Smart Thinking

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 207

SMART

THINKING
For
Jane and Verity (as ever)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
SMART
THINKING
SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING
AND WRITING Second Edition
MATTHEW ALLEN

OXFORD
UNIVERSITY P R E S S

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS
253 Normanby Road, South Melbourne, Victoria 3205, Australia
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research,
scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in
Oxford New York
Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai
Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi
Sâo Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto
OXFORD is a trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in
certain other countries
Copyright © Matthew Allen 1997, 2004
First published 1997
Reprinted 1997, 1998, 1999, 2001
Second edition published 2004
This book is copyright. Apart from any fair dealing for the purposes
of private study, research, criticism or review as permitted under
the Copyright Act, no part may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval
system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without prior
written permission. Enquiries to be made to Oxford University Press.
Copying for educational purposes
Where copies of part or the whole of the book are made under Part
VB of the Copyright Act, the law requires that prescribed procedures
be followed. For information, contact the Copyright Agency Limited.
National Library of Australia
Cataloguing-in-Publication data:
Allen, Matthew, 1965-.
Smart thinking: skills for critical understanding & writing.
2nd ed.
Bibliography.
ISBN 0 19 551733 4.
1. Critical thinking. 2. English language - Rhetoric. 3. Reasoning
(Psychology). 4. Thought and thinking. I. Title.
153.42
Typeset by OUPANZS
Printed through Bookpac Production Services, Singapore

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Contents
Preface to First Edition viii
Preface to Second Edition ix
How to Use this Book xi

1 Smart Thinking 1
What is smart thinking? 1
How do we study smart thinking? 5
Why do we need to 'think smart'? 7

2 Claims: The Key Elements of Reasoning 9


Understanding language 10
More about claims 14
Claims and reasoning 18
Review 22

3 Linking: The Key Process in Reasoning 25


Links between claims 26
The analytical structure of reasoning 28
Learning more about the analytical structure 31
Review 37

4 Understanding the Links between Claims 39


Dependent premises 39

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Vi CONTENTS

Special functions of premises 44


The link from premises to conclusion 47
Review 53

5 More Effective Reasoning I: Better Claims 55


Well-formed claims 56
Well-founded claims 60
Review 67

6 More Effective Reasoning II: Better Links 69


Effective use of dependent premises 70
Relevance 74
Strength of support 80
Review 86

7 What Kinds of Reasoning are There? 89


Deductive and inductive reasoning 89
Categorical and propositional logic 92
Five types of reasoning 93
Review 100

8 Research, Reasoning, and Analysis 102


Reasoning and analysis 103
Information understood by where we find it 106
Information as it relates to other information 108
Information classified by the topic under investigation 109
Information as it relates to how we are using it 111
Direct and indirect sources 113
Review 117

9 Planning and Creating Your Reasoning 120


The key analytical questions 121
Using the analytical structure for planning 127
Review 132

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CONTENTS vii

1 0 Bringing It All Together: Narrative and Structure 134


Example text 134
Casting and notes on each paragraph 137
Capturing the essence of the text 146
Overall narrative flow of the text 147
Summary 149
Answers, Discussion, and Further Advice 150
Glossary of Key Terms and Concepts 174
Further Reading 186
Guide to Important Skills 190

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Preface to First Edition
The study and teaching of critical thinking (also known as informal logic) is
relatively rare in Australia. There is little to guide the keen student or teacher in the
development of skills for analysis and reasoning in everyday work and study. The
orientation of most of the available books on this subject is more traditionally
logical, and this orientation further complicates the process of teaching and
learning applied critical thinking skills, since it tends to remove the use of reasoning
and logical analysis from even its most basic social contexts.
Smart Thinking'is designed to provide a simple, but not simplistic, guide for the
development of critical thinking and analytical skills. It combines the undoubted
strengths of the informal logical approach with a newer—but often-overlooked—
insight: that reasoning and analysis are always communicative acts. I would not
pretend that one can easily resolve the epistemological tensions between, on the one
hand, the commonly held commitments to objective judgment and truth that
underpin 'logic' as a mode of analysis and, on the other, the social relativism and
intersubjectivity that a communicative-theory approach demands. However, from
a pragmatic point of view, there is considerable profit to be gained from letting
these two distinct approaches jostle alongside one another. Moreover, for all my
attempts to keep competing epistemological ideas to a minimum in Smart
Thinking, the book cannot remain purely 'practical'. Simple advice on 'better
thinking' rubs up against deep and important matters of philosophy in a way that,
I hope, creates a constructive interaction between the ease with which one can
begin to improve one's thinking and the complexity of thinking about smart
thinking.
While I myself work theoretically within post-structuralist frameworks, Smart
Thinkings bias towards communicative issues stems primarily from the very
practical experiences I had in developing and teaching a critical thinking unit
(Applied Reasoning 200) at Curtin University of Technology in Perth. On the basis
of my experiences with many hundreds of students, I am confident in asserting that
it is wrong to divorce analytical thinking from its communicative context. Outside
the narrow confines of some academic disciplines, communication takes place on a

VIII https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PREFACE TO FIRST EDITION ix

vast scale, with far too little critical analysis to support it. It is precisely at the
junction between 'knowledge as something one knows' and 'knowledge as a
function of communication' that most of us need assistance in sharpening up our
thinking skills.
My work in Applied Reasoning 200 has not only helped my own development
as a critical thinker but has given me the opportunity to test ideas and approaches
on a captive audience. So, my first debt of gratitude is to all the students who have,
in so many ways, contributed to the writing of this book. Applied Reasoning 200
also became the focal point for a series of collegia! relationships from which I have
benefited enormously. For their assistance, insights (and perseverance with often
impractical ideas), my thanks are extended to Patrick Bertola, Gina Koczberski,
Des Thornton, and especially, Eamon Murphy, all of Curtin University. Thanks
also to Will Christensen, Dennis Taylor, and Roy Jones for their positive
encouragement as heads of academic departments. I also owe a debt of gratitude to
Richard Bosworth, who some years ago, when I began to study at university, first
taught me that critical enquiry involves asking about the 'who', 'when', 'why', and
'how', as well as the 'what' that was the staple of high school study. Michelle Forster
and Emma Rooksby provided invaluable research assistance and general help; both
are fine young philosophers. Thanks, as well, to my publisher, Jill Lane, and editor,
Lucy Davison, of Oxford University Press. Finally, I could not have written this
book without the unstinting support and reassurance of my wife Jane and step-
daughter Verity; most of all, they remind me that a person cannot live on logic
alone and confirm in my mind that life must be lived, not just with analytical
reserve, but also with passion and commitment.
Matthew Allen
Perth
September 1996

Preface to Second Edition


I have been fortunate enough to find that I was right to assume that a practical
book on critical thinking skills set in the context of communication would be both
popular and necessary. I continue to be involved in teaching critical thinking in the
unit Applied Reasoning, which is now a part of some courses of study through
Open Learning Australia (REAl 1—visit http://www.ola.edu.au), and is being
revived on campus at Curtin University. I have also realised that, in writing Smart
Thinking, I myself learnt as much as I would hope for its readers and so, in the end,
it was an easy decision to produce a new edition.
This second edition reflects the experiences of teaching with Smart Thinking
over the years since it was first published. In revising it, I have found that much of
what I had originally written remains valuable, and that students have learnt from

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
x PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION

it. But I have also made some significant changes, including greater assistance in
the earlier chapters to help readers with the more complicated skills and concepts,
as well as expanding later chapters on reasoning and on research. The final chapter
is now a fully worked example of the skills that underpin the whole book, providing
a model for readers of the power and value of the approach I am outlining. I would
hope that readers will now find the sometimes-confusing journey towards greater
ability in critical thinking and reasoning just that little bit easier, and with a clearer
goal ahead.
In writing the second edition, I have been aided greatly by Jane Mummery and
Robyn Mayes, both fine teachers of critical thinking, who have struggled with the
problems of the first edition in teaching Applied Reasoning and have generously
provided advice on how I might improve it. To them both, I owe a great deal. I also
wish to thank Christine Richardson with whom I taught elements of critical
thinking and who gave me the opportunity to develop further my ideas about
reasoning and research. To my long-suffering publishers at Oxford University Press,
especially my editors Lucy McLoughlin, Anne Mulvaney, and Chris Wyness, great
thanks and apologies for all the delays. Perhaps they could ask the government
about its neglect of higher education and the consequent doubling of workloads
since I wrote the first edition. And to Jane and Verity, this book is still and always
for you both.
Matthew Allen
[email protected]
Perth
February 2003

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
How to Use this Book
To get the most out of this book, you will need to read it carefully chapter by
chapter. The book builds sequentially, so that many of the ideas and concepts
introduced in earlier chapters underpin more complex discussion of related issues
in subsequent chapters. Also, as you go, you should do the exercises in each chapter.
Do not check the answers until you have completed all of a particular exercise and
are satisfied with them. When you turn to the Answers, Discussion, and Further
Advice, you will see that, in most cases, there is further discussion of the issues and
concepts relevant to each exercise. As much as you can, don't be tempted to look at
the next set of answers until you have completed the exercises for them. Often, you
will be asked to do an exercise in order to provide you with the experience neces-
sary to get the most out of the further advice offered in the answers. And, when you
have done the exercises and checked the answers, I expect you will need to reread
and revise the chapter again.
After you have read a chapter, done the exercises, and checked the answers, look
at the Concept Check and Review Exercise at the end of the chapter. The concepts
introduced in each chapter are listed. You should briefly write down what you
know about them, then turn to the Glossary to check your answers. There are, by
contrast, no answers provided for the review questions that you will find at the end
of most chapters. If you have understood and integrated the material in each
chapter, you should be able to answer these questions confidently. If you cannot,
then it is probably a sign that you have missed something.
Finally, you should integrate what you learn about reasoning in this book with
the work or study you are doing at the moment. For example, when doing the
exercises and review questions, you will often be called upon to use information
from your own life as examples or basic material with which to do an exercise. The
whole point of this book is to give practical, applied advice. I can provide the
advice; you must apply it.
This book aims to provide you with structured information, exercises, and
reflections to guide your own learning. Your investment of time and effort in
working through this structure will provide you with considerable returns in
improving your smart thinking.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books XI
https://books.yossr.com/en/books
1
Smart Thinking

There is an inner logic, and we're taught to stay far from it


It is simple and elegant, but it's cruel and antithetic
And there's no effort to reveal it ...

Bad Religion, 'Inner Logic'

What is smart thinking?


There are many words associated with what is, loosely, termed 'thinking'. We
are often told to 'think about the issues', to 'analyse in more depth', to 'use
reasoning', or to 'be rational'. Sometimes (perhaps with reference to computers,
or to the legendary Star Trek character Mr Spock) we are told to 'be logical'.
Often students are told that they must think 'critically' if they are to succeed.
When people write essays or reports, they are usually advised to make sure that
they have a good 'argument' or that they 'explain in detail'. But do students
(and lecturers) really know what these words and phrases mean? Can we
actually identify the key skills and underlying techniques that allow us to think
better?
The answer is yes. Smart thinking means.knowing how to:
• work out and express your main ideas
• plan your communication of ideas so that they can be clearly understood
• check to see if you have covered all the important parts of your topic

https://books.yossr.com/en/books 1
2 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

• establish a framework or structure in which your basic facts and evidence


make sense
• present ideas by linking them together to convince readers of your conclusion.

Moreover, we must also relate thinking to knowledge and information (what we


think about), and the processes of communicating our ideas, either in written or
oral form. Thinking is one aspect of an integrated process of finding, analysing, and
communicating information. Your thinking begins even when you are deciding
'what' to read and write about.
'Smart thinking' can assist you in:
• working out where and how to look for the information you need
• understanding that information in relation to your own work
• deciding which information is relevant to your topic and which is not
• identifying when you need to find out more information to make sense of a
problem.

Smart thinking can also improve your capacity to set your communication in
context. It alerts you to the importance of:
• your audience and their expectations of what you are doing
• the requirements upon you to communicate in a certain way in a certain
situation
• your own assumptions and biases, and the role of society in forming those
biases, which will need to be considered and explored through your
communication.

To think smart, you must use reasoning. Reasoning is the basis of much of our
thinking. It is often described simply as the process of thinking through and
communicating our reasons for holding certain views or conclusions. Reasoning is,
however, better defined as a process of understanding and exploring the relation-
ships between the many events, objects, and ideas in our world. None of these
individual 'items' can be meaningful in and of itself. An item can only be
understood in relation to other ones. Reasoning enables us to get beyond a world
of innumerable separate events, objects, and ideas. Using reasoning, we see that all
these separate items are interconnected, and what we know about any particular
object depends on our knowledge of other objects. Sometimes the connections are
obvious; other times, they are much harder to see. Reasoning involves finding and
expressing these connections or relationships so that each individual event, object,
or idea is explicable in terms of other events, objects, or ideas.

Exercise 1 . 1
Smart thinking demands that we do more than just 'think' vaguely about things.
Before we look at reasoning, the key underlying process of thinking, let's consider
some common 'informal' ideas about thinking. Look at the four actions listed

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
SMART THINKING 3

below and, writing on a piece of paper, list some examples in your own life of
when you have successfully done these actions and why you did them. The
answers contain more discussion of each one. 2

• Ask questions (of ourselves and others)


• Seek out information
• Make connections
• Interpret and evaluate

Reasoning
Reasoning represents one of the great advances that human beings have made in
their ability to understand and make sense of the world. It has been described as a
'complex weave of abilities that help you get someone else's point, explain a
complicated idea, generate reasons for your viewpoints, evaluate the reasons given
by others, decide what information to accept or reject, see the pros as well as the
cons and so forth'.3 Yet it is also the case that reasoning does not come naturally but
must be learnt and can be improved.
Let us begin with an easy example. Imagine you hold an apple in one hand and
an orange in the other. Now, at first sight, these two objects appear to be completely
different; each would seem to be understandable only in its own terms—that is, in
a way unique to each apple and each orange. However, we are better able to
understand them and to communicate what we think about them when we start to
make connections. Here are some examples:
• An apple is not an orange.
• An apple and an orange are similar: both are pieces of fruit.
• This apple will be, roughly speaking, the same as all the other apples
I have eaten.
• If I eat this orange and I like the taste, then I can assume that
generally I will like the taste of other oranges.
• You should eat this fruit because you are hungry.

Obviously, this list makes only a few simple connections between the two
particular pieces of fruit that we are considering; it also makes a few connections
between the orange and the apple and other pieces of fruit generally; and the latter
connections relate fruit to people.
If we did not make these connections, then every time we ate an orange, for
example, it would be a new experience. We would not be able to rely on past
experience or on our experiences with other things; nor would we be able to make
any predictions about future experience. Such a world might be interesting (as each
morning you drank your orange juice and had a whole new experience), but it
would also be extremely confusing. Moreover, if you think about a more complex
example (say, deciding to study for a university degree) you can see that, without
the ability to make connections between things, you would not be able to make

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
4 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

your decision in the way that all of us take for granted (by thinking, for example,
'A university degree will help me get a better job'). When we start to make con-
nections, we are able to know things of which we have no direct experience (and
which may not yet have happened). Of course, since we live in a society in which
reasoning is accepted as the main method of processing information, we already use
reasoning, but we usually do not think about it.
Often, we can feel reasonably certain about our knowledge because it is based
on evidence of things that we do know about. For example:
In the past, when driving down the freeway after work, I have found that
there is usually a traffic jam. Because of the traffic jam, it always takes a
long time to get home. So, today, because I need to get home quickly, I
had better leave work earlier.
The conclusion that 'I had better leave work earlier' follows from the evidence
or reasons given for it. We can say that it is a 'reasonable' conclusion. Using
reasoning requires us to look for and rely on structures of connections between
separate things or events in the world; it also requires us to make an active effort to
create these structures—to make the connections that we cannot easily see.
The two main kinds of relationships that underpin these structures are:
• how things relate to one another, at any given moment (syntagmatic relation-
ships such as 'an orange is a citrus fruit' or 'citrus fruits are edible')
• how things relate to one another, over time (paradigmatic relationships such
as 'eating too many oranges made me feel sick' or 'if I want vitamin C, then I
should eat an orange').
Working out the precise relationship requires attention to a number of
'patterns' that might help us to see how one thing is linked to another. These
patterns can be understood through concepts such as:

• similarity/difference
• commonality/inconsistency
• necessity and sufficiency.
When we make these connections, we are able to function much more
effectively and to make sense of the world around us. In particular, we are more
capable of communicating our ideas and discussing knowledge with other
people.
The things, then, that we do with reasoning, as a form of communication, are:
• arguing ('You should not believe what you see on television because ... ') 4
• explaining ('Digital television has been introduced because ... ')
• making decisions CI think we should buy a digital television receiver because
... ')
• predicting the future ('I expect digital television to make pay television better
because ... ')
• exploring issues ('How will digital television link to the Internet?')

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
SMART THINKING 5

• finding answers ('Why did the government decide on a higher-quality digital


television standard?')
• justifying actions ('When first introduced, I thought subscribing to pay tele-
vision was not a good idea because ... ' ) .

So, smart thinking is about reasoning, which is about the use and communi-
cation of knowledge. Researching, reading, analysing, testing, checking, planning,
and writing all depend on understanding those interrelationships. Once you
understand that knowledge consists of innumerable interrelations between small
'bits' of information, then you will be able to find, shape, and use knowledge for
yourself.
But reasoning is also about people: the authors and audiences of arguments,
explanations, and so on. And it is in relation to the human, social aspect of
reasoning that we must really be 'smart'. Reasoning is not just formal logic; nor is
it an abstract way of thinking about ideas. It is always a social act. People always use
reasoning for particular purposes (be they economic, political, or whatever). They
all have different perspectives on the issues being debated. Their age, class, race,
gender, and ethnicity all influence the broad structures upon which they rely in
reasoning. If we forget that reasoning has this social aspect, then we will run the
risk of failing to think effectively (this point will be explored in more detail in later
chapters). The connections and relations between ideas, events, proposals, and so
on only become meaningful in the context of how, when, where, and why they are
communicated with others.

How do we study smart thinking?


Thinking about thinking
Reasoning is something we already do: all of us have learnt, in one way or another,
to think and to reason, to make connections and see relationships between various
events and attitudes in our world. So, being a smart thinker is not about becoming
a different sort of person, but about improving skills that you already have. The way
to achieve this goal (and the main emphasis within this book) is to become explic-
itly aware of the analytical processes involved in reasoning. If you do, then you will
be able to analyse complex issues more deeply, understand and process information
more effectively, and communicate your ideas convincingly.
In succeeding chapters, then, we will learn a way of talking and thinking about
reasoning that allows us to understand and use reasoning better. In particular, we
will learn about the 'analytical structure' of ideas, which is, essentially, the clearest
expression of reasoning. However, we usually encounter such structures 'embedded'
in the words we read and hear, or in so-called 'natural language'. We must learn to
distinguish more effectively between the structures and the natural language
through which it comes to us. We will also encounter the idea of 'analytical
questions', which can guide the way we think about and develop the relationships
that comprise our analytical structures.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
6 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Thinkers with attitude


Remember, smart thinking always has a social dimension: we humans are doing the
reasoning. As a result, one of the key ingredients of successful thinking and analysis,
and of the effective use of reasoning, is our own attitude. For most (if not all) of us,
our knowledge will usually consist of both the basic information or 'facts' we know,
as well as a framework or structure of broader ideas with which we interpret these
facts. Many of us are quite capable of assimilating and 'knowing' the facts, but
smart thinkers constantly assess their structures and frameworks. In the process,
they develop a much deeper and more effective appreciation of situations and
events. Smart thinkers can be confident in their reasoning, precisely because they
do not rely on too many unexamined or unquestioned assumptions.
First of all, we should always be willing to reflect on our own views and
positions—to scrutinise the way we think about the world. We might ask ourselves,
from time to time:
• Are my views consistent with one another?
• What assumptions underpin my views?
• Am I open to new ideas and alternative conclusions?
• Can I look at this issue from another perspective?

We should also be constantly asking ourselves, in relation to the issues that


matter to us:
• Why did this happen?
• What should we do next?
• What does it mean?

As we will see, questioning is the key analytical skill that enables us to develop
complex knowledge about the world in the form of structures of related ideas, so as
to communicate with other people.
It is not the answers to these questions that matter, but the very fact that we ask
them of ourselves, the willingness not to 'take things for granted' or to be satisfied
with the 'obvious answer'. Indeed, a great failure of our society is that, by and large,
we are people who believe that someone has the answer and all we have to do is
develop a clever way of finding that answer. In fact, the key skill that you need, to
be an effective and thoughtful adult who is able to engage with and understand the
world, is not an ability to find the answers: it is the ability to ask the right questions.
If you can ask the right questions, then most of the answers will come very easily.
Moreover, you will also be able to determine why others do not necessarily accept
your answers but have their own views. Questions are fundamental to reasoning.

Exercise 1.2
On a piece of paper, write down a key issue that you are dealing with at the
moment—at work, perhaps an assignment, or something significant to you; don't

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
SMART THINKING 7

choose a matter that is personal and emotional since these are often best
analysed in different ways. Then start to ask yourself, in your mind, questions that
will help to analyse that issue. As you go, write them down on the page, review
them, and add more questions. Try to ask questions that are prompted by the first
questions you thought of, questions that 'connect' the dots between the issue and
another question.

Why do we need to 'think smart'?


Basically, unless we are smart thinkers, we cannot understand the world as well as
we should; we cannot solve problems effectively and consistently; we cannot be
successful in the areas of our life that concern information. Knowledge is the 'stuff
of everyday life in the early twenty-first century. We are always being asked to find
it out, develop it, communicate it, and think about it. Smart thinking improves the
ways in which we can work with knowledge and information.
First of all, smart thinking helps you to study. All academic work requires the use
of reasoning. You want to understand the content, to digest information, pick out
the key issues to learn, grasp the underlying concepts, and come to terms with un-
familiar ideas: reasoning is the way to go. Most teachers look for reasoned explan-
ations and arguments when marking assignments. More importantly, by using
smart-thinking skills to understand context—the situations in which we learn and
communicate knowledge—you can understand the system you are in, the expec-
tations and requirements on you as students, and then fulfil those requirements.
Second, smart thinking helps you at work. Work is, by and large, about decision
making. It involves initiating change, coping with new and unfamiliar situations,
finding better ways of doing things, finding out crucial information, understanding
the people and institutions you work with, and solving complex problems. You use
reasoning to accomplish these tasks, and if you have smartened up your thinking,
then you will have more confidence in your abilities and succeed more often. In
particular, the insights gained through smart thinking will assist in promoting more
effective communication. Such communication is essential to successful business
and professional life.
Third, and perhaps most importantly, smart thinking makes you an active
member of communities. We are all members of various local and national groups
and communities. While our membership of these communities gives us certain
rights (for example, the rights of citizenship), it also entails certain responsibilities.
It is our responsibility to understand what is happening in society and to act where
necessary to conserve or change, to get involved, to make things better, and to fight
injustice. We can only pick our way through the complex tangle of opinions, asser-
tions, ideas, and assumptions that make up the dominant social world in which we
live /fwe use the skills of smart thinking. Otherwise we are just going to be swept
along without any control over events, a situation that is unhelpful for us as
individuals but worse for the overall community, to which we owe the responsib-
ilities that come with our rights.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
8 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Moreover, as the neo-punk band Bad Religion sing, there is an inner logic to
the events that surround and involve us and, very often, we are taught to stay far
from it. We often think that the best way to live our lives is to stay out of the way.
As the song 'Inner Logic' continues: 'don't ask questions, don't promote
demonstration/don't look for new consensus/don't stray from constitution'. There
are two equally undesirable extremes in this refusal to think things through. At one
extreme, staying away from the 'logic' means putting too much faith in so-called
'scientific', 'objective' knowledge (which appears as if it can never be questioned).
At the other extreme, we shy away from complexity by putting too much reliance
on individual relativism, in which each person's opinion is thought to be as good as
anyone else's. We should never assume that there can be only one right view; we
should not, in turn, presume that all views are right.
We do need to make the 'effort to reveal' the logic, to 'pierce the complexity',
not only for ourselves but for the common good. Smart thinking is how to do it.
Generally, knowledge is tied up in contexts of power and influence, and is hardly
ever 'objective' or 'neutral'. Smart thinking can help empower us in the face of
knowledge, revealing its political and social purposes, its biases and consequences,
its exclusions and errors. Thinking smart is about recognising the contexts of power
and influence in which knowledge exists. Thinking smart is about using knowledge
within and against the constraints of these contexts. It also always involves remem-
bering that our own reasoning may equally involve the exercise of power and of
influence.5

Review exercise
There is no review exercise for this chapter—move on to chapter 2. Also, there is
no need to do a concept check now. When you have finished the book, however,
return to this chapter and revise it. I am sure you will read it with a very different
perspective.

NOTES

1 From Bad Religion, Stranger than Fiction (compact disc), Dragnet, 1994, MATTCD003.
2 Developed from Josina M. Makau, Reasoning and Communication: Thinking Critically
about Arguments, Wadsworth, Belmont, CA, 1990.
3 Stephen Toulmin, Richard Rieke, and Allan Janik, An Introduction to Reasoning,
Macmillan, New York, 1984, p. 6.
4 An argument, here, does not mean a 'fight' or 'dispute' but is the technical name for
reasoning that seeks to establish a conclusion on the basis of reasons.
5 These issues—objectivity, relativism, and so on—are complex. We will encounter them
again in later chapters (chapters 6, 8, and 9). You should also be aware that there are
legitimate differences of opinion on these matters among intellectuals.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
2
Claims:
The Key Elements
of Reasoning

This chapter begins our in-depth exploration of how to use reasoning more
effectively in order to make us smart thinkers. As suggested in chapter 1 ,
learning to use reasoning better requires that we be more aware of what we
are already doing. We need to learn some basic terms and concepts with
which to talk and think about reasoning. The aim of this chapter is to
improve our awareness of how we are actually doing reasoning. The focus in
this chapter is on claims. In the next chapter we look at the process of
linking claims together to form reasoning.
There are three main areas that we will cover in this chapter:

1 We will look at language, since reasoning is a way of manipulating and


using words and statements. Language allows us to make claims about
the world. Claims are the key component of reasoning.
2 We need to understand more about the significant properties of these
claims which affect how we use them in reasoning.
3 We see how claims function differently, as premises or as conclusions,
depending on how we link them together. The conclusion is what you are
arguing for or explaining. The premises are how you get to your conclu-
sion.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
10 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Understanding language
A basic look at language
Every time we argue or explain something, we use language—regardless of whether
we are thinking to ourselves or communicating with others. As children, we learn
to use language so 'naturally' that we tend to take its use for granted. In fact, there
are many subtleties and complexities in language. Knowing something about these
can help our reasoning by giving us more conscious control over the material
(language) with which we are reasoning. There are four distinct 'levels' of language-
use that build together to create 'language' as we know it.
The first level is a word—for example, 'student' or 'reasoning'—which is the
basic unit of language. Words have meanings, usually more than one, and often
multiple meanings are 'denotative' (that is, what the word explicitly says) or
'connotative' (the more subtle, 'hidden' meanings of words). We will see, through
this book, that definitions of words are important but, for the moment, we are just
interested in words insofar as they can form statements.
When we put some words together, we get the second level of language: a
statement, such as 'there are several hundred students who have studied smart
thinking at Curtin University'. We probably think of statements as being the same
things as sentences, but they are not. In the following example we can see how one
sentence can be made up of more than one statement: 'We use reasoning everyday
of our lives, but most of us have no formal training, and the more practice and the
more training, the better we will be at it'. The first statement is 'We use reasoning
everyday of our lives'; the next is 'most of us have no formal training [in reasoning]';
the third is 'the more practice and the more training, the better we will be at it
[reasoning]'.
The third level of language-use is the text, which is made up of any group of
statements, such as the sentence above. Now, usually, the texts we encounter are
much longer than just a few statements (for example, this book is a text, as is a
newspaper article). But, remembering that we are talking about something different
to 'natural' things we read and hear, we define a text as a group of statements that
is of any length, so long as there is more than one statement and these statements
are related to one another in some way. Texts are not just lists of statements; they
are groups of connected statements. In the example of a multi-statement sentence
from the previous paragraph, as well as in single statements, words like 'but' or
'and', and punctuation like commas and semi-colons, are not included in the
statements. They act both to distinguish one statement from another and, at the
same time, to join together the various statements to make a text. Practical com-
munication via texts depends on the way these words connect the statements.
Finally, the last level of language-use is the context, which consists of all the
elements outside a particular text that make it meaningful. Contexts cannot be 'seen'
in the way, say, that the text you are now reading can be. A context for this book
would include (at least) the purposes and goals of its author and readers, the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 11

assumptions about the meanings of words and ideas that lie behind it, and other texts
that, though absent, are implicitly connected with what is being written and read
here. For example, a student who reads this book as the textbook for the Open
Learning Australia unit Applied Reasoning has a very different context to someone
who is just browsing through it, casually looking for quick ideas about critical
thinking.
Assumptions are a primary component of context. Assumptions are those ideas
or values that we 'take for granted' and do not question. To be smart thinkers we
must recognise the assumptions that surround us (including our own) and that
influence every argument and explanation. Reasoning involves making connections
between our ideas about the world, expressing them as linked claims, and
constructing a text to express that knowledge. Obviously this reasoning is a
conscious process, but it also draws upon a background of implicit or assumed
connections and structures. As we grow up and learn about our environment (from
parents, school, and so on), all sorts of connections are made for us and become
embedded in our minds, so that we do not even realise we are relying on these
structures when we think. For example:
In the nineteenth century, Australian children were often warned that the
'black bogeyman' would get them if they were naughty. This apparently
mild threat created an association in children's minds between 'Blacks'
(indigenous Australians) and something dangerous. Is it any wonder, then,
that when these children grew into adults they continued to act and think
about indigenous Australians in extremely racist ways?

What makes assumptions dangerous is not their content (unlike the


previous example, the content of assumptions may actually be correct) but,
rather, that they are not consciously considered and tested to see if they are
correct. What matters first is to be conscious of the assumption so we can ask
'is this true?'.
Smart thinkers must be capable of understanding how each of these four levels
of language use relates to one another, and of how to write good statements, link
them together to make a text, and consider the contextual factors that bear upon
their text.

Statements that are claims


Our central focus for the moment is on a particular type of statement: the claim.
Here are two examples of claims:
• Prior to the war on Iraq in 2 0 0 3 , more Australians opposed the war
than supported it.
• John Howard, Australian Prime Minister in 2 0 0 3 , determined that
Australian military forces should be deployed to participate in the war
on Iraq.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
12 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Although these statements differ in what they say, each is a claim. More
precisely, they claim to represent truly something 'real' about the world. We could
test each claim to see if it is true or not (or at least get a clearer idea of whether or
not we can accept it as true). For example, if someone claimed that John Howard
had supported the war, we could check appropriate newspaper reporting of the
time. Opinion polls conducted at the time can test the first claim, to see if there
was such a majority. All statements that are claims assert the truth of some
information or knowledge about the world.
Claims are not, as you might think, the opposite of facts. Nor does a claim
'become' a fact once we know it is true. A claim is always a claim, but the truth of
some claims is established. And a claim does not necessarily involve some personal
advantage or bias. Although in everyday speech we often use the word 'claim' to try
to distinguish between statements whose truth is suspect or that are biased and
those statements (called Tacts') whose truth is established and that are unbiased,
these distinctions are dangerously misleading. All the statements that we think of
as 'facts' are, actually, claims; they are so widely and clearly accepted as true that
they seem different from claims that are not accepted. Put simply, claims are those
statements that express beliefs or views about the way the world is or the way the
world should be. Whether they are true or not is, of course, important, but it does
not determine whether or not they are claims. The reasonableness of claims (what
we think of as 'truth') does not change their status as claim or non-claim; but it does
help us to decide what to do with claims in our reasoning (as we will see).
To emphasise this point, here are three statements that are not claims:
• Do you think Australia should continue to support all American foreign
policy decisions concerning Iraq?
• Tell me immediately what you think about Australia's war on Iraq!
• G'day!

None of these statements expresses a view about the way the world is or should
be, and hence they are not claims. The first asks for information (a question);1 the
second demands that a person do something (an order); and the third is an
exclamation. Note how we do not say 'g'day' to claim that 'this day is a good day'.
We say 'g'day' as a greeting, as a ritual use of language to begin a conversation.
Similarly, orders and questions are ways of initiating or concluding communi-
cation. A few statements may fall somewhere between the two groups (claims and
non-claims)—because they might be interpreted differently in different contexts—
but generally speaking, all statements can be seen as one or the other.
We cannot tell just from the written or spoken expression of a statement
whether or not it is a claim. Rather, we must look at the defining property of a
claim: that it asserts something to be true.2 To distinguish a claim from other sorts
of statements, we simply need to consider whether it is possible to ask 'Is this
statement true or false?'. A claim need not actually be true; it need not be false. It
just has to be possible to ask if the claim could be true or false. Consider the
following three statements. Which of them do you think are claims?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 13

• Is the world round or flat?


• The world is round.
• The world is flat.

The first statement is not a claim—we cannot ask 'Is it true or false to say "Is
the world round or flat"?'. But it is possible to ask 'Is it true or false to say "The
world is round"?'. Similarly we can ask 'Is it true or false to say "The world is flat"?'.
Hence the second and third statements are both claims, even though one is true
and one is false. Claims are about the possibility of truth or falsehood, not about
whether a claim really is true or not.

Exercise 2.1
Decide which of these statements are claims and which are not. Then write three
examples of your own of statements that are claims and three examples of
statements that are not.

a. Why did you do that?


b. There is a yellow marble on the table.
c. Get out of here!
d. Somewhere over the rainbow ...
e. We should always pay our taxes on time.
f. Cheese is made from milk.

Claims as elements of reasoning


Effective thinking skills can be elusive. Reasoning has a structure and content that
can be hard to control (as an author) and hard to discern (as a reader) when it is
expressed in normal English (so-called 'natural language'). We tend to assume that
claims are indistinguishable from their particular forms of expression, and it may
be hard to grasp just what claims do within reasoning unless we shake them loose
from their normal modes of expression. Claims may be expressed in natural
language. However claims are better understood as elements of reasoning: the basic
units of analysis in our arguments and explanations.
Written and spoken English does make claims, but draws them together and
expresses them in ways that are stylish, but which also make it harder to identify
and understand individual claims. In particular, sentences, which assist in
making English easy to write and read, can obscure the more analytical function
of the statements that these sentences express. Look, for example, at the
following:
Many Australians favour making the nation a republic. However, it is
unclear just how many Australians there are in favour of this, and until we
know and are sure that a very large majority of Australians want a republic,
we should not move too quickly to implement this change.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
14 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

How do we identify the claims? In the first sentence, there is just one claim. In
the second sentence, though, there are two claims. The first is 'it is unclear just how
many Australians there are in favour of this' (note the use of 'this' to mean 'making
the nation a republic'); the second is 'until we know and are sure that a very large
majority of Australians want a republic, we should not move too quickly to imple-
ment this change'. Note how tricky the process of identifying claims can be. In the
second sentence, the first 'and' indicates a break between two claims, but the word
'and' is later used differently to combine 'know and are sure'. Similarly, the comma
after 'however' in the second sentence indicates that a claim is starting, but later on,
a comma proves to be part of a claim. Note, too, the use of pronouns such as 'this'
and 'it', which are used as substitutes for the actual nouns that claims contain.
As another example of this distinction between 'language for expression' and
'language for analysis', claims are sometimes expressed as questions. They appear as
that special form of expression known as rhetorical questions, in which the answer to
the question is presumed. For example, 'Isn't it obvious that Australia should be a
republic?' is clearly different from 'Do you think that Australia should be a republic?'.
The first question—a rhetorical question—is simply a clever way of saying Australia
should be a republic', whereas the second question genuinely seeks an answer. Hence,
to understand fully how claims are used in reasoning, we need to be aware of the
difference between making claims as part of writing or talking, and making claims as
part of the process of reasoning. Often, the claims we make in each context will be
similar—but we cannot rely on it. Natural language, when properly put together in
a narrative sequence, is an excellent tool for expressing our arguments and explan-
ations. A danger, however, is that the requirement for proper, readable expression can
confuse and mislead the unwary about the analytical units (claims) and structures
(connections between claims) which, actually, constitute the reasoning.

Exercise 2.2
Identify the claims in the following sentences. Then write three sentences of your
own, each of which expresses a number of claims in various different ways.

a. All that glitters is gold, and this nugget glitters.


b. Isn't it obvious that this song is called 'Diamonds are a Girl's Best Friend'?
c. Silver jewellery is very common because silver is a cheap metal and it is
easily worked.

More about claims


Connections within claims
A claim provides an internal connection between at least two ideas. For example, the
claim that Australia should become a republic' provides an internal connection
between, roughly speaking, Australia' and 'republic'. Similarly, Australia should

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 15

not become a republic' also makes this connection, although the meaning of that
claim is completely different. The technical, grammatical names for the two
components within a claim are the 'subject' and the 'predicate' of the statement.
Roughly speaking, the subject is the main focus of the claim, and the predicate is
some property or consequence of, or notable point about, that subject and the way
the claim is made is to identify through the verb the link between the subject and
the predicate. Hence 'Reasoning is a skill' uses the verb 'is' to assert that reasoning
is a member of the larger set of things we know about called 'skills'. As another
example, 'Reading this book on critical thinking is no use if you are not practising
critical thinking exercises' is also a claim with a more complicated link between the
subject 'Reading this book on critical thinking', and a predicate 'not practising
critical thinking'.

Exercise 2.3
Identify the subject and the predicate in the following statements:

a. Drinking milk makes some people feel sick.


b. I do not drink milk.
c. Milk drinking is not recommended for people who are lactose-intolerant.

This property of a claim—an internal connection between two or more ideas—


is fundamental. The internal connection underpins the external links between
claims that are necessary in reasoning. While reasoning does not consist simply of
one claim, it does occur when you take a number of claims and, by varying the
pattern of interconnections, produce a 'link' from the first interconnection to the
next. Here is a simple example (we will be doing much more on this concept in
later chapters).

Reasoning is a skill. Skills can be improved by practice. The book Smart


Thinking gives you a chance to practise reasoning. Reading Smart
Thinking and doing the exercises will improve your reasoning.

See how the same ideas get used, but in a different order? These claims, because
they share the same ideas even though in some the idea is the subject and in others
it is the predicate, are well on the way to being used for reasoning. So, to reason, we
always need more than one claim, all linked together in some way. It is this internal
connection within a single claim that allows these external links to be made.

Claims that include claims


One example of the importance of grasping this process of internal connection is
provided by a special kind of claim in which an entire claim serves as one element
of another claim. We find two main uses of this kind of claim-formation. First,
there are claims such as 'George W Bush said that Saddam Hussein was an evil
dictator'. In this claim, what is being asserted is that George W Bush has said those

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
16 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

words, and not that Hussein was such a person. The claim 'Saddam Hussein was
an evil dictator' here serves as the predicate to the subject 'George W. Bush',
connected with the word 'said'. Thus, if we were to assess the truth of the claim, it
would do no good to see whether or not Hussein was a dictator or evil (even though
we probably could find much evidence to support that point), because the claim is
about what Bush said. These claims, which are essentially concerned with what
others have already claimed, are vital: we often wish to reason about another's point
of view and thus must understand how to make claims about that person and their
words.
A second and even more important use for claims within claims can be found
in claims that use propositional logic, that is, claims taking the 'if..., then...' form
so common in contemporary philosophy and computer programming. Such a
claim is, for example, 'If I am unwell, then I should go to the doctor'. Now it might
look as though there are two claims here: and, indeed, there are. However, by
placing two claims in an if/then relationship, each claim becomes a subsidiary part
of a single, much more powerful claim. What is actually being asserted in the
if/then claim is not the substance of one or the other claim but, rather, the
relationship between them. Hence 'If I am unwell, then I should go to the doctor'
asserts that it is reasonable to do something (go to the doctor) when a particular
state of affairs (feeling unwell) occurs. We will see the importance of these special
'if/then' claims in chapter 3.

Exercise 2.4
Identify the claims within a claim here, remembering that an entire claim can
serve as either predicate or subject.
a. I have been told by my doctor that drinking milk makes some people feel
sick.
b. If I drink milk, then I feel sick.
c. If a person comes to a doctor and says 'If I drink milk, then I feel sick',
then the doctor will diagnose that person as lactose-intolerant.

Scope and certainty


A statement that makes a claim about the world allows us to judge the truth or
falsity of that statement. In making this judgment, we need to consider the scope of
the claim. For example, each of these claims has a different scope:

• All Australians think global terrorism threatens this country.


• Some Australians think global terrorism threatens this country.
• A few Australians think global terrorism threatens this country.

The claims are very similar, except in their reporting of the number of
Australians who believe global terrorism threatens their country. The scope, in each

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 17

case, is determined by the different value of'all', 'some', and 'few'. Scope is not just
about numbers. It can also be seen in claims about, for example, a geographic area
('Most of Western Australia is uninhabited') or time ('For much of its history,
Australia was not populated by white people').
Certainty is another characteristic of all claims. Whether explicitly stated or
not, claims include a judgment about the likelihood or probability that what they
are claiming is true, or will become true:
• There is a high probability that Australia will suffer a major terrorist
attack in the next decade.
• There is some chance that Australia will suffer a major terrorist attack
in the next decade.
• There is virtually no chance that Australia will suffer a major terrorist
attack in the next decade.

In each case, the claims are saying something about Australia and terrorism;
they differ only in their explicit statement of the probability that the substance of
the claim will come true. Understanding how to include proper indications of
scope and certainty in the claims you write, or to recognise them in other people's
work, is crucial to being an effective reasoner. Remember, scope and certainty are
tied in with the idea that claims are asserting the truth of something. If you limit
or qualify your claims by appropriately indicating scope and certainty, then you are
thinking more clearly and therefore can write better claims.

Exercise 2.5
Identify the two components that are internally linked within each of the following
claims. Then rank claims a-c in order of scope (from widest to narrowest) and
claims d-f in order of certainty (from most certain to least certain). In each case
identify the word or words that lead you to your judgment. Then write a list of some
of the other words that can be used to indicate the scope and certainty of a claim.

a. Sometimes, when I drink milk, I feel sick.


b. Whenever I eat cheese before sleeping, I have dreams.
c. Occasionally, after eating rich food, I get indigestion.
d. It is probable that humans will live in space.
e. There is no way that humans can live in outer space.
f. I'd say the odds are 50:50 that humans will live in space.

