planning to get married. We haven't got the exact date yet, but it will be before my
pregnancy begins to show.

Yes, Mother and Dad, I am pregnant. I know how much you are looking forward to being
grandparents and I know you will welcome the baby and give it the same love and devotion
and tender care you gave me when I was a child. The reason for the delay in our marriage
is that my boyfriend has a minor infection which prevents us from passing our pre-marital
blood tests and I carelessly caught it from him. I know that you will welcome him into our
family with open arms. He is kind and, although not well educated, he is ambitious.
Although he is of a different race and religion than ours, I know your often expressed
tolerance will not permit you to be bothered by that.

Now that I have brought you up to date, I want to tell you that there was no dormitory
fire, I did not have a concussion or skull fracture, I was not in the hospital, I am not pregnant,
I am not engaged, I am not infected, and there is no boyfriend. However, I am getting a
" D" in American History; and an "F" in Chemistry and I want you to see those marks in
their proper perspective.

Your loving daughter,

Sharon

FIG. 3.5. This fictitious letter is a good example of the use of context to influence
judgments of "how bad" different events are perceived. From Cialdini, R. B. (1993). Influence:
Science and Practice (3rd edition). HarperCollins: NY.

certain will be refused. (Hey, can you loan me $75?) Follow this by asking for the
smaller sum that you really need. (No, well, how about $257) They found that you are
more likely to receive the smaller amount when it follows a large request than when it
is requested without the larger request being made first. Zimbardo and Leippe re­
ported that charitable contributions are also more likely when the requester asks for
any amount-"even a penny will help." When solicitors for charities request "even a
penny," people are more likely to give larger sums of money to the charity than to
charitable appeals that do not emphasize that "even small amounts will help."

Anchoring
When we have little basis for making a meaningful decision, we often rely on
whatever information is available, even when we know it is probably worthless. For
LANGUAGE: TOOL OR MASTER OF THOUGHT 1 17

example, compare these two questions (Mussweiler & Strack, 2000):

Is the average price of a new car higher or lower than $22,OOO?


Is the average price of a new car higher or lower than $1 1,000?

You probably answered lower to the first question and higher to the second.
Now, suppose I ask you to estimate the price of the average new car. If you had only
been asked the first question, you are likely to give a higher estimate than if you had
only been asked the second question. The price asked served as an anchor-a figure
that you used as a beginning point or comparison for making your estimate. An­
chors influence our thinking, but they operate without conscious awareness unless
we are vigilant for them. Suppose you are judging something important like the
severity of a crime. Think how you might respond to "Should the defendant serve
life in jail without the possibility of parole?" compared to "Should the defendant be
sentenced to three years on probation and community service?" Without knowing
anything else, like the nature of the crime, can you see that most people would use
these examples of sentences as anchors and tend to suggest much more severe sen­
tences if they are asked the first sentence than if they are asked the second?
Have you ever wondered why solicitations for charities or political organizations
have check boxes that you are supposed to check to indicate the amount of your
contribution? Almost always, the highest values are listed first. The next time you
receive a solicitation, look at the reply card. It is likely to read something like:
_ $1000 _ $ 500 _ $200 _ $ 100
The implied message is clear-start by thinking about giving us $1000. The high
start rate should anchor your contributions so that they will be closer to $1000 than
they would have been without these suggested levels of "giving."

Barometers of Thought

Public opinion polls are often used to provide information to policymakers who
want to know how a sample from a population of interest will react to some action
like a tax cut or a military response in a troubled place in the world. Suppose that
you want to know how average American citizens will think about a controversial
issue. It is impossible to provide a straightforward answer to the question "What do
Americans think?" Not only is there the obvious problem that Americans are quite
diverse in their thinking, there is also the problem of assessing what any individual
thinks. The kind of answers that people give to opinion questions depends on the
way the questions are asked. Read the following two opinion polls, which gave very
different indices of what the American people thought about the controversial U.S.
policy in the former Yugoslavia (Brennan, 1993, p. AS).

Gallup Poll:
"As you may know, the Bosnian Serbs rejected the United Nations peace plan and Serbian
forces are continuing to attack Muslim towns. Some people are suggesting the United States
conduct air strikes against Serbian military forces, while others say we should not get militar­
ily involved. Do you favor or oppose U.S. air strikes?"

The Results:
Favor: 36%
Oppose: 55%
1 18 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

Depends: 3%
No Opinion 6%
ABC News Poll:
"Specifically, would you support or oppose the United States along with its allies in Eu-
rope, carrying out air strikes against Bosnian Serb artillery positions and supply lines?"
The Results:
Support: 65%
Oppose: 32%
No Opinion 3%

What is the difference between these two opinion polls, which were taken on the
same day, yet yielded very different results? In the Gallup Poll, no mention was made
of joining with our European allies, whereas in the ABC News Poll, the action was de­
scribed as working with our allies. Well, what did Americans really think about the
American role in Bosnia-Herzegovina on this particular day in 1993? Like all difficult
questions in life, the answer is "It depends." In this case, it depends on how and what
is asked. It is fairly easy to deliberately slant the results of an opinion poll by carefully
selecting wording that will favor one position or another. In fact, it may not be possi­
ble to find any wording that would be unbiased. Try this one for yourself:

Are you in favor of a national program that ensures good quality, affordable day care for
infants and young children whose parents work outside of the home?
YES NO NO OPINION
Are you in favor of programs that are paid for with your tax dollars that place infants and
young children in child care institutions for 9 to 10 hours each day?
YES NO NO OPINION

Can you see how it would be easy to present data to Congress and other decision­
making bodies that either support or refute the idea that most Americans are in
favor of or opposed to a program of national day care? Before you interpret the re­
sults from any poll or respond to one, consider very carefully the way in which the
questions were posed. What sort of background information was given and what
words were used?

COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE

Language is the first medium of the rational mind.


-Ferguson (1981, p. 120)
A student once told me that despite the fact that she really wanted to understand
the material in her textbook, she found that the information went "in one eye and
out the other." In other words, it "didn't stick" or seem to involve her brain at all.
Although her "eyes" read every word, she was unable to understand or remember
the material. We can sympathize with her because we've all had this experience at
one time or another. Comprehension failures often result from the language used to
express an idea and not from the difficulty of the idea itself. Good teachers know
how to communicate complex ideas so that they can be easily understood, but poor
teachers could talk or write for days without conveying the ideas to their students.
COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE 1 19

Strategies for Comprehension

What can you do to enhance your ability to comprehend? There are many compre­
hension strategies or skills designed to help make information that is presented in
natural (everyday) language more understandable. These strategies aid in discover­
ing, retaining, and utilizing the information in speech and written prose. They all in­
volve ways of building a meaningful representation that matches the one used by
the "sender" (i.e., speaker or writer).
The process of comprehension may be best described with an analogy. Imagine
that a friend has a large jungle gym (child's climbing toy) in his backyard, and that
he is giving it to you as a present. Because it is too large to transfer in its assembled
state, you need to take it apart to move it to your home. Once you get it home, you
need to reassemble it. To do so, you have to identify which part is the base and then
add component parts to it. When it is reassembled, it should look the same as it did
in your friend's yard.
The same is true of comprehension. If your friend has a complex knowledge
structure in his head, he would transfer the information to you via language. You
would have to identify the main ideas (or base) in order to build your own mental
representation. You would also have to understand the relationships among the
parts of the information so that you can graft them onto the main ideas in the correct
way. Comprehension is attained when your knowledge structure "looks the same
as" the one your friend has in his head. In other words, you would both have the
same underlying representation for the transferred information. All comprehension
strategies are activities that aid in the transfer of underlying structures. They pro­
vide guides for identifying main ideas and determining the relevance of various
components of the message. They assist the comprehender in discovering the un­
derlying relationships among the constituent parts of the message.
What do you do when you comprehend a passage? Most people respond that
they have no idea what they do to aid their understanding, yet they can say what
they do when they study. Remember, any cognitive activity that aids comprehen­
sion will also aid memory, so any effective comprehension strategy is also a mem­
ory strategy.

Re-representation
In understanding complex phenomena-anything ranging from planetary mo­
tions to our beliefs about racial and ethnic groups-we rely on mental models.
These models are connected knowledge structures that help us to make sense out of
our experiences. They guide what we see, how we interpret events, and how we re­
member them. For example, if I believe that boys are more aggressive than girls,
then I may interpret a scuffle on the playground between two boys as being more
aggressive than the same scuffle if it had involved two girls. In addition, I may re­
member details that are consistent with this interpretation (e.g., torn clothing) even
when they did not occur. It seems that we are often more likely to alter our memory
for events in ways that are consistent with our mental models than we are to alter
the models. Our goal is to maintain models or beliefs about the world that are as ac­
curate as possible, but it seems that we are better at preserving faulty mental models
than we are at altering them to reflect true experiences.
Consider this: In a random telephone survey conducted by the Public Opinion
Laboratory at Northern Illinois, 21 % of the over 2,000 adults who responded to the
1 20 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

survey believe that the sun revolves around the earth, and an additional 7% did not
know which revolves around which. Didn't most of these adults learn somewhere
that for over 400 years the scientific community unanimously determined that the
earth revolves around the sun? Although we cannot be sure, I would guess that
most of these adults learned this fact, but never altered their mental models of plan­
etary motion because their everyday observations don't support it. We see the sun
"moving" across the sky as morning turns into night. The earth-centric view of the
universe makes sense according to the naive model that is easily constructed and
tested on a daily basis. To change an individual's mental model, we need to under­
stand the ones that exist prior to instruction and design instruction so that the errors
in naive models are exposed and the benefits of the new model are obvious. This
principle applies in multiple contexts including the way we understand the physical
and social world. There are numerous demonstrations that students can write a cor­
rect answer on an exam or recognize a correct answer among a list of foils, without
ever changing the nature of their understanding. To challenge the way we under­
stand the world, we need to create situations where our beliefs are tested against
other models. To do this, we need to be open to the way in which we "connect infor­
mation." A good way to make our models explicit is to use comprehension
processes that require re-representation. We need to represent our beliefs in multi­
ple ways-to draw concept maps and other spatial layouts that represent ideas
visually when information is highly verbal and to use verbal strategies when the in­
formation is highly spatial.

Questioning and Explaining


Good thinkers are good questioners.
-Alison King (1994, p. 18)
There have been numerous demonstrations of the beneficial effects of posing
questions to oneself and others as part of the learning process. Palincsar and Brown
(1984), for example, found that when students were required to formulate relevant
questions for their peers they were better able to comprehend new passages than a
control group of students who never practiced posing questions. The best-known
technique for studying from text is based on the process of asking good questions
about the material being read and then demonstrating comprehension by answering
the questions. When students generate and answer their own questions about a text,
comprehension and recall improves (e.g., Heiman & Slomianko, 1986).
One of the best-known methods based on the combination of questioning and
paraphrase is SQ3R, which stands for Survey, Question, Read, Recite, Review
(Adams, Carnine, & Gersten, 1 982). The first thing to do when you begin reading
complex text is to Survey the chapter (or some other manageable unit of text). When
you survey, you look at section headings and subheadings to gain an overview
about what you will be reading. This tactic will allow you to anticipate related top­
ics as you read. It also forms a skeletal framework for the mental representation you
will be building that can be used to interpret and organize incoming information.
Before you read each section (approximately one or two pages is usually a good
length), turn the section heading into a Question.
The single most important variable in promoting long-term retention and transfer
is "practice at retrieval"-students need to generate responses, with minimal re­
trieval cues, repeatedly over time. For example, the main heading for this section of
COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE 121

text is "strategies for comprehension." A good question that you should be able to
answer when you finish this section is "What are some strategies for comprehen­
sion, and how do they work?" If you can't answer this question, with the book
closed, when you finish this section, then you do not know the information pre­
sented. A good question for this subsection on "questioning and explaining" is
"How are questioning and explaining used to improve comprehension?"
The first of the 3Rs is "Read." Reading is the third step; it is not the first thing you
do when learning from text. It is often useful to take notes at this time. For these notes
to be beneficial, they need to paraphrase or restate in your own words the information.
The "Recite" portion is the answering of the questions you previously posed. This
needs to be done without reference to the book or your notes-practice at recall. It is
too easy to believe that you know the material when it is sitting in front of you, only to
discover later that you really don't "own" it when away from the book or your notes.
At this point, you need to monitor the quality of your response by assessing how well
you can answer the questions. It's a good idea to recite the answer aloud or to write
out an answer. Cognitive psychologists know that "one of the most demanding tests
of people's comprehension of a text is to have them summarize it, distilling and ab­
stracting it into a few sentences" (Bower & Clapper, 1989, p. 293). If you can't answer
the questions, you need to go back and recycle through the material. Reread the sec­
tion, reconsider the questions you've posed, and review the structure of the informa­
tion. The final "R" is for Review. Go over the material again-practice spaced over
time is a powerful strategy for successful recall. Psychologists call this overlearning.
Overlearning is an important part of the process of understanding and learning be­
cause it ensures that newly acquired information will be available when it is needed.
Recall becomes increasingly automatic, accurate, and less effortful, with overlearning.
King (1 989, 1992, 1994) conducted a series of studies that clearly demonstrate the
value of reciprocal peer questioning, a technique in which learners learn to pose
thoughtful questions, which they then take turns answering. She concluded that the
ability to ask thoughtful questions is a skill that needs to be learned because most
people tend to ask "low-level" simple recall questions (e.g., What is the date of . . .
Who did . . . ) and not those that require a meaningful analysis of complex informa­
tion, if they are not trained in the formulation of thoughtful questions. King has de­
vised a series of generic questions, which can be used with modifications in almost
any context. Look at the generic questions that are presented in Table 3.1 .
When learners completed these questions using information from a lecture or
text, they showed better recall and comprehension than control groups who were
instructed either to study independently, engage in group discussions, generate
summaries, or ask questions without training in how to ask good questions (King,
1992). More importantly, King found that when students become proficient at using
higher-level questioning, they spontaneously ask these questions in a variety of
other learning situations (King, 1994). These studies provide further support for the
conclusion that I presented in the first chapter: Critical thinking skills transfer to
novel contexts when instruction emphasizes the need to practice and use these skills
in many contexts. Thus, there are very strong indications that you can improve your
comprehension and memory by using the generic questions that appear in Table 3.1.
Here are some examples applied to the information in this chapter:

• How does context affect judgment?


• Compare underlying structure with surface structure with regard to their role
in the process of communication.
1 22 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

TABLE 3. 1
Guiding Thought-Provoking Questioning

Generic Questions Specific Thinking Skills Induced


What is a new example of . . . ? Application
How could . . . be used to . . . ? Application
What would happen if . . . ? Prediction/hypothesizing
What are the implications of . . . ? Analysis / inference
What are the strengths and Analysis / inference
weaknesses of . . . ?
What is . . . analogous to? Identification and creation of
analogies and metaphors
What do we already know about . . . ? Activation of prior knowledge
How does . . . affect . . . ? Activation of relationship (cause-effect)
How does . . . tie in with what Activation of prior knowledge
we learned before?
Explain why . . . Analysis
Explain how . . . Analysis
What is the meaning of . . . ? Analysis
Why is . . . important? Analysis of significance
What is the difference between . . . and . . . ? Comparison-contrast
How are . . . and . . . similar? Comparision-contrast
How does . . . apply to everyday life? Application-to the real world
What is the counterargument for . . . ? Rebuttal argument
What is the best . . . and why? Evaluation and provision of evidence
What are some possible solutions Synthesis of ideas
to the problem of . . . ?
Compare . . . and . . . with regard to . . . Comparision-contrast
What do you think causes . . . ? Why? Analysis of relationship (cause-effect)
Do you agree or disagree with Evaluation and provision of evidence
this statement: . . . ?
What evidence is there to support
your answer?
How do you think . . . would Taking other perspectives
see the issue of . . . ?
Note. A list of generic questions provided by King (1994). These question sterns can be used in almost
any context. Research has shown that comprehension and memory are improved when students learn to
ask and answer thoughtful questions based on these sterns. More important, students use these generic
questions in novel contexts, showing that transfer of critical thinking skills occurs when students
understand that transfer is the goal of activities that improve thinking .

• Explain how analogies can be useful in enhancing comprehension.


• How does anchoring apply to everyday life?
• What is the difference between ambiguity and vagueness?
• What is the meaning of the term "generic questions"?

Can you answer these questions?

concept Maps
An oft-repeated theme in this book is to utilize both verbal and spatial-like strate­
gies as thinking aids. Concept maps, sometimes called graphic organizers, are spa­
tial arrays that require learners to attend explicitly to the underlying structure in a
COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE 1 23

passage. They can provide a picture of a learner's knowledge structures and show
the way in which new information is incorporated into information that is already
known. Mayer (1987) calls the deliberate use of graphic organizers "structure train­
ing techniques" because they force the learner to focus on the structure of a text.
There are several varieties of concept maps, but all of them use spatial representa­
tions to make efficient use of the information in a text.

Linear Arrays. Sometimes, the best way to understand a topic is to represent the
information in a linear array. This is useful when the information presented is fairly
linear or straight-line-like in its structure. An example of this would be a very simple
"line" of events occurring one after the other: The girl hit the boy. He started to cry.
The teacher heard the boy's cry. She ran into the room. She punished the girl. The
girl was sent to the principal's office, etc. This rather boring story is a straightforward
sequence of events that followed each other in a strict temporal ordering. A simple
linear representation would adequately capture all of the relevant information.

girl hit boy


boy cried
teacher arrived
teacher punished girl
girl to principal's office
etc.

Another example when a modified linear array would be a good choice of repre­
sentation is in representing any parts or processes that are aligned linearly in the
physical world. Vaughan (1984) taught medical students how to utilize graphic or­
ganizers when learning from medical texts. The digestive system is aligned in a
fairly linear manner beginning with the mouth and ending with the rectum. Stu­
dents who read about the digestive system listed the parts of the digestive system in
linear order and noted along with each part its purposes in the digestive process
and its components. The resulting linear array is shown in Fig. 3.6. Vaughan re­
ported that the medical students who learned to use graphic organizers like this one
showed significant improvement in their comprehension of medical school texts.
Time lines that are commonly used in history are helpful in providing a visual
picture of and appreciation for time spans and the co-occurrence of events. When
the distance between events is proportional to the time between their occurrence, a
much more accurate understanding of the importance of time as the key underlying
dimension of history is possible than with any verbal description. This is another sit­
uation in which a linear array can foster comprehension.

Hierarchies
Most of the information we deal with is considerably more complex than simple
linear chains. An alternative structural form for information is that of hierarchies or
tree structures in which information is organized around class inclusion rules. Class
inclusion rules are those rules in which something is a part of or a type of something
else. Examples of class inclusion rule are the classification of toes as part of the foot
and roses as a type of flower. Information of this sort can usually be categorized into
levels, with higher levels dividing into lower levels according to some rule. Biologi­
cal classification systems are a good example of hierarchically organized informa­
tion. Bower (1970) studied organizational factors in memory using hierarchically
1 24 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

What the Digestive System Does

Food Conversion
Digestion-Absorption

} {
(convers i o n ) (tran sportat i o n to
b l ood system)

Purposes Parts
1 . receives food mouth 1 . tongue (pushes food into

} {
2. prep. for (oral cavity) pharynx)
digestion 2. taste buds

1 . musc . constriction 1 . pharynx (throat)


(swallowi n g ) soft palate. uvula.
. Swa l l . Tubes
epigl ottes (sma l l l i d )

{
2. closes for breathing

}
3. carries f. to stomach 2. esophagus (9" l o n g )

1. valves

}
when fU l l . closes
· . .

{1.
Stomach top, bottom
gas t IC J U ices

I
2. pouch (folds)

chief organ of digestion duoden u m ( 1 0 - 1 2")


absorption through walls Small Intestine biJe ( d i g . of fat)
.
in v i l l i 2 0 ' ( longes t, s m a l l d l am ) 2 . j ej u n u m

I
{
t h r u portal syst. to liver

}
3. i l i u m

some absorption L o n g Intestines 1 . cecum (pouch)


of water 4- 5 ' 2. m u scle
I
Colon
(longer part of L . I . )
)
Rectum
36 + h o u r s
{ 1 . anal c a n a l
2. anus

FIG. 3.6. Modified linear array depicting the purposes and parts of the digestive system.
A linear array is a good spatial arrangement for this information because, like the array, the
digestive system is linear. Adapted from Vaughan (1984).

arranged information about minerals. Figure 3.7 depicts this hierarchy. Bower
found that when subjects organized information this way, they had significantly
better recall than a group of control subjects. He also found that when a "node" or
branch of the hierarchy was forgotten, subjects failed to recall the entire portion of
the "tree" that was below it. I'll be returning to these results later in this book in
Chapter 9 on problem solving because hierarchies or tree diagrams are sometimes
used as problem-solving aids.

Networks
The relationships among ideas in a communication are not usually based on sim­
ple class inclusion rules. Concepts can be related to each other in numerous other
ways, and it is the depiction of the correct relationship among concepts that is
central to all graphic organizing techniques. Networks are graphic organizers in
which several different types of relationships are made explicit. Much of the work in
this area has been conducted by Dansereau and his colleagues. He developed a
COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE 1 25

Level

M i n erals

/ �
/r� ?"\
2

3 Rare Common Al loy Precious Masonry

4 Plati n u m Aluminum Bronze


I
Sapphire Li mestone
Si lver Copper Steel Emerald Gran ite
Gold Lead Brass Diamond Ma rble
Iron R u by Slate

FIG. 3.7. Hierarchy of minerals. An example of a hierarchical graphic organizer.


Hierarchies are particularly useful when the information is organized according to class
inclusion rules. Adapted from Bower (1970).

training manual and program for counselors in substance abuse programs where
concept maps (he calls them guide maps) are used to create treatment plans and to
assess progress in the program (Dees & Dansereau, 2000). He found that these maps
promote organized thinking in the messy real world of drug treatment.
When students learn the technique of networking, they are taught to focus on
and identify six different types of relationships or links among concepts (Holley,
Dansereau, McDonald, Garland, & Collins, 1979; Dansersau, 1995). Two of these
relationships are the class inclusion rules of hierarchies: X is a part of Y (e.g., France is
a part of Europe), and X is a type of Y (e.g., mangoes are a type of fruit). The third re­
lationship is called a leads to link. This type of relationship occurs whenever X leads
to Y (e.g., stealing leads to jail). The other three relationships or links are analogy, X
is like Y (e.g., a paw is like an arm); characteristic, X is a characteristic or feature of Y
(e.g., brilliance is a characteristic of diamonds); and evidence, X is evidence that Y oc­
curred (e.g., antibodies are evidence of infection). These six relationships are de­
scribed more fully in Table 3.2.
As you can see from Table 3.2, networking requires students to consider the na­
ture of the relationship among concepts in a text and then to categorize them into six
different possible types. The relationships are then depicted in a network-like array
with all of the relationships labeled. Eylon and Linn (1988) reported that errors in
understanding often result from inappropriate links among concepts. When learn­
ers construct networks, they must consciously consider the relationships among
concepts, a strategy that leads to greater comprehension. Research with both
younger and older adults has shown that when they learned to identify structural
relationships in a passage, such as descriptions, sequences, cause, problem-solution,
comparisons, and listings, comprehension and retention was improved (Meyer &
Poon, 2001).
An example of a completed network is shown in Fig. 3.8. The network shows the
relationships among concepts in a nursing text on wounds. Look carefully at this fig­
ure. "Types of wounds" and the "process of healing" are parts of the discussion of
wounds. "Open," "closed," "accidental," and "intentional" are types of wounds. In the
process of healing, the "lag phase" leads to the "fibroplasia phase," which leads to the
1 26 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

TABLE 3 . 2
Six Types o f Links Used i n Networks

Type Example Structure Key Words


Part of link hand Hierarchy-the lower node is a part of
Ip is part of the higher is a segment of
finger node is a portion of
Type of! school Hierarchy-the lower node is a type of
example of It is an example of the is in the category
link private higher node is an example of
is a kind of
three procedures are
Leads to link practice Chain-the object of the leads to
11 higher node leads to or results in
perfection results in the lower node causes
is a tool of
produces
Analogy link school �factory Cluster-the content of is similar to
one node is analogous to is analogous to
the other node is like
corresponds to
Characteristic sky�blue Cluster-the content of has
link one mode is a trait of the is characterized by
other node feature is
property is
trait is
aspect is
attribute is
Evidence link broken�x-ray Cluster-the content of indicates
arm one node is evidence for is illustrated by
the other node is demonstrated by
supports
documents
is proof of
confirms
Note. This table is adapted from Holley et al. ( 1979). Notice how the "key words" suggest the type of
link that is being described.

contraction phase. "Soft, pink, and friable" is a characteristic of tissue continuity. The
other two types of relationships, analogy and evidence, are not used in this network.
Identification and use of these six types of relationships or links and their combi­
nation in a unified network requires considerable practice. This is an effortful strat­
egy, which, like some of the mnemonic techniques, pays off once it is well learned.
Holley and associates (1979) found that when subjects were well trained in this tech­
nique, they performed significantly better on subsequent tests than control students
who did not learn this technique, with the biggest improvement for students with
low grade point averages. It seems that the students who were doing very well in
school were already attending to the relationships among concepts. Then it was the
poorer students who benefited most from explicit instruction and practice in identi­
fying, labeling, and diagramming the relationships among concepts.
Look carefully at the generic "fill-in-the-blank" concept map that can be used to
understand any theory that is shown in Fig. 3.9 (Dansereau, 2001). If you take this
take steps to
m i nimize scars

c
c

-incision (sharp cutting instrument) granulation small blood


tissues (fibro­ vessels dis­
-abrasion (scraping or rubbing) blasts and small appear a n d
blood vessels)
scar shrinks
-puncture/stab (nail. bullet) grow along fibrin
network and grad­
-laceration (blunt instrument) ually absorb it

,
"
,

c Soft. pink.
and
friable

Legen d : p is a "part of" l i n k


t is a "type o f " l i n k
I is a "leads t o " l i n k
c is a "characteristic o f " l i n k

FIG. 3.8. Example of a network of a chapter from a nursing text on wounds (Holley et aI., 1 979). The use of linking relationships force the learner to
consider the way concepts are related.
1 28 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

ACADEMIC GUIDE MAP


FOR "THEORIES "
INVENTOR/PRIOR
HISTORY

�ORY N�
PARTS! CHARACTERISTICS!
COMPONENTS DESCRIPTORS

� J-
COMPETING
\ SIMIlAR/ANALOGOUS
THEORIES THEORIES

y�
EVlDENCE IMPLICAnONS

FIG. 3.9. A generic fill-in-the-blank concept map that can be used to understand any
theory in any domain of knowledge. DeSCriptive information could be filled in the circles
with the links labeled as the type of information. When you fill in the various "boxes" -for
example, giving evidence for and against the theory-you will be developing a "deep"
knowledge of the theory (Dansereau, 2001).
COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE 1 29

generic map for understanding theories to any class in which theories are being
taught, you can think of yourself as being "armed" with an information aid. As you
fill in the boxes and circles, you will develop an enhanced understanding of the
theory you are learning.

Matrices
When the material to be comprehended involves comparisons of several topics
along a number of dimensions, a matrix is the representation of choice. (The word
matrices is the plural of matrix.) Suppose, for example, that you are reading a pas­
sage about wars. The purpose of the passage is to compare and contrast various an­
tecedent conditions of war and to consider their effect. Suppose further that the
wars being considered are the Revolutionary War, World War I, World War II, the
Korean Conflict, and the Vietnam Conflict. In order to understand the nature of
these wars, you need to organize the information so that commonalities and distinc­
tions will emerge. A suggested matrix for this information is shown in Table 3.3.
By filling in the empty cells in Table 3.3, selected categories of information can
readily be compared and similarities and differences can easily be spotted. A coher­
ent "pattern" of information about these wars can then be extracted. The framework
can be applied to other wars involving other countries to determine, for example, if
there are universal commonalities for all wars. Similarly, matrices can be useful
when a judgment has to be made about products or courses of action that differ
along multiple dimensions. If you are familiar with the way in which the magazine
Consumer Reports provides information about products to consumers, you will rec­
ognize that this is the technique that they use. For example, if you want to buy a re­
frigerator, you will find that Consumer Reports rates several different brands and
models of refrigerators along many dimensions. The models would be listed in the
left-hand column and the dimensions across the top, such as cost to operate, ease of
opening the door, how well it maintains a set temperature, storage space built into
the door, and the other features that differ among refrigerators. The ratings in each
cell are pictorial (colored circles) that help to convert a large amount of information
to a format that is comprehensible in a single glance. A similar technique was used

TABLE 3 . 3
Example of a Matrix Graphic Organizer

War
Revolutionary World World Korean Vietnam
War War ! War !! Conflict Conflict
Major precipitating events
U.s. justification for the war
"Other side" justification for
the war
Number of lives lost-each
side
Major battles
Resolution
Types of weapons
Relationship to later war,
if any
Note. Matrices are particularly good spatial arrays when the information involves several different
topics (e.g., wars) that are being compared on several dimensions (e.g., characteristics of war).
1 30 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

20% Play-or-
Vol Simple Pay
Goal Subsidy Mandate Mandate

Decreased n umber
of uninsured
I ncrease
efficiency
Limit costs for
workers

Control small
business costs
Contain
rnment costs

_ Well o Somewhat o Not at all

FIG. 3. 1 0. A shaded matrix that compares three possible health care plans compared on
five "goals." The use of shading with a matrix allows for an easier comparison among the
plans. Adapted from RAND (1 992). Health care and the uninsured: Who will pay? RAND
Research Review, XVI, pp. tHl.

by the RAND Corporation (1992, p. 7) in their analysis of three different plans for
financing health insurance. Look at this matrix, which is presented in Fig. 3.10.
As you can see, the RAND Corporation listed five desirable goals for any health
care plan. These are listed under "goal." The three health care plans they compared
are a 20% voluntary subsidy, a simple mandate or law that would require employ­
ers to provide health insurance, and a play-or-pay plan that would allow employers
to shop for the best plan for their employees. The degree of shading in a square is an
indication of how well the particular plan satisfies a goal. Which plan seems the best
given their evaluation and the way they presented the data? It is easy to see that the
third option meets three goals very well, one goal somewhat, and one goal not at all.
Thus, it would seem that the third plan is the best overall, but this conclusion is only
warranted if all of the goals are equal in importance. If the containment of govern­
ment costs is much more important than any of the others, then the third plan is
not a good one because it does not satisfy this goal. The relative importance of each
goal depends on individual judgment that, ideally, is informed by knowledge of
the issues.
Matrices can also be used to organize information so that it can be used more eas­
ily. Day, Rodin, and Stoltzfus (I990) investigated the effect of changing the repre­
sentation of information on the ease with which it is used. A medication schedule
that was given to a (real) patient is shown in Fig. 3.1 1 . The list format shown on
the left side of Fig. 3.11 is the way that the physician presented the medication
schedule to the patient. The matrix format shown on the right provides the same in­
formation, but is clearly easier to use. Not surprisingly, Day, Rodin, and Stoltzfus
found that both young and old subjects were more accurate in their understanding
of and memory for the medication schedule when it was provided in a matrix for­
mat. It is clear that some representations will facilitate the use of information and
COMPREHENSION: THE REASON FOR LANGUAGE 131

LIST FORMAT MATRIX FORMAT

'VIII
Inderal - 1 tablet 3 times a day
Lanoxin - 1 tablet every a.m.
Cafafate - 1 tablet before meals � § 'S' (fj
Qj " 0 Qj
and at bedtime Inderal .I ./ ./
Zantac - 1 tablet every 1 2 hours
Lanoxin .I
(twice a day)
-
Quinaglute 1 tablet 4 times a day Cafafate .I ./ ./ .I
Coumadin - 1 tablet a day Zantac ./ .I
Quinaglute .I ./ .I .I
Coumadin .I

FIG. 3. I I . Two representations of medication schedules for an elderly patient. The list on
the left is the format that was given to the patient. The matrix on the right was devised by
Day, Rodin, and Stoltzfus (1990). Adapted from Day, R. S., Rodin, G. c., and Stoltzfus,
E. R. (1990). Alternative representations for medication instructions: Effects on young and old
adults. Paper presented at the 3rd Cognitive Aging Conference, Atlanta, GA.

others will hinder it. One goal is to understand which representation matches the
underlying structure of the information being conveyed.

General Guidelines and Principles

In a study of "at-risk students" (those identified as being at risk of failing and not
completing their education), Pogrow (1992) concluded that these students have aca­
demic difficulties because "they do not understand 'understanding' " (p. 90). What
he means by this is that these students do not know what they need to do to ensure
that information is acquired in a way that is meaningful and resistant to forgetting.
Many ideas about learning and knowing are foreign to them such as: complex infor­
mation will contain multiple interacting concepts; learners need to understand how
concepts relate to one another; difficult material has to be questioned, explained,
drawn, and discussed; and comprehension needs to be continually monitored.
There is ample empirical evidence that more of these "at-risk" students could com­
plete their education if they were taught how to improve their comprehension.
Techniques that promote understanding are critically important in our complex
world. The ability to comprehend difficult material is empowering because it allows
us to understand and act intelligently on a wide range of issues including the pur­
chase of a new refrigerator, understanding how AIDS is transmitted, or deciding
how to vote on a variety of health insurance initiatives. We all need a society in
which citizens think and respond thoughtfully, if we are to prosper, or even survive,
in a time of skyrocketing complexity.
All of the strategies for comprehension require learners to monitor their under­
standing of the information. They are all active cognitive strategies that facilitate the
construction of meaningful representations. The graphic organizers offer ways to
transform text into explicit spatial representations that display relationships among
concepts. They all make abstract concepts more concrete. Like all good cognitive
strategies, they require the learner to relate new information to prior knowledge in a
1 32 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE

way that makes remembering most efficient. Like many of the other thinking skills
presented in this book, they require effort and must be practiced in order to be use­
ful. It is not enough to read about them. They have to be used in a variety of situa­
tions to ensure transfer.
Although most of this chapter has been concerned with the process of compre­
hension, which is going from surface structure to underlying structure, many of the
principles can be used in language production or going from underlying structure
to surface structure. The task of writing involves transforming your internalized
meaning into words. Many people have difficulty with writing because they find
that this is a difficult translation. Kellogg (1990) compared the quality of persuasive
papers written by college students who either prepared an outline before they
began their papers (a linear display) or used a clustering technique in which associ­
ated ideas were first generated from memory and then connected with lines that
showed how the ideas were related. He found that the students who were required
to outline before they wrote improved in their organization and writing style (writ­
ing is a mostly linear activity), and the students who used clustering produced a
larger number of ideas than those who used outlines. I will return to these results in
Chapter 10 on creativity where I discuss the generation of ideas.
Graphic organizers, like clustering or flowcharts, or matrices, can be terrific aids
in the writing process. Suppose you were to write an essay about acquired immune
deficiency syndrome (AIDS). You could begin the planning process by considering
the kinds of links employed in networking (type of, part of, leads to, evidence
for, characteristics of, and analogy). What "types of" people are most and least
at risk? What is the "evidence for" AIDS (laboratory tests, symptoms)? What are
the "characteristics of" at-risk groups or risky activities? Some people have called
for quarantine, which is "analogous to" the way the way society has responded to
other dread diseases. Once you have considered the information you want to pre­
sent, the relationship among the facts can be depicted in a network. The network
offers a nonlinear alternative to outlines when planning the writing process. Thus,
by "running comprehension strategies backward," they can be used to produce
language (spoken or written) instead of their more usual role in comprehending
language.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

1 . What Is the Goal?


The thinking goal addressed in this chapter is how to enhance comprehension
when the medium for communication is natural language. A more formal way of
saying the same thing is that the goal is to create an accurate underlying representa­
tion (Le., re-presentation of the underlying message) from the surface structure pro­
vided in speech and written text. The newly acquired knowledge will ideally be
stored in memory in a way that will make it easily accessible when it is needed.

2 . What Is Known?

This step requires determining where you are before selecting the appropriate
thinking skill. Are you in a situation in which there is likely to be deliberate attempts
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 1 33

to bias your thinking on an issue (e.g., consumer decisions, political rhetoric)?


Do you have to learn from a text that contains information on which you will soon
be tested? Is the information particularly complex? Do you already have good back­
ground knowledge? What is the structure of the information and the reason why
you need or want to understand it? Will a graphic presentation help with compre­
hension? If so, does the material match a structure such as a linear array, hierarchy,
matrix, network or flowchart?

3 . Which Thinking Skill or Skills


Will Get You to Your Goal?
The skills described in this chapter are those involved in comprehending lan­
guage. As with every list of skills, users need to monitor their comprehension to de­
termine what is and what isn't being understood. The process of skill use often
requires trying a different skill if the one being used is not promoting understand­
ing. The following comprehension skills were presented in this chapter. Review
each skill and be sure that you understand when and how to use each one.

• Recognizing and defending against the inappropriate use of emotional language,


labeling, name calling, ambiguity, vagueness, and arguments by etymology
• Developing the ability to detect misuse of definitions, reification, euphemism,
and bureaucratese
• Thinking about the reason for a communication, the background knowledge of
the listener, and the context when deciding what and how to communicate
• Understanding the use of framing with leading questions, and negation
• Using analogies appropriately, which includes examining the nature of the
similarity and its relationship to the conclusion
• Deliberately giving a variety of examples when thinking about members of a
category so that you are not thinking about category members in terms of a
prototype (e.g., thinking about many ways to be successful, not just the most
common examples like making a high salary)
• Recognizing the emotional components of some words and the way word
choices can affect how you think and feel
• Recognizing when an anchor may be biasing your judgments about a quantity
or cost and deliberately trying other values that could be alternative anchors
• Employing questioning and explaining as a skill for text comprehension
• Practicing at retrieval of information so that remembering becomes more accu­
rate and easier with spaced practice
• Selecting and using graphic organizers (linear arrays, hierarchies, networks,
matrices, flowcharts)

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?


Have you been monitoring your understanding? Can you paraphrase a passage
with the book closed? Did you systematically consider all of the ways in which we
can be misled with language that were presented in this chapter? Did you consider
the reason for the communication and have you satisfied that reason?
1 34 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LA.;.�GUAGE

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Psycholinguistics is the branch of psychology that is concerned with under·


standing how people produce and comprehend language.
2. Psychologists view language as comprising two components or levels: a
meaning component (underlying representation) and a speech sound componenl
(surface structure). The problem of comprehension is moving from a thought by thE
sender (underlying structure) through language and then reconstruction of thE
thought by the receiver.
3. Language is ambiguous when a single surface structure has two or more pos­
sible underlying representations.
4. Language and thought exert mutual influences on each other with our
thoughts determining the language we use and, in turn, the language we use re­
shaping our thoughts.
5. Six rules of communication were presented. Every time we attempt to com­
municate with others, we utilize these rules to determine what information we will
convey and how to express the information.
6. Language comprehension requires that the listener make many inferences.
The kinds of inferences we make depends on context, manner, and the words se­
lected to convey the message.
7. There are many ways that words can be used to mislead the listener deliber­
ately. Several ways that the choice of words can influence thought were presented.
The deliberate use of emotional and nonemotional words is designed to influence
how you think about a topic.
8. Emotional words often elicit strong mental images. Because images are
highly resistant to forgetting, they are readily available when the topic is mentioned.
9. Prototypes, or the most typical member of a category, are usually thought of
first when we think about an example of a category. These prototypes bias what we
think. This bias can be overcome with deliberate practice at generating examples
that are not typical.
10. A value that is easily available in memory can unconsciously serve as an an­
chor or starting point that we use to estimate quantities or cost. We need to think
consciously of many different possible values that could serve as anchors as a way
of reducing the effect of anchors.
1 1 . The way in which we judge or evaluate a situation depends on the context in
which it is embedded and the way it contrasts with similar recent events. Our judg­
ments are strongly determined by recent experiences.
12. Strategies to improve the comprehension of text were described. They all
require learners to attend to the structure of the information and to make the rela­
tionships among concepts explicit. Multiple representations-both visual spatial
displays and verbal strategies-are used as aids to comprehension.

TERMS TO KNOW

You should be able to define or describe the following terms and concepts. If you
find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to reread the section in
which it is discussed.
TERMS TO KNOW 1 35

Psycholinguistics. The branch of psychology that is concerned with the acquisition,


production, comprehension, and usage of language.
Underlying Representation. The meaning component of language. It's the thought
that you want to convey with an utterance. Compare with surface structure.
Surface Structure. The sounds of an utterance or the outward appearance of a lan­
guage expression. Compare with underlying representation.
Given/New Distinction. The ratio of known (given) information to new information
in a communication. It is a primary determinant of the difficulty of a communication.
Cognitive Economy. Any process that reduces the mental workload and makes
thinking or remembering less effortful.
Prototype. The best or most typical example of a category. For example, dog is the
prototype for the category "animal."
Prototypical thinking. Using the most typical member in a category as a guide to
making inferences about other members of that category.
Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis of Linguistic Relativity. The hypothesis that language, at
least in part, determines or influences thought.
Semantic Slanting. The deliberate use of words designed to create a particular atti­
tude or foster certain beliefs.
Ambiguous. An utterance is ambiguous when it can have more than one meaning
or underlying representation.
Vagueness. A lack of precision in a communication. A communication is vague if it
does not specify enough details for its intended purpose.
Equivocation. A change in the meaning of a word in the course of the same discussion.
Etymology. Reference to the origin of a word in order to determine its meaning.
Reification. Occurs when an abstract concept is given a name and then treated as
though it were a concrete object.
Bureaucratese. The use of formal, stilted language that is often unfamiliar to people
who lack special training.
Euphemism. The substitution of a desirable term for a less desirable or offensive one.
Framing. Occurs when a question is asked in a way that suggests what the correct
response should be. The reader is "led" into assuming a particular perspective or
point of view.
Risk Adverse. A general preference for options that do not involve possible loss
over options that involve possible gain, even when the expected value is higher for
the option that describes a loss.
Negation. The use of denial to imply that a fact is plausible.
Anchoring. The unconscious use of a value that is easily accessible in memory as a
"starting point" for making a judgment about a quantity or cost.
Re-representation. The deliberate use of multiple ways to represent information­
concept maps, spatial arrays, and verbal strategies-as a means of enhancing com­
prehension and memory.
SQ3R. A strategy for comprehension that requires the use of questioning and para­
phrase. The letters stand for Survey, Question, Read, Recite, and Review.
Paraphrase. Restating ideas in your own words.
Overlearning. Reviewing material after it is learned so that recall becomes auto­
matic and less effortful.
Reciprocal Peer Questioning. The process of having learners pose thoughtful ques­
tions that they take turns answering.
Generic Questions. Question "sterns" that can be modified and applied to many
different topics.
1 36 3. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THOUGHT AND LAl'lGUAGE

Concept Maps (sometimes called graphic organizers). The use of spatial displays
to organize information.
Linear Arrays. A graphic organizer in which information is presented in a list format.
Hierarchies. A type of graphic organizer that uses a tree structure. Most useful
when information is organized according to class inclusion rules.
Networks. Graphic organizers in which types of relationships among concepts are
depicted.
Matrix. A rectangular array that is useful when the information presented involves
comparisons along several dimensions.
4

Reasoning: Drawing
Deductively Valid
Conclusions

Contents
Logical and Psychological Syllogistic Reasoning
Pragmatism and Logic Circle Diagrams for Determining
Inductive and Deductive Reasoning Validity
Linear Ordering Verbal Rules for Determining
Linear Diagrams Validity
Confusing Truth and Validity Syllogisms in Everyday Contexts
If, Then Statements Missing Quantifiers
Tree Diagrams Changing Attitudes with
If, Then Reasoning in Everyday Syllogisms
Contexts Common Errors in Syllogistic
Negation Reasoning
Confirmation Bias Illicit Conversions
Permission and Obligation Schemata Probabilistic Reasoning
If, and Only If Bounded Rationality
Chained Conditionals Reasoning in Everyday Contexts
If, Then Reasoning in Legal Contexts Reasoning With Diagrams
Combinatorial Reasoning Reasoning Gone Wrong
Applying the Framework
Chapter Summary
Terms to Know

1 37
1 38 4. REASO�I�G

As far as Joan's opponent was concerned, the debate wasn't going well. It was clear from
the sea of nodding heads and sounds of "uh huh" and "yeah" that Joan was scoring points
and convincing the audience; whereas, he seemed to be losing support every time he
spoke. He wasn't surprised; he had been warned. Joan had studied reasoning and now
knew how to make people believe anything. Soon she would have everyone convinced
that the war was justified and what was wrong was right. The way she's going, she could
probably make people believe that day is night. It certainly wasn't fair, but what can you
expect from someone who studied reasoning?

This fictional vignette was taken from a real-life incident. I was present at a debate
where one debater accused the other of cheating by using reasoning. At the time,
I thought that this was pretty funny because I had come to think of reasoning as an
important critical thinking skill-the sort of skill that you would use to make valid
conclusions when dealing with information that is complex and emotional. To the
losing side of this debate, it was a trick. Trick, skill, or strategy, reasoning is the best
way to decide whom and what to believe.

LOGICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL

The trick, of course, is to reason well. It isn't easy and it isn't automatic.
-Kahane (1980, p. 3)

Reasoning is often taken to be the hallmark of the human species. Colloquially, rea­
soning tells us "what follows what." When we reason, we use our knowledge about
one or more related statements that we can reasonably believe are true to determine
if another statement, the conclusion, is true. A conclusion is an inferential belief that
is derived from other statements. The ability to reason well is a critical thinking skill
that is crucial in science, mathematics, law, forecasting, diagnosing, and just about
every other context you can imagine. In fact, I can't think of an academic or "real­
world" context in which the ability to reason well is not of great importance.
Many definitions of the term critical thinking identify reasoning as central to the
concept as seen in the definition that was derived from three rounds of rankings by
school administrators in the United States. The procedure they used to derive their
preferred definition of critical thinking is called the delphi technique, which refers
to a method for achieving agreement among experts in some field. In this case, defi­
nitions were circulated among all participants three times. They agreed that "critical
thinking is . . . cohesive, logical reasoning patterns" (Stahl & Stahl, 199 1 , p. 84).

Pragmatism and Logic

When we reason logically, we are following a set of rules that specify how we
"ought to" derive conclusions. Logic is the branch of philosophy that explicitly states
the rules for deriving valid conclusions. The laws of logic provide the standard
against which we assess the quality of someone's reasoning (Garnham & Oakhill,
1994). According to logic, a conclusion is valid if it necessarily follows from some
statements that are accepted as facts. The factual statements are called premises.
Conclusions that are not in accord with the rules of logic are illogical. Although we
maintain that the ability for rational, logical thought is unique to humans, all too
LOGICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL 1 39

often we reach invalid or illogical conclusions. This fact has led Hunt (1982, p. 121) to
award "A flunking grade in logic for the world's only logical animal."
Psychologists who study reasoning have been concerned with how people
process information in reasoning tasks. The fact is that, in our everyday thinking,
the psychological processes quite often are not logical. In a classic paper on the rela­
tion between logic and thinking, Henle (1962) noted that even though everyday
thought does not generally follow the formal rules of logic, people use their own im­
perfect rules. If we were not logical, at least some of the time, we wouldn't be able to
understand each other, "follow one another's thinking, reach common decisions,
and work together" (Henle, 1962, p. 374). To demonstrate this point, stop now and
work on one of the problems Henle posed to her subjects in one of her studies:

A group of women were discussing their household problems. Mrs. Shivers broke the
ice by saying: ''I'm so glad we're talking about these problems. It's so important to talk
about things that are in our minds. We spend so much of our time in the kitchen that, of
course, household problems are in our minds. So it is important to talk about them."
(Does it follow that it is important to talk about them? Give your reasoning.) (p. 370)

Do not go on until you decide if it is valid to conclude that Mrs. Shivers is correct
when she says that it is important to talk about household problems. Why did you
answer as you did?
When Henle posed this problem to graduate students, she found that some stu­
dents arrived at the wrong answer (as defined by the rules of logic); whereas others
arrived at the right answer for the wrong reasons. Consider the following answer
given by one of her subjects: "No. It is not important to talk about things that are in
our minds unless they worry us, which is not the case" (p. 370). Where did this sub­
ject go wrong? Instead of deciding if the conclusion followed logically from the ear­
lier statements, she added her own opinions about what sorts of things it is important
to talk about. Thus, even though the answer is incorrect as evaluated by the standard
rules of logic, it is correct by the subject's own rules. Consider this answer: "Yes. It
could be very important for the individual doing the talking and possibly to some of
those listening, because it is important for people to 'get a load off their chest,' but not
for any other reason, unless in the process one or the other learns something new and
of value" (p. 370). This time, the participant gave the correct answer, but for the
wrong reasons. This participant, like the first one, added her own beliefs to the prob­
lem instead of deriving her conclusions solely on the basis of the information pre­
sented. Henle has termed this error in reasoning the failure to accept the logical task.
It seems that in everyday use of reasoning, we don't determine if a conclusion is
valid solely on the basis of the statements we are given. Instead, we alter the state­
ments we're given according to our beliefs and then decide if a conclusion follows
from the altered statements. We function under a kind of personal logic in which we
use our personal beliefs about the world to formulate conclusions about related issues.
Psychologists and philosophers have puzzled over the finding that for some
everyday and formal reasoning tasks, most people seem to behave as though they
are using the rules of logic, but for other reasoning tasks, there seems to be little evi­
dence that the laws of logic are being followed. In other words, whether most of us
appear logical depends on the type of reasoning problem that is being studied.
Simon and Kaplan (1989) do not find this state of affairs surprising. They believe
that "intelligent behavior is adaptive and hence must take on strikingly different
forms in different environments" (p. 38). More recent studies support the conclusion
that people have more than one way of reasoning, sometimes following the laws of
1 40 4. REASONING

logic and sometimes twisting or abandoning them. For example, Rips (200 1 , p. 1 33)
concluded that "arguments have different roles and purposes, and people assess
them differently depending on which purpose they have in mind."
The word pragmatic refers to anything that is practical. In real life, people have a
reason for reasoning, and sometimes the laws of logic are at odds with the setting,
consequences, and commonly agreed on reasons and rules for deriving conclusions.
As Henle's participants showed in the previous example, in real life, we add our
own beliefs and knowledge to the facts we are given when we determine if a conclu­
sion is supported by the premises. In most everyday settings, this is a pragmatic or
practical approach to reasoning problems.

Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

Actual thinking has its own logic; it is orderly, reasonable, reflective.


-Dewey (1 933, p. 75)

A distinction is often made between inductive and deductive reasoning. (See Chapter 6,
''Thinking as Hypothesis Testing" for a related discussion of this topic.) In inductive
reasoning observations are collected that support or suggest a conclusion.
It is a way of projecting information from known examples to the unknown (Heit, 2000).
For example, if every person you have ever seen has only one head, you would use this
evidence to support the conclusion (or suggest the hypothesis) that everyone in the
world has only one head. Of course, you can't be absolutely certain of this fact. It's al­
ways possible that someone you've never met has two heads. If you met just one person
with two heads, your conclusion must be wrong. Thus, with inductive reasoning you
can never prove that your conclusion or hypothesis is correct, but you can disprove it.
When we reason inductively, we collect facts and use them to provide support or
dis confirmation for conclusions or hypotheses. It's how we discover what the world is
like. Lopes (1982) described induction this way: "Scientists do it; lay people do it; even
birds and beasts do it. But the process is mysterious and full of paradox . . . induction
cannot be justified on logical grounds" (p. 626). We reason inductively both informally
in the course of everyday living, and formally in experimental research. For this rea­
son, hypothesis testing is sometimes described as the process of inductive reasoning.
When we reason inductively, we generalize from our experiences to create beliefs or
expectations. Sometimes inductive reasoning is described as reasoning "up" from par­
ticular instances or experiences in the world to a belief about the nature of the world.
In deductive reasoning, we begin with statements known or believed to be true,
like "everyone has only one head," and then conclude or infer that Karen, a woman
you've never met, will have only one head. This conclusion follows logically from
the earlier statement. If we know that it is true that everyone has only one head,
then it must also be true that any specific person will have only one head. This con­
clusion necessarily follows from the belief; if the belief is true, the conclusion must
be true. Deductive reasoning is sometimes described as reasoning "down" from
beliefs about the nature of the world to particular instances. Rips (1988) argues that
deduction is a general-purpose mechanism for cognitive tasks. According to Rips,
deduction "enables us to answer questions from information stored in memory, to
plan actions according to goals, and to solve certain kinds of puzzles" (p. 1 1 7). The
notion of "reasoning up" from observations and "reasoning down" from hypothe­
ses is schematically shown in Fig. 4 . 1 .
LINEAR ORDERING 141

�-f4\[O) The
� Horri ble -------'

© King Features Syndicate, Courtesy KFS, INC.

Although it is common to make a distinction between inductive and deductive


reasoning, the distinction may not be a particularly useful description of how peo­
ple reason in real life. In everyday contexts, we switch from inductive to deductive
reasoning in the course of thinking. Our hypotheses and beliefs guide the observa­
tions we make, and our observations, in turn, modify our hypotheses and beliefs.
Often, this process will involve a continuous interplay of inductive and deductive
reasoning. Thinking in real-world contexts almost always involves the use of multi­
ple thinking skills.

LINEAR ORDERING

Reasoning is simply a matter of getting your facts straight.


-B. F. Anderson (1 980, p. 62)
1 42 4. REASONING

Inductive Reasoning Deductive Reasoning

Conclusion Everyone has Start Here Everyone has


one head. one head.

Start Here Conclusion


Observe people: Each has one head. LaTisha, a person you've
never met, has one head

FIG. 4. I . A pictorial distinction between deductive (reasoning "down" from premises) and
inductive reasoning (reasoning "up" from examples). In most real-world settings, we use
both types of reasoning recursively.

Joel is stronger than Bill, but not as strong as Richard. Richard is stronger than Joel,
but not as strong as Donald. Who is strongest and who is second strongest?
Although I'm sure that you've never met Joel, Donald, Richard, and Bill, I'm also
sure you could answer this question. The premises or statements in this problem give
information about the orderly relationship among the terms; hence, it is called a lin­
ear ordering or linear syllogism. Like all deductive reasoning problems, the premises
are used to derive valid conclusions-conclusions that must be true if the premises
are true. In linear ordering problems, we're concerned with orderly relationships in
which the relationships among the terms can be arranged in a straight-line array.

Linear Diagrams

How did you solve the problem about Joel, Donald, Richard, and Bill? Most people
work line by line, ordering the people as specified in each line:

"Joel is stronger than Bill, but not as strong as Richard" becomes:

St ron
g
� RiChard
Joel
Bill

Not Strong
LINEAR ORDERING 1 43

t
"Richard is stronger than Joel, but not as strong as Donald" adds Donald to the previous
representation:
s
t ro
ng

Donald
Richard
Joel
Bill

Not St ro n
g

Thus, it is easy to "see" that Donald is strongest and Richard is second strongest.

Research with linear syllogisms has shown that people rely, at least in part, on spa­
tial imagery or some sort of spatial representation to answer the question.
Work through the following pairs of linear syllogisms. Try to decide if one mem­
ber of each pair is easier to solve than the other:

1 . A. Julio is smarter than Diana.


Diana is smarter than Ellen.
Who is smartest? Julio, Diana, Ellen, or don't know.
or
B. JoAnne is taller than Susan.
Rebeccah is taller than JoAnne.
Who is shortest? JoAnne, Susan, Rebeccah, or don't know.

2. A. Pat is not taller than Jim.


Jim is shorter than Tiffany.
Who is tallest? Pat, Jim, Tiffany, or don't know.
or
B. Les is worse than Moshe.
Harold is worse than Moshe.
Who is worst? Les, Moshe, Harold, or don't know.

3. A. Stuart doesn't run faster than Louis.


Louis doesn't run slower than Dena.
Who is slowest? Stuart, Lois, Dena, or don't know.
or
B. Howard is fatter than Ace.
Ace is thinner than Kyla.
Who is thinnest? Howard, Ace, Kyla, or don't know.

As you worked through these problems, did some seem more difficult to you
than others? You probably found problem lA to be the easiest. Research has shown
that when the second term in the first premise is the first term in the second premise
(Diana in problem l A), and when the comparison terms are congruent (smarter,
smarter, smartest), the linear ordering is fairly easy to solve. Problem I B does not
follow this simple form. The comparisons are between JoAnne and Susan and Re­
beccah and Susan. In addition, the comparison terms are not congruent (taller, taller,
shortest), The correct answer is lA for Julio. The correct answer for IB is Susan.
Problem 2A contains the negation term "not," which adds to the complexity of the
problem. In addition, information is given in terms of both taller and shorter, which
makes this a difficult problem. The correct answer is Tiffany. (Pat could be the same
1 44 4. REASONING

height or shorter than Jim.) You can represent this relationship graphically as:

Tall

t- Tiffany
t- Jim
Tt
Pat (same as or short er than Jim)

Short Shor

Although problem 2B contains all congruent comparison terms (worse, worse,


worst), some people find it tricky because we don't know if Les or Harold is worst.
In addition, research has shown that it is more difficult to comprehend terms like
"worse" than it is to use terms like "better" because it denotes that all three are bad,
whereas "better" is a more neutral term. (The correct answer is "don't know.") Prob­
lem 3A contains two negative terms as well as incongruent comparison terms
(faster, slower, slowest). From the information given, we can't determine who is
slowest. Problem 3B is somewhat easier because it doesn't contain negatives, but it
does contain incongruent comparison terms (fatter, thinner, thinnest). The answer
as to who is thinnest is Ace.
As you worked through these problems, you should have discovered some of the
following psychological principles of linear orderings:

1 . Orderings are easiest to solve when comparison terms are congruent (e.g.,
short, shorter, shortest).
2. Solutions will be facilitated if the second term in the first premise is the first
term in the second premise (A is better than B; B is better than C).
3. Negations make the problem more difficult (e.g., A is not hairier than B).
4. Comparisons between adjacent terms (e.g., Julio and Diana in problem 1A) are
more difficult than comparisons between end terms (Julio and Ellen) (Potts,
1972).
5. When you are faced with a difficult syllogism of any sort, a good strategy for solving it
is to draw a spatial array. With a linear syllogism, draw a linear array, so that the rela­
tionships among the terms can be inspected visually.
6. Comparison terms that limit the meaning of a sentence, like worse and
dumber, are more difficult to process than more general and neutral terms like
better and smarter. The adjectives that connote a bias (e.g., worse, dumber) are
called marked adjectives, whereas the neutral adjectives are called unmarked
adjectives.

These summary remarks can be used as an aid for clear communication of lin­
early ordered information. When you want someone to understand a linear order­
ing, use congruent terms, make the second term in the first premise the first term in
the second premise, and avoid negations and marked adjectives. These few rules for
communicating linear information show a basic cognitive principle: Negative infor­
mation (no, not) is more difficult to process than positive information, in part
because it seems to place additional demands on working memory (Matlin, 2002).
There are many advantages to using diagrams when dealing with verbal informa­
tion, including reducing the load on working memory and making relationship
obvious and visible.
LINEAR ORDERING 1 45

Confusing Truth and validity

Knowing is only part of being educated, thinking and reasoning with what we
know completes it.
-Schauble and Glaser (1 990, p. 9)

Logically, the rules for deciding if a conclusion is valid are the same no matter what
terms we use. In the first example in this section, I could provide the premise that
Donald is stronger than Richard or I could substitute any name that I wanted (Igor
is stronger than Yu-Chin or any letter or symbol, C is stronger than A). The truth is
not important in these examples, because the premises are treated as though they
were true. This probably bothered some of you. Suppose I said,

Your sister is uglier than the wicked witch in the Wizard of Oz.
You are uglier than your sister.
Therefore, you are uglier than the wicked witch in the Wizard of Oz.

You'd probably protest this conclusion. You may not even have a sister, but given
the premises, the conclusion is valid. Test it for yourself. However, that doesn't
make it true. Chapter 5 will address the issue of determining the truth or believabil­
ity of the premises. So far, we've only considered the question of validity: whether
a conclusion must be true if the premises are true. People very often have trouble
separating truth from validity. This is particularly difficult when the conclusion
runs counter to cherished beliefs or strong emotion.
Although the rules of logic dictate that content is irrelevant to the conclusions we
formulate, in most real-life situations, content does influence how we choose valid
conclusions. It is possible to construct deductive reasoning problems so that the be­
liefs most people maintain conflict with logical conclusions. Belief bias or confirma­
tion bias occurs when an individual's beliefs interfere with her or his selection of
the logical conclusion. This effect has been demonstrated many times and is so per­
vasive that it interferes with good thinking in almost every context (Nickerson,
1 998). We all seem to have difficulty in thinking critically when the reasoned conclu­
sion is one that we do not believe to be true. Consider this example, which dates
back to 1944 (Morgan & Morton). Obviously, most Americans in 1944 had very
strong beliefs about World War II, which clearly influenced their reasoning process.
When presented with deductive reasoning problems, Americans were more likely
to select conclusions that agreed with their belief biases than conclusions that ran
counter to their belief biases.
It should come as no surprise to you that human reasoning becomes illogical
when we are discussing emotional issues. This is true for people in every strata of
society, even for justices of the United States Supreme Court. When Justice William
O. Douglas was new to the Supreme Court, Chief Justice Charles Evans Hughes
gave him these words of advice, "You must remember one thing. At the constitu­
tional level where we work, ninety percent of any decision is emotional. The ratio­
nal part of us supplies the reasons for supporting our predilections" (Hunt, 1982,
p. 129). Unfortunately, appellate legal proceedings are sometimes exercises in poli­
tics, with decisions changing as frequently as the political climate. Legal "reason­
ing" has sometimes served as a framework to persuade others that a conclusion is
valid. If you understand how to formulate valid inferences, you'll be able to with­
stand and recognize its misuse by those who would use it to their advantage.
1 46 4. REASO:\,I:\,G

IF, THEN STATEMENTS

Reason, of course, is weak, when measured against its never-ending task.


Weak, indeed, compared with the follies and passions of mankind, which, we
must admit, almost entirely control our human destinies, in great things and
small.
-Albert Einstein (1 879-1 955)

If, then statements, like the other examples of reasoning presented in this chapter,
use premises that are known or believed to be true to determine if a valid conclusion
follows. If, then statements are concerned with contingency relationships-some
events are dependent or contingent on the occurrence of others. If the first part of
the contingency relationship is true, then the second part must also be true. If, then
statements are sometimes called conditional logic or propositional logic. Work
through the four following if, then statements. Decide if the third statement is
a valid conclusion.

1 . If she is rich, she wears diamonds.


She is rich.
Therefore, she wears diamonds.
Valid or Invalid?

2. If she is rich, she wears diamonds.


She isn't wearing diamonds.
Therefore, she isn't rich.
Valid or Invalid?

3. If she is rich, she wears diamonds.


She is wearing diamonds.
Therefore, she is rich.
Valid or Invalid?

4. If she is rich, she wears diamonds.


She isn't rich.
Therefore, she isn't wearing diamonds.
Valid or Invalid?

In each of these problems, the first premise begins with the word if; the then is not
explicitly stated, but can be inferred ("then she wears diamonds"). The first part of
this premise ("If she is rich") is called the antecedent; the second part ("she wears
diamonds") is called the consequent.

Tree Diagrams

Like the other types of deductive reasoning problems, conditional statements can be
represented with a spatial display. Tree diagrams, diagrams in which the critical in­
formation is represented along "branches," like a tree, are used in several chapters
in this book, and can be used to determine validity with if, then deductive reasoning
problems. Tree diagrams are very handy representational forms in many situations
and are well worth the trouble of learning to use. We will use tree diagrams in
IF, THEN STATEMENTS 1 47

Chapter 7 on understanding likelihood, Chapter 9 on problem solving, and Chapter


1 0 on creativity.
Tree diagrams are easy to begin. Every tree diagram begins with a "start" point.
A start point is a dot on the paper that you label "start." Everyone finds the first
step easy.

Start

The dots are more formally called nodes, and branches (lines) come out from nodes.
The branches represent everything that can happen when you are at that node. In if,
then problems, there are two states that are possible from the start node. In this exam­
ple, either she is rich or she is not rich. There are two possibilities, so there will be two
branches coming from the start node. The antecedent is the first event on the "tree"
with a second branch representing the consequent. The validity of the conclusion can

<
be determined by examining the branches. Let's try this with the first problem.
"If she is rich" becomes:

rich

Start

n ot rich

"She wears diamonds" is added as a second set of branches by showing that the
"rich" node is always followed by "diamonds," but the "not rich" node may or may
not be followed by "diamonds." We put both possibilities on the branches leading
from "not rich" because we are not given any information about the relationship be­
tween being "not rich" and "wearing diamonds."

wears diamonds

rich

Start ? wears diamo nds

? doesn't wear diamo nds

When we are told that "She is rich," circle the branch or branches that has this label
and move along the branches from the "rich" node and conclude that she "wears dia­
monds." There is only one node in this diagram that represents the possibility that
she is rich, and this node has only one branch attached from it-the branch that leads
to "wears diamonds." Once you locate the "rich" node, the only possible consequent
is "wears diamonds." Thus, the conclusion to problem number 1 is valid. The techni­
cal term for this problem is affirming the antecedent. In this case, the second premise
affirms or indicates the antecedent is true; therefore, its consequent is true.
Problem 2 also contains a valid conclusion. The tree diagram is exactly the same as
in the first problem because the same if, then statements are made. In determining
the validity of the conclusion, we begin with "She isn't wearing diamonds," which
is represented at only one node, so we trace this back to the "not rich" node. Because
1 48 4. REASONING

the second premise indicates that the consequent is not true, this sort of problem is
technically called denying the consequent.
Many people are willing to conclude that problem 3 is also valid when, in fact, it
is not. Although it must be assumed to be true that if she is rich, she wears dia­
monds, it is also possible that poor people wear diamonds. I have found that intelli­
gent college students (and yes, many of their professors also) have difficulty with
this problem. Because the second premise states that the consequent has occurred,
this sort of problem is called affirming the consequent. It is fallacious (i.e., wrong)
to believe that because the consequent is true, the antecedent must also be true. "If,"
in these reasoning problems, doesn't mean "if and only if," which is how many peo­
ple interpret it. Of course, she may be rich, it may even be more likely that she is
rich, but we cannot conclude that she is rich just because she is wearing diamonds.
You can see this on the tree diagram. There are two different nodes labeled "wears
diamonds," one connected to the "rich" node and one connected to the "not rich"
node. We cannot determine which must be true because either is possible.
The fallacy of affirming the consequent is one type of deductive reasoning error
called illicit conversion. Illicit conversions, in if, then statements occur when people
believe that "If A, then B" also means "If B, then A."
Problem 4 is also invalid, although it is tempting to conclude that if she isn't rich,
she isn't wearing diamonds. Can you guess the technical term for this sort of prob­
lem? It is called denying the antecedent because premise 2 states that the antecedent
is false. Again, by starting at the "not rich" node, you can see that it is connected to
both "wears diamonds" and "doesn't wear diamonds," so either is possible.
A summary of these four kinds of reasoning, with examples of each, is shown in
Table 4. 1 .
Several popular advertisements take advantage of people's tendencies to make
invalid inferences from if, then statements. There is a commercial for yogurt that
goes something like this:
Some very old people from a remote section of the former Soviet Union are shown. We're
told that it is common for people in this remote region to live to be 1 1 0 years old. We're also
told that they eat a great deal of yogurt. The conclusion that the advertisers want people to
make is that eating yogurt will make you live 1 1 0 years.
TABLE 4. 1
Four Kinds of Reasoning with If, Then Statements

Antecedent Consequent
Affirming the Antecedent Affirming the Consequellt
Valid Reasoning Invalid Reasoning
Example: Example:
Affirming If I am dieting, then If Harry went to the supermarket,
I will lose weight. then the refrigerator is full.
I am dieting. The refrigerator is full.
Therefore, I will lose weight. Therefore, Harry went to the supermarket.
Denying the Antecedent Denying the Consequent
Invalid Reasoning Valid Reasolling
Example: Example:
Denying If it is raining, then my hair is wet. If Judy and Bruce are in love, then they
It is not raining. are planning to marry.
Therefore, my hair is not wet. They are not planning to marry.
Therefore, Judy and Bruce are not in love.
IF, THEN STATEMENTS 1 49

Implicitly, we're being told that if we eat yogurt, then we'll live to be 1 10 years old.
Of course, it's possible to live to be 1 10 without ever tasting yogurt, and we have no
reason to believe that yogurt added years to their lives. There is no basis for making a
causal inference for believing that eating yogurt can cause anyone to live a long time.
These remote Russians engage in strenuous physical labor most of their lives and do
not come into contact with many outsiders who carry potentially contagious diseases.
Either of these facts, or countless others, including heredity, could account for their
longevity. (It is also possible that the longevity claim is subject to question.) The ad­
vertisers are obviously hoping that the viewers will fall prey to the fallacy of affirming
the consequent and say to themselves, "If I eat yogurt, I will live to a very old age."

If, Then Reasoning in Everyday Contexts

In questions of science, the authority of a thousand is not worth the humble


reasoning of a single individual.
-Galileo Galilei (The Quoteaholic, http: //www.quoteaholic.com.
Retrieved Jan. 15, 2002)

If, then statements, like linear orderings, appear implicitly in standard prose. Of
course, we seldom find them neatly labeled "premise and conclusion." Yet, they are
often the basis for many common arguments. The fallacies of denying the an­
tecedent and affirming the consequent in everyday contexts are quite common.
There is currently an acrimonious debate over the issue of providing junior and
senior high school students with contraceptive information. The pro side argues that
if students are given this information, then they will act responsibly when engaging
in intercourse. Formally, this becomes: If students receive contraceptive informa­
tion, then they will engage in "protected" intercourse. The con side argues that stu­
dents should not engage in intercourse (whether protected or not); therefore, they
should not receive contraceptive information. This is an example of the fallacy of
denying the antecedent. It does not follow that if they are not given contraceptive
information, then they will not engage in intercourse.
Here's another example, virtually verbatim, from this morning's news. The spe­
cific details are not important because examples of this sort probably can be gleaned
from the news on any day of the week. Viewers were told that if the president of the
United States handled a tense situation with Communist China well, then a tense in­
ternational situation would be resolved without escalation of hostilities. The situa­
tion was resolved well (hostilities did not escalate), so the commentator concluded
that the president handled the tense situation well. Of course, it is possible that the
information in the if, then statement is really not true, and even if the president did
a good job, the situation could get worse. When we reason deductively with the
laws of logic, we assume that the propositions are true, so let's put aside the very
real possibility that we should not assume it to be true and apply the principles of if,
then reasoning.

/ President handled tense situation well . • Hostilities do NOT escalate

.�
? Hostilities do NOT escalate

President didn't handle tense situation weil L ? Hostilities DO escalate


1 50 4. REASO�ING

When the situation is drawn out in a decision tree, it is easy to see that it could have
been resolved well, even if the president had not handled the tense situation well.
A point that has been made repeatedly throughout this chapter is that people
often do not reason according to the laws of formal logic without instruction in rea­
soning. This is an example where using the laws of logic would help us understand
the situation better.
In everyday (practical) reasoning, we use information that is not stated in the
premises in order to decide if the conclusion follows from the premises. One sort of
knowledge we rely on is our knowledge about the content of the premises. The fol­
lowing two sentences demonstrate this point (Braine, 1978, p. 19):

If Hitler had had the atomic bomb in 1940, he would have won the war.
and
If Hitler had had one more plane in 1940, he would have won the war.

Although logic dictates that people should be able to reason identically with both
of these premises and should avoid the fallacies of affirming the consequent and
denying the antecedent, in fact most people find it easier to reason correctly with the
first premise than the second. As with all of the forms of deductive reasoning that
will be covered in this chapter, the content of the premises and our own belief biases
influence the way we determine what sorts of conclusions we are willing to accept
as valid. When we interpret if, then statements in everyday contexts, we rely on our
knowledge about the content to decide if a conclusion follows. According to the
rules of formal logic, we should be able to reason in ways that are independent of
content. We should all arrive at identical, logically correct conclusions, no matter
what the content is. Of course, humans are not perfect logic machines and there are
important individual differences in the sorts of models people use to solve reason­
ing problems (Bucciarelli & Johnson-Laird, 1999). We do and should determine if
the premises are true before deciding if a conclusion follows. (This point will be em­
phasized in Chapter 5.)

Negation

As seen in the previous section on linear reasoning, the use of negatives ("no,"
"not") in a reasoning problem makes it much more difficult to solve (Wason, 1969).
These difficulties are apparent in the following examples in which either the an­
tecedent or consequent is negative.

If the light is not green, I will go to Rome.


It is not true that the light is not green.
What, if anything, can you conclude?

If the letter is B, then the number is not 4.


The number is not 4.
What, if anything, can you conclude?

These are difficult to deal with because of the use of negation and its affirmation
or denial. The first statement denies the negative antecedent (not (not green)) . This
is called a double negation. You can't assume anything about the consequent when
the antecedent is denied, even when the antecedent itself is negative. Look at the
IF, THEN STATEMENTS lSI

second example. Most people incorrectly decide that it is correct to conclude from
the second example that "The letter is B." You should recognize this as an example
of affirming the consequent. If you are having difficulty answering these questions,
draw the corresponding tree diagrams, and the answer will "appear."
I once heard a politician make a statement similar to these. He said, ''It is not true
that I do not favor the legislation." It took me a few seconds to realize that he im­
plied that he favored the legislation. He could have meant that he was neutral with
respect to the legislation, neither favoring nor opposing it, but in the context, I inter­
preted his statement to mean that he favored the legislation. This is an example in
which I used context to clarify intended meaning. When negative information is
given, people take longer to solve reasoning problems and are less accurate, proba­
bly because the negative information (not or no) adds to the burden of working
memory (Garnham & Oakhill, 1 994; Noveck & Politzer, 1998).

Confirmation Bias

Confirmation bias, the predilection to seek and utilize information that supports or
confirms your hypotheses or premises, can be seen in this classic problem (Johnson­
Laird & Wason, 1970):

Four cards are lying face up on a table in front of you. Every card has a letter on one side
and a number on the other. Your task is to decide if the following rule is true, "If a card has a
vowel on one side, then it has an even number on the other side." Which card or cards do you
need to turn over in order to find out whether the rule is true or false? You may turn over
only the minimum number necessary to determine if this rule is true. Please stop now and ex­
amine the cards below to determine which ones you would want to turn over. Don't go on
until you have decided which cards you would want to turn over.

Few people select the correct cards in this problem, which has become known as
the four-card selection task. It is a widely studied task that is popular in the literature
of cognitive psychology. Most people respond "A only" or "A and 4." The correct an­
swer is "A and 7." Can you figure out why? The best way to solve this reasoning prob­
lem is to draw a tree diagram that corresponds to the statement, "If a card has a vowel
on one side, then it has an even number on the other side." It should look like this:

even number

vowel

Start ? even number

? odd number
1 52 4. REASO�I�G

If A doesn't have an even number on the other side, the rule is false. Similarly, if
7 has a vowel on the other side, the rule is false. What about 0 and 4? 0 is a conso­
nant. It doesn't matter if there is an even or odd number on the back because
the rule says nothing about consonants. Because 4 is an even number, it doesn't
matter if there is a vowel or consonant on the back. The reason that this is such a
difficult problem is that people interpret the rule to also mean "If a card does not
have a vowel on one side, then it does not have an even number on the other
side" or, without negatives, "If a card has a consonant on one side, then it has
an odd number on the other side." These alternate interpretations are incorrect.
Do you recognize the error as denying the antecedent? This is a robust (strong)
effect. It is an extremely difficult task because of the crucial role of discon­
firmation. People fail to appreciate the importance of a falsification strategy. That is,
we need to think of ways to show that a hypothesis may be false, instead of
looking for evidence that would show that a hypothesis may be correct. This is
exacerbated with the incorrect assumption that the converse of the rule is also
true. The only correct way to solve this problem is to select only cards that can
falsify the rule.
Part of the difficulty people have with this task may be related to the abstract na­
ture of the problem. After all, there is very little we do in our everyday life that re­
lates vowels and even numbers. Try out a more realistic and less abstract version of
this task (adapted from Johnson-Laird, Legrenzi, & Legrenzi, 1972):

In order to understand this task, you may need some background information (depending
on your age). Many years ago, the United States Post Office had two different postage rates
known as first-class and second-class mail. You could pay full postage, which was 5 cents, if
you sealed your letter (first class), or you could pay a reduced, 3-cent rate, if you merely
folded the flaps closed and didn't seal them (second class). (First-class mail had priority for
delivery over second-class mail.)
Suppose you are a postal employee watching letters as they move across a conveyor belt.
The rule to be verified or disconfirmed is: "If a letter is sealed, then it has a 5 cent stamp on
it." Four letters are shown in Fig. 4.2. Which ones would you have to turn over to decide if the
rule is true?

Stop now and work on this problem. Don't go on until you've decided which
letters (at a minimum) you would have to turn over to test this rule.
Did you notice that this is the same task that was posed earlier? The correct an­
swer is the first sealed envelope and the last envelope (the one with the 3 cent
stamp). This is an easier problem than the more abstract one because people find it
easier to understand that a letter that is not sealed could also have a 5 cent stamp on
it than it is to understand that if the letter is not a vowel it could also have an even

FIG. 4. 2 . Which of these letters would you turn over to decide if the following rule is true:
"If a letter is sealed, then it has a 5-cent stamp on it." (Adapted from Johnson-Laird, Legrenzi,
& Legrenzi, 1 972.)
IF, THEN STATEMENTS 1 53

number on the back. Your tree diagram should look like this:

/ 5¢ stamp
sealed/
Start ? 5¢ stamp

? 3¢ stamp
Johnson-Laird and Wason (1977) found that when the problem is presented
in this realistic manner, 22 out of 24 subjects were able to solve the problem.
Johnson-Laird and Wason concluded that our everyday experiences are relevant in
determining how we reason.

Permission and Obligation Schemata

Many researchers have tried to understand why so many people have so much diffi­
culty with the four-card selection task (I also find it very confusing), but have little
difficulty when it is rephrased in the stamped-letter example. These are identical
problems from the perspective of logic-the rules for reasoning are the same in the
two problems.
Cheng and Holyoak (1985) explored the basic differences in how people think
about these two problems. They postulated that when people use if, then reasoning for
pragmatic purposes, they usually involve either the permission to do something,
called permission schema (if something is true, then you have permission to do some­
thing else) or they involve an obligation or contractual arrangement, called obligation
schema (if something is true, then you have an obligation to do something else). In real
life, these are the two most common situations in which people use if, then reasoning.
Instead of using the rules of formal logic, people tend to develop abstract general rules
that work well in specific situations and help them to achieve their goals. Cheng and
Holyoak found that the permission and obligation schemata operate across domains.
In other words, it does not matter if the topic concerns stamped letters, an agreement
to perform a job, or permission to borrow the car. Here is an example of each:

If a passenger has been immunized against cholera, then he may enter the country. (permission
schema)
If you pay me $100,000, then I'll transfer ownership of this house to you. (obligation schema)

When if, then statements involve permission or obligation, then people make few
reasoning errors. Furthermore, when most people understand the rules of permis­
sion and obligation, the content of the statement doesn't matter-people apply the
rules appropriately across domains. Cheng and Holyoak (1985) also found that
when they included a rationale for the rule, most of the people they asked to solve
this problem had no difficulty with it. In the sealed envelope problem, they added
the following rationale for the rule, "The country's postal regulation requires that if
a letter is sealed, then it must carry a 20-cent stamp" (p. 400). Thus, a rule that was
1 54 4. REASO:\,I:\'G

extremely difficult to apply when it was presented in an abstract form was easily
used by most people when it was used in a familiar context with an explanation.

If, and Only If


Certain contexts seem to require that we understand them in a way that is incon­
sistent with the laws of logic. Suppose you are told: "If you mow the lawn, I'll give
you five dollars" (Taplin & Staudenmeyer, 1 973, p. 542). This statement invites the
interpretation, "If you do not mow the lawn, I won't give you five dollars." In the
everyday inference we make from language, this is a valid conclusion, although it is
erroneous from the perspective of formal logic. In understanding statements of the
"If p, then q" variety, the conclusions that we are willing to accept as valid depend
very much on what p and q are. In this lawn-mowing example, the intended mean­
ing is "if, and only if you mow the lawn, then I'll give you five dollars." In dealing
with real-world if, then statements, you need to decide whether the intended mes­
"
sage is "if p, then q or "if, and only if p, then q. " The important point of this exam­
ple is that context is irrelevant to the laws of logic, which are the same whether you
are talking about pay for mowing a lawn or turning over a card to check an abstract
rule. It is not surprising that people vary their thinking depending on context
because context is important in real-life settings.

Chained Conditionals
We can make things just a little more complicated (just what you were hoping
for), by building on if, then statements and making them into longer chains. A
chained conditional occurs when two if, then statements are linked so that the con­
sequent of one statement is also the antecedent of the other statement. In skeleton
form, or fill-in-the-blank form, this becomes:

If A, then B. If B, then C.

As before, it doesn't matter what we use to fill in for A, B, and C, if we are reason­
ing according to the laws of logic. For example, "If Jodi wants to be a physicist, then
she will study calculus. If she is studying calculus, then she has a final exam on
Wednesday." With this conditional chain, we can conclude that she has a final exam
on Wednesday, if we learn that she wants to be a physicist.
Don't be tempted to assume that every time you have three terms, you have a
chained conditional. Consider this example.

If she wants to be a physicist, then she will study calculus.


If she wants to be a physicist, then she will have an exam on Wednesday.

These are two conditional statements, but they do not have the chained struc­
ture because the consequent of one statement is not the antecedent of the other
statement.

If, Then Reasoning in Legal Contexts


Consider the sad saga of an American star who was accused of killing his ex-wife
and her friend. The specifics of this American tragedy are not relevant because there
COMBINATORIAL REASONING 1 55

are always similar crimes in which the key to the defense or prosecution hinges
on it then reasoning. In this particular case, the suspect had an excellent alibi from
1 1 p.m. and later on the night of the killing. In other words,

If the murder occurred any time from 11 p.m. or later, the defendant is innocent.
The prosecutor attempted to show that the murder occurred prior to 1 1 p.m. Suppose that
she was successful in convincing the jury that the murder occurred at 10:30. What can we con­
clude about the guilt or innocence of the defendant?

To make it easier for you, I have drawn the tree diagram that corresponds to this
real-life situation.

defendan t is i nnoce nt

Start ? defenda nt is i nn ocent

? defendant is uilty
g

I hope that you determined that if the murder occurred at 1 0:30, we do not know
if the defendant is guilty or innocent. Unless there is other evidence that "proves be­
yond a reasonable doubt" that the defendant committed these grisly murders, then
the jury must acquit him. They cannot convict a man because of the error of denying
the antecedent. If anyone tries to tell you that this critical thinking stuff is a "bunch
of bunk" (or some more colorful phrase), then give him or her this example in which
misunderstanding could lead to a wrongful conviction. Whom would you want on
a jury that decides your guilt or innocence-people who think critically or those
who rush to a hasty decision and are easily misled with persuasive techniques?

COMBINATORIAL REASONING

We recognize the gravity of the challenge to get our students to think, to think
critically, and even to think scientifically. Certainly it is abundantly clear to me
that science education fails if it doesn't tackle the matter of thinking.
-Munby (1982, p. 8)

One approach to enhancing reasoning skills is based on a model of intelligence that


was proposed by the Swiss psychologist Jean Piaget. Piaget was primarily con­
cerned with the way people acquire knowledge and the way cognitive processes
change throughout childhood and early adulthood. According to Piaget, there are
four broad developmental periods (each broken into stages). As people move from
infancy into adolescence, their cognitive abilities mature in qualitatively distinct
stages culminating with the ability to think in orderly, abstract ways. Piaget's exam­
ples of abstract thought involve thinking skills that are needed to understand
scientific concepts. One of the scientific reasoning skills that Piaget believed to be
important is combinatorial reasoning, which is use of systematic and orderly steps
1 56 4. REASO:'oJING

FIG. 4.3. Mixing colorless liquids

when making combinations so that all possible combinations are formed. Here is a
classic task that involves this skill:

Mixing Colorless Chemicals. This task involves mixing chemicals until a yellow color is
obtained. Suppose that you were given four bottles of odorless, colorless liquids. They appear
to be identical except for being labeled 1, 2, 3, and 4. You are also given a fifth beaker labeled
X, which is the "activating solution." The activating solution is always needed to obtain the
yellow color, which results from a chemical reaction. How would you go about finding which
of the chemicals in combination will yield the yellow color?
Some rules: The amount of each chemical is not important, nor is the order in which you
combine them. It may help you in working on this problem to visualize the materials as pre­
sented in Fig. 4.3.

Stop now and think about how you would approach this problem. Do not go on
until you have written down all of the tests you would perform.
How did you approach this problem? Did you realize that you needed an orga­
nized plan or did you begin by randomly mixing the liquids? The best approach to
this task is a very methodical one. It must include mixing each liquid separately
with the activating solution (1 + X, 2 + X, 3 + X, 4 + X), then carefully mixing two
liquids at a time with X (1 + 2 + X, 1 + 3 + X, 1 + 4 + X, 2 + 3 + X, 2 + 4 + X,
3 + 4 + X), then three at a time with X (1 + 2 + 3 + X, 1 + 2 + 4 + X, 1 + 3 + 4 + X,
2 + 3 + 4 + X), then all four at once (1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + X), being careful to observe
which combinations would yield the yellow color. Look over the way the chemicals
were combined in a systematiC manner so that no combinations would be missed or
duplicated. This technique of systematic combinations will be needed to perform
the reasoning tasks in the next section.

SYLLOGISTIC REASONING

Nothing intelligible ever puzzles me.


Logic puzzles me.
-Lewis Carroll 0 832-1898)
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 1 57

Syllogistic reasoning is a form of reasoning that involves deciding whether a con­


clusion can properly be inferred from two or more statements. One type of syllogis­
tic reasoning is categorical reasoning. Categorical reasoning involves quantifiers or
terms that tell us how many. Quantifiers are terms like "all," "some," "none," and
"no." The quantifiers indicate how many items belong in specified categories.
A syllogism usually consists of two statements that are called premises and a
third statement called the conclusion. In categorical syllogisms, quantifiers are used
in the premises and conclusion. The task is to determine if the conclusion follows
logically from the premises.
The premises and conclusion of a syllogism are classified according to mood.
(The word mood has a special meaning in this context that is unrelated to its more
usual meaning about how someone feels.) There are four different moods, or combi­
nations of positive and negative statements with the terms "all" or "some." The four
moods are:

Mood Abstract Example Concrete Example


Universal Affirmative All A are B. All students are smart.
Particular Affirmative Some A are B. Some video games are fun.
Universal Negative No A are B. No smurfs are pink.
Particular Negative Some A are not B. Some democrats are not liberals.

As you can see from this table, a statement is universal if it contains the terms
"all" or "no"; it is particular if it contains the term "some"; it is negative if it contains
"no" or "not"; and it is affirmative if it is not negative. Thus, it should be easy to
classify the mood of any statement by identifying the key terms.
Several syllogisms are presented here. Each consists of two premises and a con­
clusion. Work through each syllogism and decide if the conclusion is valid (V) or in­
valid <D. To be valid, the conclusion must always be true given its premises. In other
words, when you decide that a syllogism is valid, you are saying "if the premises
are true, then conclusion must be true." In other words, "Does the conclusion 'fol­
low from' the premises?" If you can think of one way that the conclusion could be false
when the premises are true, then it is invalid. Don't go on until you have worked
through these syllogisms.

1 . Premise #1 : All people on welfare are poor.


Premise #2: Some poor people are dishonest.
Conclusion: Some people on welfare are dishonest. Valid or Invalid?
2. Premise #1 : No parents understand children.
Premise #2: Some teachers understand children.
Conclusion: No parents are teachers. Valid or Invalid?
3. Premise #1: Some lawyers are not smart.
Premise #2: Some smart people are rich.
Conclusion: Some lawyers are rich. Valid or Invalid?
4. Premise #1 : All physics students are good in math.
Premise #2: Some coeds are physics students.
Conclusion: Some coeds are good in math. Valid or Invalid?
5. Premise #1 : All Americans need health insurance.
Premise #2: Everyone who needs health insurance should vote for it.
Conclusion: All Americans should vote for health insurance. Valid or Invalid?
1 58 4. REASONING

According to the rules of logic, it should not matter if the syllogisms are presented
in abstract terms of A's and B's (e.g., Some A's are not B's), nonsense terms like zev
and creb (All zev are creb), or meaningful terms like lawyers and cool (No lawyers
are cool). The logical rules for deciding if a conclusion can be validly inferred from
the premises remain the same. We're really saying "All ___ are ." It
should make no difference how we fill in the blanks; any letters, nonsense or mean­
ingful words, or even fancy pictures should be handled in the same way. However,
from a psychological perspective, there are important content differences, and people
have difficulty using the rules of syllogistic reasoning when the conclusion is not one
that they believe to be true, even if logically it follows from the premises. One way to
avoid the problem of having one's biases affect how we reason with quantifiers is to
use circle diagrams, which, like linear diagrams and tree diagrams, alleviate the limi­
tations of short-term memory and make relationships obvious and visible.
How did you go about deciding if the conclusions were valid? There are two dif­
ferent types of strategies that can be used with syllogisms to determine if a conclu­
sion follows from its premises. If you've been reading the chapters in order, then
you know that a common approach to improving thinking is the deliberate use of
both spatial and verbal strategies. The same two approaches apply here. First, I will
present a spatial method for testing conclusions, then I will provide some verbal
rules that can also be used. Either method will "work," but you'll probably find that
you prefer one method over the other. I have been teaching this material to college
students for many years and have found that individual students have very strong
preferences for either circle diagrams or verbal rules.

Circle Diagrams for Determining validity

One way of determining if a conclusion is true is with the use of circle diagrams that
depict the relationships among the three terms (A, B, C or whatever we used to fill
in the blanks). The degree to which the circles overlap depicts the inclusion or exclu­
sion of the categories.
There are several different methods of drawing diagrams to depict the relation­
ships among the terms in a syllogism. One of these methods is known as Venn
Diagrams, named for a 1 9th century English mathematician and logician who first in­
troduced them. These are the same diagrams that you probably used in mathematics
classes if you ever studied set theory. (This was a very popular way to teach the "new
math," before it was abandoned and replaced with the "old math.") A second method
of diagramming relationships is known as Euler Diagrams. According to popular
lore, this method was devised by Leonard Euler, an 18th century Swiss mathemati­
cian, who was given the task of teaching the laws of syllogistic reasoning to a German
princess. Because the princess was having difficulty understanding the task, Euler
created a simple procedure that could be used to understand the relationships among
the terms and to check on the validity of inferences. A third method is called the bal­
lantine method because of its use of three overlapping circles. In all of these methods,
circles are used to indicate category membership. The differences among these meth­
ods is not important here, and the general strategy of checking conclusions with circle
drawings will be referred to as circle diagrams. If you've learned a different method
of circle diagrams in another context (e.g., a class on set theory or a logic class), then
continue to use that method as long as it works well for you.
Look very carefully at Fig. 4.4.
Universal A ffirmative
or
A l l A a re B .
( A l l a n g e l s a re bal d . ) A l l A a re B . and All A a re B . and
some B a re not A. all B a re A.

@
A l l A a re B . and
or

(0
A l l A a re B . and
or

Particular A ffirmative some B are not A . a l l B are A.

@ ffi
S o m e A a re B .
( S o m e a n g e l s a re ba l d . )
or

I A l l B a re A. and
Some A are not B.
Some A are B
and s o m e B a re A .
A lso s o m e A a re not B .
and s o m e B a r e n o t A .

8 8
Universal Negative

N o A are B.
( N o a n g e l s a r e ba l d . )

N o A a re B . a n d n o B are A.

0 0 or or

Particular Negative
N o A a re B . a n d A l l B a r e A. and
S o m e A a re n o t B . n o B a re A . s o m e A are not B .
(Some a ngels are not
ba l d . )

S o m e A a re B . a n d s o m e B a re A .
A l so s o m e A a re n o t B . a n d s o m e
B a r e not A .

FIG. 4.4. Circle diagrams depicting correct interpretations of the premises used in
syllogisms. Note that "all" can have two correct interpretations, "some" can have four correct
interpretations, "no" has one correct interpretation, and "some-not" can have three correct
interpretations.

1 59
1 60 4. REASO:"oJING

The four moods that statements in syllogisms can have are listed in the left-hand
column of Fig. 4.4. Next to each statement are circle diagrams that are correct depic­
tions of the relationships in the statement. Stop now and look very carefully at
Fig. 4.4. One circle represents everything that is A, and a second circle represents
everything that is B. For the purposes of deductive reasoning, it does not matter
what A and B are. In the example in Fig. 4.4, A is used to stand for angels and B is
used to stand for bald, but it could be anything. I could just as easily used A to stand
for college students and B to stand for punk rockers.
Look at the way the circles are combined so that they form a "picture" of what is
being said in words. Let's start in the middle of the figure, with "universal nega­
tive," the easiest example. When we say, "No A are B," this means that nothing that
is in category A is also in category B. This is depicted by drawing a circle labeled A
and one labeled B that do not touch or overlap in any way. There is only one way to
draw this relationship. Notice that when we say, "No A are B," we are also saying
that "No B are A" Can you see that from the circle diagram? Every time you have a
universal negative, the relationship will be "pictured" with two circles that do not
overlap-one for things that are A and one for things that are B.
Consider now universal affirmative, "All A are B." Again we use two circles­
one labeled A and one labeled B. And again, we want to draw the two circles so that
they represent the relationship in which everything that is A is B. As you can see in
Fig. 4.4, there are two different ways of depicting this relationship because there are
two possible correct ways of understanding what it means. By drawing the A circle
inside the B circle, we are depicting the case where "All A are B," but there are some
B that are not A (some bald people are not angels). The second drawing shows the
case where "All A are B," and "All B are A" (all bald people are angels). Either of
these two interpretations could be true when we are told that "All A are B."
Don't be discouraged if this seems difficult to you. It will soon be easier as it be­
comes more meaningful and you work your way through the examples. Look at the
other two possibilities in Fig. 4.4. There are three possible ways to depict particular
negative (Some A are not B) and four possible ways to depict particular affirmative
(Some A are B). Now look at all of the moods and notice the different ways that two
circles can be combined. There are five different possible ways to combine two cir­
cles, and each combination represents a different meaning!

1 . A and B do not overlap:

0 0
2. A and B are the same circle:
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 161

3. A is inside B:

4. B is inside A:

5. A and B partially overlap:

Let's draw circle diagrams to depict the relationships in Syllogism 1 . The first two
sentences are the premises. Write out each premise and next to each premise, draw
the appropriate circle diagrams. For example, the first premise states, "All people on
welfare are poor." In skeletal form, it is "All A are B" with A standing for "people
on welfare" and B standing for "poor." You should recognize this as universal affir­
mative. Go to Fig. 4.4, look across from universal affirmative, and you will see that
there are two possible ways to draw circles that correspond to this premise. Repeat
this with the second premise: Some poor people are dishonest. You already decided
that A people on welfare, and B
= poor. The new term, dishonest, can be repre­
=

sented by C. The second premise then becomes "Some B are c." This is an example
of particular affirmative. Look across from particular affirmative on Fig. 4.4 and you
will see that there are four possible ways to draw circles to represent this relation­
ship. The only difference is that for Premise 2, we are using the letters B and C to
stand for the categories. Thus, the first two premises will look like this:

A = people on welfare; B = poor; C = dishonest.

1 . All people on welfare are poor.


(All A are B.)

Premise 1 a Premise 1 b
1 62 4. REASONI:"JG

2. Some poor people are dishonest.


(Some B are C.)

Premise 2a Premise 2b

Premise 2c Premise 2d

To determine if the conclusion is valid, we systematically combine each of the fig­


ures in the first premise with each of the figures in the second premise. If we find one
combination that would not correspond to the conclusion, then we can stop and de­
cide that the conclusion is invalid. If we make all possible combinations of figures
from Premise 1 and figures from Premise 2, and they are all consistent with the con­
clusion, then the conclusion is valid. In other words, if all combinations of Premise 1
with Premise 2 support the conclusion, then the conclusion is valid. The first few
times you work on these, it may seem laborious, but you will soon "see" the answers
and find ways to shortcut the process of working through all the combinations.
Here is the conclusion:
Some poor people on welfare are dishonest.
(Some A are C).

Conclusion A Conclusion B

Conclusion C Conclusion D

Premise 1 has two possible drawings and Premise 2 has four possible drawings.
You can see that I labeled the two Premise 1 drawings la and Ib and the four
Premise 2 drawings 2a, 2b, 2c, and 2d. To work systematically, you need to use the
combinatorial reasoning rules that were presented in the last section. Start with la
and combine it with 2a, then l a and 2b, l a and 2c, la and 2d. Then repeat the pattern
by combining Ib with 2a, then Ib with 2b, then Ib with 2c, and finally Ib with 2d. Of
course, you hope that you won't have to go through this entire procedure because
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 1 63

you can stop as soon as you find one combination that violates the conclusion that
"Some A are c." Work along with me.

Premise 1 a + Premise 2a

6) 6)
(A inside B.) (B inside C.)

When I combine these two depictions, I will get a figure with A inside B and B
inside C:

This combination shows a result that is consistent with the conclusion that "Some
A are c." Go on!

Premise 1 a + Premise 2b

(A inside B.) (B and C are the same circle.)

When I combine Ib and 2b, I get a depiction where A is inside the B / C circle.

This is consistent with the conclusion that "Some A are c." Go on!

Premise 1 a + Premise 2c

6) 6)
(A inside B.) (C inside B.)

This gets a little tricky here, because there are several different ways to combine la and
2c and we have to try all of them until we run out of combinations or find one that is
not consistent with the conclusion. Here we draw all ways that A can be inside B
and C can be inside B.
1 64 4. REASONING

A and C are the same circle inside B.

This is still consistent with "Some A are c." Go on!


A and C partially overlap inside B.

This is still consistent with "Some A are c." Go on!


A and C are two circles inside B.

This does not agree with the conclusion that "Some A are c."
Stop here!
I know that this seems like a lot of work, but after you work a few problems, you
can spot the combinations that will make a conclusion invalid, so you will not need
to try every possible combination. Until then, work systematically through all com­
binations. A list of steps for checking the validity of conclusions with circle dia­
grams is shown in Table 4.2. Stop now and look over the steps. Refer back to them
as we work through the rest of the syllogisms.

TABLE 4 . 2
Steps for Detennining the validity
of Conclusions Using Circle Diagrams

1. Write out each premise and the conclusion of the syllogism.


2. Next to each statement, draw all correct diagrams using the diagrams shown in Fig. 4.1 .
3. Systematically combine all diagrams for Premise 1 with all diagrams for Premise 2. Try
Premise 1a (the first diagram for Premise 1 ) with Premise 2a (the first diagram for
Premise 2). Continue combining Premise 1a with all Premise 2 diagrams, then go on and
combine all Premise 1b with all Premise 2 diagrams. Continue in this manner (Premise 1c
with all Premise 2 diagrams, then Premise 1d with all Premise 2 diagrams) until
4. You find one diagram in which the conclusion is invalid or
5. You have tried all combinations of Premise 1 and Premise 2 diagrams.
Note. Sometimes there will be more than one way to combine diagrams from the two premises. Be
sure to try all combinations.
When trying out all combinations, remember that there are five possible ways to combine two circles:
(a) A inside B, (b) B inside A, (c) A and B overlapping partially, (d) A and B with no overlap (two separate
circles), and (e) A and B represented by one circle (A and B are the same circle). These five possibilities
are shown below.
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 1 65

(c)

(e)

8
AB

Let's try Syllogism 2.


A =parents; B= understand children; C = teachers.
No parents understand children.
(No A are B.)

Premise 1 a

00
Some teachers understand children.
(Some C are B.)

Premise 2a Premise 2b

Premise 2c
(0 Premise 2d

No parents are teachers.


(No A are C.)

Conclusion A

0 0
1 66 4. REASONING

The two circles that depict the first premise are only one figure because it is Uni­
versal Negative, and two separate circles are needed to depict this relationship. It is
labeled 1a. The second premise is Particular Affirmative, which is depicted with
four figures (2a, 2b, 2c, 2d). The conclusion is Universal Negative, so it is also
depicted with one figure consisting of two separate circles. Now combine la + 2a,
la + 2b, la + 2c, and la + 2d. You can stop as soon as you find one combination
that is not consistent with the conclusion and decide that it is invalid, or try all com­
binations and then decide that it is valid.
As you work through all combinations of the circle drawing that can be com­
bined from the premises, you will see that it is invalid. (If you would like more prac­
tice with syllogisms, you can find several more "worked examples" in Thinking Crit­
ically About Critical Thinking, the workbook that accompanies this text.)
Here are the answers to the next three syllogisms presented on page 1 57:

3. From the premises you were given, is it valid to conclude that "Some lawyers
are rich" ?
Nope-it's invalid.
4. From the premises you were given, is it valid to conclude that "Some coeds are
good in math"?
Yes!
5. From the premises you were given, is it valid to conclude that "All Americans
should vote for health insurance" ? Yes, it is.

Verbal Rules for Determining Validity

It's a peculiar thing about circle diagrams: Some people love working on them and
others seem to hate them. The problem in working with them is trying all possible
combinations of representations for both premises. People who prefer to think spa­
tially seem to "see" the combinations with apparent ease, but those who prefer ver­
bal modes of representation seem to have more difficulty. For those of you who
have difficulty combining premises into circle relationships, take heart because
there are verbal rules for determining if the conclusion of a syllogism is valid. These
rules will work just as well as circle diagrams. Sternberg and Wei! (1980) found that
verbal and spatial strategies draw on different abilities and that the effectiveness of
a given strategy depends on one's preferred mode of thought. There are five rules
that can be used to determine the validity of a conclusion. In order to use these rules
there are two additional terms that you need to learn.
There are three categories named in syllogisms, the A, B, and C, or whatever cate­
gory names we substitute for them in more concrete examples. One of these cate­
gories is called the middle term. To determine which is the middle term, go to the
conclusion. There are two categories in the conclusion; one is the subject of the sen­
tence, the other is in the predicate. The category that is not mentioned in the conclu­
sion is the middle term. It is called the middle term because it links the other two
terms in the premises. Look back at Syllogism 1 . The conclusion is "Some people on
welfare are dishonest." "People on welfare" is the subject of this sentence, and "dis­
honest" is the predicate. The middle term is "poor." The middle term is in both
premises, but it is not in the conclusion.
The second term that you need to know is distributed. A term is distributed if the
statement applies to every item in the category (Govier, 1985). Consider the four
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 1 67

TABLE 4.3
Distributed and Undistributed Terms in the Four Moods of Syllogisms

All A are B. A is distributed. (A is modified by "all.")


B is undistributed. (B is undistributed because there may be some B that
are not A.)
Some A are B. Both A and B are undistributed.
No A are B. Both A and B are distributed. (Both A and B are modified by "no.")
(This is the same as saying that "No B are A.")
Some A are not B. A is undistributed.
B is distributed. (B is modified by "not.")

TABLE 4.4
Rules for Determining Validity of Conclusions
When Reasoning with Quantifiers

1 . If the conclusion is negative, one premise must be negative, and conversely, if one premise
is negative, the conclusion must be negative.
2. The middle term must be distributed in at least one premise.
3. Any term that is distributed in the conclusion must be distributed in at least one premise.
4. If both premises are particular, there are no valid conclusions.
5. If one premise is particular, the conclusion must be particular.
6. At least one premise must be affirmative. (There are no valid conclusions with two
negative premises.)

types of category relationships shown in Table 4.3. Next to each one I've indicated
which terms are distributed and which terms are undistributed. As you will see in
Table 4.3, categories that are modified by "all," "no," and "not" are distributed.
Look carefully at the statement "All A are B." B is undistributed in this statement
because there may be some B that are not A, so the statement is not about every B.
On the other hand, consider "No A are B." In this case, B is distributed because
when we say "No A are B," we are also saying "No B are A." Thus, in the second
case, the statement is about all B.
For a conclusion to be valid, the syllogism must pass all of the rules in Table 4.4.
If it fails on any one of them, then it is invalid.
Let's apply these rules to the syllogisms we've already solved with circle
diagrams.

Syllogism 1.

A people on welfare, B poor, C dishonest


= = =

All people on welfare are poor. (All A are B.)


