Nat Lang Linguist Theory
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-021-09502-5
Distributionally restricted items
Acquisition and beyond
Jing Lin1 · Fred Weerman1 · Hedde Zeijlstra2
Received: 4 December 2017 / Accepted: 6 January 2021
© The Author(s) 2021
Abstract This paper explores the learnability of English indefinite any, Dutch modal
verb hoeven, and Mandarin Chinese (WH-)indefinite/pronoun shenme. These three
expressions, belonging to different syntactic categories in different languages, have
been referred to as Negative Polarity Items (NPIs) in the literature, as they are all restricted to contexts that in some sense count as negative although there are differences
in the types of semantic environment that may license them. By investigating the distribution of these three expressions in both child and child-directed speech recorded in
the CHILDES database (MacWhinney 2009), this paper argues that children in their
acquisition of these NPIs employ the same conservative widening learning strategy
(Berwick and Weinberg 1986; Manzini and Wexler 1987), which prevents them from
overgeneration. A two-stage acquisition process is detected for each of the three NPIs.
However, distinct learning pathways are found, which we take as evidence indicating
different underlying analyses of these expressions at different stages in child language. Taking into consideration the input characteristics, the distributional patterns
of the three expressions in adult grammar, and the children’s lexical development,
we hypothesize what the analyses of any, hoeven, and shenme at different acquisition
stages look like. This provides us with a different view of the nature, or the reason
underlying the restricted distribution of these expressions in adult language.
Keywords Conservative widening · Corpus research · Cross-linguistics semantics ·
Distributional constraints · Language acquisition · Learnability
B J. Lin
[email protected]
F. Weerman
[email protected]
H. Zeijlstra
[email protected]
1
University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, Netherlands
2
University of Göttingen, Göttingen, Germany
J. Lin et al.
1 Introduction
It is common that natural languages exhibit expressions that cannot freely occur in
all kinds of configurations. Polarity items are examples of such expressions. Take the
English expression in years for example, which is a Negative Polarity Item (hereafter
NPI), typically allowed in negative sentences like (1a) and (1b), but not in simple affirmative statements like shown in (1c). Another example is English adverb already,
which is a Positive Polarity Item (hereafter PPI), and is allowed in affirmative sentences like (2a) but not in those that include a negative marker like (2b) and (2c),
contrary to NPIs like in years.
(1)
a. John hasn’t seen his aunt in years.
b. Nobody has worn bootcut jeans in years.
c. *I have used Windows laptops in years.
(2)
a. John already finished his dissertation.
b. *John didn’t not already visit the factory.
c. *Nobody already visited the factory.
The existence of such expressions gives rise to a learnability problem for languageacquiring children. As is generally agreed in the literature, language acquisition takes
place based on positive evidence only; that is, what children encounter in their language input (e.g. Pinker 1984, 1995) (Baker and McCarthy 1981; Berwick 1985;
Braine 1971; Chomsky and Lasnik 1977; Manzini and Wexler 1987; Marcus 1993;
Marcus et al. 1992; Grimshaw 1981; Gropen et al. 1991; Pinker 1984, 1995, 2013;
Guasti 2017; among many others). However, the absence of an expression in particular contexts does not necessarily indicate its impossibility in the target grammar.
Children are therefore expected to make overgeneralization errors, which eventually
need to be unlearnt. Unlearning overgeneralization errors would require the child
to be systematically confronted with direct negative evidence, i.e. corrective feedback from parents or an explicit denial of a child’s ungrammatical utterance, though
(Baker and McCarthy 1981; Marcus 1993; among others). However, such evidence
has been shown to have little effect on language acquisition (Braine 1971; Baker and
McCarthy 1981; Grimshaw 1981; Pinker 1984, 1995, 2013; Berwick 1985; Manzini
and Wexler 1987; among others). This means that distributionally constrained expressions should be acquired by the child in such a way that they are learnable based
on positive evidence only, and are at the same time not vulnerable to loss from generations to generations—otherwise they would no longer form a common phenomenon
in natural languages. The question that then arises is how children are able to acquire
the distribution patterns of expressions like NPIs without making overgeneralization
errors (see Lin et al. 2015 for a fine-grained description and motivation for the learnability problem).