Descriptive and value claims


Some claims assert that things are, or have been, a certain way; and some claims
make judgments about the way things should or should not be. These are
respectively called descriptive claims and value claims. For example, 'This book is
printed on white paper' describes the type of paper, whereas 'We should use less

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
18 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

paper to save trees' expresses a value judgment ('it is good to save trees'). But, to
complicate matters many, and perhaps even all, claims have some implicit value
judgment. Often we find an implicit value judgment in the words that make up the
claim. For example, 'This book is comprehensive' implies some positive value
judgment, whereas 'This book provides only an outline of reasoning techniques'
implies a more negative value judgment. So, really, there are two main sorts of value
claims: those that explicitly declare a value judgment, and those whose value
judgment is hidden in the choice of words.
There are also some claims that can legitimately be called descriptive claims.
Yet, even then, claims are almost always found in combination with other claims.
So, if there is one value claim among a series of claims, then all of them tend to
create an implied value judgment. Here we can see that the context in which we
find a claim—the purposes and processes by which a text, containing many linked
claims, is produced and received—plays a very significant role. Claims that appear
to their author as descriptive may, in the context provided by their readers,
suddenly acquire value judgments. Hence, judgments of value can rarely be made
solely on the basis of one claim; they depend on the other claims with which the
claim is linked (the text) and the circumstances in which that text is presented (the
context). Being alert to the value judgments that you read and make is a skilled
smart thinking attribute.

Exercise 2.6
Decide which of these four claims are explicit value claims and which are implicit
value claims that appear to be descriptive claims. You may also decide that some of
the claims are purely descriptive and contain no value judgments. Then write three
claims of your own, one of which is explicitly a value claim, one of which has a clear
implied value judgment, and one of which is, in your opinion, clearly descriptive.

a. Fatty foods are bad for you.


b. Regular cows' milk contains fat.
c. You should drink milk each day.
d. Regular cows' milk is a white liquid.

Claims and reasoning


Using claims as conclusions and premises
We know that reasoning is, put simply, giving reasons for one's views. We reason,
therefore, by linking claims together to form a text in which most of the linked
claims provide a reason or reasons for accepting another claim, or the linked claims
explain why another claim can be made. For example, if I said Australia should
become a republic', it would only be natural for you to ask 'why?', which would
prompt me to give you a reason: that Australia's economic relationship with Asia

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 19

would be strengthened if Australia declared its final independence from its


European origins by becoming a republic'.
The claims that act as reasons are 'premises' and the claim that is being
supported or explained is the 'conclusion'. When reasoning, we will always be
dealing with at least two claims: the claim we want people to accept and the claim
we are using to support the first claim. Almost always there are a number of
premises supporting one conclusion, but the minimum requirement is one premise
and one conclusion. A fundamental skill in reasoning is to be able to identify, in
our own and in others' work, those claims that are serving as premises to support
the claim that is acting as a conclusion. Thus we need to understand how claims
can be used as conclusions and premises.
To do so, we must remember that, before we use them in reasoning, all premises
and conclusions are the same thing: they are claims. There is nothing about a claim
on its own that makes it a conclusion or a premise. Until we decide, in our
reasoning, that claim Z will be the conclusion and claims X and Y will be the
premises, X, Y, and Z are all just claims. They only become premises and con-
clusion through the act of linking them together, as in 'Because of X and Y, my
conclusion is Z'. The difference between premises and conclusions is not
dependent on any essential qualities of the claims; it is, instead, a functional
difference. Whether a claim is a conclusion or a premise depends on the function
that the claim performs in any particular argument or explanation. What
determines that function is the relationship between one claim and another.
Let us use the following claims to demonstrate this point:
• Your car is dirty.
• You drove the car through some mud.
• You should wash your car.

And here are two very simple examples of the way we can use these claims in
reasoning, with the claims marked as [c] (conclusion) or [p] (premise) to show how
they perform different functions:
• Your car is dirty [c] because you drove through some mud [p].
• You should wash your car [c] since your car is dirty [p].

The same claim—'Your car is dirty'—is used in two different ways: first, as a
conclusion being explained and, second, as a premise. The general rule, thus
demonstrated, is that any claim can be either a conclusion or a premise depending
on how it is linked with other claims and the context in which it is used.
Conclusions and premises are very similar because both are claims. However,
within reasoning, some claims serve a different purpose to other claims. The nature of
premises and conclusions is not already laid down, magically, in the words we use to
express them, but is something that we can actively control and alter. For example, we
may read someone else's conclusion and then use it as a premise in our own reasoning.
Or, we see that the premises of someone's argument need further explanation and, by
using them as conclusions, proceed to give that explanation with our own premises.3

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
20 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Exercise 2.7
Make up four short examples of reasoning using the following claims. Make sure
that you practise using the same claim as the conclusion in one example and as
a premise in another.

• The road is wet.


• You need to drive more carefully.
• You should pay attention to what you are doing.
• Verity has just come home soaking wet.
• There was a rainstorm a few minutes ago.

More on conclusions
So, when we reason, we first of all have to decide which is the claim we are trying
to argue for or explain. This claim is the conclusion. It is not a summary, but a new
statement altogether, which may be linked to the premises but goes beyond them
to give some further information, the 'truth' of which becomes clearer because of
the premises given. The conclusion is a claim in its own right, and not merely a
restatement of the claims already made as premises.
The selection of a conclusion is dependent on the purpose of our overall
argument or explanation. First, we can use claims about the future as conclusions.
These sorts of conclusions are required when we are making a prediction, as in 'In
the future, the world will be much warmer [c] because of the effects of industrial
pollution [p]'. Predictions are always doubtful since the events they predict have
not yet happened, and thus their truth can never be established except as a
prediction. Hence they require supporting argument to make them acceptable. We
can also use claims about the past or the present to establish what is the case. Often
there are doubts about what has happened or is happening (for example, in a
criminal investigation), and argument can be used to support our conclusions on
these matters.
Second, we can use as a conclusion any claim that makes an appeal for people
(whether an individual or group) to act in a certain manner, as in the argument that
'We should reduce the production of carbon monoxide [c] because this action will
reduce the rate of global warming [p]'. Such arguments, the conclusions of which are
appeals to action, are designed to convince people to do something. Sometimes the
action required is for us to think differently, as in an argument that demands that 'You
should not think highly of governments that are reluctant to stop global warming [c]
since these governments are risking the future prosperity of all humanity [p]'.4
Conclusions such as those just discussed require arguments to convince audiences
to accept them. In both cases, it is the conclusion that is in doubt (remember that
claims are statements that may or may not be true). But other conclusions, often
about events happening in the past, are not in doubt, but still involve reasoning that
explains why the conclusion can be made. In the sentence 'We now have a problem

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 21

with global warming [c] because previous governments were blind to the con-
sequences of industrial growth and technology [p]\ the conclusion reports that there
is now a problem with global warming so that the premise can explain why this has
happened. Some explanations can be characterised as justifications, as in 'I decided to
vote for the Greens at the last federal election [c] because I am very keen to see
Australia's environment protected [p]'. In this example, the conclusion reports
something that happened so that the writer can justify why they did it.

Exercise 2.8
Try to work out what sort of conclusion is used in each of the following. Remember
to think about the purpose that the conclusion is designed to fulfil. In each
example the conclusion is the second claim in the sentence.

a. Since the bushfire threat is high in the next three months, we should
improve our fire-fighting service.
b. Since there has been no rain recently, I forecast that there will be a high
bushfire threat this coming summer.
c. Because the government failed to improve the fire services, the bushfires
that occurred in 2001 were much harder to control than in previous years.
d. The government has not done much to improve the fire-fighting service—
don't you think that it is inefficient?
e. Because the budget deficit has required the government to make many
cut-backs in spending, we have done little to increase available fire-
fighting resources [assume that a government representative is speaking].

More on premises
While a basic outline of the different types of conclusions is relatively straight-
forward, there is no similar, straightforward approach for different types of
premises. Virtually any claim you can think of can serve as a premise. Even claims
that we might normally think of as conclusions can be premises. All that premises
have to do is to be able to provide support for the conclusion (either in explaining
it or arguing for it). Thus, premises tend in most cases to be initially more accept-
able than the conclusion (though not always—see 'Strength of support' in chapter
6). Furthermore, it is misleading to think about individual premise 'types'; instead,
we should look at the way in which premises connect with one another. In short,
premises function in three ways: they make a substantive point (i.e. report
something, or provide some kind of evidence), they can define some term in the
argument, or they can frame the other premises, demonstrating more clearly the
relationship of all the other premises to the conclusion (see chapter 4 for more
details on how premises function).

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
22 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Review
Words combine to form statements, which in turn combine to form texts. No
text can be understood outside its context of use and interpretation. The most
important statements for us to consider are claims. When properly linked
together, they form a text, which is either an argument or an explanation.
Claims state, in language, the events, ideas, and things that make up our
world, asserting that what they represent is true. Claims are the key elements
from which we build our arguments and explanations. The analytical function
of claims is, however, often obscured by their mode of expression.
By understanding what claims are and what their properties are, we can
better understand how to use claims as premises and conclusions in our
reasoning. Claims have three significant properties. First, a claim always
contains an internal connection between two or more components. One or both
of these components can be a claim in its own right, but functioning differ-
ently—as an element within a claim. Second, claims always include some indi-
cation of scope and certainty, though often they are implied. Third, claims are
either descriptive (what is) or are value judgments (what ought to be). Many
claims appear to be descriptive but either contain implicit value judgments or
become value-laden when read in combination with other claims.
Claims are used as either premises or conclusions; the difference
between them is determined by how we use them in any particular act of
reasoning. Any claim can serve as a premise or conclusion. That said, we can
see how conclusion-claims must relate to the particular purposes of the
reasoning: predicting, establishing, or appealing for action, and explaining or
justifying. In the last case, the reasoning involves an explanation, whereas
the other purposes require an argument.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:

argument
assumption

audience

certainty
claim

conclusion

connotation

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
CLAIMS: THE KEY ELEMENTS OF REASONING 23

context

descriptive claim

exclamation

explanation

internal connection

order

premise

purposes of reasoning

question

scope

statement

subject

text

value claim

word

Review exercise 2
Answer briefly the following questions, giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book.

a. Is a statement the same as a sentence? Why should we distinguish


between the two?
b. What distinguishes claims from statements that are not claims?
c. Why are some claims thought of as 'facts'?
d. What are the three crucial properties of claims?
e. What is special about if/then claims?
f. What is the difference between a premise and a conclusion?
g. Are all conclusions the same? If not, why not?
h. What determines the 'type' of a particular premise?
i. What happens to claims when we express them in natural language?

NOTES

1 As we will see in chapter 8, questions can also be thought of as 'potential' claims or


'claims in question'. Here, for example, the claim 'Australia should continue to support
all American foreign policy decisions concerning Iraq' has been put under scrutiny by
turning it into a question.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
24 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

2 There is considerable philosophical argument concerning the notion of truth. Some


philosophers might wish to substitute words such as 'valid' or 'sound' in this test of a
claim, but for the practical purposes of this book, 'truth' will suffice. In particular,
however, we should recognise that value claims (described a little later in this chapter)
cannot really be true or false, but they can be judged in terms of whether or not they
are reasonable.
3 We cannot simply interchange conclusions and premises as we like and still be confi-
dent of being correct. It would, for example, be incorrect to say that 'because you
should wash your car, your car is dirty'. We need to think much more carefully about the
relationships we are asserting to be true when we decide just what exactly our premises
and conclusions are. For example, the following would be good reasoning: 'I know that
if you are told to wash your car, then it is more than likely that the car is dirty; I have
just heard someone tell you to wash your car; therefore I can infer that your car is dirty
(otherwise that person would not have told you to wash it)'. We should note here, too,
that giving premises to explain a known conclusion is contextually different from giving
premises to establish by argument the soundness of an unknown or doubtful conclu-
sion. The term 'conclusion' here merely indicates the logical function of the claim we
are explaining, and not its importance or significance. In an explanation, and from the
point of view of our audience, our premises and how they explain the conclusion are
more important than the conclusion itself.
4 Because group and individual decisions carry with them the requirement that we be
able to justify and explain our decisions to others, decision making also involves
reasoning.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
3

Linking:
The Key Process
in Reasoning
Claims are the basic material of reasoning, but they must be linked together
if we are to argue and explain our points of view. We have already seen that
claims that are linked to a conclusion by supporting it or explaining it are
called premises. A conclusion, therefore, is a claim that is supported or
explained. In this chapter we investigate this linking process in more detail.
My principal goal, again, is to give you greater awareness of how you reason,
in order to improve what you actually do.
There are four main areas we will cover in this chapter:
1 We will examine natural language for the traces of this linking. Traces are
the signals in natural language that we only half-consciously use to
develop our reasoning within a narrative-flow format (what you normally
read and write).
2 We will look at the process of linking analytically, introducing the idea
that all important relationships between claims can be shown in a
diagram. Combining the diagram with a list of claims provides a clear,
analytical structure format without the confusions of natural language.
3 To assist in understanding the analytical structure format, we will learn
about casting the reasoning of others, as a useful exercise for skill devel-
opment.
4 We consider in more detail what we need to know in order to be comfort-
able expressing our critical thoughts in such a format, including the way
in which complex argument forms can be shown using a diagram.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
26 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Links between claims


Evidence of the linking process
We can directly 'see' claims in natural language, but linking, the process of
reasoning, can only be inferred, indirectly.1 In any argument or explanation in
natural language we can find the evidence of this linking process in the words or
phrases that show or signal how one claim relates to another. We have already come
across these words. Remember these examples?
• Your car is dirty [c] because you drove through some mud [p].
• You should wash your car [c] since your car is dirty [p].
The words 'because' and 'since' do not £otm part of the claims (the premises and
conclusions) but link them together, signalling which claim is the premise and
which the conclusion. These signal words are the visible traces of the mental process
of linking.
Because of the richness and complexity of the English language, we rarely find
evidence for every act of linking. Sometimes no link words are used because the
sense of the reasoning is clear just from the arrangement of the claims; sometimes
punctuation does the job. At other times, when it is stylistically appropriate,
phrases or even sentences signal the linking process. Link words are not necessarily
written directly between the premises and the conclusion, but since their function
is not determined by their position in a text, they can nevertheless still signal which
claim is which. In all cases, the linkages are between two or more claims, so that
any link words can signal that both a premise and a conclusion are present and can
distinguish between them.
Here are some examples:
• I found out today that I had passed my exam. I was elated. [The order
of the sentences signals that the first claim is linked to the second
claim as premise to conclusion.]
• Because I felt ill, I went home from work. ['Because' signals that 'I felt
ill' is the reason that explains the conclusion 'I went home from work';
the comma serves to show that there are two claims here and, hence,
that some link can be inferred.]
• We need to learn to think: it helps us to do better at work and to do
better at university. [The colon separates the claims and, at the same
time, links them. The sense of the sentence signals the link between
the first part (the conclusion) and the second part (the premises).]
• John has passed his final exams. This means that he is a fully qualified
lawyer. [The phrase 'this means that' is the linking element here: 'this'
refers to the first claim and 'means that' signals that the second
sentence contains a conclusion. Because the second claim is identi-
fied as a conclusion and is linked to the first, we know that 'John has
passed his final exams' is a premise.]

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
LINKING: THE KEY PROCESS IN REASONING 27

• Everyone knows that Australia has great natural beauty and a marvel-
lous climate, and that makes it clear why many tourists come here.
['Everyone knows that' signals that a premise or premises are following
it, and 'that makes it clear why' links these premises to 'many tourists
come here'—the conclusion that these premises explain.]

Exercise 3 . 1
Here are the five examples from above. Rewrite each of them so that the
reasoning is the same (i.e. the same premise and same conclusion) but in a
different way, thus helping you to see how natural language can vary widely and
that there is an underlying logic which can be expressed in various ways.

a. I found out today that I had passed my exam. I was elated.


b. Because I felt ill, I went home from work.
c. We need to learn to think: it helps us to do better at work and to do better
at university.
d. John has passed his final exams. This means that he is a fully qualified
lawyer.
e. Everyone knows that Australia has great natural beauty and a marvellous
climate, and that makes it clear why many tourists come here.

Exercise 3.2
Here are three claims. Using the last claim as your conclusion and the first
two as premises, write three different arguments in natural language and
using a variety of different linking formations. Monitor the way in which the
words reflect and signal your mental processes of linking premises and
conclusions.
• The road is wet.
• Wet roads increase the risk of accident.
• You should drive more carefully.

The problem of understanding linkages


There are many different words and phrases that appear in natural language to
link claims together explicitly. There are also many ways of writing claims so they
are clearly linked. But the linkages are not dependent on having the link words
there in your writing. If you think, for example, that 'Australia should become a
republic because this change will make Australia a more independent nation',
then the linkage of this conclusion with this premise occurs because you think it
is so (so long as you have sound reasons for that thought). Link words such as
'because' are very useful as signposts, which you can use to help others follow

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
28 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

your reasoning, but they are the result of your thought processes. Simply putting
in a word such as 'thus' or 'because' cannot make unlinked claims magically
become an argument.
In other words, we must think through the analytical structure of our ideas
before we express them in words. If we do this, and have some proficiency in
writing, then the proper signals and traces of our analysis will emerge through our
texts. If we simply learn to 'write' (rather than 'think'), then it is unlikely that our
analysis will improve. No matter how hard we try to 'write better', we will often
fail.2
The complex ways in which we signal the links in language are well suited to
the requirements of naturally expressing our arguments and explanations. But they
impede us in trying to understand and control our reasoning processes. First of all,
links between claims precede and exist independently of their written expression.
Because of the ways in which we use language, it is often hard to see the 'logic' in
what someone is saying or writing, and probably harder still to write and speak
ourselves in ways that make clear to our audience just what the reasoning is behind
our views. The solution is to find a format or way of writing that breaks reasoning
down into two components: first, the claims and, second, the way in which they
are linked together.

The analytical structure of reasoning


Representing the analytical structure
There two ways of understanding what we read and write. First, there is what I am
calling the narrativeflow,that is, words arranged into sentences, and then divided
into paragraphs. Second, there is the analytical structure, which is expressed in a list
of claims and a diagram or picture showing how they are related to one another.
Imagine that we have been asked to give our views on the environment by stating
one action that people should take to help improve the world's environment. The
following is an argument on this topic in the narrative flow format:
All motor cars should be fitted with devices that reduce the pollution
caused by their exhausts. My reasoning for this view is as follows. Car
exhaust emissions are one of the most significant causes of air
pollution, and if we are going to tackle the problem of improving the
environment, we should concentrate on the major causes of pollution.
Also, it is relatively simple to fit the appropriate anti-pollution device
and will not cause dramatic social and economic upheavals in the way
people live.

But there is another way to express the argument, picking out the key claims
and the links between them:
1. All motor cars should be fitted with devices that reduce the pollution
caused by their exhausts.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
LINKING: THE KEY PROCESS IN REASONING 29

2. Car exhaust emissions are one of the most significant causes of air
pollution.
3. If we are going to tackle the problem of improving the environment,
we should concentrate on the major causes of pollution.
4. It is relatively simple to fit the appropriate anti-pollution device.
5. Fitting appropriate anti-pollution devices will not cause dramatic
social and economic upheavals in the way people live.

©*©+©+©
Y

©
Can you see how the two forms (narrative flow and analytic structure) say
roughly the same thing? In the narrative flow, the linking phrase 'My reasoning for
this view is as follows' signals that the following claims are premises for the con-
clusion before them. In the diagram, this connection is indicated by the arrow
symbol [-1] connecting claims 2 - 5 with claim 1. In such a diagram we always put
the conclusion-claim at the bottom (no matter what number we give it). We do this
because, logically, the premises lead to the conclusion, and positioning the con-
clusion at the bottom reminds us of this crucial process. So, obviously, the premises
go above the conclusion.
Certain words in the narrative flow, such as 'and' and 'also', are not included in
the numbered list of claims. Why? Well, because the work that those words do
(tying the premises together) is shown in the analytical structure diagram by the
plus symbol (+). Furthermore, to indicate that all four premises work together to
support the conclusion, the diagram uses a horizontal line to 'group' these premises
( ). Finally, note that claims explicitly state the missing subject which was not
included in the narrative flow.

What the analytical structure format offers


The analytical structure format, then, is a much clearer way of showing the exact
claims being made and the ways in which they relate to one another. This
format, by representing the connections between claims through the standard-
ised form of the diagram, avoids all of the vagaries of the English language that
we have already seen, with its myriad ways of signalling what is the conclusion
and what are the premises. By listing the claims as distinct entities, it also over-
comes complex sentence formations, with multiple claims within sentences,

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
30 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

claims within claims, half-expressed claims, and so on. All the potentially
confusing 'short-hand' use of pronouns, such as 'this' and 'it', and implicit cross-
referencing is removed in favour of precisely written claims. Finally, the
diagram, with grouped premises, clarifies all of the clever ways of writing that
make English interesting to read but that mean it is hard to recognise just
exactly which premise leads to which conclusion, and in combination with
which other premises.
Here is a more complex example of how one argument can be expressed in
two different formats—as narrative flow and as analytical structure. While
there is much about this argument that you may not yet understand (and we
explore the details in later chapters), for the moment, just use it as a point of
comparison between the two formats. First, here is the underlying structure,
expressed as a list of claims and a diagram to show how they relate to one
another.
1. The Internet has no single regulatory
body to impose censorship. l )
2. The Internet is hard to censor consis-
tently and reliably.
3. The Internet is a new communications
medium that is available for anyone to
use.
4. Vast amounts of violent and porno-
graphic material are available on the
Internet.
5. Children often have access to the
Internet.
6. Children will, sooner or later, view
violent and pornographic material on
the Internet.
And here is how we might write this argument in natural language.

We need to be keenly aware that children will, sooner or later, view violent
and pornographic material on the Internet. It is a new communications
medium that is available for anyone to use. The 'Net', since it has no
single regulatory body to impose censorship, cannot be consistently and
reliably censored, meaning that vast amounts of violent and pornographic
material are available on it, and as we know, children often have access to
the Internet.

Exercise 3.3
Using the above example about the Internet, briefly list the differences and
similarities between the two formats. Check the answers carefully.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
LINKING: THE KEY PROCESS IN REASONING 31

For simple examples, such as the first one I gave, it may seem foolish to use
another format when the narrative flow (with which we are all more familiar) seems
to work well enough. Equally it may seem that, in longer examples, such as the
second one, the analytical structure only complicates the business. These obser-
vations miss the point: we need to be able to see the content and structure of
reasoning (claims and a diagram) clearly before we can learn about, and thus
smarten up, our thinking.

Learning more about the analytical structure


The analytical structure behind narrative flow
The primary purpose of the analytical structure format is to assist you in planning
your own writing. However it is very useful to look at other people's reasoning as a
way of learning about it. We can recover this analytical structure by, first, finding
the claims being made and, second, grasping the connections between them (some
signals of which can be found in the traces of reasoning represented by any linking
words or phrases). Before moving on to look at how we can use the analytical
structure in our own writing, let us use it as a tool to understanding other people's
reasoning.

Casting
The process by which we recover an analytical structure from a written argument
is called 'casting'.3 I will work through an example, step by step, and then provide
some practice examples. We will use the following natural argument—a very simple
one that I have constructed to help demonstrate this process.

Let's consider the facts. Chemical factories are very dangerous to live
nearby and one has been built near your house. You'd be crazy to put
yourself in danger, no? That's why you should move and live somewhere
else.

Before beginning, make sure you understand what you are reading and
remember that you are not doing the reasoning here and must try to stay true to
what is written, even if you disagree with it.
So, what is the first step? Earlier in this chapter, we looked at how natural
language contains 'traces' of reasoning—words that are not part of the claims, but
which represent the way the author is linking those claims together. I will under-
line the words that signal reasoning:

Let's consider the facts. Chemical factories are very dangerous to live
nearby and one has been built near your house. You'd be crazy to put your-
self in danger, no? That's why you should move and live somewhere else.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
32 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

The second step is the crucial one: identify and mark the claims that are being
made. We have already looked at the properties of claims in chapter 2 and here you
see why that discussion is so important. The easiest way to mark these claims is by
putting them in parentheses. I have also numbered the claims because we need to
diagram their interrelationship later.
Let's consider the facts. (Chemical factories are very dangerous to live
nearby) 1 and (one has been built near your house) 2 . (You'd be crazy to
put yourself in danger) 3 , no? That's why (you should move and live some-
where else) 4.

Finally, we need to draw a diagram that shows how these claims link together.
The conclusion always comes last and the premises go above it.

0 + 0+ ©
¥

©
How did I work out what the conclusion was? Look at the linking phrase
'That's why' in the last line. 'That' refers to all the things previously said and 'why'
here means 'these are the reasons that explain or justify why something else is
reasonable'. So, on that basis, I have determined that the author intended the last
claim as the conclusion, with the other claims being the premises that form one
reason why that conclusion is justified.
Also, note that I have had to deal with a contracted claim: 'one has been built
near your house'. If we were writing this claim out formally, it would be 'A chemical
factory has been built near the house where you live' but, in natural language, the
narrative flow means the author instead has written 'one', referring back to 'a
chemical factory' in the first claim and 'your house', implying a connection to 'live'
in the first claim. A key part of good casting (and indeed good reading) is to be able
to see the contractions necessary for good narrative flow and yet recognise the
substance of the analytical claims being made.

Exercise 3.4
Now you practise it. Here are four short arguments or explanations, each with a
different structure, and each with a little 'trick' to watch out for. Try underlining
the signals of linking, delineating the claims, and, using a diagram, show how
they relate to one another. Check the answers carefully for more advice on casting.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
LINKING: THE KEY PROCESS IN REASONING 33

Remember, what matters most here is correctly identifying the claims—and


claims may not be written out as 'neatly' as you would like.

a. I should not buy a car at the moment. I have just lost my driver's licence,
and besides, I can't afford it.
b. Nicole Kidman is an international movie star, and I know that, as a general
rule, international movie stars get paid a lot of money. Therefore, it is
obvious that Nicole Kidman is well paid.
c. I have not got a university education, whereas several of my colleagues do.
All of them have recently received promotions, but I did not receive one.
Given that we are all roughly equal in our job performance, I would have
to conclude that a university education really helps one to get ahead in a
career.
d. What was the explanation for Sydney beating Beijing for the 2 0 0 0
Olympics? There were two main reasons. The Sydney organisers did a
better job of lobbying the International Olympic Committee delegates and,
because of political crises in China at the time and perceived doubts about
Beijing's quality of services and venues, Sydney offered a much safer
venue for a successful Olympic games.

If you have checked the answers to these four problems, you will realise that
there is a lot more to learn about exactly how reasoning works in linking claims
together. It is not simply a matter of working out which claims are the premises and
which are the conclusions. You should also realise that casting is not an exact
science—it is a tool to help you unpick the reasoning of others and, for our
purposes, is mainly designed to help you get better at your own use of analytical
structures.

Using the analytical structure for planning


Communication involves much more than just reasoning, and that is why we do
not usually communicate via diagrams and lists of claims. But, that said, when we
want to express our arguments and explanations clearly and effectively, we need to
think carefully about the analytical structure that lies behind the narrative ex-
pression of reasoning. It is hard to recover this structure precisely from what you
read because authors themselves are often not in control of their reasoning. It is also
tricky simultaneously to write a narrative flow and reason analytically. So, before we
write, we should plan our work on the basis of the reasoning that we wish to
'embed' within our written expression. A very effective way to do this planning is
to use the analytical structure format. And, by properly planning our work, we will
dramatically improve the quality and readability of our written and oral com-
munication.
How do we develop an analytical structure format? First of all, start thinking
about structure and the logical connections between your ideas, rather than how
you will actually write them.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
34 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

1 Decide what your conclusion will be. Write this claim out carefully,
expressing exactly what you mean. Number it T \
2 Then think about the reasons that you are giving for this conclusion. These
reasons must be written as proper claims, this time serving as premises that
either explain how that conclusion comes about or show why it should be
accepted. Try to keep related premises together, but as the diagram will show
these relationships clearly, it is not essential to group them perfectly. Write
them out, making sure that you do not use pronouns but express each claim
so that it makes sense in and of itself. Number them from ' 2 ' onwards. Focus
on giving the main reasons for the conclusion at this stage.
3 Begin to draw the diagram to show the relationships between the claims. At
this stage the key point is to realise that the symbols you draw in the diagram
do not make the reasoning. They are, instead, a representation of the implied
links that come from the way you have constructed your claims. Use the line
underneath a group of related premises; use the arrow to show a premise-to-
conclusion relationship.
4 Stop and think: are you missing any claims? do you need more premises? have
you got the relationships the way you want them to be?
5 Make changes if required, adding claims and redrawing the diagram if need
be. If necessary, repeat step 4 .

Here are five important points to remember when doing this process:

Each claim must stand on its own. Do not include pronouns that refer to
nouns elsewhere in the argument. Thus, 'Illegal immigrants are treated badly
in Australia is a well-written claim, whereas 'They are treated badly in
Australia is not—who are the 'they' referred to here?
Do not include signals of reasoning in claims: 'Therefore illegal immigrants
are treated badly in Australia' is not a proper claim—the word 'therefore' does
not belong since the diagram will show that this claim is the conclusion.
Each claim must imply links to other claims which, when added together,
show the reasoning. 'Refugees are treated badly in Australia' and 'Australia
violates international human rights treaties' don't connect with one another
unless there are other claims. The word Australia appears in both, but other
claims involving internal connections between, say, refugees and international
human rights must also be included.
You cannot use the symbols (the line and arrow) for just any purpose.
Simply drawing extra arrows or lines does not work: the relationships
signalled by these symbols must be there already in the claims.
Do not be afraid to revise and rewrite. Changing the wording of the claims,
moving them around so they fit together logically is the reason you do this
process. It is called 'iteration'—you do one version, review it, see if it makes
sense, and, if not, you change it and review again.

In later chapters we will explore the subtleties of this process; for now, practise
the method as you understand it at the moment.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
LINKING: THE KEY PROCESS IN REASONING 35

Exercise 3.5
Choose an issue or topic about which you have some knowledge. If possible,
choose a topic that relates to something you are studying; alternatively, use as the
basis for your argument some topic that is important to you at the moment. Follow
the method outlined above, concentrating on writing clear, single claims and
using the diagram to show their interrelation. Then check the answers for a
discussion of common mistakes that people make. After you have checked for
mistakes, try again.

Complex analytical structures


A simple argument or explanation is one in which one 'layer' of claims (the
premises) links to another claim (the conclusion). In a simple argument the
premises are on one level and the conclusion on a second. There may be more than
one arrow in the diagram for a simple argument, but each arrow marks out a
separate reason that is directly connected to the conclusion. A complex argument or
explanation (such as that in exercise 3.3), on the other hand, has an analytical
structure with more than two levels of connection. The purpose of each layer of
claims is to show or explain the claim to which they lead via the arrow. As we will
see in chapter 5, such structures make our reasoning more effective.
A complex structure is easy to understand once we realise that it is 'built up'
from a group of simple arguments. Here are two simple arguments; the important
thing to note is that they share a common claim:

1. Australia is a multicultural society.


2. There are people from many different ethnic communities living in
Australia.
3. Different ethnic and racial communities contribute different cultures
to a society.
4. Government policies and widespread community attitudes encourage
these different cultures to mix together and flourish.

and

5. Australia is a tolerant and interesting nation.


6. Multicultural societies show more tolerance towards different groups.
7. Multicultural societies are more interesting than those in which one
culture dominates at the expense of other possible cultures.
1. Australia is a multicultural society.
Claim 1 appears twice. In the first example it is being used as the conclusion
(and thus will come below claims 2—4 in the diagram). In the second example,
claim 1 is functioning as a premise and, thus, goes with the other premises above
claim 5. Because of the common claim, we can combine the two simple examples
to produce a more complex structure, whose relationship would be easily

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
36 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

diagrammed. Because the first layer of the diagram does not lead directly to the
conclusion, but instead to claim 1, we can call the argument supporting claim 1 a
sub-argument. It is subsidiary (though still important) to the main argument for
claim 5. We just add one diagram to the other, overlapping the common claim:

A; 1 7*-

W© -0
Y

©
Theoretically, there is no limit to the ways that simple arguments can combine
in this manner, but for practical purposes, we may want to limit ourselves to no
more than three or four levels of claims, so that the process does not become
unwieldy. But it is crucial that we understand the basic idea behind complex
structures. Any conclusion is, at base, a claim for which premises are being given.
There is nothing to stop that claim from simultaneously serving as a premise itself,
which leads to another conclusion.

Exercise 3.6
Let us return to casting to assist our examination of complex structures. To help
you understand them, work through the following exercise and then refer to the
answers. There is more guidance there about how to cast but, until you have tried
it yourself, you will not be able to understand that assistance. You must cast this
argument, realising that it has a complex argument structure.
The current Australian government is, in many ways, challenging the role of
the United Nations as a body that promotes action by member nations to
maintain and extend human rights within those nations' own jurisdiction.
This challenge has a distinct and dangerous consequence for Australia
(quite apart from arguments about its dubious morality) because the chal-
lenge puts Australia in conflict with most other nations of the world over
human rights and Australian trade and foreign relations are likely to suffer
in the long run. By definition, this long-term result is dangerous. I believe
that the government's role should be to work to avoid danger and, therefore,

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
LINKING: THE KEY PROCESS IN REASONING 37

I believe the government's current approach to the UN over human rights


is incorrect.

Review
In this chapter we have looked at the key process of reasoning: linking. When
developing arguments and explanations, we link information expressed as
claims. In naturally expressed reasoning, the evidence for this process can be
found in certain words and phrases, or even in the arrangement of the claims.
But, to understand and control reasoning better, this natural expression is
inadequate. It is better to work with a format that shows the analytical
structure of reasoning more accurately and consistently. This format may not
be suitable for communicating, but it is a tremendous tool for understanding
and controlling reasoning in our minds.
The analytical structure of reasoning can be shown by separating an
argument or explanation into a list of claims, the interrelationships of
which are represented in a diagram using standardised symbols. We can
combine a number of simple structures into complex, overlapping, and
more effective reasoning. All the intricacies of reasoning can be reduced
to a much simpler format. Our initial puzzlement results, not from the
complexity of the structured format, but from our unfamiliarity with it. The
analytical structure of other people's arguments and explanations can, if
we wish, be recovered by 'casting' them into the structured format.
However, the analytical structure format is more useful as a tool for plan-
ning and thinking about our own reasoning than as a means of direct
communication.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:

analytical structure
casting

complex structure

link words
list of claims

narrative flow
simple structure

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
38 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

structure diagram

sub-argument

Review exercise 3
Answer briefly the following questions, giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book.

a. What happens to claims when they are linked together so that one gives a
reason for the other?
b. What traces of this linking process can we find in natural language?
c. What are the symbols in a structure diagram used for?
d. Are claims, when written in the analytical structure format, expressed
differently from those in natural language?
e. What are the similarities and differences between narrative flow and
analytical structure?
f. How do simple and complex reasoning structures differ?
g. Can a claim, in one example of reasoning, serve (in relation to a number
of claims) as both a conclusion and a premise at the same time?
h. What advantages and disadvantages are there in learning to use the analyt-
ical structure format?

NOTES

1 There is disagreement among philosophers about whether reasoning takes place directly
in language, or indirectly in the concepts that are expressed through language. For the
purposes of this book, I will take the second position. Of course, if an argument is well
written, then the indirect structure should be very clear. However, such clarity is rare in
most commonplace language.
2 While I focus on analysis in this book, I do not wish to understate the importance of
clear written expression. For more information, consult any of the many good books on
written communication that are available.
3 The casting method is commonly used in reasoning textbooks. It was developed princi-
pally by Michael Scriven. For an excellent, in-depth look at casting, see J . Rudinow and
V. Barry, Invitation to Critical Thinking, Wadsworth, Belmont, CA, 2 0 0 3 .

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
4

Understanding the
Links between Claims
Linking claims involves two distinct processes, as signalled by the + and 4
symbols used in analytical structure diagrams. The first process involves con-
nections between premises and other premises; the second between premises and
a conclusion. We must explore these links in more detail in order to understand,
first, the analysis that lies behind such connections and, second, how to represent
them accurately in the analytical structure format. Of course, in practice, the
process of representation often allows us to clarify what we are thinking.
This chapter will cover three main issues:

1 We will look at the way premises almost always work with other premises
in providing a reason for a conclusion. What we think of as 'a reason' may,
in the analytical structure, require many claims to express all its complex-
ities. These claims add together to form a chain of dependent premises.
2 We will extend this discussion by exploring the way in which, within a
group of premises, there can be a premise that links the rest of the prem-
ises to the conclusions, and/or a premise that states a definition, making
the other premises explicable.
3 We will look at the way links are made between premises and conclusions
to better understand the process of making premises support a conclusion.

Dependent premises
Using a group of premises
A 'reason' for a conclusion usually involves many complex ideas. It will
probably require more than one premise to express all of these ideas. All such

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
40 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

premises relating to a particular 'reason' are dependent on one another and thus are
shown, in the diagram, as being linked along the same line. Dependency involves
one of the key qualities of claims that we looked at in chapter 2: that within a single
claim there is an internal connection between two (and, occasionally, more than
two) ideas.
In the following claim, the two component parts are (a) and (b):
The Internet (a) has greatly increased the amount of information readily
available to researchers (b).

Imagine we are using it to argue for another claim:


The Internet (a) has increased the amount of work that researchers need
to do (c).

The first claim only relates to the conclusion via a third claim:
The more information available to researchers (b), the more work they
must do (c).

By adding these two claims together, the internal connection between the
Internet and more information (a-b) is combined with the connection between
more information and more work (b—c) to establish the conclusion's claim that the
Internet leads to more work (a—c). The significance of these two premises working
together is clear: most people would assume that the likely conclusion to a claim
that 'The Internet has greatly increased the amount of information readily available
to researchers' is that it has made their job easier; only by combining premises can
we support the opposite view.
Here is another example, this time written in the analytical structure for-
mat:
1. Australia's natural environment should be protected.
2. The Australian natural environment is very beautiful.
3. Beautiful natural environments make a country a popular site for
international tourism.
4. International tourism is very beneficial to a nation's economy.
5. If something is of benefit to the national economy, then it should be
protected.

0
https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 41

If you look carefully, you will see that, individually, none of the premises
support the conclusion. How, for example, does a claim about the economic
benefits of tourism help us to accept that Australia's natural environment should be
protected? It does not, unless it is combined with all the other premises. In adding
all four premises together in this manner, there is a process of cross-linking going
on, in which a connection between two ideas in one claim is extended to a third
idea via another claim, and so on, through to the conclusion. This argument is
giving one reason—regarding economic benefit—for protecting the Australian
environment. The way this reason leads to the conclusion is too complex, however,
to be handled by just one or two premises. Instead, to make sure that the relation-
ship of economics to the environment is made clear, four premises are added
together in a group.

Exercise 4.1
Write two arguments or explanations (expressed as a list of claims) that match the
following generic argument structure. Choose issues about which you have some
knowledge or that are important to you at the moment.

0^0 Y

0
Using independent premises
There is nothing in the analytical structure as such that prevents us from using
single, independent premises where each premise offers a reason for the con-
clusion that is independent of other premises. Here is another version of the
example about the environment, but this time none of the premises are
dependent on one another. Note the three arrows, one for each 'reason', in the
diagram.
1. Australia's natural environment should be protected.
2. Environmental protection improves the quality of life for all
Australians.
3. Protecting the natural environment will benefit the economy.
4. If Australia's natural environment is looked after, then other countries
might follow our example.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
42 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

While, obviously, these three reasons are broadly concerned with the same issue,
in this argument they are offered independently: no one claim needs any of the
others for the argument to make sense. I could, quite legitimately, find out that
claim 3 is wrong and yet still be convinced by claims 2 and 4 to accept claim 1. In
a dependent chain, if one of the three claims were to 'fall out' in this way, then the
entire reason expressed by that chain would be invalidated.
Now compare the previous example to the following variation on our argu-
ment, which demonstrates how to use, in one analytical structure, a combination
of dependent and independent premises:
1. Australia's natural environment should be protected.
2. Protecting the natural environment will encourage tourism.
3. Increased tourism will benefit the economy.
4. Environmental protection improves the quality of life for all
Australians.
5. If Australia's natural environment is looked after, then other countries
might follow our example.
6. It would be very good if other countries also protected their natural
environments.

©.©©©,©
Ni. Y

a
Exercise 4.2
Write two arguments or explanations (expressed as a list of claims) that match the
following generic argument structure. Choose issues about which you have some
knowledge or that are important to you at the moment.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 43

If
The weakness of independent premises
Independent premises are easier to generate, because we can quickly think of a
reason for our conclusion and then jump to expressing it as a single claim. But the
resulting independent premises are not strong. They reflect either a lack of insight
into the complexity of (most) problems or a failure to recognise that our audience
may not be as clever as us at grasping these complexities implicitly. Indeed, there
are no genuinely independent premises. What we tend to think of initially as being
a single, independent premise is often two (or more) dependent claims; alter-
natively it may well be a single claim, but one that is dependent on another claim,
which we have failed to recognise.
In the following argument, claims 2 and 3 are offered as independent premises:
1. Australia's natural environment should be protected.
2. Tourism will benefit the economy.
3. Environmental protection improves the quality of life for all
Australians, which is something we all want.

If
However, claim 2 only supports the conclusion when it is read together with
the implied (that is, unstated) premise that:

4. Protecting the natural environment will make Australia a popular


tourist destination.

Claim 3 is, when we look closely, a clever way of adding together, in written
form, two dependent claims:
3. Environmental protection improves the quality of life for all
Australians.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
44 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

5. All Australians want to improve their quality of life.

©.0 ©.0
©
In technical terms, these 'extra premises explicitly state the necessary cross-
linking between the claims' internal connections. More generally, the premises
make clear implied information, which in the original argument would have had
to be inferred by its audience for it to make sense. In other words, adding these
premises moves the information they contain from the implied context to the
actual text. In practice, we can produce and use analytical structures with in-
dependent premises, but it is rare that these structures will be well thought out and
careful. They are, more usually, a sign that we have not explicitly considered some
further connection that should be shown in the analytical structure as a chain of
dependent premises. We will return to this issue in chapter 6, where we consider
how independent premises can only work effectively when their audience can
readily supply the hidden, implied extra premises on which they are dependent.

Special functions of premises


In the groups of premises that we have explored in the first section of this chapter,
not all premises will perform the same function. Basically, there are three functions
for a premise: to make a substantive point, to provide a framework by which
substantive premises can be shown to relate to the conclusion, or to define a term
in such a way that premises make sense. We will now look in detail at the latter two,
special functions of premises.

Premises that provide a framework


When premises combine to form one reason, they usually perform different
functions: each premise provides one part of the reason, but is a different type of
component. Very often, one claim in particular in a chain of dependent premises
will serve a special role in supporting the conclusion. Consider the following
argument:
1. Australia's education system should be properly funded by the
government.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 45

2. Australia's education system is vital to the future well-being of the


nation.
3. If something is vital to the future well-being of the nation, then it
should be properly funded by the government.

The premises, claims 2 and 3, are dependent on one another. But each
performs a different function as they work together to establish the conclusion.
Claim 2 is about a specific item ('Australia's education system'); claim 3, in
contrast, is much more general ('something vital to the future well-being of the
nation').
I could change the specific focus of the argument, and yet this general claim
would remain the same:
1. Australia's defence forces should be properly funded by the
government.
2. Australia's defence forces are vital to the future well-being of the
nation.
3. If something is vital to the future well-being of the nation, then it
should be properly funded by the government.

