Gerald Boersma
Augustine’s Trinitarian Theology
in Dante’s Paradiso 33
Where does St. Augustine appear in Dante’s Commedia? As a literary character, the historical figure of the bishop of Hippo does not
appear. We might expect Dante to place Augustine in Paradiso X, in
the fourth sphere, the sphere of the Sun, along with the other theologians—Thomas Aquinas, Albertus Magnus, Boethius, Dionysius
the Areopagite, Isidore of Seville, Bede, and Richard of St. Victor,
to name a few leading lights who have a place there. But Augustine
does not appear there (or elsewhere). We have to wait until the penultimate canto—Paradiso 32—to discover his name—and only his
name—(almost inadvertently) dropped among unnamed others (e
altri).1 The virtual absence of Augustine in Dante’s Commedia is baffling, but also beguiling. After all, no one—save the apostle Paul—
does as much as Augustine to cement Christian theology. The Doctor of Grace towers above the patristic era. Augustine’s authority
is of a singular character (recall that Aquinas simply refers to him
as The Theologian). Why, then, this striking omission by the mystic
Florentine poet?2 In the Commedia Augustine does not speak, he is not
spoken to; in fact, he is not spoken about.
l o g o s 25:3 s u m m e r 2022
110
logos
We know Dante was very much familiar with Augustine and his
writings.3 The first commentators on the Commedia make reference
to the African bishop countless times.4 Also, strangely, this question—where is Augustine?—is not one that contemporary Dante
scholars frequently entertain.5 No less of an authority than Robert
Hollander remarks, “Dante’s treatment of Augustine remains a relatively infrequent object of the attention of dantisti, even if it is one of
the most tantalizing aspects of his poem.”6
Tantalizing or not, I do not intend to speculate here on the question of why Dante seems to exclude the character of Augustine from
the narrative of his poem. Rather, I want to consider in detail where
Augustine—or at least his theology—does loom large. The concluding thirty lines of the poem are, I argue, decidedly Augustinian. At
the climax of Dante’s great epic—Canto 33 of the Paradiso—the
poet relates his mystical vision of the Holy Trinity in unmistakably
Augustinian terms. Surprisingly, this theological dependence on
Augustine has been virtually ignored.7 Further, Dante’s expression
of the human person finding his place in that divine triad depends
profoundly on Augustine’s theology of the imago dei. In both cases, I
maintain, the direct vorlage is Augustine’s De Trinitate.
At the close of the poem, Dante audaciously claims to enjoy the
beatific vision and to have beheld “that Light” (quella luce):8
Così la mente mia, tutta sospesa
mirava fissa, immobile e attenta,
e sempre di mirar faceasi accesa.
A quella luce cotal si diventa,
che volgersi da lei per altro aspetto
è impossibil che mai si consenta.
(Par. 33.97–102)
Thus all my mind, absorbed,
was gazing, fixed, unmoved and intent,
becoming more enraptured in its gazing.
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
He who beholds that Light is so enthralled
that he would never willingly consent
to turn away from it for any other sight.
As we come to the last lines of the Canto, Dante—at last—tells us
what he saw, that is to say, the nature of the light beheld. He has seen
God three in one and one in three. The poem concludes with two
profound theological mysteries Dante professes to have seen, two
mysteries that are interwoven. First, the mutual indwelling of the
divine persons of the Holy Trinity. Second, the manner in which the
human person images God. Dante articulates both of these mysteries
in decidedly Augustinian terms.
I. Augustinian perichoresis in Dante’s vision
Ne la profonda e chiara sussistenza
de l’alto lume parvermi tre giri
di tre colori e d’una contenenza;
e l’un da l’altro come iri da iri
parea reflesso, e ’l terzo parea foco
che quinci e quindi igualmente si spiri.
(Par. 33.115–120)
In the deep, transparent essence of that lofty Light
there appeared to me three circles
having three colors but the same extent,
and each one seemed reflected by the other
as rainbow is by rainbow, while the third seemed fire,
equally breathed forth by one and by the other.
Why are the three persons of the Blessed Trinity described as
“three circles” (tre giri)? A circle neither begins nor ends, suggesting timelessness and eternity; it represents wholeness, completion,
111
112
logos
perfection.9 But these three circles, although equal (d’una contenenza), are not uniform.10 They are distinguished by “having three
colors.”11 The diverse persons are all equally God and are one substance.They are distinguished only by way of origin, that is to say, the
Father is Father of the Son and the Son is Son of the Father. Here Dante
tracks basic Nicene theology codified in book five of Augustine’s De
Trinitate. When Dante describes one of the circles “reflected by the
other” he invokes New Testament descriptions of the mode of the
Son’s procession as the image, representation, and very expression
of the Father’s essence (Cf. Col 1:15; Heb 1:3).12
Dante also articulates the Holy Spirit’s mode of procession as
“fire, equally breathed forth by one and by the other.” The original
creed at Nicaea did not contain the filioque now recited in Western
Christianity (“who proceeds from the Father and the Son”). Augustine, however, makes the filioque central in his analysis of trinitarian processions.13 In sum, Dante’s poetic expression of the distinct
modes of procession proper to Son and Spirit is faithful to Augustine
for whom the Son is eternally begotten (natus) while the Spirit is
eternally given (datus).14
However, one might object that this is not unique to Augustine.
