The Will to Power
5/5
()
About this ebook
Down through the Nazi period The Will to Power was often mistakenly considered to be Nietzsche's crowning systematic labor; since World War II it has frequently been denigrated, just as fallaciously, as being not worth reading. In fact, it represents a stunning selection from Nietzsche's notebooks, in a topical arrangement that enables the reader to find what Nietzsche wrote on nihilism, art, morality, religion, the theory of knowledge, and whatever else interested him.
But no previous edition - even in the original German - shows which notes Nietzsche utilized subsequently in his works, and which sections are not paralleled in the finished books. Nor has any previous edition furnished a commentary or index.
Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche (15. Oktober 1844 in Röcken -25. August 1900) war ein deutscher klassischer Sprachwissenschaftler und Philosoph. Am bekanntesten (und berüchtigtsten) sind seine Kritiken an Moral und Religion. Sein Werk wurde und wird häufig fehlinterpretiert und missbraucht. Er wird in regelmäßigen Abständen von Wissenschaft und Popkultur wiederentdeckt und als Enfant terrible einer oberflächlichen Zitatenkultur geschätzt: „Wenn du zum Weibe gehst, vergiss die Peitsche nicht!“
Read more from Friedrich Nietzsche
The Will to Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On Truth & Untruth Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On the Genealogy of Morals Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Geneology of Morals: With linked Table of Contents Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Quotable Nietzsche Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Portable Nietzsche (Portable Library) Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5THUS SPOKE ZARATHUSTRA - A Book for All and None (World Classics Series): Philosophical Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Thus Spake Zarathustra: Bilingual Edition (English – German) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Related to The Will to Power
Titles in the series (2)
The Will to Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Will to Power Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Related ebooks
The Genealogy of Morals Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Joyful Wisdom Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Human, All Too Human Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Antichrist Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Gay Science Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THUS SPOKE ZARATHUSTRA - A Book for All and None (World Classics Series): Philosophical Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Birth of Tragedy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Thus Spoke Zarathustra Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Dawn of Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ecce Homo Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche: The Complete Works Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTwilight of the Idols Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Demons Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Demons, the Possessed or the the Devils Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Brothers Karamazov Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The World as Will and Idea - Vol. I. Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Twilight of the Idols and The Antichrist Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Treatise On Human Nature Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Human, All Too Human: A Book For Free Spirits Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Notes From The Underground Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Emotions: Outline of a Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Idiot Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Wisdom of Life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Weak Heart Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMeno Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The World as Will and Representation Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Philosophy For You
Humankind: A Hopeful History Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Discipline Is Destiny: A NEW YORK TIMES BESTSELLER Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Burnout Society Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Courage To Be Disliked: A single book can change your life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Daily Laws: 366 Meditations from the author of the bestselling The 48 Laws of Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Lessons of History Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative? Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5On the shortness of life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Kama Sutra of Vatsyayana (Illustrated) Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Why Buddhism is True: The Science and Philosophy of Meditation and Enlightenment Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Courage Is Calling: Fortune Favours the Brave Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5I May Be Wrong: The Sunday Times Bestseller Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Being Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Denial of Death Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ikigai: The Japanese Secret Philosophy for a Happy Healthy Long Life With Joy and Purpose Every Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Utopia for Realists: And How We Can Get There Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Finite and Infinite Games Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Practical Stoicism: Your Action Guide On How To Implement The Stoic Philosophy Into Your Own Life Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Communicating Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Stoicism: Timeless Wisdom to Gain Resilience, Confidence, and Calmness Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Focus on What Matters: A Collection of Stoic Letters on Living Well Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Courage to be Happy: True Contentment Is Within Your Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for The Will to Power
1 rating0 reviews
Book preview
The Will to Power - Friedrich Nietzsche
The Will to Power
Pages de titre
THIRD BOOK
I.
II.
III
IV.
FOURTH BOOK
I.
II. - 1
III. - 1
Copyright
THE WILL TO POWER
AN ATTEMPTED
TRANSVALUATION OF ALL VALUES
By
FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
VOL. II
BOOKS III AND IV
THIRD BOOK
THE PRINCIPLES OF A NEW VALUATION.
I.
THE WILL TO POWER IN SCIENCE.
(a) The Method of Investigation.
466.
The distinguishing feature of our nineteenth century is not the triumph of science, but the triumph of the scientific method over science.
467.
The history of scientific methods was regarded by Auguste Comte almost as philosophy itself.
468.
The great Methodologists: Aristotle, Bacon, Descartes, Auguste Comte.