Although the substance of the argument has changed, claim 3 remains the
same. This situation prompts us to ask what task claim 3 is performing in each of
these arguments. Through the cross-linking of ideas within each claim, claim 3 is
showing why it is that the specific premise stated should give rise to the particular
conclusion. In effect, claim 3 answers the implicit question 'why does the first
premise lead me to the conclusion?'. We can call claims that function like claim 3
'framingpremises.
A framing premise shows how or why a particular case or piece of evidence
relates to the conclusion, usually by claiming that there is some 'general rule'
guiding what to do in the sort of case raised by the other premise(s). A 'reason'
will, almost always, consist of at least two premises performing two different
functions. One or more premises function to give some important information or
evidence that, on its own, is not necessarily related to the conclusion; another
premise gives the framework that shows why the information given does indeed
lead to the conclusion. The precise function of a framing premise, however,
cannot be determined in isolation. It is always dependent on the way in which the
other premises are trying to establish the conclusion. The relationship between a
premise and another premise, then, can only be made by also thinking about the
relationship between all the premises and the conclusion. Smart thinking is only
possible when we recognise the frameworks on which we and others rely.

Exercise 4.3
Identify the framing premises in the following natural arguments (the conclusion
is italicised, but you will need to identify the premises and think about how they
relate to one another and to the conclusion). Then go back to the arguments you

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
46 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

wrote in exercise 4.2: what framing premises should be added to the premises
you have already written?
a. Theresa is ill today, and as a result, she is off work. I mean, if one is sick,
then one should not come to work.
b. When the voters elect politicians, they are, essentially, placing their trust
in those politicians. Corrupt politicians have abused the public's trust in
them, and when someone abuses your trust, they should be punished.
That is why corrupt politicians should be sent to jail.
c. All human life is worth protecting, and capital punishment involves taking
a human life. Hence we should oppose capital punishment.

Premises that provide a definition


In a dependent chain, we sometimes need to include a premise that provides a defi-
nition. Definitions tell the audience the meaning of a particular word or phrase
found in the other premises and/or conclusion. Definitions are only meaningful in
concert with the other claims in the argument or explanation (the ones that actu-
ally use the term being defined by the definition). There is little value in simply
giving a definition for its own sake; it must be linked in with other premises that
depend on that definition. For example:

1. Australians are likely to win more Academy Awards in future.


2. 'Australians' means actors, writers, directors, and so on who have
lived and worked in Australia, even if they now live overseas.
3. Australians are increasingly involved in making successful films.
4. Successful films attract the most Academy Award nominations.

0.©,0 1

©
Claim 2 provides the definition. It is necessary to give it in this argument
because many people might imagine that Australians' means people actually living
and working in Australia, whereas the person making this argument is simply
talking about a more general category of Australians (for example, the actor Nicole
Kidman or the director Bruce Beresford). Claim 2 is only meaningful as a defini-
tion because of the way it relates to the other claims.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 47

Definitions are often crucial in reasoning. While many words that we use are
'obvious' in their meaning, others are more complex. Sometimes we want to use
words that have a 'common-sense' meaning that is different from the meaning we
want to convey in our own argument or explanation (like 'claim' in chapter 2 ) .
Good definitions ensure that the other premises relying on a definition can be
understood by our audiences when, without the definition, there would be a risk
of the premises being misinterpreted. There are four types of definition. Here are
some examples:
By 'regulate the free market' I mean:
• action taken by the government such as requiring that accounts be
lodged with the Australian Securities and Investments Commission
• something like placing a speed-limiting device on an engine to stop it
going too fast
• government actions requiring businesses to perform according to
policy rather than market forces
• the opposite of letting innumerable individual decisions about demand
and supply determine market interactions.
The first case is a definition by example. Such definitions are useful only where
the audience will understand the connection between the general definition and
specific situation in the example. In the second case, the definition becomes clear
via a comparison to a similar situation; these definitions are very useful where the
intended audience does not know enough about the topic to be given an example
but can, through an appropriate comparison, draw upon their knowledge of other
topics. The third case gives an analytic definition, which uses many words to define
some smaller phrase. Here the advantage is that you do not need to keep repeating
the longer and more precise definition; instead you can rely on the smaller phrase.
The final definition is by negation, in which a term's definition is established simply
by saying what it is not.

Exercise 4.4
Use each of the four methods to provide a definition for the phrase 'studying
critical thinking' in the claim 'studying critical thinking should be part of all
university curricula'.

The link from premises to conclusion


In chapter 2, we identified a number of properties of claims that help us not only
to determine what a claim is, but also then to write them properly. We have already
seen how, in forming groups of dependent premises, what makes these groups work
are the similarities and differences in the way we can form claims with these
internal connections. We will in this section continue to look at this property of
claims, as well as return to a consideration of questions of scope and certainty, and

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
48 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

also of value judgment so as to learn better how to make a good link from premises
to conclusion. In this section, I will try to model for you the process of writing an
argument in the analytical structure format so that you can see how understanding
the links between claims also depends on understanding what those claims are
saying.

The importance of internal connections


Let's begin by thinking about the following simple claim, which we will use as our
conclusion: 'Australia is a good country in which to live'. Now the reason I am
asserting this conclusion is that I believe 'Countries that permit freedom of
religious expression are good places to live'. So, in theory I could create a structure
like this:
1. Australia is a good country in which to live.
2. Countries that permit freedom of religious expression are good places
to live.

©
©
My knowledge that independent premises are a sign that another, dependent
premise is needed cues me to think 'what is missing here?'. The answer comes
from the fact that claims 1 and 2 both share the same predicate (good places to
live) but have a different subjects: Australia (1) and Countries that permit freedom
of religious expression (2). While it might seem obvious, the problem here is that
you cannot move from claim 2 to claim 1 logically without providing an
additional claim in which the two different subjects in claims 1 and 2 are them-
selves placed in a relationship. Such a claim would be 'Australia permits freedom
of religious expression'. Thus, by thinking about the internal connections of the
claim that is my conclusion, and the first premise I thought of, I have identified
an extra premise that is needed in my analytical structure, which now looks like
this:

1. Australia is a good country in which to live.


2. Countries that permit freedom of religious expression are good places
to live.
3. Australia permits freedom of religious expression.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 49

0^0 Y

©
Let us consider another example: I know that Australia has no laws that forbid
any religion, and that, by and large, the people who live in Australia let others
practise their religions peacefully, even if they do not agree with them. These in fact
are the reasons why I had assumed it was obvious that Australia permits freedom
of religious expression'. But we should not assume our readers know this, or that
we are in fact right: we better write in those ideas to make sure the logic is correct.
So, now, I am constructing a different argument:
3. Australia permits freedom of religious expression.
4. Australia has no laws that forbid any religion.
5. The people who live in Australia let others practise their religions
peacefully even if they do not agree with those religions.

0+©
©
But once again, I can see there is something missing, because of internal
connections. The conclusion has, as its predicate, 'freedom of religious expression'.
But this term in the argument is not mentioned in either of the two premises, 4
and 5. Hence, I have not yet represented accurately what I am thinking. I should
add a claim which will function as a framing premise, and incidentally is an
example of the value of the super-claim that has the if/then form: 'If a country has
no laws against individual religions and the people of that country do not object to
any religious practices, then freedom of religious expression exists in that country'.
3. Australia permits freedom of religious expression.
4. Australia has no laws that forbid any religion.
5. The people who live in Australia let others practise their religions
peacefully even if they do not agree with those religions.
6. If a country has no laws against individual religions and the people of

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
50 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

that country do not object to any religious practices, then freedom of


religious expression exists in that country.

©
As we can see here, the very fact that you could probably guess what was missing
is a sign that the pattern of interconnections in premises and conclusions is impor-
tant: we are able, often, to see what is missing but should, always, make sure that it
is written in explicitly when we are constructing these claim/diagram structures.

Making a real connection


There are times when people make the mistake of circular reasoning, that is, they
provide a premise or premises that are, effectively, the same as the conclusion. A very
obvious example is 'I have failed my exams because I have failed my exams'. No one
is foolish enough to actually use such an example. However, we can use different
words to say the same thing. Hence, sometimes, people argue in ways that are
circular because they present as their conclusion a claim that is the same, logically,
as their premise, even though the wording is different. For example 'Socialism is not
a workable economic system, because an economic system in which the means of
production is collectively owned cannot work' is circular because the claim
'Socialism is not a workable economic system' means the same thing as 'an economic
system in which the means of production is collectively owned cannot work'—you
can substitute the word 'socialism' for 'an economic system in which the means of
production is collectively owned' and not change the meaning of the second claim.
When making your link from premise to conclusion you are relying upon the
internal connection between subject and the predicate in the conclusion claim, but
you must not have the same connection in a single premise. Instead, you must have
the separate elements of the conclusion (the subject; and the predicate) each
appearing in different claims that serve as premises. Basically, you can only use a
claim once within its own argument, not twice; but the constituent components of
each claim can appear (and indeed should appear) more than once.

Covering scope and certainty


We also know that claims always imply or state their scope and certainty and
attention to this point will permit us to avoid one of the great errors in reasoning:

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 51

the sweeping generalisation. Often people will make a conclusion that is far too
general, or definitive for the reasons they are presenting to support it. An example
would be: Australia has a good education system with strong programs to teach
literacy, and thus all Australians know how to read and write.' It is true that
Australia has a good education system with such programs but it is not true,
consequentially, that all Australians know how to read and write. First, some
Australians have learning difficulties or other impairments that prevent them from
benefiting from those programs; a few Australians—usually those from dis-
advantaged backgrounds—face problems in attending school, being able to
function effectively there, and so on that again vitiate the impact of those programs.
But, logically, the mistake made here is that the scope and certainty of the con-
clusion is not in step with the scope and certainty of the premise. Therefore when
making the link between premises and conclusion, we need to align the scope and
certainty so that one can support the other. A better argument would be: Australia
has a good education system with strong programs to teach literacy, and thus it is
very likely that Australians will leave school knowing how to read and write'. The
change is in the claim that serves as the conclusion: but the consequence of the
change is in fact to strengthen the link between the claims.

Thinking about values


I argued above that Australia is a good country in which to live', a claim that is
obviously making a value judgment. Let us assume, for a moment, that my initial
thought as to why this claim is true was Australia permits freedom of religious
expression'. The mistake here of just having one premise is compounded by the fact
that this premise does not make an explicit value judgment and thus suggests
something is very wrong with my thinking. Returning to the example above, we
can see that part of the job done by the claim 'Countries that permit freedom of
religious expression are good places to live' is to place in the premises a claim that,
like the conclusion, also asserts a value judgment.
Here is another example concerning value judgments:

1. Ian will be imprisoned.


2. Ian has been convicted of defrauding Michael.
3. The penalty for someone convicted of fraud is imprisonment.
In this analytical structure, the conclusion does not make a value judgment—it does
not explicitly state that Ian should or should not be imprisoned. It simply predicts the
future based on the premises given. But imagine the argument is concluding 'It is right
that Ian should be imprisoned': the premises 2 and 3 do not, in this case, support the
conclusion because there is no value judgment there. We would have to add a premise
such as 'The penalty of imprisonment for the crime of fraud is a good penalty' to make
the structure logical. Of course, the value of being accurate like this is to expose the need
for an argument to support this added premise. While it is probably not necessary, in
most everyday arguments, to prove Ian's conviction, or that the penalty is imprisonment

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
52 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

(these claims, while not self-evident, are reasonably straightforward), I can imagine
some situations in which we might want to dispute the Tightness of that penalty.

Exercise 4.5
In the following complex argument, identify how the wording of the claims helps
you to see the logic of the five arrows which represent the movement from premise
to conclusion.
1. Ian should be jailed for between three and six months for assaulting Michael.
2. Ian threatened to attack Michael.
3. By law, threatening to attack someone is known as 'assault'.
4. Ian assaulted Michael.
5. A recent survey of 200 assault victims found that, for over 150 of them,
the assault adversely affected their lives for between three and six months
after the incident.
6. In most cases of assault, victims suffer for at least three months after the
actual assault has ended.
7. Michael will most likely be adversely affected by the assault for at least
three months.
8. Michael was relaxed and happy before the assault.
9. Now, after the assault, Michael is depressed and fearful.
10. Nothing other than the assault has happened to Michael that would cause
him to be depressed and fearful.
11. lan's assault on Michael has caused him to be depressed and fearful.
12. If Michael is suffering fear and depression, then it is only right that Ian
suffer similarly for a similar period of time.
13. Imprisonment is the only way in which suffering similar to that of
Michael's can be inflicted on Ian.

2 + 3

t
4 + 6 8 + 9 + 1 0

T
7 +12 + 13 + 11

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
UNDERSTANDING THE LINKS BETWEEN CLAIMS 53

Review
In this chapter we have explored, in considerable depth, how linking between
claims works in practice. Links between premises allow us to express the
complexities that underlie any summary 'reason'. The key property of claims
to be noted here is that a claim contains an internal connection, which then
is used as the basis for a chain of external links. Sometimes, a premise
functions to frame our argument or define some key term. Sometimes we will
encounter a single independent premise, but the connection between this
premise and its conclusion is weakened by the absence of explicit claims,
which are needed to make that connection clear.
The central idea behind developing our use of dependent premise chains
is that, when premises add together [+], they do so in relation to the next
logical link, from premises to conclusion [4]. This arrow is used, in the
analytical structure, to represent a relationship that is not just plucked from
thin air but which exists implicitly in the claims that are the premises. In
making this link, we must be careful that there is a consistency in the scope,
certainty, and value between premises and conclusion.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:

circular reasoning

defining premise

dependent premise

framing premise

independent premise

reason

sweeping generalisation

Review exercise 4
Answer briefly the following questions, giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book:

a. What distinguishes a 'reason' from a premise?


b. What is the difference between a dependent premise and an independent
premise?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
54 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

c. Why should we avoid using independent premises?


d. What does a framing premise do?
e. Why are definitions important?
f. How do we use internal connections to make sure we have the right claims
in our structure?
g. How do scope and certainty matter in an argument, not just in a single
claim?
h. How do conclusions that make value judgments need to be supported by
their premises?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
5

More Effective
Reasoning I: Better Claims
We have not yet discussed the question of how to reason more effectively.
The analytical structure format allows us to see more clearly what we are
doing and, thus, gives some basis for improvement. But of itself, the
format is not really much help: we must also know how to make our
reasoning strong and effective while planning and revising our work. This
chapter and the next discuss the ways in which we can avoid errors in
reasoning, both initially, in developing our ideas, and then when planning
them using the analytical structure format. This format, therefore, can be
regarded as a 'checkpoint' at which we can stop and evaluate the strengths
and weaknesses of our own arguments and explanations, and then improve
them, before fully expressing them in a narrative flow. Remember, the
analytical structure itself does not 'make' the reasoning work. It is simply
a way of putting your ideas on paper, logically, so you can check and revise
them.
This chapter will cover two main areas:

1 We will learn that the claims in our arguments and explanations need to
be well formed. A well-formed claim clearly states what it means in a way
that allows its truth to be evaluated. A poorly formed claim may or may
not truly state something about the world, but its weakness is that we
cannot judge its truth.
2 We will look at well-founded claims. Such claims are likely to be
accepted as true by people reading or hearing them. As we might
expect, we need to be sure that the claims we are using are true.
However, an effective argument is based as much, if not more, on
whether such claims are demonstrably true. Poorly founded claims may

https://books.yossr.com/en/books 55
56 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

be well formed, but they make claims about the world that our audience
finds hard to accept precisely because they appear to have no foun-
dation.

Well-formed claims
Writing clear claims
Smart thinking requires, first of all, that our claims be well formed. Before we
even think about how the links between claims might develop—and before we
even consider whether or not our claims are acceptable—we need to write or
speak clear claims. While this task is similar to all clear writing or speaking, it is
not exactly the same. Some of the rules of narrative exposition (such as not
repeating words too frequently, the proper use of clauses within sentences, and so
on) do not apply at this stage. Most of these rules generate implied links between
clauses and sentences; but since your analytical diagram clearly shows these links,
we do not need to complicate the claims in this way. Remember, the analytical
structure format is designed first and foremost for planning; the good exposition
will come later.
So, the primary aim in writing well-formed claims in an analytical structure
format is to make each a separate statement that contains all the information
necessary for it to express what we mean. The very act of writing the claim
carefully will, of itself, help us to understand better what it means. For example,
the claim 'Violence against indigenous Australians is wrong' is unclear and
vague—even though we would all agree with the sentiment, it is not a 'good'
claim. If it is rewritten (for example, to read 'Violence against indigenous
Australians by white settlers colonising Australia had and continues to have a
negative effect on the moral order of the nation'), then the claim is not as easy
to read but clearly shows the meaning of the claim, ready for linking analytically
to other claims.
Even at this first stage, as we put together our claims as the basis for our text,
we cannot avoid the role of context. The meaning of every word we use is not a
fixed absolute, but a socially and culturally constructed convention. By this I mean
that the meaning of a word is always determined in relation to all the other words
and meanings that are in use within a particular society.1 Though, for most
purposes, the words (and hence the claims) we use seem to be clear in what they
mean, we can never simply assume that our audience will always grasp our exact
meaning. In particular, while the surface meanings of various words are usually
commonly accepted, the connotations (or hidden implications and understand-
ings) of words can vary subtly between different groups of people.
For example, many people in Cuba (still governed within a Marxist system)
would not consider the USA a democracy, since people in the USA do not have
equal access to education, health, and welfare, whereas in Cuba they do (and thus

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING I: BETTER CLAIMS 57

Cuba is a democracy). An American would probably regard Cuba as undemo-


cratic in that it only has one political party—the Communist Party—whereas the
USA has two major parties. A Cuban might respond by pointing out that the
Democrat and Republican parties in the USA are so similar that there is little
choice between them. Obviously our hypothetical American and Cuban debaters
have different definitions of democracy. Yet, if we asked them to spell out their
definition, they might both respond by saying the same things: 'all people have
the right to vote'; 'all people are equal'; and so on. The meaning of the word
'democracy' simply depends on more words, which themselves require définition.
(What do we mean by 'all people', for example? In the USA, most poor African-
American and Hispanic citizens do not vote because they believe it will not
change the system that, by and large, has failed to benefit them. Do they fall
within the definition 'all people'?)
Hence, writing well-formed claims will always require some consideration of
both the surface and hidden meanings of the words from which these claims are
constructed—meanings that are created differently in different contexts.
Connotations can never be controlled completely. We could try to use
'definitions', but definitions themselves give rise to even more connotations
(since they, too, are made up of words). One trick is to align your choice of
words with the understanding of the intended audience so that you can be
confident that what you mean will be reasonably similar to what your audience
might think. And, to be even safer, you can actually discuss possible conflicts of
connotations. Alternatively, you can establish (to a large extent) the interpretive
context within which you want the meaning of your words to emerge. Either
way, you need to consider the possible interpretive contexts that affect your
choice of words.

Controlling the key properties of claims


Because a claim makes an internal connection between two ideas, we need to make
sure that this connection is expressed as we want it to be. Again, by writing
carefully, we also improve our 'analysis' of the issues. Look at the following claims:
a. Many colonial Australian settlers took part in military-style operations
against indigenous Australians throughout the nineteenth century, in
different parts of the country.
b. The violent conflict between white settlers and indigenous Australians
was wrong.
c. Some Australian political and religious leaders in the nineteenth
century wrote at the time that the violent conflict between white
settlers and indigenous Australians was wrong.
d. Historians should continue to debate the extent to which
indigenous Australians fought back against the process of
European settlement.
e If Australians do not come to terms with the violent events associated

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
58 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

with the nation's colonial foundation, then Australians today will


continue to experience unease and guilt about race relations with
indigenous Australians,
f. The history of the war against indigenous Australians continues to be
a political issue in the current era.

These claims might all concern the broad topic of the violence attendant on the
arrival of European settlers in the country we now call Australia, but in each case,
the primary focus of the claim is different.

• Claim a is about the actions of white settlers in the nineteenth century.


• Claim b is about the conflict between settlers and indigenous Australians.
• Claim c identifies the views of some Australian political and religious leaders
in the nineteenth century.
• Claim d concerns what historians should be debating.
• Claim e predicts the consequences that will flow from some action concerning
the history of violence in Australia, which may or may not happen (as
indicated by the 'if').
• Claim f concerns the current status of the history of the war against
indigenous Australians, about which many of the other claims might be
made.

The differences also show us that there are a variety of different uses for
claims. Claims a and b are direct claims, in the first case describing some event
and in the second case directly expressing the author's own moral judgment.
However, 'Some Australian political and religious leaders in the nineteenth
century wrote at the time that the violent conflict between white settlers and
indigenous Australians was wrong' is indirect, for it concerns what other people
think. There is no indication that the author of the claim either agrees or
disagrees with the 'political and religious leaders' who thought this way.
Arguments and explanations often require not just our own views on a particular
issue, but also our analysis of others' views. We need to make sure that our
claims are well formed so that there is no confusion between what we are
directly claiming and what we are reporting about other people's views. Claim e
demonstrates another crucial type of claim, often used in hypothetical reasoning
about a possible future event. To argue in this manner does not necessarily imply
that the effect (the 'then' part of the claim) has happened, but simply that it
probably w;/'//happen in the future. It may even be part of an argument aimed at
stopping some action from happening. We might also find such hypothetical
elements in claims such as 'Let us assume for a moment that the violence
between whites and indigenous Australians did not occur': such claims do not
propose that it did not happen, but simply develop a hypothetical situation that
might enable a clearer analysis to proceed. The key point here is to recognise
that claims can say and do all sorts of things, and if you are not careful in how
you write them, then they will provide a very weak foundation for your
analytical structure.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING I: BETTER CLAIMS 59

Making claims also involves deciding between values and descriptions. We can
think about the six examples just given from this perspective: claims a, c, and f
describe some state of affairs; whereas claims b and d make explicit value
judgments about the goodness or otherwise of some state of affairs; claim e sits
uneasily between these two alternatives; and while claim e appears to be free of
values, most of us would probably see in it some implicit value judgment, probably
because of the implication in the first half of the claim that we should do the
opposite of the ' i f . Yet it is unlikely that we will ever be able to write many claims
that are completely free of value judgments. An individual claim may be
descriptive, but it can only be understood in relation to other claims and other
words. What appears, to us, to be a description will, necessarily, appear to others
as a judgment of value. For many years, the word 'violence' was never used to
describe white settlement in Australia. Thus, when historians began to uncover the
evidence of violence, their claims appeared in comparison to be distinctly value-
laden. So we must simply be aware of the value judgments in our claims in order
to understand what we are saying.
Claims always involve, implicitly or explicitly, some statement of the scope and
certainty of the information they contain. Well-formed claims always state their
scope and certainty explicitly. For example, Australians took part in military-style
operations against indigenous Australians' is unclear. How many—all of them,
some, a few? Where did this occur? And for how long? Whatever you wish to say
about this issue (and there are competing views among historians), a well-formed
claim should try to make clear what you are asserting. Hence, (for example) 'Many
colonial Australian settlers took part in military-style operations against indigenous
Australians throughout the nineteenth century, in different parts of the country' is
a better-formed claim.

Exercise 5.1
Identify, in the following claims: (i) the two components of the claims, paying partic-
ular attention to claims that state someone else's views or that employ the 'if... then'
form; (ii) the value judgments that some of them are making (explicitly or implicitly);
(iii) the explicit or implicit markers of scope and certainty that are essential to the
claim's proper functioning; and (iv) any words that might appear to have interesting
connotations.

a. Some years ago, the Northern Territory passed legislation allowing some
people to commit voluntary euthanasia.
b. Most religious leaders at the time, and now, claim that legislation
permitting voluntary euthanasia is immoral.
c. If a state government passed voluntary euthanasia laws, then the Federal
Government would not be able to stop that legislation in the same way that
it did for the Northern Territory.
d. Several terminally ill people were reported in the media at the time as
saying they were moving to the Northern Territory.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
60 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

e. I imagine that if another state or territory were to pass similar laws, then
media reporting of the legislation would be very extensive.
f. Some politicians argued that media reporting at the time of the
Northern Territory legislation encouraged some terminally ill people to
move there.

Well-founded claims
The problem of 'true' claims
A claim, whether it is a conclusion or a premise, has one essential property: that it
claims to be a true statement (either actual or possible—what is or what ought to
be). Hence, while claims must first be well formed, so that we can express this state
of affairs precisely, claims must also be well founded, so that their truth is not too
easily called into question. If I were to say, 'This book will totally change your life!',
you would probably not accept this claim, because as it stands, this claim is
unfounded (not based on believable intellectual foundations) and is thus of
doubtful truth.
The whole purpose of using reasoning is, in fact, to give foundations (via the
premises) for the conclusion, to show that it is acceptable, or to establish an accept-
able explanation of it. Obviously, then, the 'well-foundedness' of the premises
becomes equally (if not more) important than the well-foundedness of the con-
clusion. How can an audience assess our conclusion except by first considering the
premises? Indeed, for any claim to be well founded, whether it be conclusion or
premise, there must be some reason(s) for the audience accepting it. Every claim,
in this sense, must be treated as a conclusion in need of premises. Every argument
or explanation in which we use premises to prove a conclusion depends, therefore,
on other arguments or explanations, which establish those premises. We have seen
this situation in some of the examples in previous chapters, in which a conclusion
is reached only after a series of arguments (arranged in a complex structure) have
been developed.
Here is an example:

1. Australia is a good country in which to live.


2. Countries that permit freedom of religious expression are good places
to live.
3. Australia permits freedom of religious expression.
4. Australia has no laws that forbid any religion.
5. The people who live in Australia let others practise their religions
peacefully even if they do not agree with those religions.
6. If a country has no laws against individual religions and the people of
that country do not object to any religious practices, then freedom of
religious expression exists in that country.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING I: BETTER CLAIMS 61

0,©.©
©*©
©
Claim 3 is being supported by an argument provided by 4 , 5, and 6. Of course, we
might also ask what claims should be there to support 4 , 5, and 6.
Theoretically, if all claims must be supported by reasons, then there would be
no guaranteed starting points to any process of reasoning. In structural terms, every
claim that we use at the top of a diagram would always appear to need a further
argument above it to show why that claim was acceptable. In such a situation,
reasoning would be impossible—the very ideas of 'foundations' would go out the
window.
In practice it is much simpler. We take for granted that many, perhaps most,
claims we use are not going to have explicit reasons, but instead will be presented
as being 'self-evidently' acceptable (that is, without any evidence but themselves).
Societies, and particular knowledge groups (such as a profession or academic
discipline) within them, have many agreed conventions and assumptions that
short-circuit the need to justify in detail every single claim they use; there are also
many legitimate, accepted starting points provided by claims for which no further
reasoning is required (because the argument for them exists implicitly in the
surrounding context of knowledge and audience).
Now, strictly speaking, very few claims are logically self-evident. One that is,
for example, would be the claim that 'Either you are pregnant or you are not'. No
matter who this claim is applied to, no matter what the situation, it is self-evident.
There is no category of 'a little bit pregnant'. But such claims are actually quite
rare: their function in argument is simply to define a term in such a manner as to
make clear its exclusivity. Such claims do not actually refer to the world, but to the
words we use in the world—the claim 'My sister is pregnant' is not self-evident.
However, many claims which are not self-evident are treated as z/They are self-
evident, revealing the social dimensions of reasoning. In the world of strict logic,
outside of common practice and normal human interactions, virtually every claim
must be supported by evidence; in the everyday world of reasoning, many claims
are assumed to be self-evident. They must be regarded as such. There would be no

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
62 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

way for reasoning to proceed if we did not make these assumptions of self-
evidence.
Arguments begin with claims that are more acceptable (that is, well founded
without the need for argument) and move onwards to claims that are less
acceptable (that is, most in need of an argument to justify them). An explanation
may end with a well-known claim as its conclusion but should begin with the more
readily accepted explanatory premises. Not only must the starting claims be well
founded as far as we are concerned, but we also need to be reasonably sure our
audience will concur with us. Some claims, perhaps even just one, will need to be
presented as self-evidently well founded. But many other claims will only become
effective when properly founded by something we do to support them, showing
our audience why and how they are well founded. Let us then look at the ways in
which we might do this. First of all we will consider why it is that some claims can
appear, on their own, as well founded, and then examine two ways in which we can
present extra information to our audience to support those claims that cannot
stand on their own.

Claims whose truthfulness is not in question


An example of a claim that we might expect to use self-evidently is 'The earth orbits
the sun'. But, if we are to be sure that the claims in our arguments and explanations
are well founded in the context of their audience, we cannot simply assume that
they are self-evident. For example, a group of young children would, probably, need
to be convinced that the earth orbited the sun since, just on the basis of their
observation, the sun goes around the earth. But, we can assume, a group of adults
would not require any such convincing: they will have already come to accept that
'the earth orbits the sun' is a true claim.
The difficulty, of course, is that apart from some obvious claims, such as the
example just used, most claims are in doubt to some degree or another, or for
some audience or another. And there is another category of claim that poses an
even more difficult problem: claims whose truthfulness is not in doubt, but
should bel Here is an example of this dual dilemma. If someone claimed,
without giving a foundation, that 'citizens of Singapore enjoy considerable
freedom', then many Australians (and Singaporeans) might doubt the truth of
this claim. In doing so, they would be drawing on existing (that is, contextual)
knowledge of, say, the limitations of free speech in Singapore, the many
restrictions on what one can and cannot do, and the fact that Singapore has
always been governed by the same political party since gaining independence
from the United Kingdom.
To establish the truth of the claim, its author would have to somehow overcome
the audience's initial scepticism. Such a claim might well be true if we understand
that freedom can mean both freedom to do some positive act (that is, the freedom
to voice critical opinions of the government) and freedom from some negative
circumstance (that is, freedom from hunger and poverty). Hence, although the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING I: BETTER CLAIMS 63

author of the claim is convinced that it is well founded, if the author were to
propose that 'citizens of Singapore enjoy considerable freedom' without carefully
arguing or explaining what was meant, the audience might well refuse to accept the
claim. Equally, people often believe claims about which there is considerable doubt.
For example, most Australians would not think twice before accepting that 'citizens
of Australia enjoy considerable freedom' was a true claim. In doing so, they would
draw on existing knowledge (as in the first example). But, obviously, when we
consider the 'negative freedom' definition, we might think that the claim was more
doubtful. Such doubts might readily spring to mind for indigenous Australian
people, whose capacity to enjoy the positive freedoms of Australian citizenship is
seriously constrained by inequities in, for example, housing, health, and employ-
ment.
At some point, of course, we have to use claims that, since we are giving no
argument or other support for them, are presented as self-evidently true, or that are
so widely accepted to be true (by our audience) that they do not require further
justification. We must also rely on the fact that, as authors, we are presumed by our
audience to have some knowledge about our subject and can thus be 'trusted' to
make acceptable claims. (Obviously certain authors—experts, renowned scholars,
and so on—can rely on this trust a good deal more than others; such trust is clearly
a contextual component of the overall text.) In this way, we are ourselves involved
in creating the context in which our reasoning exists.
But we need to consider many other contextual factors so that, in the end
result, our self-evident claims do indeed turn out to be acceptable to our
audience. We must, in effect, judge in advance the likelihood that someone
reading or hearing our reasoning will 'doubt' that a claim is true. If it is possible
that this situation will occur, then we must counter this 'doubt' in advance.
While the basis for our judgment must include attention to the claim itself, we
can only argue and explain the claim effectively if we also judge its acceptability
in relation to our audience. Finally, more pragmatic issues emerge from a
consideration of context: what is expected of your particular argument in terms
of length and scope. For example, it is unreasonable (according to most social
conventions) to expect most arguments and explanations to contain the level of
detail that, for example, we find in lengthy scholarly work. We can adjust our
reasoning accordingly by thinking about its context as well as what it actually
contains (the text).

Exercise 5.2
Which of the following claims would be regarded as self-evidently true by a
general adult audience? In each case, explain your answer:

a. Communism has failed.


b. Television was introduced to Australia in 1956.
c. Australia is a democracy.
d. We should legalise marijuana.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
64 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

e. The two main political parties are the Liberal Party of Australia and the
Australian Labor Party.
f. A broken leg requires immediate medical treatment.

Claims supported by authority


Perhaps the most common way of overcoming this 'problem'—the risk that our
claims may not be accepted—is to support them by an appeal to authority. This is
a very special form of reasoning that, to establish the acceptability of a claim, does
not give an argument but makes reference (in one or more ways) to an expert. In
this reference, an appeal to authority indirectly points to arguments or explanations
that would, if checked, support the claim.
There are many conventional forms of reasoning in which we come across
claims supported by authority. Here are some examples (the words that provide the
reference to a particular form of authority are italicised):

a. 'Gender and sexual definitions [have] become the focus of intense


cultural negotiation' (Gledhill 1992, p. 201).
b. Australian history is marked by considerable conflict and tension over
the competing interests of labour and capital (see Rickard 1992).
c. According to Dr Jane Long, who has studied this topic in detail, poor
women in nineteenth-century England were, by and large, worse off
than poor men.
d. In my twenty years' experience as a High Court judge, I have come
across few cases as complex as this one.
e. / look back on my childhood and recall that I was always encouraged
to ask 'why?' by my parents.
f. The experiments I have conducted show that many cleaning products
induce allergic reactions in humans.
You should be reasonably familiar with the type of support offered in claims
a and b. Here the claims are stated and a reference given to the book, chapter,
or article from which they are drawn. In the first, the reference is direct:
Gledhill's actual words are quoted (and the reference would be given in full in
the bibliography). In the second, the reference is indirect: the claim given
summarises a discussion in Rickard's book. References such as these ack-
nowledge the source of ideas and evidence, but also provide support for the
claims. In effect, they say 'This claim I now make is well founded because it has
been previously established by someone else, and here is the reference to that
person's work so you can go and check for yourself. The insistence in academic
work on proper referencing is, therefore, not simply a tedious necessity but a
significant part of the main purpose of writing: the clear expression of good
arguments or explanations.
Claims c and d are slightly different. They are similar in that the accept-
ability of the claim in each case is founded on the authority of an expert, but

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING I: BETTER CLAIMS 65

there is no 'source' to check up on. In claim c, the authority is that of someone


who has studied a subject and is, presumably, an expert on such matters. In
claim d, the authority comes not from study, but from relevant personal
experience—that is, experience that does, in fact, help to establish the claim.
Claim e provides another significant type of authority: the authority of personal
experience in relation to one's own life (one is usually an expert on one's own
life, though not always). Claim f is different again, and a significant form of
authority in most scientific and social science research. As noted above, authors
can present claims as being self-evidently true via the audience's trust that they
are accurate researchers, investigators, and thinkers. In this case, we simply find
an explicit statement that calls upon that trust. But, in each case, the inclusion
of some reference to authority functions to support the truthfulness of the
claim, and in that respect, there is more similarity than difference between the
five examples.

Exercise 5.3
For each of the following, indicate an appropriate authority to whom you might
refer if required to establish the foundation of these claims. Remember, you are
not reasoning here but are referring to some source of reasoning about the claim:

a. Communism has failed.


b. Television was introduced to Australia in 1956.
c. Australia is a democracy.
d. We should legalise marijuana.
e. The two main political parties are the Liberal Party of Australia and the
Australian Labor Party.
f. A broken leg requires immediate medical treatment.
Let us at this stage return to the analytical structure format to show how we
might represent these calls to authority. First of all, think about the way that the list
of claims is designed to express clearly what we mean. Imagine we wish to claim
that 'Australian history is marked by considerable conflict and tension over the
competing interests of labour and capital' and use as support the fact that a compe-
tent, respected historian such as John Rickard has also made this claim in his book
Australia: A Cultural History. We would write:
1. The Australian government should continue to regulate industrial rela-
tions practice and policy.
2. Australian history is marked by considerable conflict and tension over
the competing industrial interests of labour and capital.
3. Rickard, Australia-. A Cultural History (1992) asserts claim 2.
4. These conflicts and tensions have been resolved, by and large, by
government intervention.
5. It is unlikely that, in future, the conflict that results from the
competing industrial interests of labour and capital will decline.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
66 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

©
©.0 + ©
V

©
Note that, in this example, we are not engaging in an analysis of the fact that
Rickard has made this claim. That is why we separate the authority from the
substantive claim it is supporting. If we were trying to show why Rickard was right
or wrong to make it, then we would combine the claims together and write:
'Rickard has argued that Australian history is marked by considerable conflict and
tension over the competing interests of labour and capital'. By doing so, we would
be starting to analyse the fact that Rickard has made that argument. In simple use
of authority, by contrast, the authority and the claim that is relying on it have the
same logical connection as that by which claims prove or show another claim.
Hence it is appropriate to diagram the relationship using the arrow.

Claims supported by reasoning


Looking back to the last example, what should we do about claims 4 and 5, for
which no clear foundation is offered? Well, rather than allow their foundations to
remain implicit, we can argue for claims 4 and 5 in precisely the same way as we
are arguing for claim 1, thus developing a complex argument structure. We could,
for example, add the following claims to our argument, not to support claim 1
directly but to show why claim 5 was acceptable.

6. Capitalist economies are structured in a way that creates two groups:


labour (those employed) and capital (those who do the employing).
7. These two groups will always have different interests.
8. It is highly likely that, in future, Australia will continue to have a capi-
talist economy.

In the overall argument, claims 6-8 form a subsidiary argument to support


claim 5 (one of the main premises in the argument), which in turn helps to explain
the conclusion. Claim 5, therefore, serves in two different ways: as a conclusion and
a premise. There is no difference in the way that the two arrows operate, nor in the
way that the linking between premises operates in either the first or second part of

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING I: BETTER CLAIMS 67

the argument. Hence, all of the next chapter, which discusses in detail the effective
construction of links between claims, is applicable to subsidiary arguments, such as
the one involving claims 5, 6, 7, and 8, as well as to main arguments, such as that
involving claims 2, 4, 5, and 1.

6 + 7 + 8

2 + 4 + 5

1
Exercise 5.4
For each of the following, write a brief argument (in analytical structure format)
that establishes the acceptability of these claims. In each case, remember that
the claims you use in support of the following conclusions should be more self-
evident than the conclusions themselves.

a. Communism has failed.


b. Television was introduced to Australia in 1 9 5 6 .
c. Australia is a democracy.
d. We should legalise marijuana.
e. The two main political parties are the Liberal Party of Australia and the
Australian Labor Party.
f. A broken leg requires immediate medical treatment.

Review
Claims have certain key properties that we must understand if we are to be effec-
tive reasoners. The only way to achieve a level of control over our claims is to
make sure that, as we write each claim, we know—at some level—how we are
formulating each component properly. Yet we cannot ignore the contextual issues
relating to meaning and connotation that will affect others' judgments of how well
formed our claims appear to be. Making a well-founded claim involves, at the very
least, considering whether we believe it to be true (on the basis of whatever
evidence we have, or have seen or read) and then considering whether or not our

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
68 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

audiences will believe it to be true. Well-founded claims are not just 'true'; they
are accepted as true. There are three types of well-founded claims: those that are
'self-evident' (and, in that sense, are their own foundation); those that are
founded on a reference to authority or expertise (including one's own 'authority');
and those that are founded (like the conclusion to any argument or explanation)
via further reasoning.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:

appeal to authority
effective reasoning
implied premise
modes of analysis
self-evident claim
well-formed claim
well-founded claim

Review exercise 5
Answer briefly the following questions, giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book:

a. Why are well-formed claims essential?


b. What is the role of connotations in thinking about well-formed claims?
c. What is the difference between claiming 'X happened' and 'Jones has
argued that X happened'?
d. What roles do scope and certainty play in well-formed claims?
e. Which claims are least likely to be 'self-evident'?
f. What is the similarity between premise-claims supporting a conclusion
and other claims supporting those premises?
g. How might we 'found' claims so that they are more acceptable?
h. How can we judge the 'truth' of a claim in trying to communicate our
reasoning effectively?

NOTES
1 See Tony Schirato and Susan Yell, Communication and culture: an introduction, Sage,
London, 2000 for an in-depth treatment of this important issue.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
6

More Effective Reasoning II:


Better Links
Writing well-formed and well-founded claims is only half the task of
effective reasoning. The links between these claims must also be well
made if our overall argument or explanation is to be strong. Looking
carefully at the links between premises prevents us from making un-
conscious assumptions about how information is interrelated. We must
also check the connections of our premises with their conclusion, making
sure they are relevant and provide strong support. Otherwise our
conclusion will not be acceptable, or the explanation of it will be uncon-
vincing. At each stage, as discussed in chapter 5, we will need to
consider the way that the context of our reasoning will affect our
judgments about its effectiveness.
In this chapter we will consider three main issues:

1 We look at how effective reasoning requires that we work out the neces-
sary links between dependent premises. Carefully expanding our 'reasons'
into a fully expressed chain of premises ensures that our reasoning has
depth, so that no important premises remain 'implied' (not explicitly
stated).
2 We will consider how relevant premises provide information that does
actually bear on the conclusion, whereas irrelevant premises (even if well
formed and well founded) do not.
3 We examine the strength of the support that premises provide for a
conclusion. As we saw with well-founded claims, judgments of audience
expectations and other contextual issues play a central role in making
sure our reasoning is effective.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books 69
70 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Effective use of dependent premises


Dependent premises providing one reason
A reason for a conclusion is very unlikely to consist in a single claim. No matter
how we might state it in short-hand, it is, analytically, a complex interaction of
many ideas and implications. The reason must be broken down into a chain of
more precise premises. For example, the claim that 'university education should be
free for all Australians' might be supported by the reason that 'the economy bene-
fits from a well-educated Australian population'. But is our analysis of the situation
clearly expressed in just one statement? Hardly. The conclusion is about universi-
ties and free education, while the reason introduces some new ideas: economic
benefit and a well-educated population. While the link between these two ideas and
the conclusion might seem obvious, the purpose of reasoning is to avoid assuming
the 'obvious' by carefully working through the connections between the various
ideas in the initial statement of our reason.
Here is how we might do it:

1. University education should be free for all Australians.


2. A well-educated population is more productive at work.
3. Higher productivity at work benefits the economy.
4. If something benefits the economy, then the government should
encourage it.
5. The best way for the government to encourage Australians to be well
educated is to provide free university education.
6. In our complex technological society, one requires university study in
order to be well educated.

©.©,0,©,©
t

©
Now turning one reason—'the economy benefits from a well-educated
Australian population'—into five separate premises does not provide any addi-
tional, different reasons. Rather, we have 'unpacked' some of the hidden aspects
and implications of one reason and shown how they relate to one another.1 For
example, in the initial reason 'well-educated' is not defined. There are many
different opinions on what constitutes such an education, and claim 6, a definition,

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 71

overcomes this source of confusion. Claims 2 and 3 make clear the exact relation-
ship between economic benefit and education. Moreover, by expanding the hidden
aspects of our initial reason, we have discovered a key issue: who should pay. No
matter how strongly we might believe it, the reason 'education benefits the
economy' does not, of itself, mean education's users should not pay. This implica-
tion is not self-evident. If we want to argue that education should be free, then we
must say why. Claims 4 and 5 provide, then, an explication of the idea of free
education. Note how claim 4, in particular, expresses a clear value judgment: the
government should do something. Since the conclusion is a value claim ('education
should be free'), there must be a premise somewhere that addresses the value
judgment involved here.
If we were to provide an additional reason, 'free education is a fundamental
democratic right', we need to keep it separate (both in our minds and on paper)
from the reason about economic benefit. We would, of course, need to expand this
initial reason into a series of dependent premises, but they would occupy a different
place in the analytical structure of our argument. We could unpack this additional
reason into claims and include them in the format:
7. Free education is a fundamental democratic right.
8. Australia is a democracy.
9. Education includes all levels from primary to tertiary.