Is this not standard fare for Western trinitarian theology? Could we
not find the same truth stated in Boethius, Anselm of Canterbury,
Peter Abelard, or the Victorines? In fact, is it not the case that the
more immediate source of Dante’s trinitarian theology is not Augustine, but the reception of Augustine in either its Dominican iteration
(preeminently Thomas Aquinas) or its Franciscan iteration (preeminently Bonaventure)? In other words, we are straining to hear notes
in Dante’s trinitarian theology that are distinctly Augustine, and not
“the atmospheric Augustinianism that one might find in almost any
medieval work.”15
One element in Dante’s concluding lines leads me to think that it
is Augustine in particular who stands as the source of the Florentine
poet’s trinitarian theology. It is the way in which Augustine insists—
throughout his career—that knowledge of God and the soul are
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
correlative. One cannot begin to contemplate the mystery of the Holy
Trinity without also considering the triadic mystery of the human
person. Among Augustine’s very first works is the dialogue Soliloquies. It begins with Augustine’s prayer, noverim me, noverim te—may I
know myself and may I know you.16 Knowledge of self coinheres with
knowledge of God. The higher up is the deeper in: one ascends to
God by greater interiority. For Augustine, our own being, knowing,
and willing serve not only as a model, or a fertile analogical site, for
launching our thinking about God, but by reflecting on the trinitarian mystery of God we also “return” to understand more truthfully
our own being, knowing, and willing. These two mysteries—the holy
Trinity and the human soul—are necessarily correlative. We cannot
begin to understand ourselves without thinking about God, nor can
we begin to contemplate God without considering ourselves. This, in
fact, is Augustine’s central thesis in De Trinitate.17
In Book 9 of De Trinitate, Augustine reminds his readers that the
search for the Holy Trinity necessitates turning within. The human
mind loves and knows. There you have three, notes Augustine: a
mind, its love, and its knowledge. What makes this triadic analogy so
fecund for our contemplation of God? When we turn within to consider our mind, its love, and its knowledge, we discover something
wholly spiritual and noncorporeal. Further, these three are distinct,
but inseparable. We can enumerate three realities, but they coinhere
and are reciprocally constituted. Augustine drives home the point:
one cannot have mind without its knowledge and love. Nor can one
have knowledge without love and mind. Nor can one have love without mind and knowledge. Although these three can be conceptually distinguished, they are not “parts” of a whole. Nor are the three
“mixed” together. Although three—mind, knowledge, and love—
they exist wholly in each other while also whole in themselves.
Now the object of our love and knowledge is not always external—knowing and loving something or someone. I can also love and
know myself. That is to say, the mind is also reflexive: there is selfknowing and self-loving. Augustine notes, “When the mind however
113
114
logos
knows its whole self, that is knows itself completely, its knowledge
pervades the whole of it; and when it loves itself completely it loves
its whole self and its love pervades the whole of it.”18 Here the mind
(mens), its self-love (amor sui), and self-knowledge (notitia sui) are
wholly in each other. But they are not “parts” of one another nor
are they “confused” like three ingredients mixed together in a drink.
Rather, “they are each one in itself and each whole in their total,
whether each in the other two or the other two in each, in any case
all in all.”19 The mutual indwelling of mind, self-love, and self-knowledge, each wholly in the other, provides Augustine with a profound
image in the created order for contemplating the mutual indwelling
of the Holy Trinity—of God’s uncreated existence as “all in all” (1
Cor 15:28). The technical theological term for this mutual indwelling of the divine persons is perichoresis, and, at least for Augustine,
perichoresis is dimly perceived in the “disparate image” (impari imagine)
of the human mind, its self-love, and self-knowledge.20 As the mind
(mens), its self-love (amor sui), and self-knowledge (notitia sui) are
wholly in each other in a way that is neither partitive nor confused,
so too (analogously?), the divine persons are “all in all,” mutually
indwelling one another such that “each pair is in the other single.”21
Dante distills this entire Augustinian perichoretic theology in an
elliptical, lyrical tercet:
O luce etterna che sola in te sidi,
sola t’intendi, e da te intelletta
e intendente te ami e arridi!