469.
The most valuable knowledge is always discovered last: but the most valuable knowledge consists of methods.
All methods, all the hypotheses on which the science of our day depends, were treated with the profoundest contempt for centuries: on their account a man used to be banished from the society of respectable people—he was held to be an enemy of God,
a reviler of the highest ideal, a madman.
We had the whole pathos of mankind against us,—our notion of what truth
ought to be, of what the service of truth ought to be, our objectivity, our method, our calm, cautious and distrustful manner were altogether despicable.... At bottom, that which has kept men back most, is an æsthetic taste: they believed in the picturesque effect of truth; what they demanded of the scientist was, that he should make a strong appeal to their imagination.
From the above, it would almost seem as if the very reverse had been achieved, as if a sudden jump had been made: as a matter of fact, the schooling which the moral hyperboles afforded, gradually prepared the way for that milder form of pathos which at last became incarnate in the scientific man....
Conscientiousness in small things, the self-control of the religious man, was a preparatory school for the scientific character, as was also, in a very pre-eminent sense, the attitude of mind which makes a man take problems seriously, irrespective of what personal advantage he may derive from them....
(b) The Starting-point of Epistemology.>
470.
Profound disinclination to halt once and for all at any collective view of the world. The charm of the opposite point of view: the refusal to relinquish the stimulus residing in the enigmatical.
471.
The hypothesis that, at bottom, things proceed in such a moral fashion that human reason must be right, is a mere piece of good-natured and simple-minded trustfulness, the result of the belief in Divine truthfulness—God regarded as the Creator of all things.—These concepts are our inheritance from a former existence in a Beyond.
472.
The contradiction of the so-called facts of consciousness.
Observation a thousand times more difficult, error is perhaps the absolute condition of observation.
473.
The intellect cannot criticise itself, simply because it can be compared with no other kind of intellect, and also because its ability to know would only reveal itself in the presence of actual reality
; that is to say, because, in order to criticise the intellect, we should have to be higher creatures with absolute knowledge.
This would presuppose the existence of something, a thing-in-itself,
apart from all the perspective kinds of observation and senso-spiritual perception. But the psychological origin of the belief in things, forbids our speaking of things in themselves.
474.
The idea that a sort of adequate relation exists between subject and object, that the object is something which when seen from inside would be a subject, is a well-meant invention which, I believe, has seen its best days. The measure of that which we are conscious of, is perforce entirely dependent upon the coarse utility of the function of consciousness: how could this little garret-prospect of consciousness warrant our asserting anything in regard to subject
and object,
which would bear any relation to reality!
475.
Criticism of modern philosophy: erroneous starting-point, as if there were such things as facts of consciousness
—and no phenomenalism in introspection.
476.
Consciousness
—to what extent is the idea which is thought of, the idea of will, or the idea of a feeling (which is known by us alone), quite superficial? Our inner world is also appearance.
477.
I am convinced of the phenomenalism of the inner world also: everything that reaches our consciousness is utterly and completely adjusted, simplified, schematised, interpreted, the actual process of inner perception,
the relation of causes between thoughts, feelings, desires, between subject and object, is absolutely concealed from us, and may be purely imaginary. This inner world of appearance
is treated with precisely the same forms and procedures as the outer
world. We never come across a single fact
: pleasure and pain are more recently evolved intellectual phenomena....
Causality evades us; to assume the existence of an immediate causal relation between thoughts, as Logic does, is the result of the coarsest and most clumsy observation. There are all sorts of passions that may intervene between two thoughts: but the interaction is too rapid—that is why we fail to recognise them, that is why we actually deny their existence....
Thinking,
as the epistemologists understand \r it, never takes place at all: it is an absolutely gratuitous fabrication, arrived at by selecting one element from the process and by eliminating all the rest—an artificial adjustment for the purpose of the understanding....
The mind,
something that thinks: at times, even, the mind absolute and pure
—this concept is an evolved and second result of false introspection, which believes in thinking
: in the first place an act is imagined here which does not really occur at all, i.e. thinking
; and, secondly, a subject-substratum is imagined in which every process of this thinking has its origin, and nothing else—that is to say, both the action and the agent are fanciful.
478.
Phenomenalism must not be sought in the wrong quarter: nothing is more phenomenal, or, to be more precise, nothing is so much deception, as this inner world, which we observe with the inner sense.