0-0+0 ©+©-©-©+©
©
In this process of unpacking or expanding a basic reason for a conclusion, we
should carefully distinguish between the internal complexities of that statement (which
become a series of dependent claims), and any new claims that we introduce to make
a dependent claim well founded. One of the claims resulting from our expansion of
the economic benefit reason was 'The best way for the government to encourage
Australians to be well educated is to provide free university education' (claim 5). We
could show why claim 5 was true by including the following claims:
10. Any cost that the government imposes on people attending higher
education will probably reduce the numbers attending.
11. If numbers are reduced, then Australians are obviously not being
encouraged to attend.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
72 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

...©•©...

©
Claims that argue for or explain another claim are always placed above them;
claims that work together to form one reason are placed alongside one another, as a
chain of dependent premises. Getting the diagram right doesn't make this happen,
it is a way of representing—in a structured format—what is happening in our
minds.
We tend to imagine that strong reasoning involves understanding and using a
number of different reasons for our conclusion, giving our arguments and
explanations intellectual breadth. This view has considerable merit (and we
examine it in more detail in the next section), but it does not mean that we can
ignore the requirement to argue and explain in depth. Learning to 'unpack' what we
initially think of as a straightforward, simple reason and to express it as a number
of distinct, but dependent, premises is the only way to make sure our reasoning is
not too shallow.
For example, in relation to higher education, deep reasoning will bring out the
current debate about whether education is vocational (training for employment) or
liberal (education for the individual's own life). It would engage with the complex
issues of who pays, against a background of reduced government spending and
increased personal wealth for some Australians. It would engage with the social
purposes of education (education for individual benefit or for social improvement).
Each of these issues is worthy of significant argument and explanation in its own
right. Such an approach ensures that our reasoning addresses all the issues raised by
the conclusion: the meaning of certain words, the values that we are seeking to
express, the exact way in which certain situations come about, and so on.

Avoiding implied premises


If, in unpacking our reason and turning it into premises, we leave out a premise that
should (analytically speaking) be there, then we have made a serious error. Such a
claim would not be 'missing' exactly, but rather would be implied by the connection
between the claims that are explicitly stated. That we do often 'leave out' some of

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 73

these premises is a reflection of the difficulty of thinking deeply enough about


complex issues. When we do, it is usually because we have unconsciously assumed
some complex relationship that, in fact, needs more open analysis.
Here is an example. Imagine we reasoned that 'The economy is growing
strongly at the moment, so employment will also grow strongly'. If we look closely,
this explanation does not represent a clear analysis. The first claim puts together
two components ('economy' and 'growth'); the second (the conclusion) puts
together 'employment' and 'growth'. What has been implied? We do not have to
guess because, from the available information, we can infer that the implied claim
is a premise that connects 'economy' with 'employment'. Such a premise might be:
'Economic growth is necessarily a cause of employment growth'. And, from this
example, we can extract a general rule: when deciding what the implied premise
might be, ask 'on what basis, according to what other piece of information, does
the stated premise (or premises) provide a reason for accepting the conclusion?'. If
the link between the premises and the conclusion is unclear, then there is probably
an implied premise.
The original explanation about the economy contains an implied premise because
the initial 'reason' had not been unpacked, allowing each necessary element to be
written as an explicit claim. Failures to expand reasons properly lead to implied
premises and reflect assumptions made by the person arguing or explaining, which
interfere with smart analysis. Historically, economic growth has caused employment
to grow, but as is evidenced by the past decade in Australia, the new shape of capitalist
economies in the 1990s and the new century means that this old idea is no longer
valid. This mistake—of assuming it is true to say 'economic growth means more
jobs'—has been common in recent years. Because the reason was not unpacked
properly and the analytical relationship made explicit, the original explanation did not
provide a clear opportunity to analyse this assumption and check to see if it was true.
But it is also wrong to rely on implied premises (that is, those that are analyti-
cally necessary but have not been clearly stated) even when such premises are true.
Look at this example:

A computer technician is called out to look at a personal computer that is


not working very well. The technician knows perfectly well what is wrong:
the computer has only got 256 megabytes of random access memory
(RAM), and its owner is trying to run programs that require at least 5 1 2
megabytes. So, she explains to the customer, 'Your computer is not
working well because it only has 256 megabytes of RAM'.

What the technician has done, though, is to rely on the implied premise that
'If you wish to run the programs loaded on this machine, then you must have at
least 5 1 2 megabytes of RAM'. The relationship between memory, the computer,
and the problem is so obvious to the technician that she has not clearly explained
it. Yet, the customer may not know enough about computers to 'fill in' or infer the
implied premise from the stated explanation. The implied premise here is true.
What has been assumed is that the relationship between the premises and the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
74 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

conclusion is obvious. In fact, from the point of view of the customer, it is not, and
thus the reasoning used by the technician is ineffective.
By definition, all reasoning depends at some point or another on assumptions that
give rise to implied claims. So, practically speaking, effective reasoning does not require
that there be no implied premises. But it does require that we be well aware of the
claims that we do leave out. First, if we do not recognise our own implied premises,
then we may fail to judge accurately if they are true or not; second, we may fail to
communicate our message to someone else who does not share our assumptions. This
last point is particularly important. Our decisions about using implied premises can
only be guided by what we expect our audience to know, and what we know, about
the context of our reasoning. For example, academic essays and reports are usually
designed precisely to test students' abilities to avoid making assumptions, and so, we
would not want to leave many implied premises in this context, even though we might
assume our audience (the assessors) do know the claims we are making.

Exercise 6.1
Think of two completely separate reasons for each of the following two con-
clusions. Write these reasons down, and then analyse their relationship to the
conclusion, expanding each into a chain of dependent premises. In the first case,
you are explaining why the conclusion is happening; in the second case you are
arguing for it to be accepted.

a. I am reading a book on reasoning.


b. There are considerable benefits to be gained from studying how to think
better.

Relevance
What is relevance?
Here is a simple example of relevance and irrelevance concerning the conclusion
'Smith is physically unhealthy':

a. Smith has pains in his chest; he coughs a lot and is short of breath
walking up stairs. Clearly Smith is physically unhealthy.
b. Smith wears green trousers and a pink hat and has no shirt on. Clearly
Smith is physically unhealthy.

In argument a, the relevance of the premises is clear: they all report physical
symptoms that are routinely recognised as evidence of poor health. In the second
case, these premises are irrelevant because they give us no indication of physical
health. Note that it is impossible to determine the relevance of the premises by
themselves: we must look at their relationship to the conclusion. Argument b
contains a number of irrelevant premises, but if the conclusion were 'Smith has no

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 75

conventional sense of good dress', then, clearly, the claims about his hat, trousers,
and bare chest would be relevant. What determines the easy judgment that a is a
good argument and b is a bad argument is the implied premise 'physical symptoms
are relevant evidence from which to induce a conclusion about physical health'.
Indeed it is so obvious—in our society, but perhaps not others—that we would be
thought odd if we actually explicitly stated that premise.
Relevance is often a major problem in argumentation. Poor arguments regularly
report the 'facts' well, and try to draw conclusions from them but do not establish the
relevance of the premises given to the conclusion asserted. Poor skills in reasoning,
especially not identifying one's assumptions, are one cause. As we considered in chapter
4 one of the functions of premises is, precisely, to establish relevance—not something
which all people who use reasoning realise. However it is not just a problem of
technique. Often the debates in our society that are most difficult to resolve concern
disagreements about whether or not a premise is relevant to a given conclusion.
Consider the treatment of people who arrive as refugees in Australia directly, rather
than by official routes (so-called 'illegal immigrants'). Politicians who support deten-
tion of these people argue that international laws concerning the proper treatment of
refugees are not relevant to this class of immigrants because they have arrived illegally.
Opponents of detention counter by saying the international laws are relevant. On both
sides, there is agreement that there are such laws, and that they do prohibit detention;
there is also agreement that people are arriving in this manner. What differs is the
judgment as to whether or not the refugees are arriving legally or illegally and, in
consequence, whether human rights conventions are or are not relevant.
Issues of relevance are rarely as obvious as the example about Smith and his
health that I used at the start of this section. Smart thinking always involves very
careful consideration of relevance as distinct from whether or not premises are well
founded. To emphasise, relevance of premises is completely different from the
acceptability of premises. A claim can be true (and thus acceptable), but this quality
alone does not necessarily mean it is relevant to the conclusion. For example, it is
definitely the case that, as you read these words, the claim 'You are reading this
book' is true and acceptable. But is it relevant to the conclusion 'You are going to
cook fish for dinner tonight'? No! Hence, in making our arguments and explana-
tions effective, we should not be satisfied simply that our premises are acceptable
in themselves: for them to give any support to the conclusion, they must also be
relevant to it. So, put simply, a premise is relevant to the conclusion when it
provides some basis on which to decide whether or not to accept that conclusion.

Exercise 6.2
To help you to learn about relevance, let us look at some examples. In the
following arguments and explanations, decide which premises are relevant to the
conclusion (which is italicised in each case):

a. Why did the train crash? The train was going too fast and its brakes were
faulty; also, there were many people waiting at the station.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
76 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

b. Now, first of all, privatisation leads to competition and, when there is


competition, prices go down and service improves. People want reduced
prices and improved service in the postal system and so the government
postal service should be privatised.
c. Several politicians have been discovered to have lied in public; many
rarely seem to have much knowledge of what their voters want; and
generally, politicians get too many benefits. Hence we should not trust
them to make good decisions on our behalf.

Ensuring premises are relevant


But what if the connection between a premise and a conclusion is not obvious? A
crucial smart-thinking skill is the ability to think through how evidence relates to a
conclusion, and how apparently irrelevant material does indeed help to prove or
establish a conclusion. Making sure premises are relevant to a conclusion requires
careful analysis of the possible connections between them. As noted above, the key
question is whether or not the premises are concerned with the same issue as the
conclusion and, hence, whether they are capable of telling us something about it. A
way to check this relationship is to ask, in the case of arguments, 'if this premise were
true, would it make the conclusion more likely to be true' or, for explanations, 'if this
premise were true, would it make it easier to understand why the events stated in the
conclusion happened'. Equally, we must think about the way in which our knowledge
of other events and ideas might help us to see the relevance of one particular claim in
establishing another and thus prevent us from 'missing' an important relevant premise.
Presenting relevant premises is also about making it clear that they are relevant.
In other words, use a claim, as part of a linked chain of premises, to show the rele-
vance of the premises to the conclusion. An effective argument or explanation not
only reflects careful thinking, but also clearly demonstrates it, so others can follow
your reasoning. Here is an example of how to establish relevance:
1. Australia's universities are of a high quality.
2. Australian university graduates report that their lecturers are, gener-
ally speaking, good at communicating.
3. All universities now have quality-assurance programs to maintain
quality.
4. Australia's universities attract many overseas students to them.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 77

Claim 3 mentions the words 'university' and 'quality' and is demonstrably rele-
vant through this word-similarity with claim 1. Claim 2, while possibly relevant (it
certainly mentions some evidence—good communication by university teachers—
that we might assume to be relevant), depends on exactly what the conclusion is
trying to say. Claim 1, the conclusion, is not well formed. It is vague since it does
not make clear whether it is claiming that all aspects of universities are of a high
quality or whether (as hinted at by the premises) it is merely the teaching function
of universities that is of a high quality (leaving aside, for example, research work).
So the first mistake here is that the conclusion's vagueness makes it unclear
whether the premises are relevant. Claim 4 exhibits another problem with relevance.
It may, for example, be that overseas students come to Australia because studying here
is cheap, or because they like the climate in Australia. Claim 4 becomes a relevant
premise only if the reason for the students' preference for Australia is based on the
quality of the universities. So the second mistake is that another premise ought to have
been added to make clear how claim 4 is relevant to claim 1. We might say that, while
claim 3 is self-evidently relevant (it provides, in the word 'quality', its own evidence
of how it bears on the conclusion), claim 4 is not self-evidently relevant and therefore
needs an additional, dependent premise to provide this evidence.

Exercise 6.3
For each of the following claims, write three claims that, in your view, are relevant
to showing either why they are true or why they are false (depending on whether
you agree with the claims or not).

a. Voting at elections should be compulsory.


b. Protecting the environment is more important than economic development.
c. Australia's unique cultural identity is being overwhelmed by imported
American culture.
d. Everyone should own a personal computer.

The special role of framing premises


A framing premise, discussed in chapter 4, is one that in many cases functions to
make other premises (in the same chain) relevant to a conclusion—to provide the
extra information that, when combined with other claims, shows how they relate
to the conclusion. Let us look again at the argument about quality universities. The
relevance of claim 4 to claim 1 was not clear. However, if we added another claim
to it, 'Overseas students generally seek to study at high-quality universities' (claim
5), then the relevance to claim 1 of this specific piece of evidence would be clearer.
We should remember that claims initially connect two component parts. In this
case, claim 1 connects universities and quality; claim 4, on the surface, relates
universities with another issue—overseas students. This problem can be overcome
only if the third claim, claim 5, links together overseas students with quality.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
78 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Exercise 6.4
Go back to exercise 6.3 and review what you have done. You will need some
further premises to show why the ones you have given are relevant to the four
conclusions. Add a premise in each case.

Another example of using an additional claim to show the relevance of one


claim to another concerns the use of authority to give a good foundation for claims.
In the previous chapter, we saw how a claim can be well founded if it is supported
by reference to a relevant authority. Obviously, then, effective reasoning will
depend on our judgments of the relevance of various authorities to the claims that
we wish to make. But, as before, we must be prepared to demonstrate this
relevance. The following is an example we have already considered, but it has been
expanded so that our reasoning is transparent:

1. Australian history is marked by considerable conflict and tension over


the competing interests of labour and capital.
2. Rickard, Australia: A Cultural History (1992) asserts claim 1 .
3. Rickard is a relevant authority on such matters.
4. Rickard is a widely published and well-respected Australian historian.
5. If historians are widely published and well respected, then we can be
confident that they are a relevant authority.

0^0
Y

©
Think about this example and how similar it is to the basic form of reasoning
discussed in chapter 3. Can you see that claims 4 and 5 serve to establish that
Rickard is indeed a relevant authority, as asserted in claim 3 (and hence go above
this claim in the diagram)? Claim 3, in turn, is added to claim 2 (the reference to
Rickard's book) to show its relevance in founding claim 1.
From this example we can see that the reasoning that, logically, underpins the
simple use of a reference can be long-winded. However, the lesson to learn from this
is not that we should be so explicit and lengthy in our own work. Rather, when we

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 79

want to develop an effective argument or explanation, we have to decide which


premises need to have their relevance substantiated and which premises do not.
Making this decision requires that we understand what is expected of us in reasoning.
We must also consider the degree to which our audience will accept that what we
claim to be relevant really is, even though we give no evidence for its relevance.
Decisions about what to include or not include to establish relevance can only
be made by thinking about the context. Imagine if I were to argue that 'all
Australians should give due recognition to Aboriginal native title claims' (claim 1)
and I gave, broadly, three reasons to show why:
2. Both common law and legislation demand such recognition.
3. Aborigines were the first inhabitants of the continent we now call
Australia.
4. Henry Reynolds has written an excellent book on the history of
Aboriginal-European relations called The Other Side of the Frontier
(1980).

For claim 2, I would not consider it necessary to explain the relevance of the
legal position; I would simply assume that my audience would see that a legal
requirement was relevant to what all Australians should do. For claim 3, I would
consider it necessary to explain to some audiences (perhaps those ignorant of such
matters) the relevance of the claim (by adding the claim 'The first inhabitants of a
land mass have inalienable rights to that land', claim 5); I would assume that other
audiences would see the relevance. For claim 4, I would always seek to explain the
relevance of this unusual premise (by adding the claims 'This book incontrovert-
ibly demonstrates the need for reconciliation' and 'native title claims are essential to
reconciliation', claim 6).

©©.© 0 + ©
G
https://books.yossr.com/en/books
80 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Here is another example that shows how context involves both people and
ideas. Students at university usually write for a knowledgeable academic and fail to
work carefully through all the issues, assuming that the academic will 'fill in the
gaps'. In doing so, they forget that they must also meet one of the contextual
requirements of scholarly work: that they not make too many assumptions, not
presume that the audience is clever and will 'get' the point of the essay. Hence many
essays fail to achieve the required standard because their authors have not
consciously considered and learnt about the context into which they fit. This point
is significant in all communication. Whenever we communicate we must actively
imagine and reflect on our context and how that might influence the way we
present our arguments and explanations.

Exercise 6.5
For the following argument, add claims that satisfactorily show why the given
premises (claims 2, 3, and 4) are relevant to the conclusion. Then indicate two
contexts for each: one in which you would explicitly establish relevance and one
in which you would not.

1. All Australians should learn about their own nation's history.


2. History helps us to understand what is happening now.
3. Australia's history tells many stories of the fight for democracy and
justice.
4. Learning about Australian history involves learning to write essays.

Strength of support
It is very important to think about the strength of the support that we can give our
claims. There are two distinct issues involved. First of all, we must have good
evidence. A well-founded claim, by virtue of the fact that it is well founded, will
have a number of good premises, which should be provided to assist our audience
in accepting and understanding it. But a more significant issue in communicating
our reasoning is to decide which of the supporting claims that we know about
should be explicitly stated in our argument or explanation. We should also be able
to decide when we need to do more research to find out if the claims we want to
make can be supported. The issue of well-founded claims must, in part, depend on
an analysis of whether or not the claims are true or not, but it also requires that we
consider carefully how we communicate our arguments and explanations. The
following discussion addresses this second consideration.

The burden of proof


Even if all the premises are acceptable, and even if they are relevant, you neverthe-
less still may not be effective in your reasoning. Why? Because, at base, you must

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 81

always offer enough support for your audience to be convinced that the conclusion
of your argument is acceptable or that the explanation of it is complete. Strength
of support is, like relevance, very dependent upon the context in which we are
reasoning, and we can never be certain that we have given enough support for our
conclusions. On the other hand, if we do think about this context, then we can
greatly improve the chances that we will be effective.
The first such context issue concerns the burden of proof. The following
example is drawn from a legal situation. In a court case, the two opposing parties
do not come to court each with an equal task. In a criminal trial, for example, the
prosecution has the burden of proof. If it fails to establish the guilt of the
defendant, then the defendant goes free; the defence does not have to prove
innocence, but must merely defeat the prosecution's attempts to prove guilt. There
are two common measures of the burden of proof in the law. In criminal cases, the
prosecution must prove beyond reasonable doubt that the defendant is guilty. In civil
cases, a less onerous burden is carried by the plaintiff (the one who initiates the
action). The plaintiff must prove, on the balance of probabilities, that they are right;
the respondent's task is to establish a greater probability that their side of the
argument is correct.
It is rare, outside legal and quasi-legal contexts, for the burden of proof on one
side of an argument to be recognised formally. Yet, the implicit idea behind it is
found in all reasoning. One person has a more demanding job of proving a point
and, if they fail, then an alternative position remains the preferred one. One person
must provide more evidence, must positively show their conclusion to be true.
Usually existing conclusions require less evidence or, perhaps, will be taken to be
true unless clearly shown otherwise. Obviously, those who have the burden of proof
in an argumentative situation will need stronger, more compelling support for their
conclusion than their opponents. The problem, however, is to determine where this
burden lies.
As with all these contextually based judgments, it is impossible to provide some
ready formula by which we can always ascertain the burden of proof—who has it
and how onerous it is. Each situation will be different. However, as a general rule,
we must (when arguing or explaining) consider the established true claims that
conflict with our proposed reasoning. For example:

Historians in twentieth-century Australia had, up until the 1970s, a


well-established position on Aboriginal responses to white invasion:
Aboriginal people, it was claimed and accepted, did little to resist the
encroachment of Europeans' settlement. Both experts and the commu-
nity agreed; this view was found in numerous books and articles. In fact,
few historians even bothered to explore the issue, since they were sure
they had the correct answer to the question 'What was the Aborigines'
response?'. Then, from about 1 9 7 2 onwards, historians began to look
again at the evidence and come to startling new conclusions. But, as
Henry Reynolds, a leading exponent of this historical revision, has
noted, he and like-minded historians had to amass significant amounts

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
82 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

of compelling evidence before the orthodox view was overturned.


Equally, recent arguments that run counter to the new orthodoxy that
Aboriginal people resisted in numerous ways have failed—by and large—
to achieve much currency, precisely because they do not have enough
evidence behind them. 2

Who is correct is not the issue here. What matters is that we recognise that
context creates a background of accepted conclusions and explanations, which if an
established position is challenged, must be taken into account to decide if the new
reasoning provides sufficient support for its conclusions.

Justifying all aspects of the conclusion


As we know, claims are complex statements that tie together all sorts of informa-
tion about ideas, scope, certainty, values, and so on. As a result, any reasoning to
support or explain a claim (the conclusion) must attend to each aspect of that
claim. For example, if we wanted to explain why 'Most people do not understand
that late capitalism will never sustain unemployment levels lower than 5 per cent',
then there are many aspects of the claim that need explanation. At the very least,
our premises would need to answer the following questions:
• Why 'Most people' (and not some or all or none)?
• Why do they not understand this point?
• What is late capitalism?
• Why will late capitalism not sustain low unemployment?
• Why 'lower than 5 per cent' (and not a smaller or larger proportion)?
• What is unemployment (does it include, for example, partial employ-
ment)?
• Why is the word 'sustain' used?

Part of the trick in reasoning effectively is to frame our conclusions in such a


way that we can justify all of what they state explicitly. There is no point, for
example, in concluding that 'capitalism has never caused social problems'. Even if
we wish to argue that capitalism is better than any other economic system, it is
better to assert the conclusion in a way that does acknowledge its problems, while
still making an argument that it has some advantages. On the other hand, we
should not be afraid to state our conclusions (if we believe in them) and then go to
the effort of covering all the many aspects involved. For example, the Australian
historians, such as Reynolds, who dramatically improved our understanding of
Aboriginal-European relations did not back away from their conclusion that
Aboriginal people actively and persistently resisted European invasion simply
because it was hard to prove. They did the detailed research necessary to establish
this conclusion.
Justifying all aspects of the conclusion is particularly necessary when the
conclusion contains some value component. The premises must provide support
both for the descriptive basis of the claim and for the value judgment that it makes

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 83

either implicitly or explicitly. For example, to support the conclusion that 'The
problem of unemployment in a late capitalist economy demands government
regulation of the labour market' carries with it a similar range of issues as the last
example. Yet it also concerns further issues regarding the values implicit in the
claim. Is unemployment necessarily a problem? It would not be implausible to
imagine that some people would favour higher unemployment (as, for example, a
way of keeping wage costs down). The trick is to be aware of the connotations of
our conclusions—those less obvious meanings and implications, which even
though they are not explicit in the stated claim, nevertheless require explanation or
argument. Such an awareness is the hallmark of effective reasoning. Once again, it
is the context (audience, general expectations, and so on) that makes clear what
connotations we might need to consider. Arguments about Aboriginal-European
relations, for example, now occur in a context that is completely different to that
of thirty years ago, precisely because general knowledge among Australians about
this issue has changed and the attitudes towards Aboriginal people among white
Australians are somewhat more positive than in the 1970s.

Breadth of premises
It is rare to find a claim that is so simple in what it asserts about the world that it
can be easily supported by one or two premises; what is more, when explaining why
an event has occurred, the reasons on which our explanation are based are likely to
be highly complex. Hence, as well as giving depth to each individual reason
(expressed as a chain of premises), we also need to give a broad argument when
required. Such breadth ensures that reasoning is not rendered ineffective by
oversimplification. There is, of course, no general rule regarding how much
information should be given in support of a conclusion: it depends on the con-
clusion and the context. No reason should be given that is irrelevant to the con-
clusion. Yet we should not exclude relevant information; otherwise we will not deal
with the full complexity of an issue.
The need for breadth is particularly evident in reasoning about why things have
happened or why they might in future happen (cause and effect). For example, if
we were to argue that Australia's current rate of immigration is too low', we could
develop a series of arguments about the effects of low immigration, drawing on
various aspects of this topic. Without at the moment unpacking them into
complete premises, there are at least four different 'reasons':

a A larger population provides significant economic benefits.


b Higher immigration provides significant cultural benefits.
c Higher immigration is a sign to the rest of the world that Australia is
a good international citizen,
d Higher immigration will increase Australia's defence capabilities.

Each reason concerns a different aspect of the problem—a different point that,
independently, supports the conclusion. Why would a collection of reasons be

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
84 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

needed here? Well, to say simply that the economy benefits may be countered by
an argument that there is no point in having a strong economy if the result is an
impoverished culture. In such a situation, the conclusion may well not be accepted
and our argument would be ineffective. Or, for example, if we were to fail to
provide reason c, those people in our audience who would themselves argue for the
primacy of international relations in determining economic, cultural, and defence
conditions might not be convinced.
As we might expect, for most claims there are arguments for and against; there
are explanations from one angle and another. Whenever we reason, we are, by
definition, setting up an opposition with possible counter-arguments. To give
sufficient support to our own conclusion, we must give evidence that defeats, or at
least casts doubt on, likely counter-arguments in advance of them actually being
mounted against what we are proposing. For example, we know that one significant
reason that opposes our conclusion that 'Australia's current rate of immigration is
too low' is that 'social tensions will increase with increased immigration'. If we
know in advance that such a counter-reason exists and we fail to address it, then we
are making our reasoning less effective. First, we run the risk of appearing to have
failed to understand all the relevant issues (and thus casting doubt on our overall
competence). Second, we may find people unconvinced of our conclusion, even
though they accept all of the positive reasons we give. The response of such people
might be: 'Well, defence, politics, culture, and the economy will all improve, but
that means nothing if the society that all those other things serve is falling apart'.
That we disagree will not matter; the error we will have made is that our disagree-
ment has not been included in the original argument we presented. So, in general
terms, effective reasoning requires that we cover all the relevant issues involved in
establishing or explaining our conclusion, whether they are positive or negative.3
We do need to consider whether or not our arguments and explanations meet
objective criteria of strength. We need to consider whether they are well founded
and strong regardless of what any particular audience thinks of them. However,
because knowledge is never used or useful outside a social, non-objective context,4
we must also consider the audiences of our reasoning. Hence breadth of premises
can best be understood in relation to the burden of proof. In essence, to meet our
burden of proof, we must mainly meet the expectations of our audiences, but not
simply 'give in' to what they want to hear.
If an audience, for example, expects to see, in a discussion of contemporary
European-Aboriginal relations, some consideration of the history of those
relations, then we would be failing our audience if we did not offer it or did not,
at least, dismiss the relevance of such a consideration. Which approach we would
use, of course, depends on our views of the topic, but as a general rule, it is fair to
say that our arguments must address (either positively or negatively) those aspects
of a topic that we guess our audience is expecting to see covered in our reasoning.
Furthermore, if the members of our audience have mixed backgrounds—with some
being more convinced by and interested in economic arguments, others by histor-
ical arguments, and a third group by purely moral or ethical arguments—then all

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 85

groups would need to be covered. By contrast, in a report on the legal aspects of


European-Aboriginal relations, the audience's expectations would be narrower: the
context of the report ('legal aspects') would exclude other reasons, which if we were
to introduce them, might actually weaken our arguments because they would be
irrelevant to the particular issue being reported on.
In summary, not only do we need to understand issues well, but we must also
understand our audience and other contextual factors so that we can judge what
should or should not be included in any argument or explanation.

Exercise 6.6
Take any argument or explanation that you are writing at the moment or have
recently written. Begin by establishing clearly in your own mind the context for
your work, including its audience, and the sorts of constraints or requirements
that the context places on you. Step by step, apply to it all of the issues discussed
in this section, with the aim of improving it.

Coherence in scope and certainty


Finally, we must consider the relationship between what we are claiming as our
conclusion and the evidence used to support it, as expressed through the scope and
certainty aspects of the claims. If the premises and conclusion are coherent in this
respect, then our reasoning is more effective. Coherence of scope, while always
important, is particularly significant in reasoning from specific cases. Here is an
example:
John has met a few Aborigines who are alcoholics, and therefore he
concludes that all Aboriginal people are alcoholics.

The error John makes here is that the scope of his premise ('a few') is not
coherent with the scope of the conclusion ('all'). Hence he has overgeneralised in
his conclusion. Similarly, if John was to visit one Aboriginal community in
which, say, a third of its members were alcoholics, he would also be wrong to
conclude that A third of all Aboriginal people are alcoholics'. The scope of his
premises (just one community) is not coherent with the conclusion about all
Aborigines, since that community is most unlikely to be a representative sample
of the entire Aboriginal population. However, if John were to continue his
investigations and discover that, say, 70 per cent of Aboriginal people in outback
areas suffer from poor health, he would be equally in error to conclude that 'Poor
health is, thus, a small problem for outback Aboriginals'. Such a conclusion
understates the extent of the situation and again reflects a lack of coherence
between premise and conclusion. General conclusions are not, of themselves, the
problem: we could not think and know without reasonable generalisations.
Rather, we must always be sure that the generalisations are properly grounded in
the specific cases on which they rely.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
86 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Issues of scope and certainty are also important in reasoning from generalisation.
The purpose of linking together a particular case with a general rule in the premises
is to then draw a conclusion about that specific case based on the generalisation.
The scope of the conclusion, therefore, must be coherent with the generalisation.
The following example shows good coherence:
The incidence of major earthquakes in areas located away from major
tectonic fault-lines is low; Australia is such an area, and hence we can
predict that Australia will rarely suffer from major earthquakes.

However, another example demonstrates poor coherence:


Generally speaking, students at Australian universities receive a high-quality
education. Ho Ming intends to study at the University of Melbourne and fears
that he will not receive a high-quality education.

On the basis of the premise, Ho is wrong to hold these fears.

Exercise 6.7
Look at the following conclusions. Without thinking about whether they are true, and
thinking only about the words as they appear in front of you (especially those that
define the scope and certainty of the conclusion), indicate which conclusions are
milder and which are stronger (in relation to one another). Then think about the sorts
of audiences that would need more or less argument to persuade them. Who would
easily be persuaded of the conclusions? Who would be sceptical of these conclusions?

a. All Australians should be forced to do national military service.


b. One option is to consider limited military service for some young Australians.
c. We should definitely establish an inquiry to consider the possibility of
introducing national military service.

Review
Effective reasoning requires that we attend to a wide variety of factors, both
in our analysis of the connections between claims and then in the presenta-
tion of those claims and connections. We cannot, truly, separate out the needs
of effective analysis and presentation, since our analysis will always be influ-
enced by the context in which reasoning occurs, and that context is, by and
large, determined by the knowledge and expectations of our likely audience.
Some of the ways to be more effective in reasoning concern the links
between premises: if we make these links well, unpacking any initial 'reason'
for a conclusion into a clear chain of dependent premises, then our analysis
has depth. In particular, we must avoid allowing any claims that are doubtful
to remain implicit, or failing to make explicit links between claims that are not
obvious; such assumptions can only be tested if we are explicit about all the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
MORE EFFECTIVE REASONING II: BETTER LINKS 87

necessary claims in the chain. Equally, we must not confuse claims that
support another claim (diagrammed above the claim being supported) with
claims that are dependent (diagrammed alongside one another).
The relationships of premises above with conclusion below are only strong
if the premises are relevant and provide strong support. We judge relevance by
looking at whether or not the premise is connected in some way to the conclu-
sion (through the form of words or the issues involved or via some background
knowledge). To establish relevance, we can include a framing premise if
necessary or write our claims more carefully. Premises provide sufficient
support for a conclusion if, in context, other people will judge the degree of
support to be sufficient. We can ensure effective reasoning only by making
sure that we satisfy any burden of proof we have, attending to the detail of our
conclusion (justifying all aspects of it), making sure there is coherence
between scope and certainty, and reasoning broadly where necessary.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:
breadth of reasoning
burden of proof
depth of reasoning
relevance
strength of support

Review exercise 6
Answer briefly the following questions, giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book:
a. How many reasons does a chain of dependent premises offer in support of
a conclusion?
b. What is an implied premise?
c. What is the difference between the relevance and acceptability of a claim?
d. How might a framing premise be used in connection with relevance?
e. What role does the idea of well-founded claims play in relation to
relevance and support?
f. What is the difference between depth and breadth of reasoning?
g. How can we use scope and certainty to judge the effectiveness of
reasoning?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
88 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

h. What role does context (and especially audience) play in effective


reasoning?

NOTES

1 In the process of unpacking, however, we usually think of additional, separate reasons


that did not immediately occur to us. For example, in thinking through the detail of the
economic reason, we might also come up with other reasons. One that occurs to me is
that there is a moral argument concerning the rights of citizens to free education.
2 See the introduction to H. Reynolds, The Other Side of the Frontier, Penguin Books,
Melbourne, 1 9 8 0 .
3 Note that this requirement to think ahead about counter-arguments is particularly
important in written reasoning. In a conversation, we have an immediate opportunity to
respond to objections, but in a written argument, there are no such opportunities.
4 See chapter 9 for a brief discussion of objective strength (determined without reference
to audience) as opposed to intersubjective strength (in which the audience plays a
significant role). This complex philosophical debate is too involved to discuss here and,
whether or not you believe that knowledge can be objectively true, the need to think
about audiences remains very important.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
7

What Kinds of
Reasoning are There?
We have now finished with our detailed look at the analytical structure
approach. This chapter will consider, in a more general way, how to think
about the types of reasoning we might use and encounter. I already noted, in
chapter 2, that basically reasoning is either about relationships across time
(cause and effect), or within the sets or groups into which we divide and
classify objects at any given moment. But there are some other ways of
thinking about reasoning that are worth exploring in more detail, while
recognising that there is no set way to classify or assert that you are using
'one type of reasoning' but not another. In this chapter we will:
1 Examine the difference between deductive and inductive reasoning—a
commonly misunderstood difference.
2 Look at the difference between categorical and propositional logic, to
discover in particular how propositions ('if..., then...') can be useful.
3 Look at five types of reasoning, known as reasoning from cause,
generalisation, specific cases, analogy, and terms (i.e. definitional).

Deductive and inductive reasoning


A common error
The difference between deduction and induction is one of the more vexed issues in
contemporary logic. Exactly how (and why) we distinguish between them is subject
both to erroneous views and legitimate disagreements. First, let me dispose of a
common error, one that has probably been taught to you (or you have read) at some

https://books.yossr.com/en/books 89
90 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

stage. It is often claimed that deduction is a form of reasoning from general rules
to specific premises and that induction is the reverse, that is, reasoning from
specific cases to a general conclusion. Now, no matter what you might see or read
elsewhere, this is wrong. The difference between deduction and induction has
nothing to do with general or specific reasoning, but has everything to do with
what the conclusion does on the basis of the premises.
We will explore this genuine difference in a moment but let me reassure you
that, if the distinction seems hard to grasp, you are not alone. Philosophers
have generally sought to retreat to those examples and cases of reasoning which
are clearly deductive and clearly inductive: they have not engaged with the
muddy mass of indistinct cases which are, by and large, the everyday reasoning
we use.

Deduction
In deductive reasoning, your conclusion states with certainty a relationship
between two or more premises. It has to be certain, because it simply makes explicit
a relationship that is already there (but not directly obvious) in the combination of
the claims that are serving as premises. You will remember this aspect from the
discussion of claims in chapters 2 to 4 . Let us look at an example:

I am under 1 8 ; people under 1 8 in Australia cannot vote. Therefore I


cannot vote.

There are three key terms in this argument. One is age (under 18); the other is
voting; and the last is T . The conclusion simply re-expresses the implicit relation-
ship of the premises which can be expressed, in a formula way, like this:

A is one of B; B can't do C; therefore A can't do C.

The certainty with which (in this argument) the conclusion is stated relates not
to the truth or otherwise of the premises but to the logical form of the argument.
If it turns out that the premises are indeed true, then the conclusion is guaranteed
both by the truth of the premises and by the form of the reasoning.
The key test for a deductive argument is to ask yourself, being absolutely
trusting, 'can you deny the conclusion, if it is that you previously have no doubt or
deny the premises'. For example:

African swallows are migratory birds; all migratory birds fly long distances
and therefore I conclude African swallows fly long distances.

Now, let us assume absolutely and without doubt that the premises are true.
Can you deny (refuse to accept) the conclusion now? No! Do not be confused
and think 'Ah, but maybe African swallows are not migratory birds'; if you have
this doubt then you have not accepted the first premise. Deductive thinking is
something of a mind game (an important one, nevertheless): checking for
deductive entailment (where the conclusion is guaranteed by the premises) first

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
WHAT KINDS OF REASONING ARE THERE? 91

of all proceeds from the assumption that the premises are absolutely correct. If
they are, then you simply need to check that the conclusion follows logically
from them. Only then can you go back and see if there are doubts about the
premises.

Induction
In an inductive argument, unlike deduction, if the premises are true, then the
conclusion is only probably true and how big a chance that it is true depends on
the weight of evidence presented in the premises. The conclusion, then, in an
inductive argument is not guaranteed by the premises, but only supported by them.
Often, the difference expresses itself in the way that an inductive conclusion does
not state an implicit relationship but goes beyond the premises to make a new claim
altogether. Here is an example:

Imagine that, in the best traditions of the board game Cluedo, you are
conducting a murder investigation. Mr Green's body has been found
stabbed to death. In the course of your investigations, you discover
that:

Mr White says he saw Mr Black stab Green.


Black is well known to have hated Green.
Green's blood is found on Black's hands.
Ms Yellow heard Green gasp 'Black is stabbing me!'

These four claims serve as reasonably compelling evidence that Mr Black was
the murderer. However, can you be certain? No. You can only gather evidence to
increase the probability that you are correct in judging Black to be the murderer.
Indeed, if this case were to go to court, then the test used by the jury to convict or
not convict would be one of'reasonable doubt'. The jury would not have to be 100
per cent certain, simply convinced beyond a reasonable doubt that Black was guilty.
So, although you would accuse Black as if you were certain he was the murderer, in
purely logical terms you would not have deduced that conclusion from the
evidence, but have induced it and thus always be fractionally short of absolute
certainty. Remember that the claim which serves as the conclusion in this argument
'Black killed Green' is not completely implied in the premises, as we shall see ...

You, being a good detective, do some more checking and discover that:

White told people Black hated Green.


Black got bloody trying to help Green.
White disguised himself as Black to do the job.

Hence, the probability now swings around to White being the murderer. Again,
you cannot be certain, but would probably now proceed to accuse White.
Induction, then, is the process of gathering evidence and, rather than stating
something already completely contained in the premises (but not openly stated),

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
92 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

making some prediction or estimate of what the most likely conclusion would be
given that evidence.
The lesson to learn here is: if you think about the kinds of complex arguments
that you have been developing in earlier chapters of this book, what you will
probably see is that, towards the end of a complex argument, the reasoning will
become deductive, carefully delineating a logical set of relationships that, in the
earlier parts of the complex argument have been established through inductive
reasoning.

Categorical and propositional logic


Now we will look at the two common forms of deductive reasoning. For a long
time, logic was primarily thought to consist in the formation of definitive
relationships (such as the deductive examples above), normally expressed in the
form:

Humans are mammals.


All mammals breathe air.
Therefore humans breathe air.

Such reasoning is called categorical precisely because it is not about actual


events so much as the ideal categories by which we can define and discriminate
the innumerable things in the world into a regular pattern or order. What is
significant is that categorical logic is mostly associated with European thinking
prior to the modern era of scientific investigation and the constant quest to
discover what was new, rather than earlier attempts to precisely define a never-
changing pattern of categories and attributes. It should also be noted that this
form of reasoning depends absolutely on how we define terms such as air and
breathe, and how precisely we use words in our claims. Technically fish also
breathe—they breathe water and extract from it, if not 'air' then air's
constituent elements. Yet fish are not mammals. Thus while useful to
understand, categorical reasoning is more interesting for our purposes in that
it models how dominant forms of reasoning are bound up in the social order
of their time.
Propositional logic on the other hand depends upon propositions: statements
that propose a relationship between two states of affairs. Technically these
statements should be expressed as 'if..., then...' claims. However it is possible to
write them in such a way as to imply, rather than explicitly state, the propositional
nature of the claim. If the Ancient Greeks spent a lot of time philosophising about
how specific items and general groups might be put together and thus developed
categorical logic to a fine art, in the nineteenth century, European philosophers
became fascinated by propositional logic. If/then statements are, probably, at the
heart of most of our reasoning, even though we often do not realise it. They link
together one event (the ' i f part) and propose that if it happens, then something

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
WHAT KINDS OF REASONING ARE THERE? 93

else will also occur. It is, perhaps, the philosopher's version of Newton's third law
of thermodynamics, which stated that all actions have an opposite and equal
reaction. Let us have a look at an example which uses a series of if/then statements
to prove that Australia's economic health depends, not on low wages, but on high
wages:

1. If Australia's wages are reduced, then people will have less to spend.
2. If people have less to spend, then consumption will fall.
3. If consumption falls, then the economy will slow down.
4. If the economy slows, then business profits will fall.
5. Therefore, if we want to avoid a loss in profit, we must not reduce
wages.

The power and flexibility of propositional logic is demonstrated by this


example, not because these premises guarantee the conclusion is true, but rather
because they create a series of logical relationships between two otherwise
apparently unconnected events—the need to avoid a loss in profit and the desire
not to reduce wages. If we were then to set about convincing someone of this
ultimate conclusion, we would, by having set up the chain of propositions in this
manner, have identified the key sub-conclusions that would each need to be
supported by sub-arguments. Thus, we would have to establish that it was indeed
reasonable to believe that 'If consumption falls, then the economy will slow down',
and we might do this by reference to real-world examples such as previous
economic conditions in which a fall in consumption has indeed caused an
economic slowdown.
The lesson to learn here is: while categorical logic concerns itself with the
structural relationship of the categories we use, defining the inclusions and
exclusions so that we can be sure what does or does not belong together as a group,
propositional logic prompts us to ask the right questions about what we need to
establish, inductively, to then make our overall argument convincing.