Answering this question does not only help us understand the learning mechanism
that children may employ in their acquisition of distributionally restricted expressions. It also sheds light on the reasons underlying these distributional constraints,
as they must already be reflected in the child’s grammar during the acquisition process. We explore this question by investigating the acquisition of three such items,
Distributionally restricted items
belonging to different syntactic categories, in three different languages. They are English indefinite any, Dutch modal verb hoeven ‘need’, and Mandarin Chinese (WH-)
indefinite/pronoun shenme ‘any/what’, which all have been categorised as NPIs in
the literature—at least in certain usages. By analysing the distribution of these three
words in both child speech and child-directed speech recorded in the CHILDES
database (MacWhinney 2009), we will hypothesize for each of the expressions a possible learning trajectory in which children step-by-step develop a target-like analysis
based on the language input.
We organize the paper as follows. Section 2 introduces the constrained distributions of the three to-be-investigated expressions in detail, followed by a theoretical
discussion of the learning strategy that we hypothesize children to employ in their
acquisition of distributionally constrained items. Section 3 introduces our methodology. Section 4 reports the results, and describes the acquisition patterns generalized based on the results. Section 5 interprets the learning patterns. Section 6 concludes.
2 Background
2.1 The target expressions of investigation
As already mentioned in Sect. 1, English indefinite any, Dutch modal verb hoeven,
and Mandarin Chinese (WH-)indefinite/pronoun shenme are the three target expressions to be investigated in the current research. There are a number of reasons why
these three expressions are selected as the targets of investigation. First of all, these
expressions, although they may appear to be unrelated at first sight, have all been categorised as NPIs in the literature (see e.g. Ladusaw 1979, 1996; Kadmon and Landman
1993; Krifka 1995; Horn 1996, 2000, 2005 for any; see Zwarts 1981, 1986, 1995;
van der Wouden 1997; among others for hoeven; see for instance Cheng 1994, 1995;
Lin 1996, 1998; Lin 2017 for shenme). However, there are differences in terms of
both their licensing contexts, and their functions or meanings when appearing in different kinds of negative contexts. The similarity and the differences between these
expressions, together with the fact that they represent different syntactic categories
and are taken from different languages, ensure a representative sample. This may
help us detect possible universalities underlying the learning paths of such expressions.
In addition to these above-mentioned reasons, there are two more methodological
advantages of our selection of these three words. One concerns the high frequency
of these expressions in child speech, even among children who are younger than
three years. Generally, expressions that are associated with restricted distributions
like NPIs are not attested that frequently in (early) child language (see for example
van der Wal 1996). The frequent appearance of any, hoeven, and shenme in child
language thus enables us to explore their whole developmental trajectory. Another
methodological advantage of the current selection of the targets of investigation concerns the sufficiently large size of the subdatasets of Dutch, English, and Mandarin
Chinese in the CHILDES database (MacWhinney 2009). This enables us to collect
J. Lin et al.
statistically representative data, and draw statistically valid generalizations or conclusions.
In this section, we introduce the three target expressions in turn. As mentioned,
they have all been categorised as NPIs in the literature. However, from the child’s
perspective, a label like NPI does not exist a priori. Children do not have any innate
knowledge of which lexical items in a particular language are and are not NPIs. It is in
fact the task of the child to figure out, based on the language input, which expressions
are subject to a restricted distribution to negative environments, and how to analyse
them. But before doing that, we first introduce four types of negative environments,
which are typically used when describing the distributional constraints of NPIs in
the literature. They are anti-morphic, anti-additive, downward entailing, and nonveridical contexts, of which the first three are defined and categorised in terms of
their subjectiveness to De Morgan’s laws, leaving non-veridicality defined in terms
of truth. We provide the formal definitions of the four notions introduced above in fn.