Our belief that the will is a cause was so great, that, according to our personal experiences in general, we projected a cause into all phenomena (i.e. a certain motive is posited as the cause of all phenomena).
We believe that the thoughts which follow one upon the other in our minds are linked by some sort of causal relation: the logician, more especially, who actually speaks of a host of facts which have never once been seen in reality, has grown accustomed to the prejudice that thoughts are the cause of thoughts.
We believe—and even our philosophers believe it still—that pleasure and pain are the causes of reactions, that the very purpose of pleasure and pain is to occasion reactions. For hundreds of years, pleasure and pain have been represented as the motives for every action. Upon reflection, however, we are bound to concede that everything would have proceeded in exactly the same way, according to precisely the same sequence of cause and effect, if the states pleasure
and pain
had been entirely absent; and that we are simply deceived when we believe that they actually cause anything:—they are the attendant phenomena, and they have quite a different purpose from that of provoking reactions; they are in themselves effects involved in the process of reaction which takes place.
In short: Everything that becomes conscious is a final phenomenon, a conclusion—and is the cause of nothing; all succession of phenomena in consciousness is absolutely atomistic.—And we tried to understand the universe from the opposite point of view—as if nothing were effective or real, save thinking, feeling, willing! ...
479.
The phenomenalism of the inner world!
A chronological inversion takes place, so that the cause reaches consciousness as the effect.—We know that pain is projected into a certain part of the body although it is not really situated there; we have learnt that all sensations which were ingenuously supposed to be conditioned by the outer world are, as a matter of fact, conditioned by the inner world: that the real action of the outer world never takes place in a way of which we can become conscious.... That fragment of the outer world of which we become conscious, is born after the effect produced by the outer world has been recorded, and is subsequently interpreted as the cause
of that effect....
In the phenomenalism of the inner world,
the chronological order of cause and effect is inverted. The fundamental fact of inner experience
is, that the cause is imagined after the effect has been recorded.... The same holds good of the sequence of thoughts: we seek for the reason of a thought, before it has reached our consciousness; and then the reason reaches consciousness first, whereupon follows its effect. All our dreams are the interpretation of our collective feelings with the view of discovering the possible causes of the latter; and the process is such that a condition only becomes conscious, when the supposed causal link has reached consciousness.[1]
The whole of inner experience
is founded on this: that a cause is sought and imagined which accounts for a certain irritation in our nerve-centres, and that it is only the cause which is found in this way which reaches consciousness; this cause may have absolutely nothing to do with the real cause—it is a sort of groping assisted by former inner experiences,
that is to say, by memory. The memory, however, retains the habit of old interpretations,—that is to say, of erroneous causality,—so that inner experience
comprises in itself all the results of former erroneous fabrications of causes. Our outside world,
as we conceive it every instant, is indissolubly bound up with the old error of cause: we interpret by means of the schematism of the thing,
etc.
Inner experience
only enters consciousness when it has found a language which the individual can understand—that is to say, a translation of a certain condition into conditions with which he is familiar; understand
means simply this: to be able to express something new in the terms of something old or familiar. For instance, I feel unwell
—a judgment of this sort presupposes a very great and recent neutrality on the part of the observer: the simple man always says, This and that make me feel unwell,
—he begins to be clear concerning his indisposition only after he has discovered a reason for it.... This is what I call a lack of philological knowledge; to be able to read a text, as such, without reading an interpretation into it, is the latest form of inner experience,
—it is perhaps a barely possible form....
[1] When in our dream we hear a bell ringing, or a tapping at our door, we scarcely ever wake before having already accounted for the sound, in the terms of the dream-world we were in.—TR.
480.
There are no such things as mind,
reason, thought, consciousness, soul, will, or truth: they all belong to fiction, and can serve no purpose. It is not a question of subject and object,
but of a particular species of animal which can prosper only by means of a certain exactness, or, better still, regularity in recording its perceptions (in order that experience may be capitalised)....
Knowledge works as an instrument of power. It is therefore obvious that it increases with each advance of power....
The purpose of knowledge: in this case, as in the case of good
or beautiful,
the concept must be regarded strictly and narrowly from an anthropocentric and biological standpoint. In order that a particular species may maintain and increase its power, its conception of reality must contain enough which is calculable and constant to allow of its formulating a scheme of conduct. The utility of preservation—and not some abstract or theoretical need to eschew deception—stands as the motive force behind the development of the organs of knowledge; ... they evolve in such a way that their observations may suffice for our preservation. In other words, the measure of the desire for knowledge depends upon the extent to which the Will to Power grows in a certain species: a species gets a grasp of a given amount of reality, in order to master it, in order to enlist that amount in its service.