Five types of reasoning


It is important to recognise that these five types are not mutually exclusive. We
will consider causal reasoning but, for example, we also see that when looking
at causes we are also asserting analogies between the cause of one event and
another. Equally, when we look at analogies, there are ways in which analogical
reasoning is the same as reasoning from generalisations or might involve causal
relationships. Thus, the five types presented here are not done so in the same
manner as the discussion of deduction/induction which showed how arguments
of one type (in each case) could not be of the other type. Rather, I present these
five types to assist you in thinking more broadly about the kinds of questions
you might ask in your reasoning and (as we will see in chapter 8) to guide your
search for information.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
94 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Causal reasoning
Reasoning from cause is very common and we are all familiar with it, if only in a
common-sense way. If someone asks you 'Why did you buy this book?', you might
reply 'because it was reasonably cheap and looked interesting'; alternatively you
might say 'because someone recommended that I buy it' or even 'because it was a
compulsory textbook for my studies'. In all cases, you have stated what event or fact
caused you to buy this book. Hence, in a causal relationship between claims, the
premise or premises state the cause, and the conclusion states the effect resulting
from that cause.
Now, very often we use a simple causal claim, such as 'Australia's economic
weakness in the world economy is caused by its reliance on commodity exports'. As
we know, a claim does have an internal connection between the cause and the
effect. We should be careful to remember that a single claim, such as the one just
given, is not an argument or explanation. However, this claim does imply that it is
the result of (or conclusion to) causal reasoning. So, in making good links between
premises and conclusions, where we are reasoning about cause and effect, we need
to spell out what that relationship is. For example:
Australia is reliant on commodity exports; such exports are always at risk
of natural disasters and price fluctuations; these risks lead to weakness,
and hence, Australia has a weak economy in global terms.

When we are attempting to link claims in order to express a causal relationship,


there are two general rules that are particularly useful. First of all, we can look for
the factor that is the only difference between two given situations. For example:
Before recent changes to industrial relations laws, labour unions could not
be excluded by employers from most wage negotiations; now they can be.
Not much else has changed, however. Since this legislative change took
place, average wages have declined dramatically. Hence, I conclude that
the likely cause of this reduction in wages has been the exclusion of
unions from wage negotiations.

The two situations that are being compared are the higher level of average wages
in the past and the lower level of average wages now. The argument in the example
seeks to establish that the only differing factor in these two situations, which might
explain the change in wage levels, is the exclusion of unions. We can express this
rule thus:
X is the cause of Y because the only relevant difference between Y
happening and not happening is that X was only present when Y
happened.

The second general rule for determining causal relationships requires us to look
for the only similarity or common element in two or more situations. Take the
following argument as an example:

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
WHAT KINDS OF REASONING ARE THERE? 95

Jones and Wilson have both been sacked by the company that used to
employ them. Jones, a middle-aged male cleaner, was a poor worker with
a history of arriving late; Wilson, a young woman working as a filing clerk,
had always been judged by her boss to be a competent worker. But both
Jones and Wilson had just been elected union delegates, and thus, I would
reasonably conclude that it was their active participation in the union that
led to their dismissal.

The differences between the two workers contrast with their similar treatment
(both were sacked); so, the only other similarity between them (that they were
union delegates) seems to be the likely cause of their dismissal. We can express this
rule thus:

X is the cause of Y because it is the only relevant similarity between two


separate occurrences of Y happening.

The other key aspect to causal reasoning is to appreciate that some causal
events are necessary, and others are sufficient. If I assert that oxygen is necessary
for a fire to occur, I am not saying that oxygen causes fires. Thus the presence
of oxygen is a necessary condition, but not sufficient. However, while a lighted
match is sufficient to set fire to a pile of dry paper if dropped on it, it is not
necessary — I could also use a flamethrower or focus the heat of the sun with a
magnifying glass.
In the many complex causal situations that we encounter, it will be impossible
to isolate the only relevant difference or the only relevant similarity. We will also
struggle to determine necessary and sufficient causes because we cannot (normally)
conduct repeated experiments in which we determine the relative state of each causal
element. Rather, we will normally be confronted by a whole jumble of possible
differences and similarities. So, the main function of our investigation of causes, and
of the resulting causal arguments and explanations we write, will be to assign some
significance to each cause (was it a minor or major cause? was it significant enough
to count as a sufficient cause on its own?) or to discover the interrelationship
between causes. We also need to consider the degree to which each cause was beyond
or within human control (was the cause a direct human action, or something in the
general environment?). Further, we need to avoid assuming, simply because events
happen in close proximity to one another, that they are necessarily related as cause
and effect. Perhaps it was simply a coincidence that, for example, the two workers
were sacked. Alternatively, we might argue, in relation to the first example, that there
is a common cause: wage reductions and union exclusion are not necessarily effect
and cause but, rather, could both be the effects of some other cause—perhaps
structural changes in the political economy of Australia.

Reasoning from generalisation


Reasoning from generalisation is another common form of argument or
explanation. Yet it is very different from causation. If causation, at its simplest,

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
96 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

seeks to show how one event leads to another, reasoning from generalisation shows
how knowledge about a general class or category of events allows us to make a
conclusion about a specific event that fits the general category. For example:
All children who have been fully immunised are protected against some
common and life-threatening diseases, such as whooping cough, polio,
and diphtheria. Therefore, Steven, who has been immunised, is most
unlikely to fall sick with these diseases.
The general form of such arguments is as follows:
Class X is defined by the fact that the individual cases within that class
all have property A in common; hence any individual case that is a
member of that class will also exhibit property A.
So, arguing from a generalisation involves two distinct steps. First of all, it must
be established that the specific case does indeed fit the general class that is
proposed, that it is consistent. Once that 'fit' is established, then we must draw a
conclusion that relies, not on our knowledge of the specific case, but our knowledge
of the general class.
Imagine, for a moment, that you are a doctor. A woman comes to see
you with the following symptoms: swollen glands, sore throat, weakness
in the muscles, and a rash of small red spots across the back and chest.
You are not sure what is wrong with the patient but can use reasoning
to make a diagnosis: 'Almost all people who have these symptoms are
suffering from measles; this particular patient has these symptoms;
therefore she is suffering from measles'. Further, you can determine
treatment on the basis of the generalisation that 'All people suffering
from the measles need to spend a week resting in bed and take anti-
biotics to prevent secondary infections'. You know, with reasonable
confidence, that this patient has measles and so can prescribe this
treatment for her.

Let us explore this form of relationship by imagining that a class is like a box
into which we put all the items that are the same as one another. On the lid of this
box are a list of requirements that determine which items can and cannot be
included. Patients who have the swollen glands and sore throat, but not the red
spots, could not be placed in the 'measles sufferer' class because they would not
meet all the requirements. Patients with the red spots but no other symptoms
would also fail to qualify (they probably have a skin irritation instead). However, as
well as a set of requirements for membership of a class or category, a generalisation
also includes a judgment that sums up the nature of those items in the category
('people with these symptoms have measles'). Hence there are two aspects to a
generalisation: a condition that determines what specific cases fit into the
generalisation, and another condition that states the common consequence or state
relating to that generalisation.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
WHAT KINDS OF REASONING ARE THERE? 97

When we are confident about our generalisations, and a specific case does fit a
particular general category, then reasoning from generalisations is very easy and
effective. The trick is in making that initial judgment about the relationship
between the specific case and the generalisation, as expressed in the premises, so
that our conclusion (also about the specific case) is well supported. At the same
time, we should recognise that many items fit a number of generalisations—that
often an 'item' has many conflicting qualities or components that make it hard to
judge the appropriate generalisation. For example, doctors are often confronted
with a series of symptoms in a patient that could mean any one of a number of
illnesses. The tests that doctors perform are designed to work out exactly which
'generalisation' to apply to the specific patient and thus make sure that the correct
treatment is prescribed.

Reasoning from specific cases


Where do these generalisations come from? Do we just make them up? No, in most
cases they have been established via reasoning—in this instance, from specific cases
to a generalisation. The difference in reasoning from specific cases is that, although
a general statement is involved, it is not used as a premise but as the conclusion.
We routinely find such reasoning in, for example, opinion polls, statistical analyses,
or any other surveys in which the reasoning supports conclusions that generalise
beyond the specific scope of those premises. For example, I might argue from
specific cases in this manner:
I have surveyed 1 0 0 0 Australians, from all social classes and ethnic back-
grounds, and 7 0 per cent of them tell me that they favour changing from
a monarchy to a republic. Hence, I would conclude that most Australians
also support this change. Ninety per cent of.the respondents who were
born overseas or whose parents were born overseas were positive about
Australia becoming a republic. Hence, I further conclude that republican
sentiment will be strongest among the newer members of the Australian
community.

There are two conclusions here; each is a general statement about what all
Australians think, based on a sample of 1000 specific cases. The premises provide
a summary of the many specific cases. Nevertheless, relative to the premises, the
conclusions are much broader assertions ('most Australians' and 'newer members').
The general form of such arguments is as follows:

Specific cases (x) of the general category X show the common property A;
hence, generally speaking, we can expect all members of the category X to
have the common property A.

Reasoning from specific cases depends on the same sorts of judgments about
the underlying relationship between the cases and the general category that we
encountered in the previous section on reasoning from generalisations. If, for

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
98 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

example, I had 'unluckily' chosen a sample of 1000 Australians who were unusually
pro-republic, then it is unlikely that my broad conclusions would be correct. So,
good reasoning from specific cases requires some consideration of the degree to
which the cases selected represent the general category as a whole.
This question of 'representativeness' is precisely why reasoning from specific
cases needs to proceed on a sound base of'specifics'. If I were to argue, on the basis
of one bad meal of Italian food, that ^//Italian food was bad, I would be relying on
far too small a sample for my argument to be effective. Equally, we should not trust
surveys that rely on large numbers of responses from an unrepresentative group. For
example, television stations have taken to conducting 'polls' in which people ring
in to answer 'yes' or 'no' to a particular question (for example, 'Should the death
penalty be reintroduced?'). The answer is then represented as a good generalisation
of all Australians' attitudes when, in fact, it is only a generalisation of the views of
those viewers of that particular television station who were able and willing to ring
in.

Reasoning from analogy


An analogy is a special form of reasoning, which has some similarities with
reasoning from specific cases. Reasoning by analogy involves drawing an equally
specific conclusion from specific premises via a comparison of like aspects. Good
analogies avoid comparisons between items that have too many dissimilarities. For
example:
Imagine a friend gave you a guinea pig to look after but forgot to tell you
anything about what to feed it. You might say to yourself, 'I have a guinea
pig and do not know what to feed it; but I do know that my rabbit eats
carrots, and that rabbits and guinea pigs are similar. Hence, I can prob-
ably feed my guinea pig carrots as well'.

Such arguments take the following general form:


An analogy between X and Y (in the premises) supports a conclusion about
Y by showing that the conclusion is true of X; and X and Y are similar in
sufficient relevant respects and are not relevantly dissimilar.

You need to be careful to make sure that you are comparing things that are
similar in a relevant way. Take the following example of reasoning:
Shaving cream is clearly similar in colour, texture, moistness, and body to
whipped cream, and I know that whipped cream is delicious on fruit salad.
Hence, shaving cream is delicious on fruit salad.

Do you see what is wrong? The two types of cream are similar, but they are
definitely not similar in respect of the one main characteristic involved in fruit salad
eating: how they taste. This question of relevance has been explored in more detail
in chapter 6.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
WHAT KINDS OF REASONING ARE THERE? 99

While generalised and specific reasoning both depend on classifications of


individual cases in relation to general categories, analogies depend on comparison
and consistency between equally specific or equally general cases. First of all, good
analogies that do not directly involve values are formed through comparing different
things on the basis of consistency of knowledge. That is, we look around for known
cases that are similar to the unknown case, so that we are better able to predict what
we will find out. For example, if we knew that large oil spills at sea destroy the salt-
water environment, we might also predict that similar spills in a freshwater lake
would have a similarly destructive impact. Such analogies depend on the extent to
which we are sure that the world is a consistent place, and that it is very unlikely we
will find radical differences between cases similar in many respects.
Second, good analogies that involve values are formed through comparing
different things on the basis of consistency of action or belief That is, we can use
known cases that have known types of action or belief associated with them and
that are similar to the unknown case to thereby conclude that similar actions or
beliefs can be expected in those cases. Such analogies depend on the assumption
that the world ought to be a consistent place and, to the extent that we can control
what we do in the world, that we should always try to do the same things in similar
situations. For example, we would think it most unreasonable if, of three cars
parked illegally, only ours was given a parking ticket: such rules need to be applied
consistently and we expect that they will be.

Reasoning from terms


The final type of reasoning is less common but equally important. Some claims, as
we have seen, establish the definition of a particular word or phrase. Often we need
to give reasons for our definitions, either because there is some widespread doubt
about them or because we are trying to establish a particular meaning in a given
context. Here is an example:
In a true democracy, all power rests with the people; constitutionally
speaking, in a monarchy some power theoretically resides with the
monarch. Hence, a monarchy is not democratic.

Now, generally speaking, many monarchies (such as Australia) are democratic;


however, this argument establishes that, in a particular context (constitutional
theory), monarchies must be defined as undemocratic. While this definition may
seem unusual and even irrelevant to daily life in countries such as Australia, it does
have some utility within that limited context nevertheless. We tend to find that, by
its nature, definitional reasoning is deductive.

Exercise 7 . 1
Write arguments or explanations using each of the types of reasoning just
discussed. You should write these examples in the analytical structure format

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
100 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

(that is, as a list of claims and a diagram). Choose issues that are important to
you and about which you have some knowledge. You will probably find that each
one combines some elements of more than one type.

Review
This chapter has discussed various ways to think about reasoning. You have
learnt about the difference between induction and deduction: the most impor-
tant point to remember from this comparison is that some kinds of reasoning
are about the inherent logic of the way we describe the world in words: that
there are logical relationships built into claims which, necessarily, lead to
other claims. Now this kind of reasoning is not investigative but is the foun-
dation on which inductive reasoning (where you do observe and investigate the
world) is based.
You have also learnt about propositional logic which, again, is all about the
way you can use a claim that proposes how two other claims are related.
Whether or not, in the narrative flow, you actually write a claim in the stan-
dard 'if/then' format doesn't matter: very often, when we reason, we are using
propositions that, if we rewrote them more accurately, would have to be in that
form. Propositional logic is a very important way of finding the links between
apparently disparate events and drawing them together into a conclusion.
You have also considered what I call five types of reasoning. These are not
'types' like induction and deduction—an argument may contain elements of
(say) reasoning from terms, generalisation, and analogy, all through it. But an
argument can only ever be either inductive or deductive. So, these types of
reasoning are presented simply to help open your eyes to the ways in which
you need to think about your reasoning to make it better.
Thus, what we learn by considering those five types of reasoning is that all
argument and explanation starts with a consideration of similarity and differ-
ence; commonality and inconsistency; necessity and sufficiency. These
concepts are an underlying part of chapters 8 and 9, where we look at how to
find information and how to think it through.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:

analogy, reasoning from

cause, reasoning from

consistency
deduction

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
WHAT KINDS OF REASONING ARE THERE? 101

generalisation, reasoning from

induction

propositional logic

specific cases, reasoning from

terms, reasoning from

Review exercise 7
Answer briefly the following questions, giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book.

a. What is the difference between deduction and induction?


b. What is the relationship between the idea of internal connections and
propositional logic?
c. How can we work out whether one event causes another?
d. What is the purpose of giving a general rule as a premise?
e. What is the 'leap of faith' when we use a selection of cases to assert a
more general conclusion?
f. How does an example given as a premise attempt to support its con-
clusion?
g. How do I determine if an analogy is reasonable?
h. What is the point of using reasoning from terms?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
8

Research, Reasoning,
and Analysis
Advice on research usually covers 'physical' issues such as finding books,
conducting experiments, and searching computer databases. Such advice
does not, however, address the key point that, since knowledge and reasoning
are intimately connected, then searching for knowledge is a part of reasoning.
The common thread between research and reasoning is that they both involve
analysis: the thinking through of the connections between claims (or infor-
mation). If we cannot consciously control our analysis (our 'thinking moves'),
then our research will fail to address the particular needs of the argument or
explanation that we develop on the basis of what we discover. Furthermore,
there is an easy way to conceptualise what we mean by analysis: it simply
involves a constant process of asking questions. Questioning and testing
possibilities are the most important 'thinking moves'.
Four aspects of research, reasoning, and analysis will be discussed in this
chapter:

1 We will look at knowledge in more detail. Reasoning depends absolutely


on knowledge; knowledge is the way that innumerable little pieces of
information about the world are linked. Questions are a way of expressing
and testing these links and, hence, are the crucial component of analysis.
2 We will then look at four perspectives on the process of finding informa-
tion (what some might call doing research) as a reasoning process. We will
look at:

• Information understood by where we find it.


• Information as it relates to other information.
• Information classified by the topic under investigation.

102 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 103

• Information as it relates to how we are using it.


3 We will examine some general issues to do with sources. Sources can only
be used effectively if we understand that the context in which the source
was created is different from the context in which we are using the infor-
mation from that source. If we do not recognise this change in context, we
are not properly analysing that information.
4 We will look at how questions can guide our search, and at how we can
take information away from our sources, not just as 'information', but
in a form that can easily be inserted into our arguments and explan-
ations.

Reasoning and analysis


Reasoning and knowledge
What any one individual knows about the world is extremely limited. People tend
to be experts in certain small areas and ignorant in many others; their detailed
knowledge is often applicable only in limited situations. It could not be otherwise
in modern society, considering the quantities of available information and
consequent demands for specialisation. You do not need to be a walking storehouse
of information about everything, since there are many places to look if you need to
fill in gaps in your knowledge. Moreover, there are many well-established research
techniques to generate new data. In such circumstances, the truly knowledgeable
people are those who are aware of what they do not know and who have skills in
searching. These skills do not just involve knowing where and how to look for
information (for example, the ability to search the Internet for library holdings of
a particular newspaper; technical skill in interviewing; the ability to perform an
experiment). Much more importantly, searching skills involve an awareness of how
the skills are related to the process of reasoning.
We often think that 'finding things out' precedes 'thinking about them'. In fact,
just as writing and speaking (the narrative flow) are bound up with reasoning
(analytical structuring), the process of gathering the information also involves
many of the important 'thinking moves' that constitute our analysis. If we are
unaware of these 'thinking moves', then much of our research will be ineffective or
confusing. Reading, interviewing, experimenting, or any of the many research
processes are not just about finding out information; they are necessarily processes
of analysis.
Reasoning is not the result of knowing things: knowledge and reasoning are part
and parcel of one another. Knowledge consists of both individual claims and the
links between them, and hence must be expressed through arguments and
explanations. We learn knowledge by understanding these arguments and explana-
tions. Even the most specific statement of what we know (a single claim) requires

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
104 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

a connection between more than one idea. What we know is best thought of as a
network of interrelated claims—a series of potential, unexpressed arguments and
explanations in our heads and in what we read and observe. Hence, knowledge is
about relationships: our reasoning compared to, drawn from, contrasted with, and
generally taken together with the reasoning of others. One of the best ways to
understand how 'finding things out' involves various analytical processes is to
consider how questions (which can be used to guide our research) are, in fact,
deeply implicated in reasoning.

Reasoned analysis as questions


It is usually thought that the key to scholarly, intellectual work is finding the
answers. Well, it is not. Critical academic work about any topic is designed, first
and foremost, to discover the right questions to ask; the answers come later, once
those questions have been determined. While smart thinking is usually more
pragmatic than the reflective work done by intellectuals, the same general rule
applies in developing our analysis. Thinking first about questions is much smarter
than trying to think first about answers.
We can understand the significance of questions by thinking about their
relationship to the basic process of reasoning—the linking of claims. For example,
if I ask 'Does the historical racism of white Australia towards Asians still interfere
with Australia's diplomatic relations with Malaysia?', then I am tentatively making
the claim 'the historical racism of white Australia towards Asians still interferes with
Australia's diplomatic relations with Malaysia'. The answer to my question will, in
effect, be a judgment of the acceptability or otherwise of this claim; the evidence
that I gather and the arguments that I read and create in trying to answer the
question become premises for my eventual conclusion (which either confirms or
rejects that initial claim). A question, then, can be seen as a conclusion-in-prospect:
a proposed relationship between ideas that needs to be tested. The question 'What
caused Australia to become less reliant on the United Kingdom in economic and
political terms following the Second World War?' is different in that it presumes
that Australia did become less reliant and that the answers will show how that
occurred.
So, questions are a way of unlocking and understanding the relationships
between ideas. Although we might think of the answers that flow from them as
being isolated, individual 'facts' (claims), it is much more accurate to characterise
the answers as relations between claims and, within a claim, between ideas and/or
events. To ask a question is always to call on some existing knowledge and to seek
the connection between the answer and that existing knowledge. We want to
develop these relationships so that they can form our claims, as well as the links
between premises and from premises to conclusions, in our analytical structures.
Every stage in the process of analysing an issue can be thought of as one of
questioning or interrogating. Questions provide the underlying 'glue' that binds
together the initial formulation of the topic or problem about which we are

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 105

reasoning, our search for information about that topic, and the construction of an
argument or explanation that leads to a conclusion.
It is not the answers to these questions that matter, so much as the very fact that
you ask them. Most students are worried about 'the right answer'; people asked to
perform a certain task at work also worry about getting the right outcome. There
are few (if any) perfectly correct answers in the real world; instead there are
processes we go through in order to come to a conclusion (an answer or outcome)
that is going to be accepted as correct in relation to the context within which we
operate. And that is why reasoning is so important. Reasoning is not about answers
(the conclusions), but about the process of making answers more acceptable by giving
appropriate reasons for them. Thinking through a series of questions is how we
control this process.
Hence, before and during the research process, we need to have questions in
mind that are prompted by the particular topic or issue that we are investigating.
We need, at the very least, to be using questions to formulate the precise
dimensions of our topic—establishing the parameters of our analysis:
• what we do consider and what we do not consider
• what broadly defined bodies of knowledge we will and will not call upon
• what definitions of terms we will use within our reasoning
• what methods of investigation we will use.

In particular, we need to ask these questions to avoid assuming that there is 'one
right topic' in relation to a broad issue. Often the topics we are told to investigate
or write about (whether through our work or study) are poorly formed or are
deliberately 'open', thus requiring us to redefine them more carefully before we
work on them. Each issue we encounter can give rise to a wide variety of topics. As
we go about narrowing it down to the precise topic we are going to investigate, we
must always be ready to justify our choices by thinking through the fundamental
question of 'Why have I chosen this particular topic, in this way, with references to
these ideas and not some other topic?'. If we do, then we will able to argue for and
establish the acceptability of our decisions about topics.
A precise topic enables us to search efficiently for information that will become
our claims. It guides us regarding the sorts of reasoning we will need to use
(reasoning from cause, analogy, and so on). A precise topic gives us a benchmark
against which we can assess the relevance of any information we encounter, both in
our research and in the final planning and construction of our arguments and
explanations. A precise topic also provides the benchmark that enables us to judge
the degree of evidence and argumentation needed to meet any requirements of the
burden of proof, thus guiding our search further. But the key issue here is not the
final product—the topic itself—but the insights we gain through the process of
formulating it, and we must always be ready to change our topic in light of what
we discover.
We will encounter some more questions in chapter 9. For the moment, let us
turn to the ways in which we can think about the research process, not in terms of

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
106 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

'what' we will find so much as the way that information and knowledge relates to
the particular topic we are reasoning about.

Information understood by where we find it


Let us begin with a little history lesson.1 J. C. R. Licklider was a leading US scientist
in the 1950s and 1960s. One of the founders of the Internet, and a visionary, he
was lead author of a report in the 1960s on the future of the library, and libraries
of the future. The report's main argument first of all recognised the value of the
printed page. It was a superlative medium for information display and processing—
'small, light, movable, cuttable, clippable, pastable, replicable, disposable, and inex-
pensive'. But, in an early sign of the impending crisis of information overload, the
report outlined how the collecting of pages into books, journals, magazines, and
bound documents, while necessary to allow even basic retrieval of information once
printed, negated many or all of the display/processing features while only partially
solving the huge difficulties of classifying, storing, and retrieving individual pages.
It also created its own organisational problems.
Licklider concluded 'if books [and we might include here all bound collections
of pages] are intrinsically less than satisfactory for the storage, organisation, retrieval,
and display of information, then libraries of books are bound to be less satisfactory
also'. A device, he said, was needed to allow both the transport of information to the
reader 'without transporting material' and, at the same time, some processing of that
information in ways that suited the reader's particular needs/uses of that infor-
mation: 'a meld of library and computer is evidently required'.
While we might think we have that device—the Internet—we can probably see,
even from the most cursory searching and browsing, that the Internet has solved
many problems, but only at the cost of creating a lot of new problems.
I use this example to make the point that the different categories of information
sources you encounter (e.g. monographs, edited collections, journals (both print
and electronic), newspapers, magazines, web sites, email lists, reference books,
conference proceedings, and so on) are primarily designed to assist in organising
information to make it readily available, rather than to assist you immediately to
decide what to use for your reasoning. They make information accessible rather
than making it analytical, sensible, or useable.
That said, we should not ignore the way in which the places we look for
information can, with careful use, provide some clues in the search for sense and
utility. While these places might be distinguished by labels that tend to describe the
form of their production (conference papers, monographs), these labels also imply
certain judgments about the value and reliability of information one finds there.
Here are some examples:

• Academic conferences are normally held to enable scholars and experts to


present the latest findings of their research or applied work to their

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 107

colleagues; each paper that is presented is usually no more than an hour long,
often shorter. Conferences tend to be organised around a topic, or defined
subject. As a result, conference proceedings will tend to contain large
numbers of highly specific papers that present detailed information on very
tightly defined topics; the information is usually very recent.
• Journals are, in many cases, designed solely or predominantly for an academic
audience and the papers in them are refereed, that is, checked for quality by
experts. Hundreds of journals are published; like conferences, they are tightly
themed. Media International Australia is a premier journal, usually focusing
on Australian issues concerning the media: print and electronic. Articles tend
to be longer, providing academics with greater scope to explain and explore
their topic; but they also serve as part of an in-depth long-term conversation
among scholars and experts in various intellectual disciplines.
• Popular magazines are intended to be read by people without much knowledge
in a particular subject, but an interest. They are, predominantly, also governed
by the need to attract and retain readership. The information is heavily
processed to make it understandable: simplicity, rather than complexity, is the
aim; brevity ensures continued attention; examples and evidence are often
sacrificed for the sake of a strong theme; research is limited.

What creates these different categories, then, is a mix of the mode of prod-
uction, the intended audience and the manner of publication. We cannot, for
example, make the above three distinctions without relying on the others. Journals
appear as a distinct category precisely because there are other forms of publishing
that are categorised differently. It is the relationship that matters. For analytical
purposes, these clues provide only marginal assistance in making sense of the
information, rich and complex, which we find in these sources. All they do is guide
us, to some extent, as to the reliability of that information and perhaps the
directness of the source (see 'Direct and indirect sources' later in this chapter).
Thus, when we consider a key issue in reasoning—are our premises well founded?
(chapter 5)—we can see that this foundation is provided, very often, by the source
of the information. Thus, deciding what exactly to find and how to find it may not
be helped by these categories, but they are important in finalising the strength and
quality of argument. What we need at this stage are some other ways of thinking
about how to find and use information.

Exercise 8.1
Write down all the sources that you can think of, in no particular order; perhaps
start by listing the ones that you use most frequently. Then review the list and see
if there are any you have missed. Remember, we are not talking here about
specific titles, but types of sources. Thus, do not write 'The Australian', write
'newspapers'. On the other hand, do not be too general: there is no point in
writing 'books'; you need to ask what kind.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
108 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Information as it relates to other information


While each topic or subject on which we might conduct research will throw up its
own specific relations between individual pieces of information, there are some
broadly applicable general 'possibilities' of relation that can assist you in reading
critically, that is, reading in a way that makes it possible to argue and explain. We
have already encountered the basis for these general possibilities in chapter 7, when
looking at the various ways in which we can reason. Using as my broad example
here, 'the impact of the Internet on Australian society', I will give some examples
of how thinking about the relationship of information to additional information
might guide our search for more material.

Relations of specific and general


We might read in an article about two successful e-commerce ventures in Australia
(call them x.com.au and y.com.au). Immediately we need to think: are these two
specific examples unusual, representative, evidence of a trend? We are seeing if there
is a relationship between the specific claim 'x and y are successful e-commerce
businesses' and a more general claim that 'there are many successful e-commerce
businesses in Australia'. We need to read additional articles/books to find out if
there are many more examples or not.
To reverse the example, we might read that, while more men use the Internet in
Australia than women, those women who are online spend more time com-
municating and less time surfing the web. We are trying to determine what kind of
computer training needs to be given to a group of elderly women at a nursing home
who are all keen to 'get online': can we relate that general information to the specific
case we are investigating? Or, perhaps, we need more detailed information on what
older women do (not just 'women'). Again, we go to a source looking specifically for
this material, based on the tentative information-relationship we have identified.

Relations of similarity and difference


We might, for example, discover that there has been a 100 per cent increase in
Internet use in Australia in the past two years. We can immediately begin to think
about the following—was this increase the same, or more or less in previous years?
Have there been similar rises in other countries recently?
Again, in a more complex example, we read that Australia was one of the
countries that most quickly (in terms of time and number of users) adopted video
recorders and mobile phones when they were introduced. There is a relationship
there: both the Internet and VCRs/phones are information/communication
technologies—can we draw some lessons from a comparison? Are they similar
enough? Too different?
A final example: we read that the Internet cannot be easily censored; we then
read another article that outlines the reasons why it can be censored effectively. The

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 109

relationship here is one of difference: two conclusions that are contradictory. We


need to ask: how can these two positions be resolved, if at all? Why do the authors
have different perspectives on a similar theme?

Relations of cause and effect


We hear from friends that many new members of a virtual community to which
they belong report initially high levels of enthusiasm, followed by a rapid decline
in interest and a return to the activities that previously they pursued. We have
also read, in a book on virtual communities, that this effect can be seen in many
online communities. We also read, in yet another book on communities in
general, that it is not the physical area nor the communication between members
that makes 'a community' but the shared activities which members undertake
without realising they are 'in a community'. A link seems to suggest itself: we
need to look for information on the possibility that what causes the failure of
virtual communities is, in some cases, the fact that the only commonality of
members is the time they spend online 'doing' the community, rather than
actually being it.
These are, in simplified form, examples of the way we need to make information
analytical if we are to use it effectively.

Information classified by the topic under


investigation
As well as looking for information prompted by how it relates to other information,
we can also consider that there are, broadly, five classes of information involved in
reasoning.2 Each is defined in relation to the particular topic we are investigating,
and to each other. These classes can be understood as an answer to the question
'how does this information relate to the information involved in my specific topic
of investigation?'. They are:

1 information directly relating to the specific topic we are investigating


2 information about the specific background to this topic (closely related
knowledge)
3 information about other topics, different from the specific focus of our inves-
tigation, but that provides insights that are relevant or analogous to our topic
4 information about the broad field of topics into which this particular topic
fits
5 information of theoretical perspectives that are used to establish the topic as
a topic and to set the parameters of investigation.
Each class denotes a different relationship between information, focused around
the topic. For example, what allows us to talk about a 'related topics' class is the
relationship between that class and the specific topic we are reading about. To even

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
110 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

think in these terms is to be implicitly analysing the world. Let us consider an


extended example of the analysis that lies behind this classification. Imagine we are
investigating the way in which nationalism is used in Australian television adver-
tising (think, for example, of the QANTAS television commercials with the 'I still
call Australia home' theme or Telstra advertisements that emphasise 'We are
Australian'). Here are some examples of what we might find when we are guided by
the five classes above.3
First, we need to gather material on the specific topic itself. While we might well
find material written in advertising magazines (such as Ad News), we would first
watch numerous television commercials that use images of Australia. We could
interview other viewers; we could talk to advertising agencies. We could compare
nationalistic and other advertisements. This class of knowledge is what is usually
established by the regular research activities of various scholars and investigators.
So, in our own investigation, it is the principal category of knowledge that we are
creating.
Second, we should turn to material on the specific background, which is usually
found in the writings of other researchers. For example, Paul James's article,
'Australia in the Corporate Image: A New Nationalism'4 discusses in detail the use
of Australian nationalism in marketing campaigns in the 1970s.
Third, we need to know about other specific topics with relevant insights. Ruth
Abbey and Jo Crawford's 'Crocodile Dundee or Davey Crockett?'5 does not tell us
anything about television advertising. But, in its discussion of the nationalist
elements of the film Crocodile Dundee, we can find some relevant insights.
Fourth, we need to understand the broad background of the topic, which
would involve developing our knowledge of advertising and nationalism. Benedict
Anderson's Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism6 includes very little discussion specifically about Australia or adver-
tising but does provide a sophisticated discussion of nationalism. Equally, Stuart
Cunningham and Graeme Turner's edited collection The Media in Australia:
Industries, Texts, Audiences7 provides a good general background to the 'television'
side of our investigation.
Most significantly, we need to gather some information about theoretical
perspectives. These perspectives provide a particular way of investigating and
thinking about issues. Different theories lead researchers and thinkers to different
approaches and to different understandings of what makes premises well founded,
relevant, and strong. In particular, theoretical perspectives establish the topic as a
topic and set the parameters of investigation. Remember, there are many different
ways of understanding the world, which are usually related to various academic
disciplines. It was not, for example, until the 1970s that cultural studies (of the
popular media) became common. Each theoretical perspective will have different
ideas about what exactly is an appropriate topic for investigation and how we
should go about it. In broad terms, then, we could think about whether our interest
in the topic is, for example, psychological or sociological. We could also think
about whether we are developing, for example, a feminist or Marxist critique of this

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 111

use of nationalism. Judith Williamson's classic Decoding Advertisements: Ideology


and Meaning in Advertisements2, provides excellent theoretical material on critiques
(rather than description) of advertising. In contrast, Mark Poster's The Mode of
Information* discusses the difficulties of even engaging in a 'critical' analysis of
television in the 'postmodern' age. Neither book makes any reference to Australia
or nationalist advertising, but both provide knowledge of the very ways in which
we come to think about topics such as 'nationalist television advertising'.10
Although the most difficult class of knowledge to analyse and engage with,
knowledge about the processes of developing or discovering knowledge (what
philosophers call epistemological theory), is, in fact, the general key to effective
reasoning in any particular situation.

Information as it relates to how we are using it


As well as classifying information in relation to the topic we are investigating, we
can also think about four types of information in terms of how we will use that
information in our own reasoning. This typology of information answers the
question 'How does this information relate to what I am trying to do in my
argument or explanation?'. These four types do not 'coincide' in any way with the
five classes just discussed. We can find information of any type in any of the classes
just discussed; all classes can contribute to the information of one type that we are
gathering.
The four main types of information are:
1 general understanding of the context in which we are preparing our reasoning
(in effect, the context in which our text fits)
2 opinions and conclusions from other peoples' arguments and explanations
3 basic details or evidence that we need as the main source of our premises
4 values and attitudes (of ourselves and others) that relate to our inves-
tigation.
First of all, we need a general understanding of the context of our reasoning.
It helps us to see the parameters of the topic or problem—the boundaries and
overlaps between a particular topic and other related topics. Remember all
'topics' are, to some extent, artificial delineations within a swirling mass of ideas
and events. Topics emerge through the ways that people think about this mass.
We cannot impose whatever topics we want onto the world, but equally we
cannot rely on the world to throw up topics 'ready-made'. Similarly, general
information helps us to see how any topic can be approached from different
angles with different questions to be answered. In the nationalism example you
could, for example, ask 'Why do advertisers use nationalistic images and slogans?'
or 'Why do people respond well to nationalistic images and slogans?'. These
questions address distinctly different issues, since it may be that people do not,
on the whole, respond well to such images but (for some reason) advertisers think
they do.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
112 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

This sort of general information helps us think about where and how to search
for more detailed information, and to settle upon an aspect of the topic on which to
concentrate. For example, in a report to a marketing firm about what people see on
television, the main focus would be on the former question, rather than the latter.
The context of, for example, a short lecture to high-school students would require
that we keep the information in our argument or explanation consistent with their
expectations and needs; if, on the other hand, we were writing a scholarly article
about television advertising, then the different context would require more advanced
and complex arguments. We need to gather background information in order to
gain a good understanding of the context in which our reasoning takes place.
Whatever we may think of a particular issue, we are also looking in our research
for different opinions and conclusions. For any particular topic, a range of ideas
will already have been expressed, and whatever we are doing needs to take account
of them. Reasoning involves acknowledging what others have done and integrating
our contribution (no matter how small) with the body of knowledge already
assembled. We need to criticise conclusions that we oppose, ponder those that are
interesting, and add to any with which we agree. In the advertising example, we
find that some critics argue that nationalistic television commercials promote
unhealthy competition and suspicion of'foreigners'. If we agree, then we should
seek to substantiate this claim further. On the other hand, if, as part of our analysis,
we are seeking to establish a different conclusion, we would not simply ignore this
'opposing' view, but would seek information or give arguments that refute it. We
need to consider these 'other' conclusions in relation to what we are concluding in
our own reasoning.
Most of all we need to base our reasoning on premises and further support for
those premises. We might think of these premises as evidence or 'the facts' (even
though we must understand that most 'facts' are only interpretations—claims that,
depending on one's perspective, may become more or less doubtful). This
information is usually what we produce through our own direct research, seeking
to answer specific questions that we have established to guide our activities. As
always, we need to be confident in the accuracy and acceptability of this infor-
mation and be able to demonstrate it convincingly in our reasoning (for example,
through appeals to authority). Referring back to our continuing example, we could
use the following as evidence:
• Telecom spent over a billion dollars on all advertising in 1994, and most of
the commercials had a nationalist theme.
• QANTAS consciously seeks to establish itself as a national Australian airline.
• Australians see themselves in the mould of Crocodile Dundee and other 'bush'
heroes.
Yet we could also gather evidence to support any claims we make about the
ways that intellectuals have previously written about advertising. For example, if
our investigation includes a critique of marketing theorists' conclusions that
television commercials are effective, we would need evidence, first of all, that these

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 113

theorists had made such conclusions. When looking for evidence, then, we are not
looking for a specific 'thing' but simply the material that will become the majority
of our premises.
Finally, the sort of information that is most important (yet least often consid-
ered) is not actually stated in most books and articles. It remains implied, waiting
within texts to be inferred by their readers. It concerns the values and attitudes of
the authors of what you read and hear. These values include judgments about
which actions are good and which are bad. For example, many commentators on
nationalism believe that too much national pride is bad because it promotes
conflict and competition. Unless we understand this value system, we cannot
interpret and respond to what is written within it. We cannot understand the range
of possible opinions on nationalism unless we understand that the same 'facts' (say,
one particular advertisement) may lead to dramatically different conclusions when
interpreted from different political or ethical standpoints. Moreover, values can also
relate to 'correct' ways of investigating a problem. If we do a socio-economic
analysis of television advertising in relation to the ways that large companies profit
from calling upon consumers' patriotism, then, implicitly, we are making a value
judgment that it is inappropriate to use a different approach (say, a psychological
one that concentrates solely on how an individual responds to advertisements).

Exercise 8.2
Think about an investigation in which you are currently engaged (an essay, report,
experiment, whatever). Think of two examples for each of the five classes and four
types of information listed above. Remember that for each type or class, it is a
question of the relation between the knowledge or information and your topic.
Reflect in particular on the context in which your investigation is occurring.

Direct and indirect sources


Direct sources
In broad terms, direct sources are those that provide first-hand information about
events. A radio interview with a politician in which we hear what the politician has
to say about the economy is first-hand. An extensive speech delivered in Parliament
by the same politician is also first-hand. A book that analyses this politician's partic-
ular views about the economy is, by contrast, second-hand. In scientific disciplines,
experiments are the most common direct source; in other disciplines, surveys and
interviews, or research into written and oral records of events provide direct access
to information. All these sources are direct and, within the appropriate context,
recognised as containing original evidence and ideas. They are a significant source
of the material we need to form our arguments and explanations.
It used to be thought that these direct or 'primary' sources were somehow
more 'factual' or descriptive, and that interpretation was added to them by

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
114 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

investigators when they wrote about their research, thereby creating a 'secondary'
or indirect source (see below). However, direct sources do contain values and
elements of interpretation. 11 The importance of the distinction between direct
and indirect sources, then, is not that one is 'fact' and the other interpretation
but, rather, one of context. For example, the comments made by an advertising
agency director about nationalistic television commercials must be understood in
relation to the person who made these comments, why, when, how, and in what
situation the comments were made, and so on. If we do an experiment by
measuring the biological reactions of people watching nationalist advertising
under controlled conditions, then we, in effect, become the authors of that data
(via the way that we establish the experiment). We would need to ask ourselves
the same sorts of questions to understand the meaning of the data we gather. By
doing so, we will recognise that the contexts in which this direct 'evidence' of
nationalist advertising is gathered is different to that in which we use it as part of
our argument.
In every case, then, direct sources can only be used effectively when we think
about the context, as well as the content, of the information we draw from them.
Sometimes, understanding this context involves asking questions about where and
when the information was produced; by whom; for what purpose; on the basis of
what knowledge; in relation to which issues. Equally, the context can be under-
stood by thinking about our own engagement with the source. For example,
scientists must check, when performing experiments, that they have established the
experimental procedure properly, that there are no errors in their procedures, that
they are reliable observers of the events, and so on. In each discipline, in each field
of endeavour, there are basic rules that we must follow, and assumptions that we
must make, when seeking to gather information from direct sources; there are also
basic understandings about how to consider the context of the information. They
are too numerous and complex to discuss here in detail, but two examples can be
drawn from history and chemistry. In history, a standard approach is to think about
the way in which a person's social position (class, race, gender, and so on) can
influence and be seen in what they have said or written. In chemistry, experimental
design is always used to control and maintain quality of experimental work: the
information gained through an experiment is always assessed in the context of the
way the experiment was performed. In general terms, we must learn the rules that
are part of our context and consciously apply them so that we can use direct sources
effectively.

Indirect sources
As noted above, a direct source differs from an indirect source. Indirect sources
involve the reports and analysis of direct information by other people. Reports,
articles, and books by scholars are the main category of secondary sources that we
tend to use, especially when we are beginning to develop our knowledge about an
issue. Once again, the key to using such information is always to think about the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 115

context in which it was produced. In other words, information from indirect


sources is only as good as our understanding of that source itself. For example, as a
result of changes over the past two decades, an academic commentary such as the
one by James on advertising in the 1970s may not be precisely relevant to con-
temporary concerns. There is no general rule to apply to such analysis of sources,
except that we must always think about the context (who obtained the information;
when, where, and how the information was arrived at) as well as the text (what the
information is).
For example, imagine you are watching a television program on advertising.
The host makes some comments on nationalistic commercials, saying that they
always produce an emotional reaction and that is why they are effective. Is this
source useful for an academic investigation? If you answered no, then you would,
in some circumstances, be correct. But the important question to ask is 'Why?'. Let
us contrast this hypothetical television program with a more usual source: academic
writing. The trustworthiness of academic writing is based on the idea that the
person doing the writing is an expert in that area, through their close study of the
topic, their skills as a researcher, their careful, long-term analysis, and their involve-
ment in a system in which articles and books are published only after the scrutiny
of other qualified academics to determine if they are 'right' or not. In other words,
the claims are trustworthy because an institutionalised method makes them trust-
worthy. It is a social convention that academic work is regarded as being more
'sound' (if often more remote) than 'popular' work; it is also a worthwhile social
convention because there are good reasons to accept this distinction in soundness.
The usefulness of the television program depends, however, on what exactly we
are trying to find. It might be quite relevant to argue that the popular perception of
nationalist advertising is very important in the effectiveness of such commercials.
So, even if we distrust many of the claims that are advanced in the popular media
and trust those from more scholarly work instead, we can still use as evidence the
fact that people do actually make and listen to the first sort of claim. In other
words, while we may not trust the television program as an indirect commentary
on advertising, we could certainly use it as a direct source of popular views on
advertising.
Do you see the difference? Sometimes we will want to make claims in our
reasoning that convey information in the claims themselves. And sometimes we
will want to make claims about the fact that a certain type of claim, or group of
claims, has been made by others. Developing the latter type of writing is essential
in good critical work and, thus, requires you to develop skills in knowing about
sources of knowledge.