Some poor people are dishonest. (Some B are C.)
Some people on welfare are dishonest. (Some A are C.)

The middle term for this syllogism is B. It is the one mentioned in both premises
and is missing from the conclusion. The first rule starts "if the conclusion is nega­
tive." Because the conclusion is positive, we can immediately go on to the second
rule. The second rule states that the middle term must be distributed in at least one
premise. Let's check this. The middle term is B (poor people). Is it modified by "all"
or "not" in either premise? It is not distributed in either premise, so we can stop
here. This conclusion is invalid! But, of course, you already knew that because you
discovered that it was invalid when you completed the circle diagrams.
1 68 4. REASO:\,I:\'G

Let's try the verbal rules with the second syllogism.

Syllogism 2.

A parents, B understands children, C teachers


= = =

No parents understand children. (No A are B.)


Some teachers understand children. (Some C are B.)
No parents are teachers. (No A are C)

The first rule says that if the conclusion is negative, then one premise must be
negative, and vice versa. The conclusion is negative and so is one premise, so we can
check the next rule.
The second rule is that the middle term must be distributed in one premise. What
is the middle term? It is B, the one not mentioned in the conclusion. It is distributed
in the first premise, so we can move on. The third rule is that any term distributed in
the conclusion must be distributed in at least one premise. Both A and C are distrib­
uted in the conclusion. A is distributed in the first premise, but C is not distributed
in a premise, so stop here. This conclusion is invalid!
Briefly, here are the answers to the remaining syllogisms.

Syllogism 3.

A lawyers, B smart, C rich


= = =

Some lawyers are not smart. (Some A are not B.)


Some smart people are rich. (Some B are C)
Some lawyers are rich. (Some A are C)
fails #1 : passes the first part because the conclusion is not negative; fails the second part because the
first premise is negative and the conclusion is positive.
Invalid!

Syllogism 4.
All physics students are good in math. (All A are B.)
Some coeds are physics students. (Some C are A.)
Some coeds are good in math. (Some C are B.)
passes # 1 : There are no negatives.
passes # 2: The middle term is A. A is distributed.
passes # 3: No term in the conclusiol! is distributed.
passes # 4: Both premises are not particular.
passes # 5: One premise is particular and the conclusion is particular.
passes # 6: At least one premise is affirmative.
Valid!

Syllogism 5.

All Americans need health insurance. (All A are B.)


Everyone who needs health insurance should vote for it. (All B are C.)
All Americans should vote for health insurance. (All A are C)
passes # 1 : There are no negatives.
passes # 2: The middle term is B. B is distributed.
passes # 3: A is distributed in the conclusion and the first premise.
passes # 4: Both premises are universal, not particular.
passes # 5: No premise is particular.
passes # 6: At least one premise is affirmative.
Valid!
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 1 69

Syllogisms in Everyday Contexts

Somewhere during the last section, you may have said to yourself, "Why bother!" It
may seem that syllogisms are artificial stimuli created solely to make work for stu­
dents and teachers. If you did have this thought, you were questioning the ecologi­
cal validity of syllogisms. Ecological validity concerns the real-world validity or
applications of a concept outside of the laboratory or classroom. In other words, do
people use syllogistic reasoning in real-world contexts?
Syllogistic reasoning and the other types of reasoning like linear ordering and if,
then statements are sometimes considered as a subset of problem solving. Often,
when solving a problem, we begin with statements that we believe or know to
be true (the premises) and then decide which conclusions we can logically infer
from them.
Syllogisms also appear implicitly in normal English prose. Of course, in natural
context, the premises and conclusions aren't labeled, but the underlying structure is
much the same. They are especially easy to spot in legal and political arguments,
and thus often appear on standardized tests for college, graduate, and law school
admissions.
Here is an example of syllogistic reasoning that may seem more like the kind of
syllogism you'd find in everyday contexts: The death sentence should be declared
unconstitutional. It is the cruelest form of punishment that is possible, and it is also
very unusual. The Constitution specifically protects us against cruel and unusual
punishment.
Can you conclude from these statements that the death sentence is unconstitu­
tional? Try to formulate these sentences into standard syllogism form (two premises
and a conclusion). Use circle diagrams or the five rules to check on the validity of
the conclusion. Stop now and work on this natural language syllogism.
Your syllogism should be similar to this:

Premise 1 : The death sentence is cruel and unusual punishment.


Premise 2: Cruel and unusual punishment is unconstitutional.
Conclusion: The death sentence is unconstitutional.

If we put this in terms of A, B, and C, this roughly corresponds to:

A = the death sentence


B = cruel and unusual punishment
C = unconstitutional

This then becomes:

All A are B.
All B are C.
All A are C.

In its abstract form, this becomes a syllogism that can be tested with either circle
diagrams or verbal rules that will determine if the conclusion validly follows from
the premises. The point here is that syllogisms are often contained in everyday argu­
ments. Medical providers are often faced with problems that take this form: Every­
one with disease X will have results from the lab test of Y. Some people with results
from the lab test of Y will not have disease X . Although this does not "look like"
1 70 4. REASONING

some combination of "all," "some", "no," and "some not," can you see how it is the
same sort of problem with different terms to represent these relationships? Often,
we don't recognize syllogistic statements because they are not neatly labeled by
premise and conclusion, but if you get in the habit of looking for them, you may be
surprised how frequently they can be found.

Missing Quantifiers
If there is any equality now, it has been our struggle that put it there. Because
they said "all" and meant "some. " All means all.
-Beah Richards (in Beilensen & Jackson, 1992, p. 22)

When syllogisms are found in everyday use, the quantifiers are often missing.
Sometimes this absence is done deliberately in the hope that you will infer one par­
ticular quantifier (e.g., assume "all" instead of the more truthful "some.") Here is an
example of categorical reasoning used in a presidential campaign. A presidential
candidate (in the U. S. primaries) was questioned about his extramarital affairs. He
responded this way: I have not been perfect in my private life, but we have had
other great presidents who were also not perfect in their private lives.
Let's convert this to a categorical syllogism:

Premise 1 : I am not perfect (in my private life).


Premise 2: Some great presidents were not perfect (in their private lives).
Conclusion: I will be a great president.
(implied)

In its abstract form this becomes:

A = I (the speaker)
B = people who are not perfect
C = great presidents

or

All A are B.
Some C are B.
All A are (will be) C.

The conclusion he wanted listeners to draw is that he would also be a great presi­
dent. Check the validity of this conclusion either with circle diagrams or the five
rules. Is the implied conclusion valid? Note also his choice of words to describe his
extramarital affairs (not perfect).
In everyday language, the quantifiers may be different from those used here.
"Every" and "each" may be used as substitutes for "all," and "many" and "few"
may be used as substitutes for "some." It is a simple matter to change them to the
quantifiers used here and then check the conclusion for its validity (Nickerson, 1986).
Here is an example (with some editing) that I recognized in a recent conversation.
"People who go to rock concerts smoke dope. Jaye went to a rock concert. Therefore,
Jaye smokes dope." The validity of this everyday syllogism depends on whether the
speaker believes that 1/All people who go to rock concerts smoke dope" or "Some
SYLLOGISTIC REASONING 1 71

people who go to rock concerts smoke dope." In understanding statements like


these, it's important that you specify which missing quantifier is intended. If "some"
is intended, then you quickly point out that it is not valid to conclude that Jaye was
among those who smoke dope. If "all" is intended, then you can question whether it
is the appropriate quantifier.

changing Attitudes with Syllogisms


The basic organization of two premises and a conclusion is frequently used to
change attitudes. When used in this fashion, the first premise is a belief premise, the
second premise is an evaluation of that belief or a reaction to the belief premise, and
the conclusion is the attitude (Shaver, 1 981 ). The basic structure is like this:

Belief premise
Evaluation premise
Attitude Conclusion

Consider how this works in the following example (Shaver, 1 981 ):

Preventing war saves lives.


Saving lives is good.
Therefore, preventing war is good.

Over time, attitude syllogisms become linked so that the conclusion from one syl­
logism is used as the evaluation premise of another:

Defense spending prevents war.


Preventing war is good.
Therefore, defense spending is good.

In these syllogisms, the middle term (remember what this means?) becomes the
reason for the conclusion. In general, the greater the number of syllogisms with the
same conclusion that we believe are true, the greater the support for the conclusion.
If I wanted you to conclude that defense spending is good, 1'd also tell you that:

Defense spending creates jobs.


Creating jobs is good.
Therefore, defense spending is good.

The quantifiers are implicit in these syllogisms, but the underlying organization
is the same. It's a matter of determining if a conclusion follows from the premises.

Common Errors in Syllogistic Reasoning

At this point in the history of psychology, when it is claimed that machines can
think, it seems strange to say that people cannot.
-Ceraso and Protivera (1971, p. 400)

Some syllogisms are more difficult to solve than others. An analysis of the erro­
neous conclusions that people make has revealed that the errors fall into distinct
1 72 4. REASONING

JUMP START © UFS Reprinted by Permission.

types or categories. One category of errors that we will consider here is illicit
conversions.

Illicit Conversions
No, this term has nothing to do with people who make you change religions
when you don't want to. It has to do with changing the meaning of a premise. When
most people read statements like "All A are B," the representation they form in their
mind is one in which it is also true that "All B are A" (Chapman & Chapman, 1959).
As you should realize by now, "All A are B" is not the same as "All B are A" Trans­
forming a premise into a nonequivalent form is a type of error known as an illicit
conversion. An example of an illicit conversion in if, then reasoning is the erroneous
assumption that "If A, then B" is the same as "If B, then A" In real-world terms,
knowing that "all Republicans voted for this bill" is not the same as saying
that everyone who voted for this bill was Republican. These are not equivalent
statements.
Another common illicit conversion is the belief that "Some A are not B" also im­
plies that "Some B are not A" The second statement is not equivalent to the first.
Here are circle diagrams of these two statements. As you can see more clearly in
their diagrams, they are not identical statements. To make this point clearer, con­
sider the difference between "Some of the children are not immunized" and "Some
of those immunized are not children."

A = children, B = immunized

1 . Some A are not B. Premise 1 a Premise 1 b


Some children are not immunized.

00 6)Premise 1 c
PROBABILISTIC REASONING 1 73

2. Some B are not A. Premise 2a Premise 2b


Some of those immunized

00 6)
are not children.

Premise 2c

PROBABILISTIC REASONING

The straight path of reason is narrow, the tempting byways are many and easier
of access.
-Joseph Jastrow

In everyday reasoning, we don't view premises as "truths" that will necessarily re­
quire certain conclusions; instead, we think of premises as statements that either
support or fail to support certain conclusions. Probabilistic reasoning occurs when
we use the information we have to decide that a conclusion is probably true or prob­
ably not true. In everyday reasoning, we rely on notions of probability to assess
the likelihood of a conclusion being true. Although probability is discussed in
Chapter 6, it is also a reasoning skill that we need to consider in this context.
Suppose you learn that people who have untreated diabetes are frequently
thirsty, urinate often, and experience sudden weight loss. You notice that you have
these symptoms. Does it necessarily follow that you have diabetes? No, of course
not, but these symptoms do make a diagnosis of diabetes more likely. In everyday
contexts, much of our reasoning is probabilistic.
Consider this example presented by Polya (I957, p. 186):

If we are approaching land, we see birds.


Now we see birds.
Therefore, it becomes more credible that we are approaching land.

In a shorthand format this becomes:

If A, then B.
B is true.
Therefore, A is more probable than it was before we knew that B is true.

Much of our everyday reasoning is of this sort, and although A is not guaranteed
with probabilistic reasoning, it does become more probable after we've told the sec­
ond premise. When viewed from the perspective of if, then reasoning, we would be
committing the fallacy of affirming the consequent. However, in real life we need to
consider many variables and goals. Although seeing birds doesn't guarantee that
land is near, 1'd be getting happy if I saw birds while I was drifting and lost at sea.
1 74 4. REASONING

Probabilistic reasoning is often a good strategy or "rule of thumb," especially be­


cause few things are known with absolute certainty in our probabilistic world. From
the standpoint of formal logic, it is invalid to conclude that land is near. As long as
you understand the nature of probabilities and the distinction between probabilistic
and valid (must be true if the premises are true) reasoning, considering probabilities
is a useful way of understanding and predicting events. When we reason in every­
day contexts, we consider the strength and likelihood of the evidence that supports
a conclusion and often decide if a conclusion is probable or improbable, not just
merely valid or invalid. This point is explained more fully in Chapter 7 on under­
standing probabilities.
As much of our reasoning is dependent on the rules of probability, McGuire
(1 981 ) has coined the term probabilogical to describe the joint effects of these disci­
plines on the way we think. Accordingly, we place greater faith in conclusions when
we believe that the premises are highly probable than when we believe that the
premises are unlikely.

Bounded Rationality

Nothing has an uglier look to us than reason, when it is not 011 our side.
-Halifax (Stat Quotes http://www.stats.org/newsletters/
001 1 /reasonquote.htm, retrieved January I I , 2002)

Does the fact that people often do not use the laws of logic when they reason mean
that we mere mortals are illogical or irrational (not reasoned)? Many psychologists
object to the idea that most people are illogical. As you have seen, people reason dif­
ferently depending on the context and seem to be able to use the rules of reasoning
better when the valid conclusion is one that we believe to be true than when it is not.
In the real world, the content of our reasoning does matter, so perhaps it is not sur­
prising that we find it difficult to reason from false or questionable premises. It
seems that people are rational, but with some limitations. The term bounded ratio­
nality is used to describe this state of affairs (Gigerenzer & Goldstein, 1996). We
usually need to reach conclusions and make decisions with incomplete information
and under time limits, and we rarely have "true premises." For example, we know if
we are asking permission or making an obligation, and the very different implica­
tions of if, then statements under these situations.

REASONING IN EVERYDAY CONTEXTS

Reasoning is the only ability that makes it possible for humans to rule the earth
and ruin it.
-Scriven (1976, p. 2)

Syllogisms, linear orderings, disjunctions, and if, then statements are commonly
found in everyday conversation. Of course, they are embedded in discourse and not
labeled by premise or conclusion. They are sometimes used in ways that seem either
to be deliberately misleading, or at least to capitalize on the common reasoning
errors that most people make.
REASONING IN EVERYDAY CONTEXTS 1 75

If you pay careful attention to bumper stickers, you'll probably be surprised to


find that many are simple reasoning problems. Consider the bumper sticker I saw
on a pick-up truck:

Off-road users
are not abusers.

The off-road users that this bumper sticker refers to are dirt bike riders who enjoy
racing through open land (unpaved areas) . Many people are concerned that this
sport is destroying our natural resources by tearing up the vegetation. This bumper
sticker is designed to present the opposing view. Notice how this is accomplished.
The term "all" is implied in the first premise, when in fact "some" is true. You
should recognize this as a syllogism with missing quantifiers.
Another popular bumper sticker that relies on missing quantifiers to make the
point is:

If guns are outlawed,


only outlaws will have guns.

This is a standard if, then statement. The implied conclusion is "don't outlaw
guns."
Suppose someone responded to this bumper sticker by suggesting that if guns
are outlawed, approximately 80% of the crimes of violence and 90% of the petty
crimes that are committed with a gun would probably be committed with a less
dangerous weapon. How does an argument like this refute the if, then statement
and its implied conclusion on the bumper sticker?
Here is a disjunctive argument that was common during the Vietnam War:
America, love it or leave it! You may be surprised to learn that this was a slogan for
those who went to fight in Vietnam. The implication was that antiwar protest meant
that you didn't love America. In Chapter 5, I'll return to the use of disjunctions and
ask if there really are only two options when we are given two options.

Reasoning With Diagrams

Although it seems like a lot of work to get used to thinking with diagrams, they are
useful in many situations where you have to check relationships and conceptualize.
The following discussion is loosely based on a discussion by Rubinstein and Pfeiffer
(1980) that I have applied to the events surrounding the Los Angeles riots that oc­
curred in 1992.
In 1992, following an unpopular verdict in which Los Angeles police officers
were acquitted of the crime of beating a suspect, an event that was captured on
video, a massive, bloody riot occurred. In the painful trials that followed, the prose­
cution attempted to show that a particular defendant was at the scene of the riot.
One piece of evidence was a footprint that was at the site. The strategy for the de­
fense was to show that many people could have left that particular foot print, but
the prosecution tried to show that few people other than the defendant could have
left the foot print. Look at these two diagrams.
1 76 4. REASONING

What the Defense Wants What the Prosecution Wants

Everyone Everyone
Defendant

People who People who


could leave could leave the
the footprint footprint

An expert from the Nike shoe company was called to testify that the print was
left by a Nike sneaker. The prosecution then showed that the defendant owned a
pair of Nikes in the same size as the footprint. This shrinks the size of the circle, so
that few people besides the defendant would fit those particular shoes.

Everyone

Everyone with size 10 Nikes

Defendant

By contrast, the defense tried to widen the circle by showing that many people in
that neighborhood wear Nike sneakers and that it was a popular shoe size. Each
side, in turn, tried to widen and then narrow the circle in an attempt to persuade the
jury that the defendant and few others could have left that footprint or many people
could have left that footprint.
Similar strategies are used implicitly in many trials. Here is a quote from an arti­
cle that appeared in the Los Angeles Times (Timnick, October 18, 1 989). It is a descrip­
tion of a trial for an accused child molester: "Telling an attentive jury in Los Angeles
Superior Court that the totality of evidence 'draws the ring around R. B. and P. B.
closer and tighter, to the extent that you should find them guilty.' " Here the idea of
drawing smaller and smaller circles was used explicitly in the prosecution's argu­
ments. Once you get used to using diagrams as a thinking aid, you will find that you
will use them often.

REASONING GONE WRONG

I hope that you are developing an appreciation for the critical importance of good
thinking. If you are not yet convinced, then I expect that this section will be a "chilly
awakening." In later chapters, I will continue to develop the theme that there are
many people who want to persuade you to believe that something is true-for a va­
riety of reasons. Often they will be trying to sell you something-a product, a philos­
ophy, a political candidate or point of view, or even a new view of history. Groups
that are attempting to rewrite history are called revisionists. Your only defense
against the onslaught of "sales" pitches is critical thinking. I heard a revisionist
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 1 77

speaker (someone who believes that we need to revise what we know about
history) who was attempting to convince a group of young adults that slavery in the
United States was "not really so bad." The presentation had all the outward appear­
ances of a standard reasoning problem. First, listeners were asked if they agreed that
people do not harm valuable property. Most nodded in agreement. Then they were
told that slaves were valuable property; therefore, most slave owners took good care
of their slaves. The speaker went on to say that "most slaves enjoyed being taken
care of," so slavery was not as bad as we had been led to believe. The scary part of
this scene was that there were many listeners who seemed to be considering this lu­
dicrous idea or could not figure out what was wrong with it. Can you?
I hope that you are outraged at this attempt to rewrite a disgraceful part of U. S.
history and to use what seems like reasoning to do it. It is true that most people do
not harm valuable property, but there are massive amounts of historical evidence
that slaves were often subjected to the most brutal and dehumanizing conditions.
The speaker left out far too many relevant facts to make his conclusion logical. There
was a seductiveness to the speaker's "logic," but it was patently wrong. There is no
substitute for critical thinking.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

1 . What Is the Goal?

In deductive reasoning, the goal is to determine which conclusions are valid


given premises or statements that we believe are true. When you identify your goal
as a deductive reasoning task, you will use the reasoning skills presented in this
chapter.

2 . What Is Known?

In everyday prose, you will have to convert phrases and sentences into a reason­
ing format. You will have to determine what the premises are before you can decide
whether they support a conclusion. Often quantifiers are missing and conclusions
are left unstated. Sometimes you will have to consider context to decide if "if, then"
really means "if, and only if, then." You will have to decide if you are reasoning
with implied or explicit quantifiers, if there is a linear ordering, and whether an if,
then statement is being made.
Perhaps, most importantly, you need to determine if you should be assuming
that the premises are true. A conclusion is valid if it follows from the premises, but
good reasoning from poor premises will not produce desirable outcomes.

3. Which Thinking Skill Will Get You to Your Goal?


The following skills to determine whether a conclusion is valid were presented in
this chapter. Review each skill and be sure that you understand how and when to
use each one.

• Discriminating between deductive and inductive reasoning


• Identifying premises and conclusions
1 78 4. REASONING

• Using quantifiers in reasoning


• Solving categorical syllogisms with circle diagrams
• Solving categorical syllogisms with verbal rules
• Understanding the difference between truth and validity
• Recognizing when syllogisms are being used to change attitudes
• Using linear diagrams to solve linear syllogisms
• Watching for marked adjectives
• Using the principles of linear orderings as an aid to clear communication
• Reasoning with if, then statements
• Using tree diagrams with if, then statements
• Avoiding the fallacies of confirming the consequent and denying the
antecedent
• Examining reasoning in everyday contexts for missing quantifiers

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?

This is an accuracy check on your work. When determining valid conclusions


from categorical syllogisms, did you get the same answer with both the rules for
syllogisms and the circle diagrams? Did you consider all combinations of represen­
tations when drawing your diagrams? Did you consciously consider common fallac­
ies and biases so as to be sure to avoid them? Does your answer make sense?

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Deductive reasoning is the use of premises or statements that we accept as true


to derive valid conclusions.
2. People don't approach reasoning problems according to the laws of formal
logic. Instead of determining whether a conclusion logically follows from the
premises as they are stated, there is a tendency to alter the premises according to
one's own beliefs and then decide whether a conclusion follows from the altered
statements.
3. Human reasoning is often biased by beliefs about emotional issues.
4. It is common to confuse truth with validity. Validity refers to the form of an ar­
gument and is unrelated to content. If a conclusion necessarily follows from the
premises, then it is valid. The topic of truth and believability of premises are ad­
dressed in the next chapter.
5. In linear orderings, we use premises to establish conclusions about ordered re­
lationships. A good strategy for solving linear orderings is to use a spatial represen­
tation with the items arranged in an ordered manner.
6. In if, then statements a conditional relationship is established. As in syllo­
gisms and linear orderings, the premises that are given are used to determine valid
conclusions.
7. "If" is frequently interpreted as "if and only if" in if, then statements. Although
this conversion is an error according to the rules of formal logic, sometimes it is jus­
tified by the context in which it is embedded.
8. Confirmation bias is the predilection or tendency to seek and utilize informa­
tion that supports or confirms the hypothesis or premise that is being considered.
The "four-card selection task" is a demonstration of this robust bias.
TERMS TO KNOW 1 79

9. Quantitative syllogisms indicate which terms belong in the categories that are
specified. Statements in syllogisms can take one of four different moods: universal
affirmative, particular affirmative, universal negative, and particular negative.
10. When syllogisms involve meaningful terms and categories, people often use
their knowledge of the categories and their beliefs about the topics to determine
which conclusions are valid instead of reasoning from the form of the syllogism.
1 1 . Circle diagrams are useful aids for understanding relationships and checking
inferences in syllogisms. The extent to which circles overlap depicts category inclu­
sion and exclusion. An alternative to circle diagrams that many people prefer is to
check conclusions for validity using the verbal rules of syllogisms.
12. The greatest difficulty in using circle diagrams is being certain that all combi­
nations of the two premises have been represented.
13. Illicit conversions are common errors in syllogisms. The most frequent illicit
conversion is to interpret "All A are B" as also meaning that "All B are A."
14. Diagrams are useful reasoning tools in many situations. The logic of circle dia­
grams is frequently used in legal settings and other settings in which evidence is
considered.

TERMS TO KNOW

Check your understanding of the concepts presented in this chapter by reviewing


their definitions. If you find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to
reread the section in which it is discussed.

Reasoning. Has two forms: deductive and inductive. When reasoning deductively,
we use our knowledge of two or more premises to infer if a conclusion is valid.
When reasoning inductively, we collect observations and formulate hypotheses
based on them.
Conclusion. An inferential belief that is derived from other statements.
Logic. A branch of philosophy that explicitly states the rules for deriving valid
conclusions.
Valid. A conclusion is valid if it must be true if the premises are true. It "follows
from" the premises.
Premises. Statements that allow the inference of logical conclusions.
Illogical. Reaching conclusions that are not in accord with the rules of logic.
Failure to Accept the Logical Task. In everyday reasoning, we alter the statements
we're given according to our personal beliefs and then decide if a conclusion follows
from the altered statements. We reject the logical task of deciding if a conclusion fol­
lows from the statements as they are given.
Personal Logic. The informal rules that people use to determine validity.
Pragmatic. Anything that is practical. In this context, the consideration of context
and purpose when engaging in real-world reasoning tasks.
Inductive Reasoning. Observations are collected that suggest or lead to the formu­
lation of a conclusion or hypothesis.
Deductive Reasoning. Use of stated premises to formulate conclusions that can
logically be inferred from them.
Linear Ordering. Also known as linear syllogism. Reasoning that involves the infer­
ence of orderly relationships along a single dimension (e.g., size, position) among terms.
1 80 4. REASONING

Linear Syllogism. See linear ordering.


Marked Adjectives. Adjectives that connote bias when they appear in a question
(e.g., poor, dumb, or small). When asked "How poor is he/' it is presumed that the
response will be toward the poor extreme and not toward the rich extreme.
Unmarked Adjectives. Adjectives that are neutral in that they don't connote a par­
ticular direction when they appear in a question (e.g., big, smart, tall). When asked
"How big is he?" the response could be a larger or a small number. Compare with
marked adjective.
Belief Bias. Also known as confirmation bias. The interference of one's personal be­
liefs with the ability to reason logically.
If, Then Statements. Statements of a contingency relationship such that if the an­
tecedent is true, then the consequent must be true.
Contingency Relationships. Relationships that are expressed with it then state­
ments. The consequent is contingent or dependent on the antecedent.
Conditional Logic. Also known as propositional logic. Logical statements that are
expressed in an if, then format.
Antecedent. In it then statements, it is the information given in the "if' clause ap­
pealing to your reason.
Consequent. In it then statements, it is the information given in the "then" clause.
Tree Diagrams. Diagrams in which the critical information is represented along the
branches of a "tree."
Affirming the Antecedent. In if, then reasoning, the second premise asserts that the
"if part is true.
II

Denying the Consequent. In it then reasoning, the second premise asserts that the
"then" part is false.
Affirming the Consequent. In it then reasoning, the second premise asserts that
the "then" part is true.
Illicit Conversion. Illicit conversions, in it then statements occur when people be­
lieve that "If A, then B" also means "If B, then A."
Denying the Antecedent. In it then reasoning, the second premise asserts that the
"if part is false.
II

Double Negation. The denial of a negative statement.


Four-Card Selection Task. A task that is often used to demonstrate confirmation bi­
ases. Subjects are required to indicate which of four cards they need to turn over in
order to verify a rule about the contents of each side of the card. Overwhelmingly,
subjects only select cards that will confirm the hypothesis that they are considering
instead of seeking information that would disconfirm their hypothesis.
Permission Schema. Informal rules that people use when reasoning with it then
statements that pragmatically give permission.
Obligation Schema. Informal rules that people use when reasoning with it then
statements that pragmatically create an obligation.
Chained Conditional. Two it then statements linked so that the consequent of one
statement is also the antecedent of the other statement.
Combinatorial Reasoning. The use of systematic and orderly steps when making
combinations so that all possible combinations are formed .
Syllogistic Reasoning. A form of reasoning that involves deciding whether a
conclusion can be properly inferred from two or more statements that contain
quantifiers.
Categorical Reasoning. A type of syllogistic reasoning in which the quantifiers
"some/' "all/' "no/' and "none are used to indicate category membership.
II
TERMS TO KNOW 181

Quantifiers. Terms like "all," "some," "none," and "no" that are used in syllogisms
to indicate category membership.
Syllogism. Two or more premises that are used to derive a valid conclusion or
conclusions.
Mood. Used to classify the premises and conclusions of a categorical syllogism.
There are four moods that are dependent on the quantifiers used in the statements.
The four moods are: universal affirmative (all A are B); particular affirmative (some
A are B); universal negative (no A are B); and particular negative (some A are not B).
Universal Affirmative. The mood of statements in a categorical syllogism with the
format "All A are B."
Particular Affirmative. The mood of statements in a categorical syllogism with the
format "Some A are B."
Universal Negative. The mood of statements in a categorical syllogism with the
format "No A are not B."
Particular Negative. The mood of statements in a categorical syllogism with the
format "Some A are not B."
Circle Diagrams. A spatial strategy for determining the validity of a conclusion in a
categorical syllogism. Circles are used to represent category membership.
Middle Term. In a categorical syllogism it is the term that is omitted from the con­
clusion and is mentioned in both premises.
Distributed. In a categorical syllogism a term is distributed when it is modified by
"all," "no," or "not."
Ecological Validity. Concerns the real-world validity or applications of a concept
outside of the laboratory.
Illicit Conversions. Transformations of the premises in a syllogism into nonequiva­
lent forms (e.g., converting "All A are B" into "All B are A").
Probabilogical. Term coined to label the joint influences of probability and logic on
the way we think.
Bounded Rationality. People are rational, within limits. People do not behave like
logic machines, but use thinking shortcuts to save time.
5

Analyzing ArguInents

Contents
The Anatomy of an Argument How to Analyze an Argument
Premises A Rubric for Scoring Arguments­
Conclusions Even Your Own
Assumptions A Template For Writings and Arguments
Qualifiers Reasoning and Rationalizing
Counterarguments Persuasion and Propaganda
Diagramming the Structure of an The Psychology of Reasons
Argument Explaining as Knowing
Guidelines for Diagramming Twenty-One Common Fallacies
Arguments Distinguishing Among Opinion,
Using Argument Structure When Reasoned Judgment, and Fact
Writing and Speaking Visual Arguments
Actively Open-Minded Thinking How to Change Beliefs
Historical Evidence Applying the Framework
Evaluating the Strength of an Chapter Summary
Argument Terms to Know
Acceptable and Consistent Premises
Credibility
The Credibility Crisis
Premises That Support the
Conclusion
Missing Components
Sound Arguments

1 82
THE ANATOMY OF AN ARGUMENT 1 83

Eat All Day and Still Lose Weight


Trade your old body for a new one now through an amazing scientific breakthrough.
Doctors and medical technicians have made it possible for people like you and me to
lose weight quickly and permanently. Tested at university labs, retested at clinics and
major hospitals and acclaimed by doctors all over the world, finally there is something
that helps you lose weight. If years of stubborn fat build up have been your problem,
NOW AT LAST THERE IS A WAY TO ELIMINATE FAT, A WAY TO LOSE WEIGHT
FAST AND EASILY. We call it XXXXXXX because it totally attacks excess fat and fluids
that have plagued most people for years . . . . Everyday you will feel stronger and full of
pep and energy as the excess weight you have carried for so long is carved off your
body. . . . DON'T LET THIS GOLDEN OPPORTUNITY AND CHANCE OF A LIFE­
TIME PASS YOU BY. Just fill out the coupon below and let it be the ticket to a slimmer
you. So, what are you waiting for?

I hope that you weren't looking for a coupon for this marvelous weight loss prod­
uct. The paragraph above was taken verbatim from a full-page advertisement in a
popular fashion magazine. The only change that I made was to omit the name of
this "miracle" diet. The name has a chemical sound to it. It's multisyllabic and ends
with a number. The name sounds like a chemical formula. I had trouble selecting
which advertisement I wanted to use here because there were so many that made
numerous unsupported claims. Advertisements like this one can be found in most
magazines and newspapers. I'll refer back to this advertisement later in this chapter
when I talk about analyzing arguments and recognizing fallacies. Hold onto your
money until you've read this chapter.

THE ANATOMY OF AN ARGUMENT

Neither a closed mind nor an empty one is likely to produce much that would
qualify as effective reasoning.
-Nickerson (1986, p. 1 )

The technical meaning of the word argument is different from its everyday mean­
ing. When we use the word argument in everyday language, it means a dispute or a
quarrel. We say two people "are having an argument" when they disagree about
something in a heated or emotional way. More technically, an argument consists of
one or more statements that are used to provide support for a conclusion. The state­
ments that proVide the support for a conclusion are called the reasons or premises
of the argument. The reasons or premises are presented in order to persuade the
reader or listener that the conclusion is true or probably true. Let's consider an ex­
ample. Suppose that I want to convince you to stay in college until graduation. Here
are some reasons (premises) that I could give. You can think of this as an addition
problem with each premise summing to the conclusion.

Premise #1: College graduates earn more money than college dropouts or people who
have never attended college.
+ Premise #2: College graduates report that they are more satisfied with their lives than
people who have not graduated from college.
+ Premise #3: College graduates are healthier and live longer than people who have not
graduated from college.
1 84 5. Al"JALYZING ARGUMENTS

+ Premise #4: College graduates have jobs that are more interesting and more
responsible than people who have not graduated from college.
Conclusion: You should graduate from college.

Arguments are sometimes called "the giving of reasons." Harmon (1986) calls this
process "a change in view" because the objective is to change an "old view" or belief
into a "new view" or belief with reasoning.
Old View Reasoning • New View
-------'----+
or Belief or Belief

Every argument will have one or more premises (or reasons) and one or more
conclusions. Usually, there will be several premises for one conclusion, but other
combinations (one premise for several conclusions and several premises for several
conclusions) are possible. If you cannot identify at least one premise and at least
one conclusion, then it is not an argument. Of course, in everyday, natural­
language arguments, the premises and conclusions are not labeled. They are usually
embedded in extended prose. The extended prose could be a paragraph, a section or
chapter of a book, or even an entire book or semester-long class.
Here are some examples of prose that are not arguments:

• I like my critical thinking course better than my chemistry course. (No reasons
are given for this preference.)
• We drove up to the mountains, went skiing, then drove home. (This is just a de­
scriptive list of activities linked together. There are no reasons or conclusions.)
• Buy your burgers at Burgerland. (No reasons given, but see the section below
because reasons are often inferred from context in statements like this one.)
• We saw the Martians land. (This is a simple description.)
• Never trust anyone over 30. (This is an opinion without reasons.)
• Is dinner ready? (simple question.)

It may seem that it should be fairly simple to determine whether a statement or set
of statements contain an argument, but in everyday language most arguments are in­
complete. Sometimes the premises aren't stated, but are inferred, and other times the
conclusion is unstated. Sometimes arguments are deliberately disguised so that it
may appear that the speakers are not supporting some conclusion, when they really
are. Consider the popular automobile advertisement that goes something like this:
More people have bought LaBaroness automobiles than any other American car.

At first glance, this seems like a straightforward declarative sentence with no


reasons and no conclusion. But, the advertisers expect consumers to convert this
sentence into an argument. When you hear this sentence, you presumably start gen­
erating your own reasons for the popularity of La Baroness. If more people are buy­
ing it, it must be best and shouldn't you also buy the best? This is an example in
which the listener supplies both the reasons and the conclusion. Statements very
similar to this one can be found in advertisements for a diverse assortment of prod­
ucts including beer, beauty supplies, fitness clubs, and airlines. (The use of the com­
parative term "more" is discussed later in this chapter.)
If an advertiser wants to be sure that you supply the missing reasons and conclu­
sion, the advertisement could be altered slightly so that it now reads:

More people have bought LaBaroness automobiles than any other American car. There
must be some very good reasons.
THE ANATOMY OF AN ARGUMENT 1 85

Notice that a second sentence was added, but no reasons were given. It is ex­
pected that the second sentence will cue listeners (or readers) to start supplying
their own reasons.

Premises

The premises are the reasons that support a conclusion. They are the "why" part of
an argument. In everyday language, they can appear anywhere among a set of state­
ments. Sometimes, the conclusion will be stated first followed by its premises. (Here
is what I believe and the reasons for this belief are . . . . ) Other times the conclusion
may be presented last or embedded in the middle of a paragraph or other text with
premises both before and after it. Premises are not always easy to recognize. There
are certain key words, called premise indicators or premise markers, that often sig­
nal that what comes after them is a premise. Although premise indicators aren't al­
ways followed by a premise, they often are, and for this reason, it is a good idea to
check for these key words when identifying premises. These terms often indicate
that what follows is a reason.

Premise Indicators
because
for
since (when it means because and not the passage of time)
if
given that (or being that)
as shown by
as indicated by
the reasons are
it may be inferred (or deduced) from
the evidence consists of
in the first place (suggests that a list of premises will follow)
secondly
seeing that
assuming that
it follows from
whereas

Here are some simple examples of the use of premise indicators.

• You should graduate from college because you will earn more money with a
college degree.
• The need for the United States to send troops to Central America is indicated
by the buildup of armed rebels in countries neighboring those with civil wars.
• Seeing that the current policy of supplying organ transplants is benefiting the

rich, a new program is needed.

Premises can be "matters of fact" or "matters of opinion" or both. Consider, for


example, the following sentences:

• All teenagers should be taught safe sex practices because of the risk of AIDS
and other sexually transmitted diseases. (The reason is a matter of fact.)
1 86 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

• All teenagers should be taught how to knit because this will provide them with
an enjoyable hobby. (The reason is a matter of opinion.)

Conclusions

The conclusion is the purpose or the "what" of the argument. It is the belief or point
of view that is supported or defended with the premises. Both the premises and the
conclusion are important, and both are essential components of any argument.
It is usually easier to identify the conclusion of an argument than the other com­
ponents. For this reason, it is a good idea to start with the conclusion when you are
analyzing arguments. There are conclusion indicators or conclusion markers that
indicate that what follows is probably a conclusion. As with premise indicators,
they do not guarantee that a conclusion follows them.

Conclusion Indicators
therefore
hence
so
thus
consequently
then
shows that (we can see that)
accordingly
it follows that
we may infer (conclude) (deduce) that
in summary
as a result
for all these reasons
it is clear that

Some simple examples of the use of conclusion indicators are:

• Based on all of the reasons just stated, wecan conclude that the flow of illegal
drugs must be stopped.
• In summary, postal rates must be increased because we can no longer afford to
run the postal system with a deficit.
• We have had very little rain this season. Consequently, water will have to be
rationed.

Has my use of the word simple to describe these examples made you feel uneasy?
Have you begun to expect that things will soon get more complex? If so, you are
right. Natural-language is complex and so are natural-language arguments. (A nat­
ural language is a language that has evolved over time for the purpose of communi­
cation between people. Artificial languages are those languages that were created
for special purposes such as computer languages.) Although all arguments must
contain at least one argument and one conclusion, most arguments consist of addi­
tional components. Three additional components will be presented here. They are
assumptions, qualifiers, and counterarguments.
THE ANATOMY OF AN ARGUMENT 1 87

Assumptions

With enough assumptions, any policy can be justified.


-Tim Brennan (January 1 2, 2001 , from a guide to
understanding how Washington really works)

An assumption is a statement for which no proof or evidence is offered. Although


assumptions can be either stated or unstated (implied), they are most often un­
stated. Advertisements and political rhetoric are good places to look for examples of
stated and unstated assumptions. Let's go back to the example of the advertisement
for LaBaroness, which was presented earlier in this chapter (I changed the name of
the real car being advertised.):

More people have bought LaBaroness automobiles than any other American car.

The implied statement is that if more people bought LaBaroness, it must be better
(in some way) than its competitors. The unstated assumption is that when large
numbers of consumers make a choice, it is a good choice. There is no justification for
this assumption. The implied conclusion is that you should also be making this wise
choice. The advertisement could easily be altered so that the assumption is made
explicitly:

More people have bought LaBaroness automobiles than any other American car. When so
many people agree, it must be the right choice.

Notice that with the addition of the second sentence, the assumption is now
stated explicitly. It is still an assumption because it is stated without any justifica­
tion. If I had supplied some justification for this belief, then it would no longer be an
assumption. Suppose I alter these statements so that they now become:

More people have bought LaBaroness automobiles than any other American car. Recent
research by several well-known social psychologists and economists has shown that when­
ever a majority of people agree on something, they make the best choice.

Look carefully at the changes I just made. In this version, I provided a reason or
justification for believing that, whenever large numbers of people make a choice,
it is a good one. The research that I made up is phony, but suppose for now that it is
true. The research findings become the premises or reasons for the conclusion that,
whenever large numbers of people make a choice, it will be a good one. In this con­
text, it is no longer an assumption because there are now reasons supporting it. This
new conclusion then becomes the premise for the unstated conclusion that you
should also buy LaBaroness. If you read the previous chapter on reasoning, this
should not be a new idea for you. The idea that the conclusion from one set of state­
ments can then become the premise for another set of statements was demonstrated
in Chapter 4. In extended (longer) arguments, the conclusion from one set of state­
ments will often become the premise in another set of statements.
The arguments that are used to build the main argument are called subargu­
ments. The main argument in an extended passage is called the main point. The
kinds of arguments that are often found in books, book chapters, and sometimes
sections of chapters proceed in stages with subarguments linked to provide support
for a main point.
1 88 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

Here is another example of an unstated assumption. The following example was


taken from a catalogue that sells copper bracelets. I have altered it only slightly for
this context.

For hundreds of years people have worn copper bracelets to relieve pain from arthritis.
This folklore belief has persisted and copper bracelets continue to be popular. These bracelets
promote close contact between the copper and your wrist.

The writers of this advertisement expect that readers will assume that copper can
help alleviate the pain of arthritis and that the "medical" effect is enhanced by the
close contact with the wrist. Notice that this is never stated-it can't be because
there is no evidence that shows that copper has any effect on arthritis. However, this
advertisement for copper bracelets is clearly written to suggest that it works. (Many
people believe that it does.) Furthermore, there is a suggested assumption that the
popularity of copper bracelets is due to its medical effects. Maybe they have just be­
come fashionable, or cheaper, or better advertised, or perhaps there are just more
people with arthritis who are willing to believe anything that promises to relieve
their pain. We'll discuss the need to consider missing information and alternative
conclusions in a later section of this chapter.

Qualifiers

A qualifier is a constraint or restriction on the conclusion. It states the conditions


under which the conclusion is supported. An example might be helpful:

It is important that we have some indicators of what and how much students are learning
in college. For this reason, a national college-level testing program is needed. However, if the
national assessment is not related to the subjects taught in the college curriculum, then it will
not be a valid measure of college-level learning.

Let's dissect this paragraph into its component parts:

The conclusion is: A national college-level testing program is needed.


A premise is: It is important that we have some indicators of what and how much
students are learning in college. (This is the reason that supports the conclu­
sion. It tells us why we should believe that the conclusion is true.)
An unstated assumption is: A national college-level testing program is a good way
to indicate what students are learning.
A qualifier (or limiting condition) is: The conclusion is valid only when the assess­
ment is related to what is the curriculum.

As you can see from this example, a qualifier states the conditions under which
the conclusion is valid. It sets limits or constraints on the conclusion.

counterarguments

Critical thinking requires a sense of the complexity of human issues.


-Sears and Parsons (1991, p. 64)
DIAGRAMMING THE STRUCTURE OF AN ARGUMENT 1 89

Sometimes, an extended argument will state reasons that support a particular con­
clusion and reasons that refute the same conclusion. The set of statements that re­
fute a particular conclusion is called a counterargument. Let's extend the previous
argument so that it now also contains a counterargument.

It is important that we have some indicators of what and how much students are learning
in college. For this reason, a national college-level testing program is needed. However, if the
national assessment is not related to the subjects taught in the college curriculum, then it will
not be a valid measure of college-level learning. Of course, the results of a national assess­
ment of college students could be misused in a way that would keep good students from en­
tering graduate or professional school.

I hope that you're paying careful attention to the way the additions are altering
the argument. As presented above, the conclusion, premise, assumption, and quali­
fier remain the same. The counterargument presents a reason for not having a na­
tional college-level test. The reason presented (results could be misused) is counter
to the conclusion that we should have a national test-that is why these statements
are called counterarguments. Even with the addition of the counterargument, the
conclusion remains unchanged. The argument was written in a way that suggests
that the counterargument is weaker than the main argument. The point being made
is that despite the counterargument, we should still have a national test of college
students-the conclusion is the same.
Does this particular example make you uneasy? Can you think of other premises
that might support a different conclusion? If so, you have already begun to antici­
pate the content of the section on how to evaluate arguments.

DIAGRAMMING THE STRUCTURE OF AN ARGUMENT

Argument is a central feature of the resolution of scientific controversies.


Driver, Newton, and Osborne (2000, p. 287)

Arguments are a related series of statements that are made in an attempt to get the
reader or listener to believe that the conclusion is true. In order to analyze or dissect
an argument we need to know not only its component parts, but also how the parts
are related to each other. Arguments are made up of parts that are synthesized or
put together when an argument is made, and parts that can be disassembled as one
way to understand them. The parts that make up an argument are premise(s), con­
clusion(s), assumption(s), qualifier(s), and counterargument(s). The only restriction
on arguments is that each must have at least one premise and one conclusion. Be­
yond this, a large variety of arrangements is possible. A good way to understand the
relationships among the parts of a prose passage is to draw a diagram. Diagrams are
used in every chapter of this book because they require the drawer to be specific
about the relationships being depicted and to think about underlying relationships.
Drawing a diagram is a good general thinking strategy.
Let's consider the simplest argument with only one premise and one conclusion.

[Be sure to get plenty of aerobic exercise P because [aerobic exercise will help you build a
strong cardiovascular systemV
1 90 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

This argument is made up of two statements. I have indicated them by putting


brackets around each and numbering them " 1 " and "2." A statement is a phrase or
sentence for which it makes sense to ask "Is this true or false?" The answer to this
question is not relevant here; that is, it doesn't matter if the statement really is true
or false, only whether it makes sense to ask if the phrase is true or false. For exam­
ple, the following are not statements: Rinse the spaghetti. Who lives here? Is that
house for sale? Wow! Commands, questions, and exclamations are not statements
because it makes no sense to ask if they have a "truth value"; that is, it makes no
sense to ask if they are true or false.
Look again at the simple argument in the paragraph above. Identify which of the
two statements is the conclusion and which is the premise.
Conclusion: [Get plenty of aerobic exercise.] Remember, the conclusion is
the statement that indicates what you should believe or what you should do.
(I started with the conclusion because this is often the easiest part of the argument to
identify.)
Premise: [Aerobic exercise will build a strong cardiovascular system. ] This is the
"why" part of the argument that gives a reason for believing the conclusion.
A diagram of this relationship shows that the conclusion is supported by the
premise:

[1 ] [Get plenty of aerobic exercise]-the conclusion

i
[2] [Aerobic exercise will help you build a strong cardiovascular system]-the premise

As you can see, the statement that is the conclusion [ 1 ] is at the top of the diagram
and the premise [2] is holding it up. This is shown with the arrow that points from
the premise to the conclusion.
Now let's consider an argument in which two different premises support one
conclusion. Again, I have bracketed each statement and numbered each:

[Be sure to get plenty of aerobic exerciseP because [aerobic exercise will help you build a
strong cardiovascular systemF and [it will lower your resting heart ratej 3,

[1] Conclusion: Get plenty of exercise.


[2] Premise: Aerobic exercise will build a strong cardiovascular system.
[31 Premise: Aerobic exercise will lower your resting heart rate.

A diagram of this argument will look like this:

[1] [Conclusion]

/�
[2] [3]
/ �
[Premise] [Premise]

In this diagram, we have two premises supporting one conclusion. Both of the ar­
rows point to the same conclusion. This is called a convergent structure because
both premises converge onto the same conclusion; that is, they are both reasons why
you should get plenty of aerobic exercise. Longer arguments will often contain
DIAGRAMMING THE STRUCTURE OF AN ARGUMENT 191

several premises that support a conclusion. Let's compare this argument structure
to one in which two premises are linked to each other, so that instead of both
premises supporting the same conclusion, the first premise is the reason for the sec­
ond premise, which, in turn, becomes the reason for the conclusion.

[It is important that you work through all of the problems in the workbookj1 because [the
problems will help you to learn the skills of critical thinking.] 2 We can conclude that [working
the problems in the workbook will help you to learn the skillsf based on research that shows
that [active learning promotes long-term retention.j 3

In this example, we really have three different statements. The statement that I
labeled [2] appears twice.

[1] Conclusion: It is important to work through all of the problems in the work­
book. This is the conclusion-the part that tells you what to do or believe.
[2] Premise for [1]: Working through the problems will help you to learn critical
thinking skills. This is a reason for the conclusion.
[3] Premise for [2]: Active learning promotes long-term retention. This is a reason
for believing that working the problems will help you to learn critical think­
ing skills.

A diagram of this argument will look like this:

[1 ] [It is important to work through all of the problems in the workbook]

i i
[2] [Working through the problems will help you to learn critical thinking skills]

i i
[3] [Active learning promotes long-term retention]

Arguments in which the conclusion of one subargument becomes the premise of


a second argument are called chained (or linked) structures. Can you see an impor­
tant distinction between this type of argument in which [3] is a reason for [2] and [21
is a reason for [ 1 ] and the previous structure in which both [2] and [3] are reasons
for [ l ] ? Remember the old saying that a chain is only as strong as its weakest link?
When arguments have a chained structure, the conclusion is only as strong as the
weakest subargument. If [3] doesn't provide very much support for [2], then the
conclusion [1] is weakened. By contrast, when two or more premises converge onto
the same conclusion, we only increase the strength of the conclusion by adding
more premises.
Let's consider an example in which there are three premises and two conclusions.

[Taylor was late for schooll! because [she oversleptF and [she had to stop for gas.j3 [Taylor
doesn't care much about school]4, therefore [she is often late.]S

In Chapter 4 on deductive reasoning, I talked about skeleton structures-sort of


fill-in-the-blank structures where it doesn't matter what gets filled in. The skeleton
is the "bare bones" of an argument, the place where you hang your statements. Let's
reduce this argument to its skeleton:

[1] because [2] and [3]. [4] therefore [5] .


1 92 5. ANALYZlNG ARGUMENTS

This is a good way to think about premise and conclusion indicators. Any state­
ment that follows because will probably be a premise ([2] and [3]), and any state­
ment that follows therefore will probably be a conclusion ([5]).
Can you see how [2] and [3] are premises for [1], and [4] is a premise for [5]?
A diagram of this argument will look like this:

[1] [5]

/ "'"
[2] [3]
i
[4]

This is an example of two separate arguments in the same paragraph.

Guidelines for Diagramming Arguments

In understanding complex arguments, it is wise to identify the conclusions,


premises, assumptions, qualifiers, and counterarguments, and then diagram the
structure of their relationship. It is often useful to tum the argument into its skeleton
form, so that relationships can be seen more clearly apart from the content. This
strategy is a useful aid in determining how good a particular argument is. The major
difficulty in using this procedure is that complex arguments have complex struc­
tures. Sometimes there is more than one possible interpretation and, correspond­
ingly, more than one possible diagram. Sometimes the difficulty lies in deciding if a
statement is really part of a subargument or part of the main argument. In longer
text, you will often have to restate premises, conclusions, counterarguments, as­
sumptions, and qualifiers in your own words. This process can involve reducing
whole chapters of books to single statements. Although this can be difficult, it is an
excellent strategy for comprehension. Often the process of diagramming will reveal
what's wrong or right about a certain argument. If more than one diagram of an ar­
gument is pOSSible, then you can consider each separately. Does one diagram pro­
vide stronger support for the conclusion? Is one diagram a "truer" representation of
the statements being made?
You won't want to diagram every argument you read or hear, but sometimes the
issues are troublesome and important, and diagramming can be very useful in clari­
fying the underlying relationships among the statements. Writing and diagramming
unstated premises, conclusions, and assumptions can also be very helpful in consid­
ering the strength or quality of an argument by making these components explicit
and placing them in the argument framework. Like many of the other strategies pre­
sented in this book, you will have to work at learning and using the steps in analyz­
ing arguments. However, also like the other strategies, there is good evidence that
the work is worth it. Allegretti and Frederick (1995), for example, reported that col­
lege students showed significant gains on a standardized test of critical thinking
after they learned how to analyze arguments.

Using Argument Structure When Writing and Speaking

In your own writing and speaking, you often need to persuade an audience that
your conclusions are correct. Before you write or make an oral presentation, be sure
ACTIVELY OPEN-MINDED THINKING 1 93

that you can answer the following questions:

1 . What is your conclusion? In other words, what is the point (or points) you
want to make? Arguments are made, or constructed, from their parts, and
there is no argument if there is no conclusion. Although this question is first
on the list, do not start with the conclusion that you want or believe to be true
and then find reasons to support it. Look at reasons and evidence that address
a particular issue in as unbiased a way as possible to determine what conclu­
sion is best supported. The idea of taking a position on a controversial issue
and then finding support for that position is a close-minded approach to think­
ing. If an issue is controversial, then there should be support for both sides (or
more than two sides), and critical thinkers should be able to cite support for
multiple positions, and decide on the best conclusion by weighing all of the
available evidence.
2. What are the reasons that support your conclusion? How strong are they?
3. What assumptions are you making? Are they reasonable assumptions? Should
they be explicitly stated?
4. What are the conditions under which the conclusion might not be true? In
other words, are qualifiers needed?
5. What are the counterarguments? Why should a reader or listener not believe in
your conclusion? What alternative conclusions have you actively considered?
6. What's missing? Are other conclusions possible given the reasons? Are there
other reasons? Other counterarguments? Other assumptions? This step re­
quires that you look beyond the information that you are using to consider
what else might be important.

ACTIVELY OPEN-MINDED THINKING

Another reason why you should learn how to analyze arguments concerns what
Seech (1993) calls "points of logical vulnerability." There are some topics about
which we have trouble being objective. For example, I know that it would be diffi­
cult for me to be objective about the Ku Klux Klan. This is an emotional topic for me,
and I would have great difficulty concluding anything positive about this group. If I
used argument analysis, especially by reducing an argument to its skeleton and then
diagramming its structure, then I could assess the strength of the support for a con­
clusion more fairly than I could without this sort of analysis. Of course, I could still
decide that any belief or action that they are advocating is wrong.
There is a theme that reoccurs in almost every chapter in this text-the pervasive­
ness of the confirmation bias-the bias to look for and prefer information that con­
firms prior beliefs (Nickerson, 1998). It is a very strong influence on the way many,
perhaps all, of us think and feel, and for the most part, we are unaware of its effects.
Information that supports conclusions that we believe to be true just seems better
than information that doesn't. We all need to develop the conscious effort to look for
and evaluate fairly evidence that is not preferred.
Think about some topic about which you have strong feelings-it could be gun
control, censorship, school vouchers, innate differences between the sexes, the
United Nations, the death penalty, or anything else where the conclusion (what to
do or believe) is clear to you. Now suppose that you come across strong evidence
1 94 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

that supports a different conclusion than the one you prefer-let's say it makes a
strong case for allowing open access to guns and you favor strict control of gun ac­
cess or you are given data that show that the death penalty increases the crime rate
and you favor the death penalty. How would you respond? I suppose that you
would want to know more-how the data were collected, what the data actually
showed, but assume for now that there are strong data that support a conclusion
you totally oppose. Now what? Baron (1993) used the term "actively open-minded"
to describe people who can change a cherished belief when given good reasons to
do so. It turns out that actively and honestly processing information that runs
counter to prior beliefs is very difficult, but there are people who can remain open­
minded enough to evaluate an argument objectively, independent of their prior be­
liefs (Baron, 1995; Stanovich & West, 1 997). It is not impossible to be fair-minded,
but it is difficult.

Historical Evidence

How do you know that World War II really happened and that it is not just a made­
up story to serve as the background for Hollywood war movies? When I asked this
question in class one day, a student told me that he knew that World War II really
happened because his grandfather was there-his grandfather fought in the war,
and it was as horrible as we have read in our history books. Based on the information
we had, it was easy to conclude that the student's grandfather was a credible source
of information for this topic. In addition, he had war injuries to support his story.
The question may seem strange, but there are groups of people who claim that sto­
ries about World War II are exaggerated (or lies) and that there was no mass extermi­
nation of the Jews in Europe. Similarly, there are groups that claim that slavery in the
United States was not so bad (as mentioned in the last chapter). In fact, there may be
groups that deny everything we know about history and science. How can we hon­
estly assess these claims? It seems that all "fringe" groups that advocate a point of
view that is not well supported use similar methods in constructing their arguments.
How can we analyze historical arguments? In an outstanding analysis of the ar­
guments used by "Holocaust deniers" (people who claim that the Holocaust never
happened or that it has been exaggerated), Shermer (1997, p. 212) wrote that these
groups:

1 . Concentrate on any weakness in their opponents' argument instead of provid­


ing strong evidence to support their own argument;
2. Exploit errors in the opposing argument-by focusing on a mistake made by
someone who supports an opposing view, they can suggest that all or most of
the evidence is wrong;
3. Take quotes out of context, so that the meaning is altered;
4. Recast honest debates among scholars to make them seem as though the hon­
est scholars disagree about fundamental issues, when in fact they may dis­
agree only about tertiary issues; and
5. Focus on what is not known rather than what is known.

Historical arguments are correctly evaluated with the same methods that are
used in anthropology, botany, geology, and every other field. Converging evidence
(remember converging arguments from the earlier section?) shows that demo-
EVALUATING THE STRENGTH OF AN ARGUMENT 1 95

graphic data, historical records, eye-witness accounts, physical evidence, etc., all
support the conclusion that the Holocaust deniers twist and distort evidence and ar­
gument to advance a racist agenda. A basic understanding of arguments-reasons,
evidence, conclusions, counterarguments, etc.�an protect you from falling prey to
fringe groups who are trying to advance a political agenda (often a racist agenda)
that is not supported by data.

EVALUATING THE STRENGTH OF AN ARGUMENT

Advertising persuades people to buy things they don't need with money
they ain't got.
-Will Rogers (1879-1935)

All arguments are not equally good or equally bad. Think about how your belief
about an issue can be swayed or reinforced as each speaker in a debate presents the
reasons and conclusions supporting or refuting a position. Some reasons for a par­
ticular conclusion are better than others, and sometimes, good reasons don't seem to
be related to the conclusion. In this section, we consider how to evaluate the
strength of an argument.
Arguments are evaluated by how well they meet three criteria. The first criterion
concerns the acceptability and consistency of the premises. The second criterion con­
cerns the relationship between the premises and the conclusion. Do the premises
support the conclusion? Does the conclusion follow from them? The third criterion
concerns the unseen part of the argument. What's missing that would change your
conclusion? Let's consider each of these criteria in turn.

Acceptable and Consistent premises

No man can think clearly when his fists are clenched.


-George Jean Nathan (quoted in Byrne, 1988, p. 390)

The premises are the "why" part of an argument. The premises must be acceptable.
A premise is acceptable when it is true or when we can reasonably believe that it is
true. Let's consider what this means. If I say that the sun is hot, this is an acceptable
premise. I have never touched the sun, but many experts in the field have said that
the sun is hot. Much of what we believe to be true comes from experts' statements
and personal and common or shared knowledge. Similarly, I have no direct, first­
hand knowledge of bacteria, but it is reasonable to believe that they exist. Accept­
able premises are commonly acknowledged "truths" of science. I believe that
California is larger than New Jersey although I have never measured them. You
could probably give a long list of "facts" that are commonly believed to be true.
These are examples of acceptable premises.
Premises that are false are unacceptable. Examples of false premises include: men
can give birth to babies, whales can fly, all mammals are dogs, and Spanish is the
primary language of Canada. I don't want to get into the philosophical considera­
tions of how we can ever know "truth." Personal or common knowledge and expert
testimony will be the guide for determining acceptability.
1 96 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

Unfortunately, acceptability is not an either/or proposition in which a premise is


either acceptable or it is not. Sometimes, part of the job of analyzing an argument in­
volves determining how acceptable a premise is. This may require research on your
part. Suppose that you are listening to an argument about the safety of building a
chemical warfare laboratory in your backyard. The corporation that wants to build
the laboratory argues that the chemical warfare laboratory is safe; therefore, you
have nothing to worry about. One way to decide about the acceptability of this
premise is to spend some time in the library reading about the kinds of experiments
conducted in such laboratories, the kinds of safety precautions that are used, and
past accidents at other similar laboratories. You will also need to consider the state­
ments of experts in this area.
In a good argument, the premises are also consistent. When several premises are
presented to support a conclusion, they must not contradict each other. For exam­
ple, an argument in which one premise states that we have to reduce unemploy­
ment in order to improve the economy and another premise states that we have to
increase unemployment in order to improve the economy is an argument that
contains inconsistent premises. Sometimes, when premises are inconsistent, it is
possible to eliminate one of them because it is weak or faulty. If you can eliminate
the inconsistency among the premises, you will be able to judge more clearly the
strength of the argument.
When considering the premises of an argument, check for acceptability and con­
sistency. When you assess the acceptability and consistency of premises, you will
often have to determine the credibility of the experts who are asserting the premises.

Credibility

What makes an expert credible? In deciding who and what to believe you need to
consider the source of the information. Ask yourself the following questions about
an expert who is presenting the reasons for a belief:

1 . Is the "expert" a recognized authority in the same field in which she is provid­
ing testimony? Why should you believe an expert in computer graphics when
the topic concerns chemical warfare?
2. Is the expert an independent party in this issue? If the expert who says the labo­
ratory is safe was hired by the corporation that owns the laboratory, then her
testimony is suspect. The testimony is not necessarily dishonest or wrong, but
you should be wary because a motive for personal gain may be involved.
3. What are the expert's credentials? Did she write several journal articles on the
subject, which were then published in respected journals, or is her expertise
documented with a single night school course in the topic? Is the expert cur­
rent in the field? Even a renowned expert on chemical warfare from world
War II will have little knowledge of advances in the field over the last 40 years.
4. Does the expert have specific and first-hand knowledge of the issue? She could
conclude that chemical warfare laboratories are generally safe, but have no di­
rect knowledge of the one being proposed. Did she check the plans for safety
features? Does she know exactly what sorts of experiments are being planned?
5. What methods of analysis were used by the expert? Are there standard
safety assessments for laboratories that contain dangerous chemicals? Were
these used?
EVALUATING THE STRENGTH OF AN ARGUMENT 1 97

It is interesting to note that a similar list of variables was found in a study of what
makes jurors believe experts. Legal researchers found that the most important factors
in the way jurors assessed credibility were the expert's qualifications, reasoning, fa­
miliarity with the particular case and impartiality (Shuman & Champagne, 1 998).
Reread the advertisement presented at the beginning of this chapter that states
that we can "eat all day and still lose weight." Who are the doctors and universities
that support this claim? (No names are given. You should immediately begin to
question the credibility of this information.) Was their expertise in weight loss?
What are their credentials? Are they independent or will they make money if you
buy this product? What were the methods of analysis that were used to document
the statement that it will make you feel stronger and full of pep? (None were men­
tioned.) Are the claims made in this advertisement credible?
Decisions about the acceptability of premises will often depend on how you eval­
uate the source of the information. When you have two experts who disagree, which
is frequently the case, you need to understand the nature of the disagreement and
their relative expertise. Are they disagreeing on research findings or the interpreta­
tion of those findings? Try to zero in on the specific points on which they disagree,
so that you can scrutinize these points.
Carlson (1995) distinguished between experts with regard to matters of reality
and matters of value. When the topic concerns "reality" (e.g., Do people who live
near chemical warfare plants suffer from more illnesses than people who do not live
near them?), then the expert can provide evidence, such as the results of studies,
that support her conclusion. When the topic concerns values, the identification and
role of the expert is more difficult. For example, should euthanasia be allowed? This
sort of question involves issues such as whether anyone has the right to terminate
his own life, and experimental data will not be useful in formulating a conclusion in
this situation. A chemist might be a credible expert for questions concerning chemi­
cal warfare, but who is a credible expert for questions of euthanasia? Are the opin­
ions of medical personnel, clergy, or ordinary citizens equally good in making these
decisions? There are few guidelines for selecting credible experts in matters of
value. Fischhoff (1993) is an expert on expertise. As he wisely notes, by definition,
experts know more about some topic than most of us. However, expert knowledge
is always incomplete and people can legitimately disagree about a wide range of
topics such as which risks are worth taking.

The Credibility Crisis

The rapid, phenomenal expansion of information on the Internet has created a credi­
bility crisis. Almost anyone can provide information on almost any topic on the In­
ternet, and it is easily accessible with a few clicks of a mouse. Users must know how
to decide if the source of the information is credible. Some sites have "seals of ap­
proval" from credible groups like the American Association for the Advancement of
Science, but others are so junky that reading from them might be closer to a crime
than a legitimate educational experience. Sometimes, the site looks great-spiffy
graphics and scientific-sounding names-but after a few screens are read, advertise­
ments pop up to sell you something or an obviously biased message is shown.
When evaluating information from a Web site, look for:

1 . The authority-Who is sponsoring the site?, What are the authors' qualifications?
2. Accuracy-Where did the information come from? Are the data clearly labeled?
1 98 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

3. Objectivity-Is the site a public service or is it just a fancy "sales-pitch"?


4. Currency-When was the site last revised? Is the information still relevant?
5. Coverage-Is the information complete? (Tate & Alexander, 1996)

The crisis in credibility is not just an Internet issue. Consider the huge influence
of other media, especially television and movies. Have you seen the Oliver Stone
(1991) film IFK (Bassham & Nardone, 1997)? In the movie version, John F. Kennedy
was not killed by a lone gunman, which was the conclusion reached by the Warren
Commission that had been established to study this question. In the movie version
of this tragic event, he was murdered by right-wing radicals at the Central Intelli­
gence Agency and the Pentagon. According to an analysis of the information in this
popular film, Newsweek labeled the film IFK "propaganda" that omitted important
information about Lee Harvey Oswald, such as the fact that he was in a court­
ordered home for disturbed boys, had made a suicide attempt when in the Soviet
Union, and had attempted to assassinate a general (Bassham & Nardone, 1997). The
movie was not a credible source of information, although many people believed that
it was and formed their own opinion of who killed Kennedy based on the informa­
tion in this film.

Premises That Support the Conclusion

Consider the following argument:

It is important that we elect a prime minister from the New Democratic Party (a political
party in Canada) because the rain in Spain falls mainly on the plain.

I hope that your response to this was "huh?" The premise or reason why we
should support a candidate from the New Democratic Party had nothing to do with
it. The rain in Spain is unrelated to political elections in Canada. In technical terms,
the premise does not support the conclusion.
In determining the relevance or relatedness between the premises and the conclu­
sion(s), I like to use an analogy to a table. The conclusion is the top of the table and
the premises are the legs. When the premises are unrelated to the conclusion, they
are off somewhere in another room and cannot support the table. It is easy to detect
instances in which the premises are totally unrelated to the conclusion. Other exam­
ples are more difficult as relatedness is a matter of degree. Premises can be more or
less related to the conclusion.
Premises can deal with the same topic as the conclusion, yet not support the con­
clusion. For example, suppose I were to argue that you should get plenty of exercise
because athletes get plenty of exercise. Both the conclusion and the premise concern
exercise, but the premise is not a reason for the conclusion. Even if it is true that ath­
letes get plenty of exercise, it may not follow that you should therefore get plenty of
exercise. Maybe you have a "weak" heart and would die from exercise. The conclu­
sion does not follow from the premise. One way of checking for the relatedness of
the premise(s) to the conclusion(s) is to ask yourself if the conclusion must be true or
extremely likely if the premise is acceptable. If the answer is "no," then you have to
question how well the conclusion is being supported by the premise.
Determining the relatedness between the premises and the conclusion can be
tricky. This is exactly the sort of determination that judges are required to make all
EYALUATlNG THE STRENGTH OF AN ARGUMENT 1 99

of the time. Consider a rape case in which the defense wants to show that the
woman agreed to sexual intercourse. Is her previous sexual behavior related to this
issue? Most of the time, the courts have ruled that a woman's past sexual history is
unrelated to whether she was coerced at the time in question, but under special cir­
cumstances, such evidence may be admissible because the judge decides that it may
be related to a particular case.
The premises not only have to be related to the conclusion, they also have to be
strong enough to support the conclusion. Some authors call this condition adequate
grounds. When premises provide good support for the conclusion, we say that there
are adequate grounds for believing that the conclusion is true or likely to be true.
Let's return to the table analogy. Think of the conclusion as a solid wooden table­
top. A solid wooden tabletop will topple over if we try to support it with a few
toothpicks. The only way to support it is to use one or more strong legs or many
weaker legs that, when used together, will form a strong base of support. These pos­
sibilities are depicted in Fig. 5.1.
Let's consider some examples of strength of support.

1. [Marion and Engelbert have filed for divorce. P Therefore, [they plan to get a divorce.F

As before, I have bracketed and numbered the statements. In skeleton form, this
is [1] therefore [2].

Premises Unrelated to Conclusion Single Strong Premise


Supports Conclusion

I.

Many Weak Premises Few Weak Premises


Support Conclusion Fail to Support Conclusion

FIG. 5. 1 . Table analogy for understanding the strength of an argument. The tabletop is the
conclusion and the legs are the premises. Strong arguments have a firm base of support.
200 5. ANALYZlNG ARGUMENTS

I hope that you can see that statement [ 1 ] is a reason for statement [2], the conclu­
sion. Because we have one reason and one conclusion, this is an argument.
The unstated assumption that they are married will be omitted from the diagram
because it is not relevant to the point being made, but if it were included, it would
point to [1].

}
Graphically, this becomes:

j
[2]
Strong
[1 ]

I have rated the strength of support for the conclusion as strong because I believe
that filing for divorce is very strong evidence that they plan to get divorced (al­
though there are other possibilities, which is why it is not absolutely certain).

2. [Marion and Engelbert had eggs for breakfast.P Therefore, [they plan to get a divorce.F

In skeleton form, this is still [1] therefore [2] .


Because the premise is unrelated to the conclusion, it provides no support for the

}
conclusion.

j [2]
No Support
[1 ]

In this example, the reason provides no support for the conclusion. We have no
reason to believe that they plan to get a divorce.

3. [Marion and Engelbert had a fight this morning.P Therefore, [they plan to get a divorce.F

The skeleton structure is still [1] therefore [2] .

}
In this example, the premise is related to the conclusion, but the support is weak.

j
[2]
Weak Support
[1 ]

4. [Marion and Engelbert had a fight this morning.P In fact, [they fight everyday.F
[Engelbert is moving out of their apartment and plans to move in with his mother.13 [Marion
made an appointment with a divorce attorney.]4 Therefore, [they plan to get a divorce.p

This example contains five statements. Statement [5] is the conclusion. The other
four statements are premises for the conclusion. Let's consider each premise and de­
cide how well it supports the conclusion.

[5]: Marion and Engelbert plan to get a divorce. This is the conclusion.
[1]: Marion and Engelbert had a fight this morning. (weak)
[2]: They fight everyday. (weak)
[3]: Engelbert is moving out to live with his mother. (moderate)
[4]: Marion made an appointment with a divorce attorney. (strong)
EVALUATING THE STRENGTH OF AN ARGUMENT 20 1

In this example, there are multiple premises to support the conclusion. Taken to­
gether, they provide strong support.

/J [5]
} Strong Support

weak weak
N
moderate strong
[1 ] [2] [3] [4]

Look at the list of premises. With only the first one, the support for the conclusion
was very weak. The addition of the second made the support somewhat stronger
because there were now two separate weak premises, which are stronger together
than one weak premise. As additional premises were added, support for the conclu­
sion increased. This is another example of a convergent argument structure in which
multiple premises point to (converge on) the same conclusion. Additional premises,
even weak ones, increase the strength of the argument.
When analyzing the relationship between premises and a conclusion, you need to
consider their relevance to the conclusion and the strength of the support that they
supply. Using the table analogy, ask yourself if the tabletop has a sound base of sup­
port or if it is shaky and easy to topple over.
You may have been looking for rules or guidelines to determine the strength of
support. There really are no firm rules, only guidelines. How you judge the strength
of an argument depends on many personal factors, including what you already
know about the topic, your personal values, and how you make judgments. Some
psychologists and others have advocated for teaching children and adults about val­
ues (e.g., Sternberg, in press), which would include teaching them to view complex
issues from multiple perspectives-a technique that is frequently used in critical
thinking instruction, although we do not usually think of this as "teaching values."
Thinking, at its heart, is still a very personal activity. Although there are many skills
that you can learn that will improve how you think, we are in no danger of turning
all thinking into a rigid set of steps that will make us all think the same.
Here is a good example where thoughtful people disagree. How important is a
candidate's personal life in determining whether the candidate should be elected? Is
it an indication that the candidate will not be honest if you know that he cheats on
his spouse? Some people believe that anyone who cheats in marriage will be dishon­
est in other situations; others believe that the two are unrelated. Public reaction to
the sexual relationship between Monica Lewinsky, a White House intern, and for­
mer U.S. President Bill Clinton showed that there were many different opinions
about the relevance of this relationship to Clinton's job as president. Similarly, in
Russian elections, not long ago, the leading candidate was known to have a problem
with alcohol. How important would this be in your decision of whether to vote for
this candidate? In answering this question, you would also want to know about the
other candidates running for office and the extent of the alcohol problem, but ulti­
mately, many people disagree over issues such as these.

Missing Components

They will try to tell you to prove you are right; I tell you to prove you are
wrong.
-Louis Pasteur (1822-1895)
202 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

Most arguments are written to persuade the reader or listener that a conclusion is
true or probably true. Good examples of this can be found in advertisements and
political rhetoric. When you read or listen to advertisements and political claims, it
is important to keep in mind the restrictions imposed on these arguments. There are
laws that punish false statements by advertisers; similarly, false political statements
are likely to be detected by the press or opposition party. Therefore, blatantly false
statements are not usually a factor in political and advertising argument analysis, al­
though you should remain wary of them. The bigger problem in attempts to per­
suade is missing and distorted claims. In other words, it is the missing parts of most
arguments that are often the most important parts. In order to evaluate the quality
of an argument, you need to consider what's been left out.
When evaluating an argument, consider each component separately and think
about ways the statements could have been distorted and what has been omitted.
Let's try this with an example that is paraphrased from a newspaper editorial writ­
ten by Phyllis Schafly, a prominent spokesperson for several conservative issues.
This editorial appeared in the Washington Times on July 21, 1993 (p. G4).

In this commentary, Schafly argues against universal mental health care coverage. She
provides an anecdote to show that mental health care is too costly and ineffective.
The story is about a mechanic who "allegedly" injured his wrist. Although he had
wrist surgery, he still complained of pain and "claimed" to be unable to work. He then
lost his job, and with it, his insurance. During this period, his wife left him because he
was beating her. Under universal mental health care coverage, he would be eligible to
receive 30 days of psychiatric in-patient treatment and up to 20 sessions of out-patient
therapy. Schafly concludes that this would reward his "misbehavior," and create a new
welfare.

One of the best ways to think about what's missing is to change your point of
view so that you now become an advocate for the "other side." In this case, try to
view the argument from the perspective of someone who does not agree with the
conclusion that is being advocated. What premises are missing or additional infor­
mation is needed that would support an opposite conclusion? First, you should no­
tice the use of certain words that suggest that the mechanic was not really hurt.
Schafly does not know if the pain was genuine, and neither do we, but the use of
terms like "allegedly" and "claims" suggests that they were not. Second, the surgery
would have been performed at the same cost regardless of the mental health care
coverage, so it is not relevant to the conclusion that mental health care coverage is
too costly. Third, suppose that he had received the mental health care that Schafly
opposes and that it helped him to return to work and stop beating his wife. Tremen­
dous amounts of money would be saved because he could go off welfare, and the
family might also have been able to survive as a unit. Of course, you can supply
other possibilities. When you consider the issues from the perspective of what is not
given as information, you often will arrive at a different conclusion.
Although the consideration of missing components could theoretically go on for­
ever, the extent to which we scrutinize an argument depends on its importance.
I would spend a great deal of time and effort analyzing an argument in which the
conclusion concerns the safety of building a chemical warfare laboratory near my
home (or someone else's home). There are many arguments in life that should be
carefully evaluated, and this includes seeking and considering missing and mislead­
ing statements.
EVALUAT1NG THE STRENGTH OF AN ARGUMENT 203

Sound Arguments

A good argument is technically called a sound argument. An argument is sound


when it meets the following criteria:

1 . The premises are acceptable and consistent. (You may have to eliminate some
premises so that the others are consistent.)
2. The premises are relevant to the conclusion and provide sufficient support for
the conclusion.
3. Missing components have been considered and are judged to be consistent
with the conclusion.

Satisfying each of these criteria is a matter of degree. Premises are usually accept­
able on some continuum from unacceptable to totally acceptable. The nature of sup­
port that they provide for the conclusion also lies on some continuum from no
support to complete support. Similarly, the missing components, especially counter­
arguments, may weaken the argument anywhere from completely to not at all.
Because all of these assessments have to be combined to decide if an argument is
sound, we usually think of soundness as ranging from unsound to completely sound.
An argument is unsound if its premises are false, or if they are unrelated to the
conclusion, or if a critical counterargument is missing. An argument is completely
sound if the premises are acceptable and related to the conclusion in a way that
guarantees the acceptability of the conclusion. Most real-life arguments fall some­
where between these two extremes. For this reason, conclusions are often preceded
with probability terms like "it is likely that" or "we can probably conclude that."
Here are some examples of different degrees of soundness:

Completely Sound Argument (premises are acceptable and related to the conclusion
in a way that guarantees the conclusion)
All mothers are women who have (or had) children. Suzi is a woman who has a
son. Therefore, Suzi is a mother.
Unsound Arguments (either the premises are unacceptable or they are unrelated to
the conclusion)
All fathers have given birth to a child. Norbert has a son. Therefore Norbert has
given birth to a child. (Premise is unacceptable.)
Norbert has a son; therefore, Norbert also has a daughter. (Premise is unrelated
to the conclusion.)

Don't confuse the truth or acceptability of a conclusion with the soundness of an


argument. A conclusion can be objectively true, even when the argument is un­
sound. The conclusion could be true for reasons that have nothing to do with the
information stated in the argument. Here is an example of a conclusion that is objec­
tively true embedded in an unsound argument.

The structure of the family has been changing rapidly, with more single parents now
heading their own households. Consequently, the divorce rate has begun to level off and de­
cline slightly.

The conclusion about the divorce rate is true (according to demographers), but
the argument is unsound because the premise does not support the conclusion.
204 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

Complex issues rarely have one correct conclusion. More often, many conclusions
are possible, and the task of analyzing an argument involves deciding which of two
or more conclusions has the greater strength or support.

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

1 . The first step is to read or listen to the passage to determine if it contains an ar­
gument. Are there at least one premise and at least one conclusion? If not, no
further analysis is needed.
2. Identify all the stated and unstated component parts: premises, conclusions,
assumptions, qualifiers, and counterarguments.
3. Check the premises for acceptability and consistency. If all of the premises are
unacceptable, stop here because the argument is unsound. If only some of the
premises are unacceptable, eliminate them, and continue with the acceptable
premises. If the premises are inconsistent with each other, decide if you can jus­
tifiably eliminate one or more. An argument cannot be sound if the premises
are inconsistent or contradict each other, but you may be able to eliminate the
contradiction.
4. Diagram the argument. Consider the strength of the support that each premise
provides for the conclusion. Rate the strength of support as nonexistent, weak,
medium, or strong. Look over the number of supporting premises. A large num­
ber of supporting premises can provide strong support for the conclusion in a
convergent structure, even when separately each only provides weak support.
Recall that in a linked structure a single weak link can destroy an argument.
5. Consider the strength of counterarguments, assumptions, and qualifiers
(stated or omitted) and omitted premises. Do they undermine the support pro­
vided by the premises or strengthen or weaken it?
6. Finally, come to a global determination of the soundness of the argument. Is it
unsound, completely sound, or somewhere in between? If it is somewhere in
between, is it weak, medium, or strong?

You may be thinking that analyzing arguments is a lot of work. You are ab­
solutely right. Diagramming and evaluating complex arguments can be as demand­
ing as a long proof in mathematics or comprehending a complex novel. I realize that
few people will formally diagram an argument in real life; however, it is a powerful
and useful tool for comprehending complex arguments. Practice with diagramming
arguments will aid in the analysis of other arguments even when, for time or other
reasons, actual diagramming is not feasible. It will help you distinguish among the
components of an argument and make judgments about its strength. When the issue
is important and complex, making a diagram of its structure can be well worth the
time and effort required.

A Rubric for Scoring Arguments-Even Your Own

Of course, we also present arguments to other people, and don't just analyze those that
are made by other people. In a book that was written for college professors, Norris
and Ennis (1989) suggested criteria that can be used to evaluate an argumentative
A TEMPLATE FOR WRITING SOUND ARGUMENTS 205

essay. When you write your own essays or plan oral presentations, consider these
criteria:

1 . Do you clearly state the conclusion and define necessary terms?


2. Is the material that you included relevant to the conclusion?
3. Is the argument sound? Do the premises provide solid support for the
conclusion?
4. Have you considered the credibility of your experts?
5. Is the paper well organized with different issues addressed separately?
6. Have you fairly presented alternative points of view and counterarguments?
7. Have you used good grammar and a clear style of writing?

A TEMPLATE FOR WRITING SOUND ARGUMENTS

The importance of being able to write a sound argument is recognized as a critical


thinking task that is essential for success in college and in professional careers. Sev­
eral different standardized examinations are requiring test-takers to write an argu­
ment as a means of assessing critical thinking and writing skills. At the present time,
written arguments are required for everyone who takes the Graduate Record Exam­
ination, the selection test used for entry to most graduate schools in the United
States, and the examination used for selection for entry into business schools. Here
is a template for writing sound arguments.
The template is designed to help you organize your thinking on complex issues
and be able to explain evidence on two or more sides of an issue, such as the evi­
dence for and against evolutionary hypotheses of mate selection or for and against
the idea that parents are important influences on their children. In completing this
template, you will have to gather and assess evidence to determine the best conclu­
sion or conclusions and not start with what you believe is true. You will need to
consider both supporting and disconfirming evidence-an exercise that can help
you avoid the confirmation bias. Here is an applied example:

�G ARGUMENTS TEMPLATE

Example 1 : Does violence on television have a negative influence on children's behavior?


1 . State your conclusion. (Although you may begin your formal writing here, be sure
that the conclusion follows from your reasons.) As you work, this is the last part that
is filled in, not the first.

2. Give three reasons (or some other number) that support your conclusion.
a.
b.
c.
3. Rate each reason as weak, moderate, strong, or very strong.
Rating for a:
Rating for b:
Rating for c:
206 5. A..."lALYZING ARGUMENTS

4. Give three counterarguments (or some other number) that weaken your conclusion.
Rate how much each counterargument weakens the conclusion: little, moderate,
much, or very much.
a.
Rating for a:
b.
Rating for b:
c.
Rating for c:
5. List any qualifiers (limitations on the reasons for or against-for example, some evi-
dence may be restricted to early childhood).
6. List any assumptions.
7. Are your reasons and counterarguments directly related to your conclusion?
8. What is the overall strength of your argument: weak, moderate, strong, or very
strong?

Now that you have completed this worksheet, rate the overall strength of your argument.

Once the template is completed, the writing will be the easy part because you al­
ready know what you want to say and have listed your reasons and considered the
strength of your argument. (If you are planning on taking any of the standardized
admissions examinations that now require that you write an argument, this exercise
should greatly improve your score.)

Reasoning and Rationalizing

People are irrational, short-sighted, destructive, ethnocentric, emotional,


and easily misled by demagogues.
-Philip E. Tetlock (1994, p. 3)

When you evaluate arguments, you are also evaluating your own knowledge about
the subject matter. There may be other counterarguments that are quite strong, but
that are unknown to you. Similarly, your ratings of the strength of the components
may be biased in ways that support a conclusion that you favor. Nickerson (1 986)
makes an important distinction between reasoning and rationalizing. When we
rationalize, we attend to information that favors a preferred conclusion. We may se­
lectively gather information that supports a preferred conclusion or rate counterar­
guments as weak because they detract from a preferred conclusion. Rationalizing
also influences the nature of the missing components that we supply to an existing
argument. When we add to an argument, the information that we supply is infor­
mation that is readily recalled. If you've already read Chapter 2 on memory, then
you are well aware of the many ways that memory can be biased. Rationalizing is
usually not a deliberate process to distort the analysis of arguments, which makes it
difficult to recognize and guard against. It is easier to recognize rationalizing when
someone else is doing it. Perhaps the best we can do is realize that rationalization
does occur and to try to be especially vigilant for rationalizing when you prefer a
conclusion. When you analyze an argument, you must identify the main point that
PERSUASION AND PROPAGANDA 207

the author or speaker wants you to believe. You also have to consider both premises
and counterarguments.
We tend to weigh evidence that favors a belief more heavily than evidence that dis­
confirms it. This bias was clearly demonstrated in a classic study in which college stu­
dents served as subjects (Lord, Ross, & Lepper, 1 979). Students were asked to write an
essay in which they argued for or against a controversial issue such as abortion or
capital punishment. The students were then given the results of experimental studies
that supported a "middle of the road" point of view-that is, it was neither for nor
against the controversial issue. After reading the balanced review, students who fa­
vored the "pro" position of the controversial issue believed that the objectively neu­
tral paper supported the "pro" position. Similarly, students who favored the "con"
position and then read the same objectively balanced paper believed that it favored
the "con" position. Instead of bringing the two sides closer together, as might have
been expected, the balanced paper drove them farther apart. Each position focused on
the information that supported their own point of view and judged the evidence that
ran counter to their favored position to be weak. This same finding has been found
with all sorts of subject pools, including NASA scientists who favored evidence and
arguments that supported their preferred hypothesis over ones that did not.
Just telling people that we tend to judge information that we favor as stronger
than information that we oppose doesn't work to correct this bias. Is it any wonder
why it is so difficult to get people to assess controversial issues in a fair-minded man­
ner? Because we are not aware that we judge reasons in a way that supports what we
believe to be true, it is very difficult to change the way we evaluate information. One
successful attempt was accomplished by Koriat, Lichtenstein, and Fischhoff (1980).
They required students to list reasons that support a conclusion and reasons that run
counter to a conclusion (counterarguments), and to rate the strength of each. This
should be familiar because they are the steps used in analyzing arguments. They
found that students became more accurate in their assessments after this training in
"giving reasons." These results have been replicated in more recent studies in which
the bias for information that confirms a prior belief was reduced by requiring people
to provide reasons that did not support the preferred conclusion (Lenski, 2001;
Flannelly & Flannelly, 2000). The authors of one of the studies summarized their re­
search: "critical thinking skills of students should be fostered so the students come to
appreciate the importance of weighting both positive and negative evidence"
(Flannelly & Flannelly, 2000). These sorts of experimental results show that the giving
and assessing of reasons can have beneficial results that improve the thinking process.

PERSUASION AND PROPAGANDA

By the skillful and sustained use of propaganda, one can make people see even
heaven as hell, or an extremely wretched life as paradise.
-Adolf Hitler (1889-1945; cited in Falls, 1 943)

Whenever you are confronted with an argument, keep in mind that the material you
are reading or hearing has been written to persuade you to do something or to be­
lieve something. Much of the communication that you receive is concerned with
getting you to act or think in a certain way. Pratkanis and Aronson (1992) define
propaganda as "mass suggestion or influence through the manipulation of symbols
208 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

and the psychology of the individual" (p. 9). This broad definition is applicable to a
great variety of situations. Propaganda, like beauty, is often in the eye of the be­
holder. It does not require that the information be false or misleading, but it does at
least imply less concern for truth or rigorous argument than the sort of arguments
found in scholarly journals or presented by independent parties. Frequently, the in­
formation provided is charged with appeals to emotion rather than reason.
Humans are very clever in using techniques that aim to influence others' thinking.
The cleverest way to influence how someone thinks is with a well-crafted argument. If
you were thinking that the work of analyzing an argument is not worth it, you have not
considered the agonies of history in which people failed to analyze political arguments.
Consider the evil genius of men like Joseph Goebbel, Hitler's minister of propaganda.
Have you ever wondered how millions of people could be persuaded to kill millions of
other people whose sole crime was believing in another religion? Of course, such evil
was rooted in a long history of scapegoating, which is the practice of blaming a minor­
ity group for all of the ills in society. In order to kill so many people efficiently, it was
necessary to set up "death factories" that operated with the efficiency of an assembly
line, much like the factories that produce refrigerators or automobiles. First, Goebbel
told lies, false reasons to support the conclusion that genocide was justified. He spread
rumors about "secret books" that told about an alleged tradition of drinking the blood
of innocent Christian children. Of course, there were no books, and this disgusting
practice never occurred, but many people were willing to believe that it was true.
Arguments were most frequently used to persuade Nazis and others that mil­
lions of people should be slaughtered, but there were other propaganda techniques
that Goebbel used, including visual images and threats of violence for anyone who
didn't agree. Although other techniques are considered in more detail later in this
chapter and in other chapters, I note here the particularly blatant ploy of showing
pictures of Jews that were alternated with pictures of rats and roaches, so that view­
ers would come to associate certain facial features that are common in many Jews
with disgusting rodents and bugs. (If you have studied psychology, you will recog­
nize this technique as an application of classical conditioning.) These same sorts of
techniques have been used to promote other types of equally horrific genocide. The
propaganda used to justify slavery and lynchings in the United States, the slaughter
of Cambodians in Asia, and the purges by Mao Tse-tung in China and Stalin in the
former Soviet Union, show that propaganda has been used all over the world to en­
courage prejudice and killing. Why did education fail all these people in so many
places around the world? For example, how did millions of Chinese, in this century,
believe that Mao was their "loving father," when he was responsible for the death of
millions of Chinese? Why didn't they stop to consider if the reasons they were given
to support this Chinese holocaust (Le., the cultural revolution) were not acceptable?
Do you understand Hitler's now-infamous quote, "What luck for rulers that men do
not think" (quoted in Byrne, 1988, p. 359)?

The Psychology of Reasons

As you now realize, an argument requires the use of reasons, and we like to have
reasons for our beliefs, even when the reasons are not very good and the argument
itself is weak. Three psychologists conducted a study in which they examined how
people respond to the appearance of reasons (Langer, Blank, & Chanowitz, 1978). In
this study, they had a confederate (someone working with the experimenters whose
BXPLAINING AS KNOWING 209

identity is not known to the true subjects) try various combinations of requests and
reasons for barging ahead of people waiting in line to use a copier machine. There
were three different conditions: (a) Request alone ("Excuse me, I have five pages.
May I use the Xerox machine?"), (b) Request plus reason ("Excuse me, I have five
pages. May I use the Xerox because I'm in a rush?"), and (c) Request plus the ap­
pearance of a reason ("Excuse me, I have five pages. May I use the Xerox machine
because I have to make some copies?").
The results of this study are very interesting. In the request alone condition 60%
of the people waiting said that it was okay for the confederate to make the copies. In
the request plus reason condition, this figure jumped to 94%. What about the re­
quest plus appearance of a reason? In this condition, 93% of the people waiting to
use the machine let the confederate go ahead. The use of the word because suggested
that there was a reason. Remember the section on premise indicators? Because was
listed as a word that is frequently followed by a reason. The statement "because I
have to make some copies" is not a reason to let someone ahead of you in line at the
copier machine. Everyone standing in line has to make some copies. It seems that
we like to believe that our actions and beliefs are reasonable, that is, based on rea­
sons. Unfortunately, even nonreasons, poor reasons, and reasons that are unrelated
to the action or belief will often suffice. People who want to change how we think
and act often rely on this human tendency and will deliberately use unsound rea­
soning to convince us that a conclusion is true.
You probably think that irrelevant reasons for a conclusion would have no effect on
how people evaluate a conclusion. It seems that this should be true because irrelevant
reasons are, well, irrelevant. But, psychologically, irrelevant reasons often influence
what we believe and how we act even though, lOgically, they should not. A study of
consumer decisions showed that irrelevant reasons in support of a product tend to
weaken support for the product, and irrelevant reasons that run counter to a product
tend to strengthen support for the product (Simonson, Nowlis, & Simonson, 1993). For
example, suppose that you are a runner who is looking for good running shoes. As a
salesperson, I tell you that Adibok brand is well known for their aerobic shoes, but
they also make good running shoes. The fact that they are well known for their aerobic
shoes should be irrelevant to the selection of running shoes, but it seems to work
against this hypothetical brand. Consumers assume that if Adibok is good at making
aerobic shoes, then it is less good at making running shoes. Thus, an irrelevant reason
in support of this brand is psychologically converted into a reason against this brand.
Similarly, suppose that you have no interest in saunas. If I told you that the Posh
Inn Hotel Chain does not have a sauna, a seemingly irrelevant reason against the
Posh Inn Hotels, you would likely take this as a reason for selecting Posh Inn. Psycho­
logically, this irrelevant reason against Posh Inn Hotels is converted into thinking that
it may have something else positive that balances this irrelevant negative. In this way.
a reason that should be irrelevant to your decision about Posh Inn Hotel becomes a
reason for staying at Posh Inn. The point of this discussion is that people often do not
behave in ways that are logical; irrelevant reasons influence how we think.

EXPLAINING AS KNOWING

"How do you know what you know?" (Kuhn, 2001). It seems that most people make
judgments about their own knowledge by thinking about how well they can explain
210 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

a phenomenon. For example, in studies of how jurors decide on the guilt or inno­
cence of a defendant, researchers found that jurors weave a story about what might
have happened at the scene of a crime and then decide how good that story is. This
mode of knowing is often labeled "explaining." Another way of knowing is to exam­
ine the strength of the evidence that supports or refutes a particular conclusion-this
is known as argument analysis. Most people use "explanations" as the primary way
of justifying claims (Brem & Rips, in press; Cheng, 1997). Consider this example:

Which is the stronger argument?


A. Why do teenagers start smoking? Smith says it's because they see ads that make smok­
ing look attractive. A good-looking guy in neat clothes with a cigarette in his mouth is some­
one you would like to be like.
B. Why do teenagers start smoking? Jones says it's because they see ads that make smok­
ing look attractive. When cigarette ads were banned from TV, smoking went down. (Kuhn,
2001, p. 4)

Answer A provides an explanation that links smoking and teens in a way that
most people think "makes sense." Answer B provides data, albeit limited, that links
smoking and advertisements. The alternative that provides evidence for the rela­
tionship is stronger than the one that merely explains, even though many people
prefer the explanation. There are many plausible explanations that could be gener­
ated, and without evidence (i.e., data) there is no good way to choose among them.
Far too many people are very confident in their knowledge of something and very
wrong (Kuhn, 2001 ) . Think about your own understanding. How do you know
about the nature of the world? This is not meant to be an idle navel-gazing question.
If you can develop the disposition to look for evidence instead of relying on an ex­
planation that "just seems right," you will make large gains in critical thinking.
It is important to understand that people are quite confident in their knowledge
because it makes sense to them, but "making sense" is a poor measure of the quality
of your knowing. Sometimes, it is difficult to understand why data should be prefer­
able to explanation. Consider this example: During World War II, many Germans
refused to believe that the German army burned an entire village in Poland as they
were retreating from the Soviet front. They refused to believe it because the mas­
sacre did not make sense. Why should the German troops slaughter innocent people
in Poland? In fact, historical records (eye-witness accounts, physical evidence, writ­
ten accounts, etc.) clearly show that this is what happened-the village was
destroyed by frustrated German troops who were seeking revenge for their humili­
ating loss. The evidence is more compelling than the "make sense" explanation. It is
important that we learn to value evidence when formulating conclusions. The use of
data is a critical part of critical thinking.
The preference for explanations over evidence is just one of many ways that
thinking can "go wrong." In the next section, we consider other common ways that
thinking can go astray. Unsound reasoning techniques used for the purpose of per­
suasion are called fallacies. As you go through the list of fallacies presented in the
next section, you can classify each as violating one or more of the criteria for sound ar­
guments-the premises are unacceptable, or the premises are unrelated to the conclu­
sion or inconsistent, or the expert is not credible, or important information is missing.
It is impossible to list every fallacy that has been employed to change how people
think. The list would be too long to be useful, with only subtle differences among
several of the techniques. Accordingly, only the most common and representative
EXPLAINING AS KNOWING 21 1

techniques are discussed. If you understand how fallacies work in general, you'll be
better prepared to recognize and defend against them. Toulmin, Rieke, and Janik
(1979) call the ability to recognize fallacies "a kind of sensitivity training" because
they train the reader to be sensitive to common tricks of persuasion.

Twenty-One Common Fallacies

1 . Association Effects

One of the oldest principles in psychology is the notion that, if two events occur
close together in time and/or space, the mind will form an association between
them. Thereafter, when one occurs, the other is expected to occur. This principle has
become widely used in the political arena, especially to create guilt by association.
Suppose you read in the newspaper that a violent mass murderer endorsed a presi­
dential candidate. This endorsement would be detrimental to the candidate, even if
she did not desire it and did nothing to promote it.
A classic example of the propagandistic use of association came from a political
group called "California Tax Reduction Movement." Their 1983 literature stated:
"This court, dominated by Jerry Brown appointees, and having radical views close
to those of Jane Fonda and Tom Hayden, has twisted the words until we don't even
recognize them!" You might be wondering what Jane Fonda and Tom Hayden are
doing in a sentence about the California Supreme Court. In the jargon of analyzing
arguments, the premise is unrelated to the conclusion. Fonda and Hayden had no
connection with the court. This literature was written with the belief that people
who favor tax reductions will also be opposed to Jane Fonda and Tom Hayden. The
Court is being made guilty by association with them. Although it is implied, it does
not logically follow that the Supreme Court therefore has views similar to Jane
Fonda and Tom Hayden. It may or may not have had such views. (Note also the use
of the emotion-laden word "radical.") Whenever you see examples of associations
with no justifiable connection like this one, be wary of the rest of the message. It is
likely to contain an appeal to your emotions rather than to your cognition.
Just as one can have guilt by association, it is also possible to have virtue by asso­
ciation. In this instance, the names or labels attached to the person are "good" ones.
Perhaps this is why certain political offices tend to run in families. People expected
the Kennedy brothers to be similar as politicians because of their obvious associa­
tion with each other or that the Bush children will be similar to their father, former
president George Bush, Sr. This expectation is being passed onto the children and
other relatives of political figures, many of whom are now involved in or consider­
ing political careers. Would you vote for or against an unknown Kennedy or Bush
simply because he or she is from the same family as a former politician?
A wary recipient of messages that rely on association will ask about the nature of
the association. If a candidate is a leader of the Ku Klux Klan, then associating the
doctrine of the Klan with this individual is reasonable. If, on the other hand, a friend
of the candidate's mother is a member of the Klan, the association is ludicrous.

2 . Arguments Against the Person

Arguments against the person is the formal term for name calling or, in its Latin
form, argumentatum ad hominem. This form of persuasion or propaganda attacks the
212 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

people who support a cause, and not the cause itself. From the standpoint of argu­
ment analysis, the personal attack is irrelevant to the conclusion. For example, the
Nazis believed that the theory of relativity was wrong because its discoverer was a
Jew named Albert Einstein. They never considered the evidence for or against the
theory, just the religion of its originator. It is basically another form of the associa­
tion effect. In this case, the association that is being made is between an idea and a
person. The underlying principle is that if you don't like the person who supports
an idea, then you should also oppose the idea itself because the idea and the person
are associated.
Suppose you were serving on a jury that had to decide which of two witnesses
was telling the truth. Would you be swayed if one attorney told you to disregard one
man's testimony because he had been divorced twice? Presumably not, because the
man's marital status is irrelevant to the issue. Suppose you were told that one of the
men had two previous convictions for lying to a jury. Would this argument against
the person be relevant? I would think so. In this case, the information provided
about the witness is relevant to the question of whether he is lying. Consider the
strength and relevance of the argument and the purpose for which it is used, and
don't be misled by irrelevant attacks on the supporters or detractors of any position.

3. Appeals to Pity

An appeal to pity is easy to spot. "Support this position" or "buy that product"
because it needs your help. A rental car agency has made it well known that they're
number 2 in their business, and therefore will try harder. They hope that consumers
will root for the "underdog" and support the company that is number 2. Does this
conclusion logically follow from the fact that they're number 2? No! You could also
logically conclude that the number 1 company will try harder to retain their lead or
that the number 2 company would have been number 1 if it had tried harder. Ap­
peals to pity are often found in legal pleadings. A defendant's poor background or
turbulent home life will often be brought up during a trial. These appeals to pity
have nothing to do with the question of whether a defendant is guilty or innocent,
although they may be persuasive appeals for leniency in sentencing if the defendant
is found guilty. Sometimes, students use appeals to pity when attempting to per­
suade a teacher to raise a low grade. The grade is assigned on the quality of the
work that is done, but students sometimes argue that if they work hard (or some
other sad reason), the work should be graded higher than comparable work by
someone who did not work as hard.

4. Popularity and Testimonials


The popularity technique (also known as the "bandwagon") relies on the need
for conformity for its persuasive power. It is persuasive because it explains that
everyone supports a position or buys a certain product. It is expected that the recipi­
ents of the message will adopt the belief or buy the product in order to feel as if she
or he belongs to the groups mentioned. Implicitly, the message is "if everyone is
doing it, it must be right." This fallacy was presented earlier in this chapter when we
considered the advertisement for LaBaroness, the car that more people are buying
than any other American car.
A variation of the popularity technique is testimonials. Respected politicians or
movie stars endorse a belief or product. It is believed that people will want to be
EXPLAINING AS KNOWING 213

Calvin and Hobbes by Bill Watterson

IlERr."S '" COOL GIl� S��I� 9:l B�\Clli.'1 , 11\1S tAA�IC.\(


t\CQOO'I "ltUS "1M 'tolll�" -ro 1'5 IJR<;\1-IG EI/'C.R'Io\\� it)
Do. fiE 00\5 'fWo.1t.'lE2. liE �� II\'; \\'I.�I/\OIl��\T'i
W��TS �N\) \\E \3IJ'i'S TI1I'S Tl\ROJ.;II cot\\'"(lR!IIIT'( IN
P'R.oooc.T POS " RttL£<:'ll� BR/>.NO· Wo,\o\'C. stLE<:TI()\'I. "
� TI1P-T IKI>'C.I'ENt£l'.lC.E .

�---,-, G
CALVIN AND HOBBES © Watterson. Reprinted with permission of UNIVERSAL PRESS
SYNDICATE. All rights reserved.

similar to the people they respect, so they will choose to use the same deodorant or
foot powder or support the same causes. The recipients of testimonials are expected
to infer a conclusion from the information stated. It is expected that they will reason
along these lines: Christie Brinkley is a gorgeous model with very few wrinkles. She
uses the advertised beauty product. If I use this beauty product, like Christie Brinkley,
I will have very few wrinkles. Of course, this conclusion does not follow from the
first two sentences, but many people believe that it does or at least implies that it
might. This fallacy is worsened when the testimonial is not even in the area in which
the personality has expertise, Christie Brinkley also endorses a national newspaper.
As far as I know, this is an area in which she has no expertise, She is not a credible ex­
pert in the area of journalistic quality, Yet, advertisements like these do sell products.
Sometimes, however, the popularity technique and testimonials can be valid per­
suasive techniques. If, for example, all of the members of an unbiased expert panel es­
tablished to study the effects of a drug decide that it is unsafe, I would consider this
information relevant to the question of the drug's safety because it passes the test of
credibility. Similarly, if a leading educator endorses a reading text, this might prop­
erly have an impact on your evaluation of the text. Both of these examples presume
that the "experts" have no personal motives for their endorsements-that is, they're
not being paid for saying these things and their expertise is relevant to the position or
product that they're supporting. In this case, they are credible sources of information.

5. False Dichotomy
Don't give him two sides to a question to worry him.
Give him one;
better yet, give him none!
-Ray Bradbury (Farenheit 451, 1950)
There are very few political or social decisions that have simple answers or that can
be solved with simple choices. Yet simple slogans are the prototype or most com­
mon and representative form of persuasive techniques. False dichotomy is some­
times called simplification or the black or white fallacy because readers are asked to
decide between two positions, without allowing other alternatives or "gray areas"
that would combine aspects of both choices.
214 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

The following question appeared in a questionnaire that was sent by an assem­


blyman to his constituents (Assemblyman Montjoy Needs Your Views, 1983):

"Would you prefer that government cut spending or increase taxes?"


cut spending increase taxes

Does this question bother you? It should. The answers to our fiscal problems are
not this simple. You should ask where and how the cuts would be made and how
much taxes would be increased. Perhaps "cuts" could be combined with small or
temporary increases in taxes. Can you guess which answer the assemblyman
prefers? Given this choice, I believe that most people would prefer to "cut spend­
ing," yet, for many, an entirely different response would result from a question that
was worded differently. When you are faced with a false dichotomy or the simplifi­
cation of a complex issue, don't ask yourself if the ideas are good or bad. Ask in­
stead what is good about the ideas and what is bad about them. Consider other al­
ternatives and combinations of ideas. Remember that one of the steps in analyzing
arguments calls for supplying missing components--omitted premises, assump­
tions, qualifiers, and counterarguments.