(c) The Belief in the Ego.
Subject.
481.
In opposition to Positivism, which halts at phenomena and says, These are only facts and nothing more,
I would say: No, facts are precisely what is lacking, all that exists consists of interpretations. We cannot establish any fact in itself
: it may even be nonsense to desire to do such a thing. Everything is subjective,
ye say: but that in itself is interpretation. The subject is nothing given, but something superimposed by fancy, something introduced behind.—Is it necessary to set an interpreter behind the interpretation already to hand? Even that would be fantasy, hypothesis.
To the extent to which knowledge has any sense at all, the world is knowable: but it may be interpreted differently, it has not one sense behind it, but hundreds of senses.—Perspectivity.
It is our needs that interpret the world; our instincts and their impulses for and against. Every instinct is a sort of thirst for power; each has its point of view, which it would fain impose upon all the other instincts as their norm.
482.
Where our ignorance really begins, at that point from which we can see no further, we set a word; for instance, the word I,
the word do,
the word suffer
—these concepts may be the horizon lines of our knowledge, but they are not truths.
483.
Owing to the phenomenon thought,
the ego is taken for granted; but up to the present everybody believed, like the people, that there was something unconditionally certain in the notion I think,
and that by analogy with our understanding of all other causal reactions this I
was the given cause of the thinking. However customary and indispensable this fiction may have become now, this fact proves nothing against the imaginary nature of its origin; it might be a life-preserving belief and still be false.
484.
Something is thought, therefore there is something that thinks
: this is what Descartes' argument amounts to. But this is tantamount to considering our belief in the notion substance
as an a priori
truth:—that there must be something that thinks
when we think, is merely a formulation of a grammatical custom which sets an agent to every action. In short, a metaphysico-logical postulate is already put forward here—and it is not merely an ascertainment of fact.... On Descartes' lines nothing absolutely certain is attained, but only the fact of a very powerful faith.
If the proposition be reduced to Something is thought, therefore there are thoughts,
the result is mere tautology; and precisely the one factor which is in question, the reality of thought,
is not touched upon,—so that, in this form, the apparitional character of thought cannot be denied. What Descartes wanted to prove was, that thought not only had apparent reality, but absolute reality.
485.
The concept substance is an outcome of the concept subject, and not conversely! If we surrender the concept soul, the subject, the very conditions for the concept substance
are lacking. Degrees of Being are obtained, but Being is lost.
Criticism of reality
: what does a plus or minus of reality
lead to, the gradation of Being in which we believe?
The degree of our feeling of life and power (the logic and relationship of past life) presents us with the measure of Being,
reality,
non-appearance.
Subject i this is the term we apply to our belief in an entity underlying all the different moments of the most intense sensations of reality; we regard this belief as the effect of a cause,—and we believe in our belief to such an extent that, on its account alone, we imagine truth,
reality,
substantiality.
—a Subject
is the fiction which would fain make us believe that several similar states were the effect of one substratum: but we it was who first created the similarity
of these states; the similising and adjusting of them is the fact—not their similarity (on the contrary, this ought rather to be denied).
486.
One would have to know what Being is, in order to be able to decide whether this or that is real (for instance, the facts of consciousness
); it would also be necessary to know what certainty and knowledge are, and so forth.—But, as we do not know these things, a criticism of the faculty of knowledge is nonsensical: how is it possible for an instrument to criticise itself, when it is itself that exercises the critical faculty. It cannot even define itself!
487.
Should not all philosophy ultimately disclose the first principles on which the reasoning processes depend?—that is to say, our belief in the ego
as a substance, as the only reality according to which, alone, we are able to ascribe reality to things? The oldest realism at length comes to light, simultaneously with man's recognition of the fact that his whole religious history is no more than a history of soul-superstitions. Here there is a barrier; our very thinking, itself, involves that belief (with its distinctions—substance, accident, action, agent, etc.); to abandon it would mean to cease from being able to think.
But that a belief, however useful it may be for the preservation of a species, has nothing to do with the truth, may be seen from the fact that we must believe in time, space, and motion, without feeling ourselves compelled to regard them as absolute realities.