(Par. 33.124–126)
O eternal Light, abiding in yourself alone,
knowing yourself alone, and, known to yourself
and knowing, loving and smiling on yourself!
At the climax of Dante’s vision, we are invited to behold the communion of the divine persons. We see self-subsistent Life; the eternal God resting in his own perfect happiness. At the same time, we
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
witness what Catholic theology terms “‘the inner fecundity of the
Divine Life,’ the productions of that Life within itself.”22 That is to
say, the mode of procession proper to intellect (Word/the Son) and
will (Love/the Holy Spirit). Dante articulates the procession of intellect with the words “da te intelletta e intendente te” (“known to yourself and knowing”), echoing Christ’s teaching regarding the mutual
knowledge he and the Father share of one another. (“No one knows
the Son except the Father, and no one knows the Father except the
Son” (Matthew 11:27); “As the Father knows me and I know the
Father” (John 10:15)). The procession of will is described with the
words “ami e arridi” (“loving and smiling”). John Carroll’s commentary remains superlative: “It is in the mutual knowledge of Father
and Son that the Spirit ‘loves and smiles,’—the smile representing
the happiness with which this activity of the Divine Life within itself
is for ever filled.”23
Dante takes as his own Augustine’s central insight, namely, that
contemplating the mystery of God’s own inner life—che sola in te
sidi—we can do no better than contemplate our own inner life, the
mind’s self-love (amor sui) and self-knowledge (notitia sui). In this tercet, Dante linguistically reenacts Augustine’s trinitarian theology of the
mutual coinherence of the divine Persons: language falls in on itself.
In the words of Charles Singleton, “This remarkable tercet, turning—indeed, circling—upon itself, expresses in its very movement
the self-containedness of the Trinity, One and Three.”24 Perichoresis
is a compound of two Greek words, peri, meaning “around” (hence,
for example, the word “perimeter”) and chorein, meaning “stepping to
give way” or “to come or go, making room.” Chorein suggests movement that makes space. And so, the word perichoresis has a dynamic,
moving sense of “going around” and inclusive “encompassing.”25 The
dynamic, pulsating, energy of trinitarian life is a (simple and immutable) movement in which each divine person wholly encircles the
other and pours his delight, adoration, exultation, and very self into
the other two persons who each receive and return delight, adoration, exultation, and life. Our word choreography, related to dancing
115
116
logos
or “flowing around,” is suggestive of the perichoretic energy of trinitarian self-gift.26 Dante’s tercet syntactically expresses the reflexive
nature of the mind’s self-love and self-knowledge that Augustine considers to be a preeminent image of trinitarian life.
II.“How the image fits the circle”: A dynamic theology
of the imago dei
As Dante (the pilgrim) continues to gaze at these three perichoretic
colored circles, he sees the color of one “to be painted with our likeness” (pinta de la nostra effige) (Par. 33.131). This is the second and
supreme mystery that concludes the Commedia. The poem ends with
the pilgrim rapt in wonder:
tal era io a quella vista nova:
veder voleva come si convenne
l’imago al cerchio e come vi s’indova;
(Par. 33.136–138)
Such was I at that strange new sight.
I tried to see how the image fits the circle
and how it found its where in it.
Augustine’s entire theological career is consumed with fascination
by the same mystery. What is the relation between the created imago
dei and the uncreated imago dei? What is the relation between Christ,
“the image of God, the first born of all creation” (Col 1:16) and the
human person, of whom God said, “Let us make man in our image
and likeness” (Gen 1:26)? I want to suggest that here, at the climax of
the poem, we see Dante’s most explicit and consequential embrace
of Augustine. In Christ the image of God we see how humanity, created in the image of God, fits within “that circling”; how we find our
place—our “where”—in God.27 Espying the second circle “painted
with our likeness” we discover our beginning and our end. It is the
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
second circle that assumed a human nature, thereby manifesting the
Creator’s original vision for integral humanity, but also revealing its
eschatological perfection. Dante gazes intently at this second circle
trying to discern how humanity “fits” therein. On the one hand this
seems impossible. How can the finite be united with the infinite,
creation with the Creator, time with eternity? How could we possibly “fit” there? And yet, in the hypostatic union humanity is united
to the Word of God, securing us a “place” now and forever in the
Holy Trinity.