6. Appeals to Pride or Snobbery

Speech was given to man to disguise his thoughts.


-Talleyrand (1754-1838; quoted in Macmillan, 1 989, p. 544)

An appeal to pride or snobbery usually involves praise or flattery. A blatant and


humorous example can be found in an advertisement that was mailed to me at
home. (Notice that it begins with my name, a sure attention-getting technique.)

Dear Dr. Halpern,


You may just be the solution.
Here is the problem: How do you find the right subscribers for an extraordinary magazine
that is about to be published-BUT, a magazine that isn't for everyone?
A magazine that is, in fact, for only a handful of bright, literate people, people who still in
this world of instant communication love to sit down with a good book.

I'd love to believe that the publishers know me personally, and have written a
magazine just for the kind of person I'd like to be. The truth is, this letter went to
tens of thousands of people whose names were bought as part of various mailing
lists. Clearly, they are attempting to persuade me to purchase their magazine by ap­
pealing to my pride or snobbery.
Consider the following question, which appeared as part of a "1982 Congres­
sional Questionnaire" (Congressman Carlos J. Moorhead Reports, Summer, 1982):

In an attempt to make federal social programs more responsive to citizens' needs, less
wasteful and more efficient, the Administration has proposed a New Federalism where the
programs and funds-in the form of block grants-are transferred to local government for
management and administration. Do you think that you, your neighbors, and your local offi­
cials have the ability to handle this new responsibility?
yes no

Do you think that this question is slanted toward a "yes" response? The appeal to
pride and snobbery is less obvious in this question than in the first example, possibly
EXPLAINING AS KNOWING 215

making it even more potent. The question is really, Are you and your friends smart
/I

enough to handle X?" It doesn't matter what X iSj most people believe that they are
smart. The congressman has also posed the wrong question. You may be able to
"handle this new responsibility" without believing that block grants are a good
idea. Responses to this question were subsequently used to support the idea of
block grants. Be wary of persuasive communications that include flattery. Although
flattery is not in and of itself wrong, it may be used to obscure real issues.

7. Card Stacking or Suppressed Information

Card stacking or suppressed information operates as a persuasive technique by


omitting information that supports the unfavored view. An automobile company
recently compared the car they were advertising on television with a competitor.
The advertisers stressed that their car got better mileage and cost less. What about
the variables they omitted? Which car needed fewer repairs, had the more comfort­
able seating, or accelerated better? What about other makes of cars? Did a brand that
was not mentioned exceed the advertised one on all of these dimensions? When
considering persuasive information, be sure to consider what has not been stated
along with the stated claims. This is another example of the need to consider the
missing components in an argument.

8. Circular Reasoning
In circular reasoning the premise is simply a restatement of the conclusion. If you
were to diagram the structure of this sort of argument, you would get a circle be­
cause the support for the conclusion is a restatement of the conclusion. Here is an
example of circular reasoning:
We need to raise the speed limit because the current legal speed is too slow.
In this example, the reason given (current speed is too slow) is just another way
of saying that we need to raise the speed limit. It does not support the conclusion.
The conclusion would be supported with premises such as the assertion that there
has been no change in the number or severity of automobile accidents with a lower
speed limit or some similar statement that supports this conclusion.

9. Irrelevant Reasons

Arguments that utilize irrelevant reasons are fairly common. The Latin word for this
sort of fallacy is non sequitur, which literally translates to "it doesn't follow." In other
words, the reason or premise is unrelated to the conclusion. Of course, you recognize
the importance of having relevant premises as one of the criteria for sound arguments.
(If you don't, go back over the section of evaluating the quality of an argument.)
One example that comes to mind is a statement that a faculty member made at a
curriculum committee meeting in which we were discussing whether we should re­
quire every student to take classes in a foreign language. The faculty member in
favor of this proposal made this statement: ''We should require every student to
study a foreign language because it is important that we provide our students with
a quality education." Look carefully at the conclusion and the premise. Is the
premise related to the conclusion? Everyone on the curriculum committee believed
that all students should receive a quality education, but the issue was whether all
students should be required to study a foreign language. There were no reasons
2 16 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

given as to why studying a foreign language should be a required part of a quality


education. The conclusion did not follow from the reason that was given.

1 0. Slippery Slope or Continuum

The slippery slope fallacy is best described by an example. One of the arguments
against court-ordered desegregation of the schools was that, if we allow the court to
determine which public schools our children will attend, the court will also tell us
whom we have to allow into our churches, whom we have to invite into our homes,
and even whom we should marry. In this example, the action (court-ordered deseg­
regation) lies on a continuum with the court ordering whom we should marry at an
extreme end. The argument being made is that if we allow the court to have jurisdic­
tion over events at one end of the continuum, then it will take over the other events
on the continuum. For this reason, this fallacy is called either slippery slope (once
you start sliding down a slope you can't stop) or the fallacy of continuum.
Most life events can be placed along a continuum. It does not necessarily follow
that actions concerning some part of the continuum will also apply to other
portions of the continuum. Let's consider a second example. The Irish believe that
current U.s. immigration laws are biased against immigrants from Ireland. They
have asked the U.s. immigration service to increase the quota for Ireland. Those
who have argued against increasing the immigration quotas for Ireland have said
that if we increase the quota for Ireland, then we'll have to increase the quota for
every other country in the world, an action that they see as disastrous. Increasing
the number of immigrants we accept from Ireland does not mean that we would
also have to increase the quotas for other countries. The immigration office may or
may not decide to alter quotas from other countries, but taking an action on behalf
of one country does not mean that the other actions will follow. A more colorful
name for this fallacy is "the camel's nose in the tent." It is based on the idea that if
we let a camel stick its nose in the tent, the rest of the camel will soon follow.

1 1 . Straw Person

A straw person is weak and easy to knock down. With a straw person argument, a
very weak form of an opponent's argument is set up and then knocked down. It oc­
curs when an opponent to a particular conclusion distorts the argument in support of
the conclusion and substitutes one that is much weaker. For example, in a discussion
about whether students should be evaluating their professors, one opponent to this
idea offered this straw person argument: "You say that students' evaluations of their
professors should be included in decisions about which professors we should be pro­
moting. Well, I certainly don't think that the decision as to which professors get pro­
moted should be made by students." Notice how the original argument that "student
evaluations should be included in the decision-making process" was changed to
"students should not be deciding which professors get promoted." The original argu­
ment was for student evaluations to be part of the criteria used in the decision-making
process. This is not the same as having students actually make the decisions. In its
changed form, the argument is easier to knock down, just like a straw person.

1 2 . Part-Whole

Part-whole fallacies are flip sides of the same error. A part-whole fallacy is made
whenever a speaker or writer assumes that whatever is true of the whole is also true
EXPLAINING AS KNOWING 217

of all of its parts, and whatever is true of the parts is also true of the whole. Consider
some outstanding, prestigious university. (Are you thinking about your own
school?) As a whole, the student body is highly intelligent, but it would be wrong to
believe that every student who attends that university is therefore highly intelligent.
Similarly, think of several brilliant scientists. Just because they are each brilliant does­
n't mean that if we put them on a committee together (made a whole out of them),
the committee would be brilliant. They may never agree or perhaps spend so much
time impressing each other with how smart they are that no work would get done.

1 3. Appeals to Ignorance

The peculiar thing about appeals to ignorance is that they can often be used to
support two or more totally different conclusions. This should be a clue to you that
the reasoning involved is fallacious. In appeals to ignorance, the premise involves
something we don't know. Our ignorance is being used to argue because there is no
evidence to support a conclusion, the conclusion must be wrong. Our ignorance of a
topic can also be used to support a conclusion by stating that because there is no ev­
idence that contradicts it, the conclusion must be right. I have heard both sides
argue this way in a debate on the existence of God. Believers have argued that be­
cause no one can prove that God doesn't exist, He therefore must exist. Nonbeliev­
ers have argued that because no one can prove that God exists, He therefore doesn't
exist. The absence of evidence doesn't support any conclusion. The absence of evi­
dence for one conclusion is not evidence for another conclusion.

1 4. Weak and Inappropriate Analogies

The topic of analogies was presented in Chapter 3, liThe Relationship Between


Thought and Language." It also appears later in the book in Chapters 9 and 10 on
problem solving and creativity. Analogies are a basic thinking skill. We use analo­
gies whenever we encounter something new and try to understand it by reference to
something we already know. Although analogies can be extremely useful aids to
comprehension, they can also be misused. Two objects or events are analogous
when they share certain properties. When we argue with analogies, we conclude
that what is true of one object or event is true of the other.
Consider the mother who decides that her child should not be given piano
lessons because the child had dropped out of dance class. The mother formed the
analogy that the child dropped out of one type of creative arts lessons and because
dance class and piano lessons were similar in some ways, the child would also drop
out of piano lessons. The child may or may not have continued with piano lessons,
but it was a weak sort of analogy that formed the support for this conclusion. Dance
class and piano lessons are similar in certain respects, but they also have many dis­
tinct differences. When considering an argument by analogy, it is important to con­
sider the nature and the salience of the similarity relationship. It is possible that the
child would have stuck with piano.

1 5. Appeals to Authority

I already introduced this fallacy in an informal way earlier in this chapter when
I discussed expert credibility. Much of what we know and believe is based on what
we learn from authorities. The fallacy of appeals to authority occurs when the
authority we use to support the premises in an argument is the wrong authority.
2 18 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

If I wanted to sell you a stereo, it would be valid if I quoted from an article on


stereos written by a professor of acoustics (who is an independent authority). It
would be a fallacious appeal if I told you that Kobe Bryant called it the best stereo
system he had ever seen. Thus, the fallacy is not in appealing to an authority on a
topic, but to appealing to someone who is not a credible authority.

1 6. Incomplete Comparisons

"More doctors agree that Dopeys can give you the fastest pain relief." Advertise­
ments like this one are so common that it's almost impossible to open a magazine
without seeing one. Two different comparisons are made in this statement and both
are incomplete. Whenever you see comparative terms ask yourself "more than
what," "fastest compared to what?" Incomplete comparisons are missing the other
half of the equation.
Incomplete comparisons often contain evaluative terms like "better," "safest,"
and, of course, "cleanest." This is a special case of considering missing components
in an argument. How was "better" defined? How was it measured? By whom?
Compared to what? There is no way to interpret claims like, "Washo will make your
whole wash cleaner" without additional information. An ice cream store that I pass
on my way to work has a large sign outside that states, "Voted the best ice cream." I
presume that I am supposed to infer that their ice cream was voted the best, but by
whom, compared to which other ice creams, what criteria were used to decide
which was best, and how were the ice creams evaluated with these criteria? Every
time you see a comparative claim, you should ask yourself these questions. If the an­
swers aren't provided, then the comparison is incomplete, and the comparison is
usually a meaningless ploy to get you to buy something.

1 7. Knowing the Unknowable

Sometimes we are given information that it is impossible to know. This is the fal­
lacy of knowing the unknowable. Suppose you read in the newspapers that we
need to increase the size of the police force because the number of unreported rapes
has increased dramatically. A little alarm should go off when you read this: How can
anyone know about the number of unreported rapes? I don't doubt that many rapes
are not reported to the police or that this is an important issue. What is at question is
the increase or decrease in the number when the actual number is unknowable.
There are numerous times when sources give precise figures when such figures are
impossible. Child abuse is another example. This is a tragic and important issue for
society to grapple with, but estimates about the number of children involved can
never be very accurate because much of it is undetected. Researchers can try to ex­
trapolate from the number of child abuse cases that are treated in the emergency
rooms of hospitals or that go to court, but there are no good methods of extending
these known figures to unreported cases. An increase in the number of cases of rape
or child abuse may be due to increased awareness and education about these crimes.
An increase in reported cases could be associated with an increase, decrease, or no
change in unreported cases. Again, there is no way we can know the unknowable.

1 8. False Cause
The fallacy of false cause is discussed more completely in Chapter 6, "Thinking
as Hypothesis Testing," but it is also important to discuss in the context of reasoning
EXPLAINING AS KNOWING 2 19

fallacies. The fallacy of false cause occurs whenever someone argues that because
two events occur together, or one follows the other closely in time, that one caused
the other to occur. For example, consider the finding that as the number of churches
increase in a city so does the number of prostitutes. It would be false to conclude
that churches cause an increase in prostitution or that prostitutes cause more
churches to be built. In fact, as the size of a city increases so does the number of
churches and the number of prostitutes, as well as the number of schools, dry clean­
ers, volunteer agencies, and so on. Neither of them caused any of the others. They
all resulted from a third factor-in this case, an increase in population. Of course,
it is possible that one variable did cause the other to occur, but more than co­
occurrence is needed to justify a causal claim.

1 9. Put Downs

Only a fool would endorse this candidate! No patriotic American would dis­
agree! You'd have to be stupid to believe that! These are all examples of put downs
(also known as belittling the opposition). An opposing viewpoint is belittled so that
agreeing with it would put you in the class of people who are fools, or unpatriotic,
or stupid. This technique is not so much a reasoning fallacy as it is an emotional ap­
peal or dare.

20. Appeals to Tradition

"That's the way we've always done it." Anyone who has tried to change a policy
has heard this sentence or its variant, "If it ain't broke, don't fix it." In appeals to tra­
dition, the unstated assumption is that what exists is best. It may be true that cur­
rent policy is better than some suggested change, but it also may not be true. There
is nothing inherent in the fact that "that's the way we've always done it" that makes
it a good or best way to accomplish an objective. One of the attitudes of a critical
thinker that was presented in the first chapter is flexibility. Appeals to tradition
deny the possibility that a different way may be an improvement.

2 1 . False Charge of Fallacy

That's a fallacy! It seems that after some people learn to recognize fallacious rea­
soning, they then label everything that anyone says as a fallacy (Levi, 1991). Not
every statement is a fallacy. The idea of critical thinking is to develop an amiable
skepticism, not a cynical view that everything and everyone is false. It is important
to know when to accept some statements as acceptable as it is to know when and
what to question.

Distinguishing Among Opinion,


Reasoned Judgment, and Fact

Compare the following three statements.

Britney Spears is a great singer.


Britney Spears is a great singer because she can sing a wider variety of songs than any
other contemporary artist.
2 20 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

Britney Spears is a great singer with several different songs at the top of the chart and al­
bums that have gone platinum.

In the first example, I have expressed an opinion. It is a simple assertion of a pref­


erence. I like it; I think it's best. No reasons were given to support the evaluation.
Opinion reflects how an individual or group has assessed a position or product­
e.g., "Vote for Max Lake; he's the best man for the job!"
The second example also expresses a preference, but in this example, the prefer­
ence is supported by reasons. I like X because Y. This is an example of reasoned judg­
ment. Other examples of reasoned judgment are provided throughout the chapter.
The third statement concerns factual claims. Facts have a verifiable truth value­
e.g., Gravel-a's breakfast cereal has 1 00% of the recommended daily requirement of
iron. Although I can't personally check the truth-value of these facts, a credible au­
thority (e.g., the Food and Drug Administration) has verified these claims for me.
Often, the distinction among fact, opinion, and reasoned judgment is a fine one. If
we say that Gravel-a's is a good cereal because it has 1 00% of the recommended
daily requirement of iron, this is a reasoned judgment based, in part, on the un­
stated assumption that it is good to eat cereals that contain 100% of the recom­
mended daily requirement of iron. The distinction becomes even more difficult
when you recall that opinions can serve as the premises (reasons) in an argument.
Thus, when I say that Gravel-a's is a good cereal because I like its nutty taste, I have
a reason to support my conclusion. If I were to add that Gravel-a's is a good cereal
because I like its nutty taste and it supplies all of my iron needs for the day, the
strength of my argument is increased.
"Pure" facts that are untainted by opinion are often hard to find. Take for example,
your daily newspaper. Although news reporters are obligated to provide readers with
facts, their opinions certainly color what they report and how they report it. Compare
the way two different newspapers cover the same story. One newspaper could make
it the headline on page one, thus making it important news that will be read by many,
whereas the other could place it in an inside section in smaller print, thus making sure
that fewer people will read the story. Look at the words used to convey the same
story. A quiet night in Poland during a period of martial law could be described as
"Poland Enforces Martial Law" or as "All Is Quiet in Poland." Both of these headlines
could be factually correct, yet they clearly convey different ideas about Polish life.
Most news media (news magazines, newspapers, television news) are biased to­
ward providing information that "sells." The news media often treat complex issues
in a very simplistic manner with a heavy emphasis on controversies because they
are more interesting than agreements. The usual rules of scientific evidence and rea­
soning often are abandoned in the news media where deadlines determine the news
you get and interest value can drive content. The distinction between fact and opin­
ion is becoming increasingly difficult to discern. As King (1994) notes, television
programs like Hard Copy are supposedly "reenactments" of real events, but we
never know how close the story is to reality. Add some "partially fictionalized" ac­
counts of gruesome real-life murders and the filming of actual police arrests for en­
tertainment shows, and the situation gets even messier. I made this point earlier
when I discussed the partially fictionalized (or at least highly biased) version of the
movie about the JFK assassination. The fuzzy distinction between the real and un­
real gets even more difficult now that "virtual reality" computer programs are avail­
able that rival "real reality." It is a brave, new world that we are entering-one that
makes critical thinking more necessary than ever.
EXPLAINING AS KNOWING 22 1

You may be thinking that at least one source of honest facts is your textbooks. Al­
though it is usually safe to assume that text authors do not set out deliberately to
mislead students, the facts that they report are also subject to interpretation. Easily
quantified and verifiable information such as the number of soldiers sent to a South
American country or the size of the national deficit are probably correct or as close
to correct as pOSSible, presuming that there has been no deliberate attempt to lie.
Other facts such as the sequence of events and their importance in causing a war, or
strategies at political conventions, or poverty in America need to be interpreted by
text authors who will decide how to describe them. The words they use, the events
included or omitted, and the amount of information given, all contribute to the "fac­
tual" information that is printed. Personal bias will, of course, influence the way the
ideas are presented.
It has been said that there is never just one war fought. Each side has its own ver­
sion, and rarely do they agree. Unfortunately, there is always fighting somewhere
around the world so that you can verify this statement for yourself. It is not unusual
for each side to claim that the other fired first, or for both sides to claim victory in a
battle. Obviously, in the absence of verifiable truth there is no way to know which, if
either, side is presenting the facts. As before, the best way to assess the quality of the
information provided is to consider the credibility of the reporter. I would prefer a
report from an independent third party with first-hand and direct knowledge and
appropriate credentials to a report from spokespersons from either of the sides in­
volved in a dispute.
Advertisements make extensive use of opinions dressed up as fact. Consider the
advertisements for headache remedies. Often they will show an attractive man in a
white laboratory coat, obviously selected to portray a physician. He tells you that,
"Speedy works fast on headache pain." Although this may seem like a fact, it is an
opinion. "Past" is a vague term, and therefore it is a matter of judgment. If the ap­
propriate tests with a large number of people had shown that, on the average,
Speedy brings pain relief in 20 minutes, this information would be a fact. If you are
in doubt as to whether information is fact or opinion, check for vague or evaluative
terms (fast, better, lovelier, etc.), and ask yourself how the evaluative term was de­
fined and what type of test was conducted to support the claim. This topic is cov­
ered in more detail in Chapter 6.

visual Arguments

He who controls images controls everything.


-Robert Townsend (quoted in Beilensen & Jackson, 1992, p. 15)

We are living in an increasingly visual society where we get more of our informa­
tion from visual displays than from words. Television is a major source of informa­
tion and entertainment for many people. The average television viewer will see
approximately 30,000 commercials every year. The message in each is mostly the
same-whatever your problem is (e.g., rough elbows, teeth that do not dazzle with
sparkling whiteness, overweight), you can buy a product that will solve it (Postman &
Powers, 1 992). Much of the persuasive message in television commercials is con­
veyed through the pictures that we see, often with the accompanying dialogue
being of secondary importance. Images are also important in magazines, newspa­
pers, video games, the Internet, and on billboards.
222 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

The effects of visual images are more difficult to gauge because they are often
subtle. Consider a sample of cigarette advertisements. Smoking is linked to beauty,
glamour, youth, health, and popularity (Kidd, 1 991). A popular theme in visual cig­
arette advertisements is horses and the "great" outdoors. We are shown beautiful,
happy people who are smoking and enjoying the good life. The horses suggest
ruggedness and an unrestrained independence-just the sort of person who won't
be swayed with facts that link smoking with many diseases. Careful market re­
search pinpoints specific markets for cigarette smokers and designs images to ap­
peal to market segments, for example, young women, with no more than a high
school education, who wear jeans, and work at blue-collar jobs. The images in these
ads are very different from those targeted at more educated women, who are shown
reading and talking while they smoke.
Visual images are used effectively in political campaigns. Consider this descrip­
tion of the television advertisements that were used in a "race" for the governor in
California. Wilson, the Republican incumbent, used ads that made him appear to be
a leader who should not be blamed for California's woes, and Brown, the Democra­
tic challenger, used ads in which she appeared to be a bright solution to California's
problems. In Brown's television ads, California is shot in black-and-white scenes of
urban decay-only Brown appears in color. By contrast, Wilson shows scenes of ser­
ial rapists and stealthy bands of illegal immigrants with Wilson's somber face ap­
pearing to be taking care of these grave problems.
Visual images can be powerful determinants of public opinion and policy. I can­
not forget the pictures of starving children in Somalia, which eloquently spoke of
the dire need to send U.S. troops to assist with this disaster or the image of a dead
U.S. serviceman being dragged through the dusty streets of Somalia. Which image
moved the United States to promptly leave Somalia? What if the images had been
different? Suppose that, instead of the dead peacekeeper being dragged through the
street, the media had shown pictures of Somalians receiving food and clean water­
people who were alive because of the peacekeepers? The images we are shown have
profound effects on how we think and feel.
Figure 5.2 shows some old propagandist images that were popular in Russia in
the early and mid-20th century. Note the image of the fat, rich capitalist. His piglike
face and bloated body are deliberately unattractive, and his sea of gold depicts his
solitary concern with material wealth. Look also at the Soviet Army recruiter with
the outstretched, pointing finger, urging Russians to volunteer. Compare him to the
military recruiting posters that were popular in the United States during the same
time period, a time when we all knew that "Uncle Sam wants you."
Often an image can speak more persuasively for a point of view than even
the most eloquent prose. The images in Figure 5.3 were all posters from China,
Germany, France, and Cuba. You don't need to be able to read the words to under­
stand the message. Cognitive psychologists know that we have very good picture
memory-a fact that is exploited in these posters. Oftentimes we do not scrutinize
the images that bombard of us with the same care that we use for verbal arguments.
Pay attention to the images you encounter throughout the day and consider how
each is influencing what and how you think. Images are often used as nonverbal
communication that reinforce stereotypes. There are women clad in bikinis in beer
advertisements, images of housewives worrying about their laundry, images of
African Americans smoking "uptown" cigarettes. These images are so ubiquitous
that we often take them for granted. Look at and think about the images you see.
Are some groups usually depicted in menial jobs on television or in advertisements?
FIG. 5.2. Images of persuasion. The piglike man surrounded with his gold was designed
to represent the capitalist. It was a common image during the years when Soviet Communists
needed to keep the idea that "capitalism is bad" alive. By contrast, the Soviet recruiter has his
arms open to welcome all to the great cause. He bears an uncanny similarity in pose and
nonverbal gestures to the American recruiting poster where we were told that "Uncle Sam
Wants You."

223
When China and the Soviet Union sptit in the 1950s, China was left
without any allies, Soviet military forces were close to ils borders, The
dominant message was to keep foreign infiuences out of China.
Wer Burgerblatter liest wlrd blind und taub.
Weg mil den verdummungsbandagenl

(Whoever reads bourgeois newspapers


becomes blind and deaf, Away with the
!y
stulti ing bandages!) This image is by John
Heatfleld, a young German, who in 1 930,
adopted the English·sounding name as
protest against the anti·English sentiments In
Germany at that time. The young Heartfield
was Inlluenced by the soldiers on the
western front, who unable to get their reports
passed military censors, turned to pasting
photographs together in order to relate the
horror ol lhe battlefield to their friends and
relatives back home. Inspired by this as well Zhou Yuwe, 1 986. "Carry oul family planning, Implement the basic
as the collage 01 the cubists, Heartfleld and nationat policy:
his close friend and fellow artist George In this poster, we see the message that China's strong one·chlld poticy
Grosz, invented photomontage. Is on the road to a modem Westernized world. The woman and chitd
do not seem to have Chinese features.

Honore Daumier, "La Caricature' ( 1 832)


Daumier was sentenced to 6 months In prison lor publishing this
satirical drawing of King Louis·Phllipe.
(from
httpJlwww.cd.sc.chu.eslFileRoomldocumentslCase247/daumeier.html)
Rene Mederos, 1 967
This Cuban poster shows the crushed hal 01
Uncle Sam as Cubans celebrated the deleat
01 the United States in Viet Narn,

Fig, 5.3. These images originally were posters from Germany, China, Cuba, and France.
Each is a visual argument-depicting a conclusion (and implied reasons) with images.

224
EXPLAINING AS K.�OWING 225

Who is used to display high fashion and who is depicted in warnings about criminal
activity? It is only when you become consciously aware of the images you are view­
ing, that you can think critically about the visual arguments you are receiving.

How to Change Beliefs

We are constantly surrounded by individuals and groups who want to change what
we think and how we act. Nearly every social interaction involves persuasion
(Siegel, 1991 ). Advertising agencies want us to buy whatever product they are sell­
ing; political candidates want our votes; the beef council wants us to eat more beef.
The list is endless. Some of these beliefs and actions are beneficial, but others are
not. One of the best ways to understand the dynamics of changing beliefs is to con­
sider the issues from the perspective of someone who wants to change the beliefs of
someone else. You can use this knowledge to change beliefs or to resist change. The
following list is loosely adapted from a summary of the attitude change literature.

1 . Provide a credible source for the information you are presenting. The source of
information should be a person or agency with the necessary expertise in the
field who is independent with respect to the issue. Additional requirements for
assessing the credibility of an information source are provided in this chapter.
2. Anticipate counterarguments, raise them, and provide counterexamples. This
is a good technique when debating an issue before an audience. It can leave
the opposition with few points to make. As you know, counterarguments
weaken the support for a conclusion. This technique allows you to weaken the
counterarguments.
3. Don't appear one-sided, especially when the audience may be predisposed to
the opposite side. The willingness to use qualifiers and to consider counterar­
guments makes your position appear more credible.
4. Be direct. Tell your audience what to believe. By explicitly stating the conclu­
sion, you eliminate the possibility that the audience will arrive at a different
conclusion or not "see" the support for the conclusion that you are advocating.
5. Encourage discussion and public commitment. These variables have not been
discussed in this chapter, although they appear in other places in the book.
The discussion allows the audience to generate reasons and to "own" them or
view them as reasons that they provided. Public commitment is a powerful
motivator. If someone signs a document or speaks in favor of a position, a host
of psychological mechanisms are brought into play. It is a kind of a promise to
believe or act in a certain way. This technique was used extensively by Caesar
Chavez and others in their attempt to get consumers to boycott grapes. (The
motivation for the boycott was to protest the use of certain pesticides on the
grapes.) Several years ago, I had the honor of having lunch with Caesar
Chavez and a small group of students and college administrators. At lunch, he
asked us all to stand up and pledge that we would not eat grapes until the
growers agreed to stop using certain pesticides. The public commitment was
more effective than a simple nod of the head to indicate agreement would
have been. A restaurant owner in Los Angeles has borrowed this technique. A
big problem for many restaurants is the large number of people who make
reservations and then neither show up for the reservation nor call to cancel it.
In the past, when customers called to make reservations, they were told,
2 26 5. ANALYZING ARGUMENTS

"Please call if you have to cancel the reservations." Now, the person who
takes the reservation asks, "Will you please call if you have to cancel the
reservations?" The customer needs to make a commitment to call-and the
simple act of committing seems to make a difference. The number of cus­
tomers who do not cancel their reservations when they are not keeping them
is greatly reduced. What a difference two words can make.
6. Repeat the conclusion and the reasons that support the conclusion several
times. People prefer positions that are familiar to them. You can make the
same points in several different ways. Repetition is a useful aid in recall. Thus
reasons that are easily remembered (Le., more available in memory) are more
readily used to assess the strength of an argument. (The potent effects of re­
peated exposure are presented in Chapter 8, "Decision Making.")
7. Provide as many reasons to support the conclusion as is feasible. As you al­
ready know, one way to increase the strength of an argument is by increasing
the number of reasons that support it.
8. The message should be easy to comprehend. People are negatively affected
by messages they find incomprehensible (Fiske & Taylor, 1984).
9. You could use any of the 21 common fallacies presented in this chapter. But
be wary, they are examples of unsound reasoning. If you want to persuade
someone, your reasoning should be sound. Shoddy reasoning is detectable,
and if detected, it could (and should) destroy your credibility.
10. Use vivid images that will be difficult to forget and be sure that they make
your point.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

Let's consider the steps in applying the general framework for thinking to analyzing
arguments.

1 . What Is the Goal'?

You'll want to use the skills for analyzing arguments anytime you encounter at­
tempts to persuade you or you attempt to persuade someone that a particular con­
clusion is either true or likely to be true. Once you become accustomed to "looking
for arguments" (in its technical meaning, not in its everyday meaning) and looking at
reasons, you'll be surprised how frequently you are bombarded by advertisements,
political claims, and other attempts to "change your point of view." You will also
need to use the information in this chapter when you make your own arguments.

2 . What Is Known'?

This question is about starting points in the thinking process. In analyzing argu­
ments, you begin with statements and determine if they contain an argument. The
statements are then evaluated to assess the quality of the argument. The process pro­
ceeds by identifying the conclusion and premises and systematically applying the
steps of argument analysis in order to reach the goal of making a determination
about how good the argument is. When you make an argument, begin with the rea­
sons and counterarguments. Assemble the reasoning so that it supports a conclusion.
CHAPTER SUMMARY 227

3 . Which Thinking Skill or Skills Will


Get You to Your Goal?
The skills of analyzing arguments involve the sequential application of "tests of
goodness"-how acceptable are the premises, how much support do they provide for
the conclusion, and which and how many components are missing? At a minimum,
you should be able to apply the three criteria for sound arguments to any set of state­
ments. The skills involved in analyzing arguments are ordered, with less emphasis on
selecting the correct skill than on the systematic application of the entire set.
It is almost as important to be able to say why an argument is unsound as it is to
be able to identify unsound arguments. You should be able to recognize the 21 fal­
lacies presented in this chapter and explain how each of them violates one of the
principles of sound arguments.
The following skills for analyzing arguments were presented in this chapter. If
you are unsure about how to use any of these skills, be sure to reread the section in
which it is discussed.

• Identifying arguments.
• Diagramming the structure of an argument.
• Evaluating premises for their acceptability.
• Examining the credibility of an information source.
• Determining the consistency, relevance to the conclusion, and adequacy in the
way premises support a conclusion.
• Remembering to consider missing components by assuming a different
perspective.
• Assessing the overall strength of an argument.
• Recognizing, labeling, and explaining what is wrong with each of the 21 fallac-
ies that was presented.
• Recognizing differences among opinion, reasoned judgment, and fact.
• Understanding how visual arguments can be effective.
• Judging your own arguments for their strength.

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?

This is a particularly important question in analyzing arguments because one of


the steps involves considering components that are not there. Have you consciously
tried to restructure the argument using an opposite perspective? Are you able to
make an overall judgment about the strength of the argument? Have you arrived at a
sound conclusion? It is important to review the way in which you weighted the sup­
porting premises. Often a decision to weigh a premise as either weak or moderate will
have very different effects on your overall assessment of the strength of the argument.

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . An argument is an attempt to convince the reader (or listener) that a particular


conclusion is true based on the reasons presented.
2. All arguments must have at least one conclusion and one premise (reason).
Arguments may also have assumptions, qualifiers, and counterarguments.
228 5. A.."IALYZING ARGUMENTS

3. Arguments have structures that can be identified and diagrammed.


4. Sound (good) arguments meet three criteria: The premises are acceptable and
consistent; the premises provide support for the conclusion by being relevant to the
conclusion and are sufficiently strong; and missing components of the argument
(e.g., assumptions, counterarguments, qualifiers, premises, and rival conclusions)
have been considered.
5. When analyzing the strength of an argument, the amount of support each
premise supplies to the conclusion is weighed along with the negative effects of
counterarguments. Missing components are made explicit and are considered along
with the stated components.
6. It is often necessary to assess the credibility of a source of information when
deciding on the acceptability of a premise. There are important differences between
experts for issues of fact and experts for issues of value.
7. People like to believe that their beliefs and actions are "reasoned"; however,
most people are not sensitive to poor or weak reasoning. Unfortunately, there is a
general preference for explanations that "make sense" over conclusions that are jus­
tified by available data. Critical thinkers need to understand the importance of data
and value data-based conclusions.
8. There is a widespread bias to assign greater importance to reasons that sup­
port a conclusion that we favor than to reasons that run counter to a conclusion that
we favor. This bias can be reduced by listing reasons and consciously deciding how
strongly they support or run counter to a conclusion.
9. A critical part of the analysis of arguments is the consideration of missing
parts and misleading statements.
10. Arguments of all sorts have been used to justify genocide and other versions
of "ethnic cleansing." The techniques presented here could prevent future horrors, if
people are willing to invest the time and hard work in analyzing arguments.
1 1 . Twenty-one common techniques of propaganda were presented. Most can be
categorized as types of unsound reasoning in which emotional appeals are often
substituted for reasons.
1 2. A distinction was made among the terms "opinion," "reasoned judgment,"
and "fact." An opinion is an unsupported statement of preference. Reasoned judg­
ment is a belief that is based on the consideration of premises that support that be­
lief. Facts have a verifiable true value. It is often difficult to discern the difference
among these terms in real-life settings.
13. Visual images are used to persuade. Strong images that are difficult to forget
can support or refute a conclusion.
14. The beliefs of others can be changed with sound and unsound reasoning. Be­
ware of attempts to manipulate your beliefs with shoddy reasoning techniques.

TERMS TO KNOW

Check your understanding of the concepts presented in this chapter by reviewing


their definitions. If you find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to
reread the section where it is discussed.

Argument. An argument consists of one or more statements that are used to pro­
vide support for a conclusion.
TERMS TO KNOW 229

Conclusion. The belief or statement that the writer or speaker is advocating.


Reasons. The bases for believing that a conclusion is true or probably true. Note:
This word may be singular or plural as there may be one or more reasons for a con­
clusion. When we reason (singular only), we are following rules for determining if
an argument is sound.
Premises. The formal term for the statements that support a conclusion.
Premise Indicators. Key words that often (but not always) signal that the statement
or statements that follow them are premises.
Conclusion Indicators. Key words that often (but not always) signal that the state­
ment or statements that follow them are conclusions.
Assumptions. In an argument, an assumption is a statement for which no proof or
evidence is offered. They may be stated or implied.
Subarguments. Arguments that are used to build the main argument in an ex­
tended passage.
Main point. The principal argument in an extended passage.
Qualifier. A constraint or restriction on the conclusion.
Counterargument. Statements that refute or weaken a particular conclusion.
Statement. A phrase or sentence for which it makes sense to ask the question, "Is it
true or false?" Questions, commands, and exclamations are not statements.
Convergent Structures. A type of argument in which two or more premises sup­
port the same conclusion.
Chained (or Linked) Structures. Argument types in which the conclusion of one
subargument becomes the premise of a second argument.
Acceptable. A standard for assessing the quality of a premise. A premise is accept­
able when it is true or when we can reasonably believe that it is true.
Consistent. A standard for assessing the quality of an argument. When the
premises that support a conclusion are not contradictory, they are consistent.
Adequate Grounds. A standard for assessing the quality of an argument. Occurs
when the premises provide good support for a conclusion.
Sound Argument. Meets three criteria: (a) Acceptable and consistent premises,
(b) premises are relevant and provide sufficient support for the conclusion, and
(c) missing components are considered and evaluated.
Rationalizing. A biased analysis of an argument so that a preferred conclusion will
be judged as acceptable or a nonpreferred conclusion will be judged as unaccept­
able. The process of rationalizing is usually not conscious.
Propaganda. Information presented by proselytizers of a doctrine or belief. The ob­
jective is to get the reader or listener to endorse the belief.
Fallacies. Unsound reasoning techniques that are used to change how people
think.
Guilt by Association. The propaganda technique of associating a position or per­
son with an undesirable position or person in order to create a negative impression.
Virtue by Association. The propaganda technique of associating a position or per­
son with a desirable position or person in order to create a favorable impression.
Compare with guilt by association.
Arguments Against the Person. A form of propaganda that attacks the people who
support a cause and not the cause itself.
Appeals to Pity. A propaganda technique that asks for your compassion instead of
appealing to your reason.
Popularity. A propaganda technique in which the only reason for the conclusion is
that it is endorsed by "everyone."
230 5. A."'IALYZING ARGUMENT�

Testimonials. An appeal in which the sole support for a conclusion is someone':


unsupported opinion.
False Dichotomy. An argument in which two possible conclusions or courses of ac
tion are presented when there are multiple other possibilities. (Also known as blac!
or white fallacy.)
Appeals to Pride or Snobbery. The use of praise or flattery to get its recipient tc
agree with a position.
Card Stacking. A propaganda technique that omits important information tha
might support an unfavored view.
Circular Reasoning. An argument structure in which the premise is a restatemen
of the conclusion.
Slippery Slope. Counterargument for a conclusion in which the premise consists 0.
the idea that because certain events lie along some continuum it is not possible t(
take an action without affecting all the events on the continuum.
Continuum. Fallacy of the continuum is the same as slippery slope.
Straw Person. A type of propaganda technique in which an opponent to a conclusior
distorts the argument that supports the conclusion by substituting a weaker argument
Appeals to Ignorance. An argument in which the premise involves something tha
is unknown.
Appeals to Authority. Reliance on an inappropriate authority in formulatin�
conclusions.
Incomplete Comparisons. Using evaluative terms like "better," "faster," or "cleaner'
without indicating the two items that are being compared.
Knowing the Unknowable. Fallacy in which numbers are provided for events tha
cannot be quantified.
False Cause. Fallacy in which one event is said to have caused the other becausE
they occur together.
Put Downs. Belittling an opposing point of view so that it would be difficult for c
listener to agree with it.
Appeals to Tradition. A propaganda technique that utilizes the reason that whal
already exists is best.
6

Thinking as
Hypothesis Testing

Contents
Understanding Hypothesis Testing Thinking About Errors
Explanation, Prediction, and Control Experience is an Expensive Teacher
Inductive and Deductive Methods Self-Fulfilling Prophecies
Operational Definitions Making Sense Out of the World
Independent and Dependent Occult Beliefs and the Paranormal
Variables Thinking as an Intuitive Scientist
Measurement Sensitivity Applying the Framework
Populations and Samples Chapter Summary
Biased and Unbiased Samples Terms to Know
Sample Size
Variability
Science Versus Science Fiction
Amazing and Not True
Cold Reading
Determining Cause
Isolation and Control of Variables
Three-Stage Experimental Designs
Using the Principles of Isolation
and Control
Prospective and Retrospective
Research
Correlation and Cause
Validity
Convergent Validity
Illusory Validity
Reliability

23 1
232 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

Suppose that the following is true: You are seriously addicted to heroin and you
have two choices of treatment programs.
Program 1 : This program is run by former heroin addicts. Your therapist will be a recov­
ered addict who is the same age as you. The literature about this program states that among
those who stay with the program for at least 1 year, the success rate is very high (80% ). One of
the biggest advantages of this program is that your therapist knows what it's like to be seri­
ously addicted and can offer you insights from his own recovery.
Program 2: The therapists in this program have studied the psychology and biology of
heroin addiction. The success rate that they provide is much lower than that provided for
Program 1 (30%), but the percentage of successes is based on everyone who enters treatment.
Your therapist has never been addicted to heroin, but has studied various treatment options.

This is an important decision for you. Which do you choose?

UNDERSTANDING HYPOTHESIS TESTING

Research is an intellectual approach to an unsolved problem, and its function is


to seek the truth.
-Leedy (1981, p. 7)

Much of our thinking is like the scientific method of hypothesis testing. A hypothe­
sis is a set of beliefs about the nature of the world; it is usually a belief about a rela­
tionship between two or more variables. In order to understand the world around
us, we accumulate observations, formulate beliefs or hypotheses (singular is hy­
pothesis), and then observe if our hypotheses are confirmed or disconfirmed. Thus,
hypothesis testing is one way of finding out about the "way the world works." For­
mulating hypotheses and making systematic observations that could confirm or dis­
confirm them is the same method that scientists use when they want to understand
events in their academic domain. Thus, when thinking is done in this manner, it has
much in common with the experimental methods used by scientists.

Explanation, Prediction, and Control

All . . . by nature desire knowledge.


-Aristotle (cited in Bartlett, 1992, p. 77)

There is a basic need to understand events in life. How many times have you asked
yourself questions like, "Why did my good friends get divorced when they seemed
perfect for each other?" or "How can we understand why the son of the u.s. sur­
geon general, the chief doctor in the United States, is addicted to illegal drugs?"
When we try to answer questions like these we often function as an "intuitive scien­
tist." Like the scientist, we have our own theories about the causes of social and
physical events. It is important to be able to explain why people react in certain
ways (e.g., He's a bigot. She's tired and cranky after work.), to predict the results of
our actions (e.g., If I don't study, I'll fail. If I wear designer clothes, people will think
I'm coo1.), and to control some of the events in our environment (e.g., In order to get
a good job in business, I'll have to do well in my accounting course.).
The goal of hypothesis testing is to make accurate predictions about the portion
of the world we're dealing with (Holland, Holyoak, Nisbett, & Thagard, 1986).
INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE METHODS 233

In order to survive and function with maximum efficiency, we must reduce the un­
certainty in our environment. One way to reduce uncertainty is to observe sequences
of events with the goal of determining predictive relationships. Children, for example,
may learn that an adult will appear whenever they cry; your dog may learn that
when he stands near the kitchen door, you will let him out; and teenagers may learn
that their parents will become angry when they come home late. These are important
predictive relationships because they reduce the uncertainty in the environment and
allow us to exercise some control over our lives. The process that we use in determin­
ing these relationships is the same one that is used when medical researchers discover
that cancer patients will go into remission following chemotherapy or that longevity
is associated with certain lifestyles. Because the processes are the same, some of the
technical concepts in scientific methods are applicable to practical everyday thought.

INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE METHODS

Inductive reasoning is a major aspect of cognitive development and plays an


important role in both the development of a system of logical thought processes
and in the acquisition of new information.
-Pellegrino and Goldman (1983, p. 143)

Sometimes a distinction is made between inductive and deductive methods of hy­


pothesis testing (see Chapter 4 on the development of reasoning skills). In the in­
ductive method, you observe events and then devise a hypothesis about the events
you observed. For example, you might notice that Armaund, a retired man whom
you know, likes to watch wrestling on television. Then you note that Minnie and
Sue Ann, who are retired older adults, also like to watch wrestling on television. On
the basis of these observations, you would hypothesize (invent a hypothesis or ex­
planation) that older people like to watch wrestling. In this way, you would work
from your observations to your hypothesis. The inductive method is sometimes de­
scribed as "going from the specific to the general." In an excellent book entitled, In­
duction (Holland et al., 1986), the authors argue that the inductive process is the pri­
mary way in which we learn about the nature of the world. They state, "The study
of induction, then, is the study of how knowledge is modified through use" (p. 5).
In the deductive method, you begin with a hypothesis that you believe to be true
and then make systematic observations to see if your hypothesis is correct. Suppose
that you are considering the hypothesis that old people like to watch wrestling.
After developing this hypothesis, you'd look around to find out if there are many
older people who like to watch televised wrestling. The deductive method is some­
times described as "going from the general to the specific." You would also want to
compare the group of older people to a group of young adults to see if young adults
watch wrestling less often than those who are older. After all, if almost everyone
liked to watch wrestling, then there would be nothing unusual in the finding that
old people like it. When you begin with a hypothesis and then collect evidence that
would confirm or disconfirm it, you are using the deductive method. A critical com­
ponent in hypothesis testing is that you also search for disconfirming evidence, a
theme that seems to be repeated in almost every chapter in this book.
Although a distinction is usually made between these two types of reasoning, in
real life they are just different phases of the hypothesis testing method. Often people
234 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

observe events, formulate hypotheses, observe events again, reformulate hypothe­


ses, and collect even more observations. The question of whether the observations
or the hypothesis comes first is moot because our hypotheses determine what we
choose to observe, and our observations determine what our hypotheses will be. It's
like the perennial question of which came first, the chicken or the egg. Each process
is dependent on the other for its existence. In this way, observing and hypothesizing
recycle, with the observations changing the hypotheses and the hypotheses chang­
ing what gets observed.
If you are a Sherlock Holmes fan, you'll recognize this process as one that was de­
veloped into a fine art by this fictional detective. He would astutely note clues about
potential suspects. For example, Sherlock Holmes could remember that the butler had
a small mustard-yellow stain on his pants when it is well known that you don't serve
mustard with wild goose, which was the main course at dinner that evening. He
would use such clues to devise hypotheses like, "the butler must have been in the
field where wild mustard plants grow." The master sleuth would then check for other
clues that would be consistent or inconsistent with this hypothesis. He might check
the butler's boots for traces of the red clay soil that surrounds the field in question.
After a circuitous route of hypotheses and observations, Sherlock Holmes would an­
nounce, "The butler did it." When called on to explain how he reached his conclusion,
he would utter his most famous reply, "It's elementary, my dear Watson."
Many of our beliefs about the world were obtained with the use of inductive and
deductive methods, much like the great Sherlock Holmes. We use the principles of
inductive and deductive reasoning to generate and evaluate beliefs. Holmes was in­
variably right in the conclusions he drew. Unfortunately, it is only in the realm of
fiction that mistakes are never made because conclusions that result from inductive
reasoning can never be known with absolute certainty. Let's examine the compo­
nents of the hypothesis-testing process to see where mistakes can occur.

operational Definitions

Scientific reasoning and everyday reasoning both require evidence-based


justification of beliefs, or the coordination of theory and evidence.
-Kuhn (1 993, p. 74)

An operational definition tells us how to recognize and measure the concept that
you're interested in. For example, if you believe that successful women are paid
high salaries, then you will have to define "successful" and "high salary" in ways
that will allow you to identify who is successful and who receives a high salary.
If you've already read Chapter 3, liThe Relationship Between Thought and Lan­
guage," then you should recognize the need for operational definitions as being the
same as the problem of vagueness. You'd need to provide some statement like,
"Successful individuals are respected by their peers and are famous in their field of
work." You will find that it is frequently difficult to provide good operational defin­
itions for terms. I can think of several people who are not at all famous, but who are
successful by their own and other definitions. If you used the operational definition
that requires fame as a component of success, then you would conclude that home­
makers, skilled craftspeople, teachers, nurses, and others could not be "successful"
based on this definition. Thus, this would seem to be an unsatisfactory operational
definition. Suppose, for purposes of illustration, that this is our operational defini­
tion to classify people into "successful" and "unsuccessful" categories.
INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE METHODS 235

How would you operationally define "paid a high salary"? Suppose you decided
on, "earns at least $1 ,000 per week." Once these terms are operationally defined, you
could go around finding out whether successful and unsuccessful women differ in
how much they are paid. Operational definitions are important. Whenever you hear
people talking about "our irresponsible youth," "knee-jerk liberals," "bleeding
hearts," "rednecks," "reactionaries," "fascists," or "feminists," ask them to define their
terms operationally. You may find that the impact of their argument is diminished
when they are required to be precise about their terms.
Many arguments hinge on operational definitions. For example, consider the de­
bate over whether homosexuality is a mental disorder. The issue turns on the answer
to operational definitions. What defines a "mental disorder"? Who gets to decide
how "mental disorder" should be defined? Does homosexuality possess the defining
characteristics of a mental disorder? The vitriolic arguments about whether abortion
is murder can be transformed into calmer arguments over what is the appropriate
definition of murder, and again the more important question, who is the right au­
thority to define what constitutes murder. Thus, with critical thinking, explosive di­
visions over issues like abortion will not be resolved, but they will be changed in
their character as people consider what is really being argued about. When you use
operational definitions, you avoid the problems of ambiguity and vagueness. Try,
for example, to write operational definitions for the following terms: love, prejudice,
motivation, good grades, sickness, athletic, beautiful, and maturity.

Independent and Dependent Variables

A variable is any measurable characteristic that can take on more than one value.
Examples of variables are gender (female and male), height, political affiliation (Re­
publican, Democrat, Communist, etc.), handedness (right, left, ambidextrous), and at­
titudes toward traditional sex roles (could range from extremely negative to extremely
positive). When we test hypotheses, we begin by choosing the variables of interest.
In the opening scenario of this chapter, you were asked to determine which of the
two programs would more likely help you kick your heroin habit. In this example,
there are two variables-type of treatment, which is the independent variable or
the one that is under your control (Program 1 and Program 2) and recovery, which
is the dependent variable or the one that you believe will change as a result of the
different treatments (you will either [aJ recover from the addiction, or [bJ you won't
recover from it). You want to select the program that is most likely to help you to re­
cover. In the jargon of hypothesis testing, you want to know which level of the inde­
pendent variable will have a beneficial effect on the dependent variable.
The next step in the hypothesis testing process is to define the variables opera­
tionally. Suppose we decide to define "recovery" as staying drug-free for at least
two years and "not recovering" as staying drug-free for less than two years, which
would include never being drug-free. It is important to think critically about opera­
tional definitions for your variables. If they are not stated in precise terms, the con­
clusions you draw from your study may be wrong.

Measurement Sensitivity

When we measure something, we systematically assign a number to it for the pur­


poses of quantification. Someone who is taller than you are is assigned a higher
236 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

number of inches of height than you are. If not, the concept of height would be
meaningless.
When we think as scientists and collect information in order to understand the
world, we need to consider how we measure our variables. For example, suppose
you believe that love is like a fever, and that people in love have fever-like symp­
toms. To find out if this is true, you could conduct an experiment, taking tempera­
tures from people who are in love and comparing your results to the temperatures
of people who are not in love. How will you measure temperature? Suppose that
you decide to use temperature headbands that register body temperature with a
band placed on the forehead. Suppose further that these bands measure tempera­
ture to the nearest degree (e.g., 98°, 99°, 1 00°, etc.). If being in love does raise your
body temperature, but only raises it one-half of a degree, you might never know this
if you used headband thermometers. Headband thermometers just wouldn't be
sensitive enough to register the small increment in body temperature. Sensitive
measures can detect small changes in the variable you want to measure. You would
incorrectly conclude that love doesn't raise body temperatures, when in fact it may
have. As far as I know, this experiment has never been done, but it is illustrative of
the need for sensitive measurement in this and similar situations.

POPULATIONS AND SAMPLES

People make innumerable decisions daily about other people that affect their lives
and careers. These decisions are inevitably fraught with errors ofjudgment that
reflect ignorance, personal biases, or stereotypes.
-W. Grant Dahlstrom (1993, p. 393)

In deciding which heroin treatment program to enter, or for that matter, which col­
lege to attend or which job to accept, you are making a bet about the future, which
necessarily involves uncertainty. Hypothesis-testing principles are used to reduce
uncertainty. We cannot eliminate uncertainty, but we can use the principles of hy­
pothesis testing to help us make the best choice. In the example at the beginning of
the chapter, you would have to examine and evaluate information about the success
rate of both programs. You would then use this information to make your decision.
The group that we want to know about is called a population. Because we obvi­
ously can't study every heroin addict to determine which program has more suc­
cesses, we need to study a subset of this population. A subset of a population is
called a sample. In this example, all of the people who entered each of the programs
constitute the sample. A random sample is a sample in which everyone in the popu­
lation is equally likely to be in the sample.

Biased and Unbiased Samples

We want our sample to be representative of our population. To be representative,


the addicts in our sample would need to be both female and male, from all socioeco­
nomic levels, all intellectual levels, rural and urban areas, and so on, assuming that
heroin addicts come from all of these demographic groups. We need representative
samples so that we can generalize our results and decide, on average, that one
POPULATIONS AND SAMPLES 237

program is more successful than the other. Generalization refers to using the results
obtained with a sample to infer that similar results would be obtained from the pop­
ulation, if everyone in the population had been measured (Heit, 2000). Generaliza­
tions are valid only if the sample is representative of the population.
What happens when the sample is not representative of the population? Suppose
that one program is very expensive and one is county-run to serve the poor. These
are examples of biased samples. Because they are not representative or unbiased,
you could not use these samples to draw conclusions about the population of all
heroin addicts. Far too often, mistakes occur because a sample was biased. One of
the biggest fiascoes in sampling history probably occurred in 1 936 when the Literary
Digest mailed over 10 million straw ballots to people's homes in order to predict the
winner of the presidential election that was to be held that year (Kimble, 1 978). The
results from this large sample were clear-cut: The next president would be Alf
Landon. What, you don't remember learning about President Landon? I'm sure that
you don't because Franklin Delano Roosevelt was elected president of the United
States that year. What went wrong? The problem was in how the Literary Digest
sampled voters. They mailed ballots to subscribers of their literary magazine, to
people listed in the phone book, and to automobile owners. Remember, this was
1936 and only the affluent belonged to the select group of people who subscribed to
literary magazines, or had phones, or owned automobiles. They failed to sample the
large number of poorer voters, many of whom voted for Roosevelt, not Landon. Be­
cause of biased sampling, they could not generalize their results to the voting pat­
terns of the population. Even though they sampled a large number of voters, the
results were wrong because they sampled in a biased way.
It is often not easy to recognize the profound effect that biased sampling can have
on the information that we receive. For example, phone-in polls are very popular,
probably because someone makes money from the phone calls. Suppose that a
phone-in poll shows that 75% of the people who responded to a question about the
death penalty were opposed to it. What can we conclude from this poll? Absolutely
nothing! Polls of this sort are called slops, which stands for selected listener opinion
polls and also describes their worth. Only people with extreme views on a topic will
take the time and expense to call in their opinions. Even though these polls are usu­
ally preceded with warnings like "this is a nonscientific survey," the announcer then
goes on to present meaningless results as though they could be used to gauge public
opinion.
Another pitfall in sampling is the possibility of confounding. Confounds confuse
the interpretation of results because their influence is not easily separated from the
influence of the independent variable. Because patients in these two hypothetical
heroin treatment programs differ systematically in more than one way-that is Pro­
gram 1 provides peer counseling and the addicts in this program are very wealthy,
whereas addicts in Program 2 get a different type of treatment and they are very
poor-we cannot determine if any differences in recovery rate are due to the type of
treatment or income levels of the patients. Because you can't separate the effect of
type of treatment and income, you could not use these results to decide which treat­
ment is more successful.
Usually, scientists use convenience samples. They study a group of people who
are readily available. The most frequently used subjects in psychology experiments
are college students and rats. The extent to which you can generalize from these sam­
ples depends on the research question. If you want to understand how the human vi­
sual system works, college students should be useful as subjects, especially if you
238 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

want to know about young, healthy eyes. If, on the other hand, you want to under­
stand sex-role stereotyping or career aspirations in adults, college students would
not be a representative sample because college students tend to be less stereotyped
and more career-focused than other adults. In this case, you could only generalize
about college students.
In a recent election in California, there was much debate over the issue of estab­
lishing a voucher system as a means of paying for K-12 education. As you may
know, some people believe that education would improve if parents received
vouchers in an amount that is equal to what the state pays to educate a child in the
public schools. The parents could then use this voucher to select any school that
they deemed best for their children. This is a complex issue as proponents argue
that the competition would improve all schools, and opponents argue that wealthy
parents would supplement the voucher and send their children to private schools,
whereas the poor parents would have to use the vouchers at cheaper and inferior
schools. I do not want to debate the issue of vouchers here, but I do want to repeat
an advertisement that was continually seen during the pre-election period. It went
something like this:

The public schools in California are doing a poor job at educating our children. Did you
know that the California high school students score much lower than high school students
from Mississippi on the college entrance examinations?

There are many ways the thinking in this advertisement could be criticized
(including the obvious slur on the state of Mississippi), but for the purpose of this
discussion consider only the nature of the samples that are being compared. Only
students who are planning on attending college take the college entrance examina­
tions. A much greater proportion of high school students in California take these ex­
aminations than those in Mississippi. Although I don't know what the actual figures
are, suppose that the top 40% of California high school graduates take these exams
but only the top 10% of Mississippi high school graduates take these exams. Can
you see why you would expect Mississippi students to score higher because of the
bias in sampling? There are other reasons why we might expect these results, which
do not relate to the quality of education. California has many recent immigrants,
which means many students whose English is not as good as that of native English
speakers. This fact would also lower statewide averages. Again, this is a sampling
problem because comparable groups that differ only on the variable of interest (state
in which education was obtained) are not being made. Of course, it is possible that
students in Mississippi are getting a better education than those in California, but
we cannot conclude this from these data.

sample Size

Given a thimbleful of facts, we rush to make generalizations as large as a tub.


-Gordon Allport (1 954, p. 8)
The number of subjects you include in your sample is called the sample size. Sup­
pose that treatment Program 1 has had six patient/subjects and Program 2 has had
10 patient/subjects. Both of these numbers are too small to determine the success
rate of the treatments. (A subject is a person or animal or entity who participates in
POPULATIONS AND SAMPLES 239

an experiment.) When scientists conduct experiments, they often use large numbers
of subjects because the larger the sample size, the more confident they can be in gen­
eralizing the findings to the population. This principle is called the law of large num­
bers, and it is an important statistical law. If, for some reason, they cannot use a large
number of subjects, they may need to be more cautious or conservative in the conclu­
sions that they derive from their research. Although a discussion of the number of
subjects needed in an experiment is beyond the scope of this book, it is important to
keep in mind that for most everyday purposes, we cannot generalize about a popula­
tion by observing how only a few people respond. Suppose this happened to you:

After months of deliberation over a new car purchase, you finally decided to buy a
Chevrolet Impala. You found that both Consumer Reports and Road and Track magazines gave
the Impala a good rating. It is priced within your budget, and you like its circular rear lights
and "sharp" appearance. On your way out the door to close the deal, you run into a close
friend and tell her about your intended purchase. "An Impala!" she shrieks. "My brother-in­
law bought one and it's a tin can. It's constantly breaking down on the freeway. He's had it
towed so often that the rear tires need replacing."
What do you do?

Most people would have a difficult time completing the purchase because they
are insufficiently sensitive to sample size issues. The national magazines presum­
ably tested many cars before they determined their rating. Your friend's brother-in­
law is a single subject. You should place greater confidence in results obtained with
large samples than in results obtained with small samples (assuming that the "ex­
periments" were equally good). Yet, many people find the testimonial of a single
person, especially if it's someone they know, more persuasive than information
gathered from a large sample, especially when there is preference for the results ob­
tained from the small sample (Klacznski, Gordon, & Fauth, 1 997; Wilson & Brekke,
1 994).
We tend to ignore the importance of having an adequately large sample size
when we function as intuitive scientists. This is why testimonials are so very power­
ful in persuading people what to do and believe. However, testimonials are based
on the experiences of only one person, and often that person is being paid to say that
some product or purchase is good. I have an advertisement for a psychic phone line
that offers "real cases" as proof that psychics are effective sources for advice on a va­
riety of problems: "A Lancing, Michigan resident winds up with a more positive
outlook in her life after one conversation . . . . And a women from Pittsburgh,
Pennsylvania feels as if the psychic has reached into her soul" (Cosmopolitan, Janu­
ary 1994). The reference to a particular, unnamed person along with the name of a
city and state makes these comments more personal and authentic-sounding. The
more specific the information we receive, the more likely we are to believe that it is
true. Give me a break!
I would like to dismiss testimonials and similar sorts of "evidence" as hogwash
that no one would fall for, but I know differently. A family member spent over $300
in calls to psychics when struggling with decisions regarding her critically ill hus­
band. This was money that she did not have for advice that was, at best, harmless,
and, at worst, caused her to ignore the recommendations of the hospital staff. I later
was told that psychics are not permitted to predict that anyone will die, so they gave
her false hope, which made the death even more difficult to bear. I am telling you
this true personal anecdote because I hope that it will be effective in causing you to
240 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

think about the sort of evidence that you would need to spend hundreds of dollars
for advice by a paid stranger who has no credentials or training in psychology or
science.

Variability

The term variability is used to denote the fact that all people are not the same.
Suppose that you know someone who "smoked like a haystack" and lived to be 100
years old. Does this mean that the hype about the negative effects of smoking on
health is wrong. Of course not! The effect of smoking on health was determined by
numerous separate investigators using large numbers of subjects. Not everyone re­
sponds in the same way, or maintains the same opinion, or has the same abilities. It
is important to remember the role of variability in understanding results. Our stud­
ies can tell us, with some probability, what is generally true, but there will be indi­
viduals who do not conform to the usual pattern. There are people who smoke
heavily and live to a ripe old age, but this does not mean that the studies that show
that smoking causes many terminal illnesses are wrong. It just means that people
are different.
Several years ago, there was much excitement over the use of laetrile, an extract
from apricot pits, as a cure for cancer. Although the U.S. medical establishment
found that it was worthless in the fight against cancer, many people continued to
believe that it could be used as a cure. Suppose you read about someone who was
diagnosed as having cancer, and this person then took laetrile. Later, this individual
recovered from her cancer. What can you conclude? Would you be willing to
conclude that, at least for some people, laetrile can cure or help to cure cancer? This
conclusion is unwarranted. Some people recover from cancer, whereas others do
not. Just as people are variable in the beliefs and attitudes that they maintain, they
are also variable in the way they respond to disease. With a sample size of one, we
cannot conclude that the laetrile contributed to her cure. Large-scale studies are
needed that compare the survival rates of groups of people on laetrile with groups
of people who used other forms of cancer treatments to decide if laetrile can be ben­
eficial in the treatment of cancer. When these tests were conducted by the U.s. gov­
ernment, laetrile was found to be worthless. It's easy to see how desperate cancer
patients can be misled into believing results obtained with a very small number of
people.
There are many examples where people generalize inappropriately from small
samples. In a recent, tragic example, the teenage son of a prominent politician in the
United States committed suicide after taking a commonly prescribed acne medica­
tion. The family was absolutely convinced that the suicide was a result of depres­
sion caused by the drug, and they began an active campaign to get the drug taken
off the market. In their view, their son had been a normal teen until he took the
medication, and soon after taking the medication, he committed suicide. Large-scale
studies did not support their belief that teens taking this drug were more likely to be
depressed or commit suicide than similar teens not taking this drug. However, for
the family of this teen, their own tragic experience was far more convincing than
data collected on thousands of teens.
People's willingness to believe that results obtained from a small sample can be
generalized to the entire population is called the law of small numbers (Tversky &
Kahneman, 1 971). In fact, we should be more confident when predicting to or from
SCIENCE VERSUS SCIENCE FICTION 24 1

large samples than small samples. In an experimental investigation of this phenom­


enon (Quattrone & Jones, 1 980), college students demonstrated their belief that if
one member of a group made a particular decision, then the other members of that
group would make the same decision. This result was especially strong when the
college students were observing the decisions of students from other colleges. Thus,
it is easy to see how a belief in the law of small numbers can maintain prejudices
and stereotypes. We tend to believe that the actions of a single group member are
indicative of the actions of the entire group. Have you ever heard someone say,
" 's (fill in your group) are all alike?" An acquaintance once told
me that all Jamaicans are sneaky thieves. She came to this conclusion after having
one bad experience with a person from Jamaica. Expressions like this one are mani­
festations of the law of small numbers. Can you see how the law of small numbers
can also explain the origin of many prejudices like racism? A single memorable
event involving a member of a group with which we have little contact can color our
beliefs about the other members of that group. Generally, when you collect observa­
tions about people and events, it is important to collect a large number of observa­
tions before you reach a conclusion.
There is one exception to the general principle that we need large samples in
order to make valid generalizations about a population. The one exception occurs
when everyone in the population is exactly the same. If, for example, everyone in
the population of interest responded exactly the same way to any question (e.g., Do
you approve of the death penalty?) or any treatment (e.g., had no "heart attacks"
when treated with a single aspirin), then sample size would no longer be an issue.
Of course, all people are not the same. You may be thinking that this was a fairly
dumb statement because everyone knows that people are different. Unfortunately,
research has shown that most of us tend to underestimate the variability of groups
with which we are unfamiliar.
Minorities who are members of any group often report that the leader or other
group members will turn to them and ask, "What do African Americans (or women
or Hispanics, or Asians, or whatever the minority is) think about this issue?" It's as
though the rest of the group believe that the few minority members of their group
can speak for the minority group as a whole. This is a manifestation of the belief that
groups other than the ones to which we belong are much more homogeneous (less
variable) than the groups to which we belong. The ability to make accurate predic­
tions depends, in part, on the ability to make accurate assessments of variability. It
is important to keep the concept of variability in mind whenever you are testing hy­
potheses either formally in a research setting or informally as you try to determine
relationships in everyday life.

SCIENCE VERSUS SCIENCE FICTION

Science is a method for understanding; it is a way of "knowing" about the world.


Data (or evidence) are at the heart of the scientific method but not just "any old"
data or evidence-data or evidence that were collected under controlled conditions,
data that can be openly scrutinized, and data that can be replicated. Consider, for
example, the hypothesis that there are psychics who can accurately predict future
events. What sort of data or evidence would convince you that at least some people
have psychic powers?
242 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTI:'IIG

Amazing and Not True

I have been told by believers in psychics that they have good data-a psychic made
amazingly true predictions about their life. Testimonials by one or even several peo­
ple are offered as evidence that psychics exist. Believers claim that they "know" psy­
chics have true powers because they "saw it with their own eyes." (If you have
already read Chapter 2 on memory, then you know that eye-witness testimony can
be highly inaccurate-an important fact, but not the main point in this discussion.) I
like to remind them that they also saw Mr. Ed, the talking horse who had his own
television show; do they believe that there are horses who can talk? (Actually, there
are people who believe in the existence of talking horses based on the Mr. Ed show;
Cole, 1995.)
I like to begin my college classes in critical thinking by demonstrating my own
amazing psychic powers. Each semester, before the start of the first class, I check my
class roster and then look up some of the students in the university records. The
records include date of birth and sometimes information about siblings (if they are
also students), so I can determine the astrological sign and some family information
for the students enrolled in my class. I then amaze students by asking a series of
questions that lead up to my ability to name students I have never met and tell them
their astrological sign and some family information. (Let's see-I am getting the
feeling that you are a Taurus. Your name-don't tell me-it's something like Jean or
Jane, no wait, it's Jackie, isn't it? I also see a family picture with a younger sister in it.
Is that correct? And her name is Latisha, right? And so on.) It is really an easy trick,
yet, students wonder how I was able to know so much about people I have never
met. The fact that I could tell students their name, astrological sign, and other infor­
mation might look like evidence in support of psychic phenomena, and without ap­
propriate controls, it is a very easy trick.

Cold Reading
There are many people who claim to be psychics or clairvoyants-some even
claim to be able to speak with the dead. I think we can all understand the pain of
grieving relatives, who really want to believe that they can talk to the dead. Tele­
vised shows have sometimes shown a portion of the seance or session with the
dead. Typically, viewers will see only a few minutes of a session that may last for
several hours-usually a portion where the psychic made a successful prediction
like, "the person you are trying to contact-is it a parent?" What we don't see is the
many instances where questions like this one are incorrect. The Australian Skeptics
Society offers a cash prize of $1 00,000 for a proven demonstration of psychic pow­
ers. No one has collected this prize. Ray Hyman, a psychologist who studies ways to
debunk psychics, explains how they "read" your mind, "speak with the dead," and
other similar shows. The technique is called "cold reading." The psychic relies on
body language, basic statistical information (e.g., common boys' names that start
with a known letter). He offers these 13 points for amazing your own friends with
cold reading (Hyman, http : //www.skeptics.com.au/journal!coldread.htm):

1. Look confident-act as though you believe in what you are doing.


2. Use polls, surveys, and statistical abstracts-predict attitudes from a person's
educational level and religion.
3. Stage the reading-make no excessive claims; be modest.
DETERMINING CAUSE 243

4. Gain the subject's cooperation-make the subject try to find truth in what
you say.
5. Use a gimmick-crystal balls and palm reading are good.
6. Have a list of stock phrases available-there are fortune-telling and other
manuals that have lots of good ones.
7. Use your eyes-observe clothing, jewelry, speech-these can be good hints.
8. Fish-get the subject to tell about him or herself.
9. Listen-subjects want to talk about themselves.
10. Be dramatic-ham it up for effect.
1 1 . Pretend to know more than you are saying-subject will assume you do.
12. Flatter the subject-people love flattery.
13. Always tell the subject what she or he wants to hear.

People who talk to the dead, read palms or tea leaves, and have visited beings
from other planets use similar methods when providing evidence of their unusual
abilities. Remember, just because it looks like someone has made a rabbit appear
from the inside of a hat does not mean that is what really happened. Magic tricks
and science fiction can be great fun, but they are not substitutes for critical thinking.
If there is only one goal that I could have for readers of this book, it is that you come
to value data and evidence for the purpose of making sound decisions. It may be the
most critical part of critical thinking.

DETERMINING CAUSE

Do you believe that children who are neglected become teenage delinquents?
Does jogging relieve depression?
Will a diet that is low in fat increase longevity?
Do clothes make the man?
Will strong spiritual beliefs give you peace of mind?
Does critical thinking instruction improve how you think outside the classroom?

All of these questions concern a causal relationship in which one variable (e.g., ne­
glect) is believed to cause another variable (e.g., delinquency). What sort of informa­
tion do we need to determine the truth of causal relationships?

Isolation and Control of Variables

Stop and think for a minute about the way you would go about deciding if neglect­
ing children causes them to become delinquent when they are teenagers. You could
decide to conduct a long-term study in which you would divide children into
groups-telling some of their parents to cater to their every need, others to neglect
them occasionally, and still others to neglect their children totally. You could re­
quire everyone to remain in their groups, catering to or neglecting their children as
instructed until the children reach their teen years, at which time you could count
up the number of children in each group who became delinquents. Remember, of
course, that you would have to define operationally the term "delinquent." This would
be a good, although totally unrealistic, way to decide if neglect causes delinquency.
244 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTI:'IJG

It's a good way because this method would allow you to control how much neglect
each child received and to isolate the cause of delinquency, as this would be the
only systematic difference among the people in each group. It's unrealistic to the
point of being ludicrous, because very few people would comply with your request
to cater to or neglect their children. Furthermore, it would also be unethical to ask
people to engage in potentially harmful behaviors.
In some experimental settings it is possible to isolate and control the variables
you're interested in. If you wanted to know if grading students for coursework will
make college students work harder and therefore learn more, you could randomly
assign college students to different grading conditions. Half the students could be
graded as pass or fail (no letter grades), whereas the other students would receive
traditional letter grades (A, B, C, D, or F). At the end of the semester, all students
would take the same final exam. If the average final exam score for the students who
received grades were statistically significantly higher than for the students in the
pass-fail condition, we'd conclude that grades do result in greater learning. (See
Chapter 7 on probability for a discussion of significant differences. )
Can you see why it's s o important t o be able to assign students a t random t o ei­
ther the graded or pass-fail conditions instead of just letting them pick the type of
grading they want? It is possible that the students who would pick the pass-fail
grading are less motivated or less intelligent than the students who would prefer to
get grades or vice versa. If the students could pick their own grading condition, we
wouldn't know if the differences we found were due to the differences in grading
practices or due to differences in motivation or intelligence, or some other variable
that differs systematically as a function of which grading condition the students se­
lect. If we cannot use random assignment, then we usually cannot make any causal
claims.
Let's return to the question of whether child neglect causes delinquency. Given
the constraint that you cannot tell parents to neglect their children, how would you
go about deciding if child neglect causes delinquency? You could decide to find a
group of parents and ask each about the amount of care he or she gives to each
child. Suppose you found that, in general, the more that children are neglected, the
more likely they are to become teenage delinquents. Because you lost control over
your variables by not assigning parents to catering and neglecting groups, it is not
possible, on the basis of this experiment alone, to conclude that neglect causes delin­
quency. It is possible that parents who neglect their children differ from caring par­
ents in other ways. Parents who tend to neglect their children may also encourage
drug use, or engage in other lifestyle activities that contribute to the development of
teenage delinquency. A point that is made in several places in this book is that just
because two variables occur together (neglect and delinquency), it doesn't necessar­
ily mean that one caused the other to occur.

Three-Stage Experimental Designs


When researchers want to be able to make strong causal claims, they use a three­
stage experimental design (Kimble, 1978). An experimental design is a plan for how
observations will be made:

1 . The first stage involves creating different groups that are going to be studied.
In the example about the effect of pass-fail grading on how much is learned,
the two groups would be those who receive a letter grade and those who
DETERMINING CAUSE 245

receive a grade of either "pass" or "fail." It is important that the two groups dif­
fer systematically only on this dimension. You wouldn't want all the students
in the letter grade group to take classes taught by Professor Longwinded
whereas those in the pass-fail group take classes taught by Professor Mumbles.
One professor may be a better teacher, and students may learn more in one con­
dition than the other because of this confounding variable. One way to avoid
this confound is to assign half of the students in each class to each grading con­
dition with the assignment of students to either group done at random. In this
example, the students in both conditions are the subjects. A subject is a person,
animal, or entity who serves as a participant in an experiment. Strong causal
claims will involve equating the groups at the outset of the experiment. The ran­
dom assignment of subjects to groups is essential in discovering cause and effect.
2. The second stage involves the application of the "experimental treatment." If
we were conducting a drug study, one group would receive the drug and the
other group would not receive the drug. Usually, the "nondrug" group would
receive a placebo, which would look and/ or taste like the drug, but would be
chemically inert. The reason to use a placebo is to avoid any effects of subjects'
beliefs or expectancies. (The topic of expectancies and the way they can bias
results is discussed later in this chapter.) As discussed in an earlier section,
when these sorts of controls were used to determine the effectiveness of
laetrile, it was found to be worthless against cancer. In the grading example,
the term "treatment" doesn't fit well, but it corresponds to taking the course
under the two different grading conditions.
3. Evaluation is the final phase. Measurements are taken and two (or more)
groups are compared on some outcome measure. In the grading example, final
examination scores for students in the letter grade group would be compared
to the scores for students in the pass-fail group. If students in one group per­
formed significantly better than the students in the other group, then we
would have strong support for the claim that one grading method caused stu­
dents to study harder and learn more than the other.

Of course, we are not always able to equate groups at the outset and randomly
assign subjects to groups, but when we can, results can be used to make stronger
causal claims than in less controlled conditions.
Consider this hypothetical example:

Researchers at Snooty University have studied the causes of divorce. They found that 33%
of recently divorced couples reported that they had serious disagreements over money
during the two-year period that preceded the divorce. The researchers concluded that dis­
agreements over money are a major reason why couples divorce. They go on to suggest that
couples should learn to handle money disagreements as a way of reducing the divorce rate.

What, if anything, is wrong with this "line of reasoning" ? Plenty. First, we have
no data from a comparison group that did not divorce (Le., no control group).
Maybe 33% of all families disagree about money; maybe the number is even higher
in families that stay together. Second, there is no reason to believe that disagree­
ments over money caused or even contributed to divorce. Maybe couples in the
process of breaking up disagree more about everything. Third, there is the problem
of retrospective review, a topic that is discussed in the next section. Studies like this
one are found everywhere from radio talk shows, news reports, scientific journals,
246 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTI�G

and people's casual examinations of life. If you rely on the principles of hypothesis
testing to interpret findings like this one, you are less likely to be bamboozled.

using the principles of Isolation and Control


In an earlier chapter, I presented Piaget's notion that people who have attained
the highest level of cognitive development can reason about hypothetical situations.
Piaget called the highest level of cognitive development the formal stage of thought.
He developed several different tasks that could be used to identify people who
could think at this level. If you already read Chapter 4, then you will recall the
"combinatorial reasoning" task devised by Piaget. It required a planful and orderly
procedure for combining objects. Another one of Piaget's tasks involved using the
principles of isolation and control that are integral to hypothesis testing. Try this task.

Bending Rods. This task is to determine which of several variables affects the
flexibility of rods. Imagine that you are given a long vertical bar with 12 rods hang­
ing from it. Each rod is made of either brass, copper, or steel. The rods come in two
lengths and two thicknesses. Your task is to find which of the variables (material,
length, or thickness) influence how much the rods will bend. You can test this by
pressing down on each rod to see how much it bends. You may perform as many
comparisons as you like until you can explain what factors are important in deter­

\
mining flexibility. It may help you to visualize the setup as presented in Fig. 6. 1 .

J
:$:>j�::::,:�:@:::::::&:M�::::::::::::::tf�:::�::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::r::::::::::::::::::::::::

( : :; ; : ,
� f-------J
!
. .:.:.:.:. .:. . . .:.:.:. .:. . . ... . ..... ............................ .

8 1---------,

is _••••••rI\
�iiiiiilii

FIG. 6. I . Bending rods. How would you determine whether material, length, or thickness
affects rod flexibility?
DETERMINING CAUSE 247

What do you need to do to prove that length, or diameter, or the material rods are
constructed from, or some combination of these variables is important in determin­
ing flexibility? Stop now and write out your answer to this problem. Don't go on
until you have finished this problem.

Solving the Task of Bending Rods. How did you go about exploring the effect
of length, diameter, and material on rod flexibility? In order to solve this problem,
you had to consider the possible factors that contribute to rod flexibility, and then
systematically hold constant all of the variables except one. This is a basic concept in
experimental methods. If you wanted to know if material was an important factor,
which rods would you test? You would bend a brass rod, a copper rod, and a steel
rod of the same length and diameter. This would hold constant the length and di­
ameter variables while testing the material variable. Some possible tests of this
would be to compare flexibility among the short and wide brass, copper, and steel
rods. Similarly, if you wanted to find out if length is important, you would bend a
short and a long rod of the same diameter that was constructed with the same mate­
rial. An example of this would be to compare the short and wide copper rod with
the long and wide copper rod.
How would you decide if diameter influences rod flexibility? By now it should be
clear that you would compare two rods of the same material and length and differ­
ent diameters. You could test this by bending a short and wide steel rod with a short
and thin steel rod. Thus, you should be able to recognize that the same principles
used in hypothesis testing were needed in this task and be able to apply them cor­
rectly in order to solve this seemingly unrelated problem.

prospective and Retrospective Research

Consider a medical example: Some health psychologists believe that certain stressful
experiences can cause people to develop cancer. If this were your hypothesis, how
would you determine its validity? One way would be to ask cancer patients if they
had anything particularly stressful happen to them just before they were diagnosed
as having cancer. If the stress caused the cancer, it would have to precede the devel­
opment of cancer. When experiments are conducted in this manner, they are called
retrospective experiments. Retrospective experiments look back in time to under­
stand causes for later events. There are many problems with this sort of research. As
discussed in Chapter 2 on memory, memories are selective and malleable. It is pos­
sible that knowledge of one's cancer will change how one's past is remembered.
Moderately stressful events like receiving a poor grade in a college course may be
remembered as being traumatic. Happier events, like getting a raise, may be forgot­
ten. It's even possible that the early stages of the cancer were causing stress instead
of the stress causing the cancer. Thus, it will be difficult to determine if stress causes
cancer from retrospective research.
A better method for understanding causative relationships is prospective re­
search. In prospective research, you identify possible causative factors when they
occur and then look forward in time to see if the hypothesized result occurs. In a
prospective study, you would have many people record stressful life events when
they occur (e.g., death of a spouse, imprisonment, loss of a job) and then see which
people develop cancer. If the people who experience more stressful events are more
likely to develop cancer, this result would provide support for your hypothesis.
248 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

Most of the research we conduct as intuitive scientists is retrospective. We often


seek explanations for events after they have occurred. How many times have you
tried to understand why a seemingly angelic child committed a serious crime, or
why a star rookie seems to be losing his touch, or why the underdog in a political
race won? Our retrospective attempts at explanations are biased by selective memo­
ries and lack of systematic observations. (See the section on hindsight in Chapter 8
on decision making skills for a related discussion.)

Correlation and Cause

The process by which children turn experience into knowledge is exactly the
same, point for point, as the process by which those whom we call scientists
make scientific knowledge.
-Holt (1989, p. 93)

What you are about to read is absolutely true: As the weight of children increases, so
does the number of items that they are likely to get correct on standardized tests of in­
telligence. In other words, heavier children answer more questions correctly than
lighter ones. Before you start stuffing mashed potatoes into your children in an at­
tempt to make them smarter, stop and think about what this means. Does it mean that
gaining weight will make children smarter? Certainly not! Children get heavier as
they get older, and older children answer more questions correctly than younger ones.
In this example, the variables' weight and number of questions answered cor­
rectly are related. An increase in one variable is associated with an increase in the
other variable-as weight increases the number of questions answered correctly
concomitantly (at the same time also) increases. Correlated variables are two or
more variables that are related. If you've already read Chapter 5, "Analyzing Argu­
ments," then you should recognize this concept as the fallacy of false cause.
People frequently confuse correlation with causation. Consider the following ex­
ample: Wally and Bob were arguing about the inheritance of intelligence. Wally
thought about everyone he knew and concluded that because smart parents tend to
have smart children, and dumb parents tend to have dumb children, intelligence is
an inherited characteristic. Bob disagreed with Wally's line of reasoning, although
he concurred with the facts that Wally presented. He agreed that if the parents score
high on intelligence tests, then their children will also tend to score high, and if the
parents score low on intelligence tests, then their children will also tend to score
low. When two measures are related in this way-that is, they tend to rise and fall
together-they have a positive correlation. Although parents' intelligence and their
children's intelligence are positively correlated, we cannot infer that parents caused
their children (through inheritance or any other means) to be intelligent. It is possi­
ble that children affect the intelligence of their parents, or that both are being
affected by a third variable that hasn't been considered. It is possible that diet, eco­
nomic class, or other lifestyle variables determine intelligence levels, and because
parents and children eat similar diets and have the same economic class, they tend
to be similar in intelligence. In understanding the relationship between two corre­
lated variables, it is possible that variable A caused the changes in variable B (A �
B), or that variable B caused the changes in variable A (B � A), or both A and B
caused changes in each other (A � B and B � A) or that both were caused by a
third variable C (C � A and C � B).
DETERMINING CAUSE 249

Let's consider a different example. Many people have taken up jogging in the
belief that it will help them to lose weight. The two variables in this example are ex­
ercise and weight. I've heard people argue that because there are no fat athletes (ex­
cept perhaps sumo wrestlers), exercise must cause people to be thin. I hope that you
can think critically about this claim. It does seem to be true that exercise and weight
are correlated. People who tend to exercise a great deal also tend to be thin. This sort
of correlation, in which the tendency to be high on one variable (exercise) is associ­
ated with the tendency to be low on the other variable (weight), is called a negative
correlation. Let's think about the relationship between exercise and weight. There
are several possibilities: (a) It is possible that exercise causes people to be thin; or
(b) It is possible that people who are thin tend to exercise more because it is more
enjoyable to engage in exercise when you are thin; or (c) It is possible that a third
variable, like concern for one's health, or some inherited trait, is responsible for both
the tendency to exercise and the tendency to be thin. Perhaps there are inherited
body types that naturally stay thin and also are graced with strong muscles that are
well suited for exercise.
If you wanted to test the hypothesis that exercise causes people to lose weight,
then you would use the three design stages described earlier. If the subjects who
were assigned at random to the exercise group were thinner after the treatment pe­
riod than those in a no-exercise condition, then you could make a strong causal
claim for the benefits of exercise in controlling weight.
Actually, the question of causation is usually complex. It is probably more accu­
rate to use the word influence instead of cause because there is usually more than a
single variable that affects another variable. A colleague suggested the following ex­
ample to clarify this point (Dr. Richard Block at Montana State University): When a
man is being hanged for having committed a crime, is it because someone gave him
money to buy the weapon he used in the crime, or is it because someone saw him
commit the crime, or is it because no one stopped him?

Illusory Correlation. An amusing anecdote of attributing cause to events that


occur together was presented by Munson (1976):

A farmer was traveling with his wife on a train when he saw a man across the aisle take
something out of a bag and begin eating it. "Say, Mister," he asked, "What's that thing you're
eating?"
"It's a banana," the man said, "Here, try one."
The farmer took it, peeled it, and just as he swallowed the first bite, the train roared into a
tunnel. "Don't eat any, Maude," he yelled to his wife. "It'll make you go blind!" (p. 277)

Do blondes really have more fun? A popular advertisement for hair dye would
like you to believe that having blonde hair will cause you to have more fun. Many
people believe that they see many blondes having fun; therefore, blondes have more
fun than brunettes and redheads. The problem with this sort of observation is that
there are many blondes who are not having "more fun" (a term badly in need of an
operational definition) than brunettes, but because they are at home or in other
places where you are unlikely to see them, they don't get considered. The term illu­
sory correlation refers to the erroneous belief that two variables are related when, in
fact, they are not (Chapman & Chapman, 1 967, 1969). Professionals and nonprofes­
sionals alike maintain beliefs about relationships in the world. These beliefs guide
the kinds of observations we make and how we determine if a relationship exists be­
tween two variables.
250 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

Let's try another example. Do you believe that you often see fat people overeat­
ing? Most people believe that they do; yet, research has shown that overweight
adults tend to eat less in public places than normal-weight people. We expect to see
overweight people overeating; and therefore, we believe that they do. Beware of il­
lusory correlations when you play the role of an intuitive scientist. This phenome­
non works to maintain stereotypes (e.g., redheads are hot-tempered, Scots are
cheap, women can't understand math, etc.). Our beliefs about relationships between
variables guide the observations we make and the way we utilize this information to
formulate conclusions, many of which are incorrect.

Validity

The validity of a measure is usually defined as the extent to which it measures what
you want it to measure. If I wanted to measure intelligence and measured the length of
your big toe, this would obviously be invalid. Other examples of validity are less obvi­
ous. A popular radio commercial, touting the benefits of soup, points out that tomato
soup has more vitamin A than eggs. This is true, but it is not a valid measure of the
goodness of tomato soup. Eggs are not a good source of vitamin A. Thus, the wrong
comparisons were made, and the measure does not support the notion that soup is an
excellent food. If you've already read Chapter 5 on analyzing arguments, then you
should realize that the claim that tomato soup has more vitamin A than eggs does not
support the conclusion that "soup is good food." It may well be true that soup is an ex­
cellent source of vitamins, but claims like this one don't support that conclusion.
How would you react to this claim, "The Baroness is a sleek new luxury car that
will provide its owner with dependable transportation for many years to come. In
fact, in a recent laboratory test, the Baroness went from zero to 60 miles per hour in
7 seconds flat, beating out the six other cars in the competition." Is the acceleration
speed of a car a valid index of its dependability? Probably not. Even if the figure is
accurate, it is not a valid measure of dependability. If you want to know about de­
pendability, you'll want to know about the frequency of repairs, average number of
miles you could expect to drive the car before it gets turned into scrap metal, and
how it performs in collisions.

convergent Validity
When several different measures all converge onto the same conclusion, the mea­
sures are said to have convergent validity. If, for example, you wanted to measure
charisma-the psychological trait that is something more than charm that people as
diverse as Jodie Foster, Bill Cosby, and Lucy Liu are said to possess, you'd need con­
vergent validity for your measure. People who scored high on your charisma test
should also be the ones who are selected for leadership positions and have other
personality traits that are usually associated with charisma. If the class wallflower
scored high on your test of charisma, you'd need to rethink the validity of your test.
Intuitive scientists also need to be mindful of the need for convergent validity.
Before you decide that your classmate, Willa Mae, is shy because she hesitates to
talk to you, you need to determine if she acts shy with other people in other places.
If she frequently speaks up in class, you wouldn't want to conclude that she is a shy
person because this inconsistency in her behavior would signal a lack of convergent
validity. The idea of convergent validity is very similar to the topic of convergent
DETERMINING CAUSE 25 1

argument structures that was presented in the previous chapter. If you have already
read Chapter 5 on analyzing arguments, then you should recall that the strength of
an argument is increased when many premises support (or converge on) a conclu­
sion. This is exactly the same situation as when several sources of evidence support
the same hypothesis. The language used in these two chapters is different (support
for a conclusion versus support for a hypothesis), but the underlying ideas are the
same: The more reasons or evidence we can provide for believing that something is
true, the greater the confidence we can have in our belief.

Illusory validity
Everyone complains of his memory and no one complains of his judgment.
-La Rochefoucauld (1613-1 680)

Both professionals and nonprofessionals place great confidence in their conclu­


sions about most life events, even when their confidence is objectively unwarranted.
Overconfidence in judgments is called illusory validity. In an experimental investi­
gation of this phenomenon, Oskamp (1965) found that as clinicians were given more
information about patients, they became more confident in the judgments they
made about patients. What is interesting about this result is that they were not more
accurate in judgment, only more confident that they were right. Why do people place
confidence in fallible judgments? There are several reasons why we persist in main­
taining confidence in our judgments. A primary factor is the selective nature of mem­
ory. Consider this personal vignette: As a child, I would watch Philadelphia Phillies
baseball games on television with my father. As each batter would step up to home
plate, my father would excitedly yell, "He's going to hit a home run, I just know it!"
Of course, he was usually wrong. (Phillies fans had to be tough in the 50s and 60s.) On
the rare occasions when a Phillies batter actually did hit a home run, my father would
talk about it for weeks. "Yep, I knew as soon as he stepped up to home plate that he
would hit a home run. I can always tell just by looking at the batter." In this instance,
and countless others, we selectively remember our successful judgments and forget
our unsuccessful ones. This tends to bolster confidence in the judgments we make.
A second reason for the illusion of validity is the failure to seek or consider dis­
confirming evidence. (See Chapter 8 on decision making for an additional discus­
sion of this phenomenon.) This is the primary reason why people tend to believe
that variables are correlated when they are not. Suppose that you have the job of
personnel officer in a large corporation. Over a period of a year, you hire one hun­
dred new employees for your corporation. How would you go about deciding if
you're making good (valid) hiring decisions? Most people would check on the per­
formance of the one hundred new employees. Suppose that you did this and found
that 92% of the new employees were performing their jobs in a competent, profes­
sional manner. Would this bolster your confidence in your judgments? If you an­
swered yes to this question, you forgot to consider disconfirming evidence. What
about the people you didn't hire? Have most of them gone on to become vice presi­
dents at General Motors? If you found that 1 00% of the people you didn't hire are
superior employees at your competitor's corporation, you would have to revise
your confidence in your judgmental ability.
Part of the reason that we fail to utilize disconfirming evidence is that it is often
not available. Personnel officers don't have information about the employees they
don't hire. Similarly, we don't know much about the person we chose not to date, or
252 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

the course we didn't take, or the house we didn't buy. Thus, on the basis of partial in­
formation, we may conclude that our judgments are better than they objectively are.
In a scathing review of the Rorschach test, the test that is commonly known as the
inkblot test because subjects are asked to tell what they see in amorphous, symmet­
rical blots of ink, Dawes (1994) concluded that it is not a valid measure of mental
functioning. A recent review of projective tests arrived at the same conclusion
(Lilienfeld, Wood, & Garb, 2000). That is, there is no evidence that it is useful in di­
agnosing or treating mental disorders (although it is possible to determine if some­
one gives unusual answers). This means that the Rorschach has no validity. Despite
these empirical results, Dawes reports that some psychotherapists respond to this
fact with, "Yes, I know that it has no validity, but I find it useful." Do you see why
this is a ridiculous statement? If it has no validity, then it cannot be useful. If thera­
pists believe that it is useful, they are fooling themselves and demonstrating the
phenomenon of illusory validity. It may seem useful because they interpret the re­
sponses in ways that they believe make sense, but its only real value is as a clear
demonstration of the biases that we maintain.
Why do some psychologists continue to use projective tests when many reviews
of the literature show that these tests are not valid? Most psychologists genuinely
want to do a good job and many believe that the tests are valid despite the lack of
data to support that conclusion. They believe these tests are valid because they "feel
or look right"-the results confirm what they believe to be true. Few people will cast
aside their own sense of what is true for a mass of cold and impersonal data col­
lected by and from people they don't know. In general, the scientific method is not
valued when it conflicts with our personal belief system. Humans are ill-equipped
to use data from large samples, perhaps because the only information that was
available to us for most of the history of humankind came from personal experience
or the second-hand personal experience of those we know. It is important that we
use critical thinking skills for conclusions that we like and don't like.

Fl�li(ll>ilit)T

Both law and science must weigh the reliability of evidence, the trustworthiness
of experts, and the probability that something is true beyond a reasonable doubt.
-K. C. Cole (1995)
The reliability of a measure is the consistency with which it measures what it's sup­
posed to measure. If you used a rubber ruler that could stretch or shrink to measure
the top of your desk, you'd probably get a different number each time you mea­
sured it. Of course, we want our measurements to be reliable.
Researchers in the social and physical sciences devote a great deal of time to the
issue of reliable measurement. We say that an intelligence test, for example, is
reliable when the same person obtains scores that are in the same general range
whenever she takes the test. Few of us even consider reliability when we function as
intuitive scientists. When we decide if a professor or student is prejudiced, we often
rely on one or two samples of behavior without considering if the individual is
being assessed reliably.
Suppose that you learn that your friend Ricardo failed a college course, which all
others easily passed. Could you conclude that his teacher is prejudiced? You'd need
to collect many other observations of the same teacher to see how consistently or
THINKING ABOUT ERRORS 253

reliably Hispanic males failed his class. If there were an unusually high failure rate
among Hispanic males (or whatever group you're interested in) in his class com­
pared to their failure rate in other classes, then you'd have a strong case for the in­
ference that the teacher is prejudiced. Without careful measurement and, in this
case, a larger sample size, you cannot infer that the professor is prejudiced.

THINKING ABOUT ERRORS

To a scientist a theory is something to be tested. He seeks not to defend his


beliefs, but to improve them. He is, above everything else, an expert at
"changing his mind."
-Wendell Johnson (1946)

When we try to understand relationships by devising and testing hypotheses, we


will sometimes be wrong. This idea is expanded on more fully in the next chapter,
which concerns understanding probabilities. For now, consider this possibility: Sup­
pose that you drive into work every day with a friend. Every morning you stop at a
drive-up restaurant window and buy coffee. You decide that instead of hassling
every morning with who will pay ("I'll get it"-"No, no let me"), he will flip a coin.
When the outcome is heads, he will pay; when the outcome is tails, you will pay.
Sounds fair enough, but on nine of the last ten days the coin landed with tails up.
Do you think that your friend is cheating?
The truth is that your friend is either cheating or he is not cheating. Unfortunately,
you don't know which is true. Nevertheless, you need to make a decision. You will de­
cide either that he is cheating or he is not cheating. Thus, there are four possibilities: (a)
He is cheating and you correctly decide that he is cheating; (b) He is not cheating and
you correctly decide that he is not cheating; (c) He is cheating and you incorrectly de­
cide that he is not cheating; and (d) He is not cheating and you incorrectly decide that
he is cheating. With these four possibilities, there are two ways that you can be right
and two ways that you can be wrong. These four combinations are shown in Table 6.1.
As you can see from Table 6.1, there are two different ways that we can make er­
rors in any hypothesis-testing situation. These two different errors are not equally
"bad." It is far worse to decide that your friend is cheating when he is not (especially
if you accuse him of cheating) than it is to decide that he is not cheating when he is.

TABLE 6. 1
Four Possible Outcomes for the "Who Buys the Coffee" Example

You Decide
He is cheating He is not cheating
The Truth is: He is cheating. He is cheating and you He is cheating and you decide
decide that he is cheating. that he is not cheating. An
Correct Decision! Error!
He is not cheating. He is not cheating and you He is not cheating and you
decide that he is cheating. decide that he is not cheating.
A Serious Error! Correct Decision!
Note. The error associated with deciding that he is cheating is more serious than the error associated
with deciding that he is not cheating. Because of the difference in the severity of the errors, you will want
to be more certain when deciding that he is cheating than when deciding that he is not cheating.
254 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

Thus, you would want stronger evidence to decide that he is cheating than you
would want to decide that he is not cheating. In other words, you need to consider
the relative "badness" of different errors when testing hypotheses.
If you take a course in statistics or experimental design, you'll find that the idea of
error ''badness'' is handled by requiring different levels of confidence for different
decisions. The need to consider different types of errors is found in many contexts. A
basic principle of our legal system is that we have to be very certain that someone
has committed a crime (beyond a reasonable doubt) before we can convict her. By
contrast, we don't have to be convinced beyond a reasonable doubt that she is inno­
cent because wrongly deciding that someone is innocent is considered a less severe
error than wrongly deciding that someone is guilty. Similarly, when you are testing
hypotheses informally, you also need to be aware of the severity of different types of
errors. Before you decide, for example, that no matter how hard you study, you'll
never pass some course or that the medicine you're taking is or isn't making you bet­
ter, you need to consider the consequences of right and wrong decisions. Some deci­
sions require that you should be more certain about being correct than others.

Experience Is an Expensive Teacher

Suppose that your friend shares her "secret" for curing a cold-she rubs her stom­
ach with garlic and the symptoms of the cold go away. You are dubious, but she
persists, "I know it works. I've tried it, and I have seen it work with my own eyes." I
am certain that there are many people who would respond to this testimonial by
rubbing garlic over their stomach, just as there are many people who willingly swal­
low capsules filled with ground rhinoceros penis to increase their sexual potency,
megavitamins to feel less tired, and ginseng root for whatever ails them. You may
even join the ranks of those who tout these solutions because sometimes your cold
will get better after rubbing yourself with garlic-sometimes a desired effect follows
some action (like taking capsules of ground rhinoceros penis). But, did the action
cause the effect that followed it? This question can only be answered using the prin­
ciples of hypothesis testing. Personal experience cannot provide the answer.
Dawes (1994) corrected the famous expression that we attribute to Benjamin
Franklin. It seems that Franklin did not say that "experience is the best teacher," in­
stead he said "experience is a dear teacher," with the word dear meaning expensive or
costly. Sometimes, we are able to use systematic feedback about what works and
what doesn't work so that we can use our experience to improve at some task, but it is
also possible to do the same thing over and over without learning from experience.
We are far better off using information that is generated by many people to determine
causal relationships than to rely on personal experience with all of its biases and costs.

SELF-FULFILLING PROPHECIES

Science is not simply a collection of facts; it is a discipline of thinking about


rational solutions to problems after establishing the basic facts derived from
observations. It is hypothesizing from what is known to what might be, and then
attempting to test the hypotheses.
-Rosalyn S. Yalow
(distinguished professor, City University of New York, 1 988)
SELF-FULFILLING PROPHECIES 255

In a classic set of experiments, Robert Rosenthal, a well-known psychologist, and


his colleague (Rosenthal & Fode, 1963) had their students train rats to run through
mazes as part of a standard course in experimental psychology. Half of the students
were told that they had rats that had been specially bred to be smart at learning
their way through mazes, whereas the other half of the students were told that they
had rats that had been specially bred to be dumb at this task. As you probably ex­
pected, the students with the bright rats had them outperforming the dull rats in a
short period of time. These results are especially interesting because there were no
real differences between the two groups of rats. Rosenthal and Fode had lied about
the rats being specially bred. All of the rats were the usual laboratory variety. They
had been assigned at random to either group. If there were no real differences be­
tween the groups of rats, how do we explain the fact that students who believed they
had been given bright rats had them learn the maze faster than the other group?
The term "self-fulfilling prophecies" has been coined as a label for the tendency
to act in ways that will lead us to find what we expected to find. I don't know what
the students did to make the rats learn faster in the "bright" group or slower in the
"dull" group. Perhaps the bright group was given extra handling or more food in
the goal box. (When rats learn to run through mazes, they are rewarded with food
when they reach the goal box.) Maybe the students given the "dull" rats dropped
them harshly into the maze or were not as accurate in the records that they kept.
Whatever they did, they somehow influenced their experimental results, so that the
results were in accord with their expectations.
If self-fulfilling prophecies can influence how rats run through mazes, what sort
of an effect will it have on everyday thinking and behavior? Earlier in this chapter,
illusory correlations were discussed as the tendency to believe that events that you
are observing are really correlated because you believe that they should be. Psychol­
ogists are becoming increasingly aware of the ways that personal convictions direct
our selection and interpretation of facts. When you function as an intuitive scientist,
it is important to keep in mind the ways we influence the results we obtain.
One way to eliminate the effects of self-fulfilling prophecies is with double-blind
procedures. Let's consider a medical example. There are probably 1 00 home remedies
for the common cold. How should we decide which, if any, actually relieve cold
symptoms? Probably, somewhere, sometime, someone gave you chicken soup when
you had a cold. Undoubtedly, you got better. Almost everyone who gets a cold gets
better. The question is, "Did the chicken soup make you better?" This is a difficult
question to answer because if you believe that chicken soup makes you better, you
may rate the severity of your symptoms as less severe even when there was no real
change. This is just another example of self-fulfilling prophecies. The only way to test
this hypothesis is to give some people chicken soup and others something that looks
and tastes like chicken soup and then have each group rate the severity of their cold
symptoms. In this example all of the subjects are unaware or blind to the nature of the
treatment they are receiving. It is important that the experimenters also be unaware of
which subjects received the "real" chicken soup so that they don't inadvertently give
subtle clues to the subjects. Experiments in which neither the subjects nor the experi­
menters know who is receiving the treatment are called double-blind experiments.
Although the chicken soup example may seem a little far-fetched, the need for
double-blind procedures is critical in deciding whether any drug or treatment is
working. Formal laboratory research on drugs that may be effective against AIDS or
cancer always use double-blind procedures. Most people, however, do not apply
these same standards when making personal decisions such as which type of
256 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

psychotherapy is effective or whether massive doses of a vitamin or advice from a


palm reader will improve some aspect of their life. Before you decide to see a thera­
pist who claims to be able to improve your diabetes by manipulating your spine or
to engage in screaming therapy to improve your self-confidence, look carefully for
double-blind studies that support the use of the proposed therapy.

Making Sense Out of the World

Psychologists have been making the case for the 'nothing special' view of
scientific thinking for many years.
-David Klahr and Herbert Simon (2001, p. 76)

As humans, we have a great need to explain-to see patterns in the dizzying array
of life events and to be able to predict and prevent bad outcomes. In a study of how
jurors reason, psychologists found that jurors would weave the events that were re­
counted during the trial into a plausible story and would then review information to
see if it would fit with the story they constructed (Hastie & Dawes, 2001; Hastie &
Pennington, 2000). Psychologists who study how jurors reason have found that ju­
rors do not rely as much on evidence as the legal system instructs them to. Instead,
they interpret proceedings by determining how well the information that is pre­
sented can be incorporated into a meaningful story that they constructed from the
information presented during the trial. All knowledge can be thought of as a con­
struction of the knower. Thus, this process is no different from any other ordinary
cognitive process. To become better thinkers, we all need to consciously and consci­
entiously apply the skills used in hypothesis testing by carefully considering evi­
dence, especially evidence that would disconfirm the narrative explanations that we
rely on to make sense out of a vast array of information.