Exercise 8.3
Write a short analysis of the different direct and indirect sources that you use
most frequently in your current reasoning. What questions do you need to ask
about them? What rules and assumptions, stemming from the discipline or

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
116 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

profession in which you are working or studying, underlie the identification of


these sources?

Five possible outcomes


Finding information effectively is, in large measure, a matter of understanding how
that information or knowledge is to be used in your own arguments and explan-
ations. Often we simply want some basic descriptive information to serve as claims
in our reasoning without wanting to provide extensive supporting arguments. For
instance, we read, in relation to our nationalistic advertisements investigation, that
Crocodile Dundee was one of the most popular films ever screened in Australia. We
can simply state this piece of information, either quoting exactly from the original
or re-expressing the information in our own words, giving an appropriate reference
to it.12 We are simply taking a single claim from our 'source'.
We can also take an entire argument or explanation from our 'source'. We could
quote such reasoning exactly, but usually, for stylistic reasons, we express it in our
own words. For example, James's article (mentioned above) argues that nationalistic
advertisements encourage consumers to purchase a corporation's products because,
by being 'Australian' (even when the companies are often owned by foreign inter-
ests), the products are assumed to be better than others. We are, in effect, getting
claims and links (reasoning) from the 'source' (can you see the trace of linking in
'because'?). Once again, we provide a reference in order to acknowledge our debt
to the original author.
Yet very often what we want to 'take' from these sources is not that specific and
cannot simply be 'found' by looking at a certain page. Instead, we can summarise
the basic argument or explanation in a source that we have read (always in our own
words), reducing a long text to a short series of premises and a conclusion, which
we can then use in our own argument (again, with an appropriate reference). For
example, Anderson's Imagined Communities is a long and detailed work on nation-
alism that, in part, concludes that technologies that allow humans to overcome
geographical distance (for example, railways) have played a significant role in the
creation of modern nations. We could include such a summary (which, of course,
can be expressed in the analytical format in our notes) within our own reasoning.
We are, thus, taking from the source not a specific claim, nor a specific piece of
reasoning, but our understanding (analytically speaking) of the source's overall
argument or explanation.
Fourth, we can take from sources a type of information that is far more in-
definable than the information gained in any of the last three cases. This category
can be summed up as 'positions and values'. It is usually hidden within the source
and can be recovered using your judgment (based on what you read or hear) of the
underlying position that the author of the source holds. This underlying position
can be inferred from that person's own arguments or explanations, or the way in
which the arguments or explanations have been received by others. We read, for
example, in Graeme Turner's Making It National15 that Australian businesses

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 117

exploit national patriotism and sentiment to further their own profit-making goals.
Whether we agree or disagree with this conclusion, whether we can refute it or not,
we can nevertheless try to understand why he might have made such a conclusion.
We can ask, what is the political and intellectual position that is implied by such
claims? From the overall thrust of Turner's analysis, we judge that he is opposed to
unfettered capitalism, seeking instead a greater degree of regulation in the national
interest. In making this judgment, we can understand the assumptions that
underlie the information in Turner's book, and the context in which it was written
and presented to us. Without such analysis, you will always tend to respond to
reasoning from your own point of view, without understanding why others might
disagree with you. Whether or not you wish to change their minds or accept their
right to be different is immaterial: neither goal can be achieved if you do not know
why they believe what they do.
Finally, there are occasions on which we take nothing away from what we are
reading or observing—except more questions! This outcome may be frustrating at
times, but if we are seeking to be smart thinkers, we must be prepared to delve
deeply into an issue and not rush too quickly to a satisfying answer. Remember
analysis continues through every stage of research, but smart thinkers are aware of
this and draw encouragement from the way in which a book that tells you 'nothing'
might prompt the question 'Why does it not tell me anything?'. And, further, you
can ask if the problem is with the book, with you, or perhaps with your original set
of analytical questions.

Exercise 8.4
Using a long piece of written work that you are reading at the moment, practise
getting each of the five possible outcomes just discussed. Make sure that, in each
case, you express your answers in the analytical structure format (except, of
course, for the last category, for which you will simply have a list of further
questions).

Review
We have seen in previous chapters how the context in which we create our texts
of reasoning are crucial in making successful judgments about the effective-
ness of our arguments and explanations. In this chapter, we have concentrated
on learning about the process of searching for knowledge in a way that allows
us to take the information from one context (someone else's text) and put it
into another context (our text). The context influences our interpretation and
understanding of information, and so if we do not understand and recognise
these contexts, our analysis will not be sound. Knowledge, then, needs to be
understood generically, not as specific 'facts' or issues, but as a series of
classes and types that relate to our research project. The sources from which
it comes, again, must be analysed for the way they create and constrain that

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
118 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

knowledge, rather than as particular books or articles or experiments. Finally,


what we take away from these sources can be organised as elements of
reasoning: as claims, arguments, or explanations; as assumptions and values;
or simply as more questions.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:
analysis
analytical questions
information
knowledge
source

Review exercise 8
Answer briefly the following questions giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book:

a. What do we need to know to be good researchers?


b. What sorts of questions are involved in formulating a topic?
c. What allows us to classify information into five separate categories?
d. How do the four types of information compare and contrast with each
other?
e. What is the difference between a direct and an indirect source?
f. What role does the 'author' and the mode of production of information
play?
g. What are the important issues of context involved in using information
from any source?
h. Why must we ask questions when we are searching?

NOTES
1 This information, and quotes from Licklider's report, are taken from Mark Stefik,
Internet dreams: archetypes, myths, and metaphors, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.,
1996, pp. 23-32.
2 Please note that my classifying of information here is just one of many different
approaches which you may encounter. I have developed it because it usefully extends
our smart thinking abilities and not because it is 'right' in any objective sense.
3 All these examples are drawn from the process of researching and writing that went into

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
RESEARCH, REASONING, AND ANALYSIS 119

M. Allen, Telecom Adverts, Telecom Networks, Telecom Australia', Australian Journal


of Communication, vol. 20, no. 2, 1993, pp. 9 7 - 1 1 3 .
4 Arena, no. 63, 1983, pp. 65-106.
5 Meanjin, vol. 46, no. 2, 1987, pp. 1 4 5 - 5 2 .
6 Verso, London, 1981.
7 Allen & Unwin, Sydney, 1993.
8 Marion Boyars, London, 1978.
9 University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1990.
10 These sorts of theoretical insights into the intellectual issues involved in any research
or analysis often appear within more general discussions of various topics. These exam-
ples simply indicate that the purpose of looking at the two books noted was precisely to
gain this sort of knowledge.
11 There is, of course, philosophical argument about this issue. See chapter 9 for a brief
discussion of the intersubjective theory of knowledge that underpins this view of direct
sources.
12 In this case, the authority is S. Crofts, 'Re-Imaging Australia: Crocodile Dundee
Overseas', Continuum, vol. 2, no. 2, 1989, p. 1 3 3 .
13 Allen & Unwin, Sydney, 1995.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
9

Planning and
Creating Your Reasoning
Although, in practice, reasoning, knowledge, research, and analysis are all
inextricably bound together, it is also true that, from time to time, we divide
our reasoning tasks up in a way that allows us to sit down and prepare an
analytical text containing arguments and explanations. What we have learnt
about reasoning so far makes us much more effective in such preparation,
and this chapter briefly discusses two ways in which we can go about it.
However, always remember that the key to good reasoning is not a 'method'
or program of steps to follow but an attitude—a keenness to think things
through. The advice that follows is designed principally to 'jog' your mind
into this sort of keenness and should be applied judiciously, on the basis of
the particular skills and needs that apply to you as an individual smart
thinker.
In this chapter:
1 We will consider some of the key questions that can help us determine
the external context in which our argument or explanation fits. Then,
revisiting the planning method from chapter 3, we will look at the
questions that are most useful in guiding the reasoning in the text we
are preparing.
2 We conclude with a short example of the way that the analytical struc-
ture format can be used, not to represent our entire argument and
explanation, but instead as a 'plan' of ideas and relationships that can
then be used to assist in actually writing the narrative flow of our
reasoning.

120 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 121

The key analytical questions


Context: analysing the external dimensions of
reasoning
Throughout this book, we have seen how context is all-important in determining
many of our judgments about effective reasoning. When planning and creating
(and then presenting) an argument or explanation, the particular context in which
this reasoning occurs must be actively considered. The nature of context—a mass
of implied or assumed knowledge and expectations—makes it impossible for us to
develop precise guidelines for its consideration. Instead, we must explore the three-
way relationship between the person or people creating reasoning (the author), the
people receiving this reasoning (the audience), and the knowledge that this
reasoning uses and develops.
Reasoning is about the use, expression, and formation of knowledge, and
involves innumerable judgments about the 'truth' of claims and the 'truth' of the
way they link to one another in various reasoned ways. Knowledge does not exist
objectively in the world (literally in the 'objects' that claims represent). Rather it is
created intersubjectively, that is, between people such as authors and their audi-
ences (known, technically, as 'subjects').1 Knowledge (consisting of claims and their
relationships) does have an objective element, since it represents, in another form,
the actual reality of objects. However, the medium of that representation—the
form in which knowledge is expressed—is language, which (unfortunately,
perhaps) is not a perfectly representational medium. Whenever we write or talk
about things ('objects'), we add to or subtract from their essential nature through
the particular choice of words we use. Hence claims, and all knowledge built from
those claims, are always something more or less than what 'really' happens.
All humans share a common reality and appear, through the words they use
(when properly translated), to have a common language to discuss and think about
it. But remember that language consists not only of the descriptive or denotative
characteristic of words but also of their connotative function (the way in which they
carry implied meanings). These connotations ensure that we cannot assume that
knowledge always and perfectly matches up to reality. Knowledge will always be
constrained by and, in part, created from the words in which it is expressed.
Moreover, the implied values and assumed knowledge that make words meaningful
exist through the interactions of people—the authors and audiences of reasoning.
That is why knowledge is intersubjective. Moreover, it is not simply a question of
thinking about individuals: who 'we' are as subjects depends very much on the
culture and society in which we grow up and, indeed, the knowledge that we
already possess. Hence, whenever we think about ourselves as authors of reasoning
or about our potential audiences, we are thinking about cultural and social assump-
tions and expectations about knowledge and reasoning.
The aim here is not to gain a detailed understanding of the philosophical
arguments for or against objective or intersubjective knowledge; it is to understand

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
122 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

that all reasoning involves people and that, hence, knowledge and reasoning can
never completely escape the influence of the social contexts in which those people
exist and operate. Even if philosophical ideas about intersubjectivity are unfamiliar,
their practical effects should be apparent. Have you ever been in a situation in
which, despite the apparent 'logic' and 'certainty' of your argument, those listening
to you have failed to agree with your conclusion? Have you ever been asked to learn
something without understanding why you are learning it? Have you ever written
a report or essay and been pleased with what you have done, only to be told by its
readers that you have not done what was required of you? These situations come
about when the author and audience of reasoning fail to work within a shared
context of assumptions and expectations.
This context can be understood by thinking through the following questions
about our own work (many of which we encountered in chapter 8 in relation to
others' reasoning). Forget, for a moment, what-we are reasoning about and think
instead about the following questions:

• Why am I reasoning?
• For whom am I reasoning?
• In what situation is my reasoning taking place?
• According to what methods, definitions, and broad understandings am I
reasoning?
• What is expected of me?

Knowing what context we are working within may involve 'fitting in' with what
our audience expects and assumes, or it can require us to outline and discuss
possible alternative contexts explicitly, thereby helping our audience to fit in with
the context that we want to establish.
Here is one example of the importance of context. HIV/AIDS is generally
regarded as one of the world's great health risks. We know certain things about the
virus that causes AIDS, such as its methods of transmission (through blood and
other bodily fluids) and the types of activities that enable this transmission (e.g.
unprotected sex and intravenous drug use with shared needles). We also know
what it does to human beings (destroys their immune system and indirectly causes
their death). Now, as far as we can tell, these claims are objectively 'true'. Yet, think
of the different sets of assumptions about, say, how to stop unprotected sex that
would not be shared by a Western health expert and, say, a group of politicians
from a conservative Islamic community. The Westerner, with a background of
social freedom and individual choice, would be full of ideas about advertising
campaigns and other strategies to encourage people to use condoms; the Islamic
community leaders would be bemused by this approach—even actively hostile—
since their framework of assumptions does not include such liberal attitudes to
sex, nor does it include the use of condoms. Neither party is wrong here: it is
neither rational nor irrational to hold either of these two sets of assumptions, as
long as each fits in with the accepted practices of the community to which it
belongs. Yet the possibility for misunderstanding is great, unless both parties make

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 123

an effort to understand the assumptions of the other and try to find some
common ground from which to engage in the specific argument about HIV.
While the final resolution of such a clash of frameworks does not necessarily mean
'sticking with' one's original assumptions, effective reasoning requires that the
difference be acknowledged and explained properly before any moment of resolu-
tion.

Exercise 9.1
In relation to an issue that you are working on at the moment, write down a series
of questions that will help you to establish the external dimensions of your topic
(how it relates to the general audiences and knowledge of your reasoning).

Text: the internal dimensions of reasoning


Chapter 3 introduced the idea of a particular planning method, which revolves
around the use of the analytical structure format. Here, as a reminder, are the five
steps involved in this method:

1 Decide what your conclusion will be. Write this claim out carefully, express-
ing exactly what you mean. Number it T .
2 Then think about the reasons that you are giving for this conclusion. These
reasons must be written as proper claims, this time serving as premises that
either explain how that conclusion comes about or show why it should be
accepted. Try to keep related premises together, but as the diagram will show
these relationships clearly, it is not essential to group them perfectly. Write
them out, making sure that you do not use pronouns but express each claim
so that it makes sense in and of itself. Number them from ' 2 ' onwards. Focus
on giving the main reasons for the conclusion at this stage.
3 Begin to draw the diagram to show the relationships between the claims.
4 Stop and think: are you missing any claims? do you need more premises? have
you got the relationships the way you want them to be?
5 Make changes if required, adding claims and redrawing the diagram if need
be.

We can learn more about each step in the process by thinking through some of
the questions that we might ask to guide us in completing each step effectively. The
following discussion does not, of course, cover every aspect of all situations, but will
give you a general overview of the sorts of smart-thinking 'moves' we can make in
planning and creating our arguments and explanations. Moreover, although this
overview is broken up into specific advice about each step of the process, the actual
application of the ideas discussed will obviously occur in a variety of ways, at a
variety of different stages of your research and analysis. In practice, no step is
isolated from the others, even if, in theory, we can distinguish them in order to
learn more about them.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
124 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

First, think about the conclusion, which is a specific statement of what we are
going to be reasoning towards. It will relate to the general topic with which we are
concerned but must be much more precise. Ask yourself:

• What is the conclusion?


• What are its specific elements (meanings of words, key ideas, values, scope,
and certainty)?
• Is it about the present, future, or past?
• Does it require an argument or an explanation?
• How does it relate to existing 'conclusions' about this topic: is it opposing
them? supporting them? extending them?
• Is the conclusion well formed?
• What sorts of evidence will be required to support such a conclusion?
• Is there more than one conclusion involved here, and can they be combined
in some manner?

In particular, be clear about the following question:

• Is this conclusion directly about some event, decision, or issue, or is it about


the way others think and write about such events, decisions, or issues?
Take, for example, the following conclusion:

1. The Olympic games are organised and run for the profit of the large
corporations who televise, sponsor, and advertise the games.
This conclusion is distinctly different from the 'normal' conclusions we draw about the
games but is not completely 'new'. There are some important 'issues' here, for example,
issues relating to how these corporations might have gained control over an apparently
'international' event. Another issue would involve considering why the profit aspect
seems to be ignored by much reporting on the games. Much evidence will be needed to
explore and explain these issues; the claim will definitely require an argument to support
it because (as far as I can tell) this claim is not widely accepted. It will necessarily involve
discussion of others' opinions but is not, of itself, a conclusion about someone else's view.
Second, think about the main reasons. Make some initial statements of these
reasons, answering questions such as:

• Why does or should the event or idea under discussion occur or be believed?
• When does it occur?
• How does it happen?
• What does it mean that this event or idea occurs or is believed?
• What are or should be the consequences?

Then, considering each reason in turn, think about the complexities of the reasons,
expanding them into a chain of premises that not only expresses the reason fully but
also clearly explicates how the premises relate to the conclusion. Ask yourself:

• Do the reasons need any definitions or framing premises?


• Is the relevance of the premises to the conclusion well established?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 125

• Do the premises cover all the aspects of the conclusion?


• Are these premises well formed, with particular reference to the internal
connections which they make?
• Are they well founded (if not, then what support can they be given)?
• Are enough reasons given to meet the requirements for breadth?
• Are they expanded sufficiently to give depth to the argument/explanation?
• Is each idea in the conclusion referred to in some way in these premises?
• Are the premises grouped together properly?

Just one example would be to state the following reason:


The Olympic games are now very expensive to organise.

This might break down, on further analysis, into claims such as:
2. There are more sports, more athletes, and more coaches than ever
before.
3. Hosting all these events and people is very costly.
4. Non-sport costs, associated with security and entertainment, are now
much more prominent.

(There are, of course, many more possible premises.)


Third, think about the analytical relationships between the premises and the
conclusion (as seen in the diagram). Here, we can think about the sort of reasoning
that is being used:
• Do the premises show the cause of an effect? (If so, are differences or
similarities clearly stated?)
• Do they state some generalisation that provides the knowledge we need about
a specific conclusion? (If so, is the specific case really a member of the
general category?)
• Do the premises draw together specific cases so as to make a generalisation?
(If so, are these specific cases representative of the general category?)
• Is it an analogical relationship, in which similarities between the events
described in the premises and the conclusion provide the answers we are
seeking? (If so, are the events consistent with one another?)
• Is it simply reasoning from terms, with the claim simply establishing the
particular meaning of the conclusion? (If so, are we making it clear?)

In each case, remember that these questions unlock relationships. We can analyse
events by thinking about 'What is the cause of X?' or 'What effects does X cause?'; we
can think about the way that many cases of X might prompt us to generalise, or about
how X might only be explicable as a specific case of some general rule.
Continuing the previous example, the premises concerning cost are about the
cause of the increased commercialism of the games. Because of the need for money
to fund the games (a result of these costs), there is no way they could be staged
without corporate funding. Good reasoning would involve checking to see if it
really is the case that increased costs is the only factor; in doing so, we might find

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
126 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

that government funding of the Olympics has declined in the current era of low
public financing and increased privatisation:

5. There is no other source of funds for the Olympics.


As we know, premises are, by themselves, unlikely to be well founded without
some authority or further reasoning. So, at this stage, we can also add further layers
to our diagram, providing more claims that show or explain our premises. We can
add as many layers as we wish, though for practical reasons we might wish to stop
at three or four layers (see below). In each case, remember that we are using the
claim at the bottom of each vertical arrow as a conclusion, and so all of the thinking
moves involved in making good links between the main conclusion and its main
premises also apply to these relationships.
Again, claim 4 of the Olympics example—'Non-sport costs, associated with
security and entertainment, are now much more prominent'—would need to be
properly supported by its own explanation, which would involve a similar process
in which we think of a reason and then break it down into specific claims. These
supporting claims might be:
6. The Olympic games are now a prime target for terrorists.
7. Terrorism is common in the contemporary world.
8. Each new Olympic games tries to outdo the previous one in terms of
entertainment and spectacle.
9. Every new and different approach to entertainment usually involves
greater cost.

-—>

The fourth and fifth steps, which involved stopping, reflecting, and revising, are
crucial. At this point we must think through the following questions, beginning
also to relate our own reasoning to the context in which we are operating:
• What assumptions underlie the reasoning?
• Are there any implied premises?

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 127

• Is the relevance of each premise clear?


• Do they provide sufficient support to satisfy the burden of proof?
• Are all the claims well founded (either self-evidently, or with authority, or with
reasoning)?
• Are the claims clear and understandable?
• Is there coherence between the scope and certainty of premises and conclusions?
• What issues are not covered by the argument as it stands? (And should they
be included?)
• Is it clear why some reasons are not being considered?
• Are the value judgments in this reasoning clearly outlined and argued for?

Exercise 9.2
Using the same issue that you worked on in exercise 9 . 1 , write down a series of
questions that will help you to establish the internal dimensions of your topic
(how premises relate to one another and to the conclusion; how further claims
relate to the premise; and so on).

Using the analytical structure for planning


Different sorts of plans
Usually, when we are told to plan our arguments and explanations, we are given
advice about how to create a good narrative flow or sequence. For example, many
excellent books on writing discuss the need to plan written work so that we move
from the introduction through each of the main points to the conclusion. For each
stage of the work, these books give advice about what is required to make the
resulting essay or report readable and effective. These books also refer to the idea of
'mind-mapping', in which, rather than trying to write down our thoughts and ideas
in a linear sequence (as they will appear in final written form), we should begin by
'mapping' them all over a piece of paper, drawing lines to connect them together
and adding new ideas that expand on what is already there.
Both planning methods have their advantages but only if we use them at the right
time, with a clear understanding of their purpose, and knowing what each represents.
They share one important feature: by externalising thoughts, that is, putting them on
paper, they enable us to reflect and think through what it is we are doing. A written
sequence plan should be developed last, just before we commence writing. The
purpose is similar, really, to the table of contents in this book. The narrative plan guides
us and reminds us what, in turn, we need to write about within the narrative sequence.
It represents, in summary form, the order in which we are going to write our narrative.
A mind-map should be used first, before we have really begun to think about what
exactly we want to argue or explain. Its purpose is to aid us in 'brainstorming' the
jumbled mass of ideas and possible connections—to get them down on paper so we
can think more clearly about them. It represents the initial 'pool' of knowledge in our

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
128 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

heads that needs to be thought through, researched, and organised in some way before
it makes sense to others. Here is an example, covering the same topic as the analytical
structure just given.

more nat/bn? cyclihQ


more ei/enrs
more comparers' Jt^_
— LA
A SSpwos
Mo/anos
—professional bad in
s Song * Dance,
GETWG / ceremon/es
dlGGER + ¥ ENTERTAINMENT
' T 'Hollywood'
I \ extravaganzas

i \TVdemands
oumc
GAMES

/
/ ^<rv// events
/ V ^ . staged
rlOrVEy?^^

~~-~-^jnoney paid \ lots of


to networks adverts
SECURITY

Olympics as ne&dfo
A
easytargef 9 ^ ^ * ^

Munich '72?.
Atlanta <96jfe"onsm Wis changing
spent on secur/ty gt PAY-Wcost?
At/onto Murdoch

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 129

The analytical structure format as a plan for writing


The analytical structure format is different from (and, for purposes of smart
thinking, much better than) a mind-map or narrative plan. The ideas that
underpin it are used as the basis of the analytical questions that will guide every
stage of thinking, researching, and writing. The actual written-on-paper
format, with its list of claims and diagram, is then used, after initial research
but before we think about the narrative sequence. It can either guide further
research or guide the actual writing or presentation of our argument or
explanation. It allows us to externalise the analytical relationships between
ideas that are the heart of reasoning. Once on paper, these relationships and
ideas (the diagram and the claims) can be checked to see what mistakes we are
making, where more work needs to be done, how well we are analysing the
issues, and so on.
Now, throughout this book we have been using the analytical structure
format mainly as a way of understanding better what goes on within arguments
and explanations. When we use it as a planning tool, we need to be careful that
it does not 'take over' our project and become an end in itself. Always remember
that, like any planning tool, the analytical structure format simply provides
another way of helping to clarify and express your ideas in a form that assists you
to complete the final task: writing the full, narrative expression of your reasoning.
We must make sure that what is written in the plan can be easily translated into
this final product.
With this in mind, I will use an example from chapter 6 to show how a written
essay or report might develop from an analytical structure plan:

1. University education should be free for all Australians.


2. A well-educated population is more productive at work.
3. Higher productivity at work benefits the economy.
4. If something benefits the economy, then the government should
encourage it.
5. The best way for the government to encourage Australians to be well
educated is to provide free university education.
6. In our complex technological society, one requires university study in
order to be well educated.
7. Free education is a fundamental democratic right.
8. Australia is a democracy.
9. Education includes all levels from primary to tertiary.
10. Any cost that the government imposes on people attending higher
education will probably reduce the numbers attending.
11. If numbers are reduced, then Australians are obviously not being
encouraged to attend.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
130 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

©+©.©©.©,0,0,0
1
My conclusion (claim 1) is what I want my audience to agree with. Hence, I
will state it clearly in the first paragraph of my narrative flow (although there are
also times when it is better to leave the conclusion-claim until later on in the nar-
rative flow).2 At the same time, I want to signal to my readers that I will be giving
them two key reasons for accepting this conclusion—these reasons are expressed,
first, in claims 2 - 6 and, second, in claims 7-9. However, I would not go into detail
in this first paragraph but would simply indicate that, broadly, I will be discussing
free education in terms of economic benefit and democratic rights.
Next, although it is not represented anywhere in the analytical structure just
given, I would probably give a summary or overview of the history of higher edu-
cation in Australia, providing an outline of the times at which education has and
has not been free. To do this properly might involve the development of a second
structure diagram that captures the main points I want to make. I would also need
to establish a context for this argument: I could perhaps identify it as a response to
the continued pressure from the federal government to reduce public spending in
favour of more private spending by individual Australians. This section of the
written report (which, in this example, would be between ten and twelve pages, or
3000 words, in total) might be between two and three pages long.
Then I would begin my actual analysis by discussing the second of my two reasons
(the 'democratic rights' one), since it is, for me, more significant than the 'economic
benefit' reason. I would begin by writing about claim 8—'Australia is a democracy'—
and would not expend too much effort on showing why I made this claim (since it is
generally accepted). Probably a paragraph would be sufficient. My discussion of claim
7—'Free education is a fundamental democratic right'—is a different matter. I could
expect to write between four and five paragraphs exploring every aspect of this claim,
in effect developing an argument for its acceptability. I would need to consider the issue
of 'rights' and what they mean; whether or not free education is a 'fundamental' right
or just an added benefit where it is possible. You can see how it may well be necessary
for me to stop and, thinking through my argument, develop another analytical struc-
ture in which claim 7 is the conclusion. Finally, claim 9—'Education includes all levels
from primary to tertiary'—might simply be presented as a definition and expressed

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 131

quickly in one or two sentences in thefinalwritten form. Alternatively, it could become


a significant issue to develop further. I could perhaps show how, historically, govern-
ment policy on education has developed, first with the provision of free primary educa-
tion, then free secondary education for some years, then a full six years of free secondary
education, and then, in the 1970s and first half of the 1980s, free tertiary education.
Such a discussion might help me, later, to show the truth of claim 6—'In our complex
technological society, one requires university study in order to be well educated'.
At this stage in the written format, I would probably remind my readers of the
conclusion and introduce the 'economic benefit' reason, explicitly indicating that the
assumptions behind it (that the government should not simply fund all democratic
benefits for its citizens but should only pay for those that are economically signifi-
cant) come from a different philosophical position. While the two reasons overlap to
some degree, I need to make it clear that they are, essentially, quite distinct. This part
of the written report would be complex and lengthy. Looking at the structure, I see
that claims 2, 3, and 6 tend to be more closely related than claims 4 and 5- Hence,
although logically all of these five premises are dependent on one another, I would
break up my analysis into two sections and deal with each subgroup in turn. Knowing
that the second subgroup (claims 4 and 5) is the crucial framing or value-judging part
of the argument, I would be particularly detailed in arguing these premises through,
drawing on claims 10 and 11 to make out my case for claim 5. The final part of the
written work would simply restate the key reasons and the conclusion.
Here is the narrative sequence in plan form to emphasise the difference between
these two planning tools:

Introduction
• Give main conclusion (1) and key reasons: economic benefit (2—6) and
democratic right (7-9)
Main body: Background
• Give background on history of education in Australia with respect who paid
and why.
• Provide context (the current situation that leads to this argument).

Main body 2: develop 'democratic right' reason


• Write 1 paragraph on 8; 4 - 5 paragraphs on 7; 4 - 5 paragraphs on 9.

Main body 3: Develop 'economic benefit' reason


• Distinguish this reason from previous one; signal two related aspects (2 para-
graphs).
• Write 2 - 3 paragraphs on 2 and 3; 2 - 3 paragraphs on 6 (relate back to second
section).
• Write 4 - 5 paragraphs on 5; including discussion of 10 and 11; 2 - 3 para-
graphs on 4.

Conclusion.
• Sum up the two reasons and restate 1.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
132 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Exercise 9.3
Apply the questions developed in the first section of this chapter to the argument
just outlined about higher education in Australia. What do you think of the
reasoning? Is it strong? weak? Can it be improved? challenged? Write additional
claims, with appropriate diagrams, that either improve on, counter, or further
explore the issues raised in this argument. Then think about the general use of
these analytical questions and structures in relation to your own reasoning: how
can they help you to be a better smart thinker?

Review
Since reasoning is about knowledge, we must think about the epistemologies
(philosophies of knowledge) that underpin the relationship between text and
context. Questions can reveal the external boundaries of our topic and how it relates
to other topics, knowledge, or audiences; questions can also reveal important
aspects of our topic itself. The questioning process is not a 'once-off task that we
complete and then forget: it is a continuous process that relates specifically to the
way in which we set down our ideas in the analytical structure format.
This structure is most useful as a planning tool and differs from usual
plans, which either involve unstructured concepts (mind-maps) or ideas
arranged in the order that we will write them (a narrative sequence plan). The
key advantage of the analytical structure format is that it lays out, in advance
of writing or presentation, the structure of key claims and the links between
them in a way that is driven by the analysis—the reasoning—rather than by the
way we will present the argument or explanation.

CONCEPT CHECK
The following terms and concepts are introduced in this chapter. Before checking
in the Glossary, write a short definition of each term:

intersubjective

mind-map

narrative sequence plan


objective
relativism

Review exercise 9
Answer briefly the following questions giving, where possible, an example in your
answer that is different from those used in this book:

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
PLANNING AND CREATING YOUR REASONING 133

a. What are the factors we need to consider if we are to understand the


external dimensions of our text?
b. What are the factors we need to consider if we are to understand the
internal dimensions of our text?
c. How does context affect text and vice versa?
d. What is the difference between an objective and an intersubjective phil-
osophy of knowledge?
e. Why is it important to consider the connotative element of our claims?
f. What general purpose do plans fulfil?
g. What is the primary advantage of the analytical structure format when
used for planning?
h. What are the key differences between a narrative sequence plan, a mind-
map, and an analytical structure format?

NOTES

1 Some philosophers would maintain that knowledge can be objective, in those circum-
stances in which the knowledge is not affected at all by human subjectivity. I would
contend that, while theoretically possible, this objective status is never reached in prac-
tice. Although we may, as thinking human subjects, be able to utilise methods and
approaches that eliminate all possibility of subjective bias (and most academic disci-
plines have a wide range of such methods and approaches), the very use of these
methods and approaches itself creates a subjective element. For example, within
Western scientific medical practice, knowledge of diseases may be objective; however,
from a different viewpoint (such as, for example, traditional or folk medicine), the very
decision to use a scientific approach is itself a subjective element. Moreover, the human
subject is created in part by what he or she knows. To say that knowledge is intersub-
jective means all knowledge is interrelated and that the specific pattern of relationship
will depend upon who, when, where, and how subjects express and receive knowledge.
2 Remember that we often refer to the last paragraph of an essay or presentation as the
'conclusion'. Here, of course, because we are talking analytically, the conclusion is the
key claim that we want our audience to accept.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
10
Bringing It All Together:
Narrative and Structure
In this final chapter, I provide a fully worked example of a substantial written
argument, which I have cast and commented upon, so as to demonstrate the
way in which the main form in which we encounter reasoning—the narrative
flow—is perhaps better understood as an expression of an underlying process
of linking premises and conclusions. This longer example also demonstrates
in more detail how you might end up writing something based on an analyt-
ical structure, pointing out the subtleties of expression that provide a
structure and meaning surrounding that logical core.
First, read the example, which is an argument I use to convince students
of the need to reference properly when they write essays. Second, read care-
fully my analysis of the logic, broken down paragraph by paragraph (you might
even want to try casting it yourself). Third, look at the way I try to capture the
essence of the text in a simpler argument. Finally, consider my overall
assessment of the ten paragraphs that make up this text.

Example text
The value of referencing
One of the problems that confronts teachers of first-year university units each
semester is the need to ensure that students learn, quickly, the methods and
skills of correct referencing. In some courses, students are very much left to
fend for themselves, relying on, perhaps, the services of the university library,
advice offered by individual staff members, or simply muddling through on the

134 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 135

basis of critical feedback on their first assignments. The Department of Media


and Information (DMI), along with some other areas of the university, takes a
different approach. DMI, in its first-year unit MCI 101: Research and
Presentation Project, directly addresses the need that students have to learn
correct referencing techniques, devoting some weeks and an assignment to that
task. Students can also practise these techniques in the assignments required in
other first-year units.
Nevertheless, even when direct attention of the kind just outlined has been
paid to referencing, some students continue to struggle with it. The problem is
not merely a technical one, since all the students at university are capable of
learning to follow the kinds of technical directions that lay out the appropriate
steps needed to reference their work. What then is the cause of this problem?
DMI would suggest that many students (including some who are quite able
referencers) remain confused about the admittedly complex set of reasons that
explain why referencing is so important in all kinds of written communication.
This paper will outline these reasons before ending with a short exploration of
why they might be hard for some students to grasp.
As just indicated, there are three main reasons why referencing is important
in essays, reports, presentations, theses, articles, and all the other kinds of
scholarly writing in which students engage both at university and then, as
graduates, in their professions. Without seeking to assign a priority to any of
them they are: first, that referencing enables a reader to seek out more infor-
mation on the topic of the written work, based on the references given; second,
referencing acknowledges authors' ethical and academic debt of thanks to those
sources which they have used to create their own 'source' of information; and
third, referencing provides a method by which authors can establish the validity
and strength of their claims by relying on the authority of the source to which
they are referring. Let us examine these reasons in more detail.
The process of effective scholarship (finding, analysing, and communicating
information) involves an almost-constant acquisition of ideas, knowledge,
views, and general contextual understanding. One method of finding the
material from which to acquire this information, used mainly at times of inten-
sive research, is to follow the leads provided in an article or book via the
references to find, quickly and with a high degree of reliability, additional
valuable, relevant sources of information. A well-constructed piece of scholarly
writing will contain both information in its own right and information that
assists readers in further information acquisition. Thus an author needs to see
referencing as a service to the reader of their work and, using the kinds of
standard methods that are available (such as the APA system), make sure readers
are easily able to go from their text to others via those references.
The second reason noted above was that authors owe a debt to those writers
who have provided them with information, inspiration, and ideas. This debt is
both scholarly and ethical. What do I mean by assigning two different aspects
to this notion of debt? Following the 'debt' metaphor through a little further, it

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
136 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

is possible to say first that the scholarly community within which an author
writes enforces payment of the debt (their readers will check their work, either
consciously or not, for evidence that proper referencing has taken place). Second,
it is enforced, or at least made possible, by the ethical behaviour of individual
authors who, privately, must recognise they need to acknowledge those other
writers who have helped them. Without referencing, the system of mutual
obligation on authors to use each others' work, to link new pieces of work to
those already published, and to rely on one another's specific expertise would
collapse. Thus referencing is important, even if the references were never actually
followed up (though, of course, they regularly are).
The third reason why referencing is so important is, perhaps, the most difficult
to grasp. References allow an author to obviate the need to detail and support every
single premise in their arguments and explanations by relying instead on the
authority of the source from which they obtained the information they are
presenting (see Allen, Smart Thinking, chapter 6 for more explanation). Put simply,
references are part of the way one writes a convincing argument or explanation.
Since good writing always seeks to be convincing, even if to only a small degree,
then it is easy to see why the quest to teach students to be good writers must also
involve teaching them to reference effectively.
These three reasons can be summed up as follows. Each newly produced
essay, article, presentation, or whatever, is always based substantially in existing
published or presented material and becomes a part of the 'ongoing, knowl-
edgeable conversation' expressed through that material. Written work needs
good referencing so as to refer its readers elsewhere, to repay the debt to other
writers, and to reinforce its own arguments.
But what makes it hard for some students to grasp the essential elements of
this relatively simple argument as to why they must reference, even as they
dutifully follow out the instructions to 'reference correctly' laid out for them
by teachers? Without going into detail, it seems likely that many students do
not yet believe themselves to be authors, with an audience, and a comradeship
with other authors. They see themselves primarily as students, governed by a
debilitating and unequal regime of inequality in relation to their teachers.
Thus, the reasons I have just outlined are not rejected by some students
because they are not understood, or are unreasonably or wilfully ignored.
Rather the reasons are rejected because they are, quite rationally, not relevant
to a 'student', even if they are explained to students. A 'student' (by which I
mean the abstract identity rather than any particular individual) is governed by
the imperatives of 'doing as one is told' by teachers; a student's audience is
their assessor; a student's sense of comradeship is with other students as
students; the goal of writing is not, usually, 'contributing to human
knowledge' but getting a good mark.
Students in general then fail to understand the need to reference because they
do not see how the very sensible arguments in favour of referencing apply to
them. Thus, in terms of the cultural understanding of student identity—of 'who

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 1 3 7

students believe themselves to be'—we can see that students probably fail to
reference effectively because they are not motivated by genuine self-interest as
writers, but instead by the dubious and failure-prone motivation of obedience.
The problem with which I began this paper, namely the need to ensure that
students learn, quickly, the methods and skills of correct referencing, is often
addressed at university simply in a technical fashion. But, in light of the very
brief analysis of the student-as-student (rather than student-as-writer) that I
have just proposed, the real solution lies in a combination of effective technical
help and, at least as importantly, a conscious and supportive effort to encourage
students to think in new ways about themselves and the relationship they have
to their teachers. Unless a relationship can develop between teachers and
students that emphasises a shared (but still, by differences in experience and
training, unequal) responsibility for production of knowledge, then referencing
will continue to be a confusing and potentially antagonistic battleground for all
concerned.

Casting and notes on each paragraph


One of the problems that confronts teachers of first-year university units
each semester is the need to ensure that students learn, quickly, the
methods and skills of correct referencing.3 [In some courses, students are
very much left to fend for themselves, relying on, perhaps, the services of
the university library, advice offered by individual staff members, or simply
muddling through on the basis of critical feedback on their first assign-
ments.]1 [The Department of Media and Information (DMI), along with
some other areas of the university," takes a different approach.]2 [DMI, in
its first-year unit MCI 1 0 1 : Research and Presentation Project, directly
addresses the need that students have to learn correct referencing
techniques, devoting some weeks and an assignment to that task.c]3
[Students can also practise these techniques in the assignments required
in other first-year units.]4

This first paragraph establishes that it is reasonable to claim that DMI takes a
different approach. It does so, in the premises, by claiming what other departments
do, and then claims that what DMI does differs from this. Here are three inter-
esting features of the paragraph:

a The first sentence is not part of the argument directly. However, this
sentence does contribute. When claim 2 says 'takes a different approach', the
question that needs to be answered is 'a different approach to what?'. The
first sentence provides the answer... 'a different approach to the
problem... [etc].'
b The phrase 'along with some other areas of the university' is not properly

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
138 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

supported in the argument, as there is no evidence about these other areas.


Technically, one might say, it is unproven.
c The phrase 'devoting some weeks and an assignment to that task' might be
thought by some to be a separate claim, embedded in claim 3. Possibly: but
I would see it as detail which expands on and makes sensible the part of
claim 3 that says 'directly addresses'—the detail shows how it is direct.
By way of example, here is the basic analytical structure that might be seen to
lie beneath this narrative flow:
2. The Department of Media and Information takes a different approach to some
other parts ofCurtin University in solving the problem of ensuring that students
in first-year university units each semester learn, quickly, the methods and skills
of correct referencing.
1. In some courses, students are very much left to fend for themselves, relying on,
perhaps, the services of the university library, advice offered by individual staff
members, or simply muddling through on the basis of critical feedback on their
first assignments.
3. The Department of Media and Information uses itsfirst-yearunit MCI 101:
Research and Presentation Project to address directly the need that students have
to learn the methods and skills of correct referencing by devoting some weeks in
class and an assignment to that goal.
4. Students in the Department of Media and Information also practise the methods
and skills of correct referencing learned in MCI 101: Research and Presentation
Project in the assignments required in other first-year units that they are
studying at the same time.

©
Moving on to the second paragraph:
[Nevertheless, even when direct attention of the kindd just outlined has
been paid to referencing, some students continue to struggle with it.]5 [The
problem is not merely a technical one]6, since e [all the students at
university are capable of learning to follow the kinds of technical directions
that lay out the appropriate steps needed to reference their work.]7 What
then is the cause of this problem?' DM I would suggest that [many students
(including some who are quite able referencers) remain confused about the
admittedly complex set of reasons that explain why referencing is so

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 139

important in all kinds of written communication.]8 This paper will outline


these reasons before ending with a short exploration of why they might be
hard for some students to grasp.

0^0
©.©

0
This paragraph is complex. For one thing, it does not have a clear conclusion.
It is both 'structuring' the paper and also advancing an argument for that structure.
I would imagine the implied conclusion, marked here as V, to be something like
'The cause of the problem is that students remain confused about these reasons'.
There are also a number of assumptions made which mean there are implied prem-
ises. Here are three interesting features of the paragraph:
d. This inter-paragraph reference clearly demonstrates how the analytical
structure cannot be easily read off'the words in front of us', but depends on
the surrounding narrative flow.
e. 'Since' tells us that, even though we might ourselves not imagine the claim
following it is a premise for the claim that precedes it, we have no choice
but to diagram it in this way. The author intends that we use the claim 7 as
a premise for 6, and we diagram as the author intended.
f. This question is not a claim, but prompts us to think about the implied
conclusion.
Here is the analytical structure of the first argument in this passage (what we
can call a sub-argument because it is subsidiary to, but part of the overall argument
in the paragraph), but this time making explicit the implied premise. See how
'obvious' it is?
5. Nevertheless, some students continue to struggle with the methods and skills of
correct referencing even when direct attention has been paid to learning it, as for
example in MCI 101: Research and Presentation Project.
7. All students at university are capable of learning to follow the kinds of

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
140 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

technical directions that lay out the appropriate steps needed to reference their
work.
i. If everyone can follow the technical directions, then some peoples failure to
follow them indicates that technical matters are not the problem.
6. The problem of some students struggling with the methods and skills of correct
referencing is not merely a technical one.