1 and 2,1,2 and refer the reader to Van der Wouden (1994) and Giannakidou (1997),
among others, for a detailed illustration of the different types of negative contexts.
Informally, these negative environments can be interpreted as follows:
Anti-morphic (hereafter AM) contexts involve operators that generate inferences
obeying both De Morgan’s laws. Sentential negation, such as not in English, is antimorphic, since John does not smoke or drink entails both John does not smoke and
John does not drink and vice versa, and John does not drink and smoke entails John
does not drink or John does not smoke, and vice versa. Compared to AM operators, anti-additive (hereafter AA) operators only respect the second De Morgan’s law.
Typical examples in this respect are negative indefinites. Nobody drinks or smokes
entails both Nobody drinks and nobody smokes, and vice versa; however, Nobody
drinks and smokes does not entail Nobody drinks or nobody smokes. Downward entailing (hereafter DE) contexts refer to those contexts in which the entailment relation
goes from set to subset (Fauconnier 1978, 1980; among others). For instance, seminegative quantifiers like few are downward entailing as Few students have seen birds
entails that Few students have seen robins, but not the other way around. Finally,
non-veridical (hereafter NV) contexts are contexts that do not entail the truth of an
embedded proposition (Zwarts 1995, 1998; Giannakidou 1998, 2011; Giannakidou
and Zwarts 1999). Non-factive verbs such as guess are non-veridical because I guess
that John is ill does not entail the proposition John is ill. In the same vein, epistemic modal adverbs like probably and maybe are non-veridical too. A remark that
we would like to make before introducing the restricted distributions of any, hoeven,
and shenme is that the four types of negative contexts stand in a strict subset rela1 For every arbitrary X, Y of type τ ,t,: if f (X ∩ Y ) ⇔ f (X) ∪ f (Y ) and f (X ∪ Y ) ⇔ f (X) ∩ f (Y ),
then the function f is anti-morphic; iff f (X ∪ Y ) ⇔ f (X) ∩ f (Y ), then the function f is anti-additive;
if f (X ∪ Y ) ⇒ f (X) and/or f (X ∪ Y ) ⇒ f (Y ), then the function f is downward entailing (definitions
adapted from van der Wouden 1997).
2 A propositional operator F is veridical, iff Fp entails p (Fp⇒.p); otherwise F is non-veridical (definition
adapted from Zwarts 1995; see also Giannakidou 1997).
Distributionally restricted items
tionship with each other. The set of AM contexts is a strict subset of the set of AA
contexts, which is a strict subset of the set of DE contexts, which in turn is a strict
subset of the set of NV contexts.
2.1.1 English any
English any is an existential indefinite. As is well observed and discussed in the
literature (Ladusaw 1979, 1996; Kadmon and Landman 1993; Krifka 1995; Horn
1996, 2000, 2005), any is attested in a variety of DE contexts. Some examples are
given in (3) and (4).3 Apart from that, any also appears in (embedded) polar questions
(see (5)), and (embedded) WH-questions (see (6)) (see e.g. Nicolae 2013).
(3)
a.
b.
c.
John did not buy any linguistic books last Friday.
Nobody bought any linguistic books last Friday.
Few students bought any linguistic books last Friday.
(4)
a.
b.
c.
d.
Not everyone bought any linguistic books last Friday.
Only John bought any linguistic books last Friday.
Everyone who bought any linguistic books last Friday is invited to the
party.
If John bought any linguistic books last Friday, he can come to the party.
(5)
a.
b.
Did John buy any linguistic books last Friday?
I wonder if/whether John bought any linguistic books last Friday.
(6)
a.
b.
Who bought any linguistic books last Friday?