OCCULT BELIEFS AND THE PARANORMAL

Media distortions, social uncertainty, and deficiencies of human reasoning seem


to be at the basis of occult beliefs.
-Barry Singer and Victor Benassi (1981, p. 49)

Do you believe in "channeling, clairvoyance, precognition, telepathy, psychic


surgery, psychic healing, healing crystals, psychokinesis, astral travel, levitation, the
Bermuda triangle mystery, unidentified flying objects (UFOs), plant consciousness,
auras, [or] ghosts" (Gray, 1 991, p. ix)? If you answered "yes" to any of these, you are
not alone. A recent Gallup Poll showed that the proportion of the general popula­
tion in the United States who believe in psychic and paranormal phenomena has in­
creased over the last decade (The Gallup Organization, 2001 ). Belief in haunted
houses, ghosts, witches, communicating with someone who has died, psychic heal­
ing, that extraterrestrial beings have visited the earth, and clairvoyance has each in­
creased by over 5% in the last decade. One possible explanation is the increase in the
number of television shows about these topics, some of which have an almost
"newslike" appearance to them, including highly popular shows like X Files that
carry the message that beings from outer space are living among us (Gibson, 2000).
THINKING AS AN INTUITIVE SCIENTIST 257

Often these shows are narrated by people who appear to be honest and sincere. Few
people remember the difference between actors and scientists when the actors pro­
vide a good imitation of something that looks like science.
How can we understand these beliefs when there is no good evidence that they
have any basis in fact (Shermer, 1 992; Stanovich, 1999)? In our attempt to make
sense out of events in the world, we all seek to impose a meaningful explanation, es­
pecially for unusual events. Have you thought about a friend whom you haven't
seen in many years and then received a phone call from him? Did you ever change
your usual route home from school or work and then learn that there was a tragic
accident that you probably would have been in if you had not changed your route?
What about stories of people who recover from a deadly disease after they use im­
agery as a means of healing? We are all fascinated by these unusual events and try
to understand them. Can you understand how small sample sizes (usually a single
example), retrospective review (in hindsight we seek explanations that are available
in memory), illusory correlations, self-fulfilling prophecies, difficulty in understand­
ing probabilities, and other cognitive biases contribute to the popularity of paranor­
mal beliefs? It is a fact that there is no positive evidence whatsoever for the existence
of any psychic abilities. No one has collected the million-dollar prize offered by the
James Randi Foundation for credible evidence of psychic or other paranormal phe­
nomena. There are many anecdotes, but there has never been a statistically signifi­
cant finding of psychic power that has been duplicated in another independent lab­
oratory. "Anecdotes do not make a science" (Shermer, 1992, p. 19).
There are many real mysteries in the world and much that we don't understand.
It is possible that someone has found a strange herbal cure for cancer, or that the
lines on the palms of our hand or pattern of tea leaves in our tea cups are indicators
of important life events, but if these are "real" phenomena, then they will hold up
under the bright lights of double-blind, controlled laboratory testing. We can all
laugh at the predictions made by various "psychics" such as the prediction that
Fidel Castro would move to Beverly Hills after his government was overthrown and
the many predictions about Princess Diana that included almost everything imagin­
able except her tragic death (Emery, 2001). We need to become much more skeptical
when a friend tells us that crystals have healing powers or vitamin E can be used to
revive those who have recently died. This topic is also addressed in the next chapter
where I discuss how to reason with probabilities.

THINKING AS AN INTUITIVE SCIENTIST

Most people seem to believe that there is a difference between scientific thinking
and everyday thinking . . . . But, the fact is, these same scientific thinking skills
can be used to improve the chances of success in virtually any endeavor.
-George (Pinky) Nelson (1998)

One theme throughout this chapter is that everyday thinking has much in common
with the research methods used by scientists when they investigate phenomena in
their academic domains. Many of the pitfalls and problems that plague scientific in­
vestigations are also common in everyday thought. If you understand and avoid
some of these problems, you will be a better consumer of research and a better intu­
itive scientist.
258 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

When you are evaluating the research claims of others or when you are asserting
your own claims, there are several questions to keep in mind:

1 . What was the nature of the sample? Was it large enough? Was it biased?
2. Are the variables operationally defined? What do the terms mean?
3. Were the measurements sensitive, valid, and reliable? Are the appropriate
comparisons being made to support the claims?
4. Were extraneous variables controlled? What are other plausible explanations
for the results?
5. Do the conclusions follow from the observations?
6. Are correlations being used to support causative arguments?
7. Is disconfirming evidence being considered?
8. How could the experimenter's expectancies be biasing the result?

Let's apply these guidelines to the choice of treatment programs that was pre­
sented at the opening of this chapter-the scenario presented you, as a heroin ad­
dict, with two choices of treatment programs. The first program is run by former
heroin addicts and the second is run by therapists. First, what is the evidence for
success rates? Although Program 1 cites a much higher success rate than Program 2,
these numbers cannot be used to compare the two programs because Program 1
gives the success for those who stayed with the program at least one year, and we
have no information about how many dropped out before achieving the one-year
mark. Thus, the success rate for Program 1 is not a valid measure of success. We also
have no information about how likely someone is to maintain recovery without
treatment. In other words, there is no control group against which to measure the ef­
ficacy of treatment. Unfortunately, there is no information about the sample size be­
cause we are not told how many patients entered each program. If this were a real
decision, then you would ask for this information. So far, there is little to go on.
I have found that most people like the idea that the therapist is a recovered addict
who "has been there himself." The problem with this sort of qualification is that his
anecdotes about "what worked for him" may be totally worthless. Dawes (1 994) is
highly critical of the sort of reasoning that leads people to believe that a former ad­
dict is a good choice for a counselor. As Dawes notes, the thinking that goes into this
evaluation is something like this:

The therapist was an addict.


He did X and recovered.
If I do X, then I will also recover.

I hope that you can see that this is very weak evidence. If you have already read
Chapter 4 on reasoning, then you will recognize this as a categorical syllogism-one
that is invalid. You have a single individual (sample size of one), all the biases of
memory, no independent verification that X is useful, the problem of illusory corre­
lation, and more. Of course, this individual could be an excellent therapist, but with
the information that you are given, there is no reason to expect it. On the other
hand, the therapist who has studied the psychology and biology of addiction should
know about different treatment options, theories of addiction, and most importantly
the success rates for a variety of different types of treatments based on results from
large samples of addicts. This is an important point. Try posing the question that
I used at the opening of this chapter to friends and relatives. You will probably find
the bias toward selecting the recovered addict as a therapist.
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 259

If you scrutinize your own conclusions and those of others with the principles of
hypothesis testing in mind, you should be able to defend yourself against invalid
claims and improve your own ability to draw sound conclusions from observations.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

In applying the general thinking skills framework to thinking as hypothesis testing,


consider the following questions:

1 . What Is the Goal?

You should use the skills developed in this chapter whenever you are devising
hypotheses about the relationships among events and then collecting observations
to test the validity of your hypotheses. There is a virtually endless number of exam­
ples when these skills are applicable. They should be used when considering social
relationships (e.g., She likes it when I compliment her), physical relationships (e.g.,
The mercury in the tube rises when the temperature increases), treatment effects
(e.g., Laughter therapy can improve the recovery rate from some dread diseases),
and when functioning as a consumer of research.

2 . What Is Known?

This question is about how to plan the thinking process. When thinking like an
intuitive scientist, you need to begin by explicitly deciding on the nature of the hy­
pothesis that you're testing and the way you will go about making or thinking about
observations. You also need to consider the relative severity of different kinds of er­
rors. The knowns include how you will operationalize your variables and how con­
fident you want to be before you decide if your hypothesis is correct. In short, this
step involves becoming explicit about your starting point in the thinking process.
One of the most important pieces of information in determining cause is whether
the subjects were assigned at random to different "treatment" groups. If not, it is ex­
tremely difficult to make valid causal claims.

3. Which Thinking Skill or Skills


Will Get You to Your Goal?
The selection of the appropriate skill depends on how you've answered the previ­
ous questions. If you've decided that the hypothesis that you're testing is important
enough to require a formal test, then you'll want to sample subjects in an unbiased
manner and be certain that the number of subjects is sufficiently large and that mea­
surement was accurate. Of course, I don't expect you to be testing lethal drugs based
on the hypothesis-testing skills presented in this chapter. This sort of testing needs
to be conducted by researchers with extensive knowledge of research and experi­
mental design. However, you should know how to be a consumer of this sort of re­
search and look for evidence of good hypothesis-testing methods.
The skills involved when thinking as an intuitive scientist include:

• Recognizing the need for and using operational definitions.


• Understanding the need to isolate and control variables in order to make
strong causal claims.
260 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTING

• Checking for adequate sample size and unbiased sampling when a generaliza­
tion is made.
• Being able to describe the relationship between any two variables as positive,
negative, or unrelated.
• Understanding the limits of correlational reasoning.
• Seeking converging validity to increase your confidence in a decision.
• Checking for and understanding the need for control groups.
• Being aware of the bias in most estimates of variability.
• Considering the relative "badness" of different sorts of errors.
• Determining how self-fulfilling prophecies could be responsible for experi­
mental results or everyday observations.
• Knowing when causal claims can and can't be made.

These skills should be used in your own thinking and in critiquing the thinking
of others. After reading this chapter, you should be able to use these skills in any
context in which they are appropriate, and even more importantly, recognizing
when you need to use them.

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?

The final question to consider is whether you have reduced uncertainty: Can you
predict the results of certain actions or can you make better decisions because you
used the hypothesis-testing skills presented in this chapter? The ubiquitous concern
for accuracy is always the final test of the quality of the decision at which you've ar­
rived. When you function like an intuitive scientist, you will sometimes make
wrong decisions because we never know "truth." But, you can minimize wrong de­
cisions, by carefully using the hypothesis-testing skills presented in this chapter.

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Much of our everyday thinking is like the scientific method of hypothesis test­
ing. We formulate beliefs about the world and collect observations to decide if our
beliefs are correct.
2. In the inductive method we devise hypotheses from our observations. In the
deductive method we collect observations that confirm or disconfirm our hypothe­
ses. Most thinking involves an interplay of these two processes so that we devise
hypotheses from experience, make observations, and then, on the basis of our obser­
vations, we redefine our hypotheses.
3. Operational definitions are precise statements that allow the identification and
measurement of variables.
4. Independent variables are used to predict or explain dependent variables.
When we formulate hypotheses, we want to know about the effect of the indepen­
dent variable on the dependent variable(s).
5. When we draw conclusions from observations, it's important to utilize an ade­
quately large sample size because people are variable in the way they respond. Most
people are too willing to generalize results obtained from small samples.
6. In order to generalize about a population, the sample needs to be representa­
tive of the population. You need to ask if the sample you are using is biased in any
way before making generalizations.
TERMS TO KNOW 261

7. I n determining i f one variable (e.g., smoking) causes another variable (e.g.,


lung cancer) to occur, it is important to be able to isolate and control the causal vari­
ables. Strong causal claims require the three-stage experimental design that was de­
scribed in this chapter.
S. In everyday contexts, we often use retrospective techniques to understand
what caused an event to occur. This is not a good technique because our memories
tend to be selective and malleable and because we have no objective systematic ob­
servations of the cause. Prospective techniques that record events when they occur
and then see if the hypothesized result follows are better methods for determining
cause-effect relationships.
9. Variables that are related so that changes in one variable are associated with
changes in the other variable are called correlated variables. Correlations can be
positive as in the relationship between height and weight (taller people tend to
weigh more; shorter people tend to weigh less) or negative as in the relationship be­
tween exercise and weight (people who exercise a great deal tend to be thin, and
those who exercise little tend to be heavy).
10. A common error is to infer a causative relationship from correlated variables. It
is possible that Variable A caused Variable B, or that Variable B caused Variable A, or
that A and B influenced each other, or that a third variable caused them both.
1 1 . The belief that two variables are correlated when they are not (illusory corre­
lation) is another type of error that is common in human judgment.
12. It is important that you use measurements that are sensitive, valid, and reli­
able or the conclusions you draw may be incorrect. Few people consider the impor­
tance of measurement issues when they draw everyday conclusions about the
nature of the world.
13. Although many of our judgments lack validity, people report great confidence
in them. This is called illusory validity.
14. Inadvertently, we may act in ways that will lead us to confirm or disconfirm
hypotheses according to our expectations. These are called self-fulfilling prophecies.

TERMS TO KNOW

Check your understanding of the concepts presented in this chapter by reviewing


their definitions. If you find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to
reread the section in which it is discussed.

Hypothesis Testing. The scientific method of collecting observations to confirm or


disconfirm beliefs about the relationships among variables.
Hypothesis. A set of beliefs about the nature of the world, usually concerning the
relationship between two or more variables.
Inductive Method. A method of formulating hypotheses in which you observe
events and then devise a hypothesis about the events you observed.
Deductive Method. A method of testing hypotheses in which you formulate a hy­
pothesis that you believe to be true and then infer consequences from it. Systematic
observations are then made to verify if your hypothesis is correct.
Operational Definition. An explicit set of procedures that tell the reader how to
recognize and measure the concept in which you're interested.
262 6. THINKING AS HYPOTHESIS TESTI:-oJG

(A) Variable. A quantifiable characteristic that can take on more than one value
(e.g., height, gender, age, race).
Independent Variable. The variable that is selected (or manipulated) by the experi­
menter who is testing a hypothesis to see if changes in the independent variable will
result in changes in the dependent variable. For example, if you want to know if
people are more readily persuaded by threats or rational appeals, you could present
either a threatening message or a rational appeal to two groups of people (message
type is the independent variable), and then determine how much their attitudes to­
ward the topic have changed (the dependent variable).
Dependent Variable. The variable that is measured in an experiment to deter­
mine if its value depends on the independent variable. Compare with independent
variable.
Sensitive Measures. Measures that are able to detect small changes in the depen­
dent variable.
Population. For statistical and hypothesis testing purposes, a population is the en­
tire group of people (or animals or entities) in which one is interested and to which
one wishes to generalize.
Sample. A subset of a population that is studied in order to make inferences about
the population.
Random Sample. A sample in which everyone in a population has an equal chance
of being selected.
Representative Sample. A sample that is similar to the population in important
characteristics such as the proportion of males and females, socioeconomic status,
and age.
Generalization. Using the results obtained in a sample to infer that similar results
would have been obtained from the population if everyone in the population had
been measured. (When used in the context of problem solving, it is a strategy in
which the problem is considered as an example of a larger class of problems.)
Biased Sample. A sample that is not representative of the population from which it
was drawn.
Confounding. When experimental groups differ in more than one way, it's not possi­
ble to separate the effects due to each variable. For example, if you found that teenage
girls scored higher on a test of verbal ability than preteen boys, you wouldn't know if
the results were due to sex differences or age differences between the two groups.
Convenience Samples. The use of a group of people who are readily available as
participants in an experiment. Such samples may be biased in that they may not be
representative of the population from which they were drawn.
Sample Size. The number of people selected for a study.
Law of Large Numbers. Large samples provide more reliable estimates about pop­
ulation characteristics than small samples.
Variability. Term to denote the fact that people (and animals) differ in the way they
respond to experimental stimuli.
Law of Small Numbers. The willingness to believe that results obtained from a few
subjects can be generalized to the entire population.
Subject. A person, animal, or entity who serves as a participant in an experiment.
Retrospective Research. After an event has occurred, the experimenter looks back­
ward in time to determine its cause.
Prospective Research. A method of conducting research in which possible
causative factors of an event are identified before the event occurs. Experimenters
then determine if the hypothesized event occurs.
TERMS TO KNOW 263

Correlated Variables. Two or more variables that are related. See positive correla­
tion and negative correlation.
Positive Correlation. Two or more variables that are related so that increases in one
variable occur concomitantly with increases in the other variable, and decreases in
one variable occur with decreases in the other.
Negative Correlation. Two or more variables that are related such that increases in
one variable are associated with decreases in the other variable.
Illusory Correlation. The belief that two variables are correlated, when in fact they
are uncorrelated.
Validity. The extent to which a measure (e.g., a test) is measuring what you want it to.
Convergent Validity. The use of several different measures or techniques that all
suggest the same conclusion.
Illusory Validity. The belief that a measure is valid (measures what you want it to)
when, in fact, it is not. This belief causes people to be overconfident in their judgments.
Reliability. The consistency of a measure (e.g., a test) on repeated occasions.
Self-Fulfilling Prophecy. The tendency to act in ways that influence experimental
results so that we obtain results that are consistent with our expectations.
Double-Blind Procedures. An experimental paradigm in which neither the subjects
nor the person collecting data know the treatment group to which the subject has
been assigned.
7

Likelihood
and Uncertainty:
Understanding
Probabilities

Contents
Probabilistic Nature of the World Expected Values
Likelihood and Uncertainty Subjective Probability
Odds Gambler's Fallacy
The Laws of Chance Base-Rate Neglect
How We Explain Chance Events Making Probabilistic Decisions
Degrees of Belief Combining Information to Make
Factors Affecting Judgments About Predictions
Likelihood and Uncertainty Thinking With Frequencies
The Search for Meaning Nonregressive Judgments
Overconfidence Risk
Using Probability Assessing Risks
Games of Chance Biases in Risk Assessment
Cards Statistical Use and Abuse
Roulette On the Average
Computing Probabilities in Multiple Precision
Outcome Situations Significant Differences
Using Tree Diagrams Extrapolation
Conjunction Error-Applying the Bamboozled by Statistics
"And Rule" Applying the Framework
Cumulative Risks-Applying the Chapter Summary
"Or Rule" Terms to Know

264
PROBABILISTIC NATURE OF THE WORLD 265

The jury was facing a difficult decision in the case of People v. Collins, (cited in Arkes &
Hammond, 1986). The robbery victim could not identify his assailant. All he could re­
call was that the robber was a woman with a blond ponytail who, after the robbery,
rode off in a yellow convertible driven by a Black man with a moustache and a beard.
The suspect fit this description, but could the jury be certain "beyond a reasonable
doubt" that the woman who was on trial was the robber? She was blond and often
wore her hair in a ponytail. Her codefendant "friend" was a Black man with a mous­
tache, beard, and yellow convertible. If you were the attorney for the defense, you
would stress the fact that the victim could not identify this woman as the robber. What
strategy would you use if you were the attorney for the prosecution?
The prosecutor produced an expert in probability theory who testified that the proba­
bility of these conditions "co-occurring (being blond plus having a ponytail plus having
a Black male friend plus his owning a yellow convertible and so on, when these charac­
teristics are independent) was 1 in 12 million. The expert testified that this combination
of characteristics was so unusual that the jury could be certain "beyond a reasonable
doubt" that she was the robber.
The jury returned a verdict of "guilty."

PROBABILISTIC NATURE OF THE WORLD

The theory of probabilities is nothing but common sense confirmed by


calculation.
-La Place (1 749-1827)
The legal system recognizes that we can never have absolute certainty in legal mat­
ters. Instead, we operate with various degrees of uncertainty. Juries are instructed to
decide that someone is guilty of a crime when they are certain "beyond a reasonable
doubt." This standard was adopted because there is always some small amount of
doubt that the accused may be innocent. Jurors are instructed to operate under a dif­
ferent level of doubt when they are deciding about guilt or innocence in a civil case.
In civil cases, they are told to deliver a verdict of guilty when the "preponderance of
evidence" supports this decision. Thus, jurors are instructed to operate under two
different levels of uncertainty when the case before them is criminal or civil. They
need to be more certain when deciding that an accused party is guilty in a criminal
case than in a civil case.
Probability is the study of likelihood and uncertainty. It plays a critical role in all
professions and in most everyday decisions. All medical diagnoses and treatment
decisions are inherently probabilistic, as are decisions made in business, college ad­
missions, advertising, and research. Probability is the cornerstone of science; the
laws of probability guide the interpretation of all research findings. Many of our
leisure activities also rely on the principles of probability, most notably horse racing
and card games. Every time you decide to take an umbrella, invest in the stock mar­
ket, buy an insurance policy, or bet on a long shot in the Kentucky Derby, you are
making a probability judgment. Other than the proverbial death and taxes, there is
very little in life that is known with certainty. Because we live in a probabilistic
world, critical thinking will require an understanding of probability.
There is good evidence that training in the use of probability will improve your
ability to utilize probability values in appropriate manner. In an investigation of the
266 7. LIKELIHOOD AND VNCERTAINTY

use of statistical thinking in everyday reasoning tasks, researchers concluded that,


"This study indicated clearly that statistical training can enhance the use of statisti­
cal rules in reasoning about everyday life and can do so completely outside the con­
text of training" (Fong, Krantz, & Nisbett, 1986, p. 280). In other words, although the
thinking skills presented in this chapter will require the use of basic arithmetic and
probably some concentrated effort, it's likely that you'll be a better thinker for hav­
ing worked through the problems.

Likelihood and uncertainty

If your facts are wrong but your logic is perfect, then your conclusions are
inevitably false. Therefore, by making mistakes in your logic, you have at least a
random chance of coming to a correct conclusion.
-Christie-Davies' Theorem (reference unknown, taken from a calendar)

If I flip a "fair" coin (i.e., one that is not biased, which means that either a head or
tail is equally likely) into the air and ask you to guess the probability that it will land
heads up, you would say that the probability of a head is 50% (or .50) . This means
that the coin is expected to land heads up half of the time. Although the word proba­
bility is used in several different ways, the definition of probability that is most useful
in the present context is the number of ways a particular outcome (what we call a
success) can occur divided by the number of possible outcomes (when each possible
outcome is equally likely) . It is a measure of how often we expect an event to occur
in the long run. Success may seem like a strange word in this context, but you can
think of it as the outcome in which you're interested. In this case, a success is getting
the coin to land heads up. There is only one way for a coin to land heads up, so the
number of ways a success can occur in this example is one. What are all the possible
outcomes of flipping a coin in the air? The coin can either land heads up or tails up.
(I've never seen a coin land on its edge, nor have I ever seen a bird come along and
carry it off while it's flipped in the air, so I'm not considering these as possible out­
comes.) Thus, there are two possible outcomes, each of which is as likely to happen
as the other. To calculate the probability of getting a coin to land heads up, compute
the number of ways a head can occur ( 1 ), divided by the number of possible out­
comes (2), or 1 /2, an answer you already knew. Because many people find it easier
to think in percentages than in fractions, 1 /2 is sometimes changed to 50% .
Let's try another example. How likely are you to roll a 5 in one roll of a die? As
there is only one way for a 5 to occur, the numerator of the probability fraction is 1 .
A die is a 6-sided (cube) figure; thus there are 6 possible outcomes in one roll. If the
die is not "loaded," that is, when each side of the die is equally likely to land facing
up, the probability of rolling a 5 is 1 / 6, or approximately 1 7%.
What is the probability of rolling an even number in one roll of a fair die? To find
this probability, consider the number of ways a success can occur. You could roll a
2, 4, or 6, all possible even numbers. Thus, there are three ways a success can occur
out of six equally likely outcomes, so the probability of rolling an even number is
3/6 = 1 /2.
What is the probability of rolling a whole number less than 7? If someone asked
me to bet on this happening, I'd put up my house, my children, and my meager sav­
ings account to make this bet. In other words, I'd bet that this will happen. Let's see
why. The number of ways a whole number less than 7 can occur in one roll of a die
PROBABILISTIC NATURE OF THE WORLD 267

Example

W
:·•


Roll a n u m ber less than 7 1 .0 = certainty ( must occur)

increa singly more l i kely to ocr.ur

R o l l an even ( o r odd ) n u m ber .5 = maximum uncerta inty

increa singly less l i kely to occur

Roll an 8 o = certainty (cannot occur)

FIG. 7. 1 . Probability and likelihood.

is six (1, 2, 3, 4, 5, or 6), and the number of possible outcomes is six. Thus, the proba­
bility is 6/6, or 1 . When a probability is equal to 1 (or 1 00%), it must happen; it is
certain to occur.
What is the probability of rolling an 8 in one roll of a die? Again, I'd put up
everything I own, but this time I'd bet against this occurrence. The number of ways
an 8 can occur is zero. Thus, the probability of this occurring is 0; it cannot occur.
This situation also reflects absolute certainty. Probabilities range from 0 (can never
happen) to 1 (must happen). Probability values close to 0 or 1 represent events that
are almost certain not to occur or almost certain to occur, whereas probabilities
near .5 (50% ) represent maximum uncertainty, because either outcome is equally
likely, and thus there is no basis for predicting either one. This relationship is de­
picted in Fig. 7.1 .

Odds

It is often convenient to discuss probabilities in terms of odds. If a friend gives you


3-to-1 odds that his school's championship tiddiy-winks team will beat your
school's tiddly-winks team, this means that if four games were played, he would ex­
pect his team to win three of them. Authorities on organized sports (announcers,
sports page editors, and almost everyone else) usually express their degree of belief
in the outcome of a sporting event in terms of odds. (Betting odds like those posted
at racetracks and boxing matches refer to the amount of money that has been bet on
268 7. LIKELIHOOD At....D UNCERTAINTY

each contender and, thus, have a slightly different meaning from the one described
here.)
To convert odds to a probability, add the two numbers that are given (e.g., 3:1 =

4), use the first number as the numerator and the sum as the denominator (3/4), and
this is the equivalent probability.

The Laws of Chance

Uncertainty is an essential and integral facet of all forms of life and is, ill
principle, unavoidable.

-Gideon Keren and Karl Halvor Teigen (2001 )

The most important phrase i n the last section was "in the long run." Except for those
special cases when the probability of an outcome is either 0% or 100%, we cannot
know with certainty what will happen. I cannot know when I roll a die whether I
will roll a 5, but, if I keep rolling a fair die for many, many trials, I do know that
about 17% of the time I will roll a 5. I cannot know which roll will produce a 5, but I
do know approximately how many rolls will land with a 5 showing, if I keep rolling
for a long time. This is an important point. When we speak of the laws of chance (or
laws of probability), we are referring to the ability to predict the number or percent­
age of trials on which a particular outcome will occur. With a large number of trials,
I can be very accurate about the number of times a particular outcome will occur,
but I cannot know which trials will yield a particular outcome. This means that I can
make good "long-run" predictions and poor "short-run" predictions.
Let's consider insurance as an applied example of this distinction. When you buy
a life insurance policy (or any other type of insurance policy), you are making a bet
with the insurance company. You agree to pay a certain amount of money to the in­
surance company each year. They agree to pay your beneficiary a certain amount of
money when you die. There are many different types of life insurance policies avail­
able, but for the purposes of this chapter, we'll consider the simplest. I'll use some
simple numbers to demonstrate the statistical point that I want to make-in real life,
the actual costs and payoffs are different from those used in this example. Suppose
that you are 30 years old and that you agree to pay the insurance company $1,000
per year. When you die, your beneficiary will receive $20,000. You are betting with
the insurance company that you will die at a fairly young age (a bet that you hope to
lose) so that you will have paid them only a small amount of money and your bene­
ficiary will receive a larger amount of money. If you die before the age of 50, you
win the bet. Ignoring complications like inflation and interest, you will have paid
less than the $20,000 your beneficiary will receive if you die at a young age. The in­
surance company, on the other hand, will win the bet if you live to a ripe old age. If
you die when you are 70 years old, you will have paid them $40,000 and your dearly
beloved will receive only $20,000.
Insurance companies can make money because of the laws of chance. No one
knows when you or anyone else will die, but insurance companies do know how
many people aged 30 (the age at which you bought your policy) will die before they
reach their 50th birthday. Thus, although no one can predict accurately the age at
death for any single individual, we can use the laws of chance to predict how many
people will live to be any particular age.
PROBABILISTIC NATURE OF THE WORLD 269

How We Explain Chance Events


Most people can understand the laws of chance when they think about tossing a
coin or rolling a pair of dice, but find it more difficult to recognize how chance oper­
ates in complicated real-world settings. Unusual events-the sort that make you say
"imagine that"-are often reported in the news. Consider, for example, this newspa­
per headline: "Three Sisters Give Birth on the Same Day" (Chance Magazine, 200 1 ) .
According to an article in the March 14, 2001 edition of the Point Stevens Journal,
Karralee Morgan, Marrianne Asay, and Jennifer Hone (real people-real names­
no names have been changed to protect anyone) are sisters who all gave birth on
March 1 1 , 1998 (as reported in Chance Magazine). It's hard to hear this story and not
ask, "What is the probability that three sisters would give birth on the same day?"
As it turns out, this is a tricky question because there are several ways of interpret­
ing what is being asked. Consider these two possible interpretations:

What is the probability that these three sisters (Karralee, Marrianne, and Jennifer) will all
give birth on March 1 1 , 1998?
What is the probability that somewhere in the United States there will be three sisters (any
set of three sisters) who all give birth on the same day (any day of any one year)?

Before I give you the answers, think about what is being asked and decide which
of these two interpretations is more likely to occur. Did you understand that the sit­
uation described in Question 2 is much more likely than the situation described in
Question 1 ? According to calculations presented in a magazine that teaches about
chance events (Chance Magazine, 2001), the answer for Question 1 is about 1 in 50
million, but the answer for Question 2 is about 1 in 6,000. It seems likely that most
people are thinking about Question 2 when they ask about the chance of three sis­
ters giving birth on the same day, but it is easy to see why these are difficult con­
cepts because the question is prompted by the situation in Question 1 . If we want to
know about any three sisters on any day in any one year (there are 365 different pos­
sible days, so there are more ways for this to happen), it is much more likely than if
we mean a specific three sisters on a specific day.

Degrees of Belief

Probability is sometimes used to express the strength of a belief about the likelihood of
an outcome. This is a second definition for the term probability. For example, if you
interview for a job and believe that the interview went well, you might assess the prob­
ability that you will be offered the job as 80%. This probability value was not mathe­
matically derived by calculating the number of ways a success could occur divided by
the number of possible outcomes. Instead, it indicates your degree of belief that the job
will be offered. It suggests a moderate to high likelihood. If someone else interviewed
for the same job and believed that his chance of being offered the job was 50%, it would
be obvious that he was less confident about getting the job than you were.
The use of probability to express one's degree of belief in the likelihood of an out­
come is particularly prevalent at election time. Political analysts will often attach
probability values to the likelihood of a candidate's election. If a political analyst
gives a candidate a 30% chance of winning, she is predicting that although the can­
didate might win, she believes that the candidate is more likely to lose. Probability
values are handy ways of quantifying confidence in an outcome.
270 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

FACTORS AFFECTING JUDGMENTS ABOUT


LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

"The odds against there being a bomb on a plane are a million to one, and
against two bombs a million times a million to one. Next time you fly, cut the
odds and take a bomb."
-Benny Hill (quoted in Byrne, 1988, p. 349)

There is a large research literature documenting the fact that most people are biased
in their assessment of probabilities. We fail to appreciate the nature of randomness
and have strong misconceptions about likelihood and uncertainty (Garfield &
Ahlgren, 1 988). This is not a surprising finding given that we can only use probabili­
ties to understand events "in the long run" and most of our everyday experiences
are based on "short-run" observations. For example, there is a large body of data
that show that, on the average, people who smoke die at a younger age than those
who don't (Paulos, 1 994). Most of us can't discover this relationship on our own be­
cause we don't know the age at death for large numbers of people, but we may
know one or two people who smoked two packs a day and lived into their 90s. This
sort of personal experience would lead us to doubt the statistics that were collected
from many people. Remember though, personal experience is not a good way to
make many judgments about the world. Recall from the previous chapter that expe­
rience is an expensive teacher, but not a good one.

The Search for Meaning

To live, it seems is to explain, to justify, and to find coherence among diverse


outcomes, characteristics, and causes.
-Gilovich (1991, p. 22)

We seek causes for events that happen to us and others, but most of us rarely con­
sider the randomness of many events. We look for patterns and meaning, a quest
that can often be helpful, but also can lead to beliefs that are groundless. For exam­
ple, consider this true story: A student stopped in my office to talk with me. He told
about an "amazing thing" that just happened to him. He was a student in a class of
15 students. Each student had to make an oral presentation, and the order in which
they were to present was determined by drawing numbers from a box. "Guess who
picked number 1 ?" he asked excitedly. I guessed that he did. "Exactly, and do you
know the probability of that!" I did, it was 1 / 1 5 or approximately 7%. "Isn't that
amazing? Out of 15 people in the class, I picked number 1 . How can you explain
that?" I attributed this not-so-amazing outcome to chance; after all, someone had to
pick number 1 . He was certain that was a sign of something; maybe the "gods" had
intervened or his karma had gone berserk (whatever that means). He was looking
for a cause that could explain this event, and he never considered just plain
"chance."
There seems to be a universal need to find meaning in the vast array of everyday
events that confront us, a trait that makes it difficult to recognize chance events. You
may have heard about the controversy over the Bible Code, which is the title of a
book that describes how letters sampled at regular intervals (for example, every
FACTORS AFFECTING JUDGMENTS 271

50th letter) from the Bible had embedded i n them the names of famous people and
foretold events that would happen in the future (Drosnin, 1 997). Statisticians
howled with laughter (and scorn) at this book because chance alone would result in
many words appearing in these letter strings. On the other hand, it is easy to under­
stand how someone who does not understand concepts in probability might be
persuaded by the seemingly amazing number of names and words that were
embedded in long strings of letters.
The author of the Bible Code (Drosnin, 1 997) challenged statisticians to use the
same technique of letter sampling with Moby Dick, a book that presumably would
not have embedded special messages about the future into its letter sequences. A
group of Australian computer scientists (McKay, Bar-Natan, & Kalai, 1 999) took up
the challenge and found "M. 1. King," near the phrase "to be killed by them,"
"Kennedy" near the word "shoot," and many more famous names and meaningful
phrases (including "Princess Di" and "Lincoln") in letter strings taken from Moby
Dick, thus showing that mere chance would result in many meaningful names and
phrases embedded in long strings of letters. In general, we tend to underestimate
the importance of being able to think about probabilities. In an editorial on this
topic, one columnist chided the American public for making fun of a politician's
poor grammar because we should be far more concerned about our politicians'
math skills, especially their poor understanding of probabilities (Cole, 2001 ) . There
are many critical issues that depend on the ability to think with numbers-global
warming, population growth, and the economy, to name a few.

Overconfidence

Most people . . . tend to overestimate the degree to which we are responsible for
our own successes.
-Simon Gervais and Terrance Odean (2001, p. 1)

By definition, there is always some uncertainty in probabilistic events. Yet, research


has shown that people tend to be more confident in their decisions about probabilis­
tic events than they should be. Consider an example that Daniel Kahneman, a re­
searcher in this area, likes to use. When he and his coauthors began working on a
text on decision making, they were fairly confident that they would have it com­
pleted within a year, despite the fact that they knew that most books like the one
they were writing take many years to complete. They believed that they would beat
these "odds." In fact, it took them several years to complete the text.
In an experimental investigation of the overconfidence phenomenon, people
were asked to provide answers with a specified degree of confidence to factual
questions (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). Try it with this question: "I feel 98% certain
that the number of nuclear plants operating in the world in 1 980 was more than
and less than . Fill in the blanks with numbers that reflect 98% confi-
dence. The researchers investigating this effect found that nearly one third of the
time, the correct answer did not lie between the two values that reflected a 98%
level of confidence. (The correct answer to this question is 1 89.) This result demon­
strates that people are often highly confident when their high degree of confidence
is unwarranted.
Have you ever bought a lottery ticket? Do you know what the odds are against
your hitting the jackpot? The laws of probability dictate that you should expect to
272 7. LIKELIHOOD A.."JD UNCERTAINTY

lose, yet countless numbers of people expect to win. In fact, a disturbing poll pub­
lished in Money magazine revealed that almost as many people are planning for
their retirement by buying lottery tickets (39%) as are investing in stocks (43%)
(Wang, 1 994).
People tend to be most confident in uncertain situations when they believe that
they have control over the uncertain events. Many state lottery advisors are familiar
with this principle of human nature and now have a lottery plan that allows the
buyer to select his own number. People prefer to select their own numbers over
being given a number at random because it gives them an illusion of control. The
winning number is still selected randomly, but people believe they are more likely
to win in the self-selection lottery. Overconfidence can be disastrous for financial in­
vestors. In a study of individual investors, two economists found that most people
fail to recognize the role that chance plays in the stock market, so they tend to at­
tribute gains to their own expertise in picking stocks and losses to external forces
that they could not control. The result is that overconfident investors trade their
stocks far too often because they believe that they are making wise choices (Gervais &
Odean, 200 1 ) . If they could recognize the effects of random fluctuations in the stock
market instead of attributing the changes to their own trading behaviors, they
would have traded less often and ended up in better financial shape.

USING PROBABILITY

Without giving it much thought, we utilize probabilities many times each day. Let's
start with one of the few examples where probability values are made explicit.
Many people begin each day by reading the weather forecast in the morning paper.
What do you do when you read that the probability of rain is 80% today? Most peo­
ple will head off to school or work toting an umbrella. What if it does not rain? Can
we conclude that the forecaster was wrong? The forecast of an 80% probability of
rain means that out of every 1 00 days when the weather conditions are like those on
this particular day, there will be rain on 80 of them. Thus, a probability of rain is,
like all probability values, based on what we would expect in the long run. Weather
experts know that 80 out of 1 00 days will have rain, but the forecasters cannot know
with absolute certainty which days it will rain.
Suppose that you are to be married on this hypothetical day, and a magnificent
outdoor ceremony is planned. Suppose that an 80% probability of rain was forecast,
and it did not rain. Would you believe that something other than chance was re­
sponsible for the good weather or that the absence of rain is a good (or bad) sign for
your marriage? If you would interpret the good weather as a sign from the heavens
or some other astral body, then you have demonstrated the point that was just
made-we seek meaning in events, even events as seemingly uncontrollable as the
weather, and we rarely consider plain old chance.
The number of instances in which we are given explicit probability values that
have been computed for us is relatively small. One area where this practice is grow­
ing is in the use of medical information sheets that are designed to help patients
understand the risks and benefits of taking a particular drug. The Food and Drug
Administration requires that all oral contraceptive medications (birth control pills)
be packaged with statistical information about the health risks associated with them.
To arrive at an intelligent decision based on the information provided, potential oral
USING PROBABILITY 273

contraceptive users must be able to understand the statistical summaries that are
presented in the medical information sheets.
The following excerpt from an oral contraceptive package insert provides an ex­
ample: "For women aged 20 to 44, it is estimated that about 1 in 2,000 using oral
contraceptives will be hospitalized each year because of abnormal clotting. Among
nonusers in the same age group, about 1 in 20,000 would be hospitalized each year"
(Ortho Pharmaceutical Corp., 1 979, p. 1 6). Although consumers can readily assess
that clotting is more likely for pill users, this information is of little practical value
unless an oral contraceptive consumer can decide if 1 in 2,000 is a large or small
number, i.e., "Is it a danger to me if I am taking the pill?" Two related experiments
(Halpern & Blackman, 1985; Halpern, Blackman, & Salzman, 1989) have shown that
most people find information like this to be relatively meaningless.
Consider the following: Suppose you read that the risk of developing heart dis­
ease is 10.5 times more likely for oral contraceptive users than for nonusers. Most
people will conclude from this information that taking oral contraceptives presents
a substantial risk of heart disease. Suppose now that you are told that only 3 .5
women out of 1 00,000 users will develop heart disease. You probably would inter­
pret this sentence as meaning that there is little risk associated with oral contracep­
tive use. Consider the "flip side" of this information and think about how you
would assess safety if you read that 99,996.5 women out of 1 00,000 users will not de­
velop heart disease. Does it seem even safer? Another way of presenting the same
information is to convert it to a percentage. There is only a .0035% chance that oral
contraceptive users will develop heart disease. Most people would now consider the
risk associated with oral contraceptive use to be minuscule.
Which of these statements is correct? They all are. The only way they differ is the
way in which the statistical information is presented, and different ways of present­
ing the same statistical information lead to very different assessments of safety
(Halpern, Blackman, & Salzman, 1989). It is important to keep this in mind when in­
terpreting statistical information. There is a trend to provide consumers with statis­
tical risk information so that they can make informed safety judgments about a
diverse assortment of topics including how to treat a particular type of cancer and
the safety of nuclear energy. Although the topic of risk is considered in more detail
later in this chapter, keep in mind that the best way to convert risk probabilities to a
meaningful value is to write out all of the mathematically equivalent values (i.e., X
out of Y occurrences, number of times greater risk than a meaningful comparison
event, number that will die, number that will not die). Graphic representations of
relative risks can also be helpful when there are many values that need to be com­
pared simultaneously. The use of spatial arrays is touted throughout this book (e.g.,
circle diagrams when interpreting syllogisms, graphic organizers to comprehend
complex prose, tree diagrams for use in making sound decisions). One advantage
that they confer in this situation is that they reduce the memory load in working
memory and allow us to consider several different alternatives "at a glance."

Games of Chance

People love to play games. From Las Vegas to Atlantic City, and in all of the small
towns in between, and in many other countries in the world, people spend countless
hours and dollars playing games of chance, skill, and semiskill. For many people,
the only serious consideration they have ever given to probability is when playing
games of chance.
2 74 7. LIKELIHOOD A.c�D UNCERTAINTY

DRABBLE © UPS

Cards
Card playing is a ubiquitous pastime, with small children playing "fish" and "old
maid," and their older counterparts play canasta, bridge, poker, pinochle, black jack,
hearts, and too many others to mention. The uncertainty inherent in card games adds
to the pleasure of playing (although the camaraderie and pretzels and beer also help).
Good card players, regardless of the game, understand and utilize the rules of
probability. Let's apply the definitional formula for probability to card games. For
example, how likely are you to draw an ace of spades from a deck of 52 cards? The
probability of this happening is 1 /52, or approximately 2%, because there is only
one ace of spades and 52 possible outcomes. How likely are you to draw an ace of
any suit from a full deck of cards? If you've been following the probability discus­
sion so far, you'll realize that the answer is 4/52, or approximately 8%, because
there are four aces in a 52-card deck.
Although some professional card players claim to have worked out careful plans
that will help them to change the odds of winning in their favor, it is not possible to
"beat the house" for most card games, no matter how good a player one is. It is al­
ways difficult to tell the extent to which these stories of successful gamblers are
hype. Professional gamblers often enjoy bragging about their winnings and conve­
niently forget about the times when they lost. Furthermore, most of the self­
proclaimed expert gamblers are selling their "winning system." I hope that you recall
from the chapters on reasoning and analyzing arguments that when an "expert"
stands to gain from the sale of a product, the expert's opinion becomes suspect.
According to Gunther (1977), Vera Nettick (who is a real person) is a lucky lady.
While playing a game of bridge, she was dealt a hand that contained all l 3 diamonds.
Breathlessly, she won a grand slam with the once-in-a-lifetime card hand. Any statis­
tician will be quick to point out that every possible combination of cards will be dealt
to somebody sooner or later. Thus, Vera Nettick's hand was no more unusual than
any other card hand, although it certainly is more memorable. Can you guess how
often such a hand would occur? Gunther (1977) figured this out as follows:
There are roughly 635 billion possible bridge hands. Of these, eight might be called "per­
fect" hands, though some are more perfect than others. To begin with, there are four per­
fect no-trump hands. Such a hand would contain all four aces, all four kings, all four
queens, and one of the four jacks. Any of these four hands would be unequivocally perfect,
because no bid could top it. Slightly less perfect, in descending order, are hands containing
all the spades, all the hearts, all the diamonds, and all the clubs. If there are eight of these
perfect hands in a possible 635 billion, the statistical probability is that such a hand will be
dealt one in every 79 billion tries, give or take a few.
USING PROBABILITY 275

Now all we have to do is estimate how many games of bridge are played every year and
how many hands are dealt in each game. Using fairly conservative estimates, it turns out
that a perfect hand should be dealt to some lucky bridge player, somewhere in the United
States, roughly once every three or four years. (p. 30)

Actually, Gunther's figures are too low, because new decks of cards are orga­
nized in ascending order by suits so that one or two "perfect" shuffles will produce
"perfect" bridge hands (Alcock, 1981). (A perfect shuffle occurs when, following a
"cut," there is a one-to-one interweaving of cards from each half of the deck.) And,
of course, none of these calculations address the possibility of cheating, which
would change the probabilities because each possible combination of cards would
no longer be equally likely. Consider the two card hands shown in Fig. 7.2. Every
possible combination of cards is equally likely when the cards are dealt at random.
This topic is also discussed in Chapter 8, "Decision Making."

Roulette
Roulette is often thought of as an aristocratic game. It is strange that it has gained
this reputation, because it is a game of pure chance. Unlike most card games, there
is no skillful way to play roulette. As you probably know, roulette is played by spin­
ning a small ball inside a circular array of numbered and colored pockets. Eighteen
of the pockets are red; 18 are black; and 2 are green. Players can make a variety of
bets. One possible bet is that the ball will land in a red pocket. What is the probability

FIG. 7 . 2 .Which of these two card hands are you more likely to be dealt from a well­
shuffled deck of cards?
276 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAI:'IITY

of this event when the ball is equally likely to land in any pocket? There are 18 red
pockets out of 38 pockets (possible outcomes); therefore, the probability of the ball
landing in a red pocket is 18/38. Because this is a number less than .5, we know that
it will land in a red pocket slightly less than half of the time. Thus, if you kept bet­
ting on red, you would lose slightly more often than you would win. Suppose now
you bet on black pockets. Again, the probability would be 1 8/38; and again, if you
continue to bet on black pockets, you will lose more often than you win. Of course,
sometimes you will win, and at other times you will lose, but after many spins-in
the long run-you will lose at roulette.
The odds or probability of winning at any casino game are always favorable to
the "house," otherwise, casinos could not stay in business. Actually, there is one
person who has been able to "beat" the roulette odds. One of my heros is Al Hibbs,
a scientist who gained fame for his work at the Jet Propulsion Laboratory in
Pasadena, California, where much of the work on the U. S. space program is done.
When he was a student, he used his knowledge of probability to run his original
stake of $125 up to $6,300 at the Pioneer Club in Reno. Here's how he did it: Hibbs
knows that although every number in a roulette wheel should be equally likely to
occur, all manufactured devices have imperfections. These imperfections make
some numbers more likely to occur than others. Hibbs and a friend recorded the re­
sults of 1 00,000 spins of a roulette wheel to find the numbers that occurred most
often. Accordingly, they bet on these numbers. Unfortunately, none of us can dupli­
cate his success, because the wheels are now taken apart and reassembled with dif­
ferent parts each day. Thus, although each wheel is still imperfect, the imperfections
differ from day to day.

Computing Probabilities in Multiple-Outcome Situations

We are often concerned with the probability of two or more events occurring, such
as getting two heads in two flips of a coin or rolling a 6 at least once in two rolls of a
die. These sorts of situations are called multiple outcomes.

Using Tree Diagrams


Although it is relatively easy to understand that the probability of getting a head
on one flip of a fair coin is 1 /2, it is somewhat more difficult to know intuitively the
probability of getting four heads in four flips of a fair coin. Although an example of
flipping a coin may seem artificial, it is a good way of showing how probabilities
combine over many trials. Let's figure it out. (Follow along with me, even if you are
math-phobic. The calculations and mathematical thinking are relatively easy, if you
work along with the examples. Do not look at the next several figures and exclaim,
"no way, I'll just skip it." It is important to be able to think with and about numbers.)
On the first flip, only one of two possible outcomes can occur; a head (H) or tail
(T). What can happen if a coin is flipped twice? There are four possible outcomes; a
head on the first flip and a head on the second (HH); a head on the first flip and
a tail on the second (HT); a tail on the first flip and a head on the second (TH); and a
tail on the first flip and a tail on the second (TT). Because there are four possible out­
comes and only one way to get two heads, the probability of this event is 1 /4 (again,
assuming that the coin is fair, that is, that getting a head is as likely as getting a tail).
There is a general rule, the "and rule," for calculating this value in any situation.
USING PROBABILITY 277

When you want to find the probability of one event and another event (a head on the
first and second flip), you multiply their separate probabilities. By applying the
"and rule," we find that the probability of obtaining two tails when a coin is flipped
twice is equal to 1 / 2 x 1 /2, which is 1 /4. Intuitively, the probability of both events
occurring should be less likely than either event alone, and it is.
A simple way to compute this probability is to represent all possible events with
tree diagrams. Tree diagrams were used in Chapter 4 on reasoning when we figured
the validity of if, then statements. In this chapter, we will add probability values to
the "branches" of the tree to determine the probability of different combinations of
outcomes. Later in this book, I will return to tree diagrams once again as a way of
generating creative solutions to problems.
On the first flip, either an H or T will land facing up. For a fair coin, the probabil­
ity of a head is equal to the probability of a tail, which is equal to .5. Let's depict this
as follows:


Outcome Probability

head {H} .5

start ____
----- tail {T} .5

When you flip a second time, either an H on the first flip will be followed by an H
or T, or a T on the first flip will be followed by an H or T. The probability of a head
or tail on the second flip is still 5 Outcomes from a second flip are added as
. .

"branches" on a tree diagram.

Outcome Probability

{HH} .25

ta i l {HT} .25

tail head {TH} .25

tai l {TI} .25

1 st fl ip 2nd fl ip

As you can see from this tree, there are four possible outcomes. You can use this
tree to find out the probability of other events. What is the probability of getting ex­
actly one H in two flips of a coin? Because there are two ways for this to occur (HT)
or (TH), the answer is 2/4 or 1 /2. When you want to find the probability of two or
more different outcomes, add the probability of each outcome. This is called the "or
rule." Another way to ask the same questions is, "What is the probability of getting
either a head followed by a tail (1 /4) or a tail followed by a head (1 / 4)?" The correct
procedure is to add these values, which equals 1 /2. Intuitively, the probability of
278 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTl

two or more events occurring should be higher (more likely) than the probability 0
any one of them occurring, and it is.
We can only use the "or rule" and the "and rule" when the events we're inter
ested in are independent. Two events are independent when the occurrence of onE
of them does not influence the occurrence of the other. In this example, what you ge
on the first flip of a coin does not influence what you get on the second flip. In addi
tion, the "or rule" requires that the outcomes be mutually exclusive, which meam
that if one occurs, the other cannot occur. In this example, the outcomes are mutu·
ally exclusive because we cannot obtain both a head and a tail on any single flip.
Let's get away from the artificial example of coin flipping, and apply the sam(
logic in a more useful context. I'm sure that every student has, at some time or other
taken a multiple-choice test. (Some students like to call them multiple-guess tests.:
Most of these tests have five alternative answers for each question. Only one of thes(
is correct. Suppose also that the questions are so difficult that all you can do is gues�
randomly at the correct answer. What is the probability of guessing correctly on thE
first question? If you have no idea which alternative is the correct answer, then you
are equally likely to choose any of the five alternatives, assuming that each alterna­
tive is equally likely to be correct. Because the sum of all possible alternatives musi
be 1 .0, the probability of selecting each alternative, when they are equally likely, i�
.20. One alternative is correct, and four are incorrect, so the probability of selecting
the correct alternative is .20. A tree diagram of this situation is shown here.

Outcome Probability

Correct {C } .2

Incorrect {I } .2
Probability
I ncorrect {I} .2 of being
incorrect
Incorrect {I} .2 on the fi rst
question = .S.
Incorrect {I} .2

sta rt 1 st Question

What is the probability of getting the first two multiple-choice questions correct
by guessing? We'll have to add a second branch to a tree that will soon be very
crowded. To save space and to simplify the calculations, all of the incorrect alterna­
tives can be represented by one branch labeled "incorrect." The probability of being
incorrect on any single question is .8:

Outcome Probability

Correct fCC} .04

.2 ....-
... ---_ Incorrect {CI} .16
Correct
Correct {IC} .16

Incorrect {II} .64


USING PROBABILITY 279

The probability of two correct questions by guessing is .2 X .2, which equals .04.
That means that this would happen by chance only 4% of the time. Suppose we ex­
tend our example to three questions. I won't draw a tree, but you should be able to
see by now that the probability is .2 X .2 X .2 = .008. This is so unusual that it would
occur less than 1 % of the time by chance. What would you conclude about someone
who got all three of these questions correct? Most people (professors are people, too)
would conclude that the student wasn't guessing, and that she really knew some­
thing. Of course, it is possible that the student was just lucky, but it is so unlikely
that we would conclude that something other than luck was responsible for the out­
come we obtained.
Let me point out a curious side to this kind of reasoning. Consider the plight of
Sara. She took a 1 5-question multiple-choice test in which every question had five
alternatives. Sara got all 15 questions wrong. Can you determine the probability of
this happening by chance? I won't draw the tree diagram to depict this situation,
but it is easy to see that the probability of being wrong on one question is .80; there­
fore, the probability of being wrong on all 15 questions is (.80)15. This is .80 times it­
self 15 times, which equals .0352. Because this would happen by chance only 3.52%
of the time, can Sara present the argument to her professor that something other
than chance determined this unusual result? Of course, Sara can make this argu­
ment, but would you be willing to believe her if you were her professor? Suppose
she argued that she must have known the correct answer to every question. How
else could she have avoided selecting it in all 15 consecutive questions? I don't know
how many professors would buy her assertion that getting all 15 questions wrong
demonstrates her knowledge, even though identical reasoning is used as proof of
knowing correct answers when the probability of getting all the questions correct is
about the same. (In this example, the probability of getting all 1 5 questions correct
just by guessing is [.2QP5, which is a number far less than .000 1 . ) Personally, if I were
the professor, I'd give Sara high marks for creativity and for her understanding of
statistical principles. It is possible that Sara did know "something" about the topic,
but that "something" was systematically wrong. I'd also point out to her that it is
possible that she was both unprepared and unlucky enough to guess wrong 1 5
times. After all, unusual events do happen sometimes.
Before going on to the next section, be sure that you understand how tree dia­
grams are used to compute probabilities and to consider all possible outcomes. I'll be
returning to these diagrams later in this chapter. Once you learn how to use them,
you'll be surprised at how many possible applications there are for tree diagrams.

Conjunction Error-Applying the "And Rule"

The following problem was posed by Tversky and Kahneman ( 1983, p. 297):

Linda is 31 years old, outspoken and very bright. She majored in philosophy. As a student,
she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and social justice, and also partici­
pated in anti-nuclear demonstrations.

For the following list of statements, estimate the probability that it is descriptive
of Linda.

A. Linda is a teacher in elementary school.


B. Linda works in a bookstore and takes yoga classes.
280 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINT1

C. Linda is active in the feminist movement.


D. Linda is a psychiatric social worker.
E. Linda is a member of the League of Women voters.
F. Linda is a bank teller.
G. Linda is an insurance salesperson.
H. Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement.

Stop now and estimate the probability for each statement.


The short paragraph about Linda was written to be representative of an activ�
feminist, which is Statement C. Thus, if we rely on common stereotypes of the "typi·
cal feminist," C would seem to be a likely description. Look at Statements F (ban1
teller) and H (feminist and a bank teller). How did you rank these two sentences:
Most people believe that H is more probably true than F. Can you see why F must bl
more likely than H when being a bank teller and being a feminist are independent 01
each other? There are some bank tellers who are not active in the feminist move·
ment. When determining the probability of both of two events occurring, you multi·
ply the probabilities of each one occurring (the "and rule"). Thus, the probability oj
two events both occurring must be less likely than the probability of one of thest
events occurring. In Tversky and Kahneman's (1983) study, 85% of the subject�
judged Statement H to be more probable than Statement F. The error of believing
that the occurrence of two events is more likely than the occurrence of one of them i�
called the conjunction error.
For those of you who think better with spatial arrays, let's represent this problem
with circle diagrams, a form of representation that was used with syllogisms in
Chapter 4 on reasoning. Draw one circle to represent every bank teller in the world,
and a second circle to represent every feminist. The two circles have to overlap
somewhat because there are some bank tellers who are feminists. This area oj
overlap is shaded in Fig. 7.3. As you can see in Fig. 7.3, the shaded area that repre­
sents all people who are both bank tellers and feminists must be smaller than th€
circle that represents all bank tellers because there are bank tellers who are not
feminists.

All All
Feminists Bank Tellers

People who are


both feminists
and bank tellers

FIG. 7.3. The two circles represent "All Feminists" and "All Bank Tellers." The intersection
of these two circles shows those individuals who are both feminist and a bank tellers. Because
there are feminists who are not bank tellers and bank tellers who are not feminists, the area of
their overlap must be smaller than either set alone.
USING PROBABILITY 28 1

Now that you understand the conjunctive error, try the next question (also taken
from Tversky and Kahneman, 1983, p. 308):

A health survey was conducted in a sample of adult males in British Columbia, of all ages
and occupations.
Please give your best estimate of the following values:
What percentage of the men surveyed have had one or more heart attacks? __

What percentage of the men surveyed both are over 55 years old and have had one or
more heart attacks?

Stop now and fill in the blanks above with your best estimate of these values.
Over 65% of the respondents believed that a higher percentage of the men would
be both over 55 and have had a heart attack than the percentage of men who re­
ported that they had a heart attack. Do you recognize this as another example of a
conjunction error? The probability of two uncertain events both occurring cannot be
greater than the probability of just one of them occurring.
There are some psychologists who object to all of the emphasis on the ways peo­
ple make mistakes in their thinking (Gigerenzer, Todd, & the ABC Research Group,
2000). They argue that most of us think pretty well, given real-life circumstances,
which include limited time to think through problems and limited information. Most
of the time, we rely on heuristics, which are "rules of thumb" or shortcuts for think­
ing. Gigerenzer and his colleagues consider problems like the "Linda" problem to be
"tricks." In this case, we are asked to make a decision about one person, when the
probability data refer to the population of all bank tellers and all feminists. He argues
that it is not irrational to use "typicality information" (e.g., the typical feminist has
certain traits) when making a "best guess" about one person. This is an area where
psychologists disagree about what is rational or reasoned thinking and is likely to
continue to be a hotly debated topic in the next several years. The point made by
Gigerenzer and others who are more optimistic about the quality of human cognition
is certainly valid. Many of the examples that show how poorly most of us think seem
artificial or lack important information that we normally would consider. Like many
of psychology's debates, each side seems to have part of the answer. Under some cir­
cumstances, people are easily misled and thinking goes wrong in predictable ways,
but under other circumstances, people can think fairly well. The situation is like the
proverbial glass that is both half-full and half-empty. Regardless of your personal
opinion about this debate, it is true that with hard work, we can all learn to think bet­
ter-a fact that should make both the optimists and pessimists very happy.

Cumulative Risks-Applying the "Or Rule"

It should be obvious that the probability of getting three questions correct by chance
when there are five alternatives will be much smaller than the probability of getting
just one question correct by chance and that the probability of getting at least one
question correct by chance out of three questions will be higher than the probability
of getting one question correct when there is only one question. The kinds of exam­
ples presented so far were deliberately simple. Let's see how this principle applies
in real-world settings.
Most real-life risks involve repeated exposure to a risky situation. Consider dri­
ving. The probability of having an accident in one car ride is very low. But what
282 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

happens to this probability when you take hundreds or thousands of car rides?
According to the "or rule", this is the probability of an accident on the first or second
or . . . . nth car ride. In an interesting study of how people understand the concept of
cumulative risk, Shaklee (1987) gave subjects different probability values that sup­
posedly corresponded to the yearly risk of a flood. Subjects then had to estimate the
likelihood of a flood in 1 month, S years, 1 0 years, and 15 years. Only 74% of her
subjects knew that the likelihood of a flood increased with intervals over 1 year.
Among those who gave higher probability values for intervals over 1 year, most
seriously underestimated the cumulative probability.
Let's consider a similar example. In the case of contraception, a method that is
96% effective per year will result in an average of four pregnancies per 1 00 couples
per year. Assuming a constant failure rate over time, we would expect even more
women would become pregnant when using this method for a period of 5 years,
and an even greater number when using this method over 15 years (Shaklee, 1987).
In a study with college students, only 52% realized that the number of expected
pregnancies would increase over time, and most of them significantly underesti­
mated the number of pregnancies with a contraceptive method that is 96% effective.
The message here should be clear: When you are determining risk, it is important
to understand whether the value you are being given is per some unit of time (e.g.,
1 year) and how cumulative risks increase with repeated exposure. It seems that
many people do not understand the concept that cumulative risks are greater than
one-time risks.

EXPECTED VALVES

Which of the following bets would you take if you could only choose one of them?

1 . The Big 12
It will cost you $1 to play. If you roll a pair of dice and get a 12, you'll get your
$1 back, plus another $24. If you roll any other number, you'll lose your $1 .
2. Lucky 7
It will cost you $1 to play (same cost as above). If you roll a "lucky 7" with a
pair of dice, you'll get your $1 back, plus another $6. If you roll any other num­
ber, you'll lose your $ 1 .

Stop now and select either item 1 o r 2.


Most people choose item 1 , reasoning that $24 if a 12 is rolled is four times more
than they can win if a 7 is rolled, and the cost is the same for each bet. Let's see if this
thinking is correct.
In order to decide which is the better bet, we need to consider the probability of
winning and losing and the corresponding value of each. There is a formula that
will take these variables into account and yield the expected value (EV) for each
gamble. An expected value is the amount of money you would expect to win on
each bet if you continued playing over and over. Like all probability values, it de­
pends on what would happen in the long run. The formula for computing an ex­
pected value (EV) is:

EV = (probability of a win) x (value of a win) + (probability of a loss) x (value of a loss)


EXPECTED VALVES 283

Let's consider the EV for Choice 1 . We'll begin by computing the probability of
rolling a 12 with a pair of dice. There is only one way to roll a 1 2, and that is with a 6
on each die. The probability of this happening when the dice are fair is 1 /6 X 1 /6 =

1 /36 = .028. (Because we are interested in finding the probability of a 6 on the first
and the second die, we use the "and rule," and multiply.) Thus, we'd expect to roll a
1 2 about 2.8% of the time. What is the probability of not rolling a 1 2? Because we are
certain that you will either roll a 1 2 or not roll a 12 (this covers all possible events),
you can subtract .028 from 1 .00. The probability of not rolling a 12 is .972. (You
could also arrive at this figure, with some small rounding differences, by calculating
the probability of each of the 35 other possible outcomes-each will be 1 /36-and
adding them together.) (see Fig. 7.4.)
Using these probability values, the EV formula for Choice 1 becomes:

EV = (Probability of a 1 2) X (Value of a 12) +


(Choice 1 ) (Probability of not getting a 1 2) X (Value of not getting a 1 2)

EV = [(.028) X ($24)] + [(.972) X ( - $1)]


(Choice 1 )
EV = $.672 - $.972
(Choice 1 )

EV = - $.30
(Choice 1 )

Total of both die


2

+
3
4
5
6 4
5 6
, 6 7

f
1
6" - 4
6
5
6

I �'
5
1 3 6
7
8
3 • 6" 9

Ii
START
6
7
6 4 8

'i
4 5 9
6 10

5
-
6
,I 4
5
6
9
10
"

, !i
7
8
6 9
6" 4 10
5 11
6 12
lst die, lnd die

FIG. 7.4. A tree diagram depicting all possible outcomes of rolling a pair of dice.
284 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

Let's review what happened in this formula. If you rolled a 12, you'd win $24,
which is the value associated with this win. If you rolled a number other than a 12,
you'd lose the $1 you paid to play this game, thus -$1 is the value associated with
this loss. The probability of a win was multiplied by the value of a win. The proba­
bility of a loss was multiplied by the value of a loss. Then, these two products were
added together. The EV of this bet is -$.30, which means that in the long run, if you
continue playing this game many times, you could expect to lose, on the average,
$.30 for every game played. Of course, on any single game, you'd either lose $1 or
win $24, but after many, many games you would have lost an average of $.30 per
game. If you played 1,000 games, making the same bet each time, you'd be $300
poorer.
How does this compare with Choice 2? To calculate the EV of Choice 2, we'll
begin by computing the probability of rolling a 7. How many ways is it possible to
roll a 7 with a pair of fair dice? You could get a 1 on the first die and a 6 on the sec­
ond; a 2 and a 5; a 3 and a 4; a 4 and a 3; a 5 and a 2; or a 6 and a 1 . Thus, there are 6
possible ways to roll a 7 out of 36 possible outcomes. The probability of any one of
these outcomes is 1 /6 x 1 /6, which equals 1 /36. (This is the probability of rolling,
e.g., a 1 on the first die and a 6 on the second die.) Thus to determine the probability
of one number followed by a second number you would apply the "and rule" . Be­
cause you are now concerned with the probability of a 1 followed by a 6 or a 2 fol­
lowed by a 5 or a 3 followed by a 4 or a 4 followed by a 3 or a 5 followed by a 2 or a 6
followed by a I, you should recognize the second step as a case where the "or rule"
is needed. Because there are six possible combinations, you would add 1 /36 six
times (which is, of course, the same as multiplying it by 6). Thus, the probability of
rolling a 7 with a pair of dice is 6/36 0 /6 or . 1 67). The probability of not rolling a
7 is 1 - . 167, which equals .833. Now we calculate the EV of Choice 2:

EV = (Probability of a 7) x (Value of a 7) +
(Choice 2) (Probability of not getting a 7) X (Value of not getting a 7)
EV = [(.167) x ($6)] + [(.833) x ( - $1) ]
(Choice 2)
= ($1 .002 - .833)

= $.169, or approximately $.17

This means that if you continued to gamble on Choice 2, you would win an aver­
age of $ . 1 7 for every game played. Thus, after 1,000 games, you could expect to be
$170 richer. Of course, as in Choice I , you would never actually win this amount on
any single game; this is what would result if you continued playing many, many
games. This is what would happen in the long run.
Even though you might have originally thought otherwise, Choice 2 is the better
choice because of the relatively high probability associated with rolling a 7. Seven
has a high probability because there were six possible combinations that would add
up to a 7.
There is a party game that is based on the principle that the more ways an event
can occur, the more likely it is to occur. Suppose you get a random sample of 40 peo­
ple together in a room. Estimate the probability that two of them share the same
birthday. You may be surprised to learn that the probability is approximately .90.
Can you figure out why it is so high? There are many, many ways that 40 people can
SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITY 285

share the same birthday. To figure out the exact probability, you would take all
combinations of 40 people, 2 at a time. Thus, we'd have to start with the combina­
tion of Person 1 with Person 2, then Person 1 with Person 3, and so on until Person 1
is matched with Person 40, then we'd begin again matching Person 2 with Person 3,
2 with 4, on until 2 is matched with 40. This whole process would have to be re­
peated until everyone of the 40 people is matched with every other one. Because
there are so many possible combinations of any two people sharing any birthday in
the year, this "coincidence" is more probable than it may have seemed at first. The
probability of two people sharing a common birthday is over .50, when there are 23
people and over .75 when there are 32 people (Loftus & Loftus, 1 982). You can use
this knowledge to make wagers at parties or at any gathering of people. It's a fairly
good bet when the number of people is close to 40. Most people find it hard to be­
lieve that the probability is so high.
You can also use your knowledge of probability to improve your chances in other
situations. Take, for example, Aaron and Jill, who have been arguing over who
should take out the garbage. Their mother agrees to help them settle this matter by
picking a number from 1 to 10. The one whose number comes closer to the one se­
lected by their mother will win the dispute. Aaron goes first and picks 3. What num­
ber should Jill select to maximize her chances of winning? Stop now and decide
what number she should select. The best number for Jill to pick is 4. If her mother
were thinking of any number greater than 3, Jill would win with this strategy. Thus,
she can change the probability of winning in what seems like a chance situation.

SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITY

We usually do not deal directly with known or objective probabilities, such as the
probability of rain on a given day or the probability of developing heart disease if
oral contraceptives are taken. Yet, every day we make decisions using our best esti­
mate of the likelihood of events. Subjective probability refers to personal estimates
of the likelihood of events. This term is in distinction from objective probability,
which is a mathematically determined statement of likelihood about known fre­
quencies. Psychologists who have studied subjective probability have found that
human judgments of probability are often fallible, yet we rely on them to guide our
decisions in countless situations.

Gambler's Fallacy

The "Wheel of Fortune" is a popular game at fairs, casinos, amusement parks, and
on television game shows. It consists of a large wheel, that can be spun. The wheel is
divided into many numbered sections, much like a roulette wheel. A rubber marker
indicates the winning number.
Suppose that your friend, Vanna, decides to approach the Wheel of Fortune in a
scientific manner. She sits at the Wheel of Fortune and records when each number
comes up as the winning number. Suppose Vanna has recorded the following series
of winning numbers: 3, 6, 1 0, 1 9, 18, 4, 1 , 7, 7, 5, 20, 1 7, 2, 14, 1 9, 1 3, 8, 1 1 , 1 3, 1 6, 12,
15, 19, 3, 8. After examining these numbers very carefully, she proclaims that a 9 has
not appeared in the last 25 spins; therefore, she plans to bet heavily on number 9,
286 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

because it is now much more likely to occur. Would you agree with her that this is a
good bet?
If you responded "Yes," you have committed a very common error in under­
standing probability. The Wheel of Fortune has no memory for which numbers have
previously appeared. If the wheel had been built so that each number is equally
likely to win, then a 9 is equally likely on each spin, regardless of how frequently or
infrequently it appeared in the past. People believe that chance processes like spin­
ning a Wheel of Fortune should be self-correcting so that if an event has not
occurred in a while it is now more likely to occur. This misconception is called gam­
bler's fallacy.
Gambler's fallacy can be found in many settings. Consider a sports example. A
"slumping" batter who hasn't had a hit in a long while is sometimes believed to be
more likely to have a hit because he is "due" one. A sports enthusiast, who is a friend
of mine, told me the following story about Don Sutton, a former pitcher for the
Dodgers. One season, Sutton gave up a great many runs. He predicted that this
"slump" would be followed by a "correction" so that he would end up the season at
his usual average. Unfortunately, there is no correction for chance factors and, because
he had such a poor start to the season, he ended the season below his usual average.
Often, people will continue to believe in gambler'S fallacy even after it has been
explained to them. Students have told me that although they can understand on an
intellectual level why gambler'S fallacy must be wrong, on an intuitive or "gut"
level, it seems that it ought to be right. Understanding probability often requires
that we go against our intuitive hunches because they are often wrong. Let's try an­
other example.
Wayne and Marsha have four sons. Although they really don't want to have five
children, both have always wanted a daughter. Should they plan to have another
child, because they are now more likely to have a daughter, given that their first
four children were boys? If you understand gambler's fallacy, you'll recognize that a
daughter is as likely as a son on the fifth try, just as it was on each of the first four.
(Actually, because slightly more boys than girls are born, the probability of having a
boy baby is slightly higher than the probability of having a girl baby.)
Gambler's fallacy also has a flip side, the belief that random events run in streaks.
Consider the following two scenarios:

A. A basketball player has just missed 2 or 3 of the last shots in a row. She is about
to shoot again.
B. A basketball player has just made 2 or 3 of the last shots in a row. She is about
to shoot again.

Is she more likely to make the basket in A or B?


Gilovich (1991) asked questions like this one to knowledgeable basketball fans
and found that 91 % believed that the player was more likely to be successful in B
than in A. In other words, they believed that players shoot in streaks. In order to de­
termine whether there is any evidence to support the "belief in streaks," Gilovich
analyzed data from the Philadelphia 76ers. He found:

• If a player just made a shot, 51 % of the next shots were successful.


• If a player just missed a shot, 54% of the next shots were successful.
• If a player made two shots in a row, 50% of the next shots were successful.
• If a player missed two shots in a row, 53% of the next shots were successful.
SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITY 287

These data show no evidence that players shoot in streaks. Yet, interviews with
the 76ers players themselves showed that they believe that they shot in streaks. It is
very difficult to convince people that chance is exactly that-it doesn't self-correct or
run in nonrandom streaks.

Base-Rate Neglect

Charlie is anxious to experience his first kiss. lf he asks Louise to go to the movies
with him, he's only 10% sure that she'll accept his invitation, but if she does, he's
95% sure that she'll kiss him goodnight. What are Charlie's chances for romance?
Initial or a priori probabilities are called the base rate. In this problem, the first
hurdle that Charlie has to "get over" is getting Louise to go out with him. The prob­
ability of this occurring is 10%. It is important to think about this figure-the base
rate. Ten percent is a fairly low value, so it is likely that she will not go out with him.
He wants to know the probability of two uncertain events occurring-she both goes
out with him and she kisses him. Before we start to solve this problem think about
the kind of answer you would expect. Will it be greater than 95%, between 95% and
10%, or less than 10%?
To solve this problem, we'll use a tree diagram to depict the possible outcomes
and the probability associated with each. Of course, it is not likely that Charlie or
any other Romeo-wanna-be will actually compute the probability values or draw a
tree diagram for determining the probability of this momentous event, but this ex­
ample demonstrates how likelihoods combine. Maybe he'll decide that the probabil­
ity of a kiss from Louise is so small that he'll opt for Brunhilda, who is both more
likely to accept his offer of a date and succumb to his romantic charms. Besides, any­
one who has actually estimated probability values for romance might also want to
be more precise in his estimates of two or more events.
We'll start with a tree diagram that first branches into "Louise accepts his date"
and "Louise declines." A second branch will be drawn from the Louise accepts his
date node indicating whether he gets kissed or not. Each branch should have the ap­
propriate probability labels. Of course, if Louise declines his invitation, Charlie defi­
nitely won't get kissed. The branch from the "Louise declines" node is thus labeled
1 .00 for "Charlie doesn't get kissed."

Charlie gets kissed

Louise Charlie doesn't get kissed


Accepts

start Charlie doesn't get kissed

According to the "and rule" for finding the probability of two (or more) events,
the probability that Louise will kiss Charlie goodnight is:
.10 X .95 = .095
Are you surprised to find that the objective probability is less than the low base
rate of 10% and much less than the higher secondary or subsequent rate of 95%?
288 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

Most people are. Hopefully, you recognized that any value greater than 10% would
have been indicative of a conjunction error. Recall from the earlier section on con­
junction errors that the probability of two uncertain events both occurring (Louise
accepts and kisses Charlie) must be less than the probability of either event alone.
Most people ignore (or underestimate) the low base rate and estimate their answer
as closer to the higher secondary rate. In general, people tend to overestimate the
probability of two or more uncertain events occurring. This type of error is known
as base-rate neglect. Of course, in real life, estimates of probabilities for events like
having a date accept your invitation and then the probability that she or he will kiss
you are not very exact, so it may be a bit of a stretch to ask poor Charlie, in this
example, to compute the combined probabilities of both of these events actually hap­
pening. Other situations in which probabilities are calculated from population val­
ues, like the "probability of getting malaria if you travel in a tropic country during a
rainy summer" and the "probability of having a reaction to malaria medicine" may
be a more realistic example where you might want to calculate joint probabilities.
But, in either case, it is important to understand that, if one event occurs rarely, the
likelihood of that event plus another one will be even less than the rare one alone.

MAKING PROBABILISTIC DECISIONS

Most of the important decisions that we make in life involve probabilities. Although
decision making is discussed more fully in Chapter 8, let's consider how tree dia­
grams can be an aid for decision making.
Edith is trying to decide on a college major. She attends a very selective univer­
sity that has independent admissions for each of its majors. She is seriously thinking
about becoming an accountant. She knows that the accounting department accepts
25% of the students who apply for that major. Of those accepted, 70% graduate and
90% of those who graduate pass the national accounting examination and become
accountants. She would like to know what her chances are of becoming an accoun­
tant if she pursues the accounting major.
To answer this question, draw a tree diagram with branches that represent the
"path" for success in accounting.

passes national exam

doesn't pass
graduates national exam
. 30

Accepted
doesn't
graduate
Applies to
Not Probability (successfu l
Accounting
Accepted accou ntant/ =
.25 x . 70 x .90 = . 1 58

From the preceding diagram, you can see that the probability of becoming a suc­
cessful accountant is equal to .25 X .70 X .90, which is .158. At this point, Edith
might want to consider other options. For example, she could consider applying to
both the accounting major and to the education major. She could recalculate her
chances for success in one of these majors, both of these majors (if this is a possible
option for her), and neither of these majors.
MAKING PROBABILISTIC DECISIONS 289

This example assumes that we have no additional information on which to base


Edith's chances of success. Suppose instead that we know that Edith has excellent
math skills. Shouldn't this sort of information change the probabilities involved and
make it more likely that Edith be admitted, graduate, and succeed in a math-related
occupation? Intuitively, the answer is "yes." Let's see how the problem changes by
considering Jose's probability for success in the following example.

Combining Information to Make Predictions

Jose has always wanted to be an actor. Accordingly, he plans to sell his worldly pos­
sessions and head for a career in the "Big Apple" (the loving nickname for New
York). Suppose that you and Jose both know that only about 4% of all aspiring ac­
tors ever "make it" professionally in New York. This value is the base rate; it is
based on information that is known before we have any specific information about
Jose. Stop and think about this figure-the base rate. It tells us that very few aspir­
ing actors become professionals in this field. In other words, the chance of success is
low. Suppose that you had no additional information about Jose. What value would
you predict as his chance of success? If you said 4%, right on! In the absence of any
other information, use the base rate.
Jose tells you not to worry, because 75% of those who are successful have curly
hair and can sing and tell jokes well. Because he has curly hair, is a good singer, and
is a hilarious comedian, he feels confident that he will soon be sending 8 X 10 glossy
pictures of himself to his fan club members. This second value is called the
secondary; it is the probability value that relates specific information about charac­
teristics that are associated with Jose and with an outcome. We'll use these two prob­
ability values to decide if Jose's optimism is warranted. Exactly how likely is he to
succeed? Before you continue, make a probability estimate for his chance of success.
Remember, probabilities range from 0 to I, with 0 meaning he will definitely fail and
have to return to Peoria, and 1 meaning he will definitely succeed on Broadway.
Stop now and make a subjective probability judgment of his chance for success.
Can you think of a way of objectively finding his chance of success? In order to ar­
rive at an objective probability, you'll need to know another number, one that is
often ignored-the percentage of those who fail and have the attributes that are asso­
ciated with success (in this case, curly hair and the ability to sing, dance, and joke).
Few people realize that they need to consider this value in assessing the probability
of success. For ease of reference, I'll call the attributes that are associated with success
(curly hair, ability to sing and tell jokes) "curly hair," and the absence of these attrib­
utes, I'll call "not curly hair." Suppose that 50% of those who fail have these attrib­
utes. Once again, tree diagrams can be used to determine probabilities in this
context. Let's begin at a starting point and consider all possible outcomes. In this case,
he will either succeed or fail, so we'll label the first branches "succeed" and "fail." As
before, we'll put the probability of each event along the appropriate branch:

�t>.
. succeed

. 96

fail
start
290 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

These two probabilities (.04 and .96) sum to 1 .0, because they include all possibili­
ties. One of these two possibilities must occur, so they will add up to 1 .0 to indicate
absolute certainty.
Jose knows that 75% of those who succeed have curly hair. In this example, what
we are trying to find is the probability of a certain outcome (success) given that we
already have information that is relevant to the probability of that outcome. Let's
add a second branch to the tree diagram, branching off from the succeed node and
the fail node. There are four different probabilities involved in this example: the
probability of succeeding and having curly hair, the probability of succeeding and
not having curly hair, the probability of failing and having curly hair, and the prob­
ability of failing and not having curly hair. These four possibilities are shown in the
next tree diagram.

p (succeedlcurly hair)

.25
p (succeedlnot curly hair)
succeed

p (fail lcurly hair)

p (faillnot cu rly hair)


start

Because 75% (.75) of those who succeed have curly hair, and 25% (.25) do not
have this attribute, the sum of all probabilities from a tree node must sum to 1 .0.
Similarly, 50% of those who fail have curly hair, whereas 50% of those who fail do
not possess this attribute. Because we are considering everyone who fails, these val­
ues must also sum to 1 .0.
Once the tree diagram is drawn, it is a simple matter to compute Jose's objective
probability of success. As before, multiply along each branch to find the probabili­
ties. In this case, we would multiply the values along each branch of the tree dia­
gram and compile the information in a chart:

P[Succeed & Curly Hair] = .04 X .75 = .03


P[Succeed & Not Curly Hair] = .04 X .25 = .01
P[Fail & Curly Hair] = .96 X .50 = .48
P[Fail & Not Curly Hair] = .96 X .50 = .48
1 .0000

To determine Jose's true chance of success, we need to divide the proportion who
succeed and have curly hair (.03) by the total proportion who have curly hair (.48 +
.03= .51). We are trying to predict Jose's success based on the knowledge that he has
curly hair and that some proportion of all people with curly hair are successful. Of
all of those with curly hair (.51), what proportion of them succeed (.03)?
Proportion who succeed and curly hair .03
---::-=----....,.-
..- ---,-------=-:--,-
- - = -- = . 06
Total proportion of people with curly hair .03 +.48
MAKING PROBABILISTIC DECISIONS 29 1

Thus, Jose's chances for success are 50% higher (6% vs. 3%) than they are for any
unknown, aspiring actor, but they are still very low. Knowing that he has certain at­
tributes that are associated with success improved his probability of success above
the base rate, but the improvement was very small.
You may find it easier to follow the logic of these calculations by putting the in­
formation in a table format.

Succeed Fail Row Totals


Curly hair, etc. 0.03 0.48 0.51
No curly hair, etc. 0.01 0.48 0.49
Column Total 0.04 0.96 1 .00

Are you surprised to find that his chance of success is so low given that the poste­
rior or secondary probability value was so high (75%)? Most people are. The reason
that Jose has such a slim chance of becoming an actor is because so few people, in
general, succeed. The probability value Jose obtained was close to the a priori, or
base rate, of success among all aspiring actors. Because so few actors, in general,
succeed, Jose, and any other would-be thespian, has a low chance for success. In
general, most people overestimate success when base rates are low and underesti­
mate success when base rates are high. In the earlier example concerning Edith, we

© © © © ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
FIG. 7.5. Pictorial representation of a 4% success rate. Note that 4% of the faces are
smiling, which represents the base rate-4% of all aspiring actors succeed. If we had no
personal information about Jose, his expected probability of success would be 4%.
292 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

had only base-rate information to use in predicting success. By contrast, we had ad­
ditional information about Jose that allowed us to improve upon the base rate when
predicting his success, although because of the low rate of success for actors in gen­
eral, the improvement was slight.
For those of you who prefer to think spatially or think in terms of frequencies in­
stead of probabilities, think about a group of 100 people, 4 of whom are successful
actors (4%) and 96 are not (96%). This group is shown in Fig. 7.5. Four of the 100
"people" depicted are smiling-these represent the successful actors. If you had no
other information to use to predict success for Jose, you would use this base-rate in­
formation and give him a 4% probability for success.
Now let's consider the additional information. Three of the four of those who are
shown smiling have curly hair (3/4 or 75%); whereas, half (50%) of those who are
not smiling have curly hair. This information is combined with the base-rate infor­
mation. It is depicted in Fig. 7.6 with the addition of curly hair to the successful and
unsuccessful actors. Of the 4 smiling faces, 3 have curly hair (75%), and of the 96
frowning faces, 48 (50%) have curly hair.
By examining these figures, it should be easy to see that what we are doing math­
ematically is finding the proportion of smiling faces with curly hair relative to all of

© � � � ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ® ®
FIG. 7.6. Pictorial representation of the relative proportion of successful and unsuccessful
actors who have the same attributes of Jose. These are depicted by the addition of curly hair.
When we use personalized information to make predictions, we form a fraction of the
proportion of those who are successful and have the attribute (smiling and curly hair) over the
total proportion who have the attribute (curly hair). In this case, 3 smiling faces with curly
hair form the numerator and the 51 faces that have curly hair form the denominator.
MAKING PROBABILISTIC DECISIONS 293

the faces with curly hair in order to use this information about Jose to predict his
success. Graphically, this is 3 smiling faces with curly hair as a proportion (or frac­
tion) of the 51 faces that have curly hair:

3/51 "" 0.06

To review, when you are calculating the probability of an outcome, given that you
have information that is relevant to its probability, you will:

1 . Draw a complete tree diagram, with the base-rate information (e.g., success or
failure) as the first set of nodes. Use the secondary information to draw the
second set of nodes.
2. Make a chart with all combinations of the base-rate information and secondary
information as the rows in the chart.
3. Multiply probabilities across each of the branches of the tree diagram and fill
in each row of the chart with these values.
4. Form a ratio (fraction) with the probability value from the branch that you are
interested in (e.g., success given that he has curly hair) as the numerator and
the sum of this value and the other branch that contains the same conditional
statement (e.g., failure given that he has curly hair).
5. Check your answer. Does it make sense? Would you expect, as in this exam­
ple, that the probability of success is higher than the base rate because we
know something about the individual that is associated with success? (If we
knew that Jose had some trait that was associated with failure, we would pre­
dict that his chance of success would be less than the base rate, but with low
base rates, it probably won't be much less.)

Let's try a more realistic example: There are many diseases that occur with low
base rates in the population. Medical test results must be interpreted in light of the
relevant base rates for each disease. Medicine, like most other disciplines, is a proba­
bilistic science, yet few physicians receive training in understanding probabilities.
Failure to utilize base-rate information can lead to improper diagnoses. Base-rate
neglect is a pervasive error in thinking about probabilistic outcomes. Consider Dre­
man's (1979) summary of a large body of research on this effect: "The tendency to
underestimate or altogether ignore past probabilities in making a decision is un­
doubtedly the most significant problem of intuitive predictions in fields as diverse
as financial analysis, accounting, geography, engineering, and military intelligence.
The implications of such consistent errors and cognitive biases are enormous, not
only in economics, management, and investments, but in virtually every area where
such decision-making comes into play" (cited in Myers, 1995, p. 278).

Thinking With Frequencies


A common response to problems like the one with Jose is that the problem is too
difficult. In fact, even though many physicians have to interpret laboratory tests
where the information is similar to that in the Jose problem, many the physicians
admit that they do not understand how they can use probability information to
make important decisions about the health of their patients. Many people find it eas­
ier to think about probabilities in situations like this one by imaging frequencies
(Gigerenzer & Hoffrage, 1995; Lovett & Schunn, 1999). Here is a real-life example
294 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

that was used by Gigerenzer and his colleagues who looked for ways to make com­
puting probability information easier to understand. Everyone was given the same
opening paragraph:

To facilitate early detection of breast cancer, women are encouraged from a particular age
on to participate at regular intervals in routine screening, even if they have no obvious
symptoms. Imagine you conduct in a certain region such a breast cancer screening using
mammography. For symptom free women aged 40 to 50 who participate in screening
using mammography, the following information is available for this region:

After reading this paragraph, half of the physicians in the study were given the
probability format and half were given the frequency format. Here is the same infor­
mation in two different formats (Gigerenzer & Hoffrage, 1995).

Probability Format: The probability that one of these women has breast cancer is 1 %. If a
woman has breast cancer, the probability is SO% that she will have a positive mammography
test. If a woman does not have breast cancer, the probability is 10% that she will still have a
positive mammography test. Imagine a woman (aged 40 to 50, no symptoms) who has a
positive mammography test. What is the probability that she actually has breast cancer?
_____ ? (fill in your answer)
Frequency Format: Ten out of every 1 ,000 women have breast cancer. Of these 10 women
with breast cancer, S will have a positive mammography test. Of the remaining 990
women without breast cancer, 99 will still have a positive mammography test. Imagine a
sample of women (aged 40 to 50, no symptoms) who have positive mammography tests.
How many of these women actually have breast cancer? ___ out of ? ___

How did you go about answering these questions?


For the probability format:

� Cancer
Has cancer
Lab test shows

.01
cancer
X .80= .OOS
Lab test does not
show cancer
.01 X .20= .002
Row Totals
.01
Does not have cancer .99 X .10 .099
= .99 X .90 = .891 .99
Column Totals .107 .S93 1.00

.008
Probability: has cancer given that/test shows "has cancer" = = 7.5%
.008 + .099

Frequency: number who have cancer and positive test = � = 7.5'10


Number with positive test 1 07

The researchers found that when this information was given in the probability for­
mat only 10% of the physicians could reason correctly, but when the information
was given in the frequency format, 46% reasoned correctly. The ability to combine
probability information is an important thinking skill-decisions about treatment
options depend on how people understand numbers. With practice, we can all think
better with numbers. (Additional problems are shown in the workbook, Thinking
Critically About Critical Thinking, that accompanies this text.)
MAKING PROBABILISTIC DECISIONS 295

Nonregressive Judgments

Harris is a new student at Rah-Rah State University. The average grade point aver­
age (GP A) for all students at Rah-Rah is 2.8. Harris is new to this college and has not
yet taken any exams. Although we have no information about Harris specifically,
what would be your best guess that his grade point average will be?
Stop here and make your best guess for his grade point average.
After his first set of midterm exams, Harris has a midterm GPA of 3.8. Given this
new information, what would you now predict for Harris' GPA at the end of the
school year? Most people readily answer the first question with 2.8, the average
GPA for all students at Rah-Rah. This is a correct answer, as in the absence of any
specific information, the average for all students, the population at Rah-Rah, is the
best estimate for anyone. Most people answer the second question with 3.8. Unfor­
tunately, this is not the best answer. Although it is true that someone who scores
high on midterms will also tend to score high on finals, the relationship is not a one­
to-one or perfect relationship. In general, when someone scores extremely high on
some scale, she or he will score closer to the average the second time. Thus, the best
prediction for Harris' GPA at the end of the school year will be less than 3.8 and
greater than 2.8. (The actual value can be mathematically determined, but the calcu­
lations are beyond the scope of this book.) This is a difficult concept to understand,
because most people find it to be counterintuitive.
It may be useful to think about a sports example. Consider your favorite athletes.
Although they may have a truly exceptional performance one day, most often they
will perform closer to average, but still above average on other days. After all, no
one bowls all perfect games or bats 1 ,000. Sports enthusiasts will recognize this prin­
ciple as the "sophomore slump." After an outstanding first year at a sport, the star
will usually perform closer to average during her second year. Another example
that may help to clarify the concept is an often-used one about fathers' and sons'
heights. In general, very tall fathers will have sons that are closer to average
height (although still above average) than the fathers are. This phenomenon is called
regression toward the mean. (Mean is just another term for average-it is com­
puted by adding up all the values you're interested in and dividing by the number
of values.)
Earlier in this chapter, I talked about the laws of chance. No one can predict accu­
rately the height of any particular individual. But, in the long run-that is, with
many, many extremely tall fathers-most of their sons' heights will show regression
toward the mean. Thus, as before, we can make better predictions by knowing about
the laws of chance, but we won't always be accurate. It is important to understand
this concept whenever dealing with probabilistic events.
Kahneman and Tversky (1973) studied what can happen when regression toward
the mean is not understood by professionals. Israeli flight instructors were told that
they should praise their students when they successfully performed difficult flight
patterns and maneuvers and that they should criticize exceptionally poor perfor­
mance. Based on what you've just learned about regression toward the mean, what,
in general, should happen after a pilot performs extremely well? Subsequent ma­
neuvers should be closer to average, or less than exceptional, because the perfor­
mance moved or regressed toward the mean (average). Conversely, what should
you expect to happen following very poor performance? Again, subsequent maneu­
vers should tend to be more average, or in this case, they would improve, although
they may still be less than average. The Israeli flight instructors did not understand
296 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

regression toward the mean and erroneously concluded that praise led to poorer
performance and criticism improved it.
Let's consider another example of regression to the mean. Regression to the mean
is ubiquitous, yet few people ever recognize it. Suppose that you learn of a self-help
group for people with children who seriously misbehave. (There really are such
groups.) Most parents will enter these groups when their child's behavior is at its
worst because most parents will seek help only when the behavior is extremely bad.
After a few weeks in the program, many parents report an improvement in their
child's behavior. Can we conclude that the program probably worked to help par­
ents control their children's behavior? Think regression to the mean! If parents en­
tered the program when the behavior is extremely bad, then no matter what they
do, including nothing at all, the child's behavior will most likely regress toward the
mean. In other words, if a child is extremely misbehaved, it is statistically true that
the child will move toward the average on measures of behavior. We would not pre­
dict angelic or even average behavior, just some improvement or movement toward
the mean. Because this is a statistical prediction, sometimes, we will be wrong, but
on the average and in the long run, we will be right with this prediction. Thus, we
cannot conclude anything about the effectiveness of this program unless we conduct
a true experiment of the sort that was described in the last chapter. We might ran­
domly assign children and families to these groups and to "no-treatment control
groups" and then determine if the children in the self-help group were significantly
better behaved than those who received no treatment. We must be able to randomly
assign families to groups before we can conclude that the self-help group was help­
ful in improving the child's behavior. Once you start looking for regression to the
mean, you will be surprised how many events in life are best explained by "moving
toward the average" and not to other causes.

RISK

If we examine data from thousands of communities around the United States or


around the world, we will find that some communities have exceptionally high rates
of some sorts of cancers, birth defects, brain tumors, unexplained deaths, and other
maladies. How can we know if there are links between these high rates of illness
and toxic substances such as pesticides in the water, magnetic fields from electrical
power lines, or chance?
The notion of frequency, or how often an event occurs, is inherent in the defini­
tion of probability. If an event is frequent, then its occurrence is highly probable. To
determine the risk involved with a disastrous event, we need first to determine the
frequency with which it occurs. Because most disastrous events are rare (e.g., plane
crashes, leaks from nuclear plants) and, in some cases, take years before they are ev­
ident (e.g., cancers from environmental hazards), determining their frequency is a
very difficult task. To understand how people make judgments involving risks, we
need to understand how they determine the frequency of real-life risky events. Sev­
eral researchers (Lichtenstein et al., 1978) have focused on the way people judge the
frequency of lethal (deadly) events. They studied these phenomena by asking
college students and members of the League of Women Voters to decide which of
two possible causes of death is more probable for several pairs of lethal events. To
understand their experiment and their results, let's try a few examples. For the
RISK 297

following pairs of items, indicate which is the more likely cause of death, and then
estimate how much more likely your choice is than the other event:

A. Asthma or Tornado
B. Excess Cold or Syphilis
C. Diabetes or Suicide
D. Heart Disease or Lung Cancer
E. Flood or Homicide
F. Syphilis or Diabetes
G. Asthma or Botulism
H. Poisoning by Vitamins or Lightning
I. Tuberculosis or Homicide
J. All Accidents or Stomach Cancer

Researchers found that although, in general, people were more accurate as the
differences in the true frequencies of occurrence between the events increased, they
made a large number of errors in estimating the relative frequencies of the events.
Their subjects overestimated the frequencies of events that occurred very rarely and
underestimated the frequencies of those events that occurred very often. In addi­
tion, lethal events that had received a great deal of publicity (e.g., airplane crashes,
flood, homicide, tornado, botulism) were overestimated, whereas those that were
undramatic, silent killers (e.g., diabetes, stroke, asthma, tuberculosis) were underes­
timated. It seems that publicized events were more easily brought to mind and this
biased judgments of their frequency. Hazards that are unusually memorable, such
as a recent disaster or an event depicted in a sensationalized way on the news like a
major plane crash or botulism in undercooked hamburgers, distort our perceptions
of risk. This was clear when a few incidents of shootings in high schools in the
United States was immediately followed by anxious parents who took their children
out of public high schools and enrolled them in private schools. Of course, the
shooting death of high school students was extremely tragic, but these same parents
would allow their children to drive when they were sleepy or never instructed them
about ways to prevent sexually transmitted diseases, both of which are far more
likely to occur than a school shooting. The more salient events were perceived to be
the greater risk than the less publicized but more likely dangers of an automobile
accident or sexually transmitted disease. In Chapter 2, I made the point that mem­
ory is an integral component of all thinking processes. What we remember is a
major influence on how we think. The importance of being mindful of possible bi­
ases in memory when evaluating thought processes is seen in this quote:
. . . our society most often makes judgments about hazardous activities for which ade­
quate statistical data is lacking, such as recombinant DNA research or nuclear waste
disposal. We suspect that the biases found here (overestimation of rare events, underes­
timation of likely events, and an undue influence of drama or vividness) may be operat­
ing, indeed, may even be amplified in such situations. (Lichtenstein et al., 1978, p. 577)

It is not surprising that we tend to overestimate the probability of events that re­
ceive excessive coverage in the media. We rely on the information that is available to
us to make decisions, and we are usually not aware when that information is biased
or sensationalized (Fischhoff, 1993). Homicides are routinely part of every news
broadcast and every newspaper; deaths from heart disease or automobile accidents
are rarely mentioned in these contexts because they are far too common.
298 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

Assessing Risks

How do the experts make decisions that involve potentially disastrous outcomes?
How can we as informed citizens and voters make less risky decisions? Questions
like these are timely, but not easy to answer.
The goal of risk assessment is to find ways to avoid, reduce, or manage risks
(Wilson & Crouch, 1987). Risk is associated with every aspect of life. For example, ap­
proximately 200 people are electrocuted each year in accidents involving home
wiring or appliances, and 7,000 people die each year in U.S. homes as a result of falls
(most of these people are over 65). Yet, few of us would interpret these risks as great
enough either to forgo electricity or stop walking in our homes. Other risks are clearly
too large to take. Few of us, for example, would decide to cross a busy freeway wear­
ing a blindfold. And still other risks are largely unknown, such as the release of a new
chemical into the environment or the development of a new technology. Wilson and
Crouch (1987) suggested several ways of estimating risks that voters and consumers
should consider when deciding if an action or a technology is safe enough:

1 . One method of risk assessment involves examining historical data. For exam­
ple, to understand the risk of cancer due to exposure to medical X-rays, there
are data that indicate that for a given dose per year (40 mrem) there is an ex­
pected number of cancers (1,100). This sort of risk information can be com­
pared to other known risks so that consumers can decide if the benefits of
medical X-rays outweigh the risks.
2. The risk of a new technology for which there are no historical data can be com­
puted when the occurrence of the events are independent by calculating the
risk of separate components and multiplying along the branches of a decision
tree. This method of calculating probabilities was presented in an earlier sec­
tion of this chapter. A well-known example is the probability of a severe acci­
dent at a chemical plant.
3. Risks can also be calculated by analogy. (The use of analogies as an aid to
problem solving is discussed more fully in the following two chapters.) When
animals are used to test drugs, the experimenter is really using an analogy to
extrapolate the risk to humans.

Biases in Risk Assessment

Psychologists and others who study the way people determine if something is "too
risky" know that most of us fall prey to common biases when we assess the "murky
psychometrical stew" (Paulos, 1994, p. 34) that constitutes the numerical informa­
tion and misinformation that we need to interpret. Here are some common biases
(Wandersman & Hallman, 1993):

1. When a risk is voluntary, it is perceived to be less risky than one that is not
voluntary. For example, cosmetic surgery is often believed to be safer than a
nonelective surgery. After all, patients choose to undergo cosmetic surgery, so
they must rationalize that it is "safe enough."
2. Natural risks are believed to be less hazardous than artificial ones. For exam­
ple, many people believe that naturally occurring toxins in our food are less
RISK 299

dangerous than ones that are caused by pesticides or preservatives that are
added.
3. Memorial events in which many people are harmed at once are perceived as
riskier than more mundane and less vivid events. An example of this effect is
the large number of people who are terrified of plane crashes, but give little
thought to automobile safety.
4. Events over which we have some perceived control are believed to be safer
than those over which we don't have control. Most people tend to feel safer
when they are driving an automobile than when others are driving because
most of us believe that we are better-than-average drivers.
5. Phenomena that are not observable and are associated with spectacular
dreaded outcomes (DNA technology, radioactive waste, AIDS, and nuclear re­
actors) are believed to be riskier than phenomena that involve known risks or
less dreaded outcomes (smoking, auto accidents, dynamite, and handguns;
Slovic, 1987).

It is clear that personal risk perceptions are not the same as scientific risk esti­
mates. Experts in risk assessment perceive risks based on annual mortality so that
the event that results in the greater number of deaths is judged to be the greater risk.
Experts, for example, ranked motor vehicles as riskier than nuclear power (because
more people are expected to die from motor vehicle accidents); whereas, samples
of college students and members of the League of Women Voters ranked nu­
clear power as the greater risk (because it is an example of a spectacular dreaded
outcome).
A major difficulty in interpreting low-probability risks like flood or a nuclear acci­
dent is that the figures involved are not readily meaningful. Knowing that a particu­
lar risky event occurs in 1 in 10,000 individuals is difficult to interpret. We need to be
able to convert this information into an answer to the question, "Is this likely to hap­
pen to me?" One suggestion for making this sort of information more meaningful is
to convert all such risks to a standard "risk per hour" metric (Slavic, Fischhoff, &
Lichtenstein, 1986). For example, suppose you learned that the risk involved in tak­
ing a motorcycle trip is the same as the risk of being 75 years old for 1 hour. Would
this type of information be helpful in interpreting the risk of a motorcycle trip in a
meaningful way? Although information of this sort might be useful for judging
comparative risk (motorcycle trip compared to hang gliding), it may not be useful
by itself because it is still difficult to understand what is meant by the risk of being
75 years old for 1 hour.
As voters and as consumers we face countless decisions about a large and diverse
array of topics, which include nuclear energy, food irradiation, surgical procedures,
air and water quality, and drug use. An informed decision will always require
careful consideration of the information that is relevant to risk assessment (e.g., his­
torical data, risk by analogy, and risks of separate components) as well as an under­
standing of the way subjective estimates of risk are biased.
Here are the answers to the questions about the probability of lethal events we
follow along with the true frequency of each event (rate per 1 00,000,000). Check
your answer and see if you made the common errors of overestimating events that
are more memorable and likely to affect many people at one time (like a plane crash)
and underestimating those risks over which we believe we have some control (like
driving an automobile).
300 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

More Likely Rate Less Likely Rate


A. Asthma 920 Tornado 44
B. Syphilis 200 Excess Cold 163
C. Diabetes 19,000 Suicide 12,000
D. Heart Disease 360,000 Lung Cancer 37,000
E. Homicide 9,200 Flood 100
F. Diabetes 19,000 Syphilis 200
G. Asthma 920 Botulism 1
H. Lightning 52 Poisoning/Vitamins .5
I. Homicide 9,200 Tuberculosis 1 ,800
J. All Accidents 55,000 Stomach Cancer 46,600

STATISTICAL USE AND ABUSE

There are three kinds of lies: lies, damned lies, and statistics.
-Disraeli (1804-1881 )
When we want to find out something about a group o f people, i t i s often impossible
or inconvenient to ask everyone in the group. Suppose you want to know if people
who donate blood to the Red Cross are, in general, kind and generous people. Be­
cause you can't examine everyone who donates blood to determine how kind and
considerate she or he is, you would examine a portion of the population, which is
called a sample. A number calculated on a sample of people is called a statistic.
("Statistics" is also the branch of mathematics that utilizes probability theory to
make decisions about populations.)
Statistics are found everywhere, from baseball earned run averages to the num­
ber of war casualties. Many people are rightfully suspicious of statistics. A small
book by Huff (1954) humorously illustrates many of the possible pitfalls of statistics.
The book is entitled How to Lie With Statistics. In it, he rhymes the following mes­
sage: "Like the 'little dash of powder, little pot of paint,' statistics are making many
an important fact look like what she ain't" (p. 9). But, the real message is that you
won't be bamboozled with statistics if you understand them.

On the Average

What does it mean to say that the average American family has 2.1 children? This
number was computed by finding a sample of American families, adding up the
number of children they have and dividing by the total number of families in the
sample. This number could provide an accurate picture of American families, as
most may have about two children, with some having more and others less, or it
could be very misleading. It is possible that half of the families had no children and
half had four or more children, thus misleading the reader into believing that most
families had "about" two children, when in fact none did. This is like the man who
had his head in the oven and feet in the freezer and reports that, on the average, he's
quite comfortable. It is also possible that the sample used to calculate this statistic
was not representative of the population-in this case, all American families. If the
sample consisted of college students or residents in Manhattan, the number ob­
tained would be too low. On the other hand, if the sample was taken in rural farm
STATISTICAL USE AND ABUSE 30 1

areas, the number obtained may be too high. When samples are not representative
of the population, they are called biased samples. The statistics calculated on biased
samples will not yield accurate information about the population.
Averages can also be misleading, because there are three different kinds of aver­
ages. Consider Mrs. Wang's five children. The oldest is a successful corporate execu­
tive. She earns $500,000 a year. The second is a teacher who earns $25,000 a year.
Child 3 is a waiter who earns $15,000 a year. The other two are starving artists, each
earning $5,000 a year. If Mrs. Wang wants to brag about how well her children
turned out, she could compute an arithmetic average, which is called the mean. The
mean is what most people have in mind when they think about averages. It is the
sum of all of the values divided by the total number of values. The mean income for
Mrs. Wang's children is $550,000/5 = $110,000. Certainly, anyone who is told this
figure would conclude that Mrs. Wang has very successful and wealthy children.
The reason that the mean income for Mrs. Wang's children was so high is because
there is one extreme score that inflated this type of average. Averages are also called
measures of central tendency. A second kind of measure of central tendency is the
median. It is not affected by a few extreme scores. To compute the median, the val­
ues are lined up in ascending or descending order. The middle value is the median.
For Mrs. Wang's children, this would be:

$5,000; $5,000; $15,000; $25,000; $500,000.

The middle value, or median, is the third value of $15,000. Thus, she could also
claim that her children earn, on the average, $15,000. (When there is an even number
of values, the median is equal to the mean of the middle two values.)
Mrs. Wang can honestly claim that her children earn, on the average, $110,000 or
$15,000. The point of this discussion is that you should be wary of average figures.
To understand them, you need to know whether the average is a mean or median as
well as something about the variability of the data and the "shape" of the distribu­
tion (the way the numbers "stack up.").