©
The third paragraph is not reasoning:
As just indicated, there are three main reasons why referencing is impor-
tant in essays, reports, presentations, theses, articles, and all the other
kinds of scholarly writing in which students engage both at university and
then, as graduates, in their professions. Without seeking to assign a
priority to any of them they are: first, that referencing enables a reader to
seek out more information on the topic of the written work, based on the
references given; second, referencing acknowledges authors' ethical and
academic debt of thanks to those sources which they have used to create
their own 'source' of information; and third, referencing provides a method
by which authors can establish the validity and strength of their claims by
relying on the authority of the source to which they are referring. Let us
examine these reasons in more detail.
It identifies the three reasons and then says that the paper will examine them. Since
there is no attempt to argue or explain why there are three reasons, or why the paper is
looking at them in detail, and so on, there is nothing to be cast. Then, in paragraph 4:
[The process of effective scholarship (finding, analysing and communi-
cating information) involves an almost-constant acquisition of ideas,
knowledge, views, and general contextual understanding.]9 [One
method of finding the material from which to acquire this information,
used mainly at times of intensive research, is to follow the leads
provided in an article or book via the references to find, quickly and with
a high degree of reliability, additional valuable, relevant sources of
information.]10 [A well-constructed piece of scholarly writing will
contain both information in its own right and information that assists
readers in further information acquisition.]11. Thus [an author needs to
see referencing as a service to the reader of their work.]12 and, [using

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 141

the kinds of standard methods that are available (such as the APA
system)]13, make sure readers are easily able to go from their text to
others via those references.]14.

©•©
©•©

©
The last sentence could either contain two claims and an implied claim or
three claims. Since the phrase starting 'using...' is what I use to infer the exis-
tence of the implied claim, I think it is best cast as three claims as indicated.
Obviously the phrase 'using...' is not, in its current form, a complete claim. I
would suggest that what it is really saying is: 'if referencing is a service to readers,
then readers will only be able to benefit from this service by going to other texts
via the references when an author uses the kinds of standard methods that are
available'.

The second reason noted above was thatg [authors owe a debt to those
other writers who have provided them with information, inspiration and
ideas.]15 [This debt is both scholarly and ethical.]16 What do I mean by
assigning two different aspects to this notion of debt? Following the 'debt'
metaphor through a little further, it is possible to say first that [the schol-
arly community within which an author writes enforces payment of the
debt]17 [(their readers will check their work, either consciously or not, for
evidence that proper referencing has taken place)]18. Second, [it is
enforced, or at least made possible, by the ethical behaviour of individual
authors who, privately, must recognise they need to acknowledge those
other writers who have helped them.]19 [Without referencing, the system
of mutual obligation on authors to use each others' work, to link new
pieces of work to those already published, and to rely on one another's
specific expertise would collapse.]20 Thus [referencing is important, even
if the references were never actually followed uph (though, of course, they
regularly are).]21

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
142 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

0+ © + ©
©
A difficult paragraph, not least because the ideas being presented are complex
and metaphorical. A key feature here is to discern that there are sub-arguments
within the main argument. That is, some of the reasoning here proves other claims
that then help demonstrate the validity of conclusions further 'down' the chain of
reasoning. As well, there is an important implied premise that links 16,15, and 20
together. Can you identify it? Here are two interesting features of the paragraph:
g. In both cases, the extra words here are not part of the claims which follow
them. They help readers follow the narrative flow but are not, analytically,
significant.
h. We have looked at how claims contain elements that indicate scope; normally
we see these elements limiting the scope. However, in this case, the phrase
'even if...' extends the scope of the claim, attempting to counter any challenge
to the logic by people who say 'ah, but references are not always checked'.
Moving on:
The third reason why referencing is so important is, perhaps, the most diffi-
cult to grasp. [References allow an author to obviate the need to detail and
support every single premise in their arguments and explanations.]x by
[relying instead on the authority of the source from which they obtained the
information they are presenting.]y [(see Allen, Smart Thinking, chapter 6 for
more explanation).]z Put simply, [references are part of the way one writes a
convincing argument or explanation.]22 Since [good writing always seeks to
be convincing, even if to only a small degree]23\ then it is easy to see whyj
[the quest to teach students to be good writers must also involve teaching
them to reference effectively.]24

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 143

22 + 23

24

This paragraph contains repetition and the main analytical point being made
does not start until claim 22. However, to be thorough, I have also demonstrated
how the first part of the paragraph contains a 'side argument' (of sorts) (see below).
Here are two interesting features of the paragraph:
i. This claim is the general rule that is being applied to make the link from 2 2
to 24. Therefore this claim is the framing premise; and the type of reasoning
in the whole 22, 23, and 2 4 ensemble is general-to-specific.
j . The trace of reasoning 'then it is easy to see why' does not form part of the
claim and is therefore excluded from the brackets.
Here's how the 'side argument' can be written out:
x. References allow an author to obviate the need to detail and support every
single premise in their arguments and explanations.
y. References allow an author to rely on the authority of the source from
which they obtained the information they are presenting.
a. Relying on the authority of the source from which authors obtained the
information they are presenting obviates the need to detail and support
every single premise in their arguments and explanations.
z. Allen, writing in Smart Thinking, chapter 6 explains the way in which refer-
ences allow an author instead to rely on the authority of the source from
which they obtained the information they are presenting in more detail.

y i + l a

.—

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
144 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

Note how the reference to Smart Thinking serves to support the claim y, thereby
modelling the use of referencing which is the subject of the reason explained in the
paragraph.
The next paragraph is not reasoning. It summarises the three previous para-
graphs and their connection to the main theme.
These three reasons can be summed up as follows. Each newly
produced essay, article, presentation, or whatever, is always based
substantially in existing published or presented material and becomes
a part of the 'ongoing, knowledgeable conversation' expressed through
that material. Written work needs good referencing so as to refer its
readers elsewhere, to repay the debt to other writers, and to reinforce
its own arguments.
However, the next paragraph is an argument:
But what makes it hard for some students to grasp the essential elements
of this relatively simple argument as to why they must reference, even as
they dutifully follow out the instructions to 'reference correctly' laid out for
them by teachers?k Without going into detail, it seems likely that [many
students do not yet believe themselves to be authors, with an audience,
and a comradeship with other authors. They see themselves primarily as
students, governed by a debilitating and unequal regime of inequality in
relation to their teachers.125 Thus, [the reasons I have just outlined are
not rejected by some students because1 they are not understood, or are
unreasonably or wilfully ignored. Rather the reasons are rejected because
they are, quite rationally, not relevant to a 'student', even if they are
explained to students.]26 [A 'student' (by which I mean the abstract
identity rather than any particular individual) is governed by the impera-
tives of 'doing as one is told' by teachers;]27 [a student's audience is their
assessor;]28 [a student's sense of comradeship is with other students as
students;]29 [the goal of writing is not, usually, 'contributing to human
knowledge' but getting a good mark.]30

27 + 28 + 29 + 30

25

26

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 145

The most difficult paragraph in the text. First of all, the two sentences which I
have combined as claim 26 might appear to be two claims. Since they are stating
'two sides of the coin', we might better represent them as one claim, even though
the words are split over two sentences. Claim 25 shows a similar 'they are not—
they are' pairing which is, effectively in this case, one claim.
What this example demonstrates is the lack of clarity of casting: it is an
inexact science, in many cases depending on the way that a particular reader
interprets the passage, rather than on all readers agreeing with a single inter-
pretation. While we might use casting as an exercise to understand better analyt-
ical structure and logic, we should not confuse the exercise with practice. If the
specific goal of the exercise of casting is to decide on the claims and their
structure, its more general goal is to improve your understanding so that the 'real'
goal—better critical thinking in your own writing—is more obtainable. Here are
two interesting features:

k. I have indicated earlier in this book that questions can be thought of as


'claims-in-prospect' or, more fully, that a question is the way we propose a
claim so as to then find the answers we need (the reasons) that will either
support or reject that proposed claim. This question demonstrates the
point. It says 'But what makes it hard for some students to grasp the essen-
tial elements of this relatively simple argument as to why they must refer-
ence, even as they dutifully follow out the instructions to 'reference
correctly' laid out for them by teachers?', which in fact helps us to under-
stand what the paragraph is attempting to do. It is not arguing that students
do find it hard ... it is seeking to explore the reasons, the 'what makes it
hard'.
1. Be careful! In this special case 'because' is part of the claim. The claim is
claiming a link between the effect (ignoring referencing) and the cause (not
failure to grasp, but failure to see them as relevant). Hence, in this case,
because does not signal two separate claims.

The difficulty with the next paragraph (and, indeed, the previous one) is
that it relies on many assumptions and already-established ideas from the rest
of the text. Moreover, the paragraph combines explanation (explaining why
something happens) and argument, in that it argues for one explanation over
another.

[Students in general then fail to understand the need to reference.]32


because [they do not see how the very sensible arguments in favour
of referencing apply to them]33. Thus, in terms of the cultural under-
standing of student identity—of 'who students believe themselves to
be'—we can see that [students probably fail to reference effectively
because they are not motivated by genuine self-interest as writers,
but instead by the dubious and failure-prone motivation of obedi-
ence.]34

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
146 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

33

32

34

The last paragraph is a summary of what comes before and I have not cast
it.

Capturing the essence of the text


Looking back over the last three paragraphs, I have tried to produce something of
the key argument they contain as a list of claims and diagram. In doing so, I hope
not only to assist you in understanding the text as a whole but also to show how
casting is not 'the only way of doing things'. Sometimes we can try to understand
things by reconstructing the underlying argument structure, rather than directly
recovering it from the narrative flow. I have changed the words, and stripped the
argument down to its essentials so as to make clear what the logic is. This is not
casting. I am doing it here simply to show you another use for the methods of
thinking about logic I have discussed in this book.

1. We need to make students think of themselves as writers and not as


students.
2. Students write for an assessor.
3. Students have comradeship with other students.
4. Students write with the goal of getting a good mark.
5. Students write as a result of being told to write.
6. Being a writer means believing that the goal of writing is contributing
to knowledge.
7. Being a writer means thinking of one's audience as those people with
something to learn from the writer.
8. Being a writer means having a sense of comradeship with other
authors.
9. Being a writer means writing with self-motivation to write.
10. Students do not write as if they are writers, but write as students.
1 1 . Referencing only seems relevant if one is a writer.
1 2 . Students know technically how to reference.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
BRINGING IT ALL TOGETHER: NARRATIVE AND STRUCTURE 147

1 3 . The most likely explanation of students' failures to reference is that


they do not think of themselves as writers.
1 4 . We do not want students to fail to reference.

©.0.0,©.©,©.©.©
Y

0.©.©
©.©
Y

0
Overall narrative flow of the text
There are ten paragraphs in the text. Here is what each of them does, as part of a
narrative flow that expresses the underlying logical structure:
1 Sets the scene by providing background information and grabbing the
reader's attention by establishing that there is a problem that needs to be
considered.
2 This paragraph provides crucial signalling information about the whole piece.
It identifies that there is something interesting about the solution proposed
by it to the problem (always useful to know when one is looking for new and
different ideas), and signals that the paper has a two-part structure.
3 A further set of signals about the organisation of the paper. It identifies that
there will be three reasons, and each will be examined in detail.
4,5,6 Each of these paragraphs covers one of the three reasons signalled in
paragraph 3. This structure shows how paragraphing can help, indirectly, to
sustain the argument ... reflecting the intellectual decisions about what and
how many reasons in the words on the page.
7 Sums up these reasons in an accessible way. It is not a conclusion. It
summarises. Paragraphs like this are useful to help readers grasp what has been
communicated since reading something twice helps to embed it in their
minds.
https://books.yossr.com/en/books
148 SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

8 Commences the second part of the text, as cued by the question and by the
fact that the preceding paragraph was a summary.
9 Continues the second part, stating the main conclusion for this part of the
paper.
10 Takes the material from paragraphs 8 and 9 and relates it back to the problem
and context with which the text commenced in paragraphs 1 and 2. It briefly
mentions the material from paragraphs 3 to 7 so as to make a comprehensive
endpoint.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Summary
This book has concentrated on the analytical structure format, primarily as a way
of learning about reasoning, but also with an eye to its practical application as a tool
for helping you plan the creation and presentation of arguments and explanations.
Yet it would be wrong to think that the format is, of itself, something essential to
reasoning. It is not. This format—along with the idea of analytical questions—is
one way of representing the thought processes that we must go through to be smart
thinkers. It enables us to see that the key elements of smart thinking are:
• being thoughtful in considering issues in depth and with breadth, and without
'missing' any element of reasoning
• being critical in the way we assess information, not taking things for granted
or making easy assumptions, either about the truth of claims or their inter-
relationships with other claims
• being smart in the way we relate the texts of reasoning to the contexts in
which they are produced, presented, and then used
• being aware that 'knowledge' and 'reasoning' represent two perspectives on
the same fundamental concept: that we explain and argue about the world in
terms of the links between objects and ideas. No one idea or object can be
understood except in relation to others.

Smart thinking is not just a method or skill. It is also an attitude. Practising and
using the skills, with a clear awareness of what you are doing and a willingness to
reflect on and learn about the process of reasoning, will give you the right approach
to being a smart thinker, effective in your reasoning and able to achieve your goals
through arguments and explanations. Good luck!

https://books.yossr.com/en/books 149
Answers, Discussion,
and Further Advice

Chapter 1
Exercise 1 . 1
Asking questions (of ourselves and others). Your questions are designed to tell you
what you do not already know and guide you in what to find out; but they also draw
out hidden aspects of a problem; and, because questions are like claims (see chapter 2),
they provide possible conclusions for your argument. You will find that questions are
essential to good reasoning, and in chapter 9 we focus on the questions you need to ask.
Seek out information. Smart thinking requires information. It also helps us when
dealing with information by letting us sift through for the essential things we want
to know. Chapter 8 provides guidance on how to search for and recover informa-
tion analytically—that is, as part of the reasoning process.
Make connections. This activity is crucial. If you are not doing this, you are not
thinking smart. It is like doing a jigsaw puzzle—if you put the pieces together in
the right way, you come up with the 'right answer' (the picture) at the end. The
connections we might make between separate pieces of evidence or ideas are
demonstrated most clearly in chapters 3 and 4.
Interpret and evaluate. Not only do you need to interpret and evaluate what you
read: you also need to do these actions to your own thinking! Chapters 5 and 6 are
all about improving your reasoning and in that process evaluation is critical.

Exercise 1.2
Questioning is rather like concept- or mind-mapping (see chapter 9). However, it
is important that you treat this exercise as one of asking (not trying to answer) the

150 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 151

questions. Too often we begin to answer a question or two that concern us without
having first thought about what other questions need asking.

Chapter 2
Exercise 2 . 1
Statements b, e, and fare claims.

Exercise 2.2
a two claims: 'All that glitters is gold'; 'this nugget glitters'.
b one claim: 'The song is called "Diamonds are a Girl's Best Friend"', concealed
in a rhetorical question,
c three claims: 'Silver jewellery is very common'; 'silver is a cheap metal', 'it
[silver] is easily worked'. Note the use of the pronoun 'it'.

Exercise 2.3
a 'Drinking milk' subject makes 'some people feel sick' predicate
b T subject 'do not drink milk' predicate
c 'Milk drinking' subject is 'not recommended for people who are lactose-
intolerant' predicate

Exercise 2.4
a 'drinking milk makes some people feel sick'. This direct claim has been made
by the doctor. The actual meaning of the entire claim is that I have been told
this claim.
b 'I drink milk' 'I feel sick'. There are two claims here, effectively, combined to
make a propositional super-claim.
c 'a person comes to a doctor and says "If I drink milk, then I feel sick'" and
'the doctor will diagnose that person as lactose-intolerant'. These are the two
claims in the if/then statement; note also that the first claim is itself an
indirect claim, like (a).

Exercise 2.5
Order of scope: b, a, c. The key words are (b)'Whenever', (a) 'Sometimes', and (c)
'Occasionally'. Order of certainty: e, d, f. The key words are (e) 'There is no way',
(d) 'probable', and (f) 'the odds are 50:50'. The linkages are between (a) milk-
drinking and sickness; (b) eating cheese before sleeping and dreams; (c) eating rich
food and indigestion; and (d-f) humans and living in space.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
152 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

Exercise 2.6
Claims a and c are explicit value claims; claim b has an implied value judgment;
claim d is (probably) simply descriptive. Where is the value judgment in claim b?
It does, of course, depend on context, but most people in contemporary Australia
recognise that 'fat is bad for you'. Hence, claiming that some product contains fat
connects it with this value judgment; equally, though, there are some situations in
which fat is good for you (or at least better than avoiding it altogether). On the
other hand, is there some value judgment in claim d? In certain contexts, the idea
that 'white is pure' (and hence 'good for you') could be implied by this claim, thus
making it, to some extent, a value judgment. If you found this exercise hard, you
have done well: judging and identifying value claims depends, by and large, on the
contexts in which we find those claims.

Exercise 2.7
Some examples: 'Because the road is wet [p], you need to drive more carefully
[c]'; 'Because you need to drive more carefully [p], you should pay attention to
what you are doing [c]'; 'I conclude that there was a rainstorm a few minutes
ago [c] because Verity has just come home soaking wet [p]'; 'There was a
rainstorm a few minutes ago [p] and so the road is wet [c]'. In preparation for
chapter 3, think about the role of words such as 'because', 'I conclude', and so
on.

Exercise 2.8
Conclusions a and d are appeals to action, with the latter involving a change in
thinking. Note the disguised claim in the rhetorical question. Conclusion b makes
a prediction. Conclusion c is an explanation showing how the conclusion comes
about. Conclusion e is a justification on the part of the government for its past
actions (as stated in the conclusion).

Chapter 3
Exercise 3.1
Some examples of the way to rewrite them are:
a I was elated because, today, I found out that I had passed my exam. (Two
claims now contained in one sentence.)
b I felt ill and so I went home from work. (Still two claims in one sentence but
different way of signalling the conclusion... 'so'.)
c Thinking helps us to do better at work; and thinking improves our perfor-
mance at university. So we better learn to do it! (Changing where the nouns
and pronouns fit, and the order.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 153

d John is a fully qualified lawyer because he passed his final exams. (Change of
order.)
e Many tourists come to Australia because Australia has great natural beauty
and a marvellous climate. (Change of order.)

Exercise 3.2
Here are two possible answers, with the linking words in italics.
1 You should drive more carefully because of the fact that wet roads increase
the risk of accident and the road is indeed wet. [The word 'indeed' may or
may not be some sort of signal that this claim is a premise linked to the
conclusion; it suggests that the truth of the claim 'the road is wet' is very
obvious. In reasoning we use better known or accepted claims as the premises
to prove a less obvious one.]
2 Can you not see that you should drive more carefully? I mean the road is
wet and we know that wet roads increase the risk of accident. [The conclusion
has been expressed as a rhetorical question; as a standard claim, it would read
'You must see that you should drive more carefully'.]

Exercise 3.3
The order of the claims in the structure is more logical, especially when cross-
referenced to the diagram, which shows the sequence of arguments. The claims are
written without pronouns, so each is meaningful in and of itself. The arrows and
other symbols in the diagram show the specific links between claims, rather than
being hidden in the narrative flow. The claims in the analytical structure are self-
contained: you don't need to read any other claim to know what each means
whereas in the narrative flow, you do.

Exercise 3.4
a (I should not buy a car at the moment) 1. (I have just lost my driver's licence)
2 and, besides, (I cannot afford it) 3.

There are no link words that might signal the conclusion or premises. However,
of the three claims, claim 1 is the obvious conclusion. If claims 2 or 3 were the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
154 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

conclusion, then the argument would make very little, if any, sense at all. In this
case, the premises do not add together. While the word 'and' might suggest they do,
either premise on its own would be sufficient to support the conclusion. Hence
they are independent of one another in the diagram. (See chapter 4.)
b (Nicole Kidman is an international movie star) 1 and I know that, (as a
general rule, international movie stars get paid a lot of money) 2 . Therefore,
it is obvious that (Nicole Kidman is well paid) 3.

©*©
Y

©
This example should be easier than the first. This time there are two linking
phrases, which clearly show the conclusion and one of the premises. Claims 1 and
2 are dependent on one another, meaning they must be 'grouped' together. (See
chapter 4.)
c (I have not got a university education, whereas several of my colleagues do) 1.
(All of them have recently received promotions, but I did not receive one) 2.
Given that (we are all roughly equal in our job performance) 3, I would have
to conclude that (a university education really helps one to get ahead in a
career) 4.

0
It is equally acceptable to separate claims 1 and 2 into four claims (that is, 'I
have not got a university education' as the first, 'several of my colleagues do [have
a university education]' as the second, and so on), but it does not clarify the
analytical structure. The trick here is to avoid being fooled by the punctuation: the
first three claims are all dependent premises, despite being spread over three
sentences and despite the lack of clear signals for the first two claims. See the
section 'Special function of premises' in chapter 4 for a discussion of how one claim
https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 155

(claim 3 in this example) plays a significant role in explaining why the other prem-
ises lead to a particular conclusion.
d What was the explanation for (Sydney beating Beijing for the 2000
Olympics) 1? There were two main reasons. (The Sydney organisers did a
better job of lobbying the International Olympic Committee delegates) 2
and, because of (political crises in China at the time) 3 and (perceived doubts
about Beijing's quality of services and venues) 4, (Sydney offered a much safer
venue for a successful Olympic games) 5.

This example is the hardest. The 'two main reasons' signal might confuse you
about the nature of claims 3 and 4. But think about what the author is trying to
say with the 'because'. It does not relate to claim 1, but gives two reasons for claim
5. We can think of these last three claims as a sub-argument. Claim 5 functions as
the conclusion in this sub-argument but then becomes a premise in the main expla-
nation. Note, too, that 'political crises in China' is a short-hand way of saying
'There were political crises in China at that time', and similarly for claim 4. Read
further in chapter 3 for a discussion of the role of these sub-arguments inside a
main argument or explanation.

Exercise 3.5
First, do not write, as if it were one claim, a statement that is either not a claim or
is two claims. For example, the sentence 'We should study reasoning because it
will help us to understand our world better' contains two claims, linked with the
word 'because'. For your analytical structure to be workable, each numbered state-
ment must be one claim only. Use your analytical structure diagram to show the
relationship signalled by words such as 'because'. Labelling 'Reasoning is that skill
that' as claim 1 and 'helps us to solve problems' as claim 2 is also wrong. One
claim has, in this example, been split falsely into two non-claims. A claim needs
to connect internally two key ideas or concepts. 'Reasoning is that skill that helps
us to solve problems' is one claim, connecting reasoning with the idea of solving
problems.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
156 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

Second, do not write claims that make no sense on their own. While narrative
writing and speaking requires the use of pronouns and other short-hand phrases,
for planning purposes we should write more precisely. The following example, for
instance, is incorrect:
1 Matthew Allen is the author of a book on reasoning.
2 He works at Curtin University.
3 This is a short, practically oriented book.
Using 'he' and 'this' are confusing. You need to use the appropriate nouns, as in
the following example:
1 Matthew Allen is the author of a book on reasoning.
2 Matthew Allen works at Curtin University.
3 The book on reasoning that Matthew Allen wrote is short and practi-
cally oriented.
Third, avoid mistakes in diagramming the interrelationship of claims. Some
mistakes in this area are the result of not understanding clearly what you want to
say—later chapters will help you to overcome these mistakes. Other mistakes result
from not grasping the meaning of the diagram symbols. Here are two examples.
First of all, imagine I had argued that:
1 Reasoning skills should be taught more in Australian schools [as my
conclusion].
2 Reasoning is a key skill which all people should know about [as my
premise].
It would be incorrect to diagram their relationship thus:

©
Y

©
Although I have written the conclusion first, the only place for a conclusion in
the diagram is below the premise(s) that support it. The [V\ symbol indicates a
logical relationship (in this case, 'because 2, therefore 1 ') and not the order in which
you would write or say these claims.
Now imagine my argument was more complex:
1 Reasoning skills should be taught more in Australian schools.
2 Reasoning is a key skill which all people should know about.
3 Schools should teach people the key skills which they need.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 157

It would be incorrect to diagram their relationship thus:

Claims 2 and 3 are related and, indeed, are dependent on one another (see
chapter 4). It is wrong to use the [si] symbol for any form of relationship
between claims other than for the logical relationship 'because ... therefore'.
Instead the + symbol should have been used to join claims 2 and 3 on the same
line.
Other incorrect uses of the diagram tend to reflect a misunderstanding of the
fact that, first, the diagramming process must reflect what is written in the text (i.e.
the diagram brings out, explicitly, the relationships between premises and con-
clusions implicit in the wording of those claims); and second, a simple misunder-
standing that the line, arrow, and plus symbols must be used very precisely, to mean
only one thing. Here are examples of technical mistakes in diagramming you need
to avoid:

M 3

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
158 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

4 + 5

1 + 3

Exercise 3.6
[The current Australian government is, in many ways, challenging the role of
the United Nations as a body that promotes action by member nations to
maintain and extend human rights within those nations' own jurisdiction.] 1
[This challenge has a distinct and dangerous consequence for Australia]2
(quite apart from arguments about its dubious morality) because [the
challenge puts Australia in conflict with most other nations of the world over
human rights] 3 and [Australian trade and foreign relations are likely to suffer
in the long run.]4 By definition, [this long-run result is dangerous.]5 I believe
that [the government's role should be to work to avoid danger] 6 and, therefore,
I believe [the government's current approach to the UN over human rights is
incorrect.] 7

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 159

+ +

+ +

*-J—

Claim 1
The subject is: 'The current Australian government is'
The predicate is: 'challenging the role of the United Nations as a body that
promotes action by member nations to maintain and extend human rights within
those nations' own jurisdiction'
Note the limitation on scope, 'in many ways .
Claim 2
The phrase in parentheses could be included in the claim; my answer excludes it
because the words 'quite apart from...' imply that there are other issues here that
are not being discussed. Therefore it is not part of the overall logical structure.
However, one could also read it as a limitation, of sorts, on the scope of claim 2 ,
within this argument.
The subject is: 'This challenge' (note 'this, linking back to the predicate of
claim 1)
The predicate is: 'has a distinct and dangerous consequence for Australia'
Claim 3
The subject is: 'the challenge puts'
The predicate is: Australia in conflict with most other nations of the world over
human rights'
Claim 4
This claim is a 'contracted' claim. What it really says is 'if Australia is in conflict with
most other nations of the world over human rights, then Australian trade and foreign
relations are likely to suffer in the long run'. One can see how the predicate of claim
3 is positioned as the first part of the 'if/then' claim, allowing the consequence of the
challenge (the damage to trade and foreign relations) to be established.
The subject is: 'if Australia is in conflict with most other nations of the world
over human rights'
The predicate is: 'then Australian trade and foreign relations are likely to suffer
in the long run'
Claim 5
'By definition could be included in this claim or not: it is, in some ways, a certainty

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
160 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

element. It is saying 'definitely'. Alternatively, as I have done, it can be excluded as


simply indicating the kind of claim being made (definitional).
The subject is: 'this long-term result'
The predicate is: 'is dangerous' (Note the way this clearly links to the predicate
in the sub-conclusion, claim 2.)
Claim 6
'I believe should be excluded here (though it does not really matter if you included
it). If one is arguing, then it is taken that the claims on which you rely are those
one believes. However, had the claim been about another person's beliefs, the
correct answer would have included those words. The importance of claim 5, which
first raised 'danger' and then the way 'danger' is included in claim 2 starts to
become clear here.
The subject is: 'the government's role'
The predicate is: 'should be to work to avoid danger'
Claim 7
' / believe can again be excluded here. If one is arguing, then it is taken for granted
that the claims on which you rely are those you believe. However, had the claim
been about another person's beliefs, the correct answer would have included those
words. The subject of this claim is more detailed, so as to remind readers of the very
first claim made.
The subject is: 'the government's current approach to the UN over human
rights'
The predicate is: 'is incorrect'
The first part of the argument (3+4+5 —> 2)
Claim 2 is presented 'because' ... and then some more claims. As a result, these
claims are functioning as the premises for 2 . Claim 2 , therefore, functions as a
conclusion to 3, 4, and 5 and then as a premise in the rest of the argument. Note
the use of a proposition here (claim 4). 'If x happens, then y happens; x is
happening; therefore y will happen'.
The second part of the argument (1+2+6 —> 7)
Generally governments should work to avoid danger, the arguer is saying. In
this specific case the government is not doing that. Therefore the government is
wrong in this specific case.

Chapter 4
Exercise 4.1
Here is one possible answer. I have marked the main elements of interconnection
with letters.
1 Australia should [a] continue to spend a proportion of its national budget on
foreign aid [b].
2 Australia is morally obligated [c] to provide foreign aid [b].
3 If a nation is morally obligated to act [c], then it should [a].

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 161

Exercise 4.2
Here is one possible answer. Each premise functions as a different reason for the
conclusion (one concerns economics and the other morality), unlike the
previous exercise, in which two premises worked together to provide just one
reason.
1 Australia should continue to spend a proportion of its national budget on
foreign aid.
2 Providing economic aid is a prudent economic investment.
3 Australia is morally obligated to provide foreign aid.

Exercise 4.3
a If one is sick, then one should not come to work.
b When someone abuses your trust, they should be punished [another way of
saying 'if someone abuses your trust, then they should be punished'],
c All human life is worth protecting.
In each case, notice how these premises tell us why the particular evidence given
leads us to the stated conclusion. On that basis, here are the missing framework
premises for the answers to exercise 4.2:
1 Claim 2 needs claim 4: All nations should make prudent economic
investments' (alternatively, 'if an action is economically prudent, then it
should be pursued').
2 Claim 3 needs claim 5: A nation should act on its moral obligations'
(alternatively, 'if a nation has moral obligations, then it should act upon
them').
And the diagram for these claims is:

Exercise 4.4
Here are four definitions. Which example relates to which method?
a Studying critical thinking is like learning to play a difficult sport well: you
have to break it down into its components and practise each one.
b By 'studying critical thinking' I mean learning to use reasoning for arguing and
explaining and then learning about the context in which reasoning occurs.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
162 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

c Studying critical thinking is not the same as studying moral reasoning,


d Studying critical thinking means, for example, reading a book like this
one.

Exercise 4.5
The first argument is 2+3 —» 4. Claims 2 and 4 are identical, except that 'assault'
is replaced with 'threaten to attack'. Claim 3 does the work of making this equiva-
lence. It might seem foolish but it is an important point: you do not actually have
to touch someone to be charged with assault—the threat is sufficient. In this case,
one might assume the audience did not know this point and the arguer was making
it clear to them.
The second argument is 5 —> 6. In a way claim 5 is actually saying a very similar
thing to claim 6. However 5 relates to a specific survey; 6 concludes a general posi-
tion on the basis of that survey. For example, the link is made in the consistency
between 5 and 6; 150 out of 200 becomes the generalisation 'most' (which is
reasonable).
The third argument is 8+9+10 —» 11. This is a very good example of a framing
premise (which in fact is concerned with establishing the causal relationship—see
chapter 7). Claim 10 ensures that the change in state reported in 8 and 9 does
therefore support 11. Note how, in 9, it is not saying the assault caused... (which
would be circular), rather, it is simply identifying a time period in which Michael
became depressed. The causal chain is asserted in the conclusion, 11.
The fourth argument is 4+6 —> 7. Michael is the predicate of claim 4, but
becomes the subject of claim 7 because 'victims' in claim 6 is a category to which
Michael belongs.
The fifth argument is 7+12+13+11 —» 1. Note how super-claim 12 contains
something very similar to the claim 11 in the 'i f position, and that the conclusion
1 looks very similar to the 'then' sub-claim in 12. This would be sufficient on its
own, except that the conclusion provides a specific time of imprisonment and thus
claim 7 does the work of supporting that part of the concluding claim. Had you
not included 7, it would be hard to argue why three to six months and not (say) a
year or a day!

Chapter 5
Exercise 5.1
a Some years ago, the Northern Territory passed legislation allowing some
people to commit voluntary euthanasia.
There is no explicit value judgment. The claim is only about the Northern
Territory, and some time ago, so in that respect, its scope is limited. The claim also
reports the limited scope of the legislation itself: 'some people'. Implicitly, this claim

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 163

is certain that the legislation was passed. Voluntary euthanasia sounds more clinical
than, say, 'kill themselves'; while it might appear to be a more neutral term, in fact
it probably connotes some sense that the act is more legitimate. This example should
alert us to the value judgments concealed within attempts to be value-free.

b Most religious leaders at the time, and now, claim that legislation
permitting voluntary euthanasia is immoral.
This statement proposes simply that religious leaders have claimed the legis-
lation to be immoral. As a result the claim itself (as it stands) is not necessarily
making a value judgment. However, we would have to look at the way it is used in
an argument or explanation. The scope is defined by the word 'most', with the
claim also reporting the certainty of the 'original' claim—that the legislation is
immoral—which implies a 100 per cent certainty. This claim (which is indirect) is
certain of itself. The connotation that most springs to mind is that of 'leaders':
while it certainly denotes particular people in church power structures, it perhaps
connotes some sense that we should agree with these people (they are leaders and
we should follow).
c If a state government passed voluntary euthanasia laws, then the Federal
Government would not be able to stop that legislation in the same way that
it did for the Northern Territory.
This is an 'if. . . then' statement, with a connection between a cause ('if. . . ')
and a predicted outcome of that cause (' . . . then'). Once again, there is no obvious
value judgment, but we would have to look at the way in which it is used in the
argument or explanation as a whole before being sure. This claim has been carefully
constructed with due regard for scope and certainty: note the importance of
'similar' in the first half of the claim; then consider how the word 'likely' helps to
reduce further the claim's ambit. The claim does not express a certain, but merely
a likely, consequence.
d Several terminally ill people were reported in the media at the time as saying
they were moving to the Northern Territory.
As with claim b, the claim is about some other person's claim. As such, it may
or may not imply a positive value judgment in favour of the euthanasia legislation,
depending on the context. 'Several', in the first half of the claim, helps to define the
scope. Whether or not the people do move may be uncertain (since they may not
actually have done it, how can we be sure if they will), but the claim is itself
expressed in a certain manner—they have certainly told the media making the
claim of their intention.
e I imagine that if another state or territory were to pass similar laws, then
media reporting of the legislation would be very extensive.
This is, deliberately, a trick question. It is an if/then claim again. Remember
that the T who imagines is also the T making this claim. It would be wrong to

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
164 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

interpret it as a claim about what the person has imagined; rather, the phrase 'I
imagine that' is a limitation on the certainty of the claim: the person making this
claim really does not know for sure whether or not media reporting will be very
extensive and uses that phrase to tell us so. The scope, on the other hand, is quite
broad: media implies television, radio, and newspaper. Well-formed claims do not
use confusing phrases like 'I imagine that'. Media reporting may well have con-
siderable connotative aspects, depending on who was reading the claim.

f Some politicians argued that media reporting at the time of the Northern
Territory legislation encouraged some terminally ill people to move there.

An indirect descriptive claim with no real connotations (which are however very
evident in the original claim).

Exercise 5.2
Generally speaking, I would judge that claims b, e, and f would be 'self-evident' to
a general adult audience. They would, in effect, provide or hint at their own
argument for foundation. Claim d is not self-evident because it is an explicit value
claim. Few, if any, value claims can ever be safely regarded as self-evident because
there are so many competing value systems at work in the world (and within
Australia). Claims a and c involve strong implied values that would, among some
members of the Australian population, create sufficient doubt for the claims not to
be self-evident. Finally, the main reason for regarding a single claim to be self-
evident is that all opposing claims are already disproved and/or the general knowl-
edge of the broad community is good enough to provide a convincing argument
for the claim, as, for example, in claim f.
If the idea of a 'general adult audience' posed problems for you, then that's
good! Reflect on the need to have a well-developed understanding of which claims
may or may not be regarded as self-evident.

Exercise 5.3
To support claim a, we could try a scholarly work on recent political history; alter-
natively, members of a communist (or ex-communist) country might provide support
from their experience. Personal memories might be relevant authority for claim b;
other good sources of authority would be a history book or, to be precise, the
government legislation enacted in that year that authorised the introduction of
television (see chapter 8 on direct sources). Claim c would, again, draw upon histor-
ical or political books for authority. Claim d is probably too contentious for an
authority to be widely available or accepted. Perhaps we could use a report by social,
medical, or legal experts. Claim e, on the other hand, could again be sourced from a
political or history book. Note, however, possible disagreements about the term
'main'. A doctor or a medical textbook would be two sources of authority for claim f.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 165

Exercise 5.4
a An argument to support this claim would have to address the meaning of the
word 'failed': Has communism failed communists or has it failed as a polit-
ical and economic system? Does it mean failed of its own accord or defeated
by the economic power of capitalism?
b The strongly descriptive nature of this claim probably means that using
authorities is better than using supporting reasoning for such a claim.
c Although the Australian political system could be used as evidence, such an
argument might not address the hidden implications that democracy here
refers to the daily lives of Australia's citizens (freedom, choice, individuality)
rather than the strict legal definition of the Australian political system.
d The extreme nature of this claim (relative to majority opinion) would suggest
the need for a strong supporting argument that might explain the benefits to
society (if any) of such a step.
e This is a descriptive claim; it would be better to leave it as self-evident in case
our readers become incensed that we feel the need to convince them of some-
thing so 'obvious'!
f We might recognise situations in which, even with a broken leg, immediate
medical treatment is impossible or inappropriate. Any argument would have
to take such considerations into account.
Note my advice that claims b and f do not require argument but, instead,
reference to authority. Deciding when not to reason directly for a claim is part
of the smart thinker's bag of tricks. Generally speaking, these six claims need to
be assessed, first of all, in relation to the events, situations, or decisions that they
represent. Such an assessment is the traditional objective judgment of truth: if
the 'objects' described or stated in the claim are truly represented, then the
claims are acceptable. But, it is not enough to assess in this manner when
thinking about communicating an argument or explanation. Reasoning is a
social act, which requires us to think about the contexts in which we might
provide arguments and explanations: what do others judge these claims to be?
We must reason in ways that take account of the knowledge and assumptions of
our audience, and also conform to the accepted conventions of the circum-
stances in which we are arguing or explaining. For example, an audience of
marijuana-smokers may well accept claim d without question; an audience of
young people who have 'always' had television in their lives might need the
support of some authority before accepting claim b; in an academic paper or
essay, claim e, obvious though it may be, would need to be given some explana-
tion and analysis; in a short discussion between paramedics at a motor vehicle
crash, claim f would probably be stated without the need for argument in its
favour. Finally, decisions about the extent to which we present claims as being
self-evident depend on our conclusions. In any argument or explanation, it is
the specific conclusion that can help us determine (given the inevitable limi-
tations on available time or space for reasoning) what we explain in more detail

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
166 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

and what we leave for the audience to accept or reject on their own. (See chapter
9.)

Chapter 6
Exercise 6.1
For conclusion a, one reason might be 'I want to improve my reasoning skills'. To
unpack this reason requires that you consider why reading a book on critical
thinking would help you to do this. In doing so, you address each of the issues
raised by the conclusion. For example (in the form 2+3+4 —> 1):
1. I am reading a book on reasoning.
2. I want to improve my reasoning skills.
3. I cannot improve my reasoning skills without knowing more about
reasoning.
4. A book is an excellent source of knowledge about reasoning.

For conclusion b, an initial reason might be that 'thinking better stops you from
being tricked by clever advertising'. See how many different issues are involved that
are quite distinct from the conclusion? Each must be covered in some way in the
premises, for example (in the form 2+3+4+5 —> 1):
1. There are considerable benefits to be gained from studying how to
think better.
2. I do not want to be tricked by clever advertising.
3. Clever advertising works by tricking you into buying products.
4. Thinking clearly stops you being tricked by clever advertising.
5. Studying how to think better does enable you to think clearly.

Exercise 6.2
a The premise 'there were many people waiting at the station' is irrelevant.
While trains crash for a variety of reasons (human error, sabotage, faulty
machinery, and so on), the number of people waiting at a station is rarely, if
ever, a cause of the crash. Even if the claim is true, it adds no greater
explanation to why the train crashed and thus is irrelevant.
b There are no irrelevant premises here. The second premise, concerning
competition, might seem to be irrelevant (given that the conclusion is about
privatisation); however, the first premise, with its connection between com-
petition and privatisation, makes it relevant.
c The premise 'politicians get too many benefits' is irrelevant (since there are no
further premises to make it relevant to the conclusion). Whether or not it is
true does nothing to make the conclusion more likely to be accepted. Now,
we may well wonder if there is another irrelevant premise. However, the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 167

conclusion as stated involves two elements: a question of trust (and whether


or not politicians lie obviously bears on this question) and a question of the
quality of their decisions (and politicians' knowledge is relevant to this
matter). Relevance is specifically concerned with the relationship between
premise and conclusion.

Exercise 6.3
For each of the four conclusions, here are one relevant and one irrelevant premise
(can you see which is which?):
a 'In a democracy, voting is not just a right but a civic duty' and 'Many
European swallows fly south for the winter'.
b 'Humans can only survive if the environment is well protected' and 'Mining
activities in Australia usually trespass on Aboriginal lands'.
c 'Eighty per cent of the songs on commercial radio come from the USA and
'My family watches The Simpsons every night'.
d 'Personal computers help us to work, study, and relax' and 'There are two
main types of personal computer: the PC and the Macintosh'.
The first premise, in each case, is relevant. Note how all of the premises are
acceptable, even though in some cases they are patently irrelevant (as in exercise 6.3
(a)).
The most important questions to ask yourself after doing this exercise are: Why
do some irrelevant premises appear relevant? What mistakes do we make when we
misjudge relevance? Reflect on these questions and come up with some answers in
relation to an area of knowledge or expertise with which you are familiar.

Exercise 6.4
Looking back to exercise 6.3, I would add the following claims to the premises
given above:
a If something is a duty, then it is acceptable for it to be compulsory.
b Economic development is pointless if humans do not survive,
c American songs are culturally loaded with American values and opinions.
d The help given by a personal computer is only available if you actually own a
personal computer.
Can you see here how errors in relevance are usually associated with picking the
wrong dependent framework premise? When we think that a premise is relevant to
a conclusion and, on reflection, we decide that it is not, usually we are changing
our minds about the framework premise that goes along with it.
Try changing the four premises given in these answers. If you change them
enough, can you make the original four premises from exercise 6.3 irrelevant?
For instance, in example a, if the framework premise was 'Not all duties should

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
168 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

be compulsory', the original premise ('In a democracy, voting is not just a right
but a civic duty') does not become 'false' (it remains acceptable), but it simply
is not relevant to the specific conclusion 'Voting at elections should be compul-
sory'.

Exercise 6.5
Claim 2 requires a claim such as 'We should understand what is happening now'.
In the context of a class of first-year university students (caught up in their own
concerns, and finding and discovering themselves at university), I would probably
explicitly establish this relevance, allowing me to argue for the truth of this
additional framing premise (which is in itself doubtful for these students, in my
experience) and also to show clearly the relevance of the first premise. I would not,
however, make such an explicit argument for an audience of academics who them-
selves study the contemporary world.
Claim 3 requires a claim such as 'Stories of the fight for democracy and justice
in the past can help us to maintain and improve democracy and justice in the
present' (which, one assumes, is what we want to do). In the context of writing an
article for a readership of left-wing historians, for example (a group whose pro-
fessional life involves precisely the activity that this premise describes), I would not
include this claim explicitly. For non-historians, however, I would explicitly include
it to make my argument clear.
Claim 4 requires a claim such as 'It is important to learn how to write
essays'. Professional historical researchers, although they know much about
history and, on reflection, would accept this new claim, would not, in my
experience, immediately see the relevance of claim 4 to the conclusion and would
thus need the additional claim to make the relevance explicit. In the context of
talking to high-school history teachers, however, I would probably not include
it explicitly.