“In my beginning is my end,” writes T. S. Eliot (“East Coker”)
and this is especially the case for Augustine’s iteration of the human
person as “image of God.” Genesis reveals our “beginning,” and at
the same time discloses our destiny. To be created in the image of
God is, for Augustine, not a static reality—fashioned and finished,
so to speak. Rather, to be made in the “image of God” is suggestive of a dynamic, existential unfurling of potency from its divine
source and towards its divine end. It is this “journey,” if you will, that
constitutes Augustine’s account of the human person created in the
image of God.28
Dante shares with Augustine precisely this dynamic account of
the imago dei. The “strange new sight” that Dante beholds is humanity’s place in one of the circles—and if in one of the circles, necessarily in all three. The created image of God “fit the circle” and
“found its where in it” inasmuch as its origin and end is in the depths
of trinitarian love. To be an “image” is to come forth as reflective,
derived, indeed, imitative of that more primordial source. No one
would look in a mirror, remarks Augustine, and say the images causes
the person. Rather, the reverse is true; the movement of causality is
monodirectional. Also, this is a cause that needs be ever present. The
moment the source of the image steps away from the mirror, the
image vanishes. To be created in “image of God” is to receive at each
and every moment a participation in God’s own trinitarian life of
love. God does not create the human person as Michelangelo sculpts
David—something beautiful but unrelated to himself—something
117
118
logos
from which he walks away from when his work is done. Rather, as
Augustine never tires of explaining, God’s creative action is twofold:
he creates all things at once, simultaneously (in an ictus), but he is also
continually creating creatures; at each and every moment imbuing
creation with his own life (creatio continua).
Augustine recognizes this dynamic character of the image of God
inscribed in the Latin preposition ad used in the Latin text of Genesis: ad imaginem dei. To be made ad imaginem entails a driving force
ordered towards an end. Only at the end of life’s pilgrimage, when we
are led by the holy angels into the presence of God, will the image be
wholly restored.29 The dynamic character of the imago, impressed at
the moment of its inception, initiates an itinerary only complete in
the new heaven and new earth.
The ongoing creation (creatio continua) of the imago dei—its
dynamic propensity—is the process of its re-creation towards its
trinitarian exemplar. By sin the human image is “deformed and discolored” (deformis et decolor), but by the mercy and power of God it
is “reformed and renovated” (reformatur atque renouatur).30 Augustine
fills in what it means for the imago to be reformed by drawing on the
apostle Paul’s antithesis of the “old” and “new” man:
To this kind of approximation we are exhorted when it says,
Be refashioned in the newness of your mind (Rom 12:2), and elsewhere he says, Be therefore imitators of God as most dear sons (Eph
5:1), for it is with reference to the new man that it says, Who
is being renewed for the recognition of God according to the image of
him who created him (Col 3:10).31
The convalesce of the created image of God is a postbaptismal, lifelong process of being “conformed to the image of his Son” (Rom
8:29).32 And so, for Augustine, the imago dei is certainly a metaphysical and ontological datum—a given of our created nature—but
it is also a moral imperative—an aspirational injunction. An image
implies a primordial exemplar, the perfect uncreated image, which,
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
in Dante’s arresting image, is the second circle after which we are
fashioned and towards which our whole being strains.
Although Dante mysteriously scratches the great bishop of
Hippo from the canvas of his epic, our saint appears, subtly and
profoundly, in the exalted mystical pitch of the last thirty lines.
Dante gives poetic expression to Augustine’s two central theological insights articulated in De Trinitate. First, that contemplating the
perichoretic unity of the Holy Trinity requires contemplating at
the same time the triadic circling of our own mind, self-love and
self-knowledge. And, second, that the imago dei is a transforming
journey of being “conformed to the image” of Christ; this dynamic
remains in a real sense an eschatological hope. In Dante’s vision—in
the beatific vision—we will, please God, share the poet’s “strange
new sight” and “see how the image fits the circle / and how it found
its where in it” (138–139).
Notes
I’m grateful to Deana Basile Kelly for the invitation to contribute to a panel she organized
on Dante’s theology for the Honors Program at Ave Maria University. The ideas developed
in this paper first germinated in that fertile conversation. Dr. Basile Kelly first alerted me to
the profound theological import of Augustine on Dante’s anthropology and encouraged me
to explore this theme in the ultimate canto of the Commedia.
1. I have used the translation by Robert and Jean Hollander: Dante, Paradiso (New York:
Anchor Books, 2007). Of this sole reference Peter Hawkins comments, “The saint
who by anyone’s estimation should merit at least a canto’s discourse in the Paradiso becomes instead a beatific face in the crowd, a name barely mentioned.” Peter
Hawkins, “Divide and Conquer: Augustine in the Divine Comedy,” Publications of the
Modern Language Association of America 106 (1991): 472. It seems Augustine is also
referenced in Paradiso (hereafter “Par.”) 10.120: “quello avvocato de’ tempi cristiani / del
cui latino Augustin si provide” (“that advocate of the Christian times, of whose account
Augustine made use”). This is likely referring to Orosius’s Historiarum adversum paganos, commissioned at Augustine’s behest.