I asked the professor who bought any linguistic books last Friday.
Polar and WH-questions, either embedded or appearing as matrix sentences, are
not straightforwardly DE. However, they can be analysed as containing a DE operator. As Guerzoni and Sharvit (2007) illustrate, polar questions are always interpreted as strongly exhaustive (see also Heim 1994; Beck and Rullmann 1999;
Sharvit 2002), and according to Nicolae (2013) always contain a covert only as well
as WH-questions. This covert only renders the question nucleus a downward entailing operator and therefore guarantees any’s occurrence in such questions. Since polar
and WH-questions are not straightforwardly DE, we will separate them from the other
four types of licensing contexts in the current study.
In addition to DE contexts and questions, any is also attested in the scope of epistemic existential modal verbs as well, such as John may buy any linguistic books (he
finds) and You can eat any cookies on the table. Here, however, any has a different
interpretation than when it appears in examples like (3) to (6) above. More specifically, any is associated with a so-called Free Choice interpretation (hereafter FC)
when appearing in the scope of a modal like may, which gives rise to a reading that
John and the addressee are free to choose the book to be bought and the cookie to be
eaten, respectively (Horn 2000; Giannakidou 2001; among others).
3 We follow von Fintel (1999) and categorise exclusive adverbs such as English only and its Dutch counter-
part alleen (see further (9)) as a specific kind of downward entailing contexts (called Strawson downward
entailment).
J. Lin et al.
In other contexts than the ones introduced above, any is not allowed. Simple affirmative sentences such as *John bought any linguistic books last Friday, or sentences
with an epistemic modal adverb such as *John has probably bought any linguistic
books are both ungrammatical. Here, even FC any is not available.
2.1.2 Dutch hoeven
Dutch hoeven is a modal verb expressing strong necessity, and restricted to some
but crucially not all AA or DE contexts (Zwarts 1981, 1986, 1995; Van der Wouden
1994; Hoeksema 2000). For instance, hoeven can appear in the scope of the sentential
negation niet ‘not’, negative indefinites such as niemand ‘nobody’, or in the scope of
zonder ‘without’, see (7a-c), respectively, which are all categorised as at least AA
contexts.4 Recall that any is allowed in these contexts as well—as they are all DE
(see (3), for instance).
(7)
a.
b.
c.
Jan hoeft niet te koken.
John need not to cook
‘John does not have to cook.’
Niemand hoeft te koken.
nobody need to cook
‘Nobody has to cook.’
Jan was klaar zonder te hoeven haasten.
John was finished without to need hurry
‘John finished without having to hurry.’
However, not all AA contexts license hoeven. The restriction of a universal quantifier
or the antecedent clause of a conditional, for instance, do not license the modal verb.
This is illustrated in (8a) and (8b), respectively. Here we see a difference with English
any, which is grammatical in such contexts, as illustrated in (4c) and (4d).
(8)
a. *Iedereen die hoeft te koken moet nu beginnen.
everyone that need to cook must now start
Intended: ‘Everyone that has to cook must start now.’
b. *Als Jan hoeft te koken moet hij nu beginnen.
if John need to cook must he now start
Intended: ‘If John has to cook then he must start now.’
Examples of DE contexts which license hoeven are in the scope of semi-negative operators like zelden ‘seldom’, negative universal expressions such as niet iedereen ‘not
everybody’, or exclusive adverbs like alleen ‘only’, as shown in (9a-d), respectively.
Such contexts license any as well, as previously shown in (4). But questions, polar or
WH-questions, either embedded or appearing as matrix sentences (which license any
as we have shown in (5) and (6)), do not license hoeven. We demonstrate this in (10).
4 Dutch is a SOV language with Verb Second. This means that hoeven is base generated in the sentence-
final position, where it takes scope under a negative operator, even though the modal verb precedes the
negative operator at surface structure due to the verb movement. See Iatridou and Zeijlstra (2013) for more
discussion and arguments that modal verbs such as Dutch hoeven always reconstruct.