Precision

Suppose I tell you that a scientific survey was conducted on the length of workdays
for office workers. Furthermore, this study found that the mean workday is 8.167
hours long. Does this sound impressive and scientific? What if I told you that most
office workers work about 8 hours a day? Most of you would say, "I know that.
Why did they bother?" The point is that we are often impressed with precise statis­
tics, even when the precision is unwarranted.
Let me give you an example from a prestigious weekly news magazine. It is im­
portant that the magazine readers accept the articles as truthful and authoritative. A
few years ago, a news magazine ran an article about the health hazards associated
with dog droppings in New York City. To give the reader an idea of the magnitude
of the problem, they presented the daily weight of New York City dog droppings in
pounds, accurate to two decimal places (the nearest .01 pound!). I have no idea how
they arrived at that figure, nor do I even want to think about how they collected
their data. I do know that they could not measure it that accurately. Of course, the
impression that is created with such precise statistics is that the news magazine is a
carefully researched journal that can be trusted for the information it provides.
302 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

A more humorous example of overprecision comes from one of America's most


famous authors, Mark Twain. He once reported that the Mississippi River was 100
million and 3 years old. It seems that 3 years earlier, he learned that it was 100 mil­
lion years old.

Significant Differences

If you wanted to know the mean height of all women, you could select a sample of
100 women, measure their height, and compute the mean. Suppose you took an­
other sample of 1 00 women and computed their mean height. Would you expect the
means of these two samples to be exactly the same? No, of course not, because there
could be expected to be small differences or fluctuations between these values. Each
value was computed on different women, and each will yield a slightly different
mean value.
If someone measured a sample of women who belong to sororities and found
that their mean height is 5'5" and then measured women who don't belong to soror­
ities and found their mean height to be 5'4 1 /2", would you conclude that sorority
sisters are taller than nonsorority women? I hope not, because small differences be­
tween groups can be expected to occur just by chance, especially when the sample
size, or number of people in the sample, is small. There are statistical procedures to
determine if a difference computed on two or more samples is likely to have hap­
pened by chance. If it is very unlikely to be a chance occurrence, it is called a signifi­
cant difference.
The question of whether a change is meaningful also applies to populations as
well. If your college enrollment went from 15,862 to 15,879, would the administra­
tors be justified in concluding that the increase in enrollment is meaningful? The an­
swer to this question depends on many other variables. If the enrollment figure has
been edging up slowly every year for the last 5 years, then these figures may repre­
sent a slight, but steady, trend. On the other hand, the relatively small increase
could be due to chance fluctuations and may not represent a meaningful trend. Be­
cause of chance factors, it could just as easily have gone down. Similarly, a change in
the unemployment rate from 10.0% to 9.9% may be nothing more than random fluc­
tuation, or it may be signaling the end of an economic quagmire. You can expect
that Democrats and Republicans will interpret these figures differently depending
on who is in office at the time.

Extrapolation

Extrapolation occurs when a value is estimated by extending some known values. If


the number of psychology majors over the last 5 years at Podunck University was
approximately 1 50, 1 75, 200, 225, and 250, respectively, then most people would feel
comfortable about the prediction that the number of psychology majors next year
will be approximately 275.
Extrapolation can be wrong, and sometimes even ridiculous. For example, sup­
pose we were to examine the drop in the size of American families between 1900
and 1950. By extrapolation, we would predict that the average family size will soon
be zero, and then become a negative number. This is, of course, an inconceivable
idea! This is like saying that if the times for the 1 00-meter dash keep decreasing,
eventually someone will run it in zero seconds and then in negative time.
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 303

Bamboozled by Statistics

How can you turn pure fat in a concoction that is 96% fat-free? No, it's not magic; in
fact, it's easy. If you take two pats of butter and eat them, 100% of the calories are
from fat. But, if you drop the same two pats of butter into a glass of water and drink
this revolting concoction, then you have created a 96% fat-free drink (i.e., 96%
water)! You would ingest the same number of calories, all of them from fat, but the
96% fat-free drink sounds healthier.This is why products that are labeled "percent­
age fat-free" are bogus health foods labeled in a way that is intended to misinform
(Nutrition Action Newsletter, 1991).
Many of the statistics that we routinely rely upon are woefully wrong. Bozell
(1993) has questioned the accuracy of the data that we are given by the media. For
example, he cites a CBS reporter who warned that heterosexual AIDS increased by
30% in 1992 alone. But, according to Bozell, the Center for Disease Control reported
that heterosexual AIDS increased 17% in 1992, down from an increase of 21 % in
1991 . Similarly, he quotes an NBC news anchor, who claimed that right now in the
United States there are 5 million people who are believed to be homeless, yet the
Census Bureau in 1990 counted 220,000 homeless. These are big differences, but
how can we determine which of these statistics is closer to the truth?
First, it is important to develop the habit of questioning the statistics that we are
given. How were they collected and who collected them? It is difficult, for example,
to count accurately the number of homeless because they don't have convenient ad­
dresses or phones. How were the two estimates of this number derived? Did the
data collectors sample from downtown New York or from Salt Lake City? Do you
have any reason to believe that the data are being deliberately misused? For exam­
ple, a conservative political group with an obvious agenda, Concerned Women for
America, ran an advertisement in national newspapers in which they advocated a
ban on gays and lesbians in the military. In support of their position, they reported a
study that found "homosexual behavior to be promiscuous, compulsive, and uncon­
trollable" (quoted in Boxall, 1993, p. A18). The ad went on to claim that the "typical
homosexual" had at least 68 sex partners each year! Are you wondering where and
how this statistic was obtained? I hope so. The "study" was over a decade old that
deliberately sought highly promiscuous gay males and therefore is not representa­
tive of gays in general. If you question the statistics that you routinely are exposed
to, you are less likely to be misled by crooked statistics.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

Let's consider the steps in applying the general framework for thinking to under­
standing and using probabilities.

1. What Is the Goal'?


Whenever you are making decisions about uncertain events, you will need to
consider the skills developed in this chapter. This is particularly true whenever you
are given probability values or when degrees of belief are presented or implied. This
situation exists in most of the problems that we solve and decisions that we make
because they often involve future events that can never be known with certainty.
304 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

2. What Is Known?
In setting up the problem, you need to know if the probability values you are
being given were derived objectively or subjectively. You need to look for ways that
these values could be biased. Has the desirability of an outcome influenced the
probability values assigned to it? Although the topic of considering the credibility of
a source of information was presented in Chapter 5 on analyzing arguments, it is
also relevant in this context. Before you begin the process of using probabilities, you
need to assess the quality of the information that you have. Because we frequently
persuade others with probability values, you need to consider how the numbers
that are being presented relate to the argument that is being offered.
When determining what is known, look for information that can be used in com­
puting probability estimates. For example, if a probability of a risk is given, is it per
year, per exposure (e.g., X-ray), or per lifetime? Is there additional information
available that can be combined with base rates so that a more accurate prediction
can be made?

3. Which Thinking Skill or Skills


Will Get You to Your Goal?
Numerous thinking skills have been presented for use when working with proba­
bilistic events. One of the most useful is drawing a tree diagram complete
with probability values on each branch. This method allows you to "see" and objec­
tively compute the likelihood of multiple outcomes. When you are combining infor­
mation with base-rate information, it is important to form the appropriate ratios so
as to avoid the problem of base-rate neglect. Other skills require recognition of the
type of error that frequently occurs (e.g., conjunction error, failure to consider cu­
mulative risks) and use of the "or" and "and "rules to improve probabilistic deci­
sion making.
Because there are so few things in life that are known with certainty, the skills for
understanding and using probabilities should be used frequently. After reading this
chapter, you should be able to use the following skills:

• Compute expected values in situations with known probabilities.


• Recognize when regression to the mean is operating and adjust predictions to
take this phenomenon into account.
• Use the "and rule" to avoid conjunction errors.
• Use the "or rule" to calculate cumulative probabilities.
• Recognize and avoid gambler'S fallacy.
• Utilize base rates when making predictions.
• Use tree diagrams as a decision-making aid in probabilistic situations.
• Adjust risk assessments to account for the cumulative nature of probabilistic
events.
• Understand the differences among mean and median.
• Avoid overconfidence in uncertain situations.
• Understand the limits of extrapolation.
• Use probability judgments to improve decision making.
• Consider indicators like historical data, risks associated with different parts of
a decision, and analogies when dealing with unknown risks.
CHAPTER SUMMARY 305

4. Have You Reached Your Goa17


The reason for considering probabilities is to quantify and reduce uncertainty.
You will have reached your goal when you can attach more accurate probability val­
ues to uncertain events.

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Because few things are known with certainty, probability plays a crucial role in
many aspects of our lives.
2. Probability is defined as the number of ways a particular outcome (what
we call a success) can occur divided by the number of possible outcomes (when
all outcomes are equally likely). It is also used to indicate degrees of belief in
the likelihood of events with unknown frequencies and previous frequency of
occurrence.
3. In general, people tend to be more confident about uncertain events than the
objective probability values allow.
4. Mathematically equivalent changes in the way probability information is pre­
sented can lead to dramatic changes in the way it is interpreted.
5. Tree diagrams can be used to compute probabilities when there are multiple
events (e.g., two or more flips of a coin). When the events are independent, the prob­
ability of any combination of outcomes can be determined by multiplying the prob­
ability values along the tree "branches."
6. Expected values can be computed that will take into account the probabilities
and values associated with a loss and a win in betting situations.
7. Subjective probabilities are our personal estimates of how likely events with
unknown frequencies will occur. These values are distorted systematically when
people believe that they have some control over probabilistic events.
8. Most people fail to consider the cumulative nature of the likelihood of risky
events.
9. People judge events that are dramatic and more publicized to be more likely
than events that are less dramatic or less well known. In general, people overesti­
mate frequent events and underestimate infrequent ones.
1 0. There is a tendency to ignore base-rate information especially when making
predictions that involve combining information.
1 1 . Few people realize that if a person scores extremely high or low on one mea­
sure, she or he will tend to score closer to average on the second measure.
1 2. There are two measures of central tendency that are frequently used-the
mean and median. Each is computed with a different mathematical formula.
13. There are several systematic biases that operate when most people assess
risks. These include downgrading the probability of voluntary risks and those over
which we have some perceived control and overestimating risks that are artificial,
memorial, and unobservable.
14. Many people erroneously believe that statistics that are expressed in precise
numbers (e.g., many decimal places) are highly credible.
15. Extrapolation occurs when a value is estimated by extending a trend from
known values.
306 7. LIKELIHOOD AND UNCERTAINTY

TERMS TO KNOW

Check your understanding of the concepts presented in this chapter by reviewing


their definitions. If you find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to
reread the section where it is discussed.
Probability. The number of ways a particular event can occur divided by the num­
ber of possible outcomes (when all outcomes are equally likely). It is a measure of
how often we expect an event to occur in the long run. The term is also used to ex­
press degrees of belief and previous frequency of occurrence.
In the Long Run. Refers to the need for numerous trials in order to derive accurate
estimates of the proportion of outcomes that will be a "success."
Odds. A mathematical method for indicating probability that is commonly used in
sporting events.
Laws of Chance (or Probability). The ability to predict the number or percentage of
trials on which a particular outcome will occur.
Overconfidence Phenomenon. The tendency for people to be more confident in
their judgments of probability than the objective probability values allow.
Multiple Outcomes. Refers to the probability of an event occurring in two or more
trials such as getting two heads in two flips of a coin.
Tree Diagrams. Branching diagrams that may be used to compute probabilities by
considering all possible outcomes in a sequence of events.
Independent Events. Two or more events are independent when the occurrence of
one event does not affect the occurrence of the other events.
Conjunction Error. Mistaken belief that the co-occurrence of two or more events is
more likely than the occurrence of one of the events.
Cumulative Probabilities. The probability of an event occurring over many trials.
Expected Value. The amount of money you would expect to win in the long run in
a betting situation. The mathematical formula for determining expected values is
the probability of winning times the value of winning plus the probability of losing
times the value of losing.
Subjective Probability. Personal estimates of the probability or likelihood of uncer­
tain events.
Objective Probability. Mathematically determined statements about the likelihood
of events with known frequencies.
Gambler's Fallacy. The mistaken belief that chance events are self-correcting. Many
people erroneously believe that if a random event has not occurred recently, it
becomes more likely.
Base Rate. Initial or a priori probability that an event will occur.
Base-Rate Neglect. Pervasive bias to ignore or underestimate the effect of initial
probabilities (base rates) and to emphasize secondary probability values when de­
ciding on the likelihood of an outcome.
Regression Toward the Mean. In general, when someone scores extremely high or
low on some measure, she or he will tend to score closer toward the mean (average)
on a second measurement.
Sample. A subset of a population that is studied in order to make inferences about
the population.
Statistic. A number that has been calculated to describe a sample. (In its plural form
it is the branch of mathematics that is concerned with probabilities and mathemati­
cal characteristics of distributions of numbers.)
TERMS TO KNOW 307

Biased Sample. A sample that is not representative of the population from which it
was drawn.
Mean. A measure of central tendency that is calculated by taking the sum of all the
values divided by the total number of values. Also called the average.
Measures of Central Tendency. Numbers calculated on samples or populations
that give a single number summary of all of the values. Two measures of central ten­
dency are the mean and median.
Median. A measure of central tendency that is calculated by finding the middle
value in a set of scores.
Sample Size. The number of people selected for a study.
Significant Difference. A difference between two groups or observations that is so
large that it probably didn't occur by chance.
Extrapolation. The estimation of a value from a trend suggested by known values.
8

Decision Making

Contents
Making Sound Decisions Elimination by Aspects
A Framework for Decision Making Preparing a Worksheet
Good Decisions and Subjective Framing the Decision
Utility Generating the Alternatives
Descriptive and Prescriptive Listing the Considerations
Processes Weighing the Considerations
Pitfalls and Pratfalls in Decision Weighing the Alternatives
Making Calculating a Decision
Failure to Seek Disconfirming Overall Assessment
Evidence Dimensional Comparison
Overconfidence 2/3 Ideal Rule
Availability Heuristic The Problem with Numbers
Representativeness Heuristic Dilemmas in Decision Making
Wishful Thinking (Pollyanna Postdecision Commitment and
Principle) Evaluation
Entrapment Cognitive Dissonance
Psychological Reactance Foot-In-the-Door
Liking Hindsight and Forethought
Reciprocity Applying the Framework
Mere Exposure Effect Chapter Summary
Emotional States Terms to Know
Mindlessness
Evaluating Consequences
Assessing Desirable and Undesirable
Consequences

308
MAKING SOUND DECISIONS 309

Six doctors in white hospital coats approach your bed. No one is smiling. The results of
the biopsy are in. One doctor explains that the cells were irregular in shape; they ap­
peared abnormal. It seems that the tumor was not clearly malignant, but not clearly
normal either. They probably removed the entire tumor. It's hard to be certain about
these things. You have some choices. You could leave the hospital this afternoon and
forget about this unpleasant episode, except for semiannual checkups. There is an
above-average chance, however, that some abnormal cells remain and will spread and
grow. On the other hand, you could choose to have the entire area surgically removed.
Although this would be major surgery, it would clearly reduce the risk of cancer.

How do you decide what to do? Your first response is probably to ask the doctors what
they recommend. But if you do, it's likely that you won't receive a consensus of opin­
ion. Often physicians disagree about the best way to treat a disease, especially when
there are many options as in the case of complicated diseases like cancer or AIDS. It is
possible that some will believe that the risk of cancer is small enough to warrant the
wait-and-see decision (why rush to operate?); others will believe that immediate
surgery is the best decision (better safe than sorry). Ultimately, the decision is yours.
Of course, not all decisions are a matter of life and death. We are constantly mak­
ing minor decisions without much thought, such as what to wear, what to eat for
breakfast, which pen to buy, and when to go to sleep. Everyone is faced with a life­
time of decisions, and some of them have major and far-reaching consequences. In
this chapter we are concerned with life's major decisions. Major decisions include
medical decisions like the one at the beginning of this chapter, whether to marry,
whom to marry, if and when to have children, what kind of occupation to choose,
how to spend your hard-earned dollars, etc. These are all personal decisions that
virtually everyone has to make. We also must decide on a host of political and busi­
ness issues like whether to support off-shore drilling for oil, when to increase a com­
pany's inventory, which stock to invest in, how to negotiate a contract, which party to
support during political upheaval, and how to increase profits. In this chapter, you
will learn skills designed to help you make sound decisions. To accomplish this, we
look at the way psychologists and others study decision making, examine common
pitfalls and fallacies in the decision-making process, consider the risks involved, and
develop a general strategy or plan that you can use when faced with a major decision.
Decision making always involves making a choice among a set of possible alter­
natives. If you've read the previous chapters in this book, then you've already
encountered several sections on how to make intelligent choices. In Chapter 5 on an­
alyzing arguments, for example, you considered the way in which reasons support or
refute a conclusion. When analyzing arguments, you make many decisions about the
relevance and accuracy of information and how well the reasons that are provided
support an action or a belief. In Chapters 6 and 7 on hypothesis testing and using prob­
abilistic information, we learned about drawing tree diagrams, collecting information,
and computing likelihoods to make decisions. Because decision making is a central
theme in critical thinking, different aspects of it are presented throughout this book.

MAKING SOUND DECISIONS

Decisions per se, take place when a goal is specified, when information is
gathered and judged, when values are used to choose the best solution, and when
detailed plans are made and evaluated.
-Wales and Nardi (1984, p. 1 )
310 8. DECISION MAKING

The decision-making process is frequently stressful. Ask anyone you know who has
recently made an important decision and you will most likely be told about sleepless
nights, loss of appetite (or excessive eating), irritability, and generalized feelings of
anxiety. Autobiographical and biographical accounts of decision-making stress can
be found in the books written by and about several past presidents and many key fig­
ures in history. Theodore C. Sorensen (1965) in his book, Kennedy tells of the stress
John Kennedy faced during the Berlin blockade crisis, and a book written by Richard
M. Nixon before his presidency, appropriately titled Six Crises (1962), tells about the
stress caused by his early political decisions. More recently, the world watched as
U.s. President George W. Bush had to decide how to respond to the horrific attacks
on the World Trade Center in New York and the Pentagon in Washington, D.C. The
response had to have the effect of making similar attacks in the future much less
likely, and also conveying to the people of the world that it was a counterattack
against a terrorist group and not against a religious group. World leaders face crises
that can make our own personal crises look insignificant by comparison, although
they can feel just as difficult when our personal decisions will have important conse­
quences for ourselves and others we care about. Most of us can only imagine the
pressures involved when military or large-scale economic decisions have to be made.
It may seem that one way to cope with the stress of decision making is to avoid
making decisions whenever possible. Although avoidance is one way of handling
stressful decisions, it is seldom a good way. Every time you find yourself avoiding
a decision, remember that, in most cases, avoiding a decision is, in fact, making one
without any of the benefits of a carefully thought-out consideration of the problem.

A Framework for Decision Making

Results from past research have indicated that poor decisions with regard to
drugs, alcohol, and other issues involving personal risks often stem from poor
decision-making strategies.
-Knight and Dansereau (1992, p. 1 )
There is a common model o r framework that can be used to organize our thinking
about decision making. It will be extended in Chapters 9 and 1 0, which are
concerned with solving problems and thinking creatively. The three topics that
are discussed in these chapters-decision making, problem solving, and creative
thinking-have a great deal of overlap in the way they are conceptualized. Some­
times, the term "decision making" is used when the task requires the decision
maker to select the best alternative from among several possibilities, and the term
problem solving is used when the task requires the problem solver to generate alter­
natives. This sort of distinction is arbitrary, and in real life, it is often difficult to de­
cide if the task requires the generation of alternatives or the selection of alternatives.
This sort of distinction will not be used here because I do not believe that it is useful.
Take the time to examine Fig. 8.1 carefully. It contains the essential components
of a framework for understanding and improving decision making, problem solv­
ing, and creative thinking. In Fig. 8.1, the process of making a decision is depicted as
a series of boxes, each of which represents a different component, and several ar­
rows that show the recursive nature of the process. These boxes are set in a large
oval, which represents the context in which the decision is being made. The first
stage in making a decision is the identification or realization that a decision is
MAKlNG SOUND DECISIONS 31 1

Identification, Recognition, and


Framing of Decision

Generation of Alternatives Re-evaluation


- individual effects (knowledge Re-framing
values) Re-generation
- cognitive biases and
sociocultural biases

Context
- social factors (e.g., group approval)
- type of decision
- technicaVpersonal
- importance

FIG. 8. I . A multiprocess model of decision making. Each of the boxes represents a stage in
the decision-making process. The arrows show that the process is recursive with frequent
recycling through the stages (e.g., generating alternatives may be followed by reframing the
decision). The rectangular boundary represents the effects of context.

needed. This is followed by the generation of two or more alternatives that would
satisfy a goal or desired outcome that is implied by the decision. Usually each alter­
native has several pros and cons associated with it, or, in the language of decision
making, costs and benefits. The task for the decision maker is to choose the "best"
alternative. The consideration of what is "best" requires an evaluation phase in
which "best" often turns out to be multidimensional-best for whom? best by what
criteria? best in the immediate future or long term?
Decisions also involve uncertainty because we cannot know in advance the con­
sequences of our actions. Much of the difficulty when making decisions lies in judg­
ing which alternative is most likely to turn out best. Decisions usually have to be
made with missing information and involve guesses and predictions about future
events. It is also a recursive or recycling process because the nature of the decision
may change as more alternatives are generated and evaluated. The decision also re­
quires an action, although it may not be an overt movement-you could decide
whom or what to believe, or to do nothing at all. All of these processes occur in a
context that influences what happens and relies heavily on the information you
bring with you to the decision and the information that you obtain during the
decision-making process. For example, you may make a different decision if you are
being observed by your friends than if you were alone (context effect), and an expert
312 8. DECISION MAKING

in a field may reach a different decision than a novice (effect of prior knowledge).
Personal values are also a strong influence on the way the decision is phrased, the
alternatives that are generated, and the way they are evaluated.
In the medical scenario at the beginning of this chapter, the decision maker must
take into account the likelihood of developing cancer at some time in the future, the
risks and pain of surgery, the pros and cons of various treatment regimens, and per­
sonal factors such as feelings about quality-of-life issues. When you decide which
stock to invest in, you must consider what the economy might be like in the years to
come. Similarly, the decision whether to have children requires that you think about
what your life will be like with children who don't even exist yet. Most of life's im­
portant decisions involve competing goals; multiple players whose decisions will, in
turn, affect the choices that you have; time constraints; and uncertain and changing
contexts (Cannon-Bowers, Salas, & Pruitt, 1996). Not surprisingly, psychologists can
offer guidelines for making good decisions, but they do not have an exact prescrip­
tion that will work for all decisions.

Good Decisions and Subjective Utility

Decision making is an active process. The decision maker takes responsibility for
her or his own future. After all, you are in the best position for determining how
you want to spend your life and how you should make the business and profes­
sional decisions that will ultimately reflect on you. Good decision makers are more
likely to get the good jobs and make favorable decisions about their personal lives as
well. Recall from the first chapter that critical thinking was defined as the use of
those skills or strategies that increase the probability of a desirable outcome. But, the
quality of a decision needs to be judged on the basis of what was known or should
have been known at the time the decision was made; sometimes, good decisions will
have undesirable outcomes and sometimes poor decisions will have good outcomes.
Although many famous instances of good decisions (profitable investments, suc­
cessful army maneuvers) and bad decisions (Watergate, the US. attempt to rescue
American hostages in Iran) come to mind, it is important to realize that a decision
should be judged to be good or bad before the outcome is known, not after the fact.
For example, most Americans would have agreed that President Carter made a wise
decision to rescue American hostages in Iran, if it had been successful and no lives
were lost. However, because it failed and eight Americans were killed, it is now
seen as a bad decision. Thus, there is an important distinction between how good a
decision is when it is being made and its outcome. You could decide to bet your life
savings on a horse race (a bad decision), and "get lucky." Of course, good decisions
will result in desirable outcomes much more frequently than poor decisions will.
Often, we will never know if the best decision was made. If you are a college se­
nior who must decide between a lucrative career in accounting or a more personally
rewarding career as a high school English teacher, you may never be sure if you
picked the better option because you can only speculate about the career you didn't
select. Robert Frost, the famous American poet, captured this feeling in his poem
about a traveler who comes to a fork in the road. The traveler can never know about
"the road not taken."
Good decision makers will have more desirable outcomes than poor decision
makers, but what makes an outcome desirable? This is a difficult question to answer
because people have different values and different goals. In deciding on a career
MAKING SOUND DECISIONS 313

path, it seems obvious that decisions must reflect the individual predilections of
each person making this decision, just as we would not all want to marry the same
person or live the same life. Somehow, we need to weigh personal values, probabili­
ties of success, costs, and benefits to determine which choice is the best balance of
these and other difficult-to-quantify variables (Baron, 1997). The term subjective
utility refers the value of a particular choice to an individual. It is a personal assess­
ment about a choice (subjective), which is one reason why decision making will
never be an exact science like mathematics.
Before a decision can be made, the individual must realize that a decision is
needed and that there are several possible alternatives. Let's consider an example.
Monica is taking several demanding college courses. She needs to supplement her
income by working part time and has family obligations as well. Her free time is vir­
tually nonexistent. Monica needs to consider alternatives to her current lifestyle. She
must decide how to juggle all of these commitments and still have some time left for
herself. Monica has to realize that she can change her life. Too often this first step is
missed and inertia sets in. Simply stated, the problem is that Monica has too many
responsibilities and this is making her feel anxious and stressed. The best solution
will give her more time for herself and still allow her to fulfill her responsibilities;
the way she decides to balance these competing demands will depend on her per­
sonal value system (e.g., importance of spending time with her family versus the
amount of money she "needs" to maintain a lifestyle that she wants). As these are
essentially conflicting goals, the best decision will probably involve a compromise
that will only partially satisfy each goal. It is not likely that she will find a course of
action that will allow her to fill her days with leisure activities while maintaining
high grades, earning money, and caring for her family.
The objective criterion for a good decision is that it has high subjective utility for the
person making the decision. Some possible good decisions for Monica include finding
a higher paying job or reducing her expenses so she would need to work fewer hours,
beginning a more efficient study program, taking a lighter course load, and visiting
her family less frequently. You may be surprised to find that with a little effort several
possibilities occur to you that you might otherwise never have considered.
Devoted "Trekkies," (fans of the television and movie series called Star Trek) can
recall many stories in which the plot involved particularly clever decision making.
Consider, for example, the Trekkie-classic movie Star Trek II: The Wrath of Khan. In the
opening scene, an attractive pointy-eared Vulcan is facing a serious problem. A sister
spaceship has wandered into enemy territory and has sent a distress signal. If she
does not go in to save them, they will perish; if she does, she risks enemy attack. She
nervously decides to follow them into enemy territory and is immediately apprised
that her starship is under attack. We soon learn that this is a computer-simulated drill
designed to test the decision-making skills of future Starfleet commanders and that
only one person has made the correct decision in this drill. Of course, it is Captain
James T. Kirk, the hero of this series. The question of interest is whether to attempt to
save the sister ship by entering enemy territory and thus risk enemy attack. Captain
Kirk did neither-he redesigned the computer problem so that he would have addi­
tional choices with more favorable outcomes. For him, the problem was "how to
change contingencies in a mock drill." For others, the problem had been "how to
save the sister starship without being attacked." Captain Kirk made a superior deci­
sion because he defined the problem in a unique way. His unusual and excellent al­
ternative made this decision very creative, a topic that is discussed in a later chapter.
Some may say that he cheated or "copped out" by redesigning the simulation, but
3 14 8. DECISION MAKING

perhaps, he would use his ability to define problems in a unique way if he were out
in space and that's what makes him an outstanding Starfleet commander. The point
being made here is that often there are alternative ways of formulating what the deci­
sion requires, and some formulations will result in more favorable outcomes than
others. Different formulations will lead to different solutions.

Descriptive and Prescriptive Processes

Whenever there is a simple error that most laymen fall for, there is always a
slightly more sophisticated version of the same problem that experts fall for.
-Amos Tversky (quoted in Gardner, 1985, p. 360)
Researchers who study decision making look at what people do when they are
making a decision, often contrasting what people actually do with what they should
do in order to maximize the probability of a good decision. This is the difference be­
tween a descriptive and a prescriptive account of the process. Any program that is
designed to help people make better decisions will have to take into account what
typically is right and wrong with most decisions, and then provide a systematic way
of eliminating or reducing common errors and increasing those processes that un­
derlie good decisions. With so many processes involved and so many decisions that
need to be made, it is easy to find ways that decision making goes wrong.
Baron (1990) categorizes all thinking into "search" and "inference" stages. The
search occurs when we have to generate alternatives, and to a lesser extent when we
decide what constitutes a good decision. The inference relates to the kinds of judg­
ments that are made and the way information is used. Thinking goes wrong when
the search process misses some good alternatives or when the inference is incorrect
(e.g., selecting an alternative that really will not solve the problem or will create
other problems).
The alternatives that people generate are tied to the way memory is structured
and accessed (Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1993). An oft-repeated theme throughout
this book is the pervasive influence of memory on all aspects of thinking. The sort of
alternatives that are generated will depend on what we can recall in the particular
situation. Decision making is also constrained by the amount of cognitive effort that
is invested in the processes of generation and evaluation. We don't want to spend
huge amounts of time and energy in making most decisions, so we rely on shortcuts
that sometimes lead to poor decisions. The idea is to be flexible so that the cognitive
effort is proportional to the importance of the decision.
A fallacy is an error or mistake in the thinking process. An example of common
thinking fallacies among trained professionals can be found in research with nurses
conducted by Smedslund (1963) and more recently reconfirmed by Berger (1995)
with a sample of physicians. Smedslund presented trained nurses with a deck of
cards, which supposedly contained information gleaned from the files of 1 00 pa­
tients. Each card indicated whether a patient had a particular disease and whether
a particular symptom was present or absent in the patient. Thus, there were four
possible combinations for each patient. The patient (a) has the disease and has the
symptom, (b) does not have the disease and does not have the symptom, (c) does
not have the disease but has the symptom, and (4) has the disease but does not have
the symptom. The task for the nurses was to determine if there is a relationship
between the symptom and the disease. The number of cases in each of these four
PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING 315

Has the Disease Doesn't Have the Disease Marginals for Rows

Has the Symptoms 37/1 00 = 37% 33/100 = 33% 70/100 = 70% have the
symptoms

Don't Have the Symptoms 1 7/100 = 1 7% 1 3/100 = 1 3% 30/1 00 = 30% don't have
the symptoms

Marginals for Columns 54/100 = 54% have 46/1 00 = 46% doesn't 1 00% in both directions
the disease have the disease

a. Of everyone with the symptoms, 52% (37/70) have the disease. This means that if you have the
symptoms, you are about as likely to have the disease as to not have the disease.
b. Of everyone with the disease, 68% (37/54) have the symptoms. This means that if you have the disease,
you have about a 2/3 probability of having the symptoms.
c. Of everyone who does not have the disease, 72% (33/46) have the symptoms. This means that if you do
not have the disease, there is over a 2/3 probability of having the symptoms.
d. Of everyone who does not have the symptoms, 56% (17/30) have the disease. This means that if you do
not have the symptoms, there is greater than 50% probability that you have the disease.

FIG. 8.2. Number of patients within each disease/symptom category. Is there a relationship
between the disease and the symptoms? Look carefully at the numbers in the marginals and
think about the kind of information that they provide about the possibility of a disease-­
symptom relationship.

categories is shown in Fig. 8.2. Stop now and look over the data presented in Fig. 8.2.
Do you think that there is a relationship between the symptom and the disease?
Overwhelmingly, the nurses concluded that there was a symptom-disease rela­
tionship, basing their decisions on the fact that 37 patients had both the disease and
the symptom and 13 had neither the disease nor the symptom. They tended to ig­
nore the 33 cases in which the symptom was present without the disease and the 17
cases in which patients had the disease, but not the symptom. These trained nurses
and, more recently, a sample of physicians, routinely ignored half of the available
information. The correct decision should have been that there was no relationship
because there was a high probability of the disease without the symptom and the
symptom without the disease. You can see this by looking at the marginals, the
numbers at the end of the rows and columns. Think about the meaning of these
probability values and see how they support the conclusion that there is no relation­
ship. If you just finished reading Chapter 7 on likelihood and uncertainty, you
should be able to see how the probability data that are used to make decisions in
this context rely on the same thinking principles that were discussed in the likeli­
hood and uncertainty chapter. Decisions very often involve probabilistic informa­
tion, and decision-making errors using probabilities, like the one described here, are
prevalent in the everyday thinking of people from all walks of life. We need to ex­
amine common decision-making fallacies because a skilled decision maker will need
to know what to avoid as well as what to do.

PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING

Great moments in history all turned on someone's judgment as to what should


be done and someone's decision to do it.
-Arkes and Hammond (1986, pp. 21 1-212)
A pitfall is a danger or difficulty that is not easily avoided. If you've ever spent long
afternoons at the beach, you've probably seen bratty kids creating pitfalls. They dig
316 8. DECISION MAKING

holes in the sand and cover them with newspaper so that unsuspecting sun lovers
will fall into them. The word pratfall needs no formal definition for fans of comedians
who are famous for their frequent pratfalls. The American Heritage dictionary de­
fines a pratfall as "a fall on the buttocks." Put these terms together and you will real­
ize that unless common pitfalls in decision making are avoided, the decision maker
will slip and fall on the part of the anatomy that is featured on blue jeans commer­
cials. Let's examine some of the common fallacies or pitfalls in decision making.

Failure to Seek Disconfirming Evidence

Some of the worst disasters nations have known are traceable to faulty
judgments or distorted perceptions of their political leaders.
-Kruglanski (1992, p. 455)
Suppose you have a friend who is always working on crossword puzzles, anagrams,
mazes, and other similar problems from puzzle books. He corners you one day with
the following problem:

I'm going to give you a series of numbers. This series conforms to a simple rule. You have
to figure out what the rule is. The way to do this is by corning up with your own series of
numbers. I'll tell you whether your own series conforms to this rule. You can give me as
many series of numbers as necessary to discover the rule. When you believe that you
know the rule, tell it to me and I'll let you know if you're right.

Reluctantly you agree to participate. You are given the following number series:

2 4 6

Stop right now and think how you would go about generating other number se­
ries that conform to the same rule as this one.
This problem was actually presented to many subjects in an experiment con­
ducted by Wason (1960, 1968). He found that most people had difficulty with this
task. Suppose that you believe that the rule is "any continuous series of even num­
bers." To test this rule most subjects would try series like "14, 16, 18." The experi­
menter would respond that this series conforms to the rule. To be certain most
subjects would try again with another series, "182, 184, 186." Again the experi­
menter would respond affirmatively. Confidently, the subject would announce the
rule, "Any continuous even series of numbers." The experimenter then informs the
subject that this is not the correct rule.
Typically, subjects will try again, this time thinking up a new rule that will de­
scribe the correct number series. Suppose, this time the subject decides to try out the
rule "the middle number is halfway between the other two." Now the subject asks
about the series "50, 100, 150." The experimenter answers that this series is correct.
The subject tries again "1006, 1 007, 1008" and is told that this also conforms to the
rule. Even more confident this time, the subject announces that the correct rule is
"the middle number is halfway between the other two." The experimenter tells him
that this is not the correct rule.
Have you discovered the correct rule by now? It is "increasing whole numbers."
After almost an hour of working on this problem one of Wason's subjects came up
PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING 317

with this rule: "The rule is that either the first number equals the second minus two,
and the third is random but greater than the second, or the third number equals the
second plus two, and the first is random but less than the second." You can imagine
how this poor subject felt when he was told that this rule was incorrect.
Why is this problem so difficult? In all of the sample number series I've given and
most of the ones people actually try, the number series conform to the rule they
have in mind. There is an infinite number of possible number series that conform to
the correct rule, "numbers in increasing order of magnitude." What subjects should
have done is try out series that would disconfirm the rule they were trying out. For
example, if you believed that the correct rule is "any continuous series of even num­
bers" you should try the series "I, 2, 4./1 If the experimenter tells you that you are
correct, then you know that the rule "any continuous series of even numbers" must
be wrong.
The tendency to seek information that agrees with the ideas we have is called
confirmation bias. We have a bias or predilection to look for confirming informa­
tion. Another interesting example of the confirmation bias or failure to seek discon­
firming evidence is discussed in Chapter 4 on the development of reasoning skills.
This example reflects the same error that was described in the previous section in
which the nurses failed to consider evidence that disconfirmed the hypothesis that
the symptoms and disease were related. This bias is pervasive; examples can proba­
bly be found in every applied setting. For example, a recent study of how jurors
reach decisions about the guilt or innocence of a defendant shows that they con­
struct a likely story about what probably happened at the scene of the crime. They
then look for information that was revealed during the trial that is consistent with
their story (Kuhn, Weinstock, & Flaton, 1994). Thus, jurors also rely heavily on evi­
dence that confirms their beliefs.
What can we infer from the bias to seek confirming evidence? Suppose someone
confronts your best friend with "the opportunity of a lifetime." A dynamic sales­
woman offers him the chance to invest in a new corporation that will manufacture
and sell computers that are so small they will fit in your wallet. It sounds good, but
he's unsure. Prudently he decides to do some investigating. He checks out ten com­
puter companies that are listed on the New York Stock Exchange. He finds that IBM
is a large profitable corporation. If he had only invested in IBM when it was just
being formed, he'd be a rich man today. He can already imagine himself lighting
cigars with $10 bills. What advice would you give your friend?
Hopefully, you would point out to him that he only looked for evidence that sup­
ports the decision to invest in the corporation as only substantial corporations are
listed on the stock exchange. He also needs to seek evidence that would disconfirm this
decision. He should find out how many new computer corporations with big dreams
have gone bankrupt and how many have not gone bankrupt in the last 10 years. He
also should attempt to estimate the future market for wallet-sized computers.
Another real-life (nonlaboratory) example can be drawn from medical decision
making. Imagine a young physician examining a sick patient. The patient is complain­
ing of a high fever and sore throat. The physician must decide on a diagnosis from
among myriad possible diseases. The physician decided that it may be the flu. She
asks the patient if he feels "achy all over." The answer is "yes." The physician asks if
the symptoms began a few days ago. Again, the response is "yes." It should be clear
to the reader that the physician should also be seeking evidence that would discon­
firm the flu diagnosis. She should also ask about patterns of symptoms that are not
usually associated with the flu, like a rash or swollen joints or flesh-eating bacteria.
318 8. DECISION MAKING

The confirmation bias is a pitfall in decision making. Wason claims that it is


prevalent in the thoughts and research of scientists. In fact, a large-scale study of
NASA scientists showed a strong confirmation bias (Mynatt, Doherty, & Tweney,
1978). (And yes, these are rocket scientists!) We all need to be trained to seek and
examine data that are inconsistent with the ideas we are considering. There is good
evidence that when people are required to consider counterevidence, they make bet­
ter decisions (Koriat, Lichtenstein, & Fischhoff, 1980). In general, people spend re­
sources (time, effort, money) looking for the wrong sort of information to inform
their decisions-we need to deliberately seek information that would run counter to
a preferred choice (Bastardi & Shafir, 2000).

Overconfidence

Overconfidence is a decision-making pitfall that is related to the bias to seek confirm­


ing evidence. In general, most people do not see the need to improve the way they
make decisions because they believe that they are already making excellent deci­
sions. The unwarranted belief that we are usually correct is a major, real-life barrier
to critical thinking. The tendency to be overconfident about the quality of our think­
ing is a theme that runs through several chapters in this book. Most people believe
that they think well-it's other people whose thinking needs improvement. After all,
if most people are very confident that they are making the correct decision, why
should they exert the time and effort to learn and apply the skills of critical thinking?
Why do we tend to believe that we are good decision makers? In part because we
cannot remember other alternatives that might have led to better decisions (e.g.,
I can't think of any reasons why I might not be right) and because we can never
know about the outcomes that would have resulted from other decisions (Holyoak &
Simon, 1999). Furthermore, we tend to remember more positive aspects of an option
we select than of one we do not select, even when the options were manipulated ex­
perimentally to control for these differences (Mather, Shafir, & Johnson, 2000). In a
discussion of political decision making, Kruglanski (1992) lists ambition, status seek­
ing, delusions, and prejudice as some of the reasons for bad decisions. If these less­
than-ideal motives are added to politicians' overly confident belief that the decisions
they make are usually right, it is easy to explain some very bad political decisions.

Availability Heuristic

A heuristic is any "rule of thumb" that we use to solve problems. It won't always
give us the right answer, but it is a helpful aid. Psychologists usually distinguish be­
tween heuristics and algorithms. An algorithm is a procedure that will always yield
the correct answer if you follow it exactly. Let's try a simple example from mathe­
matics to clarify these terms. Remember the procedures you learned in solving long­
division problems. Given a problem like 176y7ITI9, you were first told to estimate
about how often 1 76 would "go into" 701, as it is unlikely that you ever learned the
time tables for 1 76. You might estimate it to be about 4 times. The problem thus far
would look like this:

4
)
176 7019
PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING 319

You would check out this estimate with the appropriate multiplication.

4
)
1 76 7019
704

Oops, too large!


Once you have realized that 4 was too large you would probably try 3. This pro­
cedure is a heuristic. It is a guide or aid to help you find the correct answer, but it
doesn't always work perfectly as seen in the above example. On the other hand, an
algorithm always leads to the correct answer. If you want to find the area of a rec­
tangle that is 3 feet long and 2 feet wide you will always get the correct answer if
you use the formula: length X width, or in this case, 3 feet X 2 feet 6 square feet.
=

The use of an appropriate algorithm is an example of cognitive economy, a topic


that was introduced earlier in this book. We don't need to use mental effort and
"reinvent" ways to find the area of a rectangle when there is a ready-to-use algo­
rithm that we can call upon for the correct answer.
There are many situations in which we use both heuristics and algorithms. In
cooking, for example, a recipe is an algorithm. If the recipe is followed exactly, the re­
sult should always be the same dish that is described in the cookbook. When cooks
ad lib by adding additional seasoning or when they create a new recipe, they are
using their general knowledge about the types of flavors that go together. This is an
example of a heuristic. Heuristics or "rules of thumb" are frequently used by a deci­
sion maker without the realization by the decision maker that they're being used.
Availability is a commonly used heuristic. The term availability heuristic was
coined by two prominent psychologists, Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky
(1973; Tversky & Kahneman, 1974), who conducted numerous experiments on deci­
sion making and, in the process, provided a catalog of thinking errors. In order to
understand the availability heuristic, consider the following questions:

1 . Are there more words in the English language that begin with the letter r or
have the r in the third position?
2. Would you expect the 2000 census to show that there are more librarians or
farmers in the United States?
3. Are there more deaths due to homicide or due to diabetes-related diseases?

If you answer the first question like most people, you believe that there are more
words that start with the letter r than there are words with r in the third position.
In answering this question most people find that they can think of more words that
start with r (rice, root, room, roam, religion, rhinoceros, rye) than have r in the third
position (bird, torrid, horror, hero). In the jargon of psychology, words starting with
the letter r are more available (in memory) than words with r in the third position.
That is, they come to mind more easily. If you answered "words that start with r,"
you were wrong. According to Berger (1995), the English language contains many
more words with r in the third position than in the first position. It is just more diffi­
cult to think of them because it is easier to retrieve words from memory by the first
letter than by the third. Earlier in this chapter I talked about the pervasive influence
of memory in every aspect of critical thinking. This is another example of the way in
which the kinds of memories we retrieve can determine how decisions are made.
320 8. DECISION MAKING

If you have already read Chapter 7 on likelihood and uncertainty, then you al­
ready know that there has been a backlash against the idea that humans are poor
thinkers. In recent years, there has been more emphasis on accuracy in everyday
thinking than in errors in thinking (e.g., Gigerenzer & Goldstein, 1 996; Hammond,
1996; Hoffrage, Hertwig, & Gigerenzer, 2000). Systematically, Gigerenzer and his
colleagues have examined each of several thinking biases to show that under some
conditions, thinking is fairly accurate. For example, in a study where participants
were asked to compare the frequency of letters in the first or second position of
words, frequency judgments were more accurate than when comparisons were
made for letters in the first or third position of words (except for letters that were
either very frequent or very infrequent). The conclusion from this line of research is
that accuracy in judgments depends on the way questions are asked, what is being
compared, and a host of other variables. The goal of this book is to improve think­
ing, not to argue how good most of us are as thinkers-we can all always improve.
Your answer to the second question probably depends on whether you live in an
urban or rural area. Most city dwellers believe that there are more librarians than
farmers in the United States. After all, few city dwellers have ever met a farmer
whereas they probably know, or at least know of, several librarians. Actually, there
are many more farmers in the United States than there are librarians, a fact that
was more likely to be answered correctly by readers from rural farm regions. This is
another example of how the use of the availability heuristic can lead to the wrong
decision.
Most residents of large cities probably believe incorrectly that there are more
deaths due to homicide than to diabetes. The reason for this is not difficult to under­
stand. Pick up any newspaper or watch television news on any day and there is
likely to be a report of one or more homicides. Although you may know only a few
people who have diabetes and may not know personally anyone who has been mur­
dered, you've heard or read about many homicide victims, so there seems to be
more of them. A study of people who watch many violent television shows found
that these people believe that they are more likely to be a victim of a violent crime
than those who don't watch these shows (Gerbner, Grass, Morgan, & Signorielli,
1980). Presumably they maintain this belief because examples of violent crimes are
more readily available in their memory. This finding has important implications be­
cause it would be expected to affect how frequent viewers of televised violence vote
on crime-related propositions and how they make decisions like buying a home bur­
glary alarm, keeping a gun in the house, or going out at night.
The availability heuristic can be found in many applied settings. Its influence can
best be understood with an example: In a medical text written by Gifford-Jones
(1977), the author discusses the difficult medical decision concerning whether
women in their late thirties or early forties should have their ovaries removed when
they are having a hysterectomy. Like all difficult decisions, there are pros and cons
associated with each alternative. In discussing how this decision is often made,
Gifford-Jones (1977, pp. 1 74-175) wrote:

I recall operating some time ago with a former professor of gynecology at Harvard. He
was in a rather philosophical mood and was pondering the pros and cons of what to do
with the ovaries. "Sometimes whether or not I remove the ovaries depends on what has
happened to me in the last few weeks," he said. "If I've watched a patient die from can­
cer of the ovary, I often remove them. But if I've been free of this experience for a while,
I'm more inclined to leave them in."
PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING 32 1

The availability heuristic is frequently seen in other medical examples. It is not


unusual for a pediatrician whose own children suffer from severe allergies to be es­
pecially vigilant about possible allergic reactions in his patients. This may or may
not be a good thing. The best physician is one who has a broad scope of experience
with a large variety of illnesses so that he has a large number of medical diagnoses
available to him.
Prejudice and stereotypes may also exist, at least in part, because of the human
tendency to utilize readily available information. Although prejudice and stereo­
types were discussed more fully in Chapter 2 on the development of memory skills,
it is easy to see how availability plays a role in establishing and maintaining preju­
dice and stereotypes. If a minority person is convicted of a heinous crime, many
people will distrust other members of the same minority. The thousands of honest
hard-working minority persons are forgotten or overlooked. Their existence is over­
shadowed by the salient criminal.
Availability has been carefully studied in the laboratory by research psycholo­
gists because it plays a role in decisions that are made in a wide range of settings. In
another experiment by Tversky and Kahneman (1974), groups of college students
were given one of the two following arithmetic problems:

8x7x6x5X4x3x2Xl=?
or
l X2X3X4x5x6x7x8=?

The college students examined either the first or second row of numbers for 5 sec­
onds. Their task was to estimate the product because 5 seconds was not enough time
to solve the problem. Students who were given the first problem, the one beginning
with large numbers, gave an average estimate of the product to be 2,250. Students
who were given the second problem, the one beginning with small numbers, gave
an average estimate of the product to be 512. The correct answer is 40,320. Thus,
when the problem began with large numbers the estimated answer was large com­
pared to the problem that began with small numbers. The estimate differences
between the ascending and descending series demonstrates that judgments were
systematically biased toward the most readily available information.

Representativeness Heuristic

Suppose that a young man in a pinstripe suit, black shirt, and white tie comes up to
you and asks if you'd like to make some money by betting on whether a coin lands
on "heads" or "tails." (If you have already read Chapter 7, you may recall a similar
sneaky character.) You look at him dubiously. He explains that it's really quite simple.
He'll flip one coin six times. All you have to do is bet on the pattern of heads and tails
that will result from six tosses of a coin. Although there are many sequences possible,
you decide to concentrate on three of them. Using the letter "H" to represent heads
and "T" to represent tails, on which of the following three outcomes would you bet?

H-T-H-T-T-H
H-H-H-T-T-T
H-T-H-T-H-T
322 8. DECISION MAKING

If you responded like most other people, then you selected the first series of
heads and tails, probably because it seemed more similar to a random or chance pat­
tern of heads and tails. In fact all three series are equally likely. Any series of heads
and tails taken six at a time is as likely to occur as any other. The above example
demonstrates the belief that an outcome of a random process should look like or be
representative of randomness. Because our common-sense notion of randomness is
that of a process without a pattern, we tend to think that H-T-H-T-H-T is not as
likely to occur from six tosses of a coin as a more random-looking series. This, how­
ever, is not true. (What some people find even more surprising is that H-H-H-H-H­
H is as likely to occur as H-T-H-T-H-T.)
Of course, you're more likely to get approximately equal numbers of heads and
tails after many coin flips than you are to get mostly or all heads or mostly or all tails
because there are more possible patterns that yield these outcomes. For example,
there is only one pattern of outcomes that will correspond to six heads (H-H-H-H-H­
H), whereas there are many ways to get three heads and three tails in six flips of a coin
(e.g., H-H-H-T-T-T; H-T-H-T-H-T; T-T-T-H-H-H; H-T-H-T-H-T; etc.). Each series or
pattern of heads and tails is equally likely. This concept is also discussed in Chapter 7.
To clarify the representativeness heuristic, which is the belief that any member
of a category should "look like" or have the traits associated with its category,
let's try another example. Suppose you get a letter from an old friend from whom
you haven't heard in many years. He tells you that he is the proud father of six
children-three girls and three boys. After trying to consider what life is like with
six children, you then wonder about their birth order. Which of the following orders
do you think is more likely (with "G" standing for girl and liB" standing for boy):

B-B-B-G-G-G
or
B-G-G-B-G-B

If you've followed the discussion so far, you will realize that although the second
series appears to be more representative of a random process, they are, in fact,
equally likely.

Wishful Thinking (Pollyanna Principle)

Quite often people will overestimate their chances for success or the likelihood of a
desired outcome. Halpern and Irwin (1973) found that when participants in an ex­
periment wanted an event to occur (they would win money), they believed that it
was more likely to occur than when its occurrence would have been unfavorable (they
would lose money). It seems that humans are an optimistic species. The tendency to
believe that pleasant events are more likely than unpleasant ones is a manifestation of
wishful thinking, the idea that if we want something to happen it will. This has also
been called the Pollyanna Principle in honor of the protagonist of a 1913 novel who
always found something to be happy about, no matter how bleak the situation.
A large fast-food hamburger chain is basing a promotional gimmick on wishful
thinking. The corporation that made golden arches an integral part of American life
is offering a game that pays off with large sums of money. Some lucky Big Mac
hamburger consumer will match up small game coupons for the grand prize. A blitz
of television advertising shows lucky burger eaters exclaiming over the money
PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING 323

they've won. Apparently, the lure of winning must sell more hamburgers, or it
would have been discontinued. It must be assumed that people grossly overesti­
mate their chance of winning the prizes. The actual estimated probability of win­
ning the grand prize is less than a million to one. As required by law, these odds are
posted (in fine print) on the posters that announce the game, yet they are routinely
ignored and thought to be more favorable than they actually are. Few of us can
appreciate astronomical odds like this one. You're probably more likely to find a
needle in a haystack. Yet, because of wishful thinking, many people will line up for
hamburgers and a chance to win.
Optimism is a potent human trait that often directs how we think and act.
Seligman (1991) identified optimism as a critical element in political elections. It
seems that candidates who are optimistic about the future are more likely to garner
winning votes than those who are pessimistic. He found that in 9 out of 10 presiden­
tial elections in the United States, the candidate who gave the more optimistic
speeches won the election. Optimism may be a wonderful human trait, but not
when it distorts the decision-making process. Good decisions rely on realistic as­
sessments of likelihood, not optimistic ones. Failure to consider seriously unpleasant
outcomes can lead to disastrous consequences.

Entrapment

Suppose you were offered the opportunity to bid on a $1 bill. You and some friends
can make bids, and the highest bidder will pay the amount bid and get $1 in return.
The only hitch is that both the highest bidder and second highest bidder must pay the
amount they bid, but only the highest bidder will receive the dollar in return. Suppose
that you agree to play and that you continue to raise your bid until you have offered
80 1/.. Now a friend bids $1. What do you do? You will probably decide to bid $1.05 for
the $1 because you'll certainly lose 80 1/.; unless you continue to increase your bid.
Shubik (1971) has found that people will continue to bid amounts over $1 to win the
dollar bill in an attempt to keep their losses at a minimum in this game.
What has happened in this game is entrapment, a situation in which an individ­
ual has already invested money, time, or effort and decides to continue in this situa­
tion because of the initial investment. Entrapment is also called sunk costs because
of the importance that we attach to the costs we have already "sunk" into a course
of action. People commonly fall prey to entrapment. Consider Fred's decision about
his automobile. He has already replaced the muffler, brakes, and ignition system
when he finds out that his car needs a new transmission. Because he has already
invested so much money into his car, he feels "trapped" into replacing the transmis­
sion instead of buying a new car. Or consider another common example. Everyone
has had the frustrating experience of calling on the phone for some information and
being put on "hold." After listening to the irritating strains of "elevator music" for
several minutes, you need to decide whether to hang up or continue waiting. Many
people continue to wait because of the time they've already invested.
Making decisions in light of previous investments requires that the individual
consider why the investment has been so high either in terms of money or time, and
whether, at this point in time, the car is worth the additional sum of money or the
phone call is worth an additional 1 0 minutes on "hold." Examples of entrapment are
commonly found in government budget hearings (Fischer & Johnson, 1986). One ar­
gument in favor of continuing to support the development of the MX missile is that
324 8. DECISION MAKING

the millions of dollars that have already been spent on it would be lost if we decided
to discontinue the project. Sometimes, politicians and others will try to minimize the
appearance that they have wasted money by continuing to fund projects that should
be discontinued (Arkes, 1996). If more people were vigilant for sunk costs, we
would save money and other valuable resources that could be put to better uses.
In a study of how people respond in sunk-costs situations, researchers asked sub­
jects open-ended questions about common decisions (Larrick, Morgan, & Nisbett,
1990). Consider this one:

You and a friend just spent $7 each to see a movie. About a half hour into the movie, you
both realize that it is "two thumbs down"-a really bad movie. What do you do? List some
good reasons for staying until the end of the movie, then list some good reasons for leav­
ing after a half hour.

Stop now and try this demonstration.


Look over your reasons. Of course, you just read about entrapment, so you are
not a naive subject, but review the answers that you gave anyway. If you listed the
fact that you spent $7 as a good reason for staying, you are demonstrating the fal­
lacy of entrapment. If you listed as a good reason for leaving the fact that the movie
is a waste of time, then you receive partial credit for recognizing the cost of staying.
If you also listed the fact that you could be doing something better with your time,
then you would get credit for recognizing that by staying you would also be losing
out on doing some better activity. Let's go over the reasoning again because I have
found that many students have difficulty with this concept:
You already spent the $7 for the movie. No matter what you decide to do at this
point in time, the money is gone, and you are down by $7, so it should not be rele­
vant to your decision. You lost $7, no matter what you decide to do. At a half-hour
into the movie, you have a decision to make. If you stay, you will not only have to
endure a bad movie, but you will also miss out on a more pleasurable activity that
you could be doing. Thus, there is a dual cost to staying-seeing a bad movie and
missing out on some better activity. Try out this example with some friends or fam­
ily. Explain the fallacy of entrapment to them.

Psychological Reactance

Our emotional states have a major impact on the kinds of decisions that we make
(Kavanaugh & Bower, 1985). We select alternatives that seem ''best'' to us, and our
determination of what's best is not always based on sound rational criteria. One ex­
ample of the effect of emotional states on the kinds of decisions people make has
been labeled psychological reactance, which is resistance arising from restrictions of
freedom. Consider this example (Shaver, 1 981): It's been a bitterly cold winter and
you can hardly wait for a much deserved spring break. One of your close friends is
planning on basking in the Fort Lauderdale sun. Another friend can't wait to hit the
slopes in Vail. Both friends have asked you to join them in their spring break rev­
elry. As you consider the options, you begin to favor the bikini-clad vacation when
your Florida-bound friend tells you that you must go to Florida with him. How does
this loss of freedom affect your decision?
Logically, it would seem that being told that you must do what you want to do
would have no effect on your decision, but many people do not react this way. Some
PITFALLS AND PRATFALLS IN DECISION MAKING 325

'U�LY
, ��
m U��
To J.Khl.!;
�,...

NON SEQUITUR © Wiley Miller. Dist. By UNIVERSAL PRESS SYNDICATE. Reprinted with
permission. All rights reserved.

people would react to this loss of freedom by deciding to go skiing instead. The ex­
tent to which psychological reactance affects a decision depends on the number of
freedoms that are being threatened and the source of the threat. There are also large
differences among individuals in the extent to which they are prone to reactance.
Consider how you will probably respond when you are told what to do in different
situations. If you are likely to do the opposite, no matter what you are told to do,
then you are demonstrating reactance and will sometimes make poor decisions be­
cause of this tendency. Whether you're dealing with your parents, an employer, or a
foreign government, psychological reactance can interfere with the decision-making
process by causing you to select a less desirable alternative.

Liking

It should seem obvious that people select alternatives that have been evaluated posi­
tively along some dimension. This point will be made more explicitly later in this
chapter; however, it is important to consider here some of the factors that influence
positive evaluations. In other words, what are some factors that determine liking?

Reciprocity
When assessing the pros and cons of various alternatives, our subjective feelings
about the alternatives play a large role in decision making. Simply put, we choose
people and actions that we like. Reciprocity is one determinant of what and whom
we like. We tend to like people who like us. In Cialdini's (1993) delightful book
about myriad influences that affect our thoughts and actions, he tells about the
"World's Greatest Car Salesman." The super salesman seems to differ from other
more mundane sellers in several ways, but the most interesting is his strange habit
of correspondence. Super salesman sends a card to each of his more than 13,000 for­
mer customers each month. Can you guess the message on this card? No, it's not a
list of maintenance tips or repair coupons. In fact, every card every month contains
the same message: "I like you." Twelve times a year, every former customer receives
the same obviously impersonal message. It seems to work. When the time comes to
decide where to purchase another car, these former customers are reminded of their
"friend" who likes them. Reciprocity of liking apparently has a powerful effect on
decision making in this context.
326 8. DECISION MAKING

The psychological literature is full of other examples of the influence of reciproc­


ity on decisions. For example, you are much more likely to buy a product if I give
you a free sample than if I don't. The next time you are in the supermarket when
samples are being given away, watch how people respond to the covert pressure to
buy the product they have just tasted. You'll find that a surprisingly high number
will buy the product. People seem to feel that they owe something in exchange for
the "free" sample. Political favors are blatant examples of reciprocity-induced liking
as are charitable requests that are accompanied by "gifts" like address labels, key
rings, and stamped return envelopes.

Mere Exposure Effect

Suppose that you walked into a voting booth on a primary election day and were
faced with the following choice:

County Solicitor (Choose One)


Myron Jones
John Adams
Victor Light

Unfortunately, you have not kept up with local politics, and are unfamiliar with
the record of any of these candidates. Which candidate would you vote for? Studies
indicate that you probably chose John Adams.
In an election in New Hampshire about 10 years ago, John Adams, an unem­
ployed cab driver who did not campaign, won the Republican nomination for the
state's First Congressional District. Why did John Adams, a man who spent no
money on his campaign and who never gave a speech, win his party's nomination?
Psychologists believe that when voters were confronted with three names they did­
n't recognize, they picked the one linked in history with a political figure. Hence,
prior exposure creates a sense of familiarity, which in turn can enhance your liking
for the stimulus, a phenomenon known as the mere exposure effect.
Political commercials often operate on this principle. They repeatedly hark, "Vote
for Brandon Lee, He's the One!" Such commercials give absolutely no information
about the candidate. They rely on the well-documented effect that familiarity will
enhance liking. Based on this principle, repetition was commonly used in Nazi Ger­
many and North Korean prison camps during World War II in an attempt to make
their political ideologies more palatable to the prisoners.
What should you do if you face unknown candidates' names in a voting booth? If
you can't vote intelligently for an office, skip that section and vote for the offices
with which you're familiar. Intelligent voters ask themselves, "What do I know
about these candidates?" and do not fall prey to a familiar sounding name.

Emotional States

Like many cognitive psychologists, I often forget the critical role that emotions play
in the thinking process. (Astute readers will probably recognize this as due to the
availability heuristic.) Intuitively, we all know that emotions are important. For ex­
ample, would you ask your boss for a raise if you knew that she just had a fight with
EVALUATING CONSEQUENCES 327

her husband? Of course, your boss's relationship with her husband should be ir­
relevant to whether you get a raise, but a bad mood tends to spill over and affect
unrelated decisions. So does a good mood. In an investigation of the way mood in­
fluences the way decisions are made, Bower (1994) found that interviewees for a job
were rated higher when the interviewers were given good news prior to the inter­
view than when they were given bad news. In a laboratory study of the way nega­
tive events affect the decisions people make, subjects were required to keep their
hand in a bucket of ice water-a condition that is known to be stressful. They were
then asked to provide their opinions of various people. The researchers found that
the decisions these subjects made were much more hostile than in a control condi­
tion in which they did not have the physical stressor caused by keeping a hand in
ice water (Berkowitz & Thome, 1987).
It is easier to recognize the effect of emotions on the way we think than it is to
correct for it. It is important that we all consider how our own moods may be affect­
ing the quality of the decisions that we make, and we may also try to influence the
mood of others who will be making decisions that affect us.

Mindlessness

People often think they are making carefully calculated decisions when they are
not. Cost-benefit analyses usually take place after the fact.
-Langer (quoted in Coughlin, 1993, p. A9)
Although we may believe that we are rational, thoughtful people, Langer (1989,
1994) found that many of the decisions that we make are mindless, that is, without
conscious thought about what we are doing. For example, she told about a time
when she presented a credit card to a store clerk. The clerk looked at the card and
then told her that she had not yet signed it. (It was a new card.) Langer then signed
the card and signed the charge slip. The clerk mindlessly checked the two signatures
to see if they matched. (She had just seen her sign both.) This simple example serves
to show that many of the actions that we take are done without conscious thought.
Langer argues that mindlessness is a bad habit, and that with effort, we can and
should be more consciously aware of what we are doing and why we are doing it.

EVALUATING CONSEQUENCES

Murphy's Law: Anything that can go wrong, will.


Comment on Murphy's Law: Murphy was an optimist.
If you return to Fig. 8.1, you'll see that evaluation is done repeatedly as new alterna­
tives are generated, the decision is phrased differently, and the consequences of
alternatives are considered. Decision making always involves uncertainty because
we are thinking about the way different actions will have some future effect. The de­
cisions that we make have implications for the future, and the future inherently in­
volves unknowns. For this reason, the principles involved in assessing likelihood
and uncertainty that were presented in Chapter 7 are an integral part of the
decision-making process.
328 8. DECISION MAKING

Research on how people typically deal with uncertainty has shown that the usual
response is to ignore it (Hogarth, 1988). Although this may reduce the immediate
complexity of a decision, it is obviously a maladaptive procedure that could lead to
catastrophic results. It is possible to reduce the number of unknowns in any situa­
tion. This will almost always involve some work by the decision maker, but if the
decision is an important one, it will be time well spent. Let's consider a common ex­
ample. Most of us will purchase several automobiles in our lifetimes. For a majority
of Americans, this will represent the second largest expenditure that they will
make, exceeded only by a home purchase. The quality of this decision can be im­
proved with a little research. You can determine which automobile variables are
important to you and gather relevant data about each car you are considering for
possible purchase.
Almost any decision can be improved with a little research that would reduce the
uncertainty. For example, if you are uncertain about the safety of genetically altered
foods, an afternoon at the library reading both pro and con materials should allow
you to make a much more informed decision about this important issue.

Assessing Desirable and Undesirable Consequences

We can understand judgment as the quality of analysis, reflection, and


ultimately insight that informs the making of politically consequential
framing decisions.
-Renshon (1992, pp. 481-482)
The decision maker must always be aware of the risks and benefits associated with
taking or not taking a particular course of action. The way consequences are evalu­
ated will depend on the context. For example, the consequences of not taking an um­
brella will be greater if you are heading off for a business meeting where showing
up dry is important than if you are taking the dog for a walk and then returning
home.
If you live in an apartment near a college campus, you are well aware of the
"joys" associated with apartment hunting. Rental units are often in short supply in
college communities and are priced in a range that strains the typical student's
budget. Students may find themselves considering an apartment that lacks the
amenities they were hoping for at a price that is really above their income. The risk
associated with turning the apartment down is that they might not find another
apartment within walking distance to the college campus. The risks associated with
renting the apartment must also be considered. What if they find that they really
can't afford to keep up the monthly rental payments? The decision maker has to de­
cide which risk is greater and the likelihood of each occurring. Obviously, both risks
need to be assessed very carefully and additional alternatives considered. Perhaps a
cheaper apartment can be found in another section of town with good public trans­
portation to campus, or perhaps a roommate can be found to share the rent.
A poignant example of failure to assess risks adequately can be found in an
analysis of the United States' military actions just prior to the attack on Pearl
Harbor. Admiral Kimmel, Commander in Chief of Naval Operations in the Pacific,
had received several warnings from Washington that a Japanese attack in the South­
west was possible. He decided to downplay the probability of an attack on Pearl
Harbor because he believed that other naval sites were more likely targets. Quite by
EVALUATING CONSEQUENCES 329

accident, and almost an hour before the attack, two army privates spotted on a radar
screen large numbers of unidentified aircraft flying toward Pearl Harbor. Realizing
that these could be Japanese bomber planes, they reported the presence of the
unidentified aircraft to the Army's radar center.
Let's consider the plight of the officer on duty at the radar center. The United
States was not at war with Japan. He had never received the recent warning that a
Japanese attack was imminent. He had to decide whether the unidentified objects on
the radar screen belonged to the United States or Japan. There were costs and risks
associated with either choice. If he had erroneously decided that they were Japanese
planes, he would have been responsible for recalling personal "leaves" for large
numbers of servicemen and women and creating havoc and panic on the military
base. There were also large financial costs involved in preparing for anti-aircraft
maneuvers. Because he assessed the possibility of a Japanese attack to be low, he
told the two privates to forget about the objects detected by radar. He decided that
they were probably the Army B-17s that were expected to arrive some time that
day. With the unfortunate benefit of hindsight, it is clear that he failed to assess
adequately the risks associated with each decision. The result was the worst
naval disaster in U.S. history with over 2,000 lives lost. Even though he believed
that an attack was unlikely (wishful thinking), he should have realized that the
risks were too great to justify his decision. Decisions made under extreme risks
need careful scrutiny and not an off-hand dismissal. In this case the risks
associated with deciding that the planes belonged to the United States were many
times greater than those associated with the decision that they were Japanese
bombers.
Research has shown that the Pearl Harbor scenario is not unusual. Whenever ex­
treme risk is associated with a course of action, there is a tendency to minimize the
unfavorable consequences (Janis & Mann, 1977). This is sometimes called biased
discounting-the bias or predilection to discount or reduce perceived risk or its
probability. It often operates along with wishful thinking, which causes the decision
maker to assess the probability of a desirable outcome too high, the failure to seek
disconfirming evidence, which is the tendency to ignore evidence that would not
support your favored hypothesis, and overconfidence in the quality of the decision
that was made. These tendencies, taken together, allowed the radar officer to bolster
his decision to ignore the unidentified objects by rationalizing either that even if
they were Japanese bomber planes they probably would not do much damage or it
was extremely unlikely that they were Japanese aircraft. A more recent example in
which the failure to consider the consequences of certain decision alternatives can
be seen in an analysis of the Gulf War that involved the United States, Iraq, and
Kuwait. The researcher who conducted the Gulf War analysis found many similari­
ties to the decisions that were made at Pearl Harbor (Renshon, 1992). I expect that
many analyses of the horrific attacks on the World Trade Center and Pentagon will
be forthcoming, all with the goal of understanding how the attacks could have hap­
pened and how better thinking and preparation can prevent similar attacks in the
future.
When making decisions, many people prefer risks associated from not acting to
the risks associated with taking action. The bias or preference for inaction is known
as omission bias (Baron, 1994). Consider the decision to vaccinate your child
against some dread disease. Many parents will decide not to vaccinate their children
even when the risk of serious illness or death from the vaccine is extremely small
and the risk of getting a serious disease or dying is many times higher if the child is
330 8. DECISION MAKING

not vaccinated. There is a consistent bias in which the cost of "doing nothing" is not
adequately assessed (Pence, 2001).

ELIMINATION BY ASPECTS

Let's return to the earlier problem of deciding which automobile to buy. With so
many automobiles on the market, where do you begin? Most people begin decision­
making processes of this sort with a strategy known as elimination by aspects,
although few people know it by this name (Tversky, 1972). An individual who is
concerned about unemployment in the U.S. car industry would begin by eliminat­
ing cars that are not manufactured in the United States. In this instance, the aspect
under consideration is the place in which the automobile is manufactured. At this
point, most people will decide which features (or aspects) of automobiles are impor­
tant to them. Suppose that you are on a limited budget so that cost is an important
feature to you. You would probably determine the cost of various models of Fords,
Plymouths, Chevrolets, and other U.s. autos. Models that cost more than your price
ceiling would be eliminated.
Let's suppose further that frequency of repair is another important variable.
Of course, no one can tell you how frequently the car you choose will need repair,
but you can reduce some of the uncertainty associated with this variable by finding
out how often other models similar to the ones you are considering have needed re­
pair in the past. This information is available in consumer periodicals in every li­
brary. If some of the models that you are still considering are judged as "worse than
average" on the frequency of repairs, then presumably these would be eliminated
from further consideration. The elimination by aspects strategy would be recycled
repeatedly until the decision maker is left with a few possible models from which to
choose. Typically, small and seemingly insignificant differences will come into play
to complete the process-for example, "I'm tired of shopping," or "Let's just take
this one," or "The dealer will include at no extra cost furry dice to hang from the
rearview mirror if I buy this model," or "I can drive this one home today." The use
of small and relatively inconsequential factors to close the decision is an example of
mindlessness, a topic that was discussed earlier in this chapter. Most consumers are
not aware that something as "small" as free fuzzy dice tilts the balance of what had
been a prudent process.
The method of elimination by aspects can be used in many contexts. Political can­
didates, for example, can be thought of as choices that vary along several criteria. If
you decide that the issues that are important to you include a strong military de­
fense, reduction of taxes, and school prayer, then you could rank each of these can­
didates along these aspects and eliminate the candidates who don't share your
views. You would have to determine which of these aspects is most important if you
find that none of the candidates shares all of your views about these important
issues. Elimination by aspects is "fast and frugal" reasoning (Gigenzer, Todd, & the
ABC Research Group, 1999; Gigenzer & Goldstein, 1996). It is one of several "short­
cuts" in reasoning where the decision maker does not carefully weigh a large
amount of data, but relies instead on a quicker (and some would say "dirtier")
method of reaching a decision. It is much faster than the worksheet method that is
presented next, and it works well when there are time constraints or when the
decision does not warrant the extensive work of a worksheet.
PREPARING A WORKSHEET 33 1

PREPARING A WORKSHEET

The time is ripe for a major national and international effort to include thinking
and decision-making in school curricula.
-Baron and Brown (1991, p. 6)
We have clear evidence that decision-making biases do not go away just by telling
people not to make them, but decision making can be improved with effective train­
ing programs (e.g., Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1993; Rittle-Johnson & Alibali, 1999).
Researchers have found that the best way to make an important decision involves
the preparation and utilization of a decision worksheet. The purpose of a worksheet
is to optimize decision making. Psychologists who study optimization compare the
actual decision made by a person to a theoretical "ideal" decision to see how similar
they are. Proponents of the worksheet procedure believe that it will yield optimal
(best) decisions. Although there are several variations on the exact format that a
worksheet can take, they are similar in their essential aspects. Worksheets require
framing the decision in a clear and concise way, listing many possible alternatives
that would achieve a desired goal, listing the relevant considerations that will be af­
fected by the decision, determining the relative importance of each consideration,
and mathematically calculating a decision. The end product of the worksheet proce­
dure is a single numerical summary of each possible solution or alternative. In
theory, the alternative with the highest number of points emerges as the best decision,
but more usually, the careful consideration of alternatives and their probabilities and
value to the decision maker leads to a decision before the entire process is completed
because it helps to clarify values and keeps the decision maker focused on the task.
Most important problems are multifaceted with several different ways of framing
the decision, and many alternatives to choose from, each with unique advantages
and disadvantages. One of the benefits of a pencil-and-paper decision-making pro­
cedure is that it permits us to deal with more variables than our immediate process­
ing ability would allow. If you've already read Chapter 2 on utilizing memory,
you'll recall (I hope) that working memory is limited in the number of pieces of in­
formation it can deal with at one time. A worksheet can be especially useful when
the decision involves a large number of variables with complex relationships.
Let's consider the worksheet procedure with a realistic example for most college
students: "What will I do after graduation?" A hypothetical student, Evan, has sev­
eral postgraduation opportunities. He is contemplating the following: (a) a job in a
large fashionable department store where he will train to be a buyer; (b) a teaching
position in an inner-city school, probably a fifth or sixth grade class; (c) a graduate
school degree in business administration; (d) a law school degree; and (e) a year off
to "bum around" Europe. A decision-making worksheet will be very important in
helping him choose the best alternative. Notice that I did not say "correct" alternative
because there are many possible good alternatives for real-life, complex decisions.

Framing the Decision

The first step in making a sound decision is the realization that a decision needs to
be made. A decision-making worksheet begins with a succinct statement of the
problem that will also help to narrow it. Thus, the problem for Evan becomes "What
332 8. DECISION MAKING

will I do after graduation that will lead to a successful career?" If Evan words his de­
cision this way, he has already decided that his decision will involve long-range
goals and not immediate ones. It is important to be clear about this distinction be­
cause most often long-range goals will involve a different decision than short-range
ones. Thus the options of attending graduate or law school are really statements
about working in business or as a lawyer and not decisions about school per se.
The importance of this first step cannot be overemphasized. The entire decision­
making process depends on the way the problem is defined. If Evan had posed the
problem as "How can I best earn a good living?" he would find that the process
would focus on monetary considerations. Similarly, the process would change if he
posed the problem as, "Should I go to graduate school?" Research with business
managers has shown that the ability to redefine business problems is an important
characteristic of good decision making in management (Merron, Fisher, & Torbert,
1987). The way the decision is framed will determine the alternatives that are gener­
ated and the way they are evaluated. This is an important point. If you are worried
about world hunger, you could frame the decision about what to do about it several
ways: How can we produce enough food to feed all the people in the world? How
can we adjust the world population so that it does not exceed the food supply? How
can we move food from wealthy countries to poor ones? How can we develop non­
food alternatives that are nutritious? Each of these decisions will suggest different
alternatives.
Similarly, be mindful of the way others have framed decisions for you. The media
may adhere to all guidelines of fairness and still present decisions in ways that limit
broader considerations. For example, I recently served as a juror on a complex trial
where the attorney for the defense framed the question for the jury as "Why should
you believe the alleged victim?" By contrast, the attorney for the prosecution framed
the question for the jury as "Is there sufficient evidence that the defendant commit­
ted the alleged crime?" Each of these "decision frames" led to the consideration of
different types of evidence. The jury had to be aware of the differences in framing
and attempt to see the decision about guilt or innocence from several different
perspectives as we conducted our deliberations.
A worksheet procedure can have many important applications for social prob­
lems. Consider the contemporary problem of violence, which is filled with numer­
ous decision points. It seems that it should be possible to teach aggressive children
and adults to reframe their problems in ways that suggest nonviolent alternatives.
For example, instead of asking, "How can I get even with a classmate?" the child
could be trained to ask, "How can I improve a bad situation?" Perhaps a thoughtful,
creative reader will devise an educational program that teaches children, and per­
haps even politicians, to reframe decisions so that nonaggressive alternatives are
generated.

Generating the Alternatives

The next step is to write out in separate columns across the top of the worksheet all
possible alternatives that could solve the problem. You'll need a large sheet of ruled
paper or a computerized spreadsheet because it would make no sense to cut the
worksheet process short because you ran out of space on your paper. It is important
that you don't evaluate the alternatives at this stage; however, this is not the place
for fiction either. If you are tone deaf, this is not the time to fantasize about a career
PREPARING A WORKSHEET 333

in the opera. Allow room for two columns under each alternative that will be used
later for calculations. Thus far, Evan's worksheet would look something like this:
TABLE 8 . •
What Will I Do After College That Will Lead to a Successful Career?
Dept. Store Teacher-Inner­ Graduate School- "Bum" in Europe
Alternatives Buyer City Schoof Business Law Schoof for a Year

Evan notices while drawing up his worksheet that these alternatives are not all
mutually exclusive. There's no reason why he can't decide to travel around Europe
for a year and then select a career goal; besides, a vacation in Europe is not a long­
range plan and the decision currently being made is for life career goals. He decides
at this point to erase the fifth alternative because it seems to require a separate deci­
sion from the other four. He also remembers at this point that his father always
hoped that Evan would want to run the family-owned lumber business after his
graduation from college. Although this is not an appealing idea to Evan, he substi­
tutes it as an additional choice because the rules for this step of the process do not
allow for evaluation.

Listing the Considerations

The decision Evan makes will have multiple effects. His feelings about making a
personal contribution to society, his income and his future lifestyle, his parents' and
friends' opinions of him, the quality of his workday, and many other variables are at
stake. If Evan were married with children, the impact of each decision on his spouse
and children would also need to be considered. At this point Evan should cover the
alternatives and list on the left-hand side of his worksheet the considerations or
variables that will be affected by his decision. The worksheet would now look like
Table 8.2.
Before proceeding, Evan should now put the worksheet away and mull over the
way the decision was framed and the alternatives and the considerations that he
listed. Often people find that in the course of worksheet preparation they think of
new alternatives and discover which considerations are important to them. It is also
a good idea to ask other people you trust if they can think of additional alternatives
and considerations. Considerations and alternatives that are not listed on the work­
sheet will not be considered, so it is extremely important to list all the relevant alter­
natives and considerations. This is another vulnerable point in the decision-making

TABLE 8.2
What Will I D o After College That Will Lead t o a Successful Career?
Dept. Teacher- Graduate Run Family
Store Inner-City School- Law Lumber
Alternatives Buyer School Business School Business
Considerations
Desire to Help Society
Income
Parents' Opinions
Friends' Opinions
Interest in the Work
334 8. DECISION MAKING

process-failure to consider possible alternatives. Don't cut this part of the decision­
making process short. It is important.
Be sure, however, that you don't let other people make the decision for you. Sup­
pose that Evan's friend suggests that Evan seriously pursues his interest in music
and becomes a jazz musician. In addition, Evan thinks up several additional consid­
erations, which he lists on his worksheet. He also decides that as he is planning for
his future, he should realistically consider his chances for success at each alternative.
(See Table 8.3.)
Listing all relevant considerations is an important part of the worksheet process.
Janis and Mann (1977) believe that poor decisions often result from failures to think
through all of the relevant considerations. They suggest that considerations be listed
under four categories-gains and losses for self, gains and losses for significant
others, self-approval and disapproval, and social approval and disapproval, to
avoid overlooking important considerations.

Weighing the Considerations

It is almost always true that the considerations are not equally important to the deci­
sion maker and therefore need to be weighed accordingly. A 5-point scale in which
1 of slight importance, S of great importance, and the numbers 2, 3, and 4 re­
= =

flect gradations of importance between these end points can be used to quantify the
relative importance of each consideration. Weighing considerations is a personal
matter. It is likely that each of us would assign weights somewhat differently. If
Evan felt that his desire to help society was moderately important to him, he would
rate it a 3. Similarly, if he believed that income was more than moderately important
to him, but less than "of great importance," he would rate it a 4. The appropriate
weights are placed alongside each consideration.
After assigning numbers (the weights) to each consideration you should stop to
survey the weights. If Evan rated "friend's opinions" with a larger number than
"parents' opinions," this reflects how he feels about their relative opinions. This is a
good way to clarify which considerations are most important to you. It is a good
way to consider your own values.

TABLE 8.3
What Will I Do After College That Will Lead
to a Successful Career?
Dept. Teacher­ Graduate Run Family
Store Inner-City School­ Law Lumber Jazz
Alternatives Buyer School Business School Business Musician
Considerations
Desire to Help Society
Income
Parents' Opinions
Friends' Opinions
Interest in the Work
Prestige of Occupation
Employment Security
Amount of Vacation
and Free Time
Likelihood of Success
PREPARING A WORKSHEET 335

It is not unusual to find that the process ends here because the decision maker re­
alizes which alternatives are important and does not need to complete the process.

Weighing the Alternatives

Now is the time to think carefully about each alternative and determine how well
each satisfies the considerations listed. The alternatives will be weighed using the
numbers - 2, - 1, 0, + I, and +2. A positive number indicates that it is favorable or
"pro" the consideration with + 2 indicating that it is highly favorable and + 1 indi­
cating that it is somewhat favorable. A negative number will be used if an alterna­
tive is incompatible with or "con" a consideration, with -2 indicating that it is
highly incompatible and - 1 indicating that it is somewhat incompatible. Zero will
be used when an alternative is neither favorable nor unfavorable to a consideration.
We'll use Evan's worksheet to demonstrate how to weigh alternatives. First, Evan
has to contemplate how becoming a department store buyer will satisfy his desire to
help society. Certainly it won't hurt society, but it probably won't help it either.
Evan believes that although it may create additional jobs in related industries (fash­
ion, sewing, etc.), this is not really what he had in mind when he thought about
helping society; therefore, he rates it a zero on this consideration. This number is
placed under "Department Store Buyer" in the left-hand column on the first row.
Subsequent ratings will be placed directly below this number. If he does eventually
become a buyer for a large department store, he probably will earn a satisfactory in­
come. He certainly won't be rich, but it will be enough money to allow him to live
comfortably; therefore, he gives it a + 1 . Both his parents and friends will consider it
to be a moderately good job, so he rates it a + 1 on both these considerations. He be­
lieves that it should be very interesting work and rates it a +2 on "interest in the
work." It should be a moderately prestigious occupation and thus rates a + 1 in this
category. Unfortunately, it probably won't offer much employment security because
department store sales are tied to the economy, which seems to fluctuate erratically;
he therefore rates it - 1 on "employment security." A department store buyer is re­
quired to work a 40-hour or more workweek with only a few weeks a year for vaca­
tion, thus rating a -2 on vacation and free time. He notes that he is moderately
likely to succeed as a department store buyer, so he rates it + 1 on this consideration.
It is usually necessary to gather more information at this stage of the decision­
making process. Evan may need to phone the local school district to find out what the
median salary is for school teachers. He also might seek the advice of his college advi­
sor to determine if he has the math skills needed to succeed in business administration.
We know that the way alternatives are evaluated is influenced by feelings, which, in
this case, is perfectly rational because the choice is a personal one, and Evan's feeling
about the alternatives should be part of the decision-making process (Overskeid, 2000).
Each alternative is rated in a similar manner by thinking how well it satisfies the
objectives of each consideration. When he completed weighing the alternatives,
Evan's worksheet looked like Table 8.4.

Calculating a Decision

If you have carefully followed the worksheet procedure this far, you've realized that
it requires numerous decisions before even coming close to yielding the one you
336 8. DECISION MAKING

TABLE S. 4
What Will I Do After College That Will Lead to a Successful Career?
Dept. Teacher- Graduate Run Family
Store Inner-City School- Law Lumber Jazz
Alternatives Buyer School Business School Business Musician
Considerations
Desire to Help Society (3) 0 +2 0 +1 0 0
Income (4) +1 -1 +2 +2 0 -1
Parents' Opinions (2) +1 0 +1 +2 +2 -1
Friends' Opinions (3) +1 +2 0 +1 -1 +2
Interest in the Work (5) +2 +2 +1 0 -1 +1
Prestige of Occupation (1) +1 -1 +2 +2 -2 +1
Employment Security (3) -1 -2 0 +1 +2 -2
Amount of Vacation
and Free Time (2) -2 +2 -2 -2 +1 +2
Likelihood of Success (5) +1 +1 -1 -1 +2 -2

want to make. By now Evan has decided what type of decision he's making (long
range), listed all the alternatives and all the considerations that he believes to be nec­
essary, decided how important each consideration is to him and how well each al­
ternative satisfies the objectives of each consideration.
There are three different strategies for calculating a decision at this point. They
are overall assessment, dimensional comparison, and the "2/3 Ideal Rule." Each uti­
lizes a different criterion for selecting the best decision from a worksheet.

Overall Assessment
An overall assessment of the various weights is obtained by determining how well
each alternative satisfies the considerations taken as a whole or overall. This is cal­
culated by multiplying the weight previously assigned for each consideration by the
value assigned to how well an alternative satisfies that consideration. For example,
Evan has rated his desire to help society a 3 and the department store buyer alterna­
tive a 0 on this consideration. The first cell of the worksheet is 3 X 0 O. This result,
=

0, is placed in the right-hand column under "Department Store Buyer." Continuing


down to the next consideration, we see that Evan rated income as 4 and the depart­
ment store buyer alternative + 1 on income. Because 4 X 1 4, he would place a 4 in
=

the right-hand column below Department Store Buyer and next to "Income." This
procedure is repeated for each alternative. The right-hand column for each alterna­
tive is then added yielding a total score for each alternative. This procedure is
demonstrated in Table 8.5.
Perusal of the worksheet will now show that based on an overall assessment, the
alternative with the highest total score is 'Teacher-Inner-City School." You will
also notice that the alternative to become a department store buyer obtained a fairly
high score that was close to a winning alternative. Thus far, it seems that Evan
should seriously be thinking about a career as a teacher.

Dimensional Comparison
In a dimensional comparison strategy each consideration (the "dimensions") is ex­
amined to find which alternative has the highest score. For example, if "Desire to
PREPARING A WORKSHEET 337

TABLE S.S
What Will I Do After College That Will Lead to a Successful Career?
Dept. Teacher- Graduate Run Family
Store Inner-City School- Law Lumber Jazz
Alternatives Buyer School Business School Business Musician
Considerations
Desire to Help Society (3) 0 0 +2 6 0 0 +1 3 0 0 0 0
Income (4) +1 4 - 1 -4 +2 8 +2 8 0 0 -1 -4
Parents' Opinions (2) +1 2 0 0 +1 2 +2 4 +2 4 -1 -2
Friends' Opinions (3) +1 3 +2 6 0 0 +1 3 -1 -3 +2 6
Interest in the Work (5) + 2 10 + 2 10 +1 5 0 0 -1 -5 +1 5
Prestige of Occupation (1) +1 1 -1 -1 +2 2 +2 2 -2 -2 +1 1
Employment Security (3) - 1 -3 -2 -6 0 0 1 3 +2 6 -2 -6
Amount of Vacation
and Free Time (2) -2 -4 +2 4 -2 -4 -2 -4 +1 2 +2 4
Likelihood of Success (5) + 1 � +1 � - 1 -5 - 1 -5 +2 10 -2 -10
18 20 8 14 12 -6

Help Society" is examined, you will see that "Teacher-Inner-City School" had the
highest rating among all the other alternatives; therefore, it would "win" on this
consideration and get one point. Looking at "Income" you will see that both "Grad­
uate School-Business" and "Law School" were assigned +2 on this dimension. In
the event of ties each winning tied alternative is awarded one point. If each consid­
eration is examined in a similar manner, the following number of considerations
won for each alternative will result:

Number of Considerations Won


Teacher­ Graduate Run Family
Department Inner-City School­ Lumber Jazz
Store Buyer School Business Law School Business Musician
1 4 2 3 3 2

As seen here, the alternative "Teacher-Inner-City School" scored highest among


the alternatives on four considerations. Thus, the results of the dimensional compar­
ison strategy agree with the overall assessment results. Notice that both "Law
School" and "Run Family Lumber Business" won three considerations each, yet
scored fairly low on the overall assessment.

2/3 Ideal Rule


The 2/3 Ideal Rule was suggested by Carkhuff (1973). It requires the decision maker
to calculate an overall assessment total for a perfect or ideal alternative. If an ideal
alternative were added to Evan's worksheet, it would rate +2 on each consideration
because it would be highly favorable to each consideration. A total overall score for
an ideal alternative can be arrived at by adding all of the consideration weights and
multiplying the total by 2 as seen here:

3+4+2+3+5 + 1 + 3 + 2 + 5 = �
28 X 2 = 56
338 8. DECISION MAKING

The reasoning behind the 2/3 Ideal Rule is that a best alternative may not be
good enough if it fails to measure up to 2/3 of an ideal solution. Thus, according to
this rule a minimally acceptable alternative would score an overall 37.5 (2/3 X 56 =

37.5). If you turn back to the completed worksheet, you'll see that the highest total
was for the teacher alternative and it rated, by the overall assessment method, a 20
(considerably less than the 37.5 required by this rule). Evan has several choices at
this point. He can disregard the 2/3 Ideal Rule (which is likely if he is pleased with
the decision to become a teacher), or he can expand and recycle the process by gen­
erating additional considerations and alternatives until he reaches a consensus with
all three calculating procedures.
The 2/3 Ideal Rule is based on the idea that some alternatives are "good enough"
while others are not. Searching for alternatives that are good enough is called satis­
ficing (Marsh & Shapira, 1982; Tversky & Kahneman, 1981) and refers to termi­
nating the decision making process when an alternative that is "good enough" to
satisfy most of the important considerations is found. The decision making process
cannot go on forever, so at some point, the decision maker will have to decide that
one alternative is "good enough." The problem really is when to terminate the
process, and there are no simple answers to this question. Important decisions like
the one considered in this example should be given the time and effort they deserve.
Often, better decisions are possible if the decision maker would invest more time
and effort into generating alternatives and listing considerations.

The Problem with Numbers


One problem in using worksheet procedures to make decisions is the reliance on sub­
jective estimates-estimates of the probability of success, estimates of the importance
of consideration, and estimates of the extent to which an alternative is favorable or
unfavorable for a consideration. Although a large table of numbers can look very sci­
entific, the end result is only as good as the numbers that go into the calculations (d.,
Baron, 1997). Sometimes, small differences in how you assess probabilities or values
can change the outcome. So, it is important that you think about the worksheet proce­
dure as an aid or "decision-making helper," not an absolute determinant of what you
do. It should help you to clarify your values, force you to think systematically about
multiple variables, and aid in the generation of additional possible alternatives. Ide­
ally, the decision will become clear as you work on the worksheet so that it is more of
a process for making a decision than an absolute determinant of what you decide.

Dilemmas in Decision Making

The decision maker will often encounter dilemmas in calculating a decision. It is not
unusual for two or more alternatives to have exactly the same high score or for one
alternative to obtain the highest total with the overall assessment and a different one
with the dimensional comparison. This can always be remedied by generating addi­
tional considerations and repeating the process until an alternative emerges as best.
It is also possible to combine two or more alternatives. For example, Evan could be­
come a buyer in a department store and volunteer to tutor children on weekends.
This would allow him to realize his desire to help society while maintaining the ben­
efits of the buyer alternative. Sometimes the decision maker will abandon the work­
sheet before it's completed because the process helped to clarify the issues and led
directly to a decision without the calculations.
POSTDECISION COMMITMENT AND EVALUATION 339

Certainly, the worksheet procedure requires a great deal of work, as its name im­
plies. You might be wondering if there is any evidence to suggest that it's worth the
extra effort-that it actually leads to better decisions. Yes, there is. Mann (1972) ran­
domly selected 30 high school seniors (15 females and 15 males) from a college
preparatory program to participate in an experimental investigation of the work­
sheet procedure. He taught them how to prepare a worksheet that would help them
make decisions about college. The procedure he used was similar to the one pre­
sented here, but not identical to it. He also employed a "control group" of 20 stu­
dents who were not taught the worksheet procedure. Mann contacted the students
approximately 6 weeks after they notified the colleges about their decision concern­
ing which college they planned to attend. The group that had received worksheet
training (the experimental group) had less postdecision stress and anxiety and were
happier about the decisions they made than the control group. Mann also reported
that they had considered possible unfavorable consequences of their decision more
carefully than the control group. Thus, if something does go wrong, they will more
likely be prepared for it than those in the group without worksheet training.
Additional evidence that supports the validity of the worksheet procedure comes
from a study by Wanous (1973). He conducted an experiment to study the employ­
ment decisions of telephone operators. One group of prospective telephone opera­
tors was shown a film that portrayed both the positive and negative aspects of the
job whereas a control group was shown the standard training film that stressed only
the positive aspects. All subjects in both groups decided to accept the employment
offer to become telephone operators. One month later, subjects who had viewed the
"balanced" presentation reported that they were happier with their decision than
the other telephone operators who had viewed the standard one-sided film. In addi­
tion, significantly fewer subjects from the experimental group were thinking about
quitting their job than from the control group. In a similar vein, Janis and Mann
(1977) reported several studies in which the worksheet procedure has been utilized
in health decisions (e.g., elective surgery) with beneficial outcomes.
More recently, Knight and Dansereau (1992) used a decision-making worksheet
with college students who were presented with a story about "Chris," a student
who had to make decisions about alcohol and other drug use. The students who
were required to complete a worksheet showed evidence of better decisions regard­
ing alcohol and drug use than a control group that did not receive training with
worksheets. I don't know if these college students will actually make better real-life
decisions about alcohol and other drug use, but other studies with decision-making
worksheets suggest that they will. One of the benefits of the worksheet procedure is
that it allows people to feel more confident about difficult decisions and better pre­
pared for decision-making situations because they are required to evaluate alterna­
tives in a systematic manner.

POSTDECISION COMMITMENT AND EVALUATION

To begin with it was only tentatively that I put forward the views that I have
developed . . . but in the course of time they have gained such a hold upon me
that I can no longer think in any other way.
-Sigmund Freud (1856-1939)
340 8. DECISION MAKING

The decision-making process doesn't end with the decision. Once a course of action
has been selected, the decision maker must make detailed plans to carry it out and
needs to remain committed to the decision. However, if a major change occurs in the
evaluation of the consideration, then the process should be repeated. For example, if
Evan were unexpectedly offered a lucrative contract to become a jazz musician, he
would be wise to reconsider this alternative. Success at this alternative would now
seem much more likely and a large income would be assured. Decision making is
not a static process. Our major life decisions will have to be reconsidered whenever
a major variable changes.
Commitment is also important in decision making. Once a course of action has
been decided upon, we tend to view it as the "obvious" correct alternative, often
forgetting the effort that went into the decision. Consider how commitment shapes
behavior. In a radio interview, one restaurant owner was discussing the problem of
getting reservations on Valentine's Day (although the example applies to any day).
He said that one major problem is the large number of people who make reservations,
but never show up or even bother to cancel them, so restaurant seats are empty while
diners are turned away. He said that two simple words drastically reduced the num­
ber of "no shows" he had at his restaurant. In the past, the person taking the reserva­
tions would end each call with a cheery, "Please phone to cancel your reservations if
you cannot make it." Instead, she asked, 'Will you please phone to cancel your reser­
vations if you cannot make it?" By asking "will you," the caller had to make a verbal
commitment to canceling the reservation, which according to this unnamed restau­
rant owner, greatly reduced the number of "no shows" at his restaurant.

cognitive Dissonance

Most of the time, people find that they are pleased with their decisions. This finding
has been of considerable interest to research psychologists. Leon Festinger (1964), a
famous research psychologist, proposed his theory of cognitive dissonance to ex­
plain this phenomenon. It is based on the idea that people like their beliefs, atti­
tudes, and actions to be consistent, and when they are not consistent, an unpleasant
internal state arises-dissonance. Dissonance needs to be reduced. If you believe
that it is wrong to smoke marijuana and you attend a party where you smoke mari­
juana, you will feel uncomfortable because your actions and beliefs are not in agree­
ment. They are not consistent with each other. In order to reduce the discomfort of
cognitive dissonance, which is an unpleasant internal state, you will generally
change your beliefs and conclude that you did the right thing because "marijuana
probably isn't so bad after all." In general, the theory of cognitive dissonance has re­
ceived considerable experimental support. In one study (Brehm, 1956) subjects rated
the desirability of several gifts (e.g., toaster, coffee maker). They were then asked to
choose between two gifts that they had rated as equally desirable. After a decision
had been made, subjects rated the rejected gift as being much less desirable than the
one they chose. The theory of cognitive dissonance would have predicted this result
because subjects would now believe that they must like the selected object much
more than the rejected one in order to maintain consistency. It seems that once a de­
cision is made the alternatives that were not selected will seem much less attractive
than the one that was.
The theory of cognitive dissonance can be applied in a number of situations. It
can be used to explain the famous fable The Fox and the Sour Grapes. The story
POSTDECISION COMMITMENT AND EVALUATION 34 1

goes something like this: A hungry fox spies grapes hanging high overhead. After
repeated unsuccessful attempts to reach them, he decides that they were probably
sour and walks away. Like the human subjects described in this section, he down­
played the desirability of the object he didn't obtain.
The theory of cognitive dissonance only applies when a conscious decision has
been made. If you were coerced in some way, there would be no dissonance. Sup­
pose that you were required to write an essay on some topic that you are opposed
to, like the inferiority of a racial or ethnic group, or why drugs should be available
to elementary school children. If you were coerced into doing this, there would be
no need to change your attitudes to keep them consistent with this behavior. How­
ever, if you voluntarily decided to write such an essay, then cognitive dissonance
theory would predict a change in your attitude toward the position you took in the
essay. This is a major theory in social psychology that explains why people are usu­
ally satisfied with the decisions they make. It is easy to see how it contributes to the
unwarranted confidence that most people have in their decisions.

Foot-in-the-Door
Cognitive dissonance can be used to understand a common persuasive technique
know as the foot-in-the-door. The phrase comes from common parlance among
door-to-door salespeople who claimed that they could make a sale if only they
could get a "foot-in-the-door" -get the prospective customer to allow the sales­
people to make their sales pitch. Research on the use of this technique shows that if
people agree to a small request-like signing a petition in favor of safe driving­
later, they are more likely to agree to a larger request-like donating money to a safe
driving campaign (Cialdini, Trost, & Newsom, 1995). People are more willing to
agree to an inconvenient or costly request when it follows a smaller or less costly re­
quest that is consistent with the larger one. It seems that many people reason that
they must really care about the issue or topic because they already showed their
support with a smaller action.

Hindsight and Forethought

Hindsight bias is a cheap price we have to pay for a much larger gain: a well­
functioning memory that we do not need-such as outdated knowledge-and
that constantly updates our knowledge, thereby increasing the accuracy of
our inferences.
-Ulrich Hoffrage (quoted in Azar, 2000, p. 29)
The term hindsight is probably not a new one for you. After a decision has been
made and the relevant events occur, well-meaning friends will often tell you they
could have predicted the consequences of your decision. If you have ever been di­
vorced (or have exchanged confidences with someone who has), there were proba­
bly several acquaintances, who claimed to have known all along that, "he (or she)
was no good for you." Events appear different with the benefit of hindsight. Fore­
thought is the opposite of hindsight. There should be fewer unfortunate conse­
quences if decisions are carefully thought out before they are made.
In experimental investigations of hindsight, most participants erroneously be­
lieved that they could have predicted the consequences of historical and personal
342 8. DECISION MAKING

decisions before they occurred. In our earlier analysis of the Pearl Harbor disaster, it
seemed obvious that the only possible decision was to assume that the aircraft be­
longed to the Japanese. It should be remembered that we analyzed the disaster with
the full knowledge of the ensuing events. Hindsight occurs only when poor or
wrong decisions have been made. It is seldom that good decisions are analyzed after
the fact. Forethought and hindsight are qualitatively different. At the time of the de­
cision (forethought) there is doubt and deliberation, but following the unfavorable
consequences of the decision (hindsight) there is often a great sense of certainty that
the future should have been predicted more accurately.
An example of the power of hindsight occurred in 1974 when an editorial in a
Eugene, Oregon, newspaper called upon the local prison warden to resign. A "con­
victed murderer, bank robber, and all-around bad actor" had been given a 4-hour
pass to leave the state penitentiary (Fischoff, 1975). Instead of returning, he kid­
napped and murdered an Oregon couple. With the benefit of hindsight-that is,
with the full knowledge of the result-does it seem that the warden should have
known that this would happen? Given the disastrous outcome it was a wrong deci­
sion, but was the result obvious or even likely before the pass was granted? The con­
vict had been a model prisoner before the pass was granted. Do you think that the
warden should have been required to resign?
Hindsight is of little value in the decision-making process. It distorts our memory
for events that occurred at the time of the decision so that the actual consequence
seems to have been a "foregone conclusion." Thus, it may be difficult to learn from
our mistakes. Retrospective (after the fact) review, on the other hand, can be a valu­
able aid in improving future decisions. Unlike hindsight, it does not involve a faulty
reconstruction of the information available at the time of the decision so that the
consequence appears obvious.
There are plenty of examples of the hindsight bias whenever a political decision
results in a disastrous outcome. For example, you may recall the tragic end to the
Branch Davidians in Waco, Texas, in 1993. Attorney General Janet Reno ordered
that federal agents take over the compound following a lengthy siege and the shoot­
ing of several federal agents by the members of this religious cult. At least 15 chil­
dren in the Davidian compound were killed by their parents during an apparent
murder/suicide frenzy that occurred when the Davidians were attacked by the fed­
eral agents. Did Reno make a bad decision? It is clear that the decision had a bad
outcome, but given what was known at the time the decision was made, should she
have reasonably expected that the Davidians would kill each other if the agents
stormed the compound? Federal agents are involved in many activities, with very,
very few ever resulting in disaster. There were no good reasons to have predicted
that these religious parents would kill their children and then each other. Dawes
(1993) points out how the news media used their knowledge of this salient, improb­
able, and painful outcome to cloud their understanding of the factors that were
available at the time the decision was made.
Like many of the thinking skills and biases that are presented in this book, hind­
sight bias shows up in many different contexts and often goes unrecognized. Con­
sider the plight of every clinical psychologist. Psychologists and other therapists are
legally bound by a law called "Tarasoff," which requires that they warn appropriate
authorities if a patient tells them about plans to hurt someone. (Actually, the law is
more complicated than this simple description implies.) The problem for therapists
is determining what constitutes a credible threat that needs to be reported. In one
study, a group of adults was given a scenario that described the treatment of a
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 343

potentially violent patient. The scenarios were all the same, but there were three dif­
ferent "endings"-one group of adults read that the patient had become violent, an­
other group read that the patient had not become violent, and the third group was
not given any information about the patient's behavior. As predicted, the adults
who were told that the patient became violent were much more likely to believe that
the patient's violent behavior was foreseeable from the therapy sessions than the
adults who read the same scenarios, but were given a different ending (LaBine &
LaBine, 1996). Of course, none of the adults who made these judgments had any
awareness of the hindsight bias. Hindsight bias is difficult to correct because we are
usually not aware when it is operating. The next time a major disaster follows from
a decision, pay careful attention to the way the decision is analyzed by the news
media and the political party that is likely to gain from this tragedy. Ask yourself if
the outcome could have reasonably been predicted prior to the decision.
It is a good idea to determine what went wrong if a poor decision has been made
or if a good decision had a negative consequence, as long as we do not fall prey to
hindsight.
Immediately after the tragic bombing of a federal building in Oklahoma in 1995,
numerous political pundits proclaimed that they knew that a disgruntled militia
was a serious threat to society. After it happened, we all "could see it coming."

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

In applying the general thinking skills framework to decision making, consider the
following questions:

1 . What Is the Goal'?

The skills involved in decision making should be used whenever you are faced with
selecting the best alternative among a set of alternatives. Examples of situations that
require the use of these skills include personal, professional, and political decisions.
The process starts with the recognition that a decision is needed and then a careful
consideration of how it should be framed. Because a common failure occurs in the
generation of a limited number or limited scope of alternatives, exert time and effort
on this stage of the process. The time and effort should be proportional to the impor­
tance of the decision. Think through positive and negative consequences of various
alternatives.

2 . What Is Known?