488.
The psychological origin of our belief in reason.—The ideas reality,
Being,
are derived from our subject-feeling.
Subject,
interpreted through ourselves so that the ego may stand as substance, as the cause of action, as the agent.
The metaphysico-logical postulates, the belief in substance, accident, attribute, etc. etc., draws its convincing character from our habit of regarding all our actions as the result of our will: so that the ego, as substance, does not vanish in the multiplicity of changes.—But there is no such thing as will. We have no categories which allow us to separate a world as thing-in-itself,
from a world of appearance.
All our categories of reason have a sensual origin: they are deductions from the empirical world. The soul,
the ego
—the history of these concepts shows that here, also, the oldest distinction (spiritus,
life
) obtains....
If there is nothing material, then there can be nothing immaterial. The concept no longer means anything.
No subject-atoms.
The sphere of a subject increasing or diminishing unremittingly, the centre of the system continually displacing itself, in the event of the system no longer being able to organise the appropriated mass, it divides into two. On the other hand, it is able, without destroying it, to transform a weaker subject into one of its own functionaries, and, to a certain extent, to compose a new entity with it. Not a substance,
but rather something which in itself strives after greater strength; and which wishes to preserve
itself only indirectly (it wishes to surpass itself).
489.
Everything that reaches consciousness as an entity is already enormously complicated: we never have anything more than the semblance of an entity.
The phenomenon of the body is the richer, more distinct, and more tangible phenomenon: it should be methodically drawn to the front, and no mention should be made of its ultimate significance.
490.
The assumption of a single subject is perhaps not necessary, it may be equally permissible to assume a plurality of subjects, whose interaction and struggle lie at the bottom of our thought and our consciousness in general. A sort of aristocracy of cells
in which the ruling power is vested? Of course an aristocracy of equals, who are accustomed to ruling co-operatively, and understand how to command?
My hypotheses. The subject as a plurality. Pain intellectual and dependent upon the judgment harmful, projected. The effect always unconscious
: the inferred and imagined cause is projected, it follows the event. Pleasure is a form of pain. The only kind of power that exists is of the same nature as the power of will: a commanding of other subjects which thereupon alter themselves. The unremitting transientness and volatility of the subject. Mortal soul.
Number as perspective form.
491.
The belief in the body is more fundamental than the belief in the soul: the latter arose from the unscientific observation of the agonies of the body. (Something which leaves it. The belief in the truth of dreams)
492.
The body and physiology the starting-point: why?—We obtain a correct image of the nature of our subject-entity, that is to say, as a number of regents at the head of a community (not as souls
or as life-forces
) as also of the dependence of these regents upon their subjects, and upon the conditions of a hierarchy, and of the division of labour, as the means ensuring the existence of the part and the whole. We also obtain a correct image of the way in which the living entities continually come into being and expire, and we see how eternity cannot belong to the subject
; we realise that the struggle finds expression in obeying as well as in commanding, and that a fluctuating definition of the limits of power is a factor of life. The comparative ignorance in which the ruler is kept, of the individual performances and even disturbances taking place in the community, also belong to the conditions under which government may be carried on. In short, we obtain a valuation even of want-of-knowledge, of seeing-things-generally-as-a-whole, of simplification, of falsification, and of perspective. What is most important, however, is, that we regard the ruler and his subjects as of the same kind, all feeling, willing, thinking—and that wherever we see or suspect movement in a body, we conclude that there is co-operative-subjective and invisible life. Movement as a symbol for the eye; it denotes that something has been felt, willed, thought.
The danger of directly questioning the subject concerning the subject, and all spiritual self-reflection, consists in this, that it might be a necessary condition of its activity to interpret itself erroneously. That is why we appeal to the body and lay the evidence of sharpened senses aside: or we try and see whether the subjects themselves cannot enter into communication with us.
(d) Biology of the Instinct of Knowledge. Perspectivity.
493.
Truth is that kind of error without which a certain species of living being cannot exist. The value for Life is ultimately decisive.
494.
It is unlikely that our knowledge
extends farther than is exactly necessary for our self-preservation. Morphology shows us how the senses and the nerves as well as the brain evolve in proportion as the difficulties of acquiring sustenance increase.
495.
If the morality of Thou shalt not lie
be refuted, the sense for truth will then have to justify itself before another tribunal—as a means to the preservation of man, as Will to Power.