Distributionally restricted items
(9)
a.
b.
c.
d.
(10)
Jan hoeft zelden te koken.
John need seldom to cook
‘John seldom has to cook.’
Niet iedereen hoeft in het weekend te koken.
not everybody need in the weekend to cook
‘Not everybody has to cook on the weekends.’
Jan hoeft alleen te koken.
John need only to cook
‘John only has to cook.’
Alleen Jan hoeft te koken.
only John need to cook
‘Only John has to cook.’
a. *Hoeft Jan te koken?
need John to cook
Intended: ‘Does John have to cook?’
b. *Wat hoeft Jan te koken?
what need John to cook
Intended: ‘What does John have to cook?’
Other environments in which hoeven cannot survive concern simple affirmative sentences, a similar observation as reported for English any. In Dutch, sentences like
*Jan hoeft te koken vandaag ‘John has to cook today’ are ungrammatical. As a modal
verb, hoeven is not observed to have FC readings.
Interestingly, hoeven, unlike any, is allowed in the scope of verum focus (VF),
such as wel in Dutch, which we translate as surely in English. Such contrastive markers do not seem to be negative as AM, AA or some DE operators. However, they
are typically used in contexts when one participant of a conversation denies what is
previously asserted, as is illustrated by the dialogue in (11). Partly for this reason,
Hogeweg (2009) analyses wel as a double negation.
(11)
A: Volgens mij hoef je niet te koken vandaag.
according me need you not to cook today
‘I think you don’t have to cook today.’
B: Nee, ik hoef wel te koken, helaas.
no I need VF to cook unfortunately
‘No, unfortunately, I do need to cook.’
2.1.3 Mandarin Chinese shenme
We now introduce Mandarin Chinese shenme, categorised as an existential indefinite,
or an interrogative pronoun, depending on the syntactic and semantic environment in
which it appears. It may have an interrogative reading like English what, but can also
be assigned an existential interpretation similar to English a or some. Shenme even
seems to get a FC-like reading when it appears in the scope of the universal quantifier
dou ‘all’. It is due to this fact that we choose not to translate shenme into English and
we gloss shenme in the examples depending on the contexts.
J. Lin et al.
We start with shenme’s interrogative usage, which is very similar to that of English what. The examples in (12)—a matrix and an embedded question containing
shenme—illustrate this (see for instance Huang 1982; Cheng 1991, 1994; Lin 1996).
(12)
a.
b.
Yuehan mai le shenme shu (ne)?
John buy PER what book Q
‘What kind of book(s) has John bought?’
Wo xiang zhidao Yuehan mai le shenme shu.
I want kno John buy PER what book
‘I wonder what kind of (books) John has bought.’
In addition to (embedded) WH-questions, shenme can also appear in a variety of
NV contexts. Examples of such contexts that license shenme are in the scope of a
sentential negation (AM) (see (13a-b)) or a negative indefinite (AA) (see (13c-d)),
the antecedent clause of a conditional (AA) (see (14a)), the restriction of a universal
quantifier like meige (AA) (see (14b), questions (both polar and WH-ones, see (15)),
and epistemic modal contexts (NV) (see (16)) (Huang 1982; Cheng 1991, 1994; Lin
1996, 1998; Lin et al. 2014, among others). In these examples, shenme functions as
an existential indefinite, and has a reading like English a or some. Moreover, shenme
can also obtain an epistemic interpretation in NV contexts like those illustrated in
(16) (as pointed out by an anonymous reviewer).
(13)
a.
b.
c.
d.
(14)
a.
b.
Yuehan mei mai shenme shu.
John not buy a
book
‘John did not buy (a) book.’
Bie rang ta mai shenme shu.
not let him buy a
book
‘Don’t let him buy (any/a) book(s).’