The entire decision-making process is predicated on the belief that you are selecting
from among a set of alternatives. If you have no alternatives, then there is no deci­
sion. Similarly, the process requires that you frame the decision in several ways so
that you can generate a range of alternatives. A decision can only be as good as the
information on which it is based. If you do not know much about a problem, then
you cannot select intelligently from a set of solutions. Probably the greatest
difficulty with making decisions is the failure to consider alternatives that aren't
listed on a worksheet or aren't made conscious in some other way. Good decisions
344 8. DECISION MAKING

will require information gathering and assessment before the selection of alterna­
tives begins.

3 . Which Thinking Skill or Skills


Will Get You to Your Goal?
The kind of skill you select when you are confronted with an important decision de­
pends upon the nature of the problem. Some of the skills involve avoiding common
fallacies like the failure to seek disconfirming evidence or the reliance on available
information to assess the likelihood of an outcome. If the decision has potentially
negative consequences, then the positive and negative results of a course of action
have to be compared to each other and to those associated with other alternatives.
The weighing of considerations to calculate relative importance and likelihood
is helpful whenever there are multiple alternatives and the decision is an impor­
tant one.
The following decision-making skills were developed in this chapter:

• Listing alternatives and considering the pros and cons of each.


• Reframing the decision so as to consider different types of alternatives.
• Recognizing the need to seek disconfirming evidence and deliberately seeking
disconfirming evidence.
• Understanding the way that information that is readily recalled or information
that appears representative of a random process can influence how decisions
are made.
• Considering how overly optimistic assessments bias the selection of alternatives.
• Recognizing arguments that are based on entrapment and considering why the
costs have been high.
• Being mindful of the way liking can affect the evaluation of alternatives.
• Evaluating positive assessments of alternatives that are based on reciprocity or
familiarity.
• Seeking information to reduce uncertainty when making risky decisions.
• Preparing a decision-making worksheet for important decisions.
• Understanding the distinction between the quality of a decision and its outcome.
• Understanding the way emotional states like reactance and anger can affect the
way we evaluate alternatives and behaving in ways that minimize their effects.
• Recognizing that hindsight analysis of a decision is usually biased and of
limited value.

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?

The process of making a decision could, theoretically, go on forever. Most decisions,


however, have deadlines. After you have carefully considered various outcomes,
you need to take an overview of your decision and then follow through and act on
it. Does the decision seem right? Are you satisfied with the process and outcome?
As stated in the chapter, because of the uncertainty inherent in decisions, sometimes
good decisions will have poor outcomes. When this happens, scrutinize the nature
of the outcome. Was there a consideration that you failed to consider at the time
the decision was made? Can you learn from the negative outcome? Can you imag­
ine the consequences of an alternative you rejected?
CHAPTER SUMMARY 345

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Decision making is an active process that begins with a clear definition of the
decision and a set of alternative solutions from which to choose.
2. One way to improve decisions is to frame them several ways. Additional al­
ternatives can emerge by changing the focus of what is being decided on.
3. Few people ever receive formal instruction in thinking skills, and even trained
professionals commit common decision making fallacies.
4. A common error in decision making is the failure to seek disconfirming evidence.
5. People often rely on heuristics or "rules of thumb" to help them make deci­
sions. The availability heuristic or reliance on events that are readily recalled is a
common decision-making heuristic. When time is limited or the decision does not
merit a large investment of time or effort, there are many heuristics (thinking short­
cuts) that often work quite well.
6. Because of the widespread but erroneous belief that the laws of chance are
self-correcting, many people believe that "random-looking" sequences of out­
comes are more probable outcomes of a random process than orderly sequences of
outcomes.
7. Unwarranted optimism can also lead to poor decisions because it prevents re­
alistic assessment of both desirable and undesirable consequences of a decision.
8. People often fall prey to entrapment. They find it difficult to reverse their
decision after having invested large amounts of time or money.
9. Decisions are often biased by emotional states like psychological reactance (the re­
sistance to a loss of freedom), mood, and liking induced by reciprocity and familiarity.
10. Risky decisions require special care. There is often a tendency to downplay
the likelihood of a disastrous outcome.
1 1 . When the alternatives vary along several dimensions, decisions are sometimes
made by eliminating alternatives until only one or two choices remain.
12. Important decisions can be optimized by preparing a worksheet in which al­
ternatives and considerations are listed and weighed in a table format.
13. People are most often satisfied with the decisions that they make, possibly
because cognitive dissonance works to maintain consistency between actions and be­
liefs and because they cannot think of any reason why they might be wrong. Thus,
we reason that if we decided on a course of action it must have been the best one.
14. After the consequences of a decision have occurred, there is a great sense of
certainty that the consequences should have been obvious. Hindsight is a ubiqui­
tous phenomenon that distorts how we perceive the information that was available
before the decision was made.
15. There is an important distinction between a good decision that is based on the
information that is available when the decision is being made and its outcomes.
Sometimes, good decisions will have undesirable outcomes because of the inherent
uncertainty in most important decisions.

TERMS TO KNOW

Check your understanding of the concepts presented in this chapter by reviewing


their definitions. If you find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to
reread the section in which it is discussed:
346 8. DECISION MAKING

Subjective Utility. The value of a choice to an individual who is making a


decision.
Fallacy. An error or mistake in the thinking process.
Confirmation Bias. The predilection to seek and utilize information that supports
or confirms one's hypothesis or beliefs while ignoring disconfirming information.
Overconfidence. An unwarranted confidence in the quality of decisions that are
being made.
Heuristic. A general "rule of thumb" or strategy that we use to solve problems and
make decisions. Although it doesn't always produce a correct answer, it is usually a
helpful aid. Compare with algorithm.
Algorithm. A problem-solving or decision-making procedure that will always yield
the solution to a particular problem if it is followed exactly. Compare with heuristic.
Availability Heuristic. A decision-making "rule of thumb" that is used when esti­
mates of frequency or probability are made based on the ease with which instances
come to mind; for example, many college students believe that there are more pro­
fessors in America than farmers because they can think of more professors whom
they know than farmers.
Representativeness Heuristic. A decision-making "rule of thumb" in which the de­
termination of a sample's likelihood is made by noting its similarity to a random
process. If it "looks like" a random process, it is judged to be more probable than if
it appears orderly or patterned.
Wishful Thinking. People tend to overestimate their chances of success or the like­
lihood of a desirable outcome.
Entrapment. A situation in which an individual has already invested much money,
time, or effort and therefore decides to continue in this situation because of the
money, time, or effort that has already been invested.
Psychological Reactance. Resistance arising from restrictions of freedom. Some
people will select a less preferred alternative if they are told that they must select the
preferred alternative.
Mere Exposure Effect. Very often, repeated exposure to a stimulus will enhance
your liking for it.
Mindlessness. Making decisions with little or no conscious effort.
Biased Discounting. Predilection to discount or reduce the magnitude or probabil­
ity of risk.
Omission Bias. The preference for risks associated with not taking an action over
risks associated with acting.
Elimination by Aspects. A decision-making strategy in which choices are sequen­
tially eliminated if they fail to meet one or more considerations.
Optimization. Making the best possible decision in any situation.
Overall Assessment. A method of calculating a decision from a worksheet. The al­
ternative with the highest worksheet total would be selected. Compare with dimen­
sional comparison and 2/3 Ideal Rule.
Dimensional Comparison. A method for calculating a decision from a worksheet.
The alternative that has "won" the greatest number of considerations would be se­
lected. Compare with overall assessment and 2/3 Ideal Rule.
2/3 Ideal Rule. A method for calculating a decision from a worksheet. Only alterna­
tives whose worksheet totals are at least 2/3 as large as the ideal choice would be
chosen. Compare with dimensional comparison and overall assessment.
Satisficing. Terminating the decision-making process when an alternative that is
"good enough" to satisfy most of the important considerations is found.
TERMS TO KNOW 347

Cognitive Dissonance. A theory based on the notion that people want their beliefs,
attitudes, and actions to be consistent. When they are not consistent, an unpleasant
internal state arises-dissonance-which needs to be reduced. We reduce dissonance
by changing our beliefs and attitudes so that they are in accord with our actions.
Foot-in-the-Door. A two-stage persuasive technique. People are more likely to
comply with a large request if they first comply with a smaller, but related, request.
Hindsight. Reevaluation of a decision after it has been made and its consequences
have occurred with the belief that the consequences should have been known before
the decision was made.
9

Developlll e nt of
Problelll - Solving Skills

Contents
What Is a Problem? Simplification
Anatomy of a Problem Generalization and Specialization
Stages in Problem Solving Random Search and Trial-and-Error
Incubation Rules
Insight Hints
Persistence Split-Half Method
Well-Defined and Ill-Defined Problems Brainstorming
Problem Planning and Representation Contradiction
Multiple Statements of the Goal Analogies and Metaphors
Representation of the Problem Space Consult an Expert
Write It Down Select the Best Strategy
Draw a Graph or Diagram Problem-Solving Problems
Try a Hierarchical Tree Functional Fixedness and Mental Set
Make a Matrix Misleading and Irrelevant
Manipulate Models Information
Select the Best Representation Worldview Constraints
Problem-Solving Strategies Applying the Framework
Means-Ends Analysis Chapter Summary
Working Backwards Terms to Know

348
WHAT IS A PROBLEM 349

Suppose you're driving alone at night on a long, dark stretch of freeway that is infre­
quently traveled when you suddenly hear the familiar "thump-thump" of a very flat
tire. You pull onto the shoulder of the road and begin the unpleasant task of changing a
tire, illuminated only with the light of the moon and a small flashlight. Carefully, you
remove the lug nuts and place them in the hubcap by the roadside. A speeding motorist
whizzes past you, hitting the hubcap and scattering the lug nuts across the dark free­
way and out of sight. Here you sit, a spare tire in one hand, a flat tire propped against
the car, and no lug nuts, on a dark night on a lonely stretch of freeway. To make mat­
ters worse, a cold rain is beginning to fall. What would you do?

One of my students told me that this incident actually happened. He went on to


elaborate that the flat tire occurred alongside a large mental institution near our col­
lege. While the hapless motorist sat pondering his problem, he attracted the atten­
tion of several "residents" of the institution, who gathered near the motorist along
the chain link fence that separated them. One resident offered this solution to the
motorist's problem: Remove one lug nut from each of the other three tires and use
them to attach the spare. Each tire should hold securely with three lug nuts until the
motorist reaches a gas station. The grateful motorist thanked the institution resident
and then asked, "How'd you think of such a good solution to this problem?" The
resident replied, "I'm not dumb, I'm just crazy!"
I doubt if this exchange ever really occurred. After this problem appeared in the
earlier editions of this book, students from many different countries wrote to tell me
that they heard the same story, but with the poor motorist breaking down near their
school. In any case, virtually everyone agrees that the resident offered a good solu­
tion to the motorist's predicament. Why was it so difficult for the motorist to solve
the problem? Why did the solution seem so easy and obvious after it was revealed?
How did the resident come up with such a good solution?

WHAT IS A PROBLEM?

Even now there are few schools that encourage the young or old to think out
questions for themselves. And yet, life is a continuous problem for the living,
and first of all we should be equipped to think, if possible.
-Clarence Darrow (1936, p. 25)

Everyone has problems, so it would seem that it would be an easy word to define.
We all know a problem when we see one, but how would you define the general
term "problem"? Psychologists think of a problem as a gap or barrier between
where you are and where you want to be. You have a problem if you cannot think of
a way of getting around the gap or barrier so that you can reach the place you
want to be or when there appears to be many ways around the gap or barrier, but
you do not know which of the apparent paths will actually lead to the goal. This de­
finition of a problem is graphically represented in Fig. 9.1. As you will see later in
this chapter, the way a problem is represented can influence how or whether you
can solve it. Be sure that you understand the way the word problem is visually
defined in Fig. 9.1.
3 50 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

x y
You are here You want to be here

There is a gap or barrier separating you from where you want to be. This is a problem .

FIG. 9. I. A visual representation of a "problem." To solve the problem, you need to find a
way to get over the gap or around the barrier that is keeping you from the place (or state)
where you want to be.

ANATOMY OF A PROBLEM

Finding the right answer is important, of course. But more important is


developing the ability to see that problems have multiple solutions, that getting
from X to Y demands basic skills and mental agility, imagination, persistence,
patience.
-Mary Hatwood Futrell, President, NEA
(cited in Heiman & Slomianko, 1986, p. 18)
Consider this more mundane problem that differs in several important ways
from the "lug nut" problem presented at the start of this chapter: Keith has to catch
a 9:00 a.m. plane for Philadelphia, and he's already behind schedule. The quickest
route to the airport is the freeway, except when the traffic is heavy. The traffic is al­
most always heavy with commuters during the morning rush hour. There is a back
road route that might be a good one, if the road along the river isn't flooded. The
road is frequently closed because of flooding after heavy rains. As you can probably
guess, it rained last night. The surface street route is the longest. If Keith chooses
this route, he may miss his plane. Of course, if he spends too much time pondering
this problem, he'll surely miss his plane. Which route should he take?
To understand any complex phenomenon, like problem solving, we need a
model or theoretical framework that we can use to study and understand how peo­
ple solve all sorts of problems. A model is an as, if statement. This means, let's ex­
amine the phenomenon that we want to know about "as if" it were something else.
In an earlier chapter, I suggested that you think about memory as if it consisted of
stages in a computer program and to think of different kinds of memory as different
ways of slicing a pizza. Theoretical models of this sort are useful for organizing
what we know about thinking and for suggesting new types of research and ways to
improve the process we are trying to understand.
In their classic book, Newell and Simon (1972) conceptualized all problems as
being composed of the same basic parts or structures. Their idea is that problems
can be understood by reducing them to their anatomical parts. According to this
view, the anatomy of a problem can be thought of as having a starting or initial
state (Keith's home) and a final or goal state (the airport). All of the possible solu­
tion paths from the initial state to the goal state comprise the problem space. In
solving a problem, people search through the problem space to find the best path
WHAT IS A PROBLEM 35 1

from the initial state to the goal; that is, they consider all of the alternatives that
would lead to the goal and select the best one.
In addition to an initial state, a goal state, and the paths connecting them, there
are givens-information and rules that place constraints on the problem. The givens
include the knowledge needed to reach the goal and the need to select the best
route. This information can be explicitly stated or implicitly assumed. Two implicit
givens in the problem presented earlier were the knowledge that Keith would drive
a car to the airport and that he would either take the freeway route, back-road route,
or surface-street route. This anatomy or framework for conceptualizing problems
has proven useful in understanding the process of problem solving. The anatomy of
the airport problem is schematically shown in Fig. 9.2. We return to the airport
problem later in the chapter as different problem-solving strategies are considered.
Problems differ in many ways, including difficulty and where in the problem space
the gap occurs. In the airport problem, the difficulty lies in choosing the path (route)
that would get Keith to the goal in the shortest time. In the lug nut problem, the diffi­
culty was in generating any solution path. The initial state was a spare tire with no lug
nuts; the goal was mounting the spare tire to the car securely enough to drive the car.
The problem in both scenarios was the apparent absence of paths to the goal.
Consider Rubik's cube as a difficult problem. The goal for a Rubik's cube is to
align each small colored square so that each of the six sides of the cube will be a uni­
form color. This is a prohibitive problem because there are millions of combinations
of possible moves (paths to the goal). The "trick" is to determine which combination
of moves will lead to the goal. In this sort of problem, the difficulty lies in redUCing
the number of possible paths so that only potentially correct ones will be chosen.
Newell and Simon (1972) calculated that the average 40-move chess game has 1 0 120
paths. This number is so large that it is almost impossible for most of us to imagine!
Perhaps this is why we view great chess masters with such awe. They have the
knowledge to avoid blind paths (bad moves) that won't lead to the goal (winning)
and to select the best combination of moves.
Although problem solving, decision making, and creativity are discussed in sepa­
rate chapters in this book, there is considerable overlap among these topics. Many

FIG. 9.2. The anatomy of the airport problem. Givens: Keith will drive to the airport. He
will take one of these routes. He must take the fastest route.
352 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

decisions are involved in solving a problem; generating satisfactory solution paths


often requires considerable creativity. The division among these topics is for ease of
presentation. All of the chapters in this text are interrelated in that they represent ar­
bitrary ways of "cutting up the thinking pie." The information presented in the
other chapters will also contribute to your understanding of problem solving.

STAGES IN PROBLEM SOLVING

The aim of heuristics is to study the methods and rules of discovery and
invention . . . . Heuristic, as an adjective, means "serving to discover."
-Polya (1945, pp. 1 12-1 13)
In 1926 Graham Wallas examined anecdotal accounts of creative scientists and con­
cluded that problem solving progresses in a series of stages. Although there is
disagreement among psychologists as to whether all problem solving is done in
qualitatively different stages, a brief review of the hypothesized stages may prove
useful to us as problem solvers.
The first stage is preparation or familiarization. This includes the time spent in
understanding the nature of the problem, the desired goal, and the givens. This is a
crucial part in problem solving because a correct solution cannot be generated with­
out an adequate understanding of the problem. The second stage is the production
stage. During this stage, the problem solver produces the solution paths that define
the problem space. Judgment or evaluation is the third stage. During this stage, in­
dividuals evaluate the solution paths in order to select the best one. The fourth stage
is a strange one that may or may not occur, depending on the problem. Sometimes
when we can't find a solution path, we stop working on the problem, at least for a
short while. The period when we're not actively considering the problem is called
the incubation stage. There are many reports from famous scientists that a solution
came to them during the incubation phase-seemingly "out of the blue." Because of
the fascination incubation holds for most people, it deserves separate consideration.

Incubation

Have you ever had the experience of working unsuccessfully on a problem, then
having the solution come to you sometime later when you were not consciously
thinking about it? If so, then you have experienced incubation effects first hand. The
term incubation suggests a mother hen sitting on great ideas that are about to hatch.
The idea of an incubation phase is attractive to most people. It represents one of
the few instances in which we may get something for nothing. An oft-cited example
of incubation comes from the writings of the famous French mathematician Poin­
care (1929):

Then I turned my attention to the study of some arithmetical questions apparently without
much success and without a suspicion of any connection with my preceding researches.
Disgusted with my failure, I went to spend a few days at the seaside, and thought of some­
thing else. One morning, walking on the bluff, the idea came to me, with just the same
characteristics of brevity, suddenness and immediate certainty, that the arithmetic
STAGES IN PROBLEM SOLVING 353

transformations of indeterminate ternary quadratic forms were identical with those of


non-Euclidean geometry. (p. 388)

Incubation is a poorly understood phenomenon. If your employer found you sit­


ting with your feet propped on your desk, gazing out the window, she probably
would not be pleased to learn that you were "incubating" on company time. A fa­
miliar experience is having a correct answer come to you immediately after turning
in an exam or paper. This is most likely the result of incubation. It's a good idea to
work well ahead of deadlines to allow ample time for incubation effects to occur.
We don't know how people are able to produce solutions during time-outs. There is
no evidence that people continue to work on the problem at an unconscious level,
although some people have suggested that this is how incubation occurs. Most
likely, the time-out period serves to dissipate fatigue and allow individuals to get
out of sets or ruts in their thinking processes so that they can view the problem from
a different perspective.
Herbert A. Simon (1977), the Nobel Prize-winning psychologist, has attempted to
explain incubation as due, in part, to selective forgetting. He suggested that when we
are working on a problem we rely on a relatively small number of concepts held in a
limited capacity short-term or working memory. (See Chapter 2 on Memory for a
detailed discussion of this concept.) When we're not working on a problem, the infor­
mation held in short-term memory is quickly forgotten. If this information was not
productive for discovering a solution, then having forgotten it will be beneficial to
finding a good solution. There is good evidence that when we are trying to recall a
name or word that we know we know, but can't recall (that frustrating tip-of-the
tongue feeling), successful retrieval will often occur sometime later, when we are not
actively trying to remember the name or word (e.g., Burke, MacKay, Worthley, &
Wade, 1991).
It's a good idea to put aside a problem that you're having difficulty solving and
return to it at a later time (Smith & Blankenship, 1991). This is especially good ad­
vice during an exam when you can skip a difficult problem and move on to solve
other ones that are easier. At least you'll be sure of getting credit for the easier prob­
lems, but watch your time limits carefully so that you can correctly finish as many
problems as possible in the allotted time. (Of course, it's also a good idea to work on
the problems worth the most points first to maximize your exam score.)

Insight

Did you ever have the solution to a problem come to you "in a flash"? Sudden
knowledge of the solution is called insight or the "Aha!" experience. Insightful solu­
tions can occur during periods of incubation or while actively working on a prob­
lem. It is metaphorically referred to as switching on a lightbulb in the head. Insight
experiences are common. I have found them to occur frequently in the statistics
classes that I teach. Often students will ponder over a problem or listen attentively
to a lecture, then suddenly they'll break into a broad grin and exclaim, "Now I un­
derstand!" A law school student once told me that she spent the first three-fourths
of her first year in law school in an intellectual fog. She really felt that she under­
stood very little about the basic concepts. Then, something "clicked" and she sud­
denly understood the reasoning that went into legal principles. It's as if a little light
went on that illuminated the concepts. Her insight led to a successful legal career.
354 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Reprinted with special permission of NAS, INC.

Persistence

"J have a bias, which leads me to believe that no problem of human relations
is ever insolvable."
-Ralph Bunche (quoted in Beilensen & Jackson, 1992, p. 31)
Although persistence doesn't usually appear as a stage in problem solving, it is prob­
ably the most important variable in determining success. An individual who persists
at a problem is much more likely to solve it than an individual who gives up. Persis­
tence is close to Levine's (1994) idea of "intimate engagement" (p. 3), the willingness
to work on a problem in an involved and concentrated way. For example, suppose
that you are given a problem to solve in mathematics. It should be obvious that if you
give up as soon as you find that the solution isn't immediately apparent, you will not
perform as well in solving the problem as someone who continues to work on it.
Think about the anatomy of the problems that I just described. Suppose that you
cannot find a path from the initial state to the goal. Giving up will assure failure. Sev­
eral studies have shown that terminating the search through the problem space too
early in the problem-solving process is a leading reason for failure in problem solving.
Heller, Saltzstein, and Caspe (1992) compared the way experienced physicians go
about solving the problem of making an accurate diagnosis with the way novice
physicians make a diagnosis. When you visit a physician, you are there because you
have a problem. You need to find the cause for your symptoms, so that the symp­
toms and the underlying cause can be treated. Novice physicians terminated their
search for a cause as soon as they found a plausible alternative. By contrast, the se­
nior physicians persisted in their search through the problem space even after they
found a possible cause. Similar results were found when students who were suc­
cessful in solving problems in a genetics class were compared to unsuccessful stu­
dents. The most salient difference between the successful and unsuccessful problem
solvers was the tendency to consider more options; that is, the good problem solvers
persisted longer than the poor problem solvers when searching for solutions and
continued to work on the problem after a plausible solution was found (Smith, 1988).
The same results were found in studies of mathematical problem solving. When
college students are given mathematical problems to solve, most will try to recall a
solution for a similar problem (retrieval from memory of a familiar solution) instead
of trying to reason from their knowledge of mathematics (Lithner, 2000). Those who
continue to work on the problem when they cannot readily recall a solution are
more successful than those students who "give up." This is an important point: In
WELL-DEFINED AND ILL-DEFINED PROBLEMS 355

order to become a good problem solver, you must be willing to work at the problem
and to search the problem space for solution paths even when none are obvious or a
plausible one has been found.

WELL-DEFINED AND ILL-DEFINED PROBLEMS

Here is Edward Bear, coming downstairs. Now, bump, bump, bump, on the back
of his head, behind Christopher Robin. It is, as far as he knows, the only way of
coming downstairs, but sometimes he feels that there really is another way, if
only he could stop bumping for a moment and think of it.
-A. A. Milne (Winnie-the Pooh, 1 926, p. 3)
Problems come in all shapes and sizes. Consider the following two problems:
1 . The parallelogram problem (after Wertheimer, 1959). Some time back in fifth
or sixth grade, you learned that in order to find the area of a rectangle you should
multiply the height by the length. Now you are given the following parallelogram
that is 4" long and 2" high. What is its area?

-+--- 4"--+

2. Write a poem expressing the joy you feel when spring flowers bloom.
Do these problems seem qualitatively different to you? The parallelogram prob­
lem has a single correct answer. Have you figured it out? Wertheimer (1959)
suggested that the correct answer lies in perceptual reorganization, or seeing the
problem in a new way. The new way consists of seeing the parallelogram in terms of
a rectangle and two triangles. Thus, the parallelogram becomes:

Once the problem is restructured this way, it is only a short leap to figure out that
the area of the parallelogram can be found with the same formula for the area of a
rectangle because the two triangles can be fit together so that a new rectangular fig­
ure is formed with a 4" length and a 2" height. In the present example, the area of
the parallelogram is 2" X 4" 8 square inches. There is no other correct answer. The
=

goal (correct answer) is well defined, as is the path to the goal.


Writing a poem is a different sort of problem. The goal (a beautiful poem) is ill
defined, as there are many forms a poem can take. There are countless ways to write
a poem. The greatest difficulty in this case lies in evaluating the quality of the end
product. The goal is uncertain in ill-defined problems, thus part of the difficulty lies
in determining if the problem has been solved.
Most of the problems that confront people outside of school are ill defined. The
problem solver must decide how to define the goal and then evaluate how well the
356 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

goal has been attained. By contrast, many of the problems that students are asked to
solve in school are well defined, that is, there is a single correct answer. Other exam­
ples of ill-defined problems are: creating a way to increase sales for a business; finding
more effective ways to study; writing a clear, easy-to-read textbook; saving money for
college tuition; building a better mousetrap; de-escalating the nuclear arms race; get­
ting a date with the attractive newcomer at your school; and improving the environ­
ment. In ill-defined problems, the goal may be vague or incomplete, which makes the
generation of solution paths difficult and their evaluation even more difficult.
One of the best ways to approach ill-defined problems is to make the goal ex­
plicit. It is usually possible to state the goal in several different ways for ill-defined
problems. For example, the problem of increasing sales can be reidentified as the
problem of increasing profits because the real goal is to find ways to make more
money. When stated in this form, the problem changes from its initial conceptual­
ization. Solution paths can now include ways to cut losses, reduce inventories, or
collect bad debts. The best way to approach ill-defined problems is to specify multi­
ple goals in objective terms so that a variety of solution paths can be considered.
This sort of exercise will suggest additional solutions and can improve the way you
search for solutions.
Sometimes the distinction between well-defined and ill-defined problems blurs.
Consider again the problem of getting Keith to the airport on time. If the problem is
selecting among the three routes to the airport, it is well defined, but if other solu­
tion paths and goals are possible, for example fly to the airport, or take a different
plane from a nearer airport, or take the subway, then the problem becomes some­
what more difficult to define. Even when a problem seems to be well defined, it is
useful to consider whether other goal states would solve the problem, and, if so,
what sorts of solution paths are possible with different goals.

PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION

In the mathematics and science courses I took in college, I was enormously


irritated by the hundreds of hours that I wasted staring at problems without any
good idea about what approach to try next in attempting to solve them. I
thought at the time that there was no educational value in those "blank"
minutes and I see no value in them today.
-Wickelgren (1974, p. ix)
Recent research in problem solving has focused on the importance of devising a
plan for finding and selecting solutions. Planning is a higher order thinking skill
that is used to direct and regulate behavior. A plan provides a structure that prob­
lem solvers can use in a step-by-step manner to help them reach the desired goal.

Multiple Statements of the Goal

Stating the goal in many different ways, which results in multiple goal states, even
when the problem appears to be well defined, is an example of a planful approach
to problem solving. The generation of multiple goal states will increase the size of
the problem space and provide more opportunities for finding a good solution. This
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 357

sort of plan is transcontextual, which means that it can be used in any context with
any sort of problem (Ceci & Ruiz, 1993). Here is an example of this approach:
Various opinion polls have identified "fear of crime" as the number 1 concern of
most Americans. Not too surprisingly, politicians have made crime a major part of
their campaign pledges. Fear of crime is an important and ill-defined problem. Sup­
pose we turn this problem into a clearly articulated goal.
Goal #1 : Reduce crime. Given this goal, what are some possible solutions or paths
of action that will move our society from its present start state of "fear of crime" to­
ward the goal of reducing crime? Here are two possible solutions that (might) move
us toward the goal of reducing crime:

• Make capital punishment a national law


• Incarcerate criminals for life if they are convicted of three major crimes

Now, let's restate the goal in other ways and see how each restatement of the goal
suggests different solutions. One approach for restating the goal state is to view the
problem from different perspectives. What is a goal state for those citizens who are
potential victims of crime?
Goal #2 : Make life safer for honest citizens. This sort of goal shifts solutions from
the criminals to the potential victims of crime. Some possible solutions that come to
mind for attaining this goal:

• Provide better security for honest citizens


• Teach everyone self-defense
• Organize anticrime groups in every neighborhood

Goal #3: Reduce the number of criminals. Given this goal, solutions now focus on
numbers rather than methods and on the criminals instead of the honest people in
the community. For example,

• Send criminals to Siberia


• Return to gallows and public floggings to send a strong anticrime message to
would-be criminals
• Begin community programs that act as a deterrent to a life of crime (e.g., im­
prove education and sports programs)

Goal #4: Change people's perceptions so that they no longer fear crime. This sort
of goal will not affect the actual crime rate, rather it will change how people think
about crime. Some possible solutions for this goal:

• Give everyone drugs that reduce anxiety (so they no longer fear crime)
• Provide information that shows that the crime rate is really very low (this
could be true or false; either would satisfy this goal, although lying is obvi­
ously unethical)

Goal #5: Reduce violent crimes. This goal also shifts how we think about the prob­
lem because it concerns the degree of violence instead of the number of crimes,
number of criminals, or how people feel about crime. Some possible solutions:

• Make it illegal to own a gun


• Legalize drug use
358 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Another way to generate goal states is to view the problem from the perspective
of the criminals. What would it take to get them not to engage in crime? It soon be­
comes clear that crime is not a homogeneous category, and different sorts of actions
are needed for different sorts of crimes. Suppose that you were a car-jacker. What
would prevent you from hijacking cars? Would having a job make a difference?
What if you abused your spouse? What would work to stop spousal abuse?
Of course, some of these possible solutions are ludicrous, such as sending criminals
to Siberia or giving everyone anti-anxiety drugs, and others are unethical. The idea
behind this example is that new perspectives on a difficult problem emerge when we
are forced to state an ill-defined goal in several ways. It is likely that several solutions
can be used together so that America's number 1 fear is alleviated. Try this sort of ex­
ercise with other difficult problems. You may be surprised to find that you can think
of different categories of solutions by specifying qualitatively different sorts of goals
and by viewing the problem from different perspectives. Restating the goal in multi­
ple ways and considering different perspectives are two examples of using a plan to
solve problems. Although plans for solving problems can vary in complexity, most
will consist of five basic steps: (a) recognition that a problem exists (This is an impor­
tant stage that often is the mark of creativity, a topic that is addressed in the next
chapter. Consider any major change, such as the change from horse and buggy to mo­
torized vehicles. For most of the pre-automotive world, horses worked very well, and
the proposition that they could be replaced by a box on wheels that constantly broke
down and needed fuel to run, was ludicrous. Few people saw any problem with
travel by horse and therefore did not see a problem that needed to be solved); (b) con­
struction of a representation of the problem that includes the initial and goal states;
(c) generation and evaluation of possible solutions; (d) selection of a possible solution;
and (e) execution of the possible solution to determine if it solves the problem.
Unfortunately, some or all of the steps will have to be repeated if the goal is not\
attained. Problem solving is not a simple or linear process. It often requires changes
in the representation of the problem or redefinition of the goal as well as generation
of numerous possible solutions and reevaluation of the possible solutions. Brans­
ford and Stein (1993) use the acronym IDEAL to stand for these five steps: I (Identify
the problem); D (Define and represent the problem); E (Explore possible strategies);
A (Act on the strategies); L (Look back and evaluate the effects of your activities).
General problem-solving approaches are used in many situations. For example,
basic principles in problem solving are being used to help couples avoid divorce by
teaching them how to solve their marital problems (Bodenmann, 1997) and in man­
agement training programs in many corporations where managers are taught to act
like problem solvers (O'Loughlin & McFadzean, 1999).
A major goal of The Productive Thinking Program (Covington, Crutchfield,
Davies, & Olton, 1974), one of the oldest and most popular programs designed to
help children "learn to think," was to develop the habit of planning a solution strat­
egy. Figure 9.3 shows a few sample frames from this program that emphasize the
need to approach problems in an orderly manner.

Representation of the Problem Space

There is little doubt that diagrammatic representations considerably help


humans solve certain classes of problems.
Patrick Oliver (2001 , p. 63)
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 359

Oh, lure. We picked out all the


Important objects and persons,
such as Carlos and Mike, the
mule, and the water can . . .

It will be especially important to use


that plan in the case I'm going to
give you to work on by yourselves.

FIG. 9.3. Advice for children on how to devise a problem solving plan. (From The Pro­
ductive Thinking Program by Covington, Crutchfield, Davies, & Olton, 1974, Lesson 6, p. 17).

The best way to solve a problem is to devise the best representation. In an extensive
set of studies of the way scientists think about difficult problems, Dunbar (1998)
found that, when scientists represented a problem, they naturally included those
features of the problem that they thought would be important in solving the prob­
lem, with systematic differences among the representations reflecting different be­
liefs about the nature of the problem. Consider, for example, an economics problem
like a high rate of unemployment. Members of different political parties will repre­
sent the same problem in different ways because they have different beliefs about
the cause of the problem. The same sort of representational differences were found
in studies of the way scientists solve problems in their academic discipline. Accord­
ing to Dunbar, the molecular biologists who recently identified a gene for some
types of breast cancer were successful in their quest for this elusive gene because
they used a different representation for this genetics problem than the unsuccessful
scientists.
Mayer (in press) found that good visual representations can help readers compre­
hend difficult text. Readers who have already read Chapter 2 on memory will recog­
nize this finding as an example of the principle that visual and verbal information
work together to enhance memory. (If you don't remember this principle, try draw­
ing a diagram that shows the two systems working together along with a verbal sum­
mary of the principle.) One principle of good thinking that appears in almost every
chapter of this book is to use multiple representational systems-that is, adding dia­
grams to printed text and using verbal descriptors with spatial information.
360 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

In discussing the way good representations are constructed, Newell (1983) said
that "Memory must be tickled," a phrase that I have often used because I believe
that it is a critical consideration in how we think. Every time you think, your knowl­
edge about the problem must be accessed and utilized. Every problem solver must
be able to make inferences from problem statements to build an adequate problem
representation-one in which missing and conflicting information is made obvious
and critical relationships are easy to grasp.
Try this example: Draw a representation and write an algebraic formula that corre­
sponds to the following statement:
There are six times as many students as professors at this university.
If you are like many college students, you drew a diagram like this one:

I�P
This translates into 6S=P.

If I gave you the number of students, you could use this formula to find that
number of professors and vice versa. Can you see why the formula derived from
this representation is wrong? The formula states that there are more professors than
there are students, rather than the reverse! The reason that so many students have
difficulty with this problem and others like it lies in the way in which the words are
translated into a diagram. The juxtaposition of the words "six times the number of
students" seems to automatically suggest that the number of students should be
multiplied by six. Mayer found a significant improvement in the mathematical
problem-solving skills of college students after only 3 hours of training on how to
devise correct representations (Lewis & Mayer, 1987). It is difficult to overstate the
importance of a good representation when solving problems.
The following sections contain suggestions for devising good representations and
demonstrate the intimate relationship between the representation and the solution
to the problem. Good representations share certain characteristics. They take advan­
tage of spatial locations to group information in a visual format; they also act as a
check on how well you understand the problem. Let's try some examples of ways to
represent problems.

Write It Down
All problems are initially represented in your head. It is a good idea to get the
paths and goals on paper or into some other concrete form. This tactic will reduce
the memory load and allow you to view the problem visually. The simplest example
of the aid provided by a pencil and paper is a straightforward multiplication prob­
lem. Solve the following problem without writing anything:

976
X 893

Of course, you would consider this a ridiculous request because it is a simple


problem with paper and pencil and a difficult one to perform in your head because
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 36 1

of the demands on working memory. Whenever there are several facts or different
options to keep track of, it is a good idea to use paper and pencil.

Draw a Graph or Diagram


"A bear, starting at point P, walked one mile due south. Then he changed direc­
tion and walked one mile due east. Then he turned again to the left and walked one
mile due north, and arrived exactly at the point P he started from. What was the
color of the bear?" (Polya, 1957, p. 234).
Does this problem seem strange or even impossible to you? If you draw a simple
"map" of the bear's route, it will be a pie-shaped wedge. Where on earth is this pos­
sible? Think about a globe. Did you just say "Why, of course, point P must be the
North Pole" to yourself? Once you realize that you're at the North Pole, this prob­
lem becomes easy to solve. The bear must be white, because only polar bears live at
the North Pole.
Consider the following problem:

A venerable old monk leaves the monastery at exactly 6:00 a.m. to climb a winding moun­
tain trail to the solitude of the mountain peak. He arrives at exactly 4:00 p.m. After spend­
ing the night in sleep and prayer, he leaves the mountain peak at exactly 6:00 a.m. and
arrives at the monastery at exactly 4:00 p.m. There are no constraints on the speed at which
he walks. In fact, he stops several times along the way to rest. Is there some point on the
mountain trail that he passes at exactly the same time each day?

Stop and think about this problem for a moment. Does it seem like a difficult one?
There are two ways to consider this problem that will make the answer seem sim­
ple, but before you go on, decide how you would go about solving this problem,
and then solve it. As you can probably guess, a good representation of the central
elements of the problem will be an important determinant of the solution.
One solution is to draw a graph of the monk's ascent and descent. The graph can
take any shape because you know nothing about his hourly progress. The graphs of
the ascent and descent should appear as in Fig. 9.4.
Now, superimpose the two graphs and see if there must be some point where the
graphs intersect. If there is, then there is some time when the monk passed the same
point at the same time on each day. This is shown in Fig. 9.5.
Drawing a graph provides a clear picture of the results. Actually, an easier way of
solving this problem involves changing the representation and restating the facts in
the problem in an equivalent, but different, form. Assume two people traverse the
same mountain path at the same time on the same morning. If one starts at the
monastery and the other starts at the mountain peak, both leaving at 6:00 a.m. and
both arriving at their opposite destinations at 4:00 p.m., it is obvious they must meet
somewhere along the path no matter how often each chooses to rest and reflect.
Thus, with a change in representation, a difficult problem can become trivial.
I recently taught a laboratory course in experimental psychology. In that course,
college students were required to conduct experiments, gather data, and interpret
their data in meaningful ways. Although the students were taught the statistical
methods needed for data analysis, I found that when they graphed their results they
obtained a much better understanding of the phenomenon they investigated. They
were able to use their experimental results to formulate sound conclusions because
they understood the nature of their findings. The students found that a simple graph
362 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Mowttain
Peak

Ascent-First Day

MOMS�ry ���__�__�������__������
6AM 7 8 9 10 1 1 Noon 2 3 4PM
Leave Tune Arrive

MOlUltain
Peak

-8
a
';'
<
Descent-Second Day

MOMS�ry ���__�__�������__�__����
6AM 7 8 9 10 1 1 Noon 2
Leave Tune Arrive

FIG. 9.4. Graphs of the monks ascent and descent. The graphs can take any shape because
the monk can rest as often as he wishes when he climbs the hill and when he descends.

Moun ta in
Peak

Mona stery �---;!:----'!:----' ��'::-��""__ """ ---'__---'__ ---'_�


6AM 7 8 9 JO 1 1 Noon 1 2 3 4P�
Time

FIG. 9.5. By superimposing the ascent and descent graphs, it is easy to see that there must
be some place at which the graphs intersect. Thus, there must be a place on the mountain trail
that the monk crosses at the same time each day.
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 363

was a more valuable tool for comprehension than the elaborate statistical proce­
dures that they were required to use.
Graphs and other kinds of diagrams are especially useful comprehension strate­
gies in mathematical and scientific problem solving. For example, a common prob­
lem in undergraduate statistics courses requires finding the area between two points
under a certain kind of curve called a "normal" or "bell-shaped" curve. This prob­
lem can be difficult or confusing for students, but it becomes easy if they draw the
curve and shade in the area they want to find. In fact, I don't give my statistics stu­
dents the algebraic rules for finding the appropriate area. Students find it easier to
figure it out for themselves from the diagrams they draw.
Consider the geometry problem that was posed by Kohler (1969). You are given
only information in Fig. 9.6 and the fact that the radius of the circle is 5" . Can you
find the length of line L in inches?
One of the reasons that this is a difficult problem is that in the pictorial represen­
tation line L appears most saliently as the hypotenuse of two right triangles, the
triangle with sides LDX, and the triangle with the other two sides defined by the in­
tersecting horizontal and vertical radii. How can you change this diagram so that
the solution can be obtained? Consider the information given. Because the only
length given in this diagram is the radius of the circle, it is likely that this will be
needed in solving the problem. Try drawing in additional radii around the circle as
shown in Fig. 9.7. Does this help to suggest the solution?
Look carefully at the quadrant containing L. Can you find another line equal in
length to L? If you think of L as the diagonal inside a rectangle with sides D, X, and
the unlabeled sides formed by the intersection of the horizontal and vertical radii,
the other diagonal in the rectangle must be the same length as L. The other diagonal
must be the radius; thus, line L, like the radius, is also 5" long. Although the initial
representation of the problem was somewhat misleading, a solution was found with
the appropriate operations.
Of course, there was no way of knowing at the outset that moving the radii
around the circle would lead to the answer. It was obvious, however, that the answer
would depend on the radius in some way, because it was the only measurement

FIG. 9 . 6. Using only the Information given in this figure, can you determine the length of
line L? (Problem adapted from Kohler, 1 969)
364 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

FIG. 9 . 7. Additional radii have been drawn over Fig. 9.5 as an intermediate step toward a
solution. Can you use the additional radii to find the length of the line L?

given, and the goal was to find the length of line 1. The operations used to trans­
form the givens into solution paths involved the knowledge you brought with you
to the problem. If you did not know that the two diagonals in a rectangle must be
equal, then you could not have solved the problem. Good problem solvers utilize a
solid knowledge base that is built up over a lifetime of educational experiences­
ones that are accumulated both inside and outside of the classroom. The best strat­
egy for solving problems is to know a great deal about a great many topics.
Let's try another example in which graphs or diagrams will simplify the search
for a solution path. Problems like this one were frequently used in the Analytical
Reasoning Test portion of the Graduate Record Examination, a test that is used in
admissions decisions for many graduate schools. In a study of the predictive valid­
ity of these tests for graduate students in Yale's psychology department, Sternberg
and Williams (1997) found that scores on the analytic test were significantly corre­
lated with the ratings given to graduate students by Yale faculty several years later
(at least for the male students in their sample).

To save money and their sanity, Melvin, Brock, Marc, and Claire decide to form a baby­
sitting cooperative. They agree to baby-sit for each other's children with the understand­
ing that when one of them stays with another's children, the recipient will repay the sitter
with an equal number of baby-sitting hours. They decide to tally baby-sitting hours at the
end of the month. During the month, Melvin sat with Brock's children 9 hours, Marc sat
with Melvin's children 3 hours, and Claire stayed with Melvin's children 6 hours. Marc
baby-sat 9 hours with Claire's children and Brock baby-sat 5 hours with Claire's children.
Which of these people has 12 hours of baby-sitting time due to him or her?

A good diagram of the relationship among these four people is clearly needed.
The relevant givens will involve the four people and the number of hours owed to
each. Let's start with the first sentence, "Melvin sat with Brock's children 9 hours."
Thus, Brock owes Melvin 9 hours of baby-sitting at the end of the month. The opera­
tion being used is the transformation of number of hours spent baby-sitting into
number of hours owed to each sitter. A simple diagram of this relationship is:

9 hours
Brock --------_. Melvin
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATlON 365

The next sentence translates into "Melvin owes Marc 3 hours and Melvin owes
Claire 6 hours."

/
Marc

hours

/
\
3
9 hours
Brock -----+. Melvin

6 hO

Claire

Then, changing the third sentence so that it reflects what is owed, Claire owes Marc
9 hours and Claire owes Brock 5 hours.

Marc

Brock
� ��
9 hours
3
/1

Melvin
9 hours

6 hours

Claire

It is easy to see from this diagram that only Marc is owed 12 hours of baby­
sitting, 3 hours from Melvin and 9 hours from Claire. A good diagram of the hours
owed is essential in finding the solution to this problem.
There are several other ways of representing the information in the baby-sitting
co-op problem that will display all of the essential relationships, and thus also give
the correct answer. When a colleague (Dr. Susan Nummedal at California State Uni­
versity, Long Beach) posed this problem to her students, she found that they de­
vised a variety of representations to solve the problem. One student used a simple
bar graph to keep track of the number of hours sat by each participant. This repre­
sentation is shown in Fig. 9.8.
Other students used a variety of table formats. One listed the number of hours
"gave" as a positive number and "received" as a negative number because it was
owed. Another student split the information into "sitter" and "sat for" categories,
then filled in a table of information summing across the columns for the total num­
ber of "sat for" hours for each participant, and summing down the rows for the total
number of "sitter" hours for each participant. These representations are offered in
Tables 9.1 and 9.2, respectively.
As a baby-sitting co-op problem demonstrates, there are often many ways of rep­
resenting a given problem. As you work through the problems in this chapter, try a
variety of representations. A good representation will present all of the relevant in­
formation in a way that it can be readily understood and assimilated. Good repre­
sentations provide the necessary solution paths to the goal.
366 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

-
15
-

- :-

'" -
Ill:
-
;;;) 1 0
o -
:: r
... .,.
o

Ill:
W ..
r
; 5 '-'
�� -

� -
r

;;;)
z ;
....
� � or.
- �
-
- = � = � " �
-
...
...
e

..
�� "

� "


= ::;: � :;;: � ... �
- �
o � � �
M rh i n Marc (' I a i r .

FIG. 9.8. Alternative form representation

TABLE 9. 1
A Table Format for Representing
the Information in the Babysitting
Co-op Problem
Gave Received Total Due
Melvin +9 -3, - 6 o
Marc + 3, + 9 12
Claire +6 - 9, -15 -8
Brock +5 -9 -4

TABLE 9 . 2
An Alternative Table Format That Can B e Used to Represent
the Information in the Babysitting Co-op Program
Sitter Total Number
Melvin Marc Claire Brock of Hours Sat For
Melvin 3 6 9
Sat For Marc o
Claire 9 5 14
Brock 9 9
Total Number 9 12 6 5
of Hours Sat

Try a Hierarchical Tree


Hierarchical trees are branching diagrams. They are most frequently used to
assess mathematically the probability or likelihood of uncertain outcomes. (See
Chapter 4 on reasoning for the use of tree diagrams in solving if, then problems and
Chapter 7 on probability for the use of decision trees in calculating probabilities.)
Hierarchical trees or tree diagrams can be useful aids in decision making and prob­
lem solving. In this context, they are called decision trees. If the problem you're
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 367

working on is fairly complex, with each possible solution path requiring subsequent
additional paths, a hierarchical tree or tree diagram should be considered.
Here is a classic problem that has a long history in the psychological literature on
problem solving. Although the problem is a medical one, no specialized knowledge
is needed to solve it:
Suppose you are a doctor faced with a patient who has a malignant tumor in his stomach. It
is impossible to operate on the patient, but unless the tumor is destroyed the patient will
die. There is a kind of ray that can be used to destroy the tumor. If the rays reach the tumor
all at once at a sufficiently high intensity, the tumor will be destroyed. Unfortunately, at this
intensity the healthy tissue that the rays pass through on the way to the tumor will also be
destroyed. At lower intensities the rays are harmless to healthy tissue, but they will not af­
fect the tumor either. What type of procedure might be used to destroy the tumor with the
rays, and at the same time avoid destroying the healthy tissue? (Duncker, 1945, pp. 307-308)

Research has shown that this is a difficult problem to solve (and modern medical ad-
vances since 1945 make new solutions possible). Although a variety of solutions were
attempted, the best solution is to use several weak rays, each coming from different
places outside the body focused so that they would meet and summate at the tumor
site. In this manner, the healthy tissue won't be hurt by the weak rays, and the tumor
will receive a high level of radiation. This solution was formulated from a broader cate­
gory of solutions that included having each ray grow stronger as it reached the tumor.
One subject's search for solution paths is shown in Fig. 9.9 in a hierarchical tree
diagram. Note that the goal is explicitly stated at the top of the tree. General broad
strategies are listed one level below the goal, with more specific ways of satisfying
each strategy on lower levels.
Another example of using trees to solve problems is the familiar use of family
trees. Estate lawyers, who often face a tangled web of family relationships, need to
be able to determine the relations among family members in order to handle wills
and estate taxes. Multiple spouses, cohabitation, stepchildren, half-siblings, and out­
of-wedlock births can make the difficult matter of inheritance a legal nightmare.

Treatment of tumor by rays


without destruction of healthy tissue

Avoid contact between rays Desensitize the Lower the intensity of the rays
and healthy tissue healthy tissue on their way through healthy tissue

Use free Remove I nsert protecting Displace tumor


/\
Inject Immunize by

Postpone use Give weak intensity
path to healthy wall between rays toward surface desensitizing adaptation of full intensity in periphery and

"T" �T: '0 T ,�"' 1


chemical to weak rays until tumor is concentrate in
reached place of tumor

Esophagus I nsert a Feed substance By pressure


1
By use of lens
cannula which protects

PIG. 9 . 9. A hierarchical tree diagram of one subject's attempted solutions to Duncker's x­


ray problem. (After Duncker, 1945).
368 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Make a Matrix
A matrix is a rectangular array of facts or numbers. It is really just a fancy word
for a chart. When the givens in a problem can be broken down into categories, a
matrix may be a good method of representation. Consider the problem posed by
Whimbey and Lochhead (1982):

Three men-Fred, Ed, and Ted-are married to Joan, Sally, and Vickie, but not necessarily
in that order. Joan, who is Ed's sister, lives in Detroit, Fred dislikes animals. Ed weighs
more than the man who is married to Vickie. The man married to Sally breeds Siamese
cats as a hobby. Fred commutes over 200 hours a year from his home in Ann Arbor to his
job in Detroit. Match up the men with the women they married. (p. 67)

What are the categories of information given in this problem? The givens concern
husbands and wives. Set up a three-by-three matrix and fill in as much of it as you
can with the information given above:
Joan Sally Vickie

Fred
Ed
Ted

Because Joan is Ed's sister, she cannot be his wife, so fill in a "NO" in the Joan-Ed
cell of the matrix. Skip the next two statements for the time being and go on to the
statement that Ed weighs more than the man married to Vickie; therefore, Ed is not
married to Vickie. Ed must be married to Sally. So far the matrix appears as below:
Joan Sally Vickie

Fred NO
Ed NO YES NO
Ted NO

Peruse the problem for more clues. Have you found the important one? Fred lives in
Ann Arbor and Joan lives in Detroit; therefore, we would conclude that they're
probably not married. Because Fred is not married to Joan or Sally, he must be mar­
ried to Vickie. Who's left for Ted? Joan must be married to Ted.
The completed matrix:
Joan Sally Vickie
Fred NO NO YES
Ed NO YES NO
Ted YES NO NO

(Additional problems like this one can be found in the workbook that accompanies
this text, Thinking Critically About Critical Thinking.)
Admittedly, this is an artificial problem, not much like the ones we encounter in
real life. Let's consider a more practical application of the matrix form of problem
representation:
There is considerable controversy over the issue of vitamin C as a deterrent
for the common cold. How would you decide if vitamin C prevents colds? Most
probably, you would give vitamin C to some people and not others and count the
number of colds in each group. Suppose you found the following results: 10 people
who took vitamin C did not catch a cold; 4 people who took vitamin C caught a
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 369

Vitamin C
Took Vitamin Didn't Take
C Vitamin C
Caught a cold 4 6 Total number Of those who
who caught a caught a cold, %
cold: 10 who took vitamin
C: 40%
Of those who
caught a cold, %
who didn't take
vitamin C: 60%
Didn't catch 10 8 Total number Of those who
a cold who didn't didn't catch a
catch a cold: cold, % who took
18 vitamin C: 55.5%
(10/18)
Of those who
didn't catch a
cold, % who
didn't take
vitamin C: 44.4%
(8/ 18)
Total number Total number Total number
who took who didn't in the study: 28
vitamin C: take vitamin
14 C: 14

cold; 8 people who didn't take vitamin C didn't catch a cold; and 6 people who did­
n't take vitamin C caught a cold. What would you conclude?
Because we have categories of information (took or didn't take vitamin C and
caught or didn't catch a cold), a matrix displaying the appropriate values will help
us to understand the givens.
By examining every cell of the matrix, you can determine if vitamin C prevented
colds. To see if vitamin C worked, you need to consider how many of those who
caught a cold had taken vitamin C. The answer is 4 out of 10, or 40%. You also need to
consider how many of those who didn't catch a cold had taken vitamin C. The answer
is 10 out of 18, or 55.5%. Few would be willing to conclude from these data that vita­
min C helped to prevent colds from these data. (Research concepts are discussed
more fully in Chapter 6 and 7 on thinking as hypothesis testing and probability. Sta­
tistical tests are used to decide if these numbers are significantly different.) By repre­
senting the information in a matrix, the results can be more easily determined. This is
essentially the same problem that was discussed in Chapter 8 on decision making
when the nurses and physicians had to decide if there was a relationship between a
disease and a set of symptoms. Given the overlap among the topics, you would expect
that techniques that are useful in one context would also be useful in related contexts.

Manipulate Models
It is often a good idea to make a concrete representation for abstract problems.
I'm sure that you've seen an architect's model for a planned complex like a
370 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM·SOLVING SKILLS

shopping center, office building, or college campus. The miniature buildings and
walkways are not made because architects love doll-sized buildings. Although they
are often made to communicate architectural plans to others who are not skilled at
reading blueprints, the miniature models also help the architect solve problems.
With the movable parts, she or he can move the buildings to find the best way to
place them before construction begins.
Let's try a problem where making a model will help in finding a solution. There
are two groups of beings on a mythical planet in a far-away galaxy: they are Hobbits
and Orcs. One day three Hobbits got lost while exploring the homeland of the Orcs.
The Hobbits could get home safely if they could cross the river that separates their
two homelands. The Orcs agreed to help the Hobbits cross the river, but the only
boat they had could hold only two beings at a time, and the Hobbits could not let
themselves ever be outnumbered by the Orcs or the Orcs would eat them.
Your problem is to figure out a sequence of moves that will carry all three Hob­
bits to the other side of the river and return all three Orcs on their own side. The
constraints are that only two beings can fit in the boat at one time, and if at anytime
the Orcs on one shore outnumber the Hobbits, you'll have to start over.
This would be an impossible problem to solve without some external form of rep­
resentation. Use some small objects to represent the Hobbits and Orcs and move
them across an imaginary river. Three large paper clips for the Hobbits and three
small paper clips for the Orcs will work well. You'll have to imagine that you are
transporting them in a boat. Be sure to write down all of your moves. Plan to take as
long as 1 0 to 15 minutes to solve this problem. As you work toward the solution, be
aware of how you're thinking about the moves. Don't go on until you've worked
through the problem.
The complete sequence of moves needed to move the Hobbits is shown in
Fig. 9.10. One of the greatest difficulties with this problem is the need to move all
three Orcs across the river, a situation that is not desired, in order to move the Hob­
bits without allowing them to become outnumbered. Problems of this sort have
come to be known as detour problems because the path to the goal is not a direct
linear one. Intermediate steps are required that seem directly opposite to the goal­
in this case, moving all three Orcs to the opposite side of the river when the desired
goal is to have all of them on the side from which they originated. It is important to
recognize that the route to a goal will often involve detours.
As a more realistic example, consider Leon's goal to become very wealthy. One
solution path to the goal may involve going deeply into debt in order to finance his
education. Even though going deeply into debt is seemingly antagonistic to becom­
ing wealthy, it may be a necessary detour. Be sure to consider solution paths that in­
volve detours when faced with difficult problems.

Select the Best Representation


It is a good idea to utilize an external form of representation (e.g., paper and pen­
cil, a model) whenever there are more than a few givens that need to be manipu­
lated. The immediate or working memory span can quickly become overloaded. If
you have already read Chapter 8 on decision making, you will recognize the impor­
tance of writing down alternatives and considerations so that you can reduce the
load on working memory and allow the problem solver to generate more alternative
solutions. Experimental results or almost any other pattern of numbers should al­
ways be graphed. If your problem is mathematical or spatial, a diagram is likely to
PROBLEM PLANNING AND REPRESENTATION 37 1

H H �?::�
P R O B L E M S T AT f. M O V E S AC R O S S R I V E R
Step 1 . Move 2 Orcs

�-
HH �
START 0 0 0 _ v

Step 2. Ret u rn 1 Ore

�g:� �
H 0 0

H �����
0 -

Step 3. Move 2 Orcs

�-
H

o 0 w '" 0
V V '"

Step 4. Return 1 Ore

- dj
0 0 0

����
H H H

...... ... �
: HH����� 00 Step 5. Move 2 Hobbits

�-
1
(�oi�o
Step 6. Return 1 Hobbit and Ore

-�
H
0 ,,", v H H
_ "

��(
Step 7. Move 2 Hobbits

&-
H H H

o 0 ,-" v 0
V "" "

Step 8 . Return 1 Ore

-�
HHH

0 0 0 ���� O �

G OA L O O ����� HHH

Fig. 9. 1 0. Steps needed to move three Hobbits across the river using a boat that will hold
only two beings without allowing the Orcs to ever outnumber the Hobbits.

be helpful. Diagrams can help to disentangle any situation in which the givens have
many complex interrelationships. Diagrams can make important relationships ex­
plicit, a fact that can often lead directly to the goal. Hierarchical trees are a natural
form of representation when the material itself forms a hierarchically arranged
structure. Matrices are likely to be useful when the givens can be grouped into cate­
gories for meaningful comparisons. "Mock-ups" or miniature models can aid in
problem solving when movement and placement of the givens determine the solu­
tion. Often the way a problem is represented can mean the difference between a so­
lution or nonsolution (Posner, 1973). If you find that one form of representation isn't
fruitful, try a different one.
372 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES

Solving problems can be regarded as the most characteristically human activity.


-Polya, p. ix (1981 )
It does no good to tell someone who is faced with a problem that he should plan a
solution, if he has no idea how to plan. The steps look deceptively simple-generate
and evaluate possible solutions. But what if you can't think of any solutions? There
are several strategies that can be used in a systematic manner to help you generate
solutions. Although no single strategy can guarantee perfect solutions every time,
learning how to use several different strategies can give you direction and confi­
dence when presented with a new problem.
Schoenfeld (1979) found that many mathematicians and scientists claimed to use
specific strategies and rules when solving problems in their academic disciplines.
Many of the scientists and mathematicians believed that their students would solve
problems better if they learned some basic skills for attacking problems. In addition,
several researchers have found that instruction in general problem-solving skills can
improve problem-solving ability (e.g., Lithner, 2000). You can think of the following
strategies or problem-solving aids as ways to plan a solution.

Means-Ends Analysis

Most often progress toward the goal is not made along a single well-paved road.
When the goal is not immediately attainable, we often need to take detours or break
the problem down into smaller problems, called subproblems, each with its own
goal, called a subgoal (Catrambone, 1998; Dunbar, 1998). Like all of the strategies
for solving problems, selecting and utilizing subgoals requires planning. The proce­
dure by which people select subgoals and use them to progress toward the goal is
called means-ends analysis. This is a general, often powerful method for problem
solving. The problem is first broken down into subgoals. Operations that will reduce
the distance between the problem solver's current state and the subgoal are then
used. In this manner, the problem solver will move closer and closer to the goal.
Work through the following examples in order to clarify this concept.
The first step in means-ends analysis is to enumerate appropriate subgoals and to
select the most promising one. Suppose that during a game of chess you decide that
a good subgoal is to put the opposing king in check. The goal, of course, is to win
the game, but it will be necessary to work toward subgoals to attain the goal.
Putting the opposing king in check is the immediate "end" toward which you're
working. You now need to select the "means" for obtaining that end, hence the term
"means-ends analysis." In order to achieve your subgoal, determine the current
state position of your pieces. Then identify any difference between where your
pieces are and where you want them to be. Operations would be selected that
would reduce this difference, and place the opposing king in check. Suppose no sin­
gle move can achieve this subgoal. The means-ends analysis procedure would recy­
cle, this time selecting a smaller subgoal, perhaps moving another piece out of the
way. The constant recycling of these two processes-setting subgoals and reducing
distances-will allow you to make progress toward the goal.
A favorite problem of psychologists that can be used to demonstrate means-ends
analysis is the Tower of Hanoi problem. The name of this puzzle is derived from an
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 373

dime dime
penny
+ii'i7Qjjnl" .NQjjj.
penny
Quarter Quarter
S T A R T STATE G O A. L

FIG. 9. 1 1 . Start state and goal for the Tower of Hanoi problem. Use the strategy of means­
ends analysis to solve this problem.

interesting legend. Suppose that there are 3 pegs and 64 disks, each one a different
size, stacked on one of the pegs in size order. It may help to think of the disks as 64
different size doughnuts that can stack one on top of each other on the pegs. The
task is to transfer all of the disks from the first peg to the third peg using the middle
peg as an intermediary. The rules for moving disks include moving only one disk at
a time and never placing a disk on top of a smaller one. The legend around this task
is that there are monks in a monastery near Hanoi who are working on this puzzle,
and when they complete it the world will come to an end. Even if this legend were
true, you would have little cause for worry because if they were to make perfect
moves at the rate of one per second, it would take close to a trillion years to com­
plete this task (Raphael, 1976).
Because you probably don't want to spend quite that much time solving the
Tower of Hanoi, you can try a simplified version of it using only three disks. You
can easily work this problem using any three coins of different sizes (a quarter,
penny, and dime will work well) and three small sheets of paper. Stack the coins
with the smallest on top and largest on the bottom on one sheet of paper. The task is
to move the coins from the first piece of paper to the third so that they will be in the
same size order. You may move only one coin at a time. All three pieces of paper
may be used in solving the problem. Write down all of the moves you make in solv­
ing this problem. The initial and goal states are shown in Fig. 9.1 l .
In a means-end analysis of the Tower of Hanoi problem, one obvious subgoal is
to get the quarter on the third piece of paper. This cannot be done immediately be­
cause the dime and penny are on it; therefore, a second subgoal needs to be consid­
ered. A second subgoal is to end up with the penny on the quarter. This can be ac­
complished when the penny is on the second paper and the quarter is on the third
paper. This subgoal cannot yet be pursued because the dime must be moved first. In
this manner, subgoals or ends are considered along with the means to accomplish
them. A complete solution with all of the moves is shown in Fig. 9.12. If you try the
problem with four or five coins instead of three, you'll find that it gets much more
complicated, although the strategy remains the same. A quick search on the Internet
will show several sites that have computerized versions of the Tower of Hanoi prob­
lem for those of you who want to try it with many more disks than show here.

Working Backwards

Means-ends analysis is a forward-looking strategy, which means that all of the plan­
ning is done by considering operations that move you closer to subgoals and, ulti­
mately, the final goal. Sometimes it is a better strategy to plan operations by working
backwards from the goal to your present or initial state. The simplest example of this
can be found in the paper-and-pencil mazes that many children love to solve.
Some of these mazes have several possible paths leading away from the start box
and only one correct path ending in the goal box. Even young children realize that
374 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

I!!!C'TJllI

1 1"1111 IIliluM I!ITTT!l!II

!!I!!CTlJJ!I
1 111111 I ",,' ! I

I!UCIl!!III
I I '"' 11 " ""

ITTTCTl!!I IIr" , I ,, "I

mrgm

FIG. 9. 1 2. Solution to the Tower of Hanoi problem. Notice how subgoal are planned and
obtained in reaching the goal.

they can solve the maze more quickly if they work the maze backward, beginning
from the goal and drawing their path to the start box. An example of this type of
maze is shown in Fig. 9.13.
Working backward is a good strategy to use whenever there are fewer paths
leading from the goal than there are leading from the start. Of course, mazes aren't
the only situation when working backward is a good strategy. Consider the follow­
ing problem. "Water lilies on a certain lake double in area every 24 hours. From the
time the first water lily appears until the lake is completely covered takes 60 days.
On what day is it half covered?" (Fixx, 1978, p. 50).
The only way to solve this problem is to work backwards. Can you solve it with
this hint? If the lake is covered on the 60th day and the area covered by the lilies
doubles every day, how much of the lake is covered on the 59th day? The answer is
half. Thus, by working backward, the problem is easy to solve. A forward-looking
strategy with this problem will ensure insanity.
It is often a good idea to combine forward and backward strategies. If you are
faced with the task of solving proofs in geometry and trigonometry, a combination
of forward and backward strategies may often prove most useful. You can start
from the goal, transforming expressions on each line, and then alternate operations
between the start state and the goal until the solution path meets somewhere be­
tween the two.

Simplification

You turn the problem over and over in your mind; try to turn it so it appears
simpler . . . . Is the problem as simply, as clearly, as suggestively expressed as
possible?
-Polya (1981)
Problems that are difficult to solve are often complex in nature. A good way to ap­
proach such problems is to strip away as much of the complexity as possible in
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 375

FIG. 9. 1 3. Working backward is a good strategy when there are fewer paths from the goal
than from the start.

order to reduce them to a simple form. Often, the best form of representation can
perform the task of simplification because it will allow you to "see" the solution in
an efficient way.
Suppose you are faced with the classic cat-in-the-tree problem. According to com­
mon folklore, cats can climb up trees, but not down. (There is no more truth to this
than to the notion that elephants are afraid of mice.) Suppose that you are faced
with the task of retrieving a cat from the top branch of a lO-foot-tall tree. The only
ladder you have is 6 feet long. You'll need to place the base of the ladder 3 feet from
the trunk of the tree to steady it. Will you be able to reach the cat?
Like most problems, a good way to approach this problem is to diagram the
given facts. A diagram of this problem has been drawn in Fig. 9.14. Once the infor­
mation is presented in a diagram format, it is easy to perceive the problem as a sim­
ple geometry problem: What is the hypotenuse of a triangle whose two other sides
are 10 feet and 3 feet long? At this point, you'd need to rely on previously acquired
knowledge about triangles to recognize and solve this problem. When the topic is
thinking, there is no substitute for a good education to provide the foundation and
376 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

10'

- 3' -

FIG. 9. 1 4. The cat-in-the-tree problem. Once the information is drawn in a diagram form,
it is easy to see that it is a simple geometry problem.

raw materials for thought. It is thought and knowledge that are needed for good
thinking.
The formula for finding the hypotenuse of a right triangle is:

Substituting the appropriate values in the previous equation:

1 02 + 32 = c2
1 00 + 9 = c2
109 = c2
\I'iU9 = c
10.4 =c

Thus, the ladder would need to be 10.4 feet long to reach the top. But wait, could
you redraw the problem using the information given to find out if you could still
use the 6-foot ladder to reach the cat? See Fig. 9.15 for a slightly different diagram of
the problem.
The same formula can be used, but now the unknown is not the hypotenuse, but
another one of the sides of the right triangle.
Rearranging the terms will yield:

a2 + b2 = c2
a2 = c2 - b2
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 377

\ 6'

\
FIG. 9. 1 5. If the cat-in-the-tree problem is changed so that the unknown value is how high
a 6-foot ladder will reach if it is placed 3 feet from the trunk, a different answer is obtained.

a2 =
62 - 32
a2 = 36 - 9
a2 = 27
a =
yTJ
=
a 5.2

Thus, the top rung of the ladder will touch the tree 5.2 feet above the ground. Will
you be able to reach the cat? Draw yourself near the top rung of the ladder. If you
are over 5 feet tall, you should have no trouble reaching the cat if you are standing
on the top or second rung. In fact, you won't even have to reach up.
Simplification is a good strategy when the problem is abstract or complex or con­
tains information that is irrelevant to finding a solution. Often, simplification will
work hand in hand with selecting the optimal form of representation because a
good representation will often simplify a problem. But caution is needed when try­
ing to simplify. Although it worked in this example, sometimes the attempt to sim­
plify a complex problem will lead to solving a problem that is different from the one
you have.
378 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Generalization and specialization

When confronted with a problem, it is sometimes helpful to consider it as an exam­


ple of a larger class of problems (generalization) or to consider it as a special case
(specialization). The form of problem representation that is most compatible with
the generalization and specialization strategy is the tree diagram. Most goals can be
classified as both a subset of a larger category and as a heading for a smaller one.
Let's work an example to clarify what this means. As a furniture designer, you are
given the problem of designing a chair that will be especially well suited for read­
ing. How would you go about solving this problem?
As you probably realized, this is an ill-defined problem. The difficulty is largely
centered on evaluating which of several possible chairs will best satisfy the goal.
Use a tree diagram to classify chairs in general, and "chairs for reading" in par­
ticular. Although there are many possible diagrams, one example is presented in
Fig. 9.16.
I hope that you worked through this problem and drew your own tree diagram.
As you can see in Fig. 9.16, thinking about "chairs for reading" as a subset of the cat­
egory "chairs" can help you to incorporate other features of chairs in your design
while custom tailoring the chair with some of the possibilities that are unique to
"chairs for reading." Thus, the process of generalization and/or specialization can
help you to consider your problem from both broad and narrow perspectives.

Random Search and Trial-and-Error

Recall that the anatomy of a problem consists of a start or initial state, a goal, and
solution paths leading from the start state to the goal. One strategy for searching
among possible solution paths is random search. Although this probably seems like
a nonstrategy or "un-strategy," in some cases it will work quite well. When there are
very few possible solution paths, random search will lead to the goal in a short time.
A truly random search would mean that there is no systematic order in which the

TH INGS TO SI T ON

Tree Beds Benches S t ool s


Trunks

POSITION S

UprI ght

I
F U N C TIONS
I
Eating
I
Sleeping
I
Aeadtng
I
T V
I
Ta lking

ACCESSORIES

C hairs
With
L i ghts
With
BOOk
I
C'1aIrS

Holders
with
MuSIC
I
Chairs

FIG. 9. 1 6. Possible tree diagram for the problem of designing a chair for reading.
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 379

possible paths are explored and no memory for paths already tried. A systematic
trial-and-error search through the problem space (contains the paths, goal, and start
state) is preferable. Trial-and-error search is best applied to well-defined problems
with few possible solution paths. Simple, short anagrams are good candidates for
these search methods. Unscramble the following letter to form an English word:

THA

Because there are only six possible orders for these three letters (THA, TAH,
HTA, HAT, ATH, AHT), trying each one until a solution is found is fairly straight­
forward and simple strategy. If you used a truly random search, you would not
keep track of which letter orderings you used and would repeat some until the cor­
rect order was found. Systematic trial-and-error is almost always superior to ran­
dom search, although only slightly better when there are very few possibilities.
Both trial-and-error and random search are poor strategies when the number of
possible paths increases, because of the sheer number of possible combinations.
Often, in larger problems, it is helpful to eliminate some of the paths and then
search among a smaller subset with a trial-and-error strategy.

Rules

Some kinds of problems, like series problems, depend on rules. Once the underly­
ing principles are established, the problem is solved. Most problems in mathematics
and the physical sciences follow rules. A good way to discover rules is to look for pat­
terns in the givens or subgoals. Problems requiring rule discovery are often used on
tests of intelligence.
Complete the following pattern:

ABBACCCADDDDA

This is a fairly simple series problem. The next six letters are EEEEEA. Certain
patterns are common in problems of this sort. To detect them, count the number of
repeating symbols, look across the series for repetitions at long intervals, try simple
additions and subtractions, etc. This is not a trivial problem. The decoding of enemy
war messages during World War II was a major factor contributing to our victory.
The United States and British governments employed many professional decoders
whose job it was to find rules that could be used to decipher German and Japanese
military messages.
Suppose that there is intelligent life in outer space, and that they are also wonder­
ing about us. How would they let us know that they exist? Some scientists, science
fiction authors, and members of the general public believe that they would make
their presence known by sending messages. No one believes that these messages
would be in English, or Chinese, or Samoan, or any other Earth language. They
would send messages in their own native tongue or native whatever if they don't
have tongues. How would we on Earth recognize such messages? The U. S. military
has decided that if we are being sent messages from outer space the one distin­
guishing characteristic of these messages would be a rule-governed grammar" or
II
380 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

patterned repetition. As strange as this may seem, the military does monitor outer
space for anything that seems like a patterned communication. So far, they haven't
received any and we can continue to believe, for the time being at least, that we
are the most intelligent beings in space (or that the more intelligent beings do not
want us to know they are out there, or that they can't reach us, or they don't want to
reach us).

Hints

Hints are additional information that is given after an individual has begun to work
on a problem. Often the hint provides additional information that is important to
your solution. Sometimes a hint will require that you change the way you have been
approaching the problem or limit the number of possible solutions. A common
example of the use of hints is the "hot-cold" game played by children. An object is
hidden in a room. The child who is "it" wanders around the room while the other
children yell "hotter" if she is moving closer to the hidden object and "colder" if she
is moving away from the hidden object. In this problem, the child who is "it" should
take one small step at a time continuing in the same direction when the hint is "hot­
ter" and trying a slight change in direction when the hint is "colder." Research on
the way people use hints has shown that general hints like "think of new ways of
using objects" do not facilitate the problem solution (Duncan, 1961). The more spe­
cific the hint, the greater the benefit derived from it.
One of psychology's favorite problems is the two-string problem. Imagine walk­
ing into a room with two strings hanging from the ceiling. The strings are too far
apart for you to reach both at the same time, yet your task is to do exactly that. This
situation is depicted in Fig. 9.17.
The best solution to the two-string problem involves setting one string in a
swinging motion, usually by tying a heavy object to the end of one string to serve as
a weight, so that the problem solver can reach the string as it swings toward him.
When researchers provided hints for the problem solver by pretending to acciden­
tally bump against one string to get it swinging, most of the problem solvers hit
upon this solution, but few were consciously aware that they utilized this hint
(Maier, 1931).
In one experimental investigation of how people use hints, researchers had sub­
jects learn pairs of words so that if the experimenter said one word, the subject
would respond with its pair. (This is called paired-associates learning.) One of the
pairs that the subjects learned was "candle box." After learning the list of paired­
associates, subjects were given Duncker's (1945) candle problem, which involved af­
fixing a candle to a wall by using a box as the candle-holder (see Fig. 1 . 1 in Chapter
1). Did this hint help them to solve this problem? In general, their performance on
this task was improved only if they were told by the experimenter to think about the
pairs of words they had learned as a problem-solving aid (Weisberg, DiCamillo, &
Phillips, 1978). They did not spontaneously use this hint to solve the problem, most
likely because they were unaware that it was a hint. Research has confirmed these
results with other types of problems (Perfetto, Bransford, & Franks, 1983). In gen­
eral, it seems that hints are helpful only when the problem solver perceives the hint
as a possible solution aid.
Good problem solvers will seek out hints. Gathering additional information can
be thought of as hint-seeking behavior. It is almost always a good strategy to get all
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 38 1

FIG. 9. 1 7. The two-string problem. How could you reach both strings at the same time?
(After Maier, 1930)

of the information that you can about your problem. The additional givens will help
you to restructure the problem space and provide direction so that solution paths
may be found more easily.

Split-Half Method

The split-half method is an excellent search strategy when there is no a priori rea­
son for selecting among a sequentially organized set of possible solution paths. Sup­
pose, for example, that there is a stoppage in the plumbing system that prevents
water from coming out of your kitchen faucet. The stoppage is somewhere between
the place where your pipes connect with the other pipes on your street and your
kitchen faucet. How would you search for the pipe stoppage while making as few
holes as possible in the pipe?
In this example, the solution (the place where the pipe is stopped) lies somewhere
along a linear route. The best way to search in this problem is the split-half method.
Because this problem requires that you break the pipe each place you search, you
want to search as efficiently as possible. Begin halfway between the street connec­
tion and your kitchen sink. If you find that water can still run freely at this point,
you know that the stoppage is between this point and your sink. If this happens,
look again half-way between this point and your kitchen sink. If the water is still
running freely at this point, then you'll know that the stoppage is closer still to the
sink and you'll look again midway between that point and your sink.
Suppose that on your first attempt you find that the water is not running at this
point. Then the stoppage must be between the street and this midpoint. Your next
382 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

search would be midway between the current search point and the street connec­
tion. In this manner, you would continue searching until the stoppage is found. This
is a good method anytime you have a problem that is structurally similar to this one,
such as trying to locate a break in the electrical wiring in your home or auto.
You can use the split-half method to play a party game called "Guess Your Age."
(I made this game up.) Your friends can pretend to be any age. You can guess the
age of anyone between a and 1 00 with no more than seven guesses. How would you
do it? Begin with the age that is midway between a and l Oa, which, of course, is 50.
The player would have to respond by telling you if the age she is thinking of is older
or younger than 50. Thus, she would respond with "younger" or "older." Suppose
that she responds, "younger." What age should you guess next? You'd pick the age
midway between a and 50, which is 25. Suppose she now responds, "older." Your
third guess should be halfway between 25 and 50. Because we're only concerned
with whole numbers, your next guess would be 38. If she now responds younger,
you'd guess 32, as this number is midway between 25 and 38. If the next response is
older, you'd guess 35 (midway between 32 and 38). If the response is younger,
you'd guess 33. At this point you know that she is pretending to be either 33 or 34.
Thus, any age can be guessed with at most seven guesses. Try this method out with
some friends. It will be good practice in using the split-half strategy. Consider this
strategy whenever there are several possible equally likely solutions aligned along a
single dimension.

Brainstorming

"The best way to have good ideas is to have lots of ideas."


-Linus Pauling (cited in Goertzel & Goertzel, 1995, p. 274)
Brainstorming is fun. It was originally proposed by Osborn (1963) as a method for
group problem solving, but it's also useful for individuals working alone. Brain­
storming is useful in generating additional solution paths and thus should be
considered whenever the difficulty involves finding solution paths. The goal of
brainstorming is to produce a large number of possible solutions. Problem solvers
are encouraged to think up wild, unusual, imaginative ideas and to write them all
down, no matter how silly they seem. The underlying principle is that the greater
the quantity of ideas, the greater the likelihood that at least one of them will be
good. To foster creative use of imagination, rules include no criticism or ridicule,
even when the ideas may appear ridiculous. Judgments about the worth of the ideas
are deferred until a later evaluation phase. Sometimes parts of the various ideas are
combined or refined to improve upon them.
Brainstorming can be done in large or small groups or alone. After the brain­
storming session, the list of possible solutions can be perused to find ones that will
solve the problem in light of the problem constraints, which often include financial
and time limitations and/or ethical considerations. Brainstorming was used effec­
tively by a food manufacturer faced with the problem of finding a better way to bag
potato chips. The problem solvers (corporate executives) were asked to think up the
best packaging solution they had ever seen. Someone said that bagging wet leaves
was the best packaging solution he had ever seen. If you attempt to bag dry leaves
they crumble and don't fit into trash bags well, but if you hose them down before
bagging them you can use fewer bags and fill them more easily with less empty
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 383

space in each bag. Following this lead, they tried wetting potato chips and
then putting them into bags. The result was disastrous-the potato chips dried into
tasteless crumbs. But this idea ultimately led to the popular potato chip that comes
stacked in a can. The identical chips are formed from a liquid potato mixture that is
cooked into chip-shaped molds. In this manner, a wild and not-too-good solution
(wetting potato chips) was parlayed into a highly successful product. It's true-the
original potato chip problem remains to be solved, but the executives were quite
happy with the new potato chip product.

Contradiction

The best solution to many problems often involves contradictory properties. For ex­
ample, consider the problem of the perfect pizza box-one that keeps the pizza hot,
but doesn't allow steam to collect inside the box so that the crust doesn't get wet and
soggy. These are contradictory properties-keep the pizza covered so it stays hot
and don't let the steam condense and turn the crust soggy. The next time you send
out for a pizza, examine the box. Most pizza boxes represent a compromise between
these two properties-the lid is closed to keep it hot, but it also has small vents to
allow some of the steam to escape. The result is a compromise solution. The pizza
gets cold sooner because the vents let cold air in, and the pizza gets only a little
soggy because the amount of condensed moisture is limited.
One suggestion for solving any problem that involves contradictions is to never
compromise; instead, devise a solution that satisfies all of the desirable properties of
a good solution. Sure, but how? In the pizza box problem, Valdman and Tsourikov
(cited in Raia, 1994) designed a box with "dimples" (raised dots) on the bottom so
that the moisture would condense below the crust and not on it, while trapping hot
air below the pizza to serve as additional insulation. Valdman and Tsourikov have
designed a computer-assisted program that suggests ways to satisfy contradictions
in any problem without compromising. They culled the files of the U.S. Patent Of­
fice and discovered over 200 general principles that can be used alone or in combi­
nation to solve a wide range of problems. The program begins by asking for a clear
definition of the type of problem that is being solved. It is looking for general princi­
ples (e.g., the need for insulation and eliminating condensation, without regard to
pizza). Solutions are suggested from its computerized bank of solutions based on
other problems that involve similar sorts of contradictions. They call their algorithm
(steps used to solve a problem) the theory of inventive problem solving. Although
their advertisements for this commercially available software program make fantas­
tic claims of success, additional studies by unbiased researchers are needed before
we can evaluate its efficacy. Using their basic ideas, we can all imagine an optimal
solution to any problem and then find ways to satisfy seemingly contradictory prop­
erties of the optimal solution.
Here is another example of a problem involving contradictions. Consider the
problem of picking tomatoes. Mechanical tomato pickers are cheap and fast, but
they bruise the tomato. A compromise would be to pad the arms of the mechanical
picker or slow down the process so that fewer tomatoes are bruised. But, the cardi­
nal rule of the theory of inventive problem solving is to never compromise. An even
better idea, one that won't require the picker to slow down or bruise the tomatoes,
is to develop a tomato with a thicker skin so that it won't bruise when it is picked
by the clumsy and fast-moving machine (The Cognition and Technology Group at
384 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Vanderbilt, 1993). Thus, the apparent contradiction (pick tomatoes fast with a ma­
chine and do not allow bruising) was resolved without compromise.

Analogies and Metaphors

We can scarcely imagine a problem absolutely new, unlike and unrelated to any
formerly solved problem; but if such a problem could exist, it would be insoluble.
In fact, when solving a problem, we should always profit from previously solved
problems, using their result or their method, or the experience acquired in
solving them.
-Polya (1945, p. 92)
Gick and Holyoak (1980, p. 306) ask, "Where do new ideas come from?" Many sci­
entists and mathematicians respond that their ideas or solutions to problems come
from recognizing analogies and metaphors drawn from different academic disci­
plines (Hadamard, 1954). In fact, it seems that the most common form of inference is
made by noting similarities (analogies and metaphors) between two or more situa­
tions. Like hints, the analogy must be recognized as relevant in the problem being
considered and then modified for the particular situation.
Consider the following problem:

A small country fell under the iron rule of a dictator. The dictator ruled the country from a
strong fortress. The fortress was situated in the middle of the country, surrounded by
farms and villages. Many roads radiated outward from the fortress like spokes on a wheel.
A great general arose who raised a large army at the border and vowed to capture the
fortress and free the country of the dictator. The general knew that if his entire army could
attack the fortress at once it could be captured. His troops were poised at the head of one
of the roads leading to the fortress, ready to attack. However, a spy brought the general a
disturbing report. The ruthless dictator had planted mines on each of the roads. The mines
were set so that small bodies of men could pass over them safely, since the dictator needed
to be able to move troops and workers to and from the fortress. However, any large force
would detonate the mines. Not only would this blow up the road and render it impass­
able, but the dictator would then destroy many villages in retaliation. A full-scale direct at­
tack on the fortress therefore appeared impossible. (Gick & Holyoak, 1980, p. 351 )

To help you solve this problem, I'll also give you a hint. The solution is analogous
to one discussed earlier in this chapter, although the context is entirely different.
Stop for a few minutes and attempt to work on this problem. Think about the prob­
lems presented earlier. It should help if you draw a diagram.
The solution to this problem is analogous to the one used in the inoperable stom­
ach tumor problem. In that problem (Duncker, 1945), the best solution involved
sending weak rays through the body simultaneously from several different points
so that they would converge on the tumor as depicted here.
PROBLEM-SOLVING STRATEGIES 385

Similarly, the army could be divided into small groups that would attack the
fortress from all sides. Did you recognize that these problems were essentially simi­
lar in form and could be solved with the same solution? In a study of the use of dia­
grams as an aid in analogical problem solving, Pedone, Hummel, and Holyoak
(2001) found that by animating the diagram so that the arrows moved in to a central
point, college students were more likely to use the display as a retrieval cue that
helped in solving the X-ray and fortess problems. It seems that these diagrams work
best when problem solvers have their attention drawn to the structure of the prob­
lem so that they can recognize that these two types of problems have similar struc­
tures, even though they have very different surface characteristics (content).
Gordon (1961), originator of a group called "Synectics," presented guidelines for
the use of analogies in solving problems. The term "Synectics" was taken from a Greek
term that means joining together different and apparently unrelated elements. Gordon
suggests that we consider four different types of analogies when faced with a problem:

1 . Personal Analogy

If you want to understand a complex phenomenon, think of yourself as a partici­


pant in the phenomenon. For example, if you want to understand the molecular
structure of a compound, think of yourself as a molecule. How would you behave?
What other molecules would you want to attach yourself to? Get away from reliance
on scientific notations and actually pretend to be a molecule bouncing in a com­
pound. You may see relationships from this perspective that you were blind to
when acting as a scientist.
The use of personal analogies is especially well suited for solving a wide range of
conflict problems. If each side of a conflict can imagine how the problem appears to
the other side, including acceptable goals, new solutions can become apparent. Both
sides can identify common interests and use them to invent options that they both
find acceptable (Bernstein, 1995; Fisher & Ury, 1991).

2. Direct Analogy

Compare the problems you're working on with several problems in other do­
mains. According to Gordon, this method was used by Alexander Graham Bell: "It
struck me that the bones of the human ear were very massive indeed, as compared
with the delicate thin membrane that operated them, and the thought occurred that
if a membrane so delicate could move bones relatively so massive, why should not a
thicker and stouter piece of membrane move my piece of steel. And the telephone
was conceived" (Gordon, 1961, p. 41).
A particularly fertile area for analogies is biology, where many solutions to bio­
logical problems have been evolving since the first life form appeared on Earth.
When a Synectics group was faced with the problem of devising a bottle closure that
could be used with glue or nail polish, the analogy they used was the biological clo­
sure of the anus (rectum). Apparently, this solution worked quite well. (You can
think about this the next time you use a bottle of LePage's mucilage.)

3. Symbolic Activity

This solution strategy utilizes visual imagery. Its goal is to get away from the
constraints of words or mathematical symbols. Students who utilized imagery to
386 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

CROCK

i:�
1/. /'2- .--- - If
Reprinted with special permission of King Features Syndicate.

visualize the tumor problem and the fortress problem were most likely to notice
spontaneously that the two problems were analogous. If you work on generating a
clear image of a problem, you may "see" a solution that had been overlooked.

4. Fantasy Analogy

In your wildest dreams, what would you want of a solution? An example of this
is to imagine two small insects that would automatically zip your jacket or a silk
worm that would spin silk rapidly to keep you warm when the temperature drops.
These are fantasy analogies. Like brainstorming, a fantasy analogy can result in
wild, impractical solutions that can later be modified to practical, workable ones.
Although it is clear that analogies are important aids in problem solving, it is rare
for most people to notice a potential analogy spontaneously (VanLehn, 1989). If you
are able to diagram the underlying relationships, as in the preceding problem, or to
state the general rules, as in the contradictions problem, you are more likely to no­
tice structural relationships and find useful analogies. Novice problem solvers are
less likely to perceive structural similarities between problems that have different
contents than more experienced problem solvers (Davidson & Sternberg, 1998).

Consult an Expert

"If at first you don't succeed, try, try, again. Then quit. No use being
a damned fool about it. "
-W.e. Fields <quoted in Teger, 1979, p. XIV)
Often in life, we don't have to solve problems alone. Sometimes the best way to solve
a problem is to let experts do it for us, or at least help us with solving the problem.
People seek accountants for help with their tax problems, attorneys for their legal
problems, and physicians for their health problems. We elect officials to handle the
problems of running our country and rely on military experts to wage wars. These
people became experts in their field by obtaining the appropriate knowledge in their
subject area and through repeated applications of this knowledge to real-world
problems. Consulting an expert is often an excellent solution strategy. Their greater
experience and knowledge will allow them to solve many problems in their area of
expertise much more efficiently than a novice. If you decide to consult an expert, the
PROBLEM-SOLVING PROBLEMS 387

problem becomes: (a) how to know somebody who is an expert; and (b) how to se­
lect which "expert" to use. Once you've passed these hurdles, your problems still
aren't over. You need to be sure that the expert has all of the facts and has considered
all of the relevant alternatives. Listen carefully to the expert's analysis of the risks
and alternatives, but make the decision yourself. An expert is a problem-solving aid,
not the solution. For some guidelines in recognizing an appropriate expert, consult
Carlson (1995) and review the section on authorities in Chapter 4 on reasoning.

Select the Best Strategy

Twelve different strategies have been presented as aids in problem solving. When
confronted with a problem, how do you know which to use? It is important to keep
in mind that these strategies are not mutually exclusive. It will often be best to use
them in combinations. The best strategy, or strategies, depends on the nature of the
problem. After all, if you are taking an exam, you could be expelled if you consult
the paper of an "expert" student sitting next to you.
Along with each strategy, I presented some guidelines for its appropriate use. In
general, a few higher level "strategies for selecting strategies" include:

1 . If the problem is ill defined, restate the goal or the problem in several differ­
ent ways.
2. When there are very few possible solutions, a trial-and-error approach will
work well.
3. If a problem is complex, try simplification, means-ends analysis, and general­
ization and specialization.
4. When there are fewer paths leading away from the goal than there are from
the start state, work backwards.
5. If you can gather additional information, do it. Look for and utilize hints, and
consult experts with specialized knowledge.
6. If there is an ordered array of equally likely alternatives, try the split-half
method and seek rules.
7. If the problem is a lack of possible solution paths, brainstorm to generate al­
ternative solution paths.
8. Problems in design and engineering are good candidates for devising solu­
tions that seem, at first, to require contradictions in their solution.
9. Using analogies and metaphors and consulting an expert are widely applica­
ble to all sorts of problems, but be prepared to use visualization and to delib­
erately seek analogies in order to recall an analogous solution.
10. Remember that these are only guidelines to solving problems. The best way
to be an expert problem solver is to practice solving lots of problems.

PROBLEM-SOLVING PROBLEMS

Clinging to the past is the problem. Enhancing change is the answer.


-Gloria Steinem (1994)
There are many possible reasons why people find some problems difficult, perhaps
even impossible to solve. Sometimes we're stuck in "thinking ruts" and cannot seem
388 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

to think our way out of them. Two of these "ruts" are functional fixedness and
mental set.

Functional Fixedness and Mental Set

Recall the two-string problem presented earlier in this chapter. The task was to
grasp simultaneously two strings that hung from the ceiling. The correct solution in­
volved setting one string into motion, perhaps by tying a heavy object like a pair of
pliers to its end to serve as a weight. One reason why this was such a difficult prob­
lem is functional fixedness. Subjects were fixated or "stuck" on the usual function of
a pair of pliers and have difficulty thinking of them as having a different function.
Another example of functional fixedness was presented in Chapter 1, the intro­
duction. In a classic problem, subjects were asked to attach a candle to the wall so
that it could be burned, using only a box of thumbtacks and some matches. Subjects
had difficulty thinking of the box as a candle holder because they saw it in terms of
its usual function-a container for thumbtacks.
Mental set refers to the problem solver's state of mind. It is a general term for the
inability to think of a new solution or new type of solution for familiar problems. I
think of functional fixedness and mental state as "ruts in one's thinking." They are
predispositions to think and respond in certain ways. To demonstrate how powerful
some sets can be, work on the nine-dot problem in Fig. 9.18. Stop now and work on
this problem.
The difficulty posed by the nine-dot problem comes from a perceptual set im­
posed by the square arrangement. Most people attempt to solve the problem by
staying within the imaginary boundary formed by the outer dots. If you extend
your lines beyond this imaginary boundary, you'll find that the problem is easy to
solve. In addition, most people attempt solutions in which the line goes through the
center of each dot. One solution to the nine-dot problem is shown in Fig. 9.19.
There are several other solutions to the nine-dot problem. Each of them involves
breaking set in some way. Two solutions (Adams, 1979, pp. 25-26) are presented in
Fig. 9.20. A few other more exotic solutions, including one submitted by a lO-year­
old girl, which consists of one very fat line drawn through all nine dots can be found
in Adams' (1979) gem of a book, Conceptual Blockbusting. The set of staying within
the rectangular area is pervasive and difficult to break. Strategies that get you to
view problems in novel ways, like the personal analogy strategy, are good ways to
work on set-breaking solutions.

• • •

• • •

• • •
FIG. 9. 1 8. The nine-dot problem. Using no more than four straight lines and without
lifting your pencil from the paper, draw a line through all nine dots.
PROBLEM-SOLVING PROBLEMS 389

FIG. 9. 1 9. One possible solution to the nine-dot problem. Note that the solution involves
breaking "set." Most people assume that the lines must form a square and that each line must
pass through the center of each dot.

Misleading and Irrelevant Information

My father used to love this riddle:

Suppose you are a bus driver. On the first stop you pick up 6 men and 2 women. At the second
stop 2 men leave and 1 woman boards the bus. At the third stop 1 man leaves and 2 women
enter the bus. At the fourth stop 3 men get on and 3 women get off. At the fifth stop 2 men get
off, 3 men get on, 1 woman gets off, and 2 women get on. What is the bus driver's name?

Could you answer this question without rereading the problem? The bus driver's
name is, of course, your name because the riddle began, "Suppose you are a bus dri­
ver." All of the information about the rest of the passengers was irrelevant. Often in­
formation that is irrelevant to the problem serves to mislead problem solvers down
dead-end paths. Real-life problems often involve deciding what information is rele­
vant. To avoid being misled by information, be clear about the goal state. Simplifica­
tion will sometimes help in separating the relevant from the irrelevant givens.
Let's try another example:

If you have black socks and brown socks in your drawer mixed in the ratio of 4 to 5, how many
socks will you have to take out to make sure of having a pair of the same color?" (Fixx, 1978).

Think about this problem. What is relevant? What is irrelevant? The answer is
three socks because any two must match if there are only brown and black socks.
The information about the ratio of socks is irrelevant and misleading. Imagine your­
self actually picking socks from a drawer and this problem will be easier to solve.
A common attribute of ill-defined problems is that they potentially involve a
huge amount of information. Consider the very real-world problems in interna­
tional relations such as, "How can we influence Russia so that it cleans up its environ­
mental hazards?" or "How can we provide food for the countless numbers of people
who go hungry in the United States and the rest of the world?" The "problem," with
broad problems such as these, requires the selection of information that could lead
to the desired goal. Unlike the motorist problem that I presented at the opening of
390 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

'w
·'"77"1 {jw
'; -
• I

• /0
: .
-/ '
� / ," .' . .
i • , - ,
.. • :, 0
'-. -..... 1 _

-.. .
;. �
.
�.
'-- � -j -
" . ,, � \) J
r;/:7- t •
: /1_

il1J
1 /
/t '
.
_ / . . 1 /. •

I� • I. ' / . / " • •

I �'
.
I I
,-- ->- ' ��
<=

. -;- . l
.../
... '

({ ,�.(
I.

FIG. 9.20. Other possible solutions to the nine-dot problem, (From Adams, 1979;
Reprinted by permission from W, W, Norton.)

this chapter, the difficulty is not in the absence of paths to the goal, but in too many
possible paths. Which path is most likely to be the best? How can we choose among
the better options? There are no simple answers for these questions, which is why
we continue to have environmental threats and hunger.

Worldview Constraints

Often we fail to solve problems because of the worldview constraints placed on us


by our social class, nationality, or political views. Consider the following problem:
A ping pong ball 1" in diameter falls into a 3" length of pipe that is 1 1 /S" in diameter. The
pipe is firmly affixed to the concrete pavement. It is extremely important to remove the
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 39 1

ball. You and some friends are faced with this task. All you have is some fine wire and
your collective abilities to solve this problem. What do you do?

Most people approach this task by attempting to bend fine wire into tweezers to
pluck it up. A better solution is to urinate into the pipe so that the ball will float to
the top. This probably never occurred to you because it is not an acceptable thought
for most people in our society. Although this has never been verified, it would prob­
ably be an easier task for people in other societies where urination is not considered
as private an act as it is in our society.
I received a first-hand lesson in the ways in which worldviews influence problem
solving during the semester that I spent at Moscow State University in Russia. Rus­
sia is a country emerging from communism, and a communist solution to a problem
is very different from a capitalist solution. Under communism, the state is expected
to solve problems like inflation, unemployment, and the supply of consumer goods;
whereas, under capitalism these sorts of problems are handled largely by the pri­
vate sector. It is difficult to imagine the tremendous effect that culture has on the
way we think without an extended experience in a culture other than the one you
know best. It is for this reason that I tout the educational benefits of extended for­
eign travel. It can change your own worldview and help you to appreciate the ex­
tent to which the problems we identify and the solutions we generate are influenced
by cultural factors.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

The general thinking skills framework that we've been using throughout the book is
particularly applicable to problem solving.

1 . What Is the Goal?

One of the first steps in solving a problem is to be explicit about the goal. This is
relatively easy for well-defined problems (e.g., How many ounces are in a pound?).
Most problems, however, are ill defined and can have multiple goals. Being explicit
about the goal and considering alternative goals will force you to cast the problem
in the thinking skills framework and to begin goal-directed thinking.

2 . What Is Known'?

This is part of the preparation or familiarization process. The knowns or "givens"


determine the nature of the problem. It is often possible to improve on what is
known by gathering additional information. Once you have a clear determination of
the knowns, you can use that information as a guide to selecting the best representa­
tion and best problem-solving strategy.

3. Which Thinking Skill or Skills


Will Get You to Your Goal'?
Twelve different kinds of strategies or skills were presented in this chapter along
with general guidelines such as restating the goal and selecting a representation.
392 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

You need to select strategies that are most likely to solve the problem. A trial-and­
error approach to selecting a strategy is, itself, a poor strategy. Guidelines were pre­
sented for evaluating strategies depending on the nature of the problem.
The skills for planning and solving problems that were presented in this chapter are
applicable to almost any problem. After reading this chapter you should be able to:

• Plan and monitor a strategy for finding a solution.


• Identify any problem as either well defined or ill defined and adjust your solu-
tion plan according to the type of problem.
• Use graphs, diagrams, hierarchical trees, matrices, and models as solution aids.
• Devise a quality representation of a problem.
• Select the problem-solving strategies that are appropriate for the problem.
• Use all of the following strategies: mean-ends analysis, working backwards,
simplification, generalization and specialization, random search and trial-and­
error, rules, hints, split-half method, brainstorming, contradiction, analogies
and metaphors, and consulting an expert.
• Demonstrate an awareness of functional fixedness so as to avoid it.
• Distinguish between relevant and irrelevant information.
• Understand how worldviews can constrain the problem-solving process.

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?

The final step in problem solving is an assessment of the quality of the solution.
In well-defined problems, this question becomes: Is your solution the correct one? In
ill-defined problems, the solution has to evaluated qualitatively both in an absolute
sense (Does it alleviate or reduce the problem?) and in a relative sense (Is it the best
alternative?).

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . All problems can be conceptualized as being composed of "anatomical" parts


that include a start state, a goal state, and paths leading from the start to the goal.
This entire structure is called the problem space. You have a problem when there is
a gap or barrier between where you are (start state) and where you want to be (goal
state).
2. It is common to divide the problem-solving process into four stages: prepara­
tion or familiarization; production; judgment or evaluation; and incubation. Incuba­
tion is an optional stage that does not always occur. Persistence is a critical trait of
good problem solvers.
3. Problems can be classified along a continuum ranging from well defined to ill
defined. Well-defined problems have explicit paths and goals. Ill-defined problems
are subject to multiple interpretations and judgments about the goal state. Most of
the problems encountered in life are ill defined.
4. Solution strategies need to be planned. A plan for solving a problem will in­
clude the construction of a representation and the generation and evaluation of pos­
sible solutions.
5. An invaluable aid in solving problems is to devise an external form of repre­
sentation. The best representation to choose will depend on the type of problem.
TERMS TO KNOW 393

6. Twelve different strategies for generating and evaluating solutions were pre­
sented. Often several will be used together in solving a problem. General guidelines
were offered for the appropriate use of each.
7. There are four common sources of difficulty that problem solvers encounter.
Functional fixedness refers to the failure to utilize items in unusual ways. Mental set,
which is closely related to functional fixedness, refers to the predisposition to respond
to any situation in a fixed way. Misleading and irrelevant information can "derail one's
trail of thought" and can lead you down blind paths. The constraints imposed upon us
by our society cause us to view problems from our own narrow frames of reference.

TERMS TO KNOW

You should be able to define or describe the following terms or concepts. If you find
that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to reread the section in which it
is discussed.