2. Some suggest that Augustine’s absence can be explained by Dante’s preference for the
Thomistic-Aristotelian theological synthesis as distinct from the Platonic-Christian
mystical tradition. Cf. Carlo Calcaterra, “Sant’Agostino nelle opere di Dante e
del Petrarca,” Rivista di filosofia neo-scholastica 23 (1931): 422–99. However, this
119
120
logos
explanation fails to account for the fact that throughout the poem, Dante draws in
profound ways from both theological wellsprings, allowing representatives from each
“tradition” to give voice to their particular spiritual worldview. A more compelling
explanation for the exclusion of Augustine is Dante’s positive appraisal of Rome, her
imperium, and her poet, Virgil. In this regard, the Commedia is a theo-political riposte
to Augustine’s City of God. Peter Hawkins argues, “Augustine negated pagan Rome,
discredited Vergil, and refused the idea of temporal beatitude as a legitimate human
‘end.’ It was against his authoritative naysaying that Dante had to contravene in his
own bid to underwrite not only a renewed Roman empire but a vision of redeemed
political life of earth.” Hawkins, “Divide and Conquer,” 472. For a similar claim see
Robert Hollander, “Dante’s Reluctant Allegiance to St. Augustine in the Commedia,”
L’Alighieri 32 (2008): 5–16; Giuseppe Mazzotta, Dante, Poet of the Desert (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 147–91; Jeffrey Schnapp, The Transfiguration
of History at the Center of Dante’s Paradise (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
2014).
3. In Monarchia, Dante maintains that the writings of Augustine seem to share with
Scripture a source of divine inspiration: “Sunt etiam Scripture doctotum, Augustini et
aliorum, quos a Spiritu Sancto adiutos” (3.3). Augustine is also mentioned in Convivio
4.4.
4. Hollander considers at length the place of Augustine in Dante’s commentators—
both early and modern—and concludes, “The number of citations of Augustine in
Dante’s first commentators dwarfs that of similar important major figures in the early
history of the church. . . . It seems that the early commentators thought either that
Dante knew Augustine well or, if he did not, that his ideas and ways of expressing
them were similar to Augustine’s.” Hollander, “Dante’s Reluctant Allegiance,” 5–6.
Dante’s son and one of his first commentators, Pietro di Dante, mentions Augustine
342 times in the three versions of his commentary. Cf. G. Fallani, Dante e S. Augustino,
in L’esperienza teologica di Dante (Lecce, Miella, 1976), 193; Hawkins, “Divide and
Conquer,” 480n3; Hollander, “Dante’s Reluctant Allegiance,” 5.
5. There are some significant twentieth-century exceptions, which seem to break into
three areas of interest. First, those who consider the manner in which the architectonic structures of the Commedia map onto those of the Confessions. See John Freccero, The Poetics of Conversion (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986).
Second, those who compare how the three types of vision outlined in Augustine’s De
Genesi ad litteram 12 serve as a structuring feature of the Commedia. See Marguerite
Mills Chiarenza, “The Imageless Vision and Dante’s Paradiso,” Dante Studies 90 (1972):
77–92; John Freccero, The Poetics of Conversion; Francis X. Newman, “St. Augustine’s
Three Visions and the Structure of the Commedia,” Modern Language Notes 82 (1967):
56–78. Finally, those interested in how Dante rewrites Augustine’s theology of history so as to recast ancient Rome and the poet Virgil in a more theologically favorable
light. See Hawkins, “Divide and Conquer,”; idem., “Polemical Counterpoint in De
civitate Dei,” Augustinian Studies 6 (1975): 97–106; Ronald Martinez, Dante, Statius, and
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
6.
7.
8.
9.
the Earthly City (PhD diss. Unversity of California, 1977); Giuseppe Mazzotta, Dante,
Poet of the Desert, 147–191; Jeffrey Schnapp, The Transfiguration of History.
Hollander, “Dante’s Reluctant Allegiance,” 9.
In a penetrating study of the place of dialogue in Dante’s theological anthropology,
Deana Basile Kelly points to Augustine as a key source for Paradiso 33, recognizing the
critical lacuna: “Dante’s unique poetic use of the Augustinian approach to the Trinity,
especially in this final canto, has not yet been adequately recognized by scholars.”
Basile Kelly, “Rejection of Dialogue with the Father: Vanni Fucci as Infernal Adam,”
in A Garland of Gifts: Essays in Honor of Olga Zorzi Pugliese, Vol. I, ed. Konrad Eisenbichler and Pasquale Sabbatino (Welland, ON: Soleil Publishing, 2021): 47–68 at
46n10. Basile Kelly notes that in Par. 33 it is Augustine’s relational theology of image
that serves as the positive counterpoint to Vanni Fucci’s rejection of divine dialogue
in Inferno 24 and 25. Beyond this, to my knowledge, no modern commentator has
offered a detailed study of the central place Augustine plays in Dante’s concluding
trinitarian vision.