Zuotian meiren mai shenme shu.
yesterday nobody buy a
book
‘Nobody bought (a) book(s) yesterday.’
Ta congwei mai guo shenme shu.
s/he never buy PER a
book
‘S/he never bought (any/a) book(s) before.’
Ruguo Yuehan gei ni mai guo shenme liwu, ni yiding yao
if
John for you buy PER a
present you certainly should
haohao xiexie ta.
well thank him
‘If John has ever bought a present for you, you should thank him a lot.’
Meige yao gei nvpengyou mai shenme liwu de nansheng dou hui
every want for girlfriend buy a
gift REL boy
all will
dedao ta de yige wen.
get s/he GEN one kiss
‘Every boy that wants to buy a gift for his girlfriend will get a kiss from
her.’
Distributionally restricted items
(15)
a.
b.
(16)
a.
b.
Yuehan mai shenme shu le ma?
John buy some book PER Q
‘Has John bought (any) book?’
Yuehan yao kan duoshao shu cai neng fabiao shenme
John need read how many book then able publish a
wenzhang ne?
paper
Q
‘How many books does John need to read before he can publish a paper?’
Yuehan keneng mai le shenme shu.
John maybe buy PER a/some books
‘Maybe John has bought a/some book(s).’
Yuehan kending mai le shenme shu.
John must
buy PER a/some book
‘John must have bought a/some book(s).’
Next to its interrogative what-reading and existential a/some-reading, shenme can
also obtain a FC-like interpretation in the scope of the universal quantifier dou ‘all’
(see Cheng 1995; Lin 1998; for instance). In this context, shenme seems to have the
same universal reading as every in English, as we show in the two examples in (17).5
(17)
a.
b.
Yuehan shenme shu dou xihuan kan.
John a
book all like read
‘John likes to read every book.’
dou keyi xue zuofan.
Shenme ren
person all can learn cook
a
‘Every person can learn cooking.’
Despite appearance, shenme does not have a real FC reading. Evidence for this comes
from two facts in Mandarin Chinese. One concerns the impossibility of the so-called
FC reading of shenme outside dou-contexts (see (18a) and (18b)); whereas the other
concerns the fact that bare NPs or DPs, when quantified over by dou, also give rise to
a universal FC reading (see (18c) and (18d)).6
(18)
a. *Yuehan shenme shu xihuan kan.
John a
book like read
Intended: ‘John likes to read every book.’
b. *Yuehan xihuan kan shenme shu.
John like read a
book
Intended: ‘John likes to read every book.’
5 As is already established in the Chinese literature, dou is a universal quantifier that quantifies over a
phrase or a clause preceding it (Cheng 1995; Chiu 1990; Lee 1986; Lin 1998; Pan 2006; Wu 1999; Xiang
2008). This means that the restriction of this universal precedes rather than follows it, different from other
universal quantifiers in Mandarin, like meige ‘every’.
6 We thank one of the anonymous reviewers for sharing the first argument with us.
J. Lin et al.
Table 1 Distributions and interpretations of any, hoeven, and shenme
Contexts
any
AM
Non-AM, AA
hoeven
shenme
Yes, existential
Yes
Yes, existential
Yes, existential
Some but not all
Yes, existential
Non-AA, DE
Yes, existential
Some but not all
Yes, existential
Non-DE, NV
No
No
Yes, existential
(Embedded) Polar questions
Yes, existential
No
Yes, existential
(Embedded) WH-questions
Yes, existential
No
Yes, WH or existential
Free Choice contexts
Yes, FC
No
No
Simple affirmative sentences
No
No
No
c.
d.
Yuehan shu dou xihuan kan
John book all like read
‘John likes to read every book.’
Yuehan zhexie shu dou xihuan kan.
John these book all like read
‘John likes to read each of these books.’