A Problem. A problem is defined as a state where there is a gap or barrier between


where the problem solver is and where she or he wants to be.
Anatomy of a Problem. Newell and Simon (1972) have conceptualized all problems
as consisting of parts or components-an initial state, a goal state, and solution
paths that link the initial state to the goal state.
Solution Paths. Methods or means for solving problems. Routes that lead from the
initial state to the goal state in a problem.
Initial State. The starting or beginning place in a problem. A problem is solved
when the problem solver can find "paths" from the initial state to the goal.
Goal State. The desired end state in a problem. When a problem solver finds
"paths" to the goal, the problem is solved.
Problem Space. All possible paths from the initial state to the goal state in a problem.
Givens. Information or rules that place constraints on the problem.
Preparation of Familiarization Stage. The first stage in problem solving, which in­
cludes the time spent in understanding the nature of the problem, the desired goal,
and the givens.
Production Stage. The second stage in problem solVing. During this state, the prob­
lem solver produces the solution paths that define the problem space.
Judgment or Evaluation Stage. The third stage in problem solving during which
time the problem solver evaluates the solution paths in order to select the best one.
Incubation. A period in problem solving when the problem solver is not actively
working on the problem. Sometimes people report that a solution comes to them
during this "time-out" period.
Insight. Sudden knowledge of a solution to a problem. Also known as the "Aha!"
experience.
Well-Defined Problems. Problems with a single correct answer.
Ill-Defined Problems. Problems with many possible correct answers. The difficulty
with these problems lies in evaluating possible solutions to decide which one is best.
Often the goal in these problems is vague or incomplete.
Transcontextual. A problem-solving strategy that is useful in any context with any
sort of problem. An example of a transcontextual strategy is to state the goal four
different ways whenever a problem is encountered.
394 9. DEVELOPMENT OF PROBLEM-SOLVING SKILLS

Hierarchical Trees. Branching diagrams that serve as a representational aid in solv­


ing problems. Instances of categories provide the "nodes" of the trees.
Matrix. A rectangular array of numbers that is used as a means of representing
problems that contain categories of information.
Detour Problems. Problems in which the path to the goal is not a direct linear one.
Intermediate steps are required that seem directly opposite the goal.
Subproblems. When difficulty is encountered in solving a problem, it can be bro­
ken down into several smaller problems or "subproblems."
Subgoal. When difficulty is encountered in solving a problem, it can be broken
down into several smaller problems called "subproblems." Each subproblem has its
own goal, called a "subgoal."
Means-End Analysis. A general problem-solving strategy in which operations are
used to reduce the distance between the problem solver's current state and the near­
est possible subgoal or goal.
Working Backwards. A problem-solving strategy in which operations are planned
that move from the goal to the present or initial state. This method is usually con­
trasted with the forward-looking strategy.
Forward-Looking Strategy. A problem-solving strategy in which all of the plan­
ning is done by considering operations that move the problem solver closer to sub­
goals and the goal. This method is usually contrasted with working backwards from
the goal.
Simplification. A problem-solving strategy in which as much of the complexity as
possible is removed from the problem in order to facilitate a solution.
Generalization. A problem-solving strategy in which the problem is considered as
an example of a larger class of problems.
Specialization. A problem-solving strategy in which the problem is considered as a
special case drawn from a larger set of problems.
Random Search. A problem-solving strategy in which all possible solution paths
from the initial state to the goal are considered in an unsystematic (random) man­
ner. This method is usually contrasted with trial-and-error search.
Trial-and-Error. A problem-solving strategy in which all solution paths from the
initial state to the goal are searched systematically. This method is usually con­
trasted with random search.
Rules. The principles that underlie some problems. For example, solutions to prob­
lems that require a prediction of the next element in a series depend on the discov­
ery of their rules.
Hints. Additional information that is given after an individual has begun to work
on a problem.
Split-Half Method. A problem-solving strategy that is useful when there is no a
priori reason for selecting among a sequentially organized set of possible solution
paths. The method consists of continually selecting a point that is halfway between
the present state and the goal as a systematic means for "guessing" at the solution.
Brainstorming. A group or individual method for generating solution paths for
problems. Problem solvers are encouraged to think up wild, imaginative solutions
and to defer judgment on these solutions until a later time when they may be modi­
fied or combined. The goal is to produce a large number of possible solutions.
Analogies. A problem-solving strategy in which similarities are noted between two
or more situations, while simultaneously discerning that there are also differences;
for example, by noting similarities between two different problems, the problem
solver may discover that similar solutions are applicable.
TERMS TO KNOW 395

Personal Analogy. A problem-solving strategy suggested by Gordon (1961) in


which you think of yourself as a participant in the phenomenon that you want to
understand.
Direct Analogy. A problem-solving strategy suggested by Gordon (1961) in which
you note similarities between your problem and related problems in other domains.
Symbolic Activity. The deliberate use of visual imagery or other symbolic repre­
sentation as a problem-solving aid.
Fantasy Analogy. A problem-solving strategy suggested by Gordon (1961) in
which problem solvers utilize their imagination to conceptualize ideal solutions.
Functional Fixedness. A type of mental set in which individuals only consider the
usual use (function) of objects.
Mental Set. Predispositions to think and respond in a certain way.
Worldview Constraints. Limitations on the way we approach problems placed on
us by our social class, nationality, or political views.
10

Creative Thinking

Contents
Defining Creativity Encouraging Creativity
Lateral and Vertical Thinking The Person, the Problem, the Process
Creative Genius or Pedestrian Creativity as a Goal
Process? Environmental Factors
Sensitivity, Synergy, and Serendipity Personality Factors
Creativity as Investment Theory: Buy Strategies for Creative Thinking
Low; Sell High Basic Principles
Creativity as a System Productive Thinking Program
Creativity as a Cognitive Process Quantity Breeds Quality
Stretching and Rejecting Paradigms Creative Ideas Checklist
The Problem of Problem Definition Attribute Listing
Selecting Relevant Information Crovitz's Relational Algorithm
Generation, Exploration, and Plus, Minus, Interesting
Evaluation Activating Inert Knowledge
Insight and Incubation Browsing
Analogical Thinking Visual Thinking
Making the Familiar Strange Putting It All Together
Remote Associations Test Applying the Framework
Chapter Summary
Terms to Know

396
DEFINING CREATlVITY 397

The history of civilization is essentially the record of man's [and woman's1


creative ability.
-Osborn (1963, p. ix)
I spent a morning at a special summer program for "mentally gifted kids," the ones
who score within the top one or two percent of all children in their age group on intelli­
gence tests. Every morning, the second to tenth graders gather in a small auditorium to
contemplate a "thought for the day," work on a puzzle, plan activities, and gripe about
the usual things all kids gripe about. The puzzle for the day was "How can you take
one away from 9 and get 1 0?" The kid sitting next to me whispered, "Do you know the
answer?" After a few seconds thought, I gloated with a "Yes" response, pleased as
punch that I could keep up with this elite group of short people.

Many hands shot up in response to the puzzle. The first child to answer was a tiny, red­
headed girl, reminiscent of Charlie Brown's heartthrob. "It's easy," she said as she
walked confidently to the chalkboard. "If you take away a negative one, the effect will
be the same as addition." As she spoke, she wrote the following on the board:

9 - (- 1) = 9 + 1 = 10

I was amazed. Why hadn't I thought of that? A second hand went up and a young boy on
the verge of adolescence explained another answer: "In Roman numerals, nine is written
'IX,' so if you take T (one) away, you'll end up with 'X,' the Roman numeral for 10."

Another child responded with a sheepish grin, saying that, "This is a little silly, but, if
you write 'q' and take the one, or vertical line, away and place it in front of the changed
number, you'll have '10.'" I don't know why this was a silly answer-it was the one I
had been thinking of.

Still more hands were up, anxious to demonstrate more ways to answer the puzzle.
One child wrote out the word "NINE," then erased the second letter (the i that looked
like a one), which left her with a "N NE." If you count the number of straight lines left
in these letters, there are 10 (three in each "N" and four in the "E").

Actually there were even more answers, but I lost track as I sat with my mouth gaping
open, trying to follow each explanation. How did the children corne up with so many
creative answers?

DEFINING CREATIVITY

A psychology of man is impossible without understanding man's ability to


create.
-Arasteh and Arasteh (1976, p. 3)
Creativity is a difficult word to define. We say that someone "is creative" when she
has produced an outcome or a product that is both unusual and appropriate (or
meaningful or useful or particularly good). Thus, creativity is defined by two as­
pects of its consequence (novelty and quality) and not the process that led to the
consequence.
398 I o. CREATIVE THINKING

Both the unusualness and appropriateness criteria require judgments: How un­
usual is the idea and how well does it meet some objective? Because both of these
criteria vary along quantitative dimensions, creativity exists in degrees. This means
that any action or thought can be more or less creative. Creativity is not a single
trait that people either have or don't have. Creative thinking involves cognitive
processes that occur in a context. These processes involve novelty in one or more of
the processes that lead to creative outcomes-ways of identifying that a problem ex­
ists, defining a problem, generating and evaluating possible solutions, and judging
how uniquely and how well the problem is solved.
Suppose that you are invited to supper at your friend Hazel's house. You know
that she is an adventuresome cook and therefore you look forward to the meal with
relish. The main dish is an original concoction of hot dogs and fruit salad in a cold
mustard sauce. (This part is a true story. I was once served this at a friend's house.)
The coup de grace is a dessert that she made in her new ice cream maker-liver- and
brussel sprout-flavored ice cream. Although these are unusual dishes, few people
would willingly eat them. Most of us would not judge these culinary delights as cre­
ative because they do not satisfy the criterion that the idea or product be good or
useful.
One problem with our working definition of creativity concerns the terms "un­
usual" and "good" or "useful" because satisfaction of these criteria is a matter of
judgment, and people will often disagree. This means that creativity exists in the
eyes of the observer, although there are also good data showing that experts in a
field (e.g., visual arts, music, science) generally show good agreement in the creativ­
ity ratings they assign to creations in their field (e.g., paintings, musical scores, re­
search findings; Sternberg & Lubart, 1996). It's easy to see why creativity has been
an elusive topic. Someone or some group must judge an act or idea as unusual and
good or useful before it can be labeled creative, and there will often be disagreement
on the way these attributes are judged. Judgments of creativity also change over
time so that a "zany" idea at one time in history (e.g., the earth revolves around the
sun and not the reverse) may come to be viewed as "monumental" at some time
later.
Prince (1970, p. i) offered a somewhat poetic definition of creativity, which, I be­
lieve, is itself creative. Consider his definition:

CREATIVITY: an arbitrary harmony, an expected astonishment, a habitual revelation, a


familiar surprise, a generous selfishness, an unexpected certainty, a formidable stub­
bornness, a vital triviality, a disciplined freedom, an intoxicating steadiness, a repeated
initiation, a difficult delight, a predictable gamble, an ephemeral solidity, a unifying
difference, a demanding satisfier, a miraculous expectation, an accustomed amazement.

Gardner (1989) has added an additional requirement to his definition of creativ­


ity. Gardner wants creativity to include the idea that the creative individual
regularly solves problems or fashions products that are creative. This additional re­
quirement would remove "luck" from the creative process because luck or random
actions cannot explain regular results. However we choose to define creativity, we
need it, and we all possess it to some extent. Our everyday lives are more pleasur­
able because of our creative actions; the arts depend on it for their existence; science
and mathematics could not progress without it. Every time we express a complex
thought or fill a blank piece of paper with our words, we are creating; when we do it
particularly well in an unusual way, then we are creative.
DEFINING CREATIVITY 399

Lateral and Vertical Thinking

Vertical thinking is concerned with digging the same hole deeper. Lateral
thinking is concerned with digging the hole somewhere else.
-DeBono (1977, p. 195)

The distinction between lateral and vertical thinking was first made by DeBono
(1968, p. 11). It is best illustrated with a short story that is probably an old fable that
has been told for many generations:

Many years ago when a person who owed money could be thrown into jail, a merchant in
London had the misfortune to owe a huge sum to a money-lender. The money-lender,
who was old and ugly, fancied the merchant's beautiful teenage daughter. He proposed a
bargain. He said he would cancel the merchant's debt if he could have the girl instead.
Both the merchant and his daughter were horrified at the proposal. So the cunning
money-lender proposed that they let Providence decide the matter. He told them that he
would put a black pebble and a white pebble into an empty money-bag and then the girl
would have to pick out one of the pebbles. If she chose the black pebble, she would be­
come his wife and her father's debt would be cancelled. If she chose the white pebble, she
would stay with her father and the debt would still be cancelled. But if she refused to pick
out a pebble, her father would be thrown into jail and she would starve.
Reluctantly the merchant agreed. They were standing on a pebble-strewn path in the
merchant's garden as they talked and the money-lender stooped down to pick up the two
pebbles. As he picked up the pebbles, the girl, sharp-eyed with fright, noticed that he
picked up two black pebbles and put them into the money-bag. He then asked the girl to
pick out the pebble that was to decide her fate and that of her father.

What would you do if you had been the girl? If you think about this problem in a
careful, logical, straightforward way, you're using vertical thinking, a type of think­
ing that will not be much help in this situation. Typical "vertical thinking" answers
are: let the girl sacrifice herself or expose him for the crook he is. Consider DeBono's
suggested solution: The girl should fumble when she draws the pebble from the
bag, dropping it onto the pebble-strewn path. She should then tell the villain that
they can determine the color of the pebble she took by seeing the color of the one left
in the bag. Because the remaining pebble must be black, the money-lender will be
forced to admit that she had chosen the white pebble or expose himself as a crook.
Virtually everyone agrees that this is both a good and unusual answer to the
girl's dilemma. Lateral thinking is a way of thinking "around" a problem. "Lateral
thinking generates the ideas and vertical thinking develops them" (DeBono, 1968,
p.6). Lateral thinking, then, is sometimes used as a synonym for creative thinking or
idea discovery, whereas vertical thinking is the refinement and improvement of
existing ideas.
The world's most famous fictional detective, Sherlock Holmes, often exhibited
lateral thinking. One of my favorite examples was Holmes' response to an idea by
his faithful assistant, the good Dr. Watson. Watson pointed out that a certain dog
would not be at all helpful in solving a mystery because the dog had done nothing
on the night of the murder. Sherlock cleverly noted that the dog was extremely im­
portant in solving the mystery precisely because he had done nothing on the night
of the murder because dogs would be expected to bark or become excited at the
sight of strangers or of violent struggles.
400 I O. CREATIVE THINKING

Creative Genius or Pedestrian Process?

''The human mind treats a new idea the way the body treats a strange protein; it
rejects it."
-Po B. Medawar (quoted in Byrne, 1988, p. 16)
Are creative individuals qualitatively different from the rest of us, or do we all have
(to some extent) what it takes to create something great? Increasingly, psychologists
have come to believe that there is "nothing special" about creative giants like Ein­
stein, Madame Curie, and Mozart and that the creative process can be understood as
an extension of common everyday thinking processes. Weisberg (1988, 1993) has
championed the everyday view of creativity in his analysis of the antecedents of cre­
ative thinking. For example, he presents a brief biography of Alexander Calder
(1898-1976), a popular artist who is best known for his brightly colored mobiles.
Calder invented the mobile as an art form. As a child, Calder used wire to make jew­
elry for his sister. His parents were artists who made certain that he had art lessons
and was surrounded with both sculpture (his father's profession) and drawings (his
mother's profession). He visited the studios of Piet Mondrian, an abstract artist who
used strong, primary colors and abstract designs in his work. It is easy to see how
these life experiences led to an art form in which brightly colored abstract patterns
were strung together and hung in space. The creative act was the assimilation of
these diverse forms and influences-one that, at least in hindsight, could have been
predicted from Calder's life experiences.
The view that even great creative products can be produced by almost anyone
with at least slightly above-average intelligence and expertise in a discipline is gain­
ing in popularity. For example, Hayes (1989) noted that there are no cognitive abili­
ties that separate creative and noncreative people. According to this view, most of
us have "what it takes" to be highly creative. From a cognitive perspective, creative
thinking uses thought processes that are quite ordinary. We can all come up with
"novel products of value" (Weisberg, 1993, p. 4). All we need to do is learn how­
and there's the rub!

Sensitivity, Synergy, and Serendipity

Creative thought is innovative, exploratory, venturesome.


-Kneller (1965, p. 6)
Creativity has been described as the three 5s: sensitivity, synergy, and serendipity
(Parnes, Noller, & Biondi, 1977). Sensitivity is the use of our senses, our "windows to
the world" that we use to touch, smell, taste, and see. It has been suggested that highly
creative people may experience the physical world with greater intensity than the rest
of us, although I don't know of any data to support this possibility. It does seem that
creative thinking involves the "noticing" or remembering of some critical aspect of the
environment or a problem that the rest of us overlooked. One of the benchmarks of a
creative person is the ability to find problems and not just solutions to them. Look at
Fig. 10.1. This is called "Boring's Wife-and-Mother-In-Law." Can you guess why?
Look closely. Can you see both an old woman and a young woman in the picture?
Count the prongs on Fig. 1 0.2. Do they disappear as you count them? This is an
impossible figure-impossible because it can't ever exist, except in the artist's mind.
DEFINING CREATIVITY 40 1

FIG. 1 0. 1 . Boring's Wife-and-Mother-In-Law. Can you see both an old woman and a
young woman in this picture?

FIG. 1 0. 2 . A n impossible figure. Try t o count the prongs.

In creating each of these figures, the artists displayed a sensitivity to details that is
both unusual and appropriate. Perhaps these are examples of heightened sensitivity
to visual stimuli.
Synergy is the bringing together of seemingly disparate parts into a useful and
functioning whole. It is close to Koestler's (1964) notion of bisociative thinking in
which two previously unconnected "frames of reference" are amalgamated. If you
can take ideas from different domains and bring them together so that they work
successfully in a new context, you have demonstrated synergy. Examples of synergy
can be found in the brief biography of Calder, which was presented earlier, who
brought together his experiences with wire objects, bright colors, and abstract draw­
ing to create his wildly popular mobiles.
402 1 O. CREATIVE THINKING

Gordon (1961) suggested that one way to promote creativity is to bring people
from diverse fields together to find problems and to create solutions, the two main­
streams of the creative process. In order to bring together diverse ideas, you need to
have a broad range of experiences and knowledge. Creativity is enhanced when
groups are composed of diverse team members (Jackson, 1996 ). One argument for a
liberal arts education is that it provides the breadth of knowledge needed to view
the world from different perspectives and to permit the combination of ideas across
domains of knowledge.
According to von Oech (1983), Johannes Gutenberg conceived of the printing
press by combining two previously unconnected ideas-the wine press and the coin
punch. The purpose of the coin punch was to leave an impression on a small area
such as a coin. By contrast, the wine press applied pressure over a large area in
order to squeeze the juice out of grapes. One day Gutenberg put the coin punch
under the wine press and found that he could get images on paper. This simple, but
original, combination resulted in the printing press and literally changed the world
by making books widely available.
Serendipity is a unexpected discovery that is unplanned. Biographies of great
scientists often contain accounts of serendipitous events, some of them seemingly
preposterous. I have often felt that focusing on serendipity did the scientist a great
injustice. A new miracle drug may have been the result of an accidental spill, but it
was the prepared scientist who could appreciate the results of the accident that cre­
ated the drug. The scientist was able to select the relevant information from the acci­
dent so that it could be used in a novel way instead of simply labeling it a mistake
and forgetting about it. Although serendipity may have contributed to a creative
act, the persistence, motivation, and hard work on the part of the creator allowed
the serendipitous event to occur. Serendipity may play a role in great scientific dis­
coveries, but such fortuitive "accidents" seem most likely to occur in the laboratory
at 2 a.m.
Consider how an artist friend of mine combined sensitivity, synergy, and
serendipity to create a new form of art. Robert Perine, a San Diego artist (who also
created the beautiful and novel depiction of "The Thinker" on the cover of this
book), decided to incorporate the glass that is used to cover pictures into the pictures
themselves. He cut odd-shaped glass coverings and placed them over his watercolor
paintings to see how the beveled edges in the glass would refract the paint beneath it
and give it a glossy, shimmering appearance. It was a simple idea that brought to­
gether the framing process and the picture itself in a new art form that incorporates
the picture and the glass used to protect it. Creative ideas often seem simple and sur­
prising. Like Calder's union of jewelry design and bright abstract painting to create
his mobiles, and Gutenberg'S union of the coin press and wine press to create the
printing press, this contemporary artist brought together two known processes
(framing and painting) in a novel and useful way with a creative outcome.
Jokes, puns, and witticisms could also be considered as a form of creative expres­
sion. A joke brings together two ideas that are not usually combined: Did you hear
the one about the two former schoolmates who meet unexpectedly for the first time
in 25 years? As they caught up on the details of their lives, one asked the other if he
had any children. Sorrowfully he replied, "Yes, one living and one married." The
listener was expecting the phrase "one living and one dead" and the surprise juxta­
position of "living and married" is the humorous element in this joke. Laughter is
often the response to original ideas also. The surprising combination of elements
(synergy) makes for good jokes and creative ideas.
DEFINING CREATIVITY 403

creativity as Investment Theory: Buy Low; Sell High

Even in companies that pride themselves on their encouragement of wacky,


creative thinkers--outside-the-box requires them to be wacky and creative in the
right sort of way-and to think outside the appropriate box.
-Peter Martin (2001, July 1 7, p. 10)
Suppose you were to decide right now to "do something creative." Where and how
would you begin? Would you search popular and scholarly media to identify emerg­
ing trends, such as the development of smaller computers, more powerful drugs, or
faster means of transportation, and apply your knowledge and skills in one of these
areas? If so, then you would be exhibiting a not-very-creative approach to deciding
which ideas or products to pursue. Sternberg and Lubart (1995, 1996) maintain that
creative people make unusual decisions about the topics and products in which they
are willing to invest their own time and effort; those of us who are not recognized as
creative may have made errors in selecting the topic that is worth pursuing. Creative
people work on topics that are unpopular at the time; they make creative contribu­
tions to the field, and then move on to another unpopular topic. In this way, creativ­
ity is like the classic mantra of finance, "buy low; sell high." In other words, creative
people invest in unpopular topics (topics where there is low interest) and move on to
another unpopular topic when the first one gains in popularity (leave the area when
interest is high). The definition of creativity requires "something unusual," so cre­
ative people, by definition, buck the crowd instead of following it.
The investment theory of creativity addresses an important question in the world
of ideas-what is worth thinking about? In Chapter 9 on problem solving, the prob­
lem finding (or identifying) is similar to the idea of deciding how to invest cognitive
resources. Finding the right problem to solve (or a problem worth solving) is at least
as important as deriving a successful solution. Problem solving and creativity are
closely related topics. Creative problem solvers (and finders) will have knowledge
about the topic, sufficient intellectual ability (i.e., intelligence), an encouraging envi­
ronment, an appropriately flexible thinking style, a personality that is open to new
ideas, and the motivation to persist at a task.

Creativity as a System

A scientific theory or other product is creative only if the innovation gains the
acceptance of a field of experts and so transforms the culture.
-Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi (2001, p. 337)
Creativity will involve more than just knowledge about a field or the willingness to
propose a novel idea. There are many different ways of examining this strange crea­
ture we call "creativity." Some psychologists have adopted a systems approach to cre­
ativity, which means that they believe it is the confluence of many different types of
variables that make creativity more or less probable. Of course, the creative individual
is central to the process, but she or he works in a domain of knowledge (e.g., art,
physics, decorating, teaching, horse breeding, and any other domain you can think
of). The contributions of an individual to a domain are judged by the people in the
field-the art critics, funding agencies for physics research, editors of decorating mag­
azines, etc. The people in the field act as the gatekeepers for a domain-they decide
404 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

what is and is not valued. Docents in art museums often tell stories of artists who
died penniless because their unusual style was not recognized as genius until after
their death. Of course, they never mention those dead, penniless artists whose art is
still not recognized as having value-and may never be. The role of the gatekeepers
to a domain is critical in understanding creativity because these influential people
can spur creativity or stifle it, depending on their own views of what is novel and
appropriate for their domain. In a fascinating case study of these influences, Naka­
mura and Csikszentmihalyi (2001) recount an interview with Linus Pauling, a scien­
tist who won a Nobel Prize for his work in the fields of organic chemistry and nu­
clear disarmament and ignoble scorn for his work on the role of vitamin C in
preventing colds. This fascinating account emphasizes the importance of variables
that are beyond the control of a creative individual.

CREATIVITY AS A COGNITIVE PROCESS

The man with a new idea is a Crank until the idea succeeds.
-Mark Twain (1897, aka Samuel L. Clemens)
If the creative act is "nothing special," then we should be able to understand it and
predict when it will occur using a common cognitive framework. Several different
psychologists have suggested that creativity is as "simple" as problem solving, ex­
cept that the problem or the solution are novel and appropriate. According to this
view, creative thinking is a multistage process that consists of identifying a problem,
deciding what is important about the problem, and arriving at a novel way of solv­
ing it. Perkins (1988) stresses the processes of searching and selecting as integral to
creative acts, but these are the same processes that were used to understand more
mundane problem solving and decision making. "Creativity" brings together many
topics that have been addressed in earlier chapters; yet, it is also more elusive and
mysterious because, by definition, we cannot tell anyone how to create the "un­
usual." What makes the processes of identifying problems, searching for solutions,
selecting the most promising ones, and conveying the outcome, creative?

Stretching and Rejecting Paradigms

A paradigm is an example that is used as a pattern. In psychology it usually refers


to an experimental setup, but it can be anything. In this context, it is used to mean "a
usual way of thinking or responding." Consider this example: Suppose that you are
a manufacturer of golf clubs. Like all manufacturers, you want to sell more golf
clubs. Paradigmatic thinking about this problem might lead you to increase your
advertising budget so that advertisements for your golf clubs reach more people
(McFadzean, 2000). If you stretch the paradigm, you might start to think that instead
of reaching more people with your advertisements, you want to target buyers of
golf clubs, so you would plan your advertising to reach fewer people, but a more se­
lect group. If you reject the paradigm, you change the nature of the problem that is
being solved. Callaway Golf, a U. S. manufacturer of golf clubs, did exactly that
(Kim & Mauborgne, 1999). Their creative idea-"Big Bertha Golf Clubs." What, you
don't know about Big Bertha? Instead of making golf clubs that would compete
CREATIVITY AS A COGNITIVE PROCESS 405

with other well-known brands of golf clubs, they made new golf club aimed at a
new golf-playing audience-people who don't play golf. The creative people at
Callaway thought about all of the people at country clubs who play tennis instead of
golf because these tennis players find the idea of using a tiny club to hit a tiny ball
too daunting a task. After all, the head of a tennis racket is much larger than the
head of golf club, so it should be easier to hit a tennis ball with the large head of a
tennis racket than a tiny golf ball with a small head of a golf club (other things being
equal, which, of course, they are not). Callaway saw a business opportunity that no
one had seen. A golf club with a large head makes playing golf less difficult and
more fun for people who do not play golf. Thus, they combined the larger head of
the tennis racket with the shaft of a golf club to create Big Bertha-a profitable move
that expanded the market for golf clubs. This creative act involved rejecting the
business-as-usual paradigm.
It is useful to conceptualize creative thinking within the framework that was de­
veloped in the chapter on problem solving (Chapter 9). A problem exists when there
is a discrepancy between where the problem solver is and the desired end state or
goal. A solution is a plan for attaining the goal. Guilford (1977) described the rela­
tionship between problem solving and creativity this way: " . . . problem-solving and
creative thinking are closely related. The very definitions of those two activities
show logical connections. Creative thinking produces novel outcomes, and prob­
lem-solving produces a new response to a new situation that is a novel outcome.
Thus, we can say that problem-solving has creative aspects."

The Problem of Problem Definition


All of our great inventors were problem finders. They recognized problems that
the rest of the world never saw. For example, why did people need electric lights
when gas worked well, or why should we even want to travel in a metal box pro­
pelled with a new-fangled engine when horses were more reliable (at that time)? We
all studied the great inventors of the past, people like Benjamin Franklin, George
Washington Carver, and Thomas Edison. Present-day inventors also find problems.
An "Invention Convention" is held annually in the United States to highlight the
creative talents of current inventors. Some of the items first displayed at this con­
vention are a double-headed toothbrush that can brush both sides of the teeth at the
same time, a portable hot water shower that can be used for camping because it is
lightweight and relies on the sun to heat the water, bedroom slippers with head­
lights, and an electric box that makes and bakes a loaf of bread-all you do is pour
in the ingredients. These have all become commercial successes, which means that
the general public believes that they are good solutions to a problem that most of us
never knew existed. How many of these can you identify-The Blair Witch Project,'
which used internet marketing to make a low-budget film a commercial success;
"Cows on Parade," a promotion that brought more than 2 million visitors to
Chicago to view brightly painted, whimsical, fiberglass cows in various locations
around the city; "Viagra," a drug developed to enhance the sexual abilities of men
(and vastly increase profits of the manufacturer); "America Online," an online Inter­
net service that offered services that no one before ever thought were needed (Ryan,
2001). These examples are so deeply ingrained in American culture that it is hard to
believe that these are just some of the many creative ideas and products developed
in the last two decades. In every case, someone saw an opportunity that the rest of
us missed. What can we learn from these and other creative successes?
406 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

Selecting Relevant Information


Virtually every creative act involves a novel way of defining a problem and se­
lecting information that is relevant to reaching the goal. We usually think of creativ­
ity in the arts and sciences, but it can and should exist in a host of everyday settings
that range from planning your finances so that your money lasts until the end of the
month to getting your teacher to accept a late paper.
Consider a couple seeking marriage counseling. The wife complains that her hus­
band spends too much time at work, and if he really loved her, he would spend more
time at home. The husband complains that he has a great deal of pressure at the of­
fice and that he has to work long hours to "get ahead." If his wife loved him more,
she would understand. There are multiple possible ways to define their problem.
They could pose the problem as: "Should we get a divorce?" But, other possible
problem definitions include: (a) How can we find ways to spend more time together?
(b) How can we assure each other that we are still in love? (c) How can the husband
"get ahead" while spending less time at work? (d) How can they learn to adjust to
the present situation? (e) Is "getting ahead" an important goal? (f) What can the wife
do so that she doesn't feel lonely and resentful when her husband is at work?
If you consider the problem for a few more minutes, you can come up with many
other problem definitions. The nature of the solution will change every time the
problem is redefined. The selection of relevant information to help you reach a goal
is related to your knowledge of the problem space (topic). In this example, you
would need to know more about the couple to help them find a good solution. Sup­
pose that you know that the wife is an aspiring artist. You could suggest that she
pursue her art interests so that she would feel less lonely and deserted. Alterna­
tively, if you know about the availability of other jobs for the husband, you could
suggest that he change jobs. In fact, therapists who have adopted this technique re­
port that they can help families overcome destructive conflicts by teaching them
how to discover creative solutions to their interpersonal problems (Carson, 2001).
Lateral thinking or "thinking around a problem" is really just another term for
"redefining the problem." In the story about the clever girl who knew she was being
offered two black pebbles, she didn't conceptualize the problem as "What should I
do when I pick the black pebble?" Instead, she redefined the problem as "How can I
avoid the appearance that I picked up the black pebble?" It's not so much "thinking
around the problem" as it is redefining the problem so that it can be solved in a fa­
vorable way. This point was also made in the previous chapter on problem solving.
In a review article of research and theory on creativity, Mumford and Gustafson
(1988) noted that creativity is related to "information that is seemingly irrelevant to
the solution of the problem at hand" (p. 30). By focusing on the fact that the pebbles
on the path were black and white and therefore she could drop one without its
being identified, the heroine of this short story was able to generate a novel solution.

Generation, Exploration, and Evaluation

Creativity is a puzzle, a paradox, some say a mystery.


-Margaret A. Boden (1990, p.vii)

If creative thinking is just a variant of everyday problem solving, then there should be
general principles that can be applied across domains of knowledge. Are the creative
CREATIVITY AS A COGNITIVE PROCESS 407

dancer, scientist, teacher, and writer all using the same sorts of processes in their cre­
ation despite the fact that they are using different modes of expression with very dif­
ferent problems? Although there are obvious differences, they all have to generate
possible solutions to their problem and explore the "problem space," a term that was
defined in the problem-solving chapter as all of the possible goals and ways of getting
from the start point to the goal. Finke, Ward, and Smith (1992) have posited a two­
phase model that they call geneplore, named for the repeated cycles of generation
and exploration that are part of every problem-solving process. Creative individuals
need to be involved and committed so that they continue the processes long enough
to allow a creative solution to emerge. Levine (1994) calls the willingness to work on a
problem "intimate engagement," a term that connotes the close links among motiva­
tion, hard work, time on task, and willingness to explore possibilities.
Evaluation is also a creative act because the problem solver must be able to recog­
nize when a good solution has been obtained (Doolittle, 1995). Effective evaluation
is needed to terminate the process or the problem solver can be caught in unending
loops of exploration and generation. Notice that a problem-solving view of creativ­
ity also entails all of the other stages of cognition. A successful exploration of the
problem space requires that the problem solver be able to notice and remember criti­
cal aspects of the problem. Thus, as in all of thinking "memory must be tickled."
Although it is clear that memory is an important component of both creative and
noncreative problem solving, the utilization of memory must differ in some way be­
tween these two processes. When thinking creatively, the memory task is more than
retrieval of a known fact; it involves a broader search, with fewer constraints on the
type and breadth of information retrieved (Bink & Marsh, 2000). In fact, one detri­
mental effect of expertise is the finding that the ability to retrieve a well-known so­
lution or response may hinder creativity (Sternberg & O'Hara, 1999). Thus, experts,
who can retrieve solutions to problems as readily as we might retrieve an arithmetic
fact, are less likely to consider additional possible solutions than the novice who
needs to think through a solution. This model of creative thinking offers two possi­
bilities for those who are interested in enhancing creative thinking-(a) conduct
broad searches of memory, or in other words, do not stop thinking about a problem
as soon as a solution has been found, and (b) practice synthesizing information that
has been retrieved (i.e., remembered or "thought of") so that information can be
combined in novel ways.

Insight and Incubation

Not surprisingly, both the terms "insight" and "incubation" were discussed in Chap­
ter 9 on problem solving. Insight was described as the sudden awareness of a solu­
tion; incubation was described as period of time when an individual is not actively
working on a problem that is followed by a successful solution. These two stages in
the problem-solving process are often associated with creative solutions. Although
these are both "hidden" processes that are seemingly mysterious, it is possible to
examine them within the framework of a general cognitive model.
I hope that you can recall from Chapter 2 on memory, the idea that the informa­
tion people store in memory is connected in weblike networks. For example, your
information about flowers is connected such that what you know about roses is
(metaphorically) stored close to your information about petunias, azaleas, and other
flowers. If you know a great deal about flowers, then you have an extensive and
408 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

highly interconnected network of information. If you grew up in the tropics, then


your knowledge of flowers is probably very different from that of someone who
grew up in Antarctica because you probably would have very different information
about flowers. The interconnectedness of knowledge is important here. According to
a network model of memory, all of your knowledge about flowers is also connected
to your knowledge of water and sun, which in tum are connected to many different
types of information. Theoretically, if you start at any point in this giant intercon­
nected web, you could trace your way to any other place in the web. A hypothetical
schematic of a section of someone's knowledge network is shown in Fig. 10.3.
When a new idea suddenly comes to someone, it means that he has successfully
traveled his personal knowledge network from one place to another-the new idea
representing the connection between two previously unconnected nodes. Think
about someone you love. What sorts of ideas and images come to mind? Does the
image of a rose seem appropriate? If so, it may be because I brought your knowledge
of roses to mind in the last paragraph and the path from your love to that of roses
was "activated." Does the phrase, "My love is like a red, red rose" have any meaning
for you? Does the sudden association of your love and roses seem insightful?
Psychologists call the "thinking about" or the "reminding" process spread of acti­
vation to denote the idea that the activity that was begun when I told you to think
about a loved one, spread to your knowledge of roses. People with large knowledge
nets will have more places for the activation to spread, and the best way to have a

sun
Pasadena, California

solar energy

drought

Roses


essential
chemical

grow in many
locations tulips

� Holland

� petunias


many grow from
colors bulbs
need
partial sun

FIG. 1 0.3. An example of the way information in memory is interconnected in a giant


weblike knowledge structure. Creativity involves "noticing" or making unusual connections.
CREATIVITY AS A COGNITIVE PROCESS 409

large knowledge net is to have a large number of interconnected knowledge struc­


tures. There is no substitute for knowledge about a topic; just as there is no substi­
tute for the ability to use the information stored in memory in thoughtful ways. If
you want to be more creative in the sciences, for example, you would need to ac­
quire knowledge about the field so that relevant information will be available for
solving problems about science. We use our knowledge nets for new ideas, and
skimpy nets yield few ideas. It is the ability to use the information stored in memory
that allows us to create by going beyond what we have learned.
Let's consider what else is happening when you solve a problem. Suppose that
you are reading a murder mystery in which the prime suspect is the hero, and
hence, unlikely to be the murderer. You are focusing on another character who, you
believe, "did it." Dutifully, you generate possible solutions and explore the problem
space, but to no avail. You cannot connect your prime suspect to the murder scene,
so you "forget" about the problem and resume other activities. In other words, you
create a period of incubation. Then, when you return to the book, you "see" that
it was not your prime suspect, but some other character. Using the jargon of the
problem-solving literature, you were fixated on one solution type (finding a way to
link your suspect to the crime) and the incubation period allowed you to "forget"
this type of solution so that other more profitable paths could be pursued-sort of a
release from fixation.
Good problem solvers know how to search through a large problem space, so as to
make it an efficient process. When there are a large number of possible paths to a
goal, good problem solvers use heuristics, or search plans, to "prune the search tree"
(Boden, 1990, p. 78). If you have an extensive knowledge net concerning some topic,
then you have more potential paths or links among concepts and more retrieval cues
that can help you remember and select relevant information when it is needed.

Analogical Thinking

Analogy is inevitable in human thought.


-Oppenheimer (1956, p. 129)
Analogies underlie much of our everyday thinking, our artistic expressions, and sci­
entific achievements. Sternberg (1977, p. 353) has noted, "reasoning by analogy is
pervasive in everyday experience. We reason analogically whenever we make a de­
cision about something new in our experience by drawing a parallel to something
old. When we buy a new goldfish because we liked our old one, or when we listen
to a friend's advice because it was correct once before, we are reasoning analogi­
cally." Thinking involves the ability to note resemblances or correspondence be­
tween two objects, while simultaneously discerning that there are also differences.
When you use analogies you observe that two entities are similar with respect to
some property, and dissimilar with respect to others. Analogies are discussed in
several chapters in this book because they are pervasive in human thought.
We utilize analogies to make sense of the world. They help us to understand new
events by relating them to ones already known; they allow us to communicate our
thoughts; they are the foundations of creative thinking. Analogies are one way of
making the unfamiliar known. Analogies are always imperfect because they imply a
similarity between objects and events that are not identical. In evaluating and creat­
ing analogies, carefully consider the nature of the comparison. If I say that you are
410 10. CREATIVE THINKING

like your brother because you both have two eyes, you would certainly object be­
cause the number of eyes one has is not a relevant dimension for comparison. How­
ever, if I say that you are like your brother because you are both passive and stingy,
you might still object, but the nature of the comparison is a relevant one.
One of the most famous creative uses of analogy is seen in the story of
Archimedes, a famous Greek mathematician, physicist, and inventor (287-212 B.c.).
He was given the task of determining if the crown of King Hiero II was pure gold­
the only kind of crown worthy of a king. According to the legend, Archimedes did
not know how to solve this problem because of the irregular shape of the crown.
One day, while lowering himself into a bathtub full of water, the tub overflowed.
The answer was immediately obvious. Like his body, a solid gold crown would
displace a volume of water identical to that displaced by a bar of gold that was
equal in weight to that of the crown. Because gold is denser than silver, an object
(like a crown) would displace less water than another object of the same weight that
had been mixed with silver. The story goes on to say that in his excitement he ran
naked through the street yelling, "Eureka, I have found it!" He found that Hiero's
crown displaced more water than an equal weight of gold, thus showing that the
crown had been alloyed with silver (or some other metal less dense than gold). He
had a true creative insight mediated by the analogy of his body displacing his bath­
tub water and the knowledge that a gold crown would displace a predetermined
volume of water. (In some versions of the story, the crown was pure gold and the
king was very happy, so don't take the story literally.)
Although the use of analogies from distant domains is a common theme in dis­
cussions of creativity, in fact, the spontaneous noting of similarities in very different
contexts is not a common occurrence. As discussed in Chapter 9 on problem solving,
analogical transfer is more likely to occur when we learn to think about the structure
of a problem (e.g., displace water as a form of measurement) instead of the surface
or domain features (how is a gold crown like taking a bath). Perhaps it is because it
is unusual that it figures prominently in our belief about creativity-which requires
an unusual outcome or process.

Making the Familiar Strange


Although the usual function of analogies is to make the unfamiliar familiar,
Gordon (1961, 1976), the founder of a creative technique known as synectics, sug­
gests that we reverse the process for creative results. Gordon (1976) suggests that we
use analogies and metaphors by trying "strange new contexts in which to view a fa­
miliar problem" (p. 251). Gordon suggests, as an example, that we consider a naive
student examining a fish's heart for the first time. Because the student knows noth­
ing about anatomy, the context is strange, yet the flow of blood through the heart
may remind him of a filter system for a local swimming pool. The student's analogy
is a creative contribution to his understanding of anatomy.
Gordon has suggested four specific types of analogies for use when attempting to
solve a problem creatively. They are personal analogy, direct analogy, symbolic
analogy, and fantasy analogy. Each is described in Chapter 9 on the development of
problem-solving skills. Analogies can also be used creatively to find problems. For
example, executives at Bradford Associates (Westport, Connecticut) spent an after­
noon sipping martinis and brainstorming about possible new products that would
be marketable. As they were enjoying their own liquid refreshments, they decided
that the time had come "for a six-pack that a dog could ask for by name." They are
CREATIVITY AS A COGNITIVE PROCESS 41 1

now marketing a chicken-flavored soft drink for dogs known as "Arf'n' Arf." Here is
a clear example of the use of analogies to find problems (the need for a doggie soft
drink). Similarly, a popular dog product is now being developed for people. Many
dogs enjoy munching on bone-shaped biscuits that help to keep their teeth and
gums healthy. A similar biscuit that will help humans to keep their gums and teeth
healthy is now available on some market shelves.
Bionics is a special type of analogy. It relies on analogies from nature that can be
adapted to human problems. For example, special properties of the eyes of beetles
have suggested a new type of ground speed indicator for airplanes, and the princi­
ples of adhesion used by cockleburs have served as the prototype for Velcro-type
closures. Bionics is also concerned that the broad impact of solutions be considered
because borrowing another analogy from nature, small changes in our ecological
system can result in disastrous consequences to other life forms in the food chain.
Papanek (1977) calls this the "total-chain-of-design idea." It requires the creative
consideration of entire systems and interrelationships of parts.
Weber and Perkins (1992) conceptualize the creative process as finding ways to
bridge different problem spaces, so that solutions can be applied and modified across
domains of knowledge. Consider modern surgery to unclog clogged arteries. A thin
tube is threaded into the artery. When the clog is reached, a small "balloon" is in­
flated in the artery to open the clogged area. This is the same technique that has been
used by plumbers to open clogged pipes. Thus, cardiac surgeons are saving lives
with a common problem-solving technique that was designed for plumbing. Many
creative acts involve adapting solutions from one field for use in an unrelated field.

Remote Associations Test


There is a test of creativity that rests on the notion that creative people can form
connections between seemingly very different topics. Mednick and Mednick (1967)
have created a test to tap this dimension of creativity. It is called the Remote Associ­
ations Test or RAT for short. Test takers are given three words and are asked to
come up with a fourth word that relates to all three. As an example, what word re­
lates to:

RIVER NOTE BLOOD

Can you come up with the relational word? (The answer is bank-river bank,
bank note, blood bank.) Try some other remote associations similar to the ones on
the RAT:

1. BOARD DUCK DOLLAR


2. FILE HEAD TOE
3. BOILED LID FLOWER
4. BALL MALARIA BUTTER
5. CLASS STAGE SOCCER

(The answers are at the end of the chapter.)


Do creative people come up with remote associations when they think creatively?
It seems that some do, but there is very little direct evidence that tests like the RAT
can predict creativity in natural contexts. An invention by Michael Reynolds of
Taos, New Mexico, seems to epitomize this type of thinking. He combined his
412 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

knowledge of the high cost of housing with the problem of soda cans littering the
countryside and the proverbial lightbulb went on. He made these remote associa­
tions and constructed a house of aluminum soda cans. For his second house, he is
filling the cans with water so that the solar-heated cans of water can supplement his
home energy needs.

ENCOURAGING CREATIVITY

One of the objections I hear to setting forth creativity as a goal for higher
education is, 'We can't all be Einsteins.' This is undeniable; it is also irrelevant.
-Hutchings (1986, p. 14)
There has been considerable debate over the question of whether it is possible to
make people more creative by providing them with special experiences that are de­
signed to enhance creativity. There is a sizable research literature that shows that it
is possible. This notion is not really a surprising conclusion given that creative
thinking shares many features with everyday sorts of problem solving, and the evi­
dence reviewed in the first chapter and several places throughout this book showed
that improved thinking is a possible outcome of education. In a review of the re­
search literature on creativity, Baer (1993) cautiously concluded that there are many
variables that are involved in the enhancement of creative thinking.
What are the many variables that are important in determining when and how
much creativity can be enhanced?

The Person, the Problem, the Process

Discovery consists of looking at the same thing as everyone else and thinking
something different.
-Albert Szent-Gjorgyi (Nobel Prize winner in medicine;
quoted in von Oech, 1 983, p. 7)
It is clear that creativity is not something that exists in an all-or-none fashion. People
are more or less creative, just as they are more or less athletic or good-looking or
prejudiced. The question of whether there is some inborn or inherited trait that is as­
sociated with high creativity has been difficult to answer. Most of the research has
centered on the relationship between creativity and intelligence. Are intelligent peo­
ple the most creative people?
In general, people with above average scores on intelligence tests tend to be cre­
ative, whereas those with low IQ scores tend not to be; but the relationship is not a
perfect one. It is not true that the very smartest people are always the most creative.
There is a certain minimum intelligence that is needed to be creative, but beyond the
minimal level, IQ doesn't seem to matter much. Even if you're not a particularly in­
telligent person, you may have great creative potential. In addition, we all have dif­
ferent abilities. A person with a broad knowledge net about football strategies and
skill in running and throwing is more likely to be a creative football player than an
individual who has little knowledge of the field and is clumsy with a football, but
ENCOURAGING CREATIVITY 413

the second individual may be more creative in an unrelated domain of knowledge


such as poetry or ballet.

Creativity as a Goal

We want creative citizens, who can take responsibilities and who are able to
solve problems that do not yet exist today.
-Olli-Pekka Heinonen (Finland's minister of education,
quoted in Shavinina, 2001, p. 292)
The easiest way to enhance creativity is to value it. In an experimental study,
Shalley (1991) found that college students who were told that creativity was valued
produced more creative products (had creativity goals) than students who had been
told that they were being judged on the number of products they produced (had
productivity goals) or told nothing about expectations for creativity or number pro­
duced. The underlying idea behind this research was that most people pay more at­
tention and exert more effort if they have clear goals. It seems that people will be
more creative when they are told to be creative. This is probably not a surprising re­
sult to the college students who are reading this. After all, how often are students
encouraged or even permitted to be creative in school? Most often, the learning goal
in school is to be able to repeat back something that was learned in class or to be
able to apply a skill in an appropriate setting. Apparently, we can be more creative
if we are expected to be creative.

Environmental Factors

People will be most creative when they feel motivated primarily by the interest,
enjoyment, satisfaction, and challenge of the work itself-not by external
pressures.
-Hennessey and Amabile (1988, p. 1 1)
Creative thinking, like all activities, takes place in a social context-a fact that is
often overlooked in the cognitive literature. Amabile (1996, 1997, 2001) has studied
the environmental-social factors that can encourage or discourage creativity. Like
other researchers in the field of creativity, she concluded that much of what happens
in school and work settings is not conducive to the development of creativity. She
found that creative individuals often view their work as a labor of love. They work
long hours because they are impelled by their curiosity and their own desire to
achieve a goal. Hard work is a repeated theme among those who study the creative
process. This sort of motivation is called intrinsic motivation because it comes from
within the individual. By contrast, much of the motivation provided at school and
work is extrinsic motivation, which is motivation that comes from others, such as
promises of a good grade or money. According to Amabile, the best way to promote
creativity is to arrange the environment so as to maximize intrinsic motivation. Six
conditions that tend to kill intrinsic motivation are (a) constant evaluation, (b) sur­
veillance, (c) reward, (d) competition, (e) restricted choice (e.g., limited choice of
materials to use), and (f) an extrinsic orientation toward work.
414 1 o. CREATIVE THINKING

Most school and work environments tend to be heavily weighted towards the
negative end of these six factors; teachers and supervisors watch while students and
employees work, competition is either overt or covert, but almost always present,
and the workers receive grades or payment for their efforts. It is impossible to avoid
extrinsic motivators completely as there will always be deadlines, competition, and
restrictions, for example. Despite these realities, it is possible to design school and
work environments to foster creativity by reducing the focus on extrinsic motivators
and emphasizing the intrinsic rewards of the creative process. Environmental fac­
tors like these are only part of the creativity equation--creativity needs more than a
conducive environment to flourish. In addition to changes in the environment, cre­
ativity training also needs a skills component. No one can become a creative scien­
tist or great author or talented artist without the factual knowledge and technical
skills that are relevant to their chosen field. There is no substitute for knowledge.
Not surprisingly, blanket statements like "external rewards hinder creativity"
have been challenged by several researchers who found that, at least sometimes, ex­
ternal rewards can stimulate creative responses. For example, in Nakamura and
Csikszentmihalyi's (2001 ) case study of the life of Linus Pauling, it is clear that
Pauling changed the focus of his work to organic chemistry because he was given
grant money for research in organic chemistry. He then went on to make highly cre­
ative advances in this new field of study, so the extrinsic motivation provided by the
grants did not seem to diminish his creative genius; instead the grants refocused his
creativity in a new domain. In a study of the effects of extrinsic rewards on creativ­
ity, researchers found that there are many other variables that influence creativity
and, under some conditions, external rewards like providing money for creative
outcomes, can enhance creativity (Eisenberger & Cameron, 1998). The effect of in­
trinsic rewards on creativity remains a contested area of research.
There is at least one conclusion on which everyone can agree: A quality education
(both inside and outside of school) will give you the basis for the remote associa­
tions or divergent thoughts or novel ideas. Creative people need a head filled with
thoughts and facts in order to create with them. The inferences from Amabile's
work are clear: cultivate a love of learning, reward your own creative efforts, take
the college courses that will fill your mind with new thoughts (and not just the easi­
est courses offered). Creative endeavors result from hard, intellectual work that is
self-motivated and self-monitored. Don't be afraid to engage in it.

Personality Factors

Multiple studies have found that the primary determinant of new product
failure is an absence of innovativeness.
-Sethi, Smith, and Park (2001, p. 73)
There are certain personality factors that are consonant with creativity. Because cre­
ativity (as we have defined it) requires an unusual or novel act, the creative individ­
ual must not be swayed by a need for conformity nor be resistant to change. In order
to persist in doing or thinking the unusual, the creative person will also need to
have enough self-confidence so as not to be dissuaded from a pursuit when others
denigrate or deride it. There also needs to be a love or joy with pursuits that are cog­
nitively complex. Perhaps there is some validity to the notion of the "eccentric"
artist or scholar. If you read the first chapter of this book, you will recognize that
ENCOURAGING CREATIVITY 415

these are dispositions of critical thinkers-not surprisingly, I return to some of the


same themes that were presented in the first chapter as I near the end of this book.
The creative person must be self-motivated so that he or she will persist at a task.
Sometimes, school experiences tend to favor the noncreative students, as many tradi­
tional assignments don't call for creative responses. Creative people may have to
create their own rewards for their actions and find satisfaction in the creative process
itself. The ability and willingness to take risks and to tolerate ambiguity is also needed
for creative acts. When we try to do things differently, we sometimes fail. Most of the
great discoveries in modern times were initially met with ridicule and repeated failure
(a horseless carriage, a machine that could fly, etc.). We need to teach children and
learn for ourselves that failure is an important part of life and that every great success
was built upon previous failures. Creative people are able to "slow down" and take
the time to review and rethink their usual way of doing things and resist quick closure
on problems (Larson, 2001). In the first chapter of this book, I made the case for the im­
portance of a critical-thinking attitude. The same themes are repeated in this chapter
on enhancing creativity. The only seeming contradiction comes from recent research
on creativity in teams. Team cohesion seems to be detrimental to creativity (Sethi,
Smith, & Park, 2001). If team members are quick to agree with each other (high cohe­
sion), then unusual solutions or conclusions will never emerge from a team because
usual and common outcomes will be generated most often. We need teams that foster
and encourage dissent (in a positive way). Group leaders who insist on consensus are
inadvertently stifling creativity. If everyone in a group agrees, then it is likely that only
one person is doing the thinking. Of course, it can be uncomfortable to "go against the
crowd," yet creative people are able to be a lone dissenter. In order to be an effective
dissenter, creative people often persuade group members to consider seriously his or
her unusual perspective. In real-life settings, social skills are vital for successful ideas.
In a study of creative people (Barron, 1958), writers, artists, musicians, and math­
ematicians were given a battery of tests to determine if they had any personality
traits in common. In general, these highly creative individuals were nonconforming,
unconventional, and generally less concerned with "making a good impression."
One contemporary American hero is the recently deceased Richard Feynman.
Feynman was the Nobel prize-winning physicist who became famous in the nonsci­
entific world when he investigated the tragic explosion of the Challenger. He
demonstrated that "0" rings, rubber circular gaskets used on the Challenger, get
brittle when they get cold. His simple test consisted of dunking an "0" ring in ice
water and showing that it could crack when cold. The attitude of risk taking and
nonconformity is exemplified by the title of an autobiographical book about his life
entitled What Do You Care What Other People Think? (1989). Of course, this does not
mean that if you become nonconforming and unconventional, you'll then become
highly creative, but it suggests that a more open-minded and less self-conscious ap­
proach to life's problems can pay off. Feynman also demonstrated a natural curios­
ity and immense breadth of knowledge. His interests weren't limited to physics and
extended to many domains including the arts and music.
I had the great honor to meet this remarkable man. I recall with great clarity a
time when I sat next to him at an informal dinner party. He remarked to my daugh­
ter, who was young at that time, that growing old was a peculiar thing. When he
was my daughter's age, he could never get enough dessert, and now that he is old
and can have all the dessert he wishes, he no longer wants it! At the time, I thought
that this was an odd discussion between a child and older man, but now I think it
was just part of the eccentricity that marked his genius.
416 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

STRATEGIES FOR CREATIVE THINKING

The nation that neglects creative thought today will assuredly have its nose
ground into the dust of tomorrow.
-Fred Hoyle (1915-2001 , astronomer and physicist)

Creativity has never been given the attention it deserved in standard educational
settings. Over four decades ago, Lowenfeld (1962) called creativity "education's
stepchild," a fact that remains true today. There seems to be no place in the tradi­
tional school curriculum for creativity training. There have been many programs de­
veloped with the specific goal of training people to be creative in order to fill this
gap, probably because leaders in the corporate and manufacturing worlds know
that they must produce new and better products than the competition, or they will
find themselves working for the competition.

Basic Principles

Although there are considerable differences among creativity-training programs,


they all share some basic common principles:

1 . Teach students to think of different ways to accomplish an objective and then


how to select the best one.
2. Provide plenty of examples and exercises to model and practice creative skills.
3. Teach students how to ask relevant questions and how to discover when a
problem exists.
4. Evaluate the quality of an idea by its consequences.
5. Reward original and relevant ideas, but be certain to keep the reward sec­
ondary to the enjoyment of the creative process. Let students know that their
ideas are valuable.
6. Provide unstructured situations. Teach them the value of persistence when
they fail.
7. Provide students with a tangible plan for finding solutions. This means that
they should be trained in ways that will help them to make relevant information
that they have stored in memory accessible and to find ways to bridge areas of
knowledge. Plans include recognizing puzzling facts, seeking information, gen­
erating possible solutions, changing perspectives, and restating the goal.
8. Restrain from labeling or categorizing problems or solutions too quickly in
the problem-solving process because labeling tends to encourage fixation, the
opposite sort of set that is needed for flexible thinking.
9. Create the expectation that creative outcomes result from hard work, persis­
tence, a broad knowledge base, and the willingness to continue thinking after
a satisfactory solution or answer has been found.
10. Encourage risk taking and nonconformity, along with a repertoire of re­
sponses that are needed for teamwork.

You may be thinking that there is no such thing as "strategies for creative thinking"
because creativity involves breaking rules, not following them-a sort of a free activ­
ity. Bailin (1987) has argued against this notion of creativity. As she noted, most cre­
ative actions take place within a framework of rules. Even the most beautiful sonnet
STRATEGIES FOR CREATIVE THINKING 417

contains 1 4 lines of specified meter and rhyme, all great ballets are performed with
the principles and techniques of dance, and all scientific discoveries are made by ex­
perts who are knowledgeable in their field. In order to depart from a framework or
to bend the usual rules, the creative individual must have some knowledge of con­
vention as well as some guidelines for unconventional thinking.

productive Thinking Program

One of the first and best-known creative training programs was developed by
Covington, Crutchfield, Davies, and Olton in 1974 for fifth and sixth graders. The pro­
gram consisted of a workbook in which the brother-and-sister team of Jim and Lila
had to solve a series of detective stories. The reader, along with Jim and Lila, had to
formulate hypotheses, gather evidence, and ask questions in order to solve the crime.
If you've already read Chapter 6, "Thinking as Hypothesis Testing", you'll recognize
this sequence as the steps used in experimental methods of discovery. All along Jim
and Lila were guided by a wise "Uncle John" who would provide hints and explain
their mistakes. This program was discussed briefly in Chapter 9 on problem solving.
One of my favorite stories from the Productive Thinking Program concerns a
missing jewel. As guests arrived at a party, they brought wrapped gifts for the
wealthy hostess. Suddenly, the lights went out, and when they went on again a
valuable jewel was missing. Lila and Jim had to determine what had happened to
the jewel. No one could have left or entered the room as the door had remained
locked. The window was opened, but there were no footsteps in the fresh snow that
covered the ground. Later we learn that there is a feather on the floor and that one of
the boxes has a hole in the bottom. Have you solved the crime by now? A trained pi­
geon was taken from a wrapped box and used to transport the jewel to an accom­
plice. The pigeon escaped with the jewel by flying through the open window.
It takes Lila and Jim a while to find and put together the clues in order to solve this
crime. Crutchfield (1966) believes that with direct training with stories like this one, chil­
dren can learn to think more creatively. The reader engages in the discovery process
along with the protagonists, and may even solve the problem before Lila and Jim. A
modern version of this sort of student involvement in using clues and solving problems
that are embedded in realistic situations is now on interactive computer discs. For exam­
ple, The Adventures of Jasper Woodbury, an interactive educational program that teaches
mathematics and other sorts of problem-solving skills was developed by the Technol­
ogy Group at Vanderbilt University (Van Haneghan, Barron, Young, Williams, Vye, &
Bransford, 1992). It includes many of the principles that are discussed in this chapter.
The Jasper Woodbury series has been constantly evaluated over the last 10 years for its
effectiveness in teaching mathematical problem-solving skills. The researchers report
generally positive results (http://peabody. vanderbilt.edu/ctrs/lsi/research.htm).
Several other programs have recently arrived on the market or are scheduled for
release in the near future. Although many of these programs are promising, potential
users are urged to ask for the evidence that they actually work as promised. It is very
difficult to find solid evidence that children trained with these methods actually grow
up to be more creative adults or that they ever apply these skills in real-life settings.
This is, of course, the real goal of any thinking skills program-use of the skills in un­
related situations. The teacher was an important variable in any program's success
because it is what students are asked to do with information that is important in
determining the outcome.
418 10. CREATIVE THINKING

There are some popular programs that claim to increase creativity, but unless there
are solid data to back up these claims, you are not thinking critically if you accept the
claims at face value. Mall bookstores have rows of books that lure readers who want
to be more creative to "try on different hats" and to stimulate different ways of think­
ing by "thinking outside of the box"-quick claims that offer little in the way of em­
pirically validated findings (DeBono, I98S, 1992). Critical thinkers look for evidence
to support claims-especially when the claim is that thinking can be improved.

Quantity Breeds Quality

Since 1990 30% of (Glaxo Wellcome's) revenues has come from new
products . . . Glaxo Wellcome aims to increase research and development
productivity threefold to produce 20 new compounds from exploratory research
each year, leading to the launch of three significant new products annually.
-Sue Godfrey (executive director, Glaxo Wellcome, 2001, p. 1)
The notion that if you have lots of ideas, some of them will be good is the major
thrust of brainstorming. Brainstorming was discussed in Chapter 9 on the develop­
ment of problem-solving skills as a way to find solution paths that solve problems.
It is a creative way to generate solution paths and is often used in creative problem
solving. Brainstorming is a way of producing a list of ideas that can subsequently be
evaluated. Although brainstorming can be done individually, it is more commonly
considered a group activity. The only rule of brainstorming is that all judgment be
deferred until some later time so that no one hesitates to offer unusual or off-beat
ideas. Osborn (1963) offers many examples in his book, Applied Imagination. For
example, Osborn reports that a IS-minute brainstorming session at American
Cyanamid Corporation produced 92 ideas, or more than six ideas per minute. This
was an average of eight ideas per participant. Simonton (referenced in Begley, 1993)
found that creative people had many more bad ideas and many more good ideas
than their less creative peers because they had many more ideas overall.
The quantitative advantages of brainstorming are without question. But do more
ideas necessarily imply better ones? Often, the best ideas result from the combina­
tion (synergy) and alteration of the ideas listed. The atmosphere of deferred judg­
ment is clearly consistent with the discussion on environment presented earlier in
the chapter. It encourages risk taking and unconventionality, both of which are pre­
requisites to creative thinking. At the very least, brainstorming is fun. It is a recom­
mended strategy for enhancing creative thought because it incorporates several of
the principles for creative thinking, but the evidence that brainstorming produces
more high-quality ideas than other techniques is still limited.
Osborn had a group of parents brainstorm on how to get their children to watch
less television and read more books. Read carefully through the list of ideas the par­
ents came up with. It seems to me that some combination of these ideas would
surely be effective.

1. Pull plug in TV set.


2. Break up the set.
3. Set a definite time for looking at TV.
4. Arouse interest in books.
5. Acquire a bad horizontal tube.
STRATEGIES FOR CREATIVE THINKING 419

6. Reorient antenna in order to get bad reception.


7. Select a book that has been seen on TV.
8. Set example by reading yourself.
9. Buy a portable radio for children.
10. Evaluate TV programs.
11. Encourage visits to library.
12. Have the children write book reports.
13. Give money for movies.
1 4. Donate a TV to library.
15. More outdoor companionship with parents.
1 6. As a result of seeing TV story (say Robinson Crusoe) children given same
book to read and do research on.
1 7. Start reading aloud to them when young.
18. Read them good books.
19. Make reading as convenient as TV.
20. Give them their own bookcase in room.
21 . Give records for Hi-Fi.
22. Give subscriptions to children's magazines.
23. Select books suitable to age.
24. Get them interested in daily newspapers, even if only the comics.
25. Help them with their homework.
26. Select type of news they read.
27. Discuss with them the books they have read.
28. Have them read to you.
29. At PTA meeting, have subject discussed with teachers; get teachers to recom-
mend books.
30. Encourage group reading.
31. Buy them a good dictionary.
32. Always answer questions if you can.
33. Buy a good children's encyclopedia.
34. Institute games requiring the use of words and general knowledge.
35. Get local schools to have course in fast reading and good reading.
36. Have children checked physically-there may be some reason why they are
unable to read.
37. In addition to their allowance, give them a fee for each good book that they read.

Creative Ideas Checklist

Another method for producing creative ideas is to present people with a checklist of
diverse categories or adjectives or questions that could conceivably apply to the
question or problem at hand. These lists are called creative ideas checklists. By forc­
ing people to change the type of answer that they are considering, flexibility in think­
ing is encouraged. Doolittle (1995) found that the use of many different types of
solutions is more important in creative problem solving than just having many differ­
ent solutions that all involve the same category of response. In order to understand
this distinction, consider a problem that involves moving A to B. There may be many
different ways to move A (car, boat, roller skates), but a flexible list would include
other categories of responses such as having them meet in the middle or moving B or
moving both to point C, or solving the problem without moving either A or B.
420 1 o. CREATIVE THINKING

In one study of the use of lists to stimulate creative ideas, Davis and Roweton
(1968) gave students the following list, which was labeled "Aids in Thinking of
Physical Changes" :

a. Add or Subtract Something


b. Change Color
c. Change the Materials
d. Change by Rearranging the Parts
e. Change Shape
f. Change Size
g. Change Design or Style

Students who were given this list were told to, "List as many physical changes as
you can for a thumbtack." Davis and Roweton reported that the group that had re­
ceived the checklist produced a greater number of ideas and more creative ideas
than a control group that had not been given the checklist. A cookie manufacturer
began making "reverse" chocolate chip cookies---chocolate cookies with white
chocolate chips. They have become an overnight financial and taste success. You
should recognize this simply as (d) in the above list-a change by rearranging the
parts. This simple creative act has paid well for its innovator.
Perhaps the most famous checklist is a generalized one that can be applied in a
variety of situations. Whiting (1958, p. 62) attributes this list to Osborn.

Put to Other Uses? New ways to use as is? Other uses if modified?
Adapt? What else is like this? What other idea does this suggest? Does past offer
parallel? What could I copy? Whom could I emulate?
Modify? New twist? Change meaning, color, motion, odor, form, shape? Other
changes?
Magnify? What to add? More time? Greater frequency? Stronger? Larger?
Thicker? Extra value? Plus ingredient? Duplicate? Multiply? Exaggerate?
Minify? What to substitute? Smaller? Condensed? Miniature? Lower? Shorter?
Lighter? Omit? Streamline? Split up? Understate?
Substitute? Who else instead? What else instead? Other ingredient? Other material?
Other process? Other power? Other place? Other approach? Other tone of voice?
Rearrange? Interchange components? Other pattern? Other layout? Other se­
quence? Transpose cause and effect? Change pace? Change schedule?
Reverse? Transpose positive and negative? How about opponents? Turn it back­
ward? Turn it upside down? Reverse roles? Change shoes? Turn tables? Turn
other cheek?
Combine? How about a blend, an alloy, an assortment, an ensemble? Combine
units? Combine purposes? Combine appeals? Combine ideas?

Although there are many such lists, a third one worth considering is from Parnes
(1967, p. 231 ) who suggests that you ask yourself these idea-spurring questions
when you're looking for new ideas:

1. Effects on objective?
2. Individuals and/or groups affected?
3. Costs involved?
4. Tangibles involved (material, equipment, etc.)?
5. Moral or legal implications?
STRATEGIES FOR CREATIVE THINKING 42 1

6. Intangibles involved (opinions, attitudes, feelings, aesthetic values, etc.)?


7. New problems caused?
8. Difficulties or implementation and follow-up?
9. Repercussions of failure?
10. Timeliness?, etc.

In a recent twist on the idea of lists that stimulate creative thinking, McGuire
(1997) listed several techniques for finding creative hypotheses that are worth pursu­
ing. The research literature in psychology and other sciences is huge, but much of it
involves problems that are trivial (at least in the opinions of some people). How can
researchers find and recognize those research problems that are potentially impor­
tant? His long list of strategies for answering this question includes: (a) counterexam­
ples or thinking about ways the opposite would be true (e.g., instead of thinking that
bad parents cause neurosis suppose bad parenting causes good mental health);
(b) reverse causal direction (e.g., instead of hypothesizing that coffee causes headaches
maybe having headaches leads people to drink coffee); (c) push an example to an ex­
treme (e.g., if children's use of grammar shows that they learn general grammatical
rules what would perfect grammar in children suggest?); (d) extrapolate from similar
problems (e.g., older adults can improve their memory for names with mnemonics so
perhaps they could improve their memory for locations with mnemonics); (e) shift at­
tention to the opposite end of a problem (e.g., instead of thinking about the cost of a new
technology think about its benefits); and (f) pay attention to outliers or unusual responses
(what it is about Person X that led her to respond differently from the other partici­
pants). McGuire's list is considerably longer than the sample items presented here,
but these examples should demonstrate the main idea of manipulating how one
thinks to discover hypotheses that are potentially important enough to warrant em­
pirical investigation. He notes that he has only informal data on the effectiveness of
these strategies and calls for more research on the important problem of finding out
which techniques can enhance creativity.
Although the purpose of creative ideas checklists is to create novel ideas, it is also
possible that they could have an inhibiting effect. If you only considered the possi­
bilities on a small checklist, you could miss other ideas by narrowing your search to
ones that are suggested by the list. These lists cannot be used as algorithms that
would always lead to a creative response, but may be helpful as heuristics to help
get a stalled thinking process moving again.
We've all had the experience at one time or another of being "stuck," when ideas
don't seem to flow. If you go through these checklists, pondering each item, you're
bound to get your thoughts flowing again. Using the cognitive framework intro­
duced earlier, they all provide probes for searching knowledge networks so that dif­
ferent sorts of information can become available for use.

Attribute Listing

More innovation is the key weapon for UK companies to outperform world


competitors.
-McHardy and Allan (2000, p. 496)
In attribute listing, every characteristic or quality of the item or situation is listed
and then examined for possible modification or recombination. Let's try an example.
422 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

Suppose you want to make something really different for dinner tonight. In fact,
you want to make a food that no one else in the world has ever tasted before. How
would you go about doing this? First, you could list many different foods:

eggs
hot dogs
baked Alaska
stewed tomatoes
steak Tartare
chocolate pudding
etc.

Alongside each food, you would list several of its attributes, such as shape, con­
sistency, color, texture, odor, temperature, etc. You'd then randomly pair attributes
to come up with a new food. You might think of the "soft and shimmery" attribute
of jello and the cold, hard attribute of ice cream and combine the two so that you'd
freeze the jello or whip the ice cream. Attribute listing is a good procedure for fash­
ion deSign. You could list every part of a dress, for example, and every attribute of
that part. A partial example is:

Dress Part Attribute


collars pointed, rounded, none, Nehru
sleeves raglan, short, rolled, long
waist cinched, gathered, dropped, loose
skirt full, straight, ruffled, pointed

A talented dress designer could combine possible dress attributes, coming up


with thousands of unique designs (e.g., a dress with a Nehru collar, short sleeves,
gathered waist and ruffled skirt.) This unique combination shows why I should stay
out of fashion design-although the resulting dress would be unusual, it would
probably not pass the evaluative test for creativity-appropriate or good.

Crovitz's Relational Algorithm

Those of you who have already read Chapter 8 on the development of decision
making skills know that an algorithm is a step-by-step guide that leads to a solution.
Crovitz's (1970) Relational Algorithm is a solution guide that relies on changing the
relations among items. Crovitz lists 42 "relational words" (p. 1 00). They are:

about at for of round to


across because from off still under
after before if on so up
against between in opposite then when
among but near or though where
and by not out through while
as down now over till with

When you are in need of a creative solution, you have only to try different ways of
"relating" the elements. Crovitz uses Duncker's classic X-ray problem as an example.
STRATEGIES FOR CREATIVE THINKING 423

Although this problem was described in Chapter 9 on the development of problem­


solving skills, I'll present it again briefly. The problem is to get rid of an inoperable
stomach tumor with X-rays without harming the healthy tissues. However, when the
radiation is intense enough to destroy the tumor, it will also harm the healthy tissue
surrounding it. The best solution involves using several weak rays through different
parts of the body so that they will summate on the tumor. Crovitz demonstrates how
the relational algorithm can be used to find a solution to this and other problems. The
procedure is fairly simple. Form a sentence with each relational word using it as it
might relate to the tumor. For example:

1. Take the rays through the esophagus.


2. Take the sensitivity from the tissues.
3. Take tissue off the tumor.
4. Take strong rays after weak rays.
5. Take a shield on stomach walls.
6. Take the tumor across the stomach.
7. Take a cannula through the stomach wall.
8. Take the power from the rays.
9. Take the tumor to the exterior. (Crovitz, 1970, p. 1 02).

Crovitz claims that this method works well because it forces the individual to
consider new relationships among the parts of the problem.

Plus, Minus, Interesting

Plus, Minus, Interesting (PM!) is a plan for beginning the problem-solving process
that was suggested by DeBono (1976). When you are searching for a solution to an in­
tractable problem, one way to begin is to list all of the "givens" in a problem and all
possible solutions (even ones that are unrealistic) and to consider for each what is
positive about it, what is negative about it, and what makes it interesting. The idea
behind this process is that a careful and methodic consideration of various compo­
nents of different solutions and other aspects of the problem will help the problem
solver to find new solutions by highlighting positive aspects and eliminating negative
ones. The use of the "interesting" category will help the problem solver to consider
what makes a solution interesting, and thereby lead to the consideration of additional
alternatives. It is a plan for seeking information that may be relevant to a solution,
and like all of the other strategies, it provides a guide for exploring knowledge nets.

Activating Inert Knowledge

All of the strategies for creative thinking are designed to increase the "flow of
ideas." Psychologists call this improving ideational fluency. In PMI, for example,
the problem solver is given a plan for generating ideas. She is told the kind of infor­
mation she should consider (givens and possible solutions) and how to evaluate
them. Earlier in this book, I talked about the importance of tickling memory. This is
particularly important when you seem to have "run out of ideas." There are several
simple plans that can be employed when this happens. For example, in a study de­
scribed by Perkins (1985), children were instructed to list words that they might use
424 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

when writing a composition about a selected topic. The children were given a few
minutes to complete this prewriting task. The researchers reported that after only a
few hours of training with this method, the children were writing longer and better
passages. Let's consider the simple elegance behind this procedure. By listing topic­
relevant words, the students were required to think about their knowledge of the
topic before they began to write. They made their knowledge about the topic more
available for use in their composition. It forced them to plan their response.
Writing is one of the most creative tasks that we can be asked to do. Students and
even prolific authors often complain about "writer's block." This simple method,
which is applicable at all levels, should help to eliminate writer's block because it is
a way of activating one's knowledge of the topic so that it can be used. I have used it
in several college classes that I teach with good results.

Browsing

In our society we have great institutions that function as repositories for ideas. They
are called libraries. Wicker (1981) suggests that we "probe library sources" to gener­
ate new ideas. Pick up newspapers and magazines, case histories and biographies,
scholarly journals, joke books, and even children's literature. Use a broad range of
sources. You can't make "remote associations" or borrow ideas from other fields if
your own knowledge is confined to a narrow discipline. This technique is easier
than ever because there are many quality library resources available online, so we
can "browse" in our jammies late at night, but be careful-there is also a great deal
of worthless and even harmful junk on the Internet. Be sure that you can tell the dif­
ference between scholarly and applied research and unsubstantiated "hot air" that
is blowing around on the Internet.
Use qualitative and quantitative information. Census reports can suggest new
problems because they succinctly state what people are doing, where they are doing
it, what they are eating, how they are living, and how they are dying. Learn some­
thing new every day. If you pick up a journal at random and read one new article a
day, you'll be surprised at how the newly acquired information crops up in everyday
contexts. You can also browse with quality television shows like Nova, 60 Minutes,
and National Geographic. They contain a wealth of fascinating information on almost
any topic of interest. Don't forget to go to museums, art galleries, theater, and the
opera. If you feel that you can't afford these outings, remember that many have a
"free day" once a month and offer reduced rates for students, the elderly, and groups.

visual Thinking

When Mozart was asked where he got his ideas he said, " Whence and how they
come I know not; nor can I force them."
-(quoted in Vernon, 1970, p. 53)
Creative thinking often calls for images. The musician must first "hear" the sounds
before she places the notes on paper; the poet must hear the rhyme before it is writ­
ten; the painter must see the forms before his first brush stroke; and the chef must
"taste" the combination of ingredients before the new recipe is created. It does seem
that there are certain creative acts for which words are inadequate. Most people
APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK 425

report that, at least some of the time, they think in images. An image is a picture-like
representation in the mind. (See Chapter 2 on the development
. of memory skills for
discussion of imagery.)
Gonzalez, Campos, and Perez (1997) examined the relationship between imagery
and creativity. They gave high school students tests of imagery and spatial ability
and the Torrence Test of Creative Thinking. They found positive relationships be­
tween imagery and creativity, which were stronger for the students with high IQs
than for students who score within the average range on intelligence tests. Other re­
searchers have suggested a relationship between creativity and imagery. The ratio­
nale behind this proposed relationship is that good imagers should be able to "see"
problems in ways that should help them to generate solutions that are different
from their peers who are low in the ability to create images. A suggested method for
solving problems is to draw a diagram, thus transforming a verbal problem into a
visual one. Adams (1979) calls visual thinking an "alternative thinking language." It
is an alternative to verbal-based thought. Adams suggests that we each take a draw­
ing course to improve our ability to see and, in turn, to think creatively. He claims
that we can improve our visual thinking with practice, but like many similar claims,
the evidence is not presented in a form that can be scrutinized.
Imagine the following (Adams, 1979, p. 91):

1. A pot of water coming to a boil and boiling over;


2. Your Boeing 747 being towed from the terminal, taxiing to the runway, wait-
ing for a couple of other planes, and then taking off;
3. Your running cow changing slowly into a galloping racehorse;
4. An old person you know well changing back into a teenager;
5. A speeding car colliding with a giant feather pillow;
6. The image in (5) in reverse.

Putting It All Together

Several different strategies or methods to produce creative thoughts have been pre­
sented. It would be naive to believe that if you can recite each of these methods, you
will automatically have creative thoughts. They are merely guidelines for hard
work, and some of us will have to work harder than others.
It is clear that creative thinking is a skill that can be cultivated (Shalley, 1991). The
strategies presented in this chapter are the plans for developing that skill. You may
be wondering, "Where do I begin7" You begin with a problem or a need. For some,
creative ideas will immediately seem to flow; for others it will be more like pulling
teeth. If you find yourself "out of fresh new ideas," try the techniques listed above.
Visualize the situation, use analogies and metaphors, consider relations, list attrib­
utes, mull checklists, and brainstorm. The creative process within you should ignite
with some help from these strategies.

APPLYING THE FRAMEWORK

In applying the general thinking skills framework to creative thinking, consider the
following questions.
426 1 0. CREATIVE THINKING

1. What Is the Goal'?


The creative process is defined by its outcome. The goal in thinking creatively is
the production of a novel and appropriate response. Often it also involves the iden­
tification of a novel problem. The creative problem solver knows which problems
are solvable and worth solving. In the language of investment theory, they buy low
and sell high (become interested in the problem when the general interest level is
low and move on to other problems when the problem becomes popular).

2 . What Is Known'?

A point that was made in this chapter is that one cannot be creative in a vacuum.
You need the knowledge and skills of a domain to be creative. There is no substitute
for information about the problem. You may have the potential to become a truly
great architect or writer, but without knowledge of these fields, it is unlikely that
you will design an innovative structure or write a truly great novel. In the problem
about the merchant's daughter that was told in this chapter, there would have been
no creative answer if she had not used her knowledge about the dishonest money
lender to watch closely when he picked up the pebbles. Similarly, a careful consider­
ation of the particular aspects of any problem is needed for finding problems and
for finding solutions. Begin the creative process by listing the "givens."

3. Which Thinking Skill or Skills Will


Get You to Your Goal?
This is really the question of how can we be creative. Numerous skills were sug­
gested to guide the creative thinking process. The skill you select will depend on the
nature of the problem. For example, visualizing the problem is more likely to be
helpful with problems that have a spatial aspect to them such as geometry problems
or terrain problems. The skill of generating a list of topic-relevant words can be
helpful in a variety of situations, but seems particularly well suited for writing and
composing. Creative thinking checklists are useful in design problems; whereas
"plus, minus, interesting" can be used anytime you find that you don't know how
to begin finding a solution. The following creative thinking skills were developed
in this chapter. Review each skill and be sure that you understand how to use
each one.

• Defining a problem in multiple ways.


• Brainstorming to increase the number of ideas produced.
• Working with people from different backgrounds in order to increase the prob-
ability of bisociative thinking.
• Considering the physical changes listed in the creative ideas checklist.
• Arranging the environment to maximize intrinsic motivation.
• Encouraging an attitude of risk taking.
• Evaluating possible solutions using the questions suggested by Parnes (1967).
• Listing and combining attributes to devise a novel product.
• Forming sentences about the problem using relational words.
• Evaluating solutions and other aspects of the problem along the dimensions of
plus, minus, interesting.
• Listing terms that are related to the problem before you attempt a solution.
CHAPTER SUMMARY 427

• Gathering additional information.


• Using analogies to make the unfamiliar known and distorting analogies to
make the familiar unknown.
• Visualizing the problem.
• Using the hypothesis generating suggestions made by McGuire (counterexam­
ples, opposites, anomalous data, and the others.)
• Discouraging group cohesiveness so unusual thoughts can be considered.

4. Have You Reached Your Goal?

Because the creative process is judged by its outcome, the solution or product
will need to be evaluated along the twin dimensions of originality and appropriate­
ness. The evaluation is also a component in the creative process. If it fails on either
of these dimensions, then the thinking process will have to begin again until a cre­
ative outcome is produced.

CHAPTER SUMMARY

1 . Creativity involves the dual notion of unusual or unique and good or useful. It
always involves judgment, and people may not agree on which actions or outcomes
deserve to be labeled "creative."
2. DeBono has made a distinction between vertical thinking and lateral thinking.
Vertical thinking is logical and straightforward, whereas lateral thinking is a cre­
ative way to think "around" a problem.
3. An increasingly popular view in psychology is that creative individuals are not
qualitatively different from the rest of us. We all have the ability to be creative.
4. Virtually all creative acts will involve novel ways of defining a problem and
the selection of relevant information.
5. Creativity has been described as a blend of sensitivity, synergy, and serendip­
ity. It is as if a fortuitous event brings together remote ideas in a person who is
sensitive to their combination.
6. Creativity can be understood as a cognitive process that involves using the
information stored in memory to go beyond what is learned from experience.
Cognitive psychologists describe the process as a spread of activation through a
knowledge network with repeated cycles of generation and exploration.
7. Although it is true that, in general, intelligent people are more creative than
less intelligent people, it seems that a minimal level of intelligence is all that is
needed for creative expression.
8. Analogies are often part of the creative process in which solutions are adapted
from different domains of knowledge.
9. Creative people tend to be self-motivated, persistent, tolerant of ambiguity,
self-confident, and willing to take risks.
10. Intrinsic motivation seems to be one of the best predictors of creative behav­
ior. In order to encourage the production of creative outputs, the environment
should be designed to support intrinsic motivation.
1 1 . Several strategies to foster creative thinking were presented. Brainstorming is
based on the supposition that if you have many ideas some of them will be good. Each
item on a checklist of creative ideas can be applied to a problem to see if a creative
428 1 O. CREATIVE THINKING

spark is struck. Crovitz's relational algorithm relies on changing the relations


among the parts of a problem to arrive at a solution. The PMI strategy encourages
novel solutions by requiring the problem solver to evaluate various aspects of the
problem. Analogies and metaphors tune us in to similarities and differences that can
be valuable in creating novel solutions. Visual thinking seems to be involved in
many sorts of creative endeavors-especially the arts and sciences. The easiest way
to foster creativity is to value it.
12. All of the strategies to enhance creativity involve searching an individual's
knowledge net so that remote ideas can be associated, analogies applied across do­
mains of knowledge, and information that is stored in memory can become available.

TERMS TO KNOW

You should be able to define or describe the following terms and concepts. If you
find that you're having difficulty with any term, be sure to reread the section in
which it is discussed.

Creativity. The act of producing something that is original and useful.


Vertical Thinking. Thinking that is logical and straightforward. Used in the refine­
ment and development of ideas. Compare with lateral thinking.
Lateral Thinking. Thinking "around" a problem. Used to generate new ideas.
Sometimes used as a synonym for creative thinking. Compare with vertical thinking.
Sensitivity. Responsiveness to the information we perceive through our senses,
which includes "noticing" stimuli that may be critical to a creative solution.
Synergy. The bringing together of seemingly disparate parts into a useful and func­
tioning whole. Creative thinking often seems to involve such combinations.
Bisociative Thinking. Bringing together two previously unassociated ideas or
"frames of reference."
Serendipity. A happy, unexpected discovery.
Paradigm. An example that is used as a pattern.
Geneplore. Term coined by Finke, Ward, and Smith (1992) to denote the cycles of
generation and exploration that are part of the creative process.
Bionics. The use of analogies from nature that can be adapted to human problems.
Intrinsic Motivation. Inherent desire to engage in a task for its own sake and with­
out regard for reward or punishment.
Extrinsic Motivation. Engaging in a task in order to receive reward or to avoid
punishment.
Brainstorming. A group or individual method for generating solution paths for
problems. Problem solvers are encouraged to think up wild, imaginative solutions
and to defer judgment on these solutions until a later time when they may be modi­
fied or combined. The goal is to produce a large number of possible solutions.
Creative Ideas Checklists. Lists that suggest ways to generate creative ideas by
varying a problem's components and relationships among the components.
Attribute Listing. A method of generating creative solutions in which every charac­
teristic or quality of the item or situation is listed and then examined for possible
modification or recombination.
Relational Algorithm. A method for generating creative ideas that relies on chang­
ing the relations among items using relational words such as "on," "between,"
"under," and "through."
TERMS TO KNOW 429

Plus, Minus, Interesting. De Bono's (1976) plan for searching for a solution by not­
ing positive, negative, and other interesting aspects of the solutions being consid­
ered.
Ideational Fluency. The process of generating many ideas in order to solve problems.
Image. A picture-like representation in the mind.

Answers to remote associations presented earlier in the chapter: 1 . Bill, 2. Nail,


3. Pot, 4. Fly, 5. Coach.
1 1

The Last Word

Thinking is like loving and dying:


Each must do it for him (her) self.
-Anonymous
You may find that this is your favorite chapter because it is essentially a blank chap­
ter. As you worked your way through this book, you learned information that
should help you to become a better thinker. This is especially true if you also
worked your way through the exercises, questions, and reviews in the Exercise
Book that accompanies this text. Each chapter dealt primarily with one type of
thinking category. This was necessary because a large block of information needed
to be broken down so that it could be presented in manageable units. Unfortunately,
thinking doesn't break into neat and separate categories and mixed sorts of skills are
needed in most situations. Memory must always be accessed, the type of representa­
tion and the words we use will influence how we think, evidence always needs to be
considered, thinking must be logical, and so on. As you go through life, you will
need to use all of the skills that you practiced and improved upon in each of the
chapters. But, most importantly, you need to adopt the attitudes and dispositions of
a critical thinker. You need to find problems that others have missed, support con­
clusions with good evidence, and work persistently on a host of problems. I hope
that your encounters with this book will help you become a better thinker.
This is also a good time to step back and reflect on the definition of critical think­
ing that was presented in the first chapter and the broad categories of information
and strategies in the following chapters. Does the working definition of critical
thinking seem like it captured the multiple dimensions of complexity that are inher­
ent in critical thinking? Can you and will you use some of the thinking skills in your
own life-to make decisions, read about and plan research, understand the struc­
ture of a written passage, think creatively, remember more effectively, and more?
Are you more likely to have a desirable outcome because of something that you
learned? Have you adopted at least some of the attitudes of a critical thinker?

430
THE LAST WORD 43 1

Although this is a nonchapter, there is a corresponding chapter in the Exercise


Book, Thinking Critically About Critical Thinking, that requires you to select and inte­
grate thinking skills as you think through a variety of problems. As you work on
these problems, try to put the entire text together in some way that is useful and
meaningful to you. You are what and how you think. Be sure to act on your
thoughts and to use them to advance yourself and to improve even a small corner of
the world. Think well and with great wisdom. The future depends on it.

1 THAT� ENOUGH
iHIHKIWG, ZE-RO
I
i
1

1
I
I

I
���__ � o �c.�2L�==���

Reprinted with special permissions of King Features Syndicate.


References

Adams, A., Carnine, D., & Gersten, R (1982). Instructional strategies for studying content
area texts in the intermediate grades. Reading Research Quarterly, 1 8(1), 27-55.
Adams, J. L. (1979). Conceptual blockbusting: A guide to better ideas. New York: Norton.
Alcock, J. E. (1981). Parapsychology: Science or magic? Oxford, England: Pergamon.
Allegretti, C. L., & Frederick, J. N. (1995). A model for thinking critically about ethical issues.
Teaching of Psychology, 22, 46-48.
Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice. Cambridge, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Amabile, T. M. (1996). Creativity in context: Update to the social psychology of creativity. Boulder,
CO: Westview.
Amabile, T. M. (1997). Motivating creativity in organizations: On doing what you love and
loving what you do. California Management Review, 40, 39-58.
Amabile, T. M. (2001). Beyond talent: John Irving and the passionate craft of creativity. Ameri­
can Psychologist, 56, 333-336.
American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders.
Washington, DC: Author.
American Psychological Association. (1992). Learner-centered psychological principles:
Guidelines for school redesign and reform. The Psychology Teacher Network, 2, 5-12.
Anderson, B. F. (1980). The complete thinker: A handbook of techniques for creative and critical prob­
lem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Arasteh, A. R, & Arasteh, J. D. (1976). Creativity in human development. New York: Schenkman.
Aristotle. (1954). Rhys Roberts (Trans.). Rhetoric III (141Ob, 1st Modern Library ed.). New
York: Modern Library (exact wording varies by translation).
Arkes, H. R (1996). The psychology of waste. Journal of Behavior and Decision Making, 9, 213-224.
Arkes, H. R, & Hammond, K R (1986). Law. In H.R Arkes & KR Hammond (Eds), Judge­
ment and decision making: An interdisciplinary reader (pp. 211-212). Cambridge, MA: Cam­
bridge University Press.
Asimov, I. (1989, March 31). Combatting US scientific illiteracy. Los Angeles Times, p. 8.
Atkinson, R C. (1975). Mnemotechnics in second-language learning. American Psychologist,
30(8), 821-828.
Azar, B. (2000, May). Blinded by hindsight. Monitor on Psychology, pp. 28-29.
Baddeley, A. D. (1986). Working memory. Oxford, England UK: Clarendon Press/Oxford
University Press.
Baddeley, A. D. (1992). Working memory. Science, 255(5044), 556-559.
Baddeley, A. D., & Andrade, J. (2000). Working memory and the vividness of imagery. !oumal
of Experimental Psychology: General, 1 29(1), 126-145.
Baer, J. (1993). Creativity and divergent thinking. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bahrick, H. P., & Hall, L. K (1991). Lifetime maintenance of high school mathematics content.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 120(1 ), 20-33.
Bahrick, H. P., Hall, L. K., & Berger, S. A. (1 996). Accuracy and distortion in memory for high
school grades. Psychological Science, 7(5), 265-271 .

432
REFERENCES 433

Bailin, S. (1987). Creativity and skill. In DN. Perkins, J. Lochhead, & J. Bishop (Eds.), Thinking:
171e second international conference (pp. 323-332). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Baron, J. (1987). An hypothesis about the training of intelligence. In D. N. Perkins,
J. Lochhead, & J. Bishop (Eds.), Thinking: The second international conference (pp. 60-67).
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Baron, J. (1990). Harmful heuristics and the improvement of thinking. In D. Kuhn (Ed.), Develop­
mental perspectives on teaching and learning thinking skills (pp. 28-47). New York: Basel, Karger.
Baron, J. (1993). Why teach thinking?-An essay. Applied Psychology: An International Review,
42, 191-214.
Baron, J. (1994). Nonconsequentialist decisions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1 7, 1-42.
Baron, J. (1995). My side bias in thinking about abortion. Thinking and Reasoning, 1 , 221-225.
Baron, J. (1997). Biases in the quantitative measurement of values for public decision. Psycho-
logical Bulletin, 1 22, 72-88.
Baron, J., & Brown, R V. (1991). Teaching decision making to adolescents. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Barron, F. (1958). The psychology of imagination. Scientific American, 1 99, 151-166.
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Bartlett, J. (1980). Familiar quotations: A collection of passages, phrases, and proverbs traced
to their sources in ancient and modern literature (15th and 125th anniversary eds.). Boston:
Little, Brown.
Bartlett, J. (1992). Familiar quotations (1 7th ed.), Boston: Little, Brown.
Bassham, G, & Nardone, H. (1997). Using the film JFK to teach critical thinking. College Teach­
ing, 45, 1 0-1 1 .
Bastardi, A , & Shafir, E . (2000). Nonconsequential reasoning and its consequences. Current
Directions in Psychological Science, 9(6), 216-219.
Begley, S. (1 993, June). The puzzle of genius. Newsweek, pp. 46-49.
Beilensen, J., & Jackson, H. (1992). Voices of struggle, voices of pride. White Plains, NY: Peter
Pauper Press, Inc.
Benjamin, A S., Bjork, R A, & Schwartz, B. L. (1998). The mismeasure of memory: When re­
trieval fluency is misleading as a metamnemonic index. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
General, 127, 55-68.
Berger, D. (1995). Errors in judgments and decisions: Understanding our cognitive fallibilities.
In P. Foster (Ed.), Critical Thinking: Views and values in college teaching (pp. 48-68). River­
side, CA: La Sierra University Press.
Berkowitz, L., & Thome, P. R (1987). Pain expectation, negative affect, and angry aggression.
Motivation and Emotion, 1 1 , 183-193.
Berlin, B., & Kay, P. (1969). Basic color terms: Their universality and evolution. Berkeley: Univer­
sity of California Press.
Bernstein, D. A. (1995). A negotiation model for teaching critical thinking. Teaching of Psychol­
ogy, 22, 22-24.
Beyth-Marom, R, Dekel, S., Gombo, R, & Shaked, M. (1985). An elementary approach to think­
ing under uncertainty. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bink, M. L., & Marsh, R I. (2000). Cognitive regularities in creative activity. Review of General
Psychology, 4, 59-78.
Blasko, D. G (1999). Only the tip of the iceberg: Who understands what about metaphor?
Journal of Pragmatics, 3 1 (12), 1 675-1683.
Block, R A. (1985). Education and thinking skills reconsidered. American Psychologist, 40, 574-575.
Boden, M. A. (1990). The creative mind: Myths & mechanisms. New York: Basic Books.
Bodenmann, G. (1997). Can divorce be prevented by enhancing the coping skills of couples?
Journal of Divorce & Remarriage, 27, 1 77-194.
Bollag, B. (1 997) School-reform effort grows in Eastern Europe [Web Pagel. URL http://
chronicle.com/search97cgi/s973gi? [2000, December 281.
Boring, E. G (1932). Intelligence as the tests test it. New Republic, 35, 35-37.
434 REFERENCES

Bousfield, W. A. (1953). The occurrence of clustering in the recall of randomly arranged asso­
ciates. Journal of General Psychology, 49, 229-240.
Bower, G. (1994, May 25). Electronic communication from Marina Volkov at the Federation of
Behavioral, Pyschological, and Cognitive Sciences, [email protected]
Bower, G. H. (1972). Mental imagery and associative learning. In L. Gregg (Ed.), Cognition in
learning and memory. New York: Wiley.
Bower, G. H. (1970). Organizational factors in memory. Cognitive Psychology, 1 , 18-46.
Bower, G. H., & Cirilo, R K. (1985). Cognitive psychology and text processing. In Handbook of
discourse analysis (Vol. I , pp. 71-105). New York: Academic Press.
Bower, G. H., & Clapper, J. P. (1989). Experimental methods in cognitive science. In M. I.
Posner (Ed), Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 245-301). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Bower, G. H., & Clark, M. C. (1969). Narrative stories as mediators for serial learning. Psycho­
nomic Science, 14, 181-182.
Boxall, B. (1993, October 12). Statistics and science can be trusted to suit debate. The Los Ange-
les Times, p. A18.
Bozzell, L. B., III. (1993, July 21). Exposing statistical myths. The Washington Times, p. 64.
Bradbury, R (1950). Fahrenheit 451 . New York: Simon & Schuster.
Braine, M. D. (1978). On the relation between the natural logic of reasoning and standard
logic. Psychological Review, 85(1), 1-21.
Bransford, D. (1 979). Human cognition: Learning, understanding and remembering. Belmont, CA:
Wadsworth.
Bransford, J. D., Arbitman-Smith, R, Stein, B. S., & Vye, N. J. (1985). Improving thinking and
learning skills: An analysis of three approaches. In J. W. Segal & S. F. Chipman (Eds.),
Thinking and learning skills: Volume 1 . Relating instruction to research (pp. 133--206). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bransford, J. D., Brown, A. L., & Cocking, R R (Eds.). (1999). How people learn: Brain, mind,
experience and school. National Research Council Commission on Behavioral & Social Sci­
ences & Education. Committee on Developments in the Science of Learning. Washington,
DC: National Academy Press.
Bransford, J. D., & Johnson, M. K. (1 972). Contextual prerequisites for understanding: Some
investigations of comprehension and recall. Journal of Verbal Learning & Verbal Behavior,
1 1 (6), 717-726.
Bransford, J. D., Sherwood, R, Vye, N., & Rieser, J. (1986). Teaching thinking and problem
solving: research foundations. American Psychologist, 41 (10), 1078-1089.
Bransford, J. D., & Stein, B. S (1993). The ideal problem solver: A guide for improving thinking,
learning, and creativity (2nd ed.). New York: Freeman.
Brehm, J. W. (1956). Postdecision changes in the desirability of alternatives. Journal of Abnor-
mal and Social Psychology, 52, 384--389.
Brem, S., & Rips, L. (in press). Explanation and evidence in informal argument. Cognitive Science.
Brennan, J. (1993 May). Why polls can be poles apart. The Los Angeles Times, p. A5.
Brennan, T. (2001 January). An academic's guide to the way Washington really works. The
Chronicle of Higher Education, p. Bl1.
Brim, O. G., Jr. (1966). High and low self-estimates of intelligence. In O. G. Brim, R S.
Crutchfield, & W. H. Holtzman (Eds.), Intelligence: perspectives 1 965. New York, Harcourt,
Brace & World.
Brooks, 1. W., Simutis, Z. M., & O'Neil, H. F., Jr. (1985). The role of individual differences in
learning strategies research. In R F. Dillon (Ed.), Individual differences in cognition (Vol. 2,
pp. 219-251). New York: Academic Press.
Bross, I. D. J. (1973). Languages in cancer research. In G. P. Murphy, D. Pressman, & E. A.
Mirand (Eds.), Perspectives in cancer research and treatment (pp. 213-221). New York: Alan R
Liss.
Brown, A. L., & Campione, J. C. (1990). Communities of learning and thinking or a context by
any other name. In D. Kuhn (Ed), Developmental perspectives of teaching and learnillg thinking
skills. Contributions to human development (Vol. 21, pp. 108-126). Basel, Switzerland: Karger.
REFERENCES 435

Bruer, J. T. (1993). Schools for thought: A science of learning in the classroom. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Bruner, J. S. (1957). On going beyond the information given. In J. S. Bruner (Ed.), Contemporary
approaches to cognition (pp. 41-69). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bucciarelli, M., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1999). Strategies in syllogistic reasoning. Cognitive Sci­
ence, 23, 247-306.
Bugliosi, V. (1978). Till death do us part. New York: Bantam Books.
Burke, D. M., MacKay, D. G., Worthley, J. 5., & Wade, E. (1991). On the tip of the tongue:
What causes word finding failures in young and older adults? Journal of Memory and Lan­
guage, 30, 542-579.
Byrne, R. (1988). One thousand nine hundred eleven best things anybody ever said. New York:
Fawcett.
Cannon-Bowers, J. A., Salas, E., & Pruitt, J. S. (1996). Establishing the boundaries of a para­
digm for decision-making research. Human Factors, 38, 193-205.
Carey, J., Foltz, K., & Allan, R. A. (1983). The mind of the human machine. Newsweek.
Carkhuff, R. R. (1973). The art of problem solving. Amherst, MA: Human Resource Develop­
ment Press.
Carlson, E. (1995). Evaluating the credibility of sources: A missing link in the teaching of criti­
cal thinking. In D. F. Halpern & S. G. Nummedal (Eds.)., Psychologists Teach Critical
Thinking [Special issuel. Teaching of Psychology, 22, 39-4 1 .
Carroll, D . W . (1986). Psychology of language. Belmont, CA: Brooks/Cole.
Carroll, L. (1971). Through the looking glass. London: Oxford University Press (Original work
published 1872).
Carson, D. (2001). Innovative treatments in couples and family therapy. Annals of the American
Psychotherapy Association, 4, 13-14.
Catrambone, R. (1998). The subgoal learning model: Creating better examples so that students
can solve novel problems. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 127, 355-376.
Ceci, S. J. (1996). On intelligence: A bioecological treatise on intellectual development. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Ceci, S. J., & Ruiz, A. 1. (1993). Inserting context into our thinking about thinking: Implications
for a theory of everyday intelligent behavior. In M. Rabinowitz (Ed.), Cognitive science foun­
dations of instruction. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Center for Media and Public Affairs. (Merchandizing Mayhem: Violence in popular culture
1 998-1999. [Web Pagel. URL http: / /www.cmpa.com/archive/vioI98.htm [2002, Februaryl .
Ceraso, J . , & Protivera, A. (1971). Sources o f error i n syllogistic reasoning. Cognitive Psychol­
ogy, 2, 400-410.
Champagne, A. B. (1992). Cognitive research on thinking in academic science and mathemat­
ics: Implications for practice and policy. In D. F. Halpern (Ed), Enhancing thinking skills in
the sciences and mathematics (pp. 1 1 7-134). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Chance Magazine. (Spring, 2001 ). Three sisters give birth on the same day, pp. 23-25.
Chance, P. (1986). Thinking in the classroom: A survey of programs. New York: Teachers College
Press.
Chang, J. (1993). Wild swans: Three daughters of China. New York: HarperCollins.
Chapman, L. J., & Chapman, J. P. (1959). Atmosphere effect re-examined. Journal of Experimen­
tal Psychology, 58, 220-226.
Chapman, L. J., & Chapman, J. P. (1967). The genesis of popular but erroneous psychodiag­
nostic observations. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 72, 1 93-204.
Chapman, L. J., & Chapman, J. P. (1969). Illusory correlation as an obstacle to the use of valid
psychodiagnostic signs. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 74, 271-280.
Cheng, P. W. (1997). From covariation to causation: A causal power theory. Psychological
Review, 104, 367-405.
Cheng, P. W., & Holyoak, K. J. (1985). Pragmatic reasoning schemas. Cognitive Psychology,
1 7(4), 391-416.
Chesler, P. (1972). Women and madness. New York: Doubleday.
436 REFERENCES

Chi, M. T., Glaser, R, & Farr, M. J. (Eds.). (1988). The nature of expertise. Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
The Chronicle of Higher Education. (1 987). p. A2.
The Chronicle of Higher Education. (1994). p. A8.
The Chronicle of Higher Education. (2000) Survey finds that most Americans want college to
prepare them for a job [Web PageJ. URL http:/ /chronicle.com/search97cgi/s97_cgi? [2000,
December 28J .
Cialdini, R B . (1993). Influence: Science and practice (3rd ed.). Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman.
Cialdini, R B., Trost, M. R, & Newson, J. T. (1995). Preference for consistency: The develop­
ment of a valid measure and the discovery of suppressing behavioral implications. Journal
of personality and social psychology, 69, 318-328.
Clark, H. H., & Haviland, S. E. (1977). Comprehension and the given-new contract. In R O.
Freedle (Ed.), Discourse production and comprehension. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Clemens, S. L. (1897). Following the equator. Hartford: The American Publishing Co.
Clinton's message to USA's students: Learn to earn. (1 994 February). USA Today International
Edition, p. 6A.
The Cognition and Technology Group at Vanderbilt. (1983). Toward integrated curricula:
Possibilities from anchored instruction. In M. Rabinowitz (Ed), Cognitive science foundations
of instruction (pp. 33-56). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Cohen, D. (2000) With Asian economies on the rebound, the region's colleges are also upbeat (April 27)
[2000, December 28J .
Cohen, M. S., Freeman, J. T., & Wolf, S . (1996). Metarecognition i n time-stressed decision
making: recognizing, critiquing, and correcting. Human Factors, 38(2), 206-219.
Cole, K. C. (1995 June). Finding the truth is a slippery thing. Los Angeles Times, p. B2.
Cole, K. C. (2001 June). Leaders; Poor math skills add up to bad public policy. Los Angeles
Times, p. 8.
Collett, P. (1994) A new university for Pakistan [Web Pagel . URL http: / I chronicle.com I
search97cgil s97 cgi? [2000, December 28 J .
_

Connor-Greene, P. A. (2000). Assessing and promoting student learning: Blurring the line be­
tween teaching and testing. Teaching of Psychology, 27, 84-88.
Conway, M. A., Cohen, G., & Stanhope, N. (1991). On the very long-term retention of knowl­
edge acquired through formal education: Twelve years of cognitive psychology. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: General, 1 20(4), 395--409.
Coughlin, E. K. (1 993, November). When people make up their minds, psychologist says, they
often do not really make up their minds at all. The Chronicle of Higher Education, p. 9.
Covington, M. V., Crutchfield, R S., Davies, L. B., & Olton, R M., Jr. (1974). The productive
thinking program. Columbus, OH: Charles E. Merrill.
Crovitz, H. F. (1970). Galton's walk: Methods for the analysis of thinking, intelligence and creativity.
New York: Harper & Row.
Crutchfield, R S. (1966). Creative thinking in children: Its teaching and testing. In O. G. Brim, Jr.,
R S. Crutchfield, & W. H. Holtzman (Eds.), Intelligence: Perspectives 1965, The Terman-Otis
Memorial Lectures. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.
Cull, W. L. (2000). Untangling the benefits of multiple study opportunities and repeated test­
ing for cued recall. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 1 4, 215-235.
Cybernation International. The People's Cybernation [Web PageJ. URL http:/ I www.cyber­
nation.com/victory I quotes/thoughtsandthinking.html [2002, January 15J.
Dahlstrom, G. W. (1993). Tests: Small samples, large consequences. American Psychologist,
48(4), 393-399.
d' Angelo, E. (1971). The teaching of critical thinking. Amsterdam: Gruner.
Darner, T. E. (1987). Attacking faulty reasoning (2nd ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Dansereau, D. F. (1 995). Derived structural schemas and the transfer of knowledge. In
A. McKeough, J. Lupart, & A. Marini (Eds.), Teaching for transfer: Fostering generalization
in learning (pp. 93-121). Mahwah, NT: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Dansereau, D. F. (2001). (personal communication).
REFERENCES 437

Darrow, C. (1932). The story of my life. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.
Davidson, D., & Sternberg, R J. (1998). Smart problem solving: How metacognition helps. In
D. J. Hacker, J. Dunlosky, & A. C. Graesser (Eds.), Metacognition in educational theory and
practice (pp. 47-65). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Davidson, J. (1996). Choosing when it's confusing. Vital Speeches, 63(3), 84-90.
Davis, G. A., & Roweton, W. (1968). Using idea checklists with college students: Overcoming
resistence. Journal of Psychology, 70, 221-226.
Davis, M., & HuIt, R E. (1 997). Effects of writing summaries as a generative learning activity
during note taking. Teaching of Psychology, 24, 47-49.
Dawes, R M. (1993, June). Finding guidelines for tough decisions. The Chronicle of Higher Edu­
cation, p. 40.
Dawes, R M. (1994). House of cards: Psychology and psychotherapy built on myth. New York: The
Free Press.
Day, R S., Rodin, G. c., & Stoltzfus, E. R (1990). Alternative representations for medication
instructions: Effects on young and old adults. Paper presented at the 3rd Cognitive Aging
Conference, Atlanta.
DeBono, E. (1968). New think: The use of lateral thinking in the generation of new ideas. New York:
Basic Books.
DeBono, E. (1 976). Teaching thinking. London: Temple Smith.
DeBono, E. (1977). Information processing and new ideas-lateral and vertical thinking. In
R B. Noller, A. M. Biondi, & S. J. Parnes (Eds.), Guide to creative action: Revised edition of
creative behavior guidebook. New York: Scribner's.
DeBono, E. (1985). Six thinking hats. Boston: Little-Brown.
DeBono, E. (1992). Serious thinking: Using the power of lateral thinking to create new ideas. New
York: HarperCollins.
De Lopez, R S. (1992 June). Promote thinking, say university leaders. The News, Mexico City,
p. B4.
Decyk, B. N. (1994). Using examples to teach concepts. In D. F. Halpern (Ed.), Changing college
classrooms: New teaching and learning strategies for an increasingly complex world (pp. 39-63).
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Dees, S. M., & Dansereau, D. F. (2000). TCU guide maps: A resource for counselors. Fort Worth,
TX: Texas Christian University, Institute of Behavioral Research.
deGroot, A. D. (1966). Perception and memory versus thought: Some old ideas and recent
findings. In B. Kleinmuntz (Ed), Problem solving: Research, method, and theory. New York:
Wiley. p. 1 14
deGroot, A. D. (1983). Heuristics, mental programs, and intelligence. In R Groner, M. Groner, &
W. F. Bischof (Eds), Methods of heuristics (pp. 109-129). Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associ­
ates.
Dewey, J. (1933). How we think: A restatement of the relation of reflective thinking to the educative
process. Boston: Heath.
Dews, S., & Winner, E. (1999). Obligatory processing of literal and nonliteral meanings in
verbal irony. Journal of Pragmatics, 3 1 (12), 1579-1599.
Diamond, R M. (1997). Curriculum reform needed if students are to master core concepts [Web
Pagel. URL http: / /chronicle.com/search97cgi/s97_cgi? [2000, December 28].
Donovan, J. J., & Radosevich, D. J. (1998). A meta-analytic review of the distribution of prac­
tice effect: Now you see it, now you don't. Journal ofApplied Psychology, 84, 795-805.
Doolittle, J. H. (1995). Using riddles and interactive computer games to teach problem
solving. In D. F. Halpern & S. C. Nummedal (Eds.), Psychologists teach critical thinking
[Special Issue]. Teaching of Psychology, 22, 33-36.
Dreman, D. (1979). Contrarian investment strategy: The psychology of the stock market success.
New York: Random House.
Driver, R, Newton, P., & Osborne, J. (2000). Establishing the norms of scientific argumenta­
tion in classrooms. Science Education, 84, 287-312.
Drosnin, M. (1997). The bible code. New York: Simon & Schuster.
438 REFERENCES

Drysdale, W. (1887). Proverbs for plymouth pulpit. New York: D. Appleton and Company.
Dunbar, K. (1998). Problem solving. In W. Bechtel (Ed.), A companion to cognitive science
(pp. 289-298). London: Blackwell.
Dunbar, K. (2001). The analogical paradox: Why analogy is so easy in naturalistic settings yet
so difficult in the psychological laboratory. In D. Gentner & K. Holyoak (Eds.), The analogi­
cal mind: Perspectives from cognitive science (pp. 313-334). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Duncan, C. P. (961). Attempts to influence performance on an insight problem. Psychological
Reports, 9, 35--42.
Duncker, K. (945). On problem solving. Psychological Monographs (Whole No. 270).
Eisenberger, R, & Cameron, J. (1998). Reward, intrinsic interest, and creativity: New findings.
American Psychologist, 53, 676--679.
Ekman, P. (992). Telling lies: Clues to deceit in the marketplace, politics and marriage. New York:
Norton.
Emery, G. (2001). Failed psychic predictions for 1 998: Psychic report card dubious once again [Web
Pagel . URL http: / /wysiwyg I I 17/www.csicop.org/article/psychic-predictions/l998.
html [2001, July 31.
Eylon, B. S., & Linn, M. C. (1988). Learning and instruction: An examination of four research
perspectives in science education. Review of Educational Research, 58(3), 251-30l .
Facione, P. (1991). Teaching and college-level critical thinking skills. Paper Presented at the 1 1 th
Annual International Conference on Critical Thinking and Educational Reform. Sonoma, CA.
Facione, P. A., Facione, N. c., & Giancarlo, C. A (2000). The disposition toward critical think­
ing: Its character, measurement, and relationship to critical thinking skill. Informal Logic,
200), 61-84.
Falls, C. (1943). Ordeal by battle. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ferguson, G. (1981). Architecture. In N. L. Smith (Ed.), Metaphors for evaluation: Sources of Ilew
methods. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Festinger, L. (1964). Conflict, decision and dissonance. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.
Feynman, R (1989). What do you care what other people think? New York: Bantam.
Finke, R A, Ward, T. B., & Smith, S. M. (1 992). Creative cognition: Theory, research, and applica­
tions. Cambridge, MA: Bradford.
Fischer, G. W., & Johnson, E. J. (1986). Behavioral decision theory and political decision
making. In R R Lau & D. O. Sears (Eds.), The 1 9th Annual Carnegie Symposium 011 Cognition:
Political Cognition (pp. 55--(5). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Fischer, S. c., & Spiker, V. A (2000). A framework for critical thinking research and training. (Re­
port Prepared for the U. S. Army Research Institute).
Fischhoff, B. (1975). Hindsight does not equal foresight: The effect of outcome knowledge on
judgment under uncertainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Per­
formance, 1 , 288-299.
Fischhoff, B. (1993). Controversies over risk: Psychological perspective on competence. Psy­
chological Science Agenda, 6, 8-9.
Fisher, R, & Ury, W. (1991). Getting to "yes": Negotiating agreement without giving in (2nd ed.).
New York: Penguin.
Fisher, R P. (1 995). Interviewing victims and witnesses of crime. Psychology, Public Policy, &
Law, 1 (4), 732-764.
Fiske, S. T., & Taylor, S. E. (1984). Social cognition. New York: Random House.
Fiske, S. T. (1993). Controlling other people: The impact of power on stereotyping. American
Psychologist, 48(6), 621--628.
Fixx, J. F. (1978). Solve it. New York: Doubleday.
Flannelly, L. T., & Flannelly, K. J. (2000). Reducing people's judgment bias about their level of
knowledge. Psychological Record, 50, 587--600.
Fletcher, M. (2000, March). Why crime is down in America. Milwaukee Sentinel, [retrieved
online at http:/ /www.jsonline.com/news/ editorials I marOO I fletcher26032500.asp 1.
Fogelin, R J. (1987). Understanding arguments, an introduction to informal logic (3rd ed.). New
York: Harcourt Brace.
REFERENCES 439

Fong, G. T., Krantz, D. H., & Nisbett, R. E. (1986). The effects of statistical training on thinking
about everyday problems. Cognitive Psychologist, 1 8(3), 253-292.
Fox, 1. 5., Marsh, G., & Crandall, J. c., Jr. (1983). The effect of college classroom experiences on for­
mal operational thinking. Paper presented at the 1983 Annual Convention of the Western
Psychological Association, San Francisco.
Frammolino, R. (1993 December). Most college GEDs fail simple tests, study finds. The Los
Angeles Times, pp. A41, A43.
Freud, S. (1930). Civilization and its discontents. Newark, DE: the Hogarth Press.
The Gallup Organization. (Americans' belief in psychic and paranormal phenomena is up over the
last decade [Web Pagel. URL http:/ /www.gallup.com/poll/releases/pr010608.asp). [2001,
July 31.
Gardner, H. (1983). Frames of mind: The theory of multiple intelligences. New York: Basic Books.
Gardner, H. (1985). The mind's new science: A history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic
Books.
Gardner, H. (1989). To open minds. New York: Basic Books.
Gardner, H., Krechevsky, M., Sternberg, R. J., & Okagaki, 1. (1 994). Intelligence in context: En­
hancing students' practical intelligence for school. In K. Mc Gilly (Ed.), Classroom Lessons:
Integrating cognitive theory and classroom practice (pp 1 05-127). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Garfield, J., & Ahlgren, A. (1988). Difficulties in learning basic concepts on probability and
statistics: Implications for research. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 1 9(1),
44-63.
Garnham, A., & Oakhill, J. (1994). Thinking and reasoning. Oxford, England: Blackwell.
Gazzaniga, M. S., Ivry, R. B., & Magnun, G. R. (1998). Cognitive neuroscience: The biology of the
mind. New York: Norton.
Geiselman, R. E., & Fisher, R. P. (1985, December). Interviewing victims and witnesses of
crime. Research in Brief, National Institute of Justice, 1--4.
Gentner, D., & Gentner, D. R. (1983). Flowing water or teeming crowds: Mental models of
electricity. In D. Gentner & A. 1. Stevens (Eds.), Mental models. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erl­
baum Associates.
Gentner, D., & Holyoak, K. J. (1997). Reasoning and learning by analogy: Introduction. Ameri­
can Psychologist, 52(1), 32-34.
Gerbner, G., Grass, 1., Morgan, M., & Signorielli, N. (1980). Violence profile No. 1 1 : Trends in
network television drama and viewer conceptions of social reality. Philadelphia: Annenberg
School of Communication.
Gervais, S., & Odean, T. (2001). Learning to be overconfident. The Review of Financial Studies,
14, 1-27.
Gibson, S. (2000). X-files and X-fictions. Skeptic, 8, 8-10.
Gick, M. 1., & Holyoak, K. J. (1980). Analogical problem solving. Cognitive Psychology, 1 2,
306-355.
Gifford-Jones, W. (1 977). What every woman should know about hysterectomy. New York: Funk &
Wagnalls.
Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. C. (1996). Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of
bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 1 03, 650-669.
Gigerenzer, G., & Hoffrage, U. (1995). How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruc­
tion. Psychological Review, 102, 684-704.
Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., & the ABC Research Group. (2000). Simple heuristics that make us
smart. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gilbreth, F. B. (1963). Cheaper by the dozen. New York: Crowell.
Gillette R. (1 987, December). Exotic ways to learn doubted by U.s. study. The Wall Street Jour­
nal, pp. 1 , 32.
Gilovich, T. (1991). How we know what isn't so: The fallibility of human reason in everyday life.
New York: Macmillan.
Glaser, R. (1984). Education and thinking: The role of knowledge. American Psychologist, 39(2),
93-104.
440 REFERENCES

Glaser, R (1992). Expert knowledge and processes of thinking. In D. F. Halpern (Ed.), Enhanc­
ing thinking skills in the sciences and mathematics (pp. 63-75, ix, 155). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Glucksberg, S., & Weisberg, R W. (1966). Verbal behavior and problem solving: Some effects
of labeling in a functional fixedness problem. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 71 (5),
659-664.
Godfrey, S. (2001). Are you creative? Glaxo Wellcome Newsletter, p. 1 .
Goertzel, T., & Goertzel, B . (1995). Linus Pauling: A life i n science and politics. New York: Basic
Books.
Goleman, D. ( 1 995). Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.
Gonzalez, M. A., Campos, A., & Perez, M. J. (1 997). Mental imagery and creative thinking.
Journal of Psychology, 131, 357-364.
Gordon, W. J. J. ( 1 961). Synectics. New York: Harper & Row.
Gordon, W. J. J. (1976). Metaphor and invention. In A. Rothenberg, & C R Hausman (Eds.),
.