Dante boldly asserts what Scripture states to be impossible: to see God in this life.
God tells Moses emphatically, “No man shall see Me, and live” (Ex 33:20). The apostle Paul teaches that God “dwells in unapproachable light, whom no one has seen or
can see” (1 Tim 6:16) and that “eye has not seen . . . what God has prepared” (1 Cor
2:9). Interestingly, however, both Moses and Paul did see God. Moses spoke to God
face to face as to a friend (Ex 33:11) and the Apostle was “caught up to the third
heaven” where he “heard unspeakable words, which it is not lawful for a man to utter”
(2 Cor 12:2–4). A maelstrom of medieval theological commentary sought to make
sense of these remarkable exceptions—men who saw God and lived. Undaunted,
Dante places himself in a category with Moses and the apostle Paul, such that one
commentator remarks, “No Christian except for St. Paul has seen so much—or such
is the unspoken claim the poet makes us share.” Dante, Paradiso, trans. Robert Hollander (New York: Anchor Books, 2007), 924.
Dante inherits a rich theological tradition of speaking of the Trinity in terms of a
“circle.” One of the most compelling examples is Nicholas of Cusa. See David Albertson, Mathematical Theologies: Nicholas of Cusa and the Legacy of Thierry of Chartres
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), esp. 243–252. For a broader discussion
see Georges Poulet, The Metamorphoses of the Circle, trans. C. Dawson and E. Coleman
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1966). Most translators render the tre
giri “three circles”; however, in a detailed study of these lines (Par. 33.115–120),
Arielle Saiber and Aba Mbirika point out that giro occupies a broader semantic range
than the English “circle”; giro can describe a disc, sphere, ball, cylinder, spiral or other
round thing. Regardless, the conclusion of the Commedia “is a monument to the use
of geometric imagery to describe the ineffable.” Arielle Saiber and Aba Mbirika, “The
Three ‘Giri’ of Paradiso 33,” Dante Studies 131 (2013): 242. The authors also raise the
fascinating question of whether the tre giri that the Pilgrim espies are spinning or
still: “In their very shapes, circles and spheres evoke both eternal stillness and eternal
121
122
logos
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
motion. On the one hand, they are free from a beginning and an end; on the other,
they are in themselves both beginning and end, like the giro of Christ, the alpha and
omega” (Saiber and Mbirika, “The Three ‘Giri,’” 247–248).
Similar questions surround the meaning of contenenza. Many translators take it
to entail spatial dimension (“extent”), such that the tre giri are “of the same size.”
Given its trinitarian reference, however, it is perhaps better to render d’una contenenza “of the same substance / essence.” Cf. Saiber and Mbirika, “The Three ‘Giri,’”
248–249.
In addition to questions about what contenenza means in reference to the tre giri, there
is also ambiguity about how to render “di tre colori.” Does Dante intend three distinct
colors? If so, it would lend credence to the claim that Dante explicitly adopts the
trinitarian illustration of the Franciscan abbot, Joachim of Fiore. Marjorie Reeves and
Beatrice Hirsch-Reich maintain that Joachim of Fiore is the source for Dante’s reference to three distinctly colored circles. See The Figurae of Joachim of Fiore (Oxford:
Clarendon: 1972), 323–324. See also Beatrice Hirsch Reich, “Die Quelle der
Trinitätskreise von Joachim von Fiore und Dante,” Sophia 22 (1954): 170–178; Peter
Dronke, The Medieval Poet and hisWorld (Rome: Edizioni di storia e letteratura, 1984),
98–104; Robert Wilson, Prophecies and Prophecy in Dante’s Commedia (Florence: Biblioteca Dell’archivum Romanicum 2008), 213–214. In the Liber figurarum, Joachim
depicted three rings interlocking on a horizontal plane; the first ring (the Father) is
green, the second ring (the Son) is blue, and the third ring (the Holy Spirit) is red.
Of course, Dante does not mention three distinct colors and he is well aware that
the Fourth Lateran Council (1215) condemned Joachim for undermining the unity
of the divine substance with such illustrations. (On the other hand, Dante includes
the condemned abbot among the beatified theologians in the sphere of the Sun in
Par. 12.140–141.) Cf. Steno Vazzana, ‘‘Parvemi tre giri (Par. 33, 116),’’ L’Alighieri 24
(1983): 53–61. On this score Saiber and Mbirika note, “It appears that Dante wanted
to avoid attributing a single color to each giro, perhaps in order to avert the criticism
that Joachim of Fiore received by giving the three persons three separate colors in his
illustration of the Trinity.” Saiber and Mbirika, “The Three ‘Giri,’” 250. In any case,
the tre colori are linked in the next line to double rainbow. Pietro di Dante suggests
that the rainbow connects the poet’s vision with the vision in the Apocalypse of God’s
throne in heaven: “And immediately I was in the spirit: and, behold, a throne was set
in heaven, and one sat on the throne. And he that sat was to look upon like a jasper
and a sardine stone: and there was a rainbow round about the throne, in sight like
unto an emerald” (Rev 4: 2–3).