Likewise our love of the beautiful: it is also the creative will. Both senses stand side by side; the sense of truth is the means wherewith the power is appropriated to adjust things according to one's taste. The love of adjusting and reforming—a primeval love! We can only take cognisance of a world which we ourselves have made.
496.
Concerning the multifariousness of knowledge. The tracing of its relation to many other things (or the relation of kind)—how should knowledge
be of another? The way to know and to investigate is in itself among the conditions of life; that is why the conclusion that there could be no other kind of intellect (for ourselves) than the kind which serves the purpose of our preservation is an excessively hasty one: this actual condition may be only an accidental, not in the least an essential; one.
Our apparatus for acquiring knowledge is not adjusted for knowledge.
497.
The most strongly credited a priori truths
are, to my mind, mere assumptions pending further investigation; for instance, the law of causation is a belief so thoroughly acquired by practice and so completely assimilated, that to disbelieve in it would mean the ruin of our kind. But is it therefore true? What an extraordinary conclusion! As if truth were proved by the mere fact that man survives!
498.
To what extent is our intellect also a result of the conditions of life?—We should not have it did we not need to have it, and we should not have it as we have it, if we did not need it as we need it—that is to say, if we could live otherwise.
499.
Thinking in a primitive (inorganic) state is to persevere in forms, as in the case of the crystal.—In our thought, the essential factor is the harmonising of the new material with the old schemes (= Procrustes' bed), the assimilation of the unfamiliar.
500.
The perception of the senses projected outwards: inwards
and outwards
—does the body command here?
The same equalising and ordering power which rules in the idioplasma, also rules in the incorporation of the outer world: our sensual perceptions are already the result of this process of adaptation and harmonisation in regard to all the past in us; they do not follow directly upon the impression.
501.
All thought, judgment, perception, regarded as an act of comparing[2] has as a first condition the act of equalising, and earlier still the act of making equal.
The process of making equal is the same as the assimilation by the amœba of the nutritive matter it appropriates.
Memory
late, in so far as the equalising instinct appears to have been subdued: the difference is preserved. Memory—a process of classification and collocation; active—who?
[2] The German word vergleichen, meaning to compare,
contains the root equal
(gleich) which cannot be rendered in English. TR.
502.
In regard to the memory, we must unlearn a great deal: here we meet with the greatest temptation to assume the existence of a soul,
which, irrespective of time, reproduces and recognises again and again, etc. What I have experienced, however, continues to live in the memory
; I have nothing to do with it when memory comes,
my will is inactive in regard to it, as in the case of the coming and going of a thought. Something happens, of which I become conscious: now something similar comes—who has called it forth? Who has awakened it?
503.
The whole apparatus of knowledge is an abstracting and simplifying apparatus—not directed at knowledge, but at the appropriation of things: end
and means
are as remote from the essence of this apparatus as concepts
are. By the end
and the means
a process is appropriated (—a process is invented which may be grasped), but by concepts
one appropriates the things
which constitute the process.
504.
Consciousness begins outwardly as co-ordination and knowledge of impressions,—at first it is at the point which is remotest from the biological centre of the individual; but it is a process which deepens and which tends to become more and more an inner function, continually approaching nearer to the centre.
505.
Our perceptions, as we understand them—that is to say, the sum of all those perceptions the consciousness whereof was useful and essential to us and to the whole organic processes which preceded us: therefore they do not include all perceptions (for instance, not the electrical ones);—that is to say, we have senses only for a definite selection of perceptions—such perceptions as concern us with a view to our self-preservation. Consciousness extends so far only as it is useful. There can be no doubt that all our sense-perceptions are entirely permeated by valuations (useful or harmful—consequently, pleasant or painful). Every particular colour; besides being a colour, expresses a value to us (although we seldom admit it, or do so only after it has affected us exclusively for a long time, as in the case of convicts in gaol or lunatics). Insects likewise react in different ways to different colours: some like this shade, the others that. Ants are a case in point.
506.
In the beginning images how images originate in the mind must be explained. Then words, applied to images. Finally concepts, possible only when there are words—the assembling of several pictures into a whole which is not for the eye but for the ear (word). The small amount of emotion which the word
generates,—that is, then, which the view of the similar pictures generates, for which one word is used,—this simple emotion is the common factor, the basis of a concept. That weak feelings should all be regarded as alike, as the same, is the fundamental fact. There is