The creativity question. Durham, NC: University Press.


Govier, T. (1985). A practical study of argument. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Gra£, P., & Komatsu, S. I. (1994). Process dissociation procedure: Handle with caution. Euro­
pean Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 6(2), 1 1 3-129.
Gray, W. (1991). Thinking critically about new age ideas. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Greenwald, A. G. (1992). New Look 3: Unconscious cognition reclaimed. American Psycholo­
gist, 47, 766-779.
Greenwald, A. G., Spangenberg, E. R, Pratkanis, A. R, & Eskenazi, J. ( 1 991 ). Double-blind
tests of subliminal self-help audiotapes. Psychological Science, 2(2), 1 1 9-122.
Guilford, J. P. (1 977). Way beyond the IQ. Buffalo, NY: Creative Education Foundation.
Gunther, M. ( 1977). The luck factor. New York: Macmillan.
Hadamard, L. (1954). The psychology of invention in the mathematical field. Princeton, NJ: Prince­
ton University Press.
Halpern, D. F. (1985). The influence of sex-role stereotypes on prose recall. Sex Roles, 12(3-4),
363-375.
Halpern, D. F. (1 987). Analogies as a critical thinking skill. In D. Berger, K. Peydek, &
W. Banks (Eds), Applications of cognitive psychology: Computing and education (pp. 75-86).
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Halpern, D. F. (1994). A national assessment of critical thinking skills in adults: Taking steps
toward the goal. In A. Greenwood (Ed.), The national assessment of college student learning:
Identification of the skills to be taught, learned, and assessed (pp. 24-64). Washington, DC: U. S.
Department of Education, National Center for Education Statistics.
Halpern, D. F. (Ed). (1 994). Changing college classrooms: New teaching and learning strategies for
an increasingly complex world. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Halpern, D. F. ( 1 995). The skewed logic of the bell-shaped curve. [Special Issue]. Race & IQ.
Skeptic, 3, 64-71 .
Halpern, D. F. (1 998). Teaching critical thinking for transfer across domains: Dispositions,
skills, structure training, and metacognitive monitoring. American Psychologist, 53, 449-455.
Halpern, D. F. (2000). Sex differences in cognitive abilities (3rd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum and Associates, Inc.
Halpern, D. F. (in press). Why wisdom? Educational Psychologist.
Halpern, D. F., & Blackman, S. ( 1 985). Magazines vs. physicians. The influence of information
source on intentions to use oral contraceptives. Women and Health, 1 0, 9-23.
Halpern, D. F., Blackman, S., & Salzman B. (1989). Using statistical risk information to assess
oral contraceptive safety. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 3, 251-260.
Halpern, D. F., & Collaer, M. L. (in press). Sex differences in visuospatial abilities: More than
meets the eye. In P. Shah & A. Miyak (Eds.), Higher-level visuospatial thinking and cognition.
Cambridge: MA: Cambridge University Press.
Halpern, D. F., Hansen, c., & Riefer, D. (1990). Analogies as an aid to understanding and
memory. Journal of Educational Psychology, 82(2), 298-305.
REFERENCES 44 1

Halpern, D. F., & Irwin, F. W. (1973). Selection of hypotheses as affected by their preference
values. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1 01 , 105-108.
Halpern, D. F., & Nummedal, S. G. (1995). Closing thoughts about helping students improve
how they think. Teaching of Psychology, 22(1), 82-83.
Hammond, K. R (1996). Human judgment and social policy: Irreducible uncertainty, inevitable
error, unavoidable injustice. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hanson, N. R (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Harman, G. (1986). Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Harris, R J. (1977). Comprehension of pragmatic implications in advertising. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 62(5), 603-608.
Harris, S. B. (1993). The resurrection myth in religion, science, and science fiction. Skeptic, 2,
50-59.
Hasher, L., & Zacks, R T. (1984). Automatic processing of fundamental information: The case
of frequency of occurrence. American Psychologist, 39(12), 1 372-1388.
Hastie, R, & Dawes, R (2001). Rational choice in an uncertain world: The psychology of judgment
and decision making. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Hastie, R, & Pennington, N. (2000). Explanation-based decision-making. In T. Connelly, Judg­
ment and decision making: An interdisciplinary reader. New York: Cambridge.
Hayes, J. R (1989). Cognitive processes in creativity. In J. A Glover, R R Ronning, & c. R
Reynolds (Eds.), Handbook of creativity (pp. 135-145). New York: Plenum.
Heiman, M., & Slomianko, J. (1986). Critical thinking skills. Washington, DC: National Educa­
tion Association.
Heit, E. (2000). Properties of inductive reasoning. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 7(4), 569-592.
Heller, R, Saltzstein, H. D., & Caspe, W. (1992). Heuristics in medical and non-medical deci­
sion-making. The Journal of Experimental Psychology, 211-235.
Henle, M. (1962). On the relation between logic and thinking. Psychological Review, 69,
366--378.
Hennessey, B. A, & Amabile, T. M. (1988). The conditions of creativity. In R J. Sternberg
(Ed.), The nature of creativity: Contemporary psychological perspectives (pp. 11-38). Cambridge,
MA: Cambridge University Press.
Herrmann, D. J., & Gruneberg, M. M. (1999). How to cure your memory failures. London: Blandford.
Herrnstein, R J., Nickerson, R S., de Sanchez, M., & Swets, J. A. (1986). Teaching thinking
skills. American Psychologist, 41, 1279-1289.
Herrnstein, R J., & Murray, C. A (1994). The bell curve: Intelligence and class structure in
American life. New York: The Free Press.
Hoffrage, u., Hertwig, R, & Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Hindsight bias: A by-product of knowl­
edge up-dating? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 26,
566--5 81.
Hogarth, R M. (1988). Judgment and choice: The psychology of decision. Chichester, England:
Wiley.
Holland, J. H., Holyoak, K. J., Nisbett, R E., & Thagard, P. R (1986). Induction: Processes of
inference, learning, and discovery, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Holley, C. D., Dansereau, D. F., McDonald, B. A, Garland, J. D., & Collins, K. W. (1979).
Evaluation of a hierarchical mapping technique as an aid to prose processing. Contempo­
rary Educational Psychology, 4(3), 227-237.
Holt, J. (1964). How children fail. New York: Dell.
Holt, J. (1989). Learning all the time. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Holyoak, K. J., & Simon, D. (1999). Bidirectional reasoning in decision making by constraint
satisfaction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 128, 3-3 1 .
Hostetler A J. (1988). Army eyes novel learning methods. The American Psychological Associa­
tion Monitor, 1 9, 7.
Huff, D. (1954). How to lie with statistics. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.
Hummel, J. E., & Holyoak, K. J. (1997). Distributed representations of structure: A theory of
analogical access and mapping. Psychological Review, 104, 427-466.
442 REFERENCES

Hunt, E . B. (1989). Cognitive science: Definition, status, and questions. Annual Review of Psy­
chology, 40, 603-629.
Hunt, E. B. (1995). Will we be smart enough ? A cognitive analysis of the coming workforce. New
York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Hunt, M. (1982). The universe within: A new science explores the human mind. New York: Simon &
Schuster.
Hutchings, P. (1986). Some late night thoughts on teaching creativity. American Association for
Higher Education, 39, 9-14.
Hyman, R. (2001). Australian Skeptics Guide to "Cold Reading" [Web Pagel. URL http: / / www.
skeptics.com.au/journal! coldread.htm [2002, January 201 .
Izawa, C. (1993). Efficient learning: The total time, exposure duration, frequency, and pro­
gramming of the study phase. In C. Izawa (Ed), Cognitive pSyc/lOlogy applied (pp. 15-42).
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Izawa, c., & Hayden, R. G. (1993). Race against time: Toward the principle of optimization in
learning and retention. In C. Izawa (Ed.), Cognitive psychology applied (pp. 15-41 ). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Jackson, S. E. (1996). The consequences of diversity in multidisciplinary work teams. In M. A
West (Ed.), Handbook of work group psychology (pp. 53-76). Chichester, England: Wiley.
Jacoby, L. L., Kelley, C. M., & Dywan, J. (1989). Memory attributions. In H. L. Roedinger III &
F. I. M. Craik (Eds), Varieties of memory and consciousness: Essays in honour of Endel Tulving
(pp. 391-422, xx, 445). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
James Randi Educational Foundation. (One Million Dollar Paranormal Challenge [Web Pagel.
URL http://www.randLorg/research/index.html [ [February 2, 2002]].
James Rogan Communications. (1993). Bits & Pieces, p. 7.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York: Holt.
Janis, I. L., & Mann, L. (1977). Decision making: A psychological analysis of conflict, choice, and
commitment. New York: The Free Press.
Jensen, A R. (1980). Bias in mental testing. New York: Free Press.
Jepson, c., Krantz, D. H., & Nisbett, R. E. (1993). Inductive reasoning: Competence or skill? In
R. E. Nisbett, Rules for reasoning (pp. 70-89). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., Legrenzi, P., & Legrenzi, M. S. (1972). Reasoning and a sense of reality.
British Journal of Psychology, 63(3), 395-400.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., & Wason, P. C. (1970). A theoretical analysis of insight into a reasoning
task. Cognitive Psychology, 1 (2), 134-148.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., & Wason, P. C. (1977). Thinking: Readings in cognitive science. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Johnson, M. K., & Raye, C. L. (1981) . Reality monitoring. Psychological Review, 88(1), 67-85.
Johnson, W. (1946). People in quandries: The semantics of personal judgement. New York: Harper &
Row Publishers.
Jones, E. A, Dougherty, B. c., Fantaske, P., & Hoffman, S. (1995). Identifying college graduates' essen­
tial skills in reading and problem-solving: Perspectives of faculty, employers and policymakers. (Con­
tract No. Rl17G1 0037 /CDFA84.117G.). University Park: U.S. Department of Education/OER!.
Jones, E. A., Hoffman, S., Moore, L. M., Ratcliff, G., Tibbetts, S., & Click, B. A (1995). National
assessment of college student learning: Identifying college graduates' essential skills in writing,
speech and listening, and critical thinking. (NCES 95--(01). Washington, DC: US. Government
Printing Office.
Juge, M. L. (2000 March). What's in a name? More than meets the eye. The Chronicle of Higher
Education, p. B4.
Kahane, H. (1980). Logic and contemporary rhetoric: The use of reason in everyday life (2nd ed.).
Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Kahane, H. (1992). Logic and contemporary rhetoric: The use of reason in everyday life (6th ed.).
Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A (1 973). On the psychology of prediction. Psychological Review,
80, 237-251 .
REFERENCES 443

Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk.
Econometrica, 47, 263-291 .
Kavanaugh, D. J . , & Bower, G. H. (1985). Mood and self-efficacy: Impact o f joy and sadness on
perceived capabilities. Cognitive Therapy & Research, 9, 507-525.
Kellogg, R. T. (1990). Effectiveness of prewriting strategies as a function of task demands.
American Journal of Psychology, 103(3), 327-342.
Keren, G., & Teigen, K. H. (2001). Why is p .90 better than p .70? Preference for definitive
= =

predictions by lay consumers of probability judgements. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 8,


191-202.
Kidd, v. (1991). An analysis of the California tobacco education campaign's visual anti-smok­
ing messages. Feedback, 32, 14-18.
Kim, W. c., & Mauborgne, R. (1999). Strategy, knowledge, innovation and the knowledge
economy. Sloan Management Review, 40, 41-54.
Kimble, G. A. (1978). How to use (and misuse) statistics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
King, A. (1989). Effects of self-questioning training on college students' comprehension of
lectures. Contemporary Educational Psychology, 14(4), 366-381 .
King, A. (1992). Facilitating elaborative learning through guided student-generated question­
ing. Educational Psychologist, 27(1), 1 1 1-126.
King, A. (1994). Inquiry as a tool to critical thinking. In D. F. Halpern (Ed), Changing college
classrooms: New teaching and learning strategies in an increasingly complex world (pp. 13-38).
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
King, P. M., & Kitchener, K. S. (1994). Developing reflective judgment: Understanding and
promoting intellectual growth and critical thinking in adolescents and adults. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Klaczynski, P. A. (1993). Reasoning schema effects on adolescent rule acquisition and transfer.
Journal of Educational Psychology, 85(4), 679-692.
Klaczynski, P. A, Gordon, D. H., & Fauth, J. (1997). Goal-oriented critical reasoning and indi­
vidual differences in critical reasoning biases. Journal of Educational Psychology, 89 (3),
470-485.
Klahr, D., & Simon, H. A. (2001). What have psychologists (and others) discovered about the
process of scientific discovery? Current Directions in Psychological Science, 1 0, 75-79.
Klauer, K. c., & Meiser, T. (2000). A source-monitoring analysis of illusory correlations. Per­
sonality & Social Psychology Bulletin, 26, 1074-1093.
Kneller, G. F. (1965). The art and science of creativity. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Knight, K., & Dansereau, D. F. (1992). Tools for drug and alcohol education: Using decision
worksheets in personal problem solving. Journal of Drug Education, 22(3), 261-271 .
Koestler, A. (1964). The act of creation. London: Hutchinson.
Kohler, W. (1969). The task of Gestalt psychology. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Koriat, A, Lichtenstein, S. F., & Fischhoff, B. (1980). Reasons for confidence. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 6, 107-1 18.
Kosonen, P., & Winne, P. H. (1995). Effects of teaching statistical laws on reasoning about
everyday problems. Journal of Educational Psychology, 87, 33-46.
Kronholm, M. M. (1993). The impact of a developmental instruction approach to environmental edu­
cation at the undergraduate level on reflective judgment. Unpublished doctoral dissertation,
Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, IL.
Kruglanski, A. W. (1992). On methods of good judgment and good methods of judgment.
Political Psychology, 13, 455-475.
Kuhn, D., Weinstock, M., & Flaton, R. (1994). How well do jurors reason? Competence dimen­
sions of individual variation in a juror reasoning task. Psychological Science, S, 289-296.
Kuhn, D. (1993, January). Connecting scientific and informal reasoning. Merrill-Palmer Quar­
terly, pp. 74-103.
Kuhn, D. (2001). How do people know? Psychological Science, 1 2(1), 1-8.
La Place, M. (1951). A philosophical essay on probabilities (exact wording varies by translation).
New York: Dover Publications, Inc.
444 REFERENCES

La Rochefoucauld. (1959). The maxims of La Rouchefoucauld. Louis Kronenberger (Trans.).


New York: Random House.
LaBine, S. J., & LaBine, G. (1996). Determination of negligence and hindsight bias. Law &
Human Behavior, 20, 501-516.
Langer, E. J. (1989). Mindfulness. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co.
Langer, E. (1994, July). Improving the quality of thinking in a changing world. Paper presented at
the Sixth International Conference on Thinking. Cambridge, MA
Langer, E. J. (2000). Mindful learning. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 9, 220-223.
Langer, E. J., Blank, A, & Chanowitz, B. (1978). The mindlessness of ostensibly thoughtful ac­
tion: The role of "placebic" information in interpersonal interaction. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 36, 635-642.
Larrick, R. P., Morgan, J. N., & Nisbett, R. E. (1990). Teaching the use of cost-benefit reasoning
in everyday life. Psychological Science, 1 , 362-370.
Larson, C. F. (2001). Management for the new millennium-the challenge of change. Research
Technology Management, 6, 1 0-12.
Lawson, T. J. (1999). Assessing psychological critical thinking as a learning outcome for psy­
chology majors. Teaching of Psychology, 26, 207-209.
Leedy, P. D. (1981). How to read research and understand it. New York: Macmillan.
Lehman, D. R., Lempert, R. 0., & Nisbett, R. E. (1988). The effects of graduate training on rea­
soning: Formal diScipline and thinking about everyday-life events. American Psychologist,
43(6), 431-442.
Leive, C. (1994). Miss America. Glamour, pp. 234-237, 275-281 .
Leming, J . S . (1998). Some critical thoughts about the teaching of critical thinking. Social Stud­
ies, 89(2), 61-66.
Lenski, S. D. (2001). Intertextual connections during discussions about literature. Reading Psy-
chology, 22, 313-335.
Levi, D. S. (1991). Critical thinking and logic. Salem, MI: Sheffield.
Levine, M. (1994). Effective problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Lewis, A B., & Mayer, R. E. (1987). Students' misconceptions of relational statements in arith­
metic word problems. Journal of Educational Psychology, 79, 363-371 .
Lichtenstein, S., Slovic, P., Fischoff, B., Layman, M., & Combs, B. (1978). Judged frequency of
lethal events. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning & Memory, 4(6), 551-578.
Lilienfeld, S. 0., Wood, J. M., & Garb, H. N. (2000). The scientific status of projective tech­
niques. Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 1 , 27-66.
Lithner, J. (2000). Mathematical reasoning and familiar procedures. International Journal of
Mathematical Education in Science & Technology, 31, 83-96.
Loftus, E. F. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 560-572.
Loftus, E. F. (1979). Eyewitness testimony. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Loftus, E. F. (1993). The reality of repressed memories. American Psychologist, 48(5), 518-537.
Loftus, G. R., & Loftus, E. F. (1982). Essence of statistics. Monteray, CA: Brooks/Cole.
Lopes, L. L. (1982). Doing the impossible: A note on induction and the experience of random­
ness. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 8(6), 626-636.
Lorayne, H. (1 975). Remembering people. New York: Stein & Day.
Lorayne, H., & Lucas, J. (1974). The memory book. New York: Stein & Day (Also published in
paperback by Ballantine Books, 1975).
Lord, c., Ross, L., & Lepper, M. (1979). Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The ef­
fects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 3 7, 2098-2109.
Lovett, M. c., & Greenhouse, J. B. (2000). Applying cognitive theory to statistics instruction.
The American Statistician, 54, 196-209.
Lovett, M. c., & Schunn, C. D. (1999). Task representations, strategy variability, and base-rate
neglect. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 1 2 8(2) , 1 07-130.
Lowenfeld, V. (1962). Creativity: Education's stepchild. In S. J. Parnes & H. F. Harding (Eds.),
A source book from creative thinking. New York: Scribner's.
REFERENCES 445

Macmillan Publishers. ( 1 989). Macmillan dictionary of quotations. New York: Author.


Maier, N. R. F. (1931). Reasoning in humans II: The solution of a problem and its appearance
in consciousness. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 12, 1 81-194.
Mann, L. (1972). Use of a ''balance sheet" procedure to improve the quality of personal deci­
sion making: A field experiment with college applicants. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 2,
291-300.
Marsh, J. G., & Shapira, Z. (1982). Behavioral decision theory and organizational decision
theory. In G. R. Ungson, & D. N. Braunstein (Eds.), Decision making: An interdisciplinary
inquiry. Boston, MA: Kent.
Martin, P. (2001 July). Life after the myth. Financial Times, p. 1 0.
Mather, M., Shafir, E., & Johnson, M. K. (2000). Misremembrance of options past: Source mon-
itoring and choice. Psychological Science, 1 1 , 132-138.
Matlin, M. (2002). Cognition (5th ed.). Orlando, FL: Harcourt College Publishers.
Mayer, R. E. ( 1 987). Educational psychology: A cognitive approach. Boston: Little, Brown.
Mayer, R. E. (in press). Cognitive theory and the design of multimedia instruction: An exam­
ple of the two-way street between cognition and instruction. In D. F. Halpern & M. G.
Hakel (Eds.), From theory to practice: Applying the science of learning to the university and
beyond. New directions for teaching and learning. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Mazzoni, G. A L., Loftus, E. F., Seitz, A, & Lynn, S. J. ( 1 999). Changing beliefs and memories
through dream interpretation. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 1 3(2), 125-144.
McCormick, C. B., & Levin J. R. (1987). Mnemonic prose-learning strategies. In M. A
McDaniel & M. Pressley (Eds), Imagery and related mnemonic processes (pp. 392-406).
New York: Springer-Verlag.
McFadzean, E. (2000). Techniques to enhance creative thinking. Team Performance Manage­
ment, 6, 62-72.
McGuire, W. J. (1981). The probabilogical model of cognitive structure and attitude change. In
R. E. Petty, T. M. Ostrom, & T. C. Brock (Eds.), Cognitive responses in persuasion (pp.
392-406). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
McGuire, W. J. (1997). Creative hypothesis generating in psychology: Some useful heuristics.
Annual Reviews of Psychology, 48, 1 -30.
McHardy, P., & Allan, T. (2000). Closing the gap between what industry needs and what HE
provides. Education and Training, 42, 496-508.
McKay, B., Bar-Natan, D., & Kalai, G. (1999). Solving the bible code puzzle. Statistical Science,
14, 150.
McKeachie, W. J. (1992). Update: Teaching thinking. In D. J. Stroup & R. Allen (Eds.), Critical
thinking: A collection of readings. Dubuque, IA: Brown.
McKinnon, J. W., & Renner, J. W. (1971). Are colleges concerned with intellectual develop­
ment? American Journal of Psychology, 39, 1 047-1052.
Mednick, S. A, & Mednick, M. T. ( 1 967). Remote associates test: Examiners manual. Boston:
Houghton Mifflin.
Mehrabian, A (2000). Beyond IQ: Broad-based measurement of individual success potential
or "emotional intelligence." Genetic, Social, & General Psychology Monographs, 126(2),
1 33-239.
Merron, K., Fisher, D., & Torbet, W. R. ( 1987). Meaning making and management action.
Groups & Organizational Studies, 12, 274-286.
Meyer, B. ]. F., & Poon, L. W. (2001). Effects of structure strategy training and signaling on re-
call of text. Journal of Educational Psychology, 93(1), 141-159.
Miller, J. E., Jr. (1972). Words, self, reality: The rhetoric of imagination. New York: Dodd, Mead.
Milne, A A ( 1 926). Winnie the Pooh. New York: Dutton.
Morgan, J. J. B., & Morton, J. T. (1944). The distortion of syllogistic reasoning produced by
personal convictions. Journal of Social Psychology, 20, 39-59.
Moss, J. (1950). How to win at poker. Garden City, NY: Garden City Books.
Mumford, M. D., & Gustafson, S. B. (1988). Creativity syndrome: Integration, application, and
innovation. Psychological Bulletin, 1 03, 27-43.
446 REFERENCES

Munby, H. (1982). Science in the schools. Toronto: University of Toronto.


Munson, R (1976). The way of words. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (2000). The use of category and exemplar knowledge in the solu­
tion of anchoring tasks. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 78(6), 1038-1052.
Myers, D. G. (1 995). Psychology. New York: Worth.
Mynatt, C. R, Doherty, M. E., & Tweney, R D. (1978). Consequences of confirmation and dis­
confirmation in a simulated research environment. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psy­
chology, 30(3), 395-406.
Nakamura, J., & Csikszentmihalyi, M. (2001). Catalytic creativity: The case of Linus Pauling.
American Psychologist, 56, 337-341 .
National Commission o n Excellence i n Education. (1983). A nation at risk: The imperative for
educational reform. Washington, DC: Author.
National Education Goals Panel. (1991). The national education goals report: Building a nation of
learners. Washington, DC: U. S. Printing Office.
National Research Council. (1994). Learning, remembering, and believing: Enhancing human per­
formance. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Neisser, U. (1982). Memory observed: Remembering in natural contexts. San Francisco: Freeman.
Neisser, U., Boodoo, G., Bouchard, T. J. J., Boykin, A W., Brody, N., Ceci, S. J., Halpern, D. F.,
Loehlin, J. c., Perloff, R, Sternberg, R J., & Urbina, S. (1996). Intelligence: Knowns and un­
knowns. American Psychologist, 51 (2), 77-101.
Nelson, G. P. (1998 April). You don't have to be a rocket scientist to think like one. Star Tri­
bune, p. A14.
Nelson, T. 0. ( 1 996). Consciousness and metacognition. American Psychologist, 51, 102-1 16.
Nelson, T. 0., & Narens, L. (1990). Metamemory: A theoretical framework and new findings.
The Psychology of Learning and Motivation, 26, 125-141 .
Neubert, G. A, & Binko, J. B. (1992). Inductive reasoning in the secondary classroom. Washington,
DC: NEA Professional Library, National Education Association.
Newell, A. (1983). The heuristic of George Polya and its relation to artificial intelligence. In
M. G. R Groner, & W.F. Bischof (Eds.), Methods of heuristics (pp. 195-243). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Newell, A, & Simon, H. A (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice­
Hall.
Nickerson, R S. (1987). Why teach thinking? In J. B. Baron, & R J. Sternberg (Eds), Teaching
thinking skills: Theory and practice (pp. 27-37). New York: Freeman.
Nickerson, R S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review
of General Psychology, 2(2), 1 75-220.
Nickerson, R S. (1986). Reflections on reasoning. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Nickerson, R S., & Adams, M. J. (1979). Long-term memory for a common object, Cognitive
Psychology, 1 1 , 287-307.
Nisbett, R E. (1993). Rules for reasoning. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Nixon, R M. (1962). Six crises. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Norman, D. A (1976). Memory and attention: An introduction to human information processing.
New York: Wiley.
Norman, D. A (1988). The psychology of everyday things. New York: Basic Books.
Norris, S. P. (1992). The generalizability of critical thinking: Multiple perspectives on an educational
ideal. New York: Teachers College Press.
Norris, S. P., & Ennis, R H. (1989). Evaluating critical thinking. Pacific Grove, CA: Critical
Thinking Press & Software.
Noveck, I. A., & Politzer, G. (1998). Leveling the playing field: Investigating competing claims
concerning relative inference difficulty. In M. D. S. Braine & D. P. O'Brien (Eds.) Mental
logic (pp. 367-384). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Nutrition Action Health Letter (1991, July / Aug). Eater's Digest, p. 13.
O'Loughlin, A. & McFadzean, M. E. (1999). Toward a holistic theory of strategic problem
solving. Team Performance Management, 5, 103-120.
REFERENCES 447

Oliver, P. (2001). Diagrammatic reasoning: An artificial intelligence perspective. Artificial


Intelligence Review, 1 5, 63-78.
Oppenheimer, J. R (1956). Analogy in science. American Psychologist, 1 1 , 1 27-135.
Ortho Pharmaceutical Group. (1979). The pill-After your doctor prescribes . . . Raritan, NJ: Author.
Orwell, G. (1949). 1 984. New York: Harcourt, Brace.
Osborn, A. F. (1963). Applied imagination: Principles and procedures of creative problem solving.
New York: Scribner's.
Osgood, C. E. (1953). Method and theory in experimental psychology. New York: Oxford Univer­
sity Press.
Oskamp, S. (1953). Method and theory in experimental psychology. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Overskeid, G. (2000). The slave of the passions: Experiencing problems and selecting solu­
tions. Review of General Psychology, 4(3), 284-309.
Paas, F. G. (1992). Training strategies for attaining transfer of problem-solving skill in statis­
tics: A cognitive-load approach. Journal of Educational Psychology, 84, 429-434.
Palincsar, A. S., & Brown, A. 1. (1984). Reciprocal-teaching of comprehension-monitoring
activities. Cognition and Instruction, 1 , 1 1 7-175.
Papanek, V. J. (1977). Tree of life: Bionics. In S. J. Parnes, R B. Noller, & A. M. Biondi (Eds.),
Guide to creative action: Revised edition of creative behavior guidebook. New York: Scribner's.
Parducci, A. (1968). The relativism of absolute judgments. Scientific American, 2 1 9 (6), 84-90.
Park, D. C. (1992). Applied cognitive aging research. In F. I. M. Craik & T. A. Salthouse (Eds.),
The handbook of aging and cognition (pp. 449-493). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Parnes, S. J. (1967). Creative behavior workbook. New York: Scribner's.
Parnes, S. J., Noller, R B., & Biondi, A. M. (1977). Guide to creative action: Revised edition of cre­
ative behavior guidebook. New York: Scribner's.
Patterson, M. E., Dansereau, D. F., & Wiegmann, D. A. (1993). Receiving information during a
cooperative episode: Effects of communication aids and verbal ability. Learning & Individ­
ual Differences, 5(1), 1-1 1 .
Paulos, J . A . (1994). Commentary: Counting o n dyscalculia. Discovery, 30-36.
Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R, & Johnson, E. J. (1993). The adaptive decision maker. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Peck, J. (1986). Not killing is a crime? In B. Lown & E. Chazov (Eds.), Peace: A dream unfolding
(p. 146). Ontario, Canada: Sommerville House Books Ltd.
Pedone, R, Hummel, J. E., & Holyoak, K. J. (2001). The use of diagrams in analogical problem
solving. Memory & Cognition, 29, 214-22l .
Pellegrino, J. W., & Goldman, S. R (1983). Developmental and individual differences in ver­
bal and spatial reasoning. In R F. Dillon & R R Schmeck (Eds.), Individual differences in
cognition (pp. 137-180). New York: Academic.
Pence, G. E. (2001, January). Setting a common, careful policy for bioethics. The Chronicle of
Higher Education, p. 20.
Perfetto, G. A., Bransford, J. D., & Franks, J. J. (1983). Constraints on access in a problem solv­
ing context. Memory & Cognition, 77, 562-57l.
Perkins, D. N. (1988). Creativity and the quest for mechanism. In R J. Sternberg & E. E. Smith
(Eds.), Psychology of human thought. New York: Cambridge.
Perkins, D. N. (1985). Postprimary education has little impact on informal reasoning. Journal
of Educational Psychology, 77, 562-57l.
Perkins, D. N., & Grotzer, T. A. (1997). Teaching intelligence. American Psychologist, 52(10),
1125-1133.
Pinkley, R L., & Northcraft, G. B. (2000). Get paid what you're worth: The expert negotiator's guide
to salary and compensation. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Pitt, J., & Leavenworth, R (1968). Logic for argument. New York: Random House.
Pogrow, S. (1992). A validated approach to thinking development for at-risk populations.
In C. Collins & J. Mangieri (Eds), Teaching thinking: An agenda for the twenty-first century
(pp. 87-101). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
448 REFERENCES

Poincare, H. (1929). The foundations of science. New York: Science House.


Polya, G. (1945). How to solve it: A new aspect of mathematical method. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Polya, G. (1957). How to solve it: A new aspect of mathematical method. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Polya, G. (1981). Mathematical discovery (Combined ed.). New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Posner, M. 1. (1973). Cognition: An introduction. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman.
Postman, N., & Powers, S. (1992). How to watch TV news. New York: Penguin.
Potts, G. R (1 972). Information processing strategies used in the encoding of linear orderings.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1 1, 727-740.
Powell, D. (1985). The wisdom of a novel: A dictionary of quotations. New York: Garland.
Pratkanis, A. R, & Aronson, E. (1 992). Age of propaganda: The everyday use and abuse of persua­
sion. New York: W. H. Freeman.
Prince, G. M. (1 970). The practice of creativity. New York: Harper.
Quattrone, G. A., & Jones, E. E. (1980). The perception of variability within in-groups and out­
groups: Implications for the law of small numbers. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol­
ogy, 38, 141-152.
The Quoteaholic. Gali/eo [Web PageJ. URL www.quoteaholic.com [2002, January 15-201.
Raia, E. (1994, June 2), Russian style. Purchasing, pp. 28-29.
RAND Corporation. (1992). Health care and the uninsured: Who will pay? RAND Research Re­
view, XVI, 6-8.
Raphael, B. (1976). The thinking computer: Mind inside matter. San Francisco: Freeman.
Reber, P. J., & Kotovsky, K. (1997). Implicit learning in problem solving: The role of working
memory capacity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 126(2), 1 78-203.
Regents of the University of California. How much information? [Web Pagel. URL
http://www.sims.berkeley.edu/how-much-info/ [2001, January 301 .
Reisberg, D. (2001). Cognition. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.
Renshon, S. A. (1992). The psychology of good judgment: A preliminary model with some ap­
plications to the Gulf War. Political Psychology, 13, 477-495.
Resnick, L. B. (1985). Cognition and instruction: Recent theories of human competence. Psy­
chology and Learning (pp. 1 27-186, 243).
Restak, R M. (1988). The mind. New York: Bantam Books.
The Review. Science and Pseudoscience Review in Mental Health [Web Pagel. URL
http: / /www.pseudoscience.org/ definitions-pseudo.html [1920J.
Reyes, R M., Thompson, W. c., & Bower, G. H. (1980). Judgmental biases resulting from dif­
fering availabilities of arguments. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 39(1), 2-12.
Rhoads, K. (1997). What's in a frame? [Web Pagel. URL www.influenceatwork.com [2002,
February 10].
Rips, L. J. (1988). Deduction. In R J. Sternberg & E. E. Smith (Eds.), The psychology of human
thought (pp. 1 1 6-152). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rips, L. J. (2001). Two kinds of reasoning. Psychological Science, 12, 129-134.
Rittle-Johnson, B., & Alibali, M. W. (1999). Conceptual and procedural knowledge of mathe­
matics: Does one lead to the other? Journal of Educational Psychology, 91(1), 1 75-189.
Roediger, H. L. (1990). Implicit memory: Retention without remembering. American Psycholo­
gist, 45(9), 1 043-1056.
Roediger, H. L. 1., & Bergman, E. T. (1998). The controversy over recovered memories. Psy­
chology, Public Policy, & Law, 4(4), 1091-1109.
Rokeach, M. (1960). The open and closed mind: Investigations into the nature of belief systems and
personality systems. New York, Basic Books.
Rosch, E . (1977). Human categorization. In N. Warren (Ed.), Studies in cross-cultural psychology
(Vol. 1). New York: Academic Press.
Rosenthal, R, & Fode, K. L. (1 963). The effect of experimental bias on the performance of the
albino rat. Behavioral Science, 8, 183-187.
Ross, J., & Laurence, K. A. (1968). Some observations on memory artifice. Psychonomic Science,
13(2), 107-108.
REFERENCES 449

Rothenberg, A (1979). The emerging goddess: The creative process in art, science, and other fields.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rubinstein, M. F., & Pfeiffer, K. R (1980). Concepts in problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall.
Ryan, M. (2001). Top 10 ideas of marketing. Advertising Age, 72, 6-8.
Sadler, W. A Jr., & Whimbey A (1985). A holistic approach to improving thinking skills. Phi
Delta Kappa, 67, 199-202.
Salovey, P., & Sluyter, D. J. (1997). Emotional development and emotional intelligence: Educational
implications. New York: Basic Books.
Sapir, E. (1960). Culture, language and personality. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Schacter, D. L. (1999). The seven sins of memory: Insights from psychology and cognitive
neuroscience. American Psychologist, 54(3), 182-203.
Schafly, P. (1993 July). A mental health care nightmare. The Washington Times, p. G4.
Schauble, L., & Glaser, R (1990). Scientific thinking in children and adults. In D. Kuhn (Series
Ed., Vol. Ed.), Contributions to human development: Vol. 2 1 . Developmental perspectives on
teaching and learning thinking skills (pp. 9-27). New York: Basel, Karger.
Schmidt, H. G., Peeck, V. H., Paas, F., & van Breukelen, G. J. P. (2000). Remembering the street
names of one's childhood neighbourhood: A study of very long-term retention. Memory,
8(1), 37-49.
Schmolck, H., Buffalo, E. A, & Squire, L. R (2000). Memory distortions develop over time:
Recollections of the O.J. Simpson trial verdict after 15 and 32 months. Psychological Science,
1 1 (1), 39-45.
Schoenfeld, A H. (1979). Can heuristics be taught? In J. Lochhead & J. Clement (Eds.), Cogni­
tive process instruction: Research on teaching skills, Philadelphia: Franklin Institute Press.
Schoenfeld, A H. (1985). Mathematical problem solving. Orlando, FL: Academic Press.
Schoenfeld, A H., & Herrmann, D. J. (1982). Problem perception and knowledge structure in
expert and novice mathematical problem solvers. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learn­
ing, Memory, & Cognition, 8(5), 484-494.
Science in the Public Interest. (2000). Bar exams: Energy bars flunk. Nutrition Action Health
Letter, 27, 10-12.
Scriven, M. (1976). Reasoning. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Seamon, J. G., Williams, P. c., Crowley, M. J., Kim, I. J., Langer, S. A., Orner, P. J., &
Wishengrad, D. L. (1995). The mere exposure effect is based on implicit memory: Effects
of stimulus type, encoding conditions, and number of exposures on recognition and affect
judgments. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 21, 711-721 .
Sears, A, & Parsons, J. (1991). Towards critical thinking as an ethic. Theory and Research in
Social Education, 1 9(1), 45-68.
Seech, Z. (1993). Open minds and everyday reasoning. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Seligman, M. (1991). Learned optimism. New York: Knopf.
Sethi, R, Smith, D. c., & Park, C. W. (2001). Cross-functional product development teams,
creativity, and the innovativeness of new consumer products. Journal of Marketing Research,
38, 73-85.
Shaklee, H. (1987). Estimating cumulative risk: Flood and contraceptive failure. Twenty-Eighth
Annual Meeting of the Psychonomic Society, Seattle, WA
Shalley, C. E. (1991). Effects of productivity goals, creativity goals, and personal discretion on
individual creativity. Journal of Applied Psychology, 7(2), 179-185.
Shaver, K. G. (1981). Principles ofsocial psychology. Cambridge, MA: Winthrop.
Shavinina, L. V. (2001). A new wave of innovations in psychology: High intellectual and cre­
ative education multimedia technologies. Review of General Psychology, 5, 291-315.
Shermer, M. (1992). Anecdotes do not make a science: The skeptics reply. Skeptic, 1, 1 8--1 9.
Shermer, M. (1 997). Why people believe weird things: Pseudoscience, superstition, and other confu­
sions of our time. New York: W. H. Freeman.
Shubik, M. (1971). The dollar auction game: A paradox in noncooperative behavior and esca­
lation. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 15, 109-1 1 1 .
450 REFERENCES

Shuman, D. W., & Champagne, A. (1998). Removing the people from the legal process: The
rhetoric and research on judicial selection and juries. Psychology, Public Policy, & Law,
3(2-3), 242-258.
Siegal, E. (1991, May). Persuasion and decision-making. APS Observer, p. 8.
Simon, H. A. (1977). The psychology of scientific problem solving. In H.A. Simon (Ed.), Mod­
els of discovery. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D.Reidel.
Simon, H. A., & Kaplan, C. A. (1989). Foundations of cognitive science. In I. Posner (Ed.),
Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 1-47). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Simonson, I., Nowlis, S. M., & Simonson, Y. (1993). The effect of irrelevant preference argu-
ments on consumer choice. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 2, 287-306.
Singer, B., & Benassi, V. A. (1981). Occult beliefs. American Scientist, 69, 49-55.
Slovic, P. (1987). Perception of risk. Science, 236, 280-285.
Slovic, P., Fischhoff, B., & Lichtenstein, S. (1986). Knowing with certainty: The appropriate­
ness of extreme confidence. In H. Arkes & K. R. Hammond, Judgement and decision making:
An interdisciplinary reader (pp. 397-416). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Smedslund, J. (1963). The concept of correlation in adults. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology,
44, 165-173.
Smith, L. (1992, June). Rick's place revisited. The Los Angeles Times, p. AI.
Smith, M. U. (1 988). Successful and unsuccessful problem solving in classical genetic pedi­
grees. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 25(6), 41 1-433.
Smith, S. M., & Blankenship, S. E. (1991 ). Incubation and the persistence of fixation in prob­
lem solving. American Journal of Psychology, 104(1), 61-87.
Snyder, M., & Uranowitz, S. W. (1978). Reconstructing the past: Some cognitive consequences
of person perception. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 36(9), 941-950.
Soler, M. J., & Ruiz, J. C. (2000). The spontaneous use of memory aids at different educational
levels. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 1 0, 41-5I .
Solorzano, L. (1985). Think! Now schools are teaching how. U.S. News & World Report.
Sorensen, T. C. (1965). Kennedy. New York: Harper & Row.
Spellman, B. A., & Holyoak, K. J. (1992). If Saddam is Hitler then who is George Bush? Ana­
logical mapping between systems of social roles. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology,
62(6), 913-933.
Stahl, N. N., & Stahl, R. J. (1991). We can agree after all! Achieving consensus on critical think­
ing using the delphi technique. Roeper Review, 1 4(2), 79-88.
Stanovich, K. E. (1999). Studies of individual differences in reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (1999). Discrepancies between normative and descriptive mod­
els of decision making and the understanding/acceptance principle. Cognitive Psychology,
38(3), 349-385.
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (1997). Reasoning independently of prior belief and individual
differences in actively open-minded thinking. Journal of Educational Psychology, 89(2), 342-357.
Steinem, G. (1994). Moving beyond words. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Sternberg, R. J. (1 977). Component processes in analogical reasoning. Psychological Review, 84,
353-373.
Sternberg, R. J. (1982). Who's intelligent? Psychology Today, 1 6, 30-33, 35-39.
Sternberg, R. J. (1 992). Ability tests, measurement and markets. Journal of Educational Psychol­
ogy, 84, 134-140.
Sternberg, R. J. (1999). The theory of successful intelligence. Review of General Psychology, 3(4),
292-316.
Sternberg, R. J. (in press). Why schools should teach for wisdom: The balance theory of
wisdom in educational settings. Educational Psychologist.
Sternberg, R. J., & Lubart, T. I. (1995). Defying the crowd: Cultivating creativity in a culture of
conformity. New York: Free Press.
Sternberg, R. J., & Lubart, T. 1. (1 996). Investing in creativity. American Psychologist, 51,
677-688.
REFERENCES 45 1

Sternberg, R J., & O'Hara, A. (1999). Creativity and intelligence. In R J. Sternberg (Ed.), Hand­
book of creativity (pp. 251-272). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sternberg, R J., & Weil, E. M. (1980). An aptitude strategy interaction in linear syllogistic rea­
soning. Journal of Educational Psychology, 72(2), 226-239.
Sternberg, R J., & Williams, W. (1997). Does the graduate record examination predict mean­
ingful success in the graduate training of psychologists? A case study. American Psycholo­
gist, 52, 630-641 .
Stewart, J. K. (1985). From the director. National Institute of Justice: Research in brief. Washing­
ton, DC: US Department of Justice.
Swanson, H. L. (1990). Influence of metacognitive knowledge and aptitude on problem solv­
ing. Journal of Educational Psychology, 82 (2), 306-314.
Taplin, J. E., & Staudenmayer, H. (1973). Interpretation of abstract conditional sentences in
deductive reasoning. Journal of Verbal Learning & Verbal Behavior, 12 (5), 530-542.
Tate, M. A., & Alexander, J. (1996). Teaching critical evaluation skills for World Wide Web re­
sources. Computers in Libraries, 1 6, 49-52.
Teger, A. 1. (1979). Too much invested to quit: The psychology of escalation of conflict. New York:
Pergamon.
Tetlock, P. E. (1 994). The psychology of futurology and the future of psychology. Psychological
Science, 5, 1-4.
Texas Library Association. Knowledge is Power [Web Pagel. URL http://www.txla.org/groups/
godort/kip-award.html [2002, January 291.
Time. (1998, June 1 ). Sounds like, smells like, feels like, p. 25.
Timnick, Lois. (1989). McMartin defense urges jury to end years of 'vile allegations' [Web Pagel.
URL www.latimes.com [2002, January 15-20021.
Toulmin, S., Rieke, R, & Janik, A. (1979). An introduction of reasoning. New York: Macmillan.
Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving & W. Donaldson (Eds), Or­
ganization of memory. New York: Academic Press.
Tutu, D. (1986). How to eat an elephant. In B. Lown & E. Chazov (Eds.), Peace: A dream unfold­
ing (p. 216). New York: Academic Press.
Tversky, A. (1972). Elimination by aspects. A theory of choice. Psychological Review, 79,
281-299.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1971). Belief in the law of small numbers. Psychological Bulletin,
76, 104-1 10.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction
fallacy in probability judgement. Psychological Review, 90, 293-315.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice.
Science, 211, 453-458.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Sci­
ence, 185, 1 1 24-1 131.
Tversky, B. (1973). Encoding processes in recognition and recall. Cognitive Psychology, S, 275-287.
Tweney, R. D., & Chitwood, S. T. (1995). Scientific reasoning. In S. E. Newstead & J. s. B. T.
Evans (Eds.), Perspectives on thinking and reasoning: Essays in honour of Peter Wason
(pp. 241-260). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Van Haneghan, J., Barron, L., Young, M., Williams, S., Vye, N., & Bransford, J. (1992).
The "jasper" series: An experiment with new ways to enhance mathematical thinking.
In D. F. Halpern (Ed.), Enhancing thinking skills in the sciences and mathematics (pp. 15-38, ix,
155). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
VanLehn, K. (1989). Problem solving and cognitive skill acquisition. In M. Posner (Ed.), The
foundations of cognitive science (pp. 527-580). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Vaughan, J. L. (1984). Concept structuring: The technique and empirical evidence, In C. D.
Holley & D. F. Dansereau (Eds.), Spatial learning strategies: Techniques, applications, and
related issues (pp. 127-147). New York: Academic Press.
Vernon, P. (1 970). Creativity: Selected readings. Harmondsworth, England: Penguin.
von Oech, R (1983). A whack on the side of the head. New York: Warner Books.
452 REFERENCES

Vosniadou, S., & Orotony, A (Eds). (1989). Similarity and analogical reasoning. Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1 978). Mind in society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wales, C. E., & Nardi, A (1984). Successful decision-making. Morgantown, WV: Center for
Guided Design.
Walsh, J. (1981) . A plenipotentiary for human intelligence. Science, 214, 640-641 .
Wandersman, A H., & Hallman, W. K. (1993). Are people acting irrationally? Understanding
public concerns about environmental threats. American Psychologist, 48, 681-686.
Wang, P. (1994). How to retire with twice as much money. Money, pp. 77-84.
Wanous, J. P. (1973). Effects of a realistic job preview on job acceptance, job attitudes, and job
survival. Journal ofApplied Psychology, 58, 327-332.
Wason, P. C. (1968). On the failure to eliminate hypotheses: A second look. In P. C. Wason &
P. N. Johnson-Laird (Eds.), Thinking and reasoning. Baltimore: Penguin.
Wason, P. C. (1960). On the failure to eliminate hypotheses in a conceptual task. Quarterly
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 1 2 , 129-140.
Wason, P. C. (1969). Structure simplicity and psychological complexity. Bulletin of the British
Psychological Society, 22, 281-284.
Weber, R. J., & Perkins, D. N. (Eds.). (1992). Inventive minds: Creativity in technology. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Wegner, D. M., Wenzlaff, R., Kerker, R. M., & Beattie, A E. (1981) . Incrimination through in­
nuendo: Can media questions become public answers? Journal of Personality & Social Psy­
chology, 40 (5) , 822-832.
Weisberg, R. W. (1 988). Problem solving and creativity. In R. J Sternberg (Ed.), The nature of
creativity: Contemporary psychological persepctives (pp. 148-177). New York: Cambridge Uni­
versity Press.
Weisberg, R. W. (1993). Creativity: Beyond the myth ofgenius. New York: Freeman.
Weisberg, R., Dicamillo, M., & Phillips, D. (1978). Transferring old associations to new situa-
tions; A nonautomatic process. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1 7, 219-228.
Wertheimer, M. (1959). Productive thinking. New York: Harper.
Whimbey, A (1976). Intelligence can be taught. New York: Bantam.
Whimbey, A, & Lochhead, J. (1982). Problem solving and comprehension: A short course in ana-
lytic reasoning. Philadelphia: Franklin Institute Press.
Whiting, C. S. (1958). Creative thinking. New York: Reinhold.
Whorf, B. (1956). Language, thought, and reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wickelgren, W. (1974). How to solve problems. San Francisco: Freeman.
Wicker, A W. ( 1 981). Getting out of our conceptual ruts: Strategies for generating new perspectives
on familiar research problems. Paper presented at the 1 981 annual convention of the Western
Psychological Association, Los Angeles.
Williams, W., Blythe, T., White, N., Li, J., Sternberg, R., & Gardner, H. (1996). Practical intelli­
gence for school handbook. New York: HarperCollins.
Wilson, R., & Crouch, E. A C. (1 987). Risk assessment and comparisons: An introduction. Sci­
ence, 286, 267-270.
Wilson, T. D., & Brekke, N. (1994). Mental contamination and mental correction: Unwanted
influences on judgments and evaluations. Psychological Bulletin, 1 1 6, 1 1 7-142.
Zimbardo, P. G., & Leippe, M. R. (1991). The psychology of attitude change and social influence.
New York: McGraw-Hill.
Author Index

A Benjamin, A S., 70
Berger, D., 314, 319
Adams, A, 120 Berger, S. A, 80
Adams, J. L., 388, 425 Bergman, E. T., 63
Adams, M. L 53 Berkowitz, L., 327
Ahlgren, A, 270 Berlin, B., 107
Alcock, J. E., 275 Bernstein, D. A., 385
Alexander, L 198 Bettman, J. R, 314, 331
Alibali, M. W., 331 Beyth-Marom, R, 79
Allan, R A, 6 Bink, M. L., 407
Allan, T., 421 Binko, J. B., 4
Allegretti, C. L., 192 Biondi, A. M., 400
Allport, G. W., 61, 238 Bjork, R A, 70
Amabile, T. M., 413 Blackman, S., 1 1 3, 273
Anderson, B. F., 141 Blank, A, 208
Andrade, J., 73 Blankenship, S. E., 353
Arasteh, A R, 397 Blasko, D. G., 97
Arasteh, J. D., 397 Block, R A., 10, 1 1
Arbitman-Smith, R, 98 Blythe, T., 22
Arkes, H. R, 265, 315, 324 Boden, M. A, 409
Aronson, E., 207 Bodenmann, G., 358
Asimov, I., 4 Bollag, B., 5
Atkinson, R c., 74 Boodoo, G., 22
Azar, B., 341 Boring, E. G., 23
Bouchard, T. J. L 22
B Bousfield, W. A., 57
Bower, G. H., 42, 57, 73, 89, 121, 123, 1 24, 1 25, 324
Baddeley, A. D., 67, 73 Boxall, B., 303
Baer, J., 412 Boykin, A. W., 22
Bahrick, H . P., 80 Bozell, L. B. III, 303
Bailin, 5., 416 Bradbury, R, 213
Bar-Natan, D., 271 Braine, M. D., 150
Baron, A. L., 1 3 Bransford, D., 69
Baron, J., 1 94, 313, 314, 329, 331, 338 Bransford, J. D., 54, 58, 66, 69, 94, 98, 358,
Barron, F., 415, 417 380, 417
Barron, L., 58 Brehm, J. W., 340
Bartlett, F. c., 62 Brekke, N., 239
Bartlett, J., 26, 232 Brem, 5., 210
Bassham, G., 198 Brennan, J., 1 1 7
Bastardi, A, 318 Brennan, T., 187
Beattie, A F., 48 Brim, O. G., Jr., 21
Beecher, H. W., 107 Brody, N., 22
Begley, 5., 418 Brooks, L. W., 50
Beilensen, L 1 70, 221, 354 Bross, I. D. L 31
Benassi, V., 256 Brown, A. L., 69, 94, 120

453
454 AUTHOR INDEX

Brown, R. V., 331 Crutchfield, R. S., 358, 359, 4 1 7


Bruer, J. T., 12, 21 Csikszentmihalyi, M . , 403, 404, 414
Bruner, J. 5., 91 Cull, W. L., 56
Bucciarelli, M., 150
Buffalo, E. A, 59 D
Bugliosi, V., 98
Burke, D. M., 353 d'Angelo, E., 7
Byrne, R., 1 95, 208, 270, 400 Dahlstrom, W. G., 236
Damer, T. E., 1 1 1
C Dansereau, D . F., 31, 124, 125, 126, 128,
310, 339
Cameron, J., 414 Darrow, c., 47
Campione, J. c., 13 Davidson, D., 386
Campos, A, 425 Davidson, J., 2
Cannon-Bowers, J. A., 312 Davies, L. B., 358, 359, 417
Carey, J., 6 Davis, G. A., 420
Carkhuff, R. R., 337 Davis, M., 54
Carlson, E., 1 97, 387 Dawes, R. M., 252, 254, 256, 258, 342
Carnine, D., 120 Day, R. 5., 130, 131
Carroll, D. W., 1 1 5 De Lopez, R. 5., 5
Carroll, L., 92, 156 de Sanchez, M., 1 1
Carson, D., 406 DeBono, E., 399, 418, 423
Caspe, W., 354 Decyk, B. N., 105
Catrambone, R., 372 Dees, S. M., 125
Ceci, S. J., 22, 69, 357 deGroot, A D., 25, 68
Ceraso, J., 171 Dekel, 5., 79
Champagne, A. B., 46, 197 Dewey, J., 140
Chance, P., 10, 1 2 Dews, S., 91
Chang, J . , 94 Diamond, R. M., 4
Chanowitz, B., 208 DiCamillo, M., 380
Chapman, J. P., 249 Doherty, M. E., 318
Chapman, L. J., 249 Donovan, J. J., 56
Cheng, P. W., 153, 210 Doolittle, J. H ., 407, 419
Chesler, P., 109 Dougherty, B. c., 6
Chi, M. T., 68 Dreman, D., 293
Chitwood, S. T., 97 Driver, R., 189
Cialdini, R. B., 1 1 5, 1 1 6, 325, 341 Drosnin, M., 271
Cirilo, R. K, 89 Drysdale, W., 107
Clapper, J. P., 121 Dunbar, K, 97, 359, 372
Clark, H. H., 93 Duncan, C. P., 380
Clark, M. c., 57 Duncker, K, 380, 384, 422
Clemens, S. L., 404 Dywan, J., 80
Click, B. A., 6
Clinton, B., 8 E
Cocking, R. R., 69, 94
Cohen, D., 5 Einstein, A., 146
Cohen, G., 80 Eisenberger, R., 414
Cohen, M. S., 1 9 Ekman, P., 95, 100
Cole, K c . , 242, 252, 271 Emery, G., 257
Collaer, M. L., 7 Ennis, R. H., 204
Collett, P., 5 Eskenazi, J., 26
Collins, K W., 125 Eylon, B. 5., 125
Combs, B., 296
Connor-Greene, P. A., 54 F
Conway, M. A, 80
Covington, M. V., 358, 359, 417 Facione, N. c., 10, 12, 15
Crandall, J. c., Jr., 11 Facione, P. A , 10, 12, 15
Crouch, E. A c., 298 Falls, c., 207
Crovitz, H. F., 422-423 Fantaske, P., 6
Crowley, M. J., 47 Farr, M. J., 68
AUTHOR INDEX 455

Fauth, J., 239 Gordon, W. J. J., 385, 402, 410


Ferguson, G., 1 1 8 Govier, T., 166
Festinger, L., 340 Graf, P., 47
Feynman, R., 415 Grass, L., 320
Finke, R. A, 407 Gray, W., 256
Fischer, G. W., 323 Greenhouse, J. B., 1 3
Fischer, S. c., 6 Greenwald, A G., 26, 47
Fischhoff, B., 1 97, 207, 296, 297, 299, 318, 342 Grotzer, T. A, 21, 22, 25
Fisher, D., 332 Gruneberg, M. M., 77
Fisher, R., 385 Guilford, J. P., 405
Fisher, R. P., 78 Gunther, M., 274, 275
Fiske, S. T., 60, 61, 226 Gustafson, S. B., 406
Fixx, J. F., 374
Flannelly, K J., 207 H
Flannelly, L. T., 207
Flaton, R., 3 1 7 Hadamard, L., 384
Fletcher, M . , 4 1 Hall, L. K, 80
Fode, K L . , 255 Hallman, W. K, 298
Fogelin, R. J., 109 Halpern, D. F., 7, 10, 14, 22, 61, 96, 109, 1 1 3,
Foltz, K, 6 273, 322
Fong, G. T., 12, 266 Hammond, K R., 265, 315, 320
Fox, L. 5., 1 1 Hansen, c., 96
Frammolino, R., 5 Hanson, N. R., 55
Franks, J. J., 380 Harris, R. J., 92
Frederick, J. N., 192 Harris, S. B., 49
Freeman, J. T., 1 9 Hasher, L., 45
Freud, S., 339 Hastie, R., 256
Haviland, S. E., 93
G Hayden, R. G., 4
Hayes, J. R., 400
Garb, H. M., 252 Heiman, M., 120, 350
Gardner, H., 22, 31, 314, 398 Heit, E., 140, 237
Garfield, J., 270 Heller, R., 354
Garland, J. D., 125 Henle, M., 139
Garnham, A, 1 38, 151 Hennessey, B. A, 413
Gazzaniga, M. S., 27 Herrmann, D. J., 1 2, 77
Geiselman, R. E., 78 Herrnstein, R. J., 1 1 , 22, 25
Gentner, D. R., 96, 99 Hertwig, R., 320
Gerbner, G., 320 Hoffman, S., 6
Gersten, R., 120 Hoffrage, U., 293, 294, 320
Gervais, S., 271 Hogarth, R. M., 328
Giancarlo, C. A, 1 0, 1 2, 1 5 Holland, J. H., 232, 233
Gibson, S., 256 Holley, C. D., 125, 1 26, 127
Gick, M. L., 384 Holt, J., 54
Gifford-Jones, W., 320 Holyoak, K J., 18, 99, 153, 232, 233, 318,
Gigerenzer, G., 1 74, 281, 293, 294, 320, 330 384, 385
Gilbreth, F. B., 1 1 5 Hostetler, A J., 26
Gillette, R., 26 Huff, D., 300
Gilovich, T., 270 Hult, R. E., 54
Glaser, R., 10, 68, 145 Hummel, J. E., 18, 385
Glucksberg, 5., 29, 30 Hunt, E. B., 2, 43
Godfrey, 5., 418 Hunt, M., 139, 145
Goertzel, B., 382 Hutchings, P., 412
Goertzel, T., 382 Hyman, R., 242
Goldman, S. R., 233
Goldstein, D. c., 174, 320, 330
Goleman, D., 23
Gombo, R., 79 Irwin, F. W., 322
Gonzalez, M. A, 425 Ivry, R. B., 27
Gordon, D. H., 239 Izawa, c., 4, 50
456 AUTHOR INDEX

J Larrick, R P., 324


Larson, C. F., 415
Jackson, H., 1 70, 221, 354 Laurence, K A, 75
Jackson, S. E., 402 Lawson, T. J., 46
Jacoby, L. L., 80 Layman, M., 296
James, W., 59 Leavenworth, R, 88
Janik, A., 21 1 Leedy, P. D., 232
Janis, I. L., 329, 334, 339 Legrenzi, M. S., 152
Jensen, A R, 23 Legrenzi, P., 152
Jepson, c., 1 2 Lehman, D. R, 12
Johnson, E. J., 314, 323, 331 Leippe, M. R., 1 1 5, 1 16
Johnson, M. K, 54, 62, 318 Leive, c., 1 1 2
Johnson, W., 253 Leming, J. S., 1 2
Johnson-Laird, P. N., 150, 151, 152, 153 Lempert, R . 0., 12
Jones, E. A, 442 Lenski, S. D., 207
Jones, E. E., 241 Lepper, M., 207
Juge, M. L., 100 Levi, D. S., 219
Levin, J. R, 77
K Levine, M., 354, 407
Lewis, A. B., 360
Kahane, H., 108, 138 Li, J., 22
Kahneman, D., 240, 271, 279, 295, 319, 321, 338 Lichtenstein, S., 41, 207, 296, 299, 318
Kalai, G., 271 Lilienfeld, S. 0., 252
Kaplan, C. A, 139 Linn, M. c., 125
Kavanaugh, D. J., 324 Lithner, J., 354, 372
Kay, P., 107 Lochhead, J., 368
Kelley, C. M., 80 Loehlin, J. c., 22
Kellogg, R T., 132 Loftus, E. F., 62, 63, 79, 285
Keren, G., 268 Loftus, G. R., 285
Kerker, R M., 48 Lopes, L. L., 140
Kidd, V., 222 Lorayne, H., 72, 74, 82
Kim, I. J., 47 Lord, c., 207
Kim, W. C., 404 Lovett, M. c., 13, 293
Kimble, G. A., 237, 244 Lowenfeld, V., 416
King, A, 6, 1 20, 121, 220 Lubart, T. I., 398, 403
King, P. M, 1 2 Lucas, J., 72
Kitchener, K S., 12 Lynn, S. J., 79
Klacznski, P. A, 239
Klahr, D., 256 M
Klauer, K c., 61
Kneller, G. F., 400 MacKay, D. G., 353
Knight, K, 310, 339 Magnun, G. R, 27
Koestler, A., 401 Maier, N. R. F., 380, 381
Kohler, W., 363 Mann, L., 329, 334, 339
Komatsu, S. I., 47 Marsh, G., 1 1
Koriat, A, 207, 318 Marsh, J . G., 338
Kosonen, P., 12 Marsh, R. I., 407
Kotovsky, K., 69 Martin, P., 403
Krantz, D. H., 12, 266 Mather, M., 318
Krechevsky, M., 22 Matlin, M., 144
Kronholm, M. M., 12 Mauborgne, R, 404
Kruglanski, A. W., 318 Mayer, R E., 123, 360
Kuhn, D., 209, 210, 317 Mazzoni, G. A L., 79
McClelland, J. L., 95
L McCormick, C. B., 77
McDonald, B. A., 125
La Rochefoucauld, 251 McFadzean, E., 404
LaBine, G., 343 McFadzean, M. E., 358
LaBine, S. J., 343 McGuire, W. J., 1 74, 421, 427
Langer, E. J., 17, 208 McHardy, P., 421
Langer, S. A, 47 McKay, B., 271
AUTHOR INDEX 457

McKeachie, W. L 1 0 Orwell, G., 8


McKinnon, J. W., 5 , 1 2 Osborn, A. F., 382, 397, 418
Mednick, M. T., 411 Osborne, J., 189
Mednick, S. A., 41 1 Osgood, C. E., 55
Mehrabian, A., 23 Oskamp, S., 251
Meiser, T., 61 Overskeid, G., 335
Merron, K., 332
Meyer, B. J. F., 125 p
Miller, J. E., Jr., 88, 106
Milne, A. A., 355 Paas, F. G., 13, 81
Moore, 1. M., 6 Palinscar, A. S., 120
Morgan, J. J. B., 145 Papanek, V. J., 4 1 1
Morgan, J. N., 324 Parducci, A . , 1 1 5
Morgan, M., 320 Park, C. W., 414
Morton, J. T., 145 Park, D. c., 76
Moss, J., 68 Parnes, S. J., 400, 420, 426
Mumford, M. D., 406 Parsons, J., 15, 188
Munby, H., 155 Pascal, B., 15
Munson, R., 249 Patterson, M. E., 31
Murray, C. A., 22, 25 Paulos, J. A., 298
Mussweiler, T., 1 1 7 Payne, J. W., 314, 331
Myers, D . G., 293 Peck, J., 102
Mynatt, C. R., 318 Pedone, R., 385
Peeck, V. H., 81
N Pellegrino, J. W., 233
Pence, G. E., 330
Nakamura, J., 403, 404, 414 Pennington, N., 256
Nardi, A., 309 Perez, M. J., 425
Nardone, H., 198 Perfetto, G. A., 380
Narens, 70, 90 Perkins, D. N., 21, 22, 25, 404, 411, 423
Neisser, U., 22, 40 Perloff, R., 22
Nelson, G., 257 Pfeiffer, K. R., 175
Nelson, T. 0., 21, 70 Phillips, D., 380
Neubert, G. A., 4 Pinkley, R. 1., 1 1 4
Newell, A., 350, 351, 360 Pitt, J . , 88
Newsom, J. T., 341 Pogrow, S., 131
Newton, P., 189 Poincare, H., 352
Nickerson, R. 5., 1 1 , 25, 53, 1 70, 193, 206 Politzer, G., 151
Nisbett, R. E., 12, 13, 232, 233, 266, 324 Polya, G., 21 , 1 73, 352, 361, 372, 374, 384
Nixon, R. M., 310 Poon, 1. W., 125
Noller, R. B., 400 Posner, M. I., 371
Norman, D., 72, 73 Postman, N., 221
Norris, S. P., 10, 204 Potts, G. R., 144
Northcraft, G. 8., 114 Powell, D., 40
Noveck, I. A., 151 Powers, S., 221
Nowlis, S. M., 209 Pratkanis, A. R., 26, 207
Nummedal, S. G., 1 0 Prince, G. M., 398
Protivera, A., 171
o Pruitt, J. 5., 312

O'Hara, A., 407 Q


O'Loughlin, A., 358
O'Neil, H. F., Jr., 50 Quattrone, G. A., 241
Oakhill, J., 138, 151
Odean, T., 271 R
Okaguki, J., 22
Oliver, P., 358 Radosevich, D. J., 56
Olton, R. M., Jr., 358, 359, 417 Raia, E., 383
Oppenheimer, J. R., 409 Raphael, 8., 373
Orner, P. J., 47 Ratcliff, G., 6
Orotony, A., 97 Raye, C. 1., 62
458 AUTHOR INDEX

Reber, P. J., 69 Shavinina, L. V., 413


Reisberg, D., 43 Shermer, M., 1 94, 257
Renner, J. W., 5, 12 Sherwood, R., 66
Renshon, S. A, 328, 329 Shubik, M., 323
Resnick, L. B., 6, 88 Shuman, D. W., 1 97
Restak, R. M., 27, 34, 88 Siegel, E., 225
Reyes, R. M., 42 Signorielli, N., 320
Rhoads, K., 1 1 3 Simon, D., 318
Riefer, D . , 96 Simon, H. A., 139, 256, 350, 351, 353
Rieke, R., 21 1 Simonson, L, 209
Rieser, J., 66 Simonson, Y., 209
Rips, L. J., 1 40, 210 Simutis, Z. M., 50
Rittle-Johnson, B., 331 Singer, B., 256
Rodin, G. c., 130, 131 Slomianko, J., 1 20, 350
Roediger, H. L., 47, 63 Slovic, P., 296, 299
Rogan, J., 1 6 Sluyter, D. ]., 23
Rojankovsky, F . , 5 1 Smedslund, J., 314
Rokeach, M . , 1 6 Smith, D. c., 414
Rosch, E . , 107 Smith, L., 407
Rosenthal, R., 255 Smith, M. U., 354
Ross, J., 75 Smith, S. M., 63, 353
Ross, L., 207 Snyder, M., 60
Rothenberg, A., 29 Soler, M. J., 73
Roweton, W., 420 Solorzano, L., 1 0
Rubinstein, M. F., 1 75 Sorensen, T. c . , 3 1 0
Ruiz, A L, 69, 357 Spangenberg, E. R . , 26
Ruiz, J. c., 73 Spellman, B. A, 99
Rumelhart, D. E., 95 Spiker, V. A, 6
Russell, B., 2, 7 Squire, L. R., 59
Ryan, M., 405 Stahl, N. N., 138
Stahl, R. ]., 138
s Stanhope, N., 80
Stanovich, K. E., 19, 1 94, 257
Sadler, W. A., Jr., 25 Staudenmeyer, H., 154
Salas, E., 312 Stein, B. S., 98, 358
Salovey, P., 23 Steinem, G., 387
Saltzstein, H. D., 354 Sternberg, R. J., 7, 22, 25, 166, 364, 386, 398, 403,
Salzman, B., 1 13, 273 407, 409
Sapir, E., 106 Stewart, J. K., 78
Schacter, D. L., 62, 80 Stoltzfus, E. R., 130, 131
Schafly, P., 202 Strack, F., 1 1 7
Schauble, L., 145 Swanson, H . L., 21
Schmidt, H. G., 81 Swets, J. A, 1 1
Schmolck, H., 59
Schoenfeld, A H., 12, 16, 372 T
Schunn, C. D., 293
Schwartz, B. L., 70 Taplin, ]. E., 154
Scriven, M., 1 74 Tate, M. A, 198
Seamon, ]. G., 47 Taylor, S. E., 226
Sears, A, 15, 188 Teger, A L, 386
Seech, Z., 193 Teigen, K. H., 268
Seitz, A, 79 Tetlock, P. E., 206
Seligman, M., 323 Thagard, P. R., 232, 233
Sethi, R., 414 Thome, P. R., 327
Shafir, E., 318 Thompson, W. c., 42
Shaked, M., 79 Tibbetts, S., 6
Shaklee, H., 282 Timnick, L., 1 76
Shalley, C. E., 425 Todd, P. M., 281, 330
Shapira, Z., 338 Torbert, W. R., 332
Shaver, K. G., 1 71 , 324 Toulmin, S., 2 1 1
AUTHOR INDEX 459

Trost, M. R., 341 Weber, R. J., 411


Tulving, E., 44 Wegner, D. M., 48
Tutu, D., 99 Weil, E. M., 166
Tversky, A, 45, 240, 271, 279, 295, 319, 321, Weinstock, M., 317
330, 338 Weisberg, R., 380
Tweney, R. D., 97, 318 Weisberg, R. W., 29, 30, 400
Wenzlaff, R., 48
U Wertheimer, M., 355
West, R. F., 19, 194
Uranowitz, S. W., 60 Whimbey, A, 25, 70, 368
Urbina, S., 446 White, N., 22
Ury, W., 385 Whiting, C. 5., 420
Whorf, B., 106
v Wickelgren, W., 356
Wicker, A W., 424
van Breukelen, G. J. P., 81 Wiegmann, D. A, 31
Van Haneghan, J., 58, 417 Williams, P. c., 47, 364, 417
VanLehn, K., 386 Williams, S., 58
Vaughan, J. L., 1 23, 1 24 Williams, W., 22
Vernon, P., 424 Wilson, R., 298
von Oech, R., 109, 402, 412 Wilson, T. D., 239
Vosniadou, 5., 97 Winne, P. H., 12
Vye, N. J., 58, 66, 98, 417 Winner, E., 91
Vygotsky, L., 22, 23 Wishengrad, D. L., 47
Wolf, 5., 19
w Wood, J. M., 252
Worthley, J. 5., 353
Wade, E., 353
Wagner-Pacifici, 101 Y
Wales, C. E., 309
Wallas, G., 352 Yalow, R. 5., 254
Walsh, J., 27 Young, M., 58, 417
Wandersman, A. H., 298
Wang, P., 272 z
Wanous, J. P., 339
Ward, T. B., 407 Zacks, R. T., 45
Wason, P. c., 150, 151, 153, 316, 317 Zimbardo, P. G., 1 15, 1 1 6
Subj ect Index

A explaining as knowing, 209-226


persuasion and propaganda, 207-209
Acceptable, 229 template for writing, 205-207
Acceptable premises, 195 Arguments against the person, 211-212, 229
Acquisition, 84 Assumptions, 187-188, 229
of information, 43 Attention, paying, 52-54
Acquisition goal, see Encoding goal Attitude changes, and syllogisms, 171
Adequate grounds, 229 Attribute listing, 428
in arguments, 199 and creativity, 421-422
Advance organizers, 85 Automatic memory, 45, 84
Advertisements, role of inference, 91-92 Automatic thinking, 7
Affirming the antecedent, 147, 180 Availability, 319
Affirming the consequent, 148, 180 Availability heuristic, 318-321, 346
Algorithm, 318, 346
Ambiguous, 135 B
words, 109
American Psychiatric Association, Chronicle of Bandwagon, see Popularity
Higher Education, 101 Base rate, 306
American Psychological Association, 69 and probability, 287-288
Analogical thinking, and creativity, 409-412 Base-rate neglect, 306
Analogies, 96--99, 394 and probability, 287-288
aid to understanding, 96--9 7 Belief bias, 145, 180
in argument, 217 The Bell Curve (Hermstein & Murray), 25
to persuade, 97-99 Bending rods, experiment of, 246--247
as problem-solving aids, 97 Biased discounting, 329, 346
and problem-solving skills, 384-386 Biased sample, 262, 301, 307
Anatomy of a problem, 350-352, 393 and hypothesis testing, 236-238
Anchor, 1 1 7 Bible Code, 270
Anchoring, 1 1 6--1 1 7, 135 Bionics, 41 1, 428
Antecedent, 1 46, 180 Bisociative thinking, 401, 428
Appeals to authority, 230 Bounded rationality, 1 74, 1 81
in argument, 217-218 Brainstorming, 394, 428
Appeals to ignorance, 217, 230 and problem solving, 382-383
Appeals to pity, 212, 229 Browsing, and creative thinking, 424
Appeals to pride or snobbery, 214, 230 Bureaucratese, 1 1 1-112, 135
Appeals to tradition, 230
in argument, 219 C
Argument, 1 83-230, 228
actively open-minded thinking, 1 93-195 Cards, 274-275
analyzing, 204-205 Card stacking, 215, 230
anatomy of, 183-189 Categorical reasoning, 157, 180
applying the framework, 226-227 Categories, power of, 103-104
changing beliefs, 225-226 Chained conditional, 1 54, 180
diagramming the structure, 189-193 Chained structures, 229
evaluating the strength of, 1 95-204 of argument, 1 91

460
SUBJECT INDEX 46 1

Chance, see Laws of chance Creative idea checklists, 428


Chance Magazine, 269 Creative thinking, 396-429
Changing College Classrooms (Halpern), 109 applying the framework, 425--427
Cheaper by the Dozen (Gilbreth), 1 1 5 as cognitive process, 404-412
Chronicle o f Higher Education, 4 , 27 defining creativity, 397-404
Chunking, 67--{'9, 85 encouraging creativity, 412-415
Circle diagrams, 1 81 strategies for, 41 6-425
and syllogistic reasoning, 1 58-166 Creativity, 428
Circular reasoning, 215, 230 Credibility
Classical conditioning, 4�9 crisis, 1 97-198
Cocktail party effect, 52, 85 of experts, 1 96-197
Cognitive dissonance, 347 Critical thinking, 38
and decision making, 340-341 common media depictions, 32-33
Cognitive economy, 103, 135 instruction, 14-25
Cognitive interview, 78-79, 86 need for, 2-10
Cognitive process instruction, 8, 38 working definition of, 6-7
Cold reading, and hypothesis testing, Critical thinking attitude, 15, 38
242-243 Crovitz's Relational Algorithm, 422-423
Combinatorial reasoning, 155-156, 180 Cumulative probabilities, 306
Communication, rules for, 92-93 Cumulative risks, and probability, 281-282
Comprehension of language, 1 18-132
questioning and explaining, 1 20-122 D
re-representation, 1 1 9-120
strategies for, 1 1 9 Debiasing goal, 86
Concept maps, 1 22-123, 136 of memory, 81
Conceptual Blockbusting (Adams), 388 Decision making, 308-347
Conclusion, 1 79, 183, 229 applying the framework, 343-344
of arguments, 186 dilemmas in, 338-339
Conclusion indicators, 186, 229 elimination by aspects, 330
Conclusion markers, 186 evaluating consequences, 327-330
Conditional logic, 1 46, 180 framework for, 310-312
Conditioning, See Classical conditioning making sound decisions, 309-31 5
Confidence, and memory, 70 pitfalls and pratfalls, 315-327
Confirmation bias, 79-80, 145, 151-153, postdecision commitment and evaluation,
317, 346 339-343
Confounding, 262 preparing a worksheet, 331-339
and hypothesis testing, 237 and subjective utility, 312-314
Conjunction error, 306 Declarative memory, 44, 84
and probability, 279-281 Deductive method, 261
Consequent, 146, 1 80 of hypothesis testing, 233-236
Consistent, 229 Deductive reasoning, 140-141, 142, 1 79
Consistent premises, 195 Degree of confidence judgments, 70, 85
Consumer Reports, 129 Degrees of belief, and probability, 269
Context, meaning evaluations, 1 1 5-1 16 Denying the antecedent, 148, 1 80
Contingency relationships, 146, 180 Denying the consequent, 148, 180
Continuum, 230 Dependent variable, 262
Continuum fallacies, in argument, 216 of hypothesis testing, 235
Contradiction, and problem solving, 383-384 Detour problems, 394
Contrast, meaning evaluations, 1 15-1 16 and problem solving, 370
Convenience samples, 262 Diagrams, and problem solving, 361-366
and hypothesis testing, 237-238 Dimensional comparison, 336-337, 346
Convergent structures, 229 Direct analogy, 395
of argument, 190-191 and problem solving, 385
Convergent validity, 263 Directed thinking, 38
and hypothesis testing, 250-251 outcomes, 7
Correlated variables, 263 Distortion, and memory, 61--{i2
and hypothesis testing, 248 Distributed, 166-167, 181
Correlation, and hypothesis testing, 248-250 Double-blind procedures, 263
Cosmopolitan, 239 and hypothesis testing, 255-256
Counterargument, 1 88-189, 229 Double negation, 150-151, 180
462 SUBJECT INDEX

E Generalization, 262, 394


and hypothesis testing, 237
Ease of learning judgments, 70, 85 and problem solving, 378
Ecological validity, 169, 1 81 Generic questions, 121-122, 135
Effortful memory, 45, 84 Given/ new distinction, 135
Elimination by aspects, 330, 346 presenting information to listeners, 93
Emotional states, and decision making, 326--327 Givens, 351, 393
Encoding goal, 86 Goals, 35-37
of memory, 81 achieving, 36
Encoding specificity, 85 setting, 35-36
Entrapment, 323, 346 Goal state, 393
Episodic memory, 44, 84 in problem solving, 350
Equivocation, 1 1 1 , 135 Graphic organizers, See Concept maps
Errors, and hypothesis testing, 253-254 Graphs, and problem solving, 361-366
Etymology, 1 1 1 , 135 Guilt by association, 21 1 , 229
Euler diagrams
and syllogistic reasoning, 158 H
Euphemism, 1 12, 135
Evaluation, see Judgment stage Habit of planning, 38
Executive processes, 38 critical thinking, 1 6
Expected value (EV), 306 Hard Copy, 220
and probability, 282-285 Heuristic, 31 8-322, 346
Experts, credibility of, 1 96--1 97 availability, 31 8-321
Explaining, 121-122 representativeness, 321-322
Explicit memory, 47, 85 Hierarchical trees, 394
External memory aids, 72, 77-78, 85 and problem solving, 366--368
Extrapolation, 302, 307 Hierarchies, 123-1 24, 136
Extrinsic motivation, 413, 428 Hindsight, 341-343, 347
Eyewitness testimony, and memory, 62 Hints, 394
and problem solving, 380-381
F Historical evidence, in arguments, 1 94-195
How to Lie With Statistics (Huff), 300
Failure to accept the logical task, 1 79 How to Win at Poker (Moss), 68
Fallacies, 210-211, 229 Hypothesis, 261
Fallacy, 314, 346 Hypothesis testing, 232-263, 261
False curse, 230 applying the framework, 259-260
fallacies in argument, 218-219 determining cause, 243-253
False dichotomy, 213-214, 230 and errors, 253-254
Familiarization, see Preparation stage inductive and deductive methods, 233-236
Fantasy analogy, 395 and the occult and paranormal, 256-257
and problem solving, 386 population and samples, 236-241
Feelings of knowing judgments, 70, 85 science vs. science fiction, 241-243
First letter mnemonics, 76, 86 and scientific thinking, 257-259
Foot-in-the-door, 347 and self-fulfilling prophecies, 254-256
and decision making, 341 understanding, 232-233
Forethought, 341-343 Hypothetical constructs, 42, 84
Forgetting, and memory, 63---65
Forward-looking strategy, 394
of problem solving, 374
Four-card selection task, 151-153, 180 Ideational fluency, 423-424, 429
Framing, 1 1 3-1 15, 135 If, and only if statements, 154
Functional fixedness, 395 If, then reasoning
and problem solving, 388 in legal contexts, 1 54-155
If, then statements, 146-- 155, 180
G chained conditionals, 154
confirmation bias, 151-153
Gambler's fallacy, 285-287, 306 in everyday contexts, 149-150
Games of chance, 273-276 four kinds of reasoning, 148
Geneplore, 428 if, and only if, 154
and creativity, 407 if. then reasoning in legal contexts, 1 54-155
SUBJECT INDEX 463

negation, 150-151 Knowing the unknowable, 230


permission and obligation schemata, 153-154 fallacy in argument, 218
tree diagrams, 146-149 Knowledge, see also prior knowledge
Ill-defined problems, 355-356, 393 critical thinking, 5-6
Illicit conversions, 1 48, 1 72-173, 180, 181
Illogical, 1 38, 1 79 L
Illusion of truth, 48, 85
Illusory correlation, 263 Labels, power of, 1 03-104
and hypothesis testing, 249-250 Language, 88-133
Illusory validity, 263 analogy and metaphor, 96-99
and hypothesis testing, 251-252 and comprehension, 1 1 8-132
Image, 429 emotional, 1 08-109
and creativity, 425 framework application, 1 32-133
Imagery, 28-31, 38 implications and inference, 90-91
Implicit memory, 47, 85 psycholinguistics, 88
Incidental learning, 45, 85 rules for clear communication, 92-96
Incomplete comparisons, 230 tool or master of thought, 106-1 18
in argument, 218 underlying representation and surface
Incubation, 393 structure, 88-90
and creativity, 407-409 words and meanings, 1 00-106
in problem solving, 352-353 Lateral thinking, 399, 428
Independent events, 306 Law of large numbers, 262
and probability, 278 and hypothesis testing, 239
Independent variable, 262 Law of small numbers, 262
of hypothesis testing, 235 and hypothesis testing, 240-241
Inductive method, 261 Laws of chance, 268-269, 306
of hypothesis testing, 233-236 Laws of probability, see Laws of chance
Inductive reasoning, 140-141, 142, 1 79 Learning
Inert knowledge, 85 noncognitive factors, 58-59
and strategies for creative thinking, 423-424 strategies that promote, 50-59
Inference, and memory, 61-62 Liking, and decision making, 325-326
Information explosion, 50 Linear arrays, 1 23, 136
Initial state, 393 Linear ordering, 141-145, 1 79
in problem solving, 350 linear diagrams, 142-144
Insight, 393 Linear syllogism, 1 80
and creativity, 407-409 Linked structures, see Chained structures
in problem solving, 353 Literary Digest, 237
Intelligence, see also Stanford-Binet test Logic, 1 79
learning, 25-26 and pragmatism, 138-140
measurement of, 23-25 Los Angeles Times, 176
nature of, 21-23
Intentional learning, 45, 85 M
Interference theory of forgetting, 63-64, 85
Internal memory aids, 72, 85 Main point, 229
In the long run, 266, 306 Marked adjectives, 144, 180
and probability, 282 Matrices, 129-131
Intrinsic motivation, 428 Matrix, 136, 394
and creativity, 413 and problem solving, 368-369
Irrelevant reasons, fallacies in argument, 21 5-216 Mean, 301, 307
Meaning, monitoring, 54-56
J Means-end analysis, 372-373, 394
Measurement sensitivity, of hypotheSiS testing,
JFK, 198 235-236
Judgment stage, 393 Measures of central tendency, 301, 307
in problem solving, 352 Median, 301, 307
Mein Kampf (Hitler), 102
K Memory, 40-84
acquisition of, 49-59
Kennedy (Sorensen), 310 applying the framework, 81-83
Keywords, 72-74, 85 biases in, 79-80
464 SUBJECT INDEX

and long-term accuracy, 80-81 Northern Illinois University, Public Opinion


as mediator of cognitive processes, 40-49 Laboratory, 4, 1 19
metamemory, 69-71 Nutrition Action Health Letter, 26
and mnemonics, 71-79
real and false, 62-63 o
retention of, 59-63
retrieval, 63-66 Objective probability, 306
varieties of, 43-46 Obligation schema, 1 53, 180
without awareness, 47 Occult beliefs, and hypothesis testing,
working memory, 66-69 256-257
Mental set, 395 Odds, 267-268, 306
and problem solving, 388 Omission bias, 329, 346
Mere exposure effect, 326, 346 Operational definition, 261
Metacognition, 1 9-21, 38 of hypothesis testing, 234-235
Metamemory, 69-71, 85 Optimization, 331, 346
Metaphor, 428 Organization, and learning, 56
Metaphors, and problem solving, 384-386 Overall assessment, 336, 346
Method of places, 75-76, 86 Overconfidence, 318, 346
Middle term, 1 66, 181 Overconfidence phenomenon, 306
Mindfulness, 38 and probability, 271-272
Mindlessness, 327, 346 Overlearning, 58, 121, 135
Misleading/irrelevant information, and problem
solving, 389-390 p
Missing components, in arguments,
201-202 Paradigm, 428
Missing quantifiers, in syllogistic reasoning, stretching and rejecting, 404-405
1 70-171 Paranormal, and hypothesis testing, 256-257
Mnemonic devices, 71, 85 Paraphrase, 135
Mnemonics, 71-79 Paraphrasing, 121
external memory aids, 77-78 Particular affirmative, 181
first letter, 76 mood in syllogistic reasoning, 157
keywords and images, 72-74 Particular negative, 1 81
methods of places, 75-76 mood in syllogistic reasoning, 157
principles, 77 Part-whole fallacies, in argument, 216-217
remembering events, 78-79 Performance-competence distinction, 1 5-18, 38,
rhymes, 74-75 see also Thinking
Model manipulation, and problem solving, Permission schema, 153, 180
369-370 Persistence, in decision making, 354-355
Mood, 1 57, 181 Personal analogy, 395
Motor memory, 44, 84 and problem solving, 385
Multiple outcomes, 306 Personality factors, and creativity, 414-415
Personal logic, 1 79
N Plus, minus, interesting (PM!), 423, 429
Point Stevens Journal, 269
Name calling, 1 08-109 Pollyanna effect, see also Wishful thinking
National Academy of Sciences, 26 in memory, 80
National Commission of Excellence in Popularity, 212-213, 229
Education, 4 Population, 262
National Education Goals Panel, goals for college and hypothesis testing, 236
graduates, 4 Positive correlation, 263
National Research Council, 26 and hypothesis testing, 248
Negation, 1 1 4-1 15, 135, 150-151 Pragmatic, 140, 1 79
Negative correlation, 263 Precision, and statistics, 301-302
and hypothesis testing, 249 Preferred modes of thought, 38
Networks, 124-129, 136 Prejudice, and memory, 60--{j3
types of links, 126 Premise indicators, 185, 229
No good evidence, and hypothesis testing, 257 Premise markers, 185
Nondirected thinking, 7, 3 8 Premises, 1 38, 1 79, 183, 229
Nonregressive judgments, and probability, acceptable, 1 95
295-296 of arguments, 185-186
SUBJECT INDEX 465

consistent, 195 Random search, 394


supporting conclusions, 1 98-201 and problem solving, 378-379
Preparation of familiarization stage, 393 Rationalizing, 229
Preparation stage, in problem solving, 352 vs. reasoning, 206-207
Prior knowledge, 60, see also Knowledge Reasoning, 138-181, 1 79
Probability, 265-307, 306 applying the framework, 1 77-178
and expected values, 282-285 confusing truth and validity, 145
and games of chance, 273-276 with diagrams, 1 75-176
judgments about likelihood and uncertainty, in everyday contexts, 1 74-176
270-272 if, then statements, 1 46-155
and making decisions, 288-296 inductive and deductive, 1 40-141
in multiple outcome situations, 276-279 and linear ordering, 141-145
nature of the world, 265-269 logical and psychological, 1 38-140
and risk, 296-299 probabilistic, 1 73-174
statistical use and abuse, 300-303 syllogistic, 1 56-173
subjective, 285--288 vs. rationalizing, 206-207
using, 272-282 Reasons, 183, 229
Probabilogical, 1 74, 181 and analyzing arguments, 208-209
Problem, 349, 393 Recall errors, and memory, 64-65
Problem-solving skills, 348-395 Reciprocal peer questioning, 121, 135
anatomy of a problem, 350-352 Reciprocity, and decision making, 325-326
applying the framework, 391-392 Regression toward the mean, 295, 306
defining problem, 349-350 Reification, 1 1 1, 135
problem planning and representation, 356-371 Relational Algorithm, 422-423, 429
problems, 387-391 Reliability, 263
stages in, 352-355 and hypothesis testing, 252-253
strategies, 372-387 Remote Associations Test (RAT), 41 1-412
well-defined and ill-defined problems, Representation, and problem solving, 370-371
355-356 Representativeness heuristic, 322, 346
Problem space, 393 Representative sample, 262
in problem solving, 350 and hypothesis testing, 236-237
representation of, 358-360 Re-representation, 1 1 9-120, 135
Procedural memory, 44, 84 Retention interval, 43, 84
Production stage, 393 Retrieval, 43, 84
in problem solving, 352 Retrieval cues, and memory, 57-58, 65-66
Propaganda, 207-208, 229 Retrieval goal, 86
Propositional logic, 146 of memory, 81
Prospective memory, 77, 86 Retrospective experiments, and hypothesis
Prospective research, 262 testing, 247-248
and hypothesis testing, 247-248 Retrospective research, 262
Prototype, 105, 135 Rhymes, 74-75
Prototypical thinking, 104-106, 135 Risk, 296-299
Psycholinguistics, 88, 135 assessing, 298
Psychological reactance, 324, 346 biases in, 298-299
Put downs, 230 Risk adverse, 1 1 3, 135
in argument, 219 Roulette, 275-276
Rules, 394
Q and problem solving, 379

Qualifier, 229 s
of arguments, 188
Quality of learning judgments, 70, 85 Sample, 262, 300, 306
Quantifiers, 157, 181 and hypothesis testing, 236
Questioning, 1 20-122 Sample size, 262, 302, 307
and hypothesis testing, 238-240
R Sapir-Whorf hypothesis of linguistic relativity,
1 06-107, 135
RAND Corporation, 130 Satisficing, 338, 347
Random sample, 262 Schemata, 38
and hypothesis testing, 236 internal representations, 6
466 SUBJECT INDEX

Science in the Public Interest, 26 barometers of thought, 1 1 7-1 18


Scientific thinking, and hypothesis testing, as biological process, 27-28
257-259 defined, 43
Self-fulfilling prophecy, 263 directed, 7
and hypothesis testing, 254-256 framework for, 34-37
Semantic memory, 44, 84 as imagery, 28-31
Semantic slanting, 109, 135 improving, 10-14
Sensitive measures, 262 nondirected, 7
of hypothesis testing, 235-236 preferred modes of thought, 31-32
Sensitivity, 400-401, 428 prototypical, 1 04-106
Serendipity, 402, 428 Thought and knowledge, relationship of, 5-6
Significant difference, 307 Thought barometers, 1 1 7-1 18
and statistics, 302 Three-stage experimental design, and hypothesis
Simplification, 394 testing, 244-246
and problem solving, 374-377 Time, 49, 98
Six Crises (Nixon), 310 Time line, of memory, 42--43
Slippery slope, 230 Transcontextual, 393
fallacies in argument, 216 definition of, 357
Solution paths, 350, 393 Transfer of training, 1 3-14, 1 8-19, 38
Sound argument, 203-204, 229 Tree diagrams, 146-149, 1 80, 276-278, 306
Specialization, 394 Trial-and-error, 394
and problem solving, 378 and problem solving, 379
Split-half method, 394 Truth, and reasoning, 145
and problem solving, 381-382 2/3 Ideal rule, 337-338, 346
SQ3R, 120, 135
Stanford-Binet test, 23, see also Intelligence; U
Thinking
Statement, 229 Unbiased samples, and hypothesis testing,
of argument, 190 236-238
Statistics, 300-303, 306 Underlying representation, 89, 135
applying the framework, 303-305 Universal affirmative, 1 8 1
bamboozled by, 303 mood i n syllogistic reasoning, 157
Stereotyping, and memory, 60-63 Universal negative, 181
Straw person, 230 mood in syllogistic reasoning, 157
fallacies in argument, 216 Unmarked adjectives, 144, 1 80
Subarguments, 229
Subgoal, 372, 394 v
Subject, 262
Subjective probability, 285-288, 306 Vagueness, 1 1 0, 135
Subjective utility, 346 Valid, 138, 1 79
Subproblems, 372, 394 Validity, 263
Sunk costs, 323 and hypothesis testing, 250
Surface structure, 89, 135 and reasoning, 145
Syllogism, 1 57, 1 8 1 verbal rules for, 1 66-168
Syllogistic reasoning, 156-1 73, 180 Variability, 262
circle diagrams for determining validity, and hypothesis testing, 240-241
1 58-166 Variable isolation and control, in hypothesis
common errors in, 171-173 testing, 243-244
in everyday contexts, 1 69-171 Variables, 262
verbal rules for determining validity, 1 66-168 of hypothesis testing, 235
Symbolic activity, 395 Vertical thinking, 399, 428
and problem solving, 385-386 Virtue by association, 211, 229
Synergy, 401, 428 Visual arguments, 221-225
Visual thinking, and creative thinking,
T 424-425

Testimonials, 212-213, 230 w


Thinking, 84, see also Performance-competence
distinction; Stanford-Binet test Washington Times, 202
automatic, 7 Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale (WAIS), 23
SUBJECT INDEX 467

Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children Working memory, 66-69, 85


(WISC), 23 chunking, 67-69
Well-defined problems, 355-356, 393 and problem solving, 69
Wishful thinking, 322-323, 346 Worldview constraints, 395
Women and Madness (Chesler), 109 and problem solving, 390-391
Word meanings, and language, 1 00-106
Working backwards, 394
in problem solving, 373-374

You might also like