Other trinitarian references in the Paradiso include Par. 10.1–6; Par. 13.25–27,
52–57, 79–87; Par. 14.28–29; Par. 15.47; Par. 24.139–144; Par. 31.28.
Augustine, De Trinitate (hereafter “De Trin.”). 5.13.14–4.14.15; 6.5.7; 15.26.47.
Commenting on the poet’s description of divine processions, Pietro di Dante also
makes the connection here to Augustine’s De Trinitate.
De Trin. 5.13.14–4.14.15. The dual procession of the Holy Spirit is important to
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
Dante’s trinitarian theology. Upon entering the Sphere of the Sun in Paradiso 10,
Dante invites the reader to join him in raising his eyes to behold triune unity: “Gazing on His Son with the Love / the One and the Other eternally breath forth” (Par.
10.1–2). In Par. 13.57 the Holy Spirit is described as “the Love that is intrined with
them.” “Intrined” captures Dante’s neologism intrearsi (“to inthree oneself ”).” Cf.
Hollander, Paradiso, 357.
Hawkins, “Divide and Conquer,” 472.
Soliloquies. 2.1.1.
Cf. Lewis Ayres, “The Discipline of Self-knowledge in Augustine’s De trinitate Book
X,” In The Passionate Intellect, ed. Lewis Ayres (London: Rutgers Press 1995), 261–
296; Rowan Williams, “The Paradoxes of Self-Knowledge in Augustine’s Trinitarian
Thought” in On Augustine (London: Bloomsbury Continuum 2016), 155–170.
De Trin. 9.7. I have used the translation by Edmund Hill, The Trinity (New York: New
City Press, 1991).
De Trin. 9.8.
Perichoresis is a theological term of art describing the “necessary being-in-one-another
or circumincession of the three divine Persons of the Trinity because of the single
divine essence, the eternal procession of the Son from the Father and of the Spirit
from the Father and (through) the Son, and the fact that the three Persons are distinguished solely by the relations of opposition between them.” “Perichoresis,” in
Dictionary of Theology, ed. Karl Rahner and Herbert Vorgrimler (New York: Crossroad, 1987), 377. The term likely derives from the Stoic notion of mixture, krasis
di’holon, whereby two or more substances wholly interpenetrate one another while
preserving their distinct properties. Cf. August Deneffe, “Perichoresis, circumincessio, circuminsessio. Eine terminologische Untersuchung,” Zeitschrift furkatholische
Theologie 47 (1923): 497–532. The first Christian theological use of perichoresis is not
trinitarian, but Christological. Gregory Nazianzen uses the term to describe what
will be codified at Chalcedon (451) as the communicatio idiomata. He writes, “Just as
the natures are mixed (kirnamenon), so also the names pass reciprocally (perichorouson) into each other by the principle of this coalescence (sumphuias)” (ep. 101 [PG
37.181C]). In the seventh century, Pseudo-Cyril uses the term perichoresis in reference to trinitarian relations. The three hypostases share a common essence differing
only according to their mode of origin. Further, while being undivided and unconfused, they “‘possess coinherence in each other’ (ten en allelais perichoresin echousai)
(De Trin. 10 [PG 77.1144B]). John of Damascus seems to have been familiar with
Pseudo-Cyril’s use of the term. In the De fide orthodoxa, Damascene maintains that the
three Persons of the Holy Trinity “are made one not so as to commingle, but so as to
cleave to each other, and they have their being in each other (kai ten en allelais perichoresin) without any coalescence or commingling” (De fide orthodoxa 1.8 [PG 94.829A]).
The application of perichoresis shifts in its technical theological usage from serving
to articulate a Christology of two natures to articulating trinitarian relations. What
is retained, however, is the initial (Stoic) sense of term as preserving distinct and
123
124
logos
21.
22.
23.
24.
diverse characteristics within a common unity. Cf. John Egan, “Toward Trinitarian
Perichoresis: Saint Gregory the Theologian, Oration 31.14,” The Greek Orthodox Theological Review 39 (1994): 83–93; Daniel Stramara, “Gregory of Nyssa’s terminology
for trinitarian perichoresis,” Vigiliae Christianae 52 (1998): 257–263; Karen Kilby,
“Perichoresis and Projection: Problems with Social Doctrines of the Trinity,” New
Blackfriars 81 (2000): 432–445; Randall Otto, “The Use and Abuse of Perichoresis in
Recent Theology,” Scottish Journal of Theology 54 (2001): 366–384.