Exercise 6.6
Context basically involves both audiences and knowledge. In a sense, we know
and think about audiences in terms of what they know and what they expect us
to know. We know that reasoning is about linking claims together in various
ways. We will do this in our own reasoning, but when our audience hears or
reads it, they will themselves immediately 'connect' what we have presented to
their existing knowledge. If they know something that we have not included and
make connections that run counter to our general argument, then we will fail to
convince them. If, at the moment, you are studying or working and must
regularly produce reasoning in some form, reflect on any stated, explicit require-
ments that you must meet in this presentation. Try to determine what under-
lying assumptions about reasoning these requirements express. (See also chapters
8 and 9.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 169

Exercise 6.7
a The scope and certainty involved make it a strong conclusion. However, the
particular burden of proof involved in proving this conclusion would be
affected by the audience and by its existing commitments to, and under-
standing of, the claim. Serving military officers, for whom national service
involves considerable disruption to their preferred volunteer armed forces,
would need more convincing than, say, a conservative group of older veterans
who themselves had undertaken national service.
b Words like 'one option' and 'some' limit the scope considerably and make it
a mild conclusion. Yet the burden of proof involved in proving this claim to
a group of peace activists, for whom military service would never be an appro-
priate option, would still be very high.
c This is tricky because the claim is stated with certainty but is of fairly
limited scope (not advocating service, but an inquiry). Moreover, the word
'possibility' suggests that the inquiry may not conclude that military service
should be introduced. It is strong, but only in the precise context of the
establishment of an inquiry. Note that, from the perspective of someone
who has already made up their mind that national service should be intro-
duced, a commitment to establishing an inquiry will seem like an opposing
conclusion, especially in a context in which it is often assumed that the
purpose of inquiries is simply to postpone indefinitely difficult decisions
such as this.

Chapter 7
Exercise 7.1
Here are five examples, one of each type. In each case, claim 1 is the conclusion,
and the other claims are all dependent premises in one group.

Reasoning from cause


1 Cigarette smoking is the most significant cause of lung cancer.
2 Almost all people with lung cancer have been exposed to cigarette smoke.
3 Few lung cancer sufferers show any evidence that other causes are responsible
for their disease.
Notice how the two premises establish the common element (smoking) and
also assert that no other factor is usually involved.

Reasoning from generalisation

1 Giulio is not likely to live for much longer.


2 Giulio has lung cancer.
3 Very few lung cancer patients survive their disease for more than a year.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
170 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

4 Giulio has been ill for over six months now.


Claim 3 acts as the framing premise, showing why Giulio's illness and its length
lead to the given conclusion.

Reasoning from specific cases


1 Smoking should be banned in restaurants.
2 A recent representative survey of Australians found that most of them
believed smoking should be banned in restaurants.
3 In a democratic country such as Australia, the wishes of the majority should
be implemented.
Many arguments from specific cases establish factual claims, but (with the
appropriate framing premise), they can also support an explicit value claim. Claim
2 is written as a summary of the survey subjects' views, representing the hundreds
of individual opinions expressed in that survey.

Reasoning from analogy

1 Cigarette smoking that does not harm other people should not be
banned.
2 Cigarettes and alcohol are similar in that they are addictive, potentially
disease-causing substances.
3 Society condones the drinking of alcohol as long as it does not cause harm to
other people.
4 It is good for societies to treat similar situations in a consistent manner.

The strength of this analogy depends on the similarity of drinking and


smoking in relevant respects. Claim 2 seeks to establish this similarity, while
claim 4 asserts that the similarity should be interpreted within a framework of
consistency (normally we would 'leave out' this claim—see chapter 5 on implied
premises).

Reasoning from terms


1 Cigarette smoke includes smoke inhaled both actively, from one's own
smoking, and passively, from others' cigarettes.
2 Cigarette smoke can enter the lungs actively when a person is smoking.
3 Cigarette smoke can enter the lungs passively when a person is inhaling
others' smoke.
4 Whichever way smoke enters the body, there is no qualitative difference in its
effects on the lung.
This argument establishes a particular definition of 'cigarette smoke' (which
might then be used to simplify another argument). The framework for this argu-
ment is provided by claim 4. Note that it is definitely not a causal argument: it is
simply defining some term or concept.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 171

Chapter 8
Exercise 8.1
At this stage, there is no 'answer'. However you might want to review and organise
your list after having done exercise 8.3.

Exercise 8.2
Here are two further Comments. First, learn how to 'read' effectively ('reading'
includes watching, listening, observing, and so on). The 'knowledge' we want in
those five classes will not have a label that tells us where it fits into this classification
system. Rather, it is our own analysis, while we read, that begins to make these
interconnections between classes of knowledge. Hence active reading—with a keen
awareness of the possible outcomes, the questions to be answered, the extra
questions that might emerge, and so on—is crucial.
Second, everyone is reasonably good at searching for the third of these four types
(basic details and evidence), yet smart thinking is precisely about the way that evidence
gathered in this search can be related to values, assumptions, other possible con-
clusions, and contexts. In that sense, we need to work hardest and learn most about
the other types of information. Experience and study tend to throw up great masses of
'facts', data, or evidence, and the other three types of information get 'hidden' or 'lost';
learn to read through the detail to seek out the more general types of information.

Exercise 8.3
The point of the exercise is not to come to conclusions about the 'right answer' but
to develop your conscious ability to ask questions about the sources of the
information you are seeking. In other words, to be effective reasoners, we need to
do more than ask 'What is in this book/experiment/article/interview that I can use
in my argument?'; we must also ask questions such as:

• Why should I use this source?


• Can I trust this source?
• What sort of source is it: direct? indirect?
• Under what conditions was the information in this source produced?
• What was the original purpose of the source?
• What methods, approaches, or definitions does the source employ?
• Who is it being written for?
• Does it tell me more about the author or about the topic?
• When was it written or performed?
• How does the context of this source affect the information within it?

As noted at the start of chapter 8, good analysis is as much about asking


questions as it is about finding answers. Hence, if our research is to be an active and

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
172 ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE

effective part of our analysis, we need to think about the questions that will help us
to understand our sources of information, as well as what they contain. Put simply,
these questions help to reveal what lies in and behind the text, and to orient our
research towards what we intend to do with the information once we have it.

Exercise 8.4
While we are usually more than capable of taking single claims and whole
arguments or explanations from what we read, and probably are learning the art of
coming away from research with more questions, the third and fourth categories are
tricky. Summarising an entire piece of written work does not involve noting down
individual bits and pieces ('key points', facts, main conclusions) but requires that
you understand the entirety of the work and then, in your own words, write a short
argument that sums up what the author is saying (perhaps using the analytical
structure format). Identifying the assumptions and values that underlie a text is
equally tricky and demands, at the very least, that you think carefully about the
sorts of questions covered in exercise 8.3.

Chapter 9
Exercise 9.1
The main aim of this exercise is to make you think about the following crucial
philosophical idea: how you study a topic (for example, the methods used, your
definitions and founding assumptions about the nature of that topic, the way that
the topic is 'isolated' from other possible topics, or other possible ways of studying
the topic) will always influence the results you get. We tend to think that knowl-
edge becomes objective when we put aside our personal biases, assumptions, and
beliefs, and seek the truth in a 'disinterested' manner. However, the main external
influence on our reasoning is not our emotions or subjective prejudices, but the in-
built 'bias' of the methods and theories we use. Of course, that said, many
disciplines (especially in the sciences) work from a different philosophical assump-
tion: that the methods used are 'neutral', that they have no influence on the
outcome of the research and analysis, and hence that knowledge is not intersubjec-
tive. Find out for yourself just what sort of philosophy of knowledge your
'discipline' or profession works within.

Exercise 9.2
The sorts of internal questions you might ask are, by and large, determined by the
methodological, definitive, and theoretical frameworks in which you are operating.
Moreover, because questions are always about the relationships between knowledge,
any question you ask to find out information or knowledge will be based on
something you already know. The trick to being a smart thinker is to know enough

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 173

to be able to ask the right questions, but also to be prepared continually to adjust
the questions you are asking and answering in light of the answers you come up
with.
If you want further practice, develop the 'Olympic games' example that I have
been using: begin with the claims that I have given you and expand on them.

Exercise 9.3
I will leave this one for you to work out. However, it might be worth reviewing
chapters 5 and 6, which can assist you in considering the strengths and weaknesses
of the argument. Once you know its weaknesses you can correct them; the
strengths can, perhaps, be emphasised. If you want more practice, you can keep
working through the 'Olympic games' example in a similar manner.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Glossary of Key
Terms and Concepts

These 'key terms' summarise and draw together various points and concepts
discussed in the text. Each includes a reference to the chapter in which they are first
discussed; many are generally applicable throughout the book.

analogy, reasoning from


The conclusion is established by comparing similarities between like objects in the
premises. The key questions to ask are about the similarities and differences
between the known case and the case under discussion. (See chapter 7.)

analysis
The process of thinking through the connections and interrelations between individual
'bits' of information (be they facts, values, opinions, possibilities, predictions, or what-
ever). Arguing and explaining are about communicating your considered view of these
connections (in relation to a particular topic). Analysis is the process of finding out about,
thinking through, and reflecting upon the connections in preparation for communi-
cating. Compare with analytical questions and analytical structure. (See chapter 8.)

analytical questions
Any questions designed to guide our research or reasoning by suggesting possible
relations between claims. Questions can either relate primarily to our own text or
to its connections with the surrounding context. (See chapter 8.)

analytical structure
The essential structure of claims and of the links between them, which lies behind the
narrative expression of arguments and explanations, and which can be represented as

174 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS 175

a list of claims and a diagram. The primary use of the analytical structure format is as
a planning tool before or during writing and research. (See chapter 3.)

appeal to authority
A special form of reasoning in which a claim is supported by reference to an
authority on that subject. Authority may stem from academic qualification,
experience, or special knowledge, but in each case, the authority must be relevant
to the claim being supported. References and footnotes are two of the most
common forms in which we encounter appeals to authority. Theoretically, an
appeal to authority is itself an argument that establishes the credentials of the
authority and its relevance. However, in practice, it is an accepted convention
simply to refer to the authority concerned. (See chapter 5.)

argument
Reasoning that seeks to establish the truth of a doubtful claim (which is its con-
clusion). It does not, in this context, mean a disagreement. But the process of
arguing tends to involve assertions and counter-assertions. Arguments are required
where the proposition claimed in the conclusion is in doubt or is presumed
doubtful for 'argument's sake' (as we often say). An argument is not the same as a
theme or topic: themes or topics are the broad areas of interest and investigation
within which arguments (or explanations) occur. Compare with explanation. (See
chapter 2.)

assumption
In relation to the particular structures of reasoning, any claim or link that is not
explicitly expressed can be said to be implied or assumed. These implications are
the result of our assuming that the claim or link is 'obvious'. Such assumptions
impede our ability to think clearly about the possibility that we might be wrong,
or that other connections or claims are involved. More generally, an assumption is
any unconscious or unexamined idea in the context of reasoning. Compare with
context. (See chapter 2.)

audience
In relation to reasoning, the 'audience' is that group of people who we wish to
convince of the correctness of our argument or explanation. The expectations,
understandings, and assumptions of audiences form part of the context of our
reasoning and are central to decisions about the effectiveness of that reasoning. The
audience should be thought of as consisting both of people and of the knowledge
on which those people will draw when responding to our arguments and explana-
tions. Compare with context and subject. (See chapter 2.)

breadth of reasoning
Good, effective arguments and explanations reason broadly, including a number of
alternative and distinct 'reasons'. (See chapter 6.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
176 GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS

burden of proof
In any situation involving reasoning, we can discuss the degree of support needed
for a conclusion to be acceptable in terms of the 'burden of proof on the person
presenting the argument or explanation. Burdens of proof are usually implied and
contextual. (See chapter 6.)

casting
Casting is a process of looking at someone else's argument or explanation, in the narra-
tive form, and then recovering from that form, an analytical structure which is done
best by marking claims and traces of reasoning in the text, and then drawing a diagram
to show the interlinkage of those claims. Casting is most usefully used as a way of
building your understanding of reasoning, so that you can use the analytical structure
format from scratch for your own arguments and explanations. (See chapter 3.)

cause, reasoning from


The conclusion proposes the relationship between cause and effect; the premises
give evidence about the cause or causes and show why it is that the effect relates to
that cause or causes. The key questions to ask in relation to reasoning from cause
concern similarities and differences that might reveal the cause(s). Care is needed
to avoid assuming a causal relationship when two events are simply coincidental or
are both effects of an underlying cause. (See chapter 7.)

certainty
The measurement of probability involved in a claim; an important property in
well-formed claims, useful in assessing the degree of support necessary for a partic-
ular conclusion. A conclusion and its premises are said to be 'coherent' in certainty
when there is little variation in the measure of probability that all the claims make.
The certainty component of a claim is often implicit but, in good reasoning, should
be stated explicitly. Compare with scope. (See chapter 2.)

circular reasoning
A false form of reasoning in which the premise(s) appears to be different from the
conclusion but which in fact is a restatement of that conclusion. You cannot reason
for a claim by using the same claim again. (See chapter 4.)

claim
A claim is a statement that represents some event or idea about the way the world is
or should be. It is distinguishable from other statements because, when considering a
claim, it is possible to ask 'is this statement true or false?'. In relation to value claims,
'true or false' may be better expressed as 'sound or unsound'. (See chapter 2).

complex structure
Arguments and explanations are complex when they involve more than two layers
of claims, that is, when they have premises that lead to a conclusion, and claims

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS 177

that establish the acceptability of those premises. A complex structure is built up


from a series of overlapping simple structures. (See chapter 3.)

conclusion
In general terms, a claim that is being argued for or explained by the premises. The
term 'conclusion' is only meaningful in relation to 'premise'. A conclusion can also
be a premise to a further conclusion; these overlaps in function (claim as both
premise and conclusion) can be seen in complex structures. Do not confuse with
the more common use of 'conclusion' to mean 'the last part of an essay or presen-
tation'. (See chapter 2.)

connotation
Words and statements have a denotative function (they denote or describe some-
thing), but they also carry with them varying connotations or hidden meanings
about the objects and events they denote. Connotations do not spring from a word
on its own but from the interrelations between words, and from the ways in which
words are used and understood by authors and audiences. A text will always contain
many connotations, which spring from the ways that audiences use their existing
knowledge and expectations to interpret the words in the text. Obviously, if you
and your audience share the same background or context, those connotations are
less likely to cause misunderstandings. (See chapter 2.)

consistency
In an analogy, there is always a need to assess the degree of consistency between the
like objects being compared or between the actions or ideas associated with those
objects. Often, errors in analogies stem from assumptions of consistency that are
not sustainable upon further analysis. (See chapter 7.)

context
The context in which reasoning takes place involves innumerable factors. They may
include the audience (its knowledge, expectations, beliefs, relationship to the
author of the reasoning), the conventional rules of presentation for particular
knowledge groups, the goals authors are trying to achieve by reasoning, the other
knowledge (assumptions, possible alternative arguments and explanations, and so
on) that may bear upon our reasoning. Compare with audience and assumption.
(See chapter 2.)

deduction
Deduction occurs only in those arguments where the premises implicitly outline a
logical relationship that is expressed explicitly in the conclusion and where, if one
accepts all the premises as true, one cannot then deny the conclusion. Essentially,
this form of reasoning is simply a way of moving the key moment of proof from
the final stage of the argument to the point where one is providing arguments in
support of the premises. The opposite of induction. (See chapter 7.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
178 GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS

defining premise
A claim that, when serving as a premise, functions to define some term that is
important to the whole argument. A defining premise must be used in a chain with
other premises. Compare with dependent premise. (See chapter 4.)

dependent premise
Premises are said to be dependent when they form a chain that, when taken
together, provides a reason for a conclusion. Unpacking a reason leads to the proper
development of such chains. They should be grouped together above a horizontal
line ( ) in the structure diagram. (See chapter 4.)

depth of reasoning
Arguments or explanations are deep when they explore all the subtleties of their
reasons (unpacked into chains of dependent premises, possibly with further
support for each of these premises). (See chapter 6.)

descriptive claim
A claim that describes without judging what is good or bad about the object being
described. Descriptive claims that are completely free of value judgment are few in
number because of the way in which all words, when written and read in context,
can imply certain values. Values are often a significant aspect of the connotation
that accompanies the obvious meanings of words or claims. Compare with value
claim. (See chapter 2.)

effective reasoning
Effective reasoning does not necessarily guarantee that our conclusions will be
proven correct or that the explanation for them will be accurate. However,
consciously thinking about making our arguments and explanations more effective,
first, provides us with a mental framework for better analysis and, second, ensures
that, when we communicate with others, our reasoning is as convincing as it can
be. (See chapters 5 and 6.)

exclamation
A statement that is exclaimed (that is, expressed with surprise or emotion). Many
exclamations do not make statements that can be assessed as true or false, or as reason-
able or unreasonable. Hence, many exclamations are not claims. (See chapter 2.)

explanation
A type of reasoning that seeks to explain, by means of premises, why a particular
circumstance or idea has come about. (This idea or circumstance is reported in the
conclusion.) Compare with argument. (See chapter 2.)

framing premise
A claim that, when serving as a premise, functions to establish why it is that the

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS 179

other premise(s) supports the conclusion. A framing premise must be used in a


chain with other premises. Compare with dependent premise. (See chapter 4.)

generalisation, reasoning from


The conclusion is about a specific case; the premises show that the case fits some
general category, and they state the particular property or consequence that pertains
to all members of the general category. The key questions to ask about a particular
case are: Does it fit this generalisation? And, if so, what general knowledge thereby
applies to this case? (See chapter 7.)

implied premise
A premise not explicitly stated in an argument or explanation that, nevertheless,
can be inferred by a reader as being necessary to make sense of the reasoning.
Implied premises are often associated with the use of apparently independent prem-
ises. Compare with assumption. (See chapter 5.)

independent premise
A single premise that expresses a reason for a conclusion on its own. An inde-
pendent premise is likely to be a sign that there are implied dependent premises.
(See chapter 4.)

induction
Reasoning in which the conclusion may be more or less likely if the premises are
true but which is not conclusively guaranteed even if all the premises are true. We
see induction in arguments that depend on the observation and reporting of real-
world events which, by their nature, can never be certain. The opposite of deduc-
tion. (See chapter 7.)

information
Information is often thought to be a more disorganised, unprocessed version of
knowledge. Information is a collection of claims; knowledge is that informa-
tion processed and interrelated. In this book, knowledge and information are
used interchangeably, but the basic idea that reasoning enables us to organise
what we know is still important. Compare with knowledge. (See chapters 8 and
9.)

internal connection (within a claim)


The key property of claims that allows them to be used in reasoning to express
complex ideas. Internal connections provide the basis for the external links between
claims. Compare with dependent premise. (See chapter 2.)

intersubjective
Knowledge is said to be intersubjective when the decisions about the 'truth' of
claims and claim relationships are made by 'subjects' (that is, people)—in this case

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
180 GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS

the authors and audiences of reasoning. Compare with objective and subject. (See
chapter 9.)

knowledge
Knowledge (which we might also call information) is the 'stuff of reasoning.
Knowledge is always relational. First, knowledge is about claims and the links
between them. Second, knowledge is created and maintained intersubjectively, that
is, between audiences and authors. Classes of knowledge and types of information
(see chapter 8) are ways of thinking about the generic relations of knowledge to our
particular topic when researching. Compare with objective. (See chapters 8 and 9.)

link words
The traces to be found in natural language of the mental processes of reasoning;
a useful but unreliable guide to the exact connections between claims. (See
chapter 3.)

list of claims
One half of the analytical structure format. A list of claims shows clearly the claims
to which the diagram of interrelationships refers. Compare with structure diagram.
(See chapter 3.)

mind-map
A tool that assists in analysing connections, concepts, and so on. A mind-map is
not an analytical structure format because the ideas and links are written down in
a tentative way, simply as a way of 'externalising' unprocessed information. (See
chapter 9.)

modes of analysis
Direct analysis concerns, as much as possible, the particular topic of an argument
or explanation. Indirect analysis concerns what others think and write about that
topic. Hypothetical analysis involves the explicit consideration of possible (rather
than actual) situations and the open discussion of assumptions. All three modes are
interrelated and are usually used in concert. For example, if I were to discuss the
way people write about reasoning, that would be direct; if I then considered philo-
sophical arguments about the way people write about reasoning, that would be
indirect. Compare with source. (See chapter 5.)

narrative flow
The written or spoken expression of reasoning in which the analytical structure is
turned into natural language. In narrative flow, we find traces of the linking
process, as well as claims that have been reorganised to meet the requirements of
good expression. As a result, it can be hard to see what is going on in reasoning
unless we also think about the analytical structure that lies behind the narrative.
Compare with analytical structure. (See chapter 3.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS 181

narrative sequence plan


A plan for writing or presenting in which ideas are listed in the same order that they
will appear on the written page or in the presentation. The links between the ideas
are, thus, indications of the flow (rather than the analytical structure). Such a plan
is useful because it 'externalises' the order in a way that allows you to check it and
revise it. (See chapter 9.)

objective
Some philosophers regard knowledge and judgments as objective when they appear
to relate solely to the object that they make claims about (which may be a thing,
event, circumstance, or whatever). An objective claim is usually considered to be a
'true' claim. Other philosophers argue that no claim can ever be solely about the
object since language is an intersubjective medium, full of connotations and hidden
implications, which make it impossible to be objective. According to this view, the
'truth' of claims is settled intersubjectively, through a complex process of social
interaction that draws in part on objective knowledge but is different from it.
Compare with knowledge. (See chapter 9.)

order
A type of statement that is not a claim but that demands obedience from its audi-
ence. (See chapter 2.)

premise
In general terms, a claim that is used to argue for or explain another claim (the
conclusion). The term 'premise' is only meaningful in relation to a conclusion. (See
chapter 2.)

propositional logic
Occurs when an if/then statement (or its differently worded equivalent) is used to
propose, in the premises, a relationship between two states of affairs, or events, or
matters; normally the other premise in such arguments is the 'if component of the
proposition, permitting the 'then' component to be the conclusion. Often associ-
ated with deductive reasoning. (See chapter 7.)

purposes of reasoning
The purposes of reasoning are what arguments and explanations seek to achieve.
Arguments predict future events, establish what is or was the case, or show why a
certain action should occur. Explanations explain why something happened or is
happening, or they justify why someone did something. (See chapter 2.)

question
A type of statement that is not a claim but that genuinely seeks information. A
question can imply some relationship. Compare with analytical questions. (See
chapter 2.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
182 GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS

reason
Used loosely, tliis term describes the information that supports or explains a particular
conclusion. As used in this book, a 'reason is an initial statement of why a particular
conclusion is acceptable—a reason that must then be 'unpacked' or expanded into a
chain of premises in order to give appropriate depth to our reasoning. (See chapter 4.)

relativism
A short-hand term for the idea that knowledge is not to be judged 'true or false' by
comparing it to the real world, but instead by reference to the humans who hold
that knowledge. Extreme relativism, in which 'everyone's opinion is as good as
anyone else's opinion' (subjective knowledge), is the opposite of the anti-relativist
position of objective knowledge. In neither case is the social aspect of reasoning
properly thought through. Smart thinking is primarily concerned with social rela-
tivism, in which knowledge is constructed intersubjectively. Compare with inter-
subjective and knowledge. (See chapter 9; see also chapter 1.)

relevance
Premises are relevant to a conclusion if they provide some basis on which to accept
that conclusion. We can say that, if true, a relevant premise makes the conclusion
more likely. Relevance is involved in reasoning in many ways. For example, appeals
to authority require the use of relevant authorities; reasoning from analogy requires
that comparisons be made between relevantly similar cases; reasoning from gener-
alisation requires that the relevance of the generalisation to the specific case be
established. Crucially, a framing premise is often used explicitly to establish just
how premises relate to a conclusion. (See chapter 6.)

scope
The extent or coverage of a claim; an important property in terms of writing well-
formed claims and assessing the degree of support necessary for a particular conclu-
sion. A conclusion and its premises are said to be 'coherent' in scope when there is
little variation in the way that the claims report the extent of their information. The
scope component of a claim is often implicit but, in good reasoning, should be
stated explicitly. Compare with certainty. (See chapter 2.)

self-evident claim
A self-evident claim is one that, relative to the audience and context in which it is
presented, requires no foundation or, literally, is so obviously acceptable that it
provides its own evidence of acceptability. What is self-evident for one group or
individual, or in one context, may not be self-evident in other situations. Compare
with well-founded claim. (See chapter 5.)

simple structure
An argument or explanation is said to be simple when it involves only two layers of
claims: the premises and the conclusion. No matter how many premises are offered,

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS 183

no matter how many distinct groups of dependent premises there are, such argu-
ments are not complex. Compare with complex structure. (See chapter 3.)

source
Sources can be either direct (primary) or indirect (secondary). The difference
between them is usually contextual, but generally speaking, direct sources relate to
the topic of our reasoning; indirect sources relate to what others have reasoned
about our topic. Obviously, if the topic of our argument or explanation is what
others have written or said, then what appears to be an indirect source can in fact
be direct. (See chapter 8.)

specific cases, reasoning from


The conclusion generalises beyond the scope of the specific cases in the premises;
the premises give the evidence regarding those cases. The key question to ask is: do
these cases give rise to some reliable generalisation that applies to all of them or all
like cases? (See chapter 7.)

statement
The generic name for an ordered, meaningful group of words. Statements may or
may not be claims. A statement is not a sentence: 'sentence' is a term used to
describe the narrative flow of words; statement is a term to denote the analytical
units that make up reasoning. Compare with claim. (See chapter 2.)

strength of support
Even acceptable and relevant premises do not always provide sufficient support to
show or explain their conclusions. Judgments of the necessary strength of support
needed in reasoning are difficult, since they depend largely on the context in which
that reasoning is taking place. Compare with burden of proof. (See chapter 6.)

structure diagram
One half of the analytical structure format. A structure diagram shows the inter-
relationship of claims in a standardised way. It is distinguished from the arrangement
of claims in narrative flow by the fact that, in a diagram, the conclusion is always last
and the order of claims above it indicates the 'steps' we need to take to reach that
conclusion from our starting point. The key elements are the [<l] symbol, to show
premise-conclusion links; the + symbol, to show premise-premise links; and the use
of horizontal lines ( ), to show grouped chains of premises. (See chapter 3.)

sub-argument
Any one component layer of a complex argument. For example, consider an
argument structure in which claims 2 and 3 support claim 4, which in turn joins
with claim 5 to support the conclusion—claim 1. The main argument concerns
claim 1 and so the sub-argument consists in the structure 2+3 [-1] 4. (See
chapter 3.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
184 GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS

subject
The term 'subject' is used in many different ways in English. Used loosely, it can
mean the topic one is investigating, as in 'the subject of my paper is the continued
inequalities of patriarchal culture'. In grammar, 'subject' refers to the part of a
sentence with which the verb agrees: 'domestic violence [subject] remains rife in our
society [object]'. However, in this book, subject is used to refer to a thinking,
conscious person (so that authors and audiences of reasoning are 'human subjects').
Its meaning only becomes clear in relation to the term 'object'—those events, ideas,
things in the world about which we (as subjects) make claims. For example, some
philosophers might argue that the difference between 'subjective' and 'objective'
analysis is that the former involves the desires and biases of the subject doing the
analysis, whereas the latter is uninfluenced, except by the true nature of the object.
However, it can also be argued that knowledge and reasoning (whatever their
objective elements) always involve people and so can be regarded as 'inter-
subjective'. The human subjects bringing about this intersubjectivity are not merely
'people' but include the knowledge, ideas, structures, and attitudes that make those
people who they are. (See chapters 2 and 9.)

sweeping generalisation
A mistake in reasoning that occurs when the scope or certainty of the conclusion is
inconsistent with (normally much greater than) the scope or certainty of the
premises that support it. (See chapter 4.)

terms, reasoning from


The conclusion proposes a particular définition based on the terms laid out in the
premises. The key question is: how can I express my definition in terms that make
clear its meaning in a particular context? (See chapter 7.)

text
We call any connected series of statements a text. Texts are only meaningful in
context, which is literally all the potential knowledge and audiences that go along
with a text. Compare with context. (See chapter 2.)

value claim
Many claims have a value component. Some are explicit; others are implicit, buried
in the particular choice of words. Often a claim that is (in itself) descriptive takes
on a value element from other claims to which it is connected. Remember, too, that
in such situations different authors and audiences can invest the same claim with
different values. Compare with descriptive claim. (See chapter 2.)

well-formed claim
A claim is well formed when it clearly expresses what its author intends it to say.
Good formation of claims requires authors to consider consciously properties of
connections and issues of value, scope, and certainty. A well-formed claim may or

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GLOSSARY OF KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS 185

may not be true, but at least its clarity allows us to assess its truth. While, no matter
how hard we try, we can never be sure our audience will always understand exactly
what we mean, writing well-formed claims ensures that at least we know what we
are trying to say. Compare with connotation. (See chapter 5.)

well-founded claim
A claim is well founded if, relative to the audience and context in which it is
presented, it is likely to be accepted as true. Well-founded claims often depend on
appeals to authority or a complete argument or explanation to ensure that their
truth is less open to doubt. Compare with self-evident claim. (See chapter 5.)

word
The basic unit from which we construct statements. Words are only meaningful in
relation to other words. Compare with connotation. (See chapter 2.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Further Reading
Further reading on knowledge and philosophy
Doyal, Len and Harris, Ken, Empiricism, Explanation and Rationality in the Social
Sciences, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1986.
A very comprehensive treatment of the topic. The authors' main argument is
that naive empiricism (that is, the belief that facts are facts and we find them) is
wrong because all 'facts' are interpretive claims based in political and/or social
circumstances.
Gaarder, Jostein, Sophies World: A Novel about the History of Philosophy, Phoenix
House, London, 1995.
A story about a teenage girl who is drawn into a mystery that involves an unseen
philosophy teacher who sends her short commentaries on philosophy. The plot is
excellent, and the philosophy 'lessons' are not bad either.
Gellner, Ernest, Reason and Culture, Blackwell, Oxford, 1992.
A broad-brush history of the development of modern 'Reason', pointing to the ways
in which knowledge and knowledge systems (such as reasoning) are non-objective.
Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago
Press, Chicago, 1970.
A revolutionary book in itself. It argues for the centrality of non-objective theo-
retical paradigms and for the cultural practices of scientists in determining 'facts'.
Lloyd, Genevieve, The Man of Reason, Methuen, London, 1984.
Much Western philosophy (the basis of this book) is gender-biased, both in its
practical exclusion of women and also in its founding ideas. Lloyd gives a very
readable account of the ways in which the social context of patriarchy (men in
charge) has influenced the 'objective' ideas of philosophy.
McCarthy, E. Doyle, Knowledge as Culture: The New Sociology ofKnowledge,
Routledge, London, 1996.

186 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
FURTHER READING 187

Excellent introduction to, and then extended discussion of, the way that social
and cultural theorists have developed more sophisticated understandings of
'knowledge' as a product of social and cultural forces in the past fifty years.
Morton, Adam, Philosophy in Practice, Blackwell, Oxford, 1996.
Covers many issues relating to both epistemology and other aspects of philos-
ophy (such as identity, ethics, and so on); particularly useful for its discussions of
certainty and doubt.
Schirato, Tony and Yell, Susan, Communication and Culture: An Introduction,
Sage, London, 2000.
A very comprehensive treatment of the way meaning is generated by context,
intertextuality, and discourse within culture and society. This book, unlike many
critical thinking texts, is grounded in the insights of post-structuralist
philosophy and will significantly assist your understanding of the way 'objective'
truth is a construct of social processes as much as it is a property of objects in
the world.
Stefik, Mark, Internet Dreams: Archetypes, Myths, and Metaphors, MIT Press,
Cambridge, Mass., 1996.
An eclectic collection of primary and secondary analysis of the early days of the
Internet. Used here for the work of Licklider but an interesting commentary on
why technologies of information and communication do not substitute for
reasoning in our search for information.

Further reading on reasoning

Bowell, Tracy and Kemp, Gary, Critical Thinking: A Concise Guide, Routledge,
London, 2002.
Alternative book to the larger reasoning textbooks listed below: good concise
explanations and advice.
Browne, M. Neil and Keeley, Stuart M., Asking the Right Questions: A Guide to
Critical Thinking, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 2003 (7th edn).
An excellent book that organises its ideas around the key concept of analytical
questioning, which I deploy in chapters 8 and 9.
Cederblom, Jerry and Paulsen, David W., Critical Reasoning, Wadsworth,
Belmont, CA, 2000 (5th edn).
A large reasoning textbook that contains an excellent discussion of the problems
and advantages of relying on experts and authorities.

Dowden, Bradley H., logical Reasoning, Wadsworth, Belmont, CA, 1998.


Another textbook with a particularly good chapter on explanations and on
causal reasoning.
Little, J. Frederick, Groarke, Leo A., and Tindale, Christopher W., Good

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
188 FURTHER READING

Reasoning Matters! A Constructive Approach to Critical Thinking, McClelland


& Stewart, Toronto, 1989.
This book was, in part, responsible for my emphasis on writing arguments and
explanations, rather than analysing them. Its advice on writing good arguments is
particularly helpful.

Makau, Josina M., Reasoning and Communication: Thinking Critically about


Arguments, Wadsworth, Belmont, CA, 1990.
A shorter work, with less emphasis on methods (such as casting). It is particu-
larly useful for its discussion of the contexts in which argumentation takes place; a
new edition was published in 1998.
Nickerson, Raymond S., Reflections On Reasoning, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale,
NJ, 1986.
This book provides some very revealing insights into the processes of teaching
and learning the skills of reasoning.
Rudinow, Joel and Barry, Vincent, Invitation to Critical Thinking, Wadsworth,
Belmont, CA, 2003 (5th edn).
Contains an excellent section on casting and a comprehensive discussion of the
generic errors that people make in reasoning.
Ruggiero, Vincent Ryan, Beyond Feelings: A Guide to Critical Thinking, Mayfield,
Mountainview, CA, 1984.
A much republished book that provides simple, common-sense advice on many
issues related to reasoning; it also provides an excellent example of how the failure
to consider contextual issues can render much of this advice impractical.
Ruggiero, Vincent Ryan, The Art of Thinking: A Guide to Critical and Creative
Thought, Pearson Longman, 2000 (6th edn).
More up-to-date work by Ruggiero that expands on the original guide in a more
'textbook' manner. Of value is the focus the author places on personal change and
commitment to critical thinking, instead of simple technique.

Rybacki, Karyn C. and Rybacki, Donald J., Advocacy and Opposition: An


Introduction to Argumentation, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1986.
This work gives considerable advice on the process of proving particular types
of conclusions and inspired my approach in chapter 8.
Toulmin, Stephen, The Uses of Argument, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 2003.
Most recent book by Toulmin, one of the most influential analysts of critical
thinking and argumentation.
Toulmin, Stephen, Rieke, Richard, and Janik, Allan, An Introduction to Reasoning,
Macmillan, New York, 1984.
An excellent, thorough critical thinking textbook, with a particular emphasis on
the different ways in which premises and premise-like statements combine to

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
FURTHER READING 189

demonstrate a conclusion. My concept of 'framing premises' was developed from


Toulmin's much more complex discussion of the 'warrants' and 'backgrounds' that
are involved in argumentation. This book is useful, also, for its recognition of the
need for a contextualised approach to critical thinking.
Waller, Bruce N., Critical Thinking: Consider your Verdict, Prentice-Hall,
Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 2000 (4th edn).
Although this book concentrates on the role of critical thinking in the decisions
made by juries (and thus draws most of its examples from the legal context), it
provides particularly sensible discussions of relevance and assumptions.

Further reading on writing and communicating


Hay, Iain, Bochner, Diane, and Dungey, Carol, Making the Grade, OUP,
Melbourne, 2002.
Wide-ranging and up-to-date advice on study skills, including assistance with
writing and communicating.
Murphy, Eamon, You Can Write: A Do-it-YourselfManual, Longman, Melbourne,
1985.
Excellent advice on writing and the use of plans; still useful twenty years after
publication because of its clear tone and style.
Summers, Jane and Brett Smith (eds), Communication Skills Handbook: How to
Succeed in Written and Oral Communication, Milton, Qld, John Wiley, 2002.
Covers many different aspects of communication, with a particular emphasis on
business communication.

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
Guide to Important Skills
Use the following questions and answers as an index to specific advice in Smart
Thinking on the key skills of reasoning. They are designed to help you 'get back
into' the book after you have read it thoroughly for the first time; they also provide
a basic summary of what Smart Thinking can do to 'smarten up' your own thinking.
These questions provide a connection between the skills discussed in this book and
the most common concerns that people have when faced with the task of writing
an essay or report, or preparing an oral presentation. In other words, these ques-
tions show you how to understand and apply smart-thinking skills in practical
contexts.
Each question is answered in brief, and then page references are given to direct
you to the detailed advice necessary for you to answer the question for yourself. The
guide is divided into two sections. The first contains questions that are more
general and that are expressed without mentioning specific concepts from the book
(the answers then give those concepts); the key issue in each of these questions is
presented in bold type. The second section contains questions that guide you
towards specific concepts that are mentioned in the book (in bold). If you have not
yet read Smart Thinking through thoroughly, you should begin with the first
section.

General questions
How can I think through complex ideas so that I have a good under-
standing of them?
Ask questions, do not be satisfied with easy answers, and do not make assumptions
about what things mean. (See pp 83-6, 105-7, 124-8.)

What do I need to do to be convincing in my reports, essays, and presen-


tations?
Make sure you have a good analytical structure and have a strong argument or
explanation. (See pp 81-6, 121-8.)

190 https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GUIDE TO IMPORTANT SKILLS 191

How do I make my reasoning easy to follow for people reading or listening


to my arguments and explanations?
Make sure that you properly indicate the reasoned links you are making, signalling
the analytical structure to your audience. (See pp 27-9.)

Why, and how, should I use footnotes or other references in my work?


They provide references to authority, which strengthen the substance of your
reasoning. (See pp 65-7, 78-9.)

What should be the goal of my reasoning?


Reasoning has many purposes, each of which will affect the precise way that you
argue or explain. (See pp 4, 21—2, 124-5.)

When writing or presenting, how do I deal with ideas with which I do not
agree?
Make sure you use reasoning to show explicitly why an idea is wrong, thereby
preventing criticism of your work. (See pp 85-6, 112-13.)

How do I make sure that I understand the interpretive frameworks that


are central to all knowledge?
In your thinking, you need to distinguish between 'facts' and the way that they can
be understood as relating to other 'facts'; in your writing, make sure that you use
framing premises. (See pp 5-6, 45-6, 78, 111-13.)

What are the two key components of a good argument or explanation?


You need premises (reasons, evidence) to support your conclusion (a clear state-
ment of what you are arguing for or explaining). (See pp 19-22, 32-6.)

How can I distinguish between my ideas and what I am saying about


others' ideas in my essays and presentations?
Clearly distinguish between when you are arguing directly and when you are
arguing indirectly. (See pp 57-60, 112-16.)

What is wrong with giving just one reason for my conclusion?


Your arguments will not have enough breadth and will not address all the issues
that your audience is expecting you to consider. (See pp 4 4 - 5 , 71-4.)

How can I be more effective in doing research and reading before I write?
Ask questions, and understand the relationship between your sources and your own
essay, presentation, or report. (See pp 107-13.)

How can I assess someone else's reasoning to see if they have presented
a good argument or explanation?
You can 'cast' their work into claims and a structure diagram. (See pp 12-15, 32-7.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
192 GUIDE TO IMPORTANT SKILLS

Specific questions
How do I use analogies?
By comparing items and drawing conclusions based on their similarities. (See
pp 99-100.)

How do I avoid making assumptions in my essays, presentations, and


reports?
Do not take the truth of a claim—or its relationship with other claims—for
granted; stop and think about what your audiences expect you to do and what they
already know. (See pp 7, 1 1 - 1 2 , 73-4, 122-7.)

How can I begin to understand the audiences of my arguments and


explanations?
Regard your audiences as having certain expectations about what you should say to
them and how you should say it, as well as certain background knowledge that
directly affects your reasoning. (See pp 63-4, 73-4, 81-6, 122-7.)

What is casting?
Casting is a process of recovering the analytical structure from another author's
narrative. (See pp 3 2 - 4 , 135-49.)

How do I write about causes and effects?


Reasoning from cause requires you to use premises that state the cause(s) of an
effect that is expressed in the conclusion. (See pp 95—6, 110.)

What do I need to know about claims in order to use them effectively in


planning my reports, essays, and presentations?
You must attend to their key properties and express them precisely. (See pp 11-14,
57-61, 86-7.)

How do I plan complex argument structures?


A complex argument structure is just a series of overlapping, intertwined simple
arguments. (See pp 36-8, 53-4, 65-8, 71-4.)

Why is context so important in reasoning effectively?


No argument or explanation (text) is ever written or read in isolation: background
(or context)—which includes the expectations, assumptions, and implied
concepts of both author and audience—always affects the text. (See pp 1 1 - 1 2 ,
81-6, 122-4.)

How do I go about using definitions in my work?


Make sure that your definitions are clear and are integrated in the main structure
of your reasoning. (See pp 47-8, 57-8, 100.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books
GUIDE TO IMPORTANT SKILLS 193

How do I make sure that my essays and presentations go into enough


depth to be convincing?
Make sure that you expand the reasons for your conclusion so that they are com-
prehensive and form a chain of dependent premises. (See pp 40—5, 71—4.)

How are knowledge and reasoning connected?


They are two aspects of the same whole: knowledge is expressed and learnt as
reasoning; reasoning utilises and relies on knowledge. (See pp 104-6, 109—13.)

How would I define reasoning, and what can it do for me?


Reasoning is about the relationships between ideas and events; using it helps you
to think smart and communicate effectively. (See pp 1-9.)

How can I make sure that I am being relevant?


Make sure that your premises really do say something that supports your conclu-
sion and that your audience understands this connection. (See pp 75-80.)

What do I need to know if I want to use specific cases and general rules
in my arguments?
You need to understand the way in which general conclusions can flow from
specific cases and how general rules provide the framework for establishing specific
conclusions. (See pp 96-9, 108.)

How can I improve the structure and logic of my essays, reports, and
presentations?
Use the analytical structure format to plan your work before you begin writing. (See
pp 34-6, 128-32.)

Why is the truth (or falsity) of claims so important?


All arguments and explanations are designed to establish the truth of one claim on
the basis of other true claims. (See pp 1 2 - 1 3 , 61-7.)

https://books.yossr.com/en/books

You might also like