De Trin. 9.8. Cf. De Trin. 10.11.18: “These three then, memory, understanding, and
will, are not three lives but one life, not three minds but one mind. . . . Therefore
since they are each and all and wholly contained by each, they are each and all equal
to each and all, and each and all equal to all of them together, and these three are one,
one life, one mind, one being.” In the words of Etienne Gilson, “The consubstantiality, at least the relative consubstantiality, of the elements constituting these created
trinities [in the soul] enables us to obtain some idea of the real consubstantiality of the
three Persons in the Trinity.” Etienne Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine
(New York: Random House, 1960), 219. Gilson continues, “The distinctive feature
of this first image is that it unfolds entirely within the substance of the mens before it
appears in acts. The thing which guarantees the substantial unity of the mens with its
love and knowledge is also the basis for the substantiality of its knowledge and love.
If self-love and self-knowledge were in the mind as accidents in a subject, the mind
could only know or love itself, but the fact is that it can love and know anything else.
Therefore it is not a mind which has a knowledge or love itself; it is a mind which
is love and knowledge substantially and therefore naturally capable of knowing and
loving itself pending the time when it will love and know everything else. And vice
versa, the love and knowledge the mind has of itself are substances in virtue of their
being its substance. There substantiality is born of their consubstantiality, and this is
the reason why these three terms constitute a trinity.” Ibid., 220–221.
John Carroll, Exiles of Eternity (Inf.); Prisoners of Hope (Purg.); In Patria (Par.) (London:
Hodder and Stoughton, 1904–1911). Basile Kelly articulates how Augustinian interiority underwrites Par. 33 and that to achieve the vision of the Trinity, the pilgrim
must first perceive the trinity within. She writes, “The light of the Triune God activates a seemingly reciprocal transformation. The Trinity itself is of course perfect,
never changing, and so we must understand that the pilgrim himself must experience participation and inner transformation in order to perceive it. According to
Augustine, man comes to know God through his own mind, through the impression
of the Trinity that exists in the mind. Similarly, the pilgrim perceives the Triune God
by experiencing an interior change and recognition, mirroring the visual transformation of the Trinity within his mind.” Basile Kelly, “Vanni Fucci as Infernal Adam,”
45–46.
John Carroll, In Patria.
Charles Singleton, The Divine Comedy, Translated, with a Commentary (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press,1970–1975).
augustine’s trinitarian theology in dante’s paradiso 33
25. Cf. περιχωρέω in Liddell and Scott, Greek-English Lexicon (1940) and Slobodan
Stamatović, “Perichoresis,” Open Theology 2 (2016): 303–323.
26. Perichoresis and choreography are, in fact, false cognates that are frequently confused. Although they appear etymologically related (and a “divine dance” seems a
wonderful expression of trinitarian perichoresis), χορεύω is the Greek verb “to
dance” while χωρέω is another verb altogether expressing backward and forward
movement. Χωρέω entails “to go back:” or “withdraw” and “go forward” or “proceed.” Cf. Slobodan Stamatović, “Perichoresis,” Open Theology 2 (2016): 303–323.
27. Translating indova as “where” is an excellent choice. Dante coins the verb “indova”
from the adverb dove.
28. In a similar vein, John Took argues that a fundamental existential convergence is discerned in Dante and Augustine: “Dante’s theology, like Augustine’s, is the theology of
becoming. It focuses, not simply, nor ever primarily, on the nature of God in himself
(the whole enterprise thus resolving itself in an act of understanding), but on the
notion of oneness with God as existential possibility. . . . It entails, over and above
the act of understanding, the act of commitment, the risk and irrationality of choice;
hence, in Dante, the purposefulness of the whole undertaking. There is no time to
be lost. There can be no dallying over past distractions, no waylaying of the spirit
by pleasures apt to detain and to divert it. All instead is dedication, Dante’s concept of human experience flowing characteristically into the categories of struggle
and of arduous ascent. John Took, “Dante and the ‘Confessions’ of Augustine,” Annali
d’Italianistica 8 (1990): 378.
29. De Trin. 14.17.23: “For only when it comes to the perfect vision of God will this
image bear God’s perfect likeness.”
30. De Trin. 14.16.22.
31. De Trin. 7.6.12. Augustine readily avails himself of these Pauline texts in his account
of the restoration of the image. Cf. De Trin. 12.7.12; De Trin. 14.18.24. See MarieAnne Vannier, “Creatio,” “Conversio,” “Formatio” chez S. Augustin (Fribourg: Éditions Universitaires Fribourg, 1991).
32. De Trin. 14.17.23.
125
Copyright of Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought & Culture is the property of Logos: A
Journal of Catholic Thought & Culture and its content may not be copied or emailed to
multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission.
However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.