The examples in (18), together with those in (17) clearly show that it is not shenme
that gets a FC-like reading when appearing in dou-sentences, but that this universal
interpretation is encoded in the quantifier dou. We therefore do not consider shenme’s
appearance in the scope of dou as an instance of its FC use but rather as having a
regular existential interpretation in an AA context.
As has been well established in the Chinese literature, shenme, when not interpreted as having an interrogative meaning, is ungrammatical in simple affirmative
contexts such as in the perfect tense (Cheng 1994; Li 1992; Lin 1996; Xie 2007; see
also recent work by Chierchia and Liao 2015), as shown in (19).
(19)
*Yuehan zuotian mai le shenme shu.
John yesterday buy PRF a
book
Intended: ‘John has bought (a) book(s) yesterday.’
2.1.4 Summary
We conclude this section by giving an overview of the restricted distributions of any,
hoeven, and shenme in Table 1. Since both any and shenme are subject to different
readings in different contexts, we also include possible interpretations in the table.
2.2 Conservative widening
The existence of distributionally restricted items like any, hoeven, or shenme gives
rise to a learnability problem for language-acquiring children. We refer the reader to
van der Wal (1996); Tieu (2010, 2013); Lin (2015, 2016) for a fine-grained description of this learnability problem, and to Lin et al. (2015) for a detailed argumentation
of why negative evidence, either direct or indirect, has little influence on children’s
Distributionally restricted items
Stage 1: Analysed input in the onset
→
Stage 2: Analysed input that falsifies Analysis 1
→
Stage 3: Analysed input that falsifies Analysis 2
→
...
...
...
Stage n: Analysed input that falsifies Analysis (n-1)
→
Initial analysis
(Analysis 1)
Reanalysis of Analysis 1
(Analysis 2)
Reanalysis of Analysis 2
(Analysis 3)
...
(Analysis (n-1))
Reanalysis of Analysis (n-1)
(Analysis n)
Fig. 1 A learning process under the hypothesis of conservative widening
acquisition of what is impossible in the target language in the particular case of distributionally constrained items. Here we focus on a potential solution to the learnability
problem, namely conservative widening (Manzini and Wexler 1987; see also Snyder
2002, 2007, 2008, 2011; Tieu 2010, 2011).
Conservative widening is a general learning mechanism that can be best defined in
terms of the Subset Principle (Manzini and Wexler 1987): “Briefly, the subset principle demands that a learning procedure should guess the narrowest possible language,
consistent with positive evidence seen so far. By hypothesizing as narrow a target
language as possible, the acquisition procedure is protected from disastrous overgeneralisation” (Berwick and Weinberg 1986:233).
Under the hypothesis of conservative widening, language acquisition is predicted
to exhibit several developmental stages. Children start with the strictest possible analysis of their target language, based on the limited input data that they are able to
perceive and analyse in the acquisition onset. This analysis may not be identical to
the target one but it is at least compatible with all the input data a child has been
able to analyse so far. However, such a strict, narrow analysis can be easily falsified
by more input data analysed by the child in a succeeding stage. This will then lead
language learners to weaken down the initial analysis and to construct a reanalysis
explaining the input data perceived and processed in both stages. Such an iterative
process continues until children arrive at an analysis that explains all input data. The
above-sketched learning process under the hypothesis of conservative widening is
schematically illustrated in Fig. 1.
Figure 1 clearly illustrates how children are able to acquire the distributional constraints of particular expressions, such as NPIs, without any explicit instruction or
correction, by first building an initial analysis based on limited input data that they
are able to analyse in the onset, and then gradually refining this analysis upon perceiving and analyzing ever more data from the input. Note that we do not assume
substantial changes or differences in the input data that children receive at different stages. However, we do assume that the child’s cognitive and linguistic ability to
analyse the input improves and develops over time.
The question is still open as to how children make the very first step in their acquisition of an expression that is restricted in its distribution. We here take the children’s
establishment of their initial analysis to be solely input-based in a similar way as has
been proposed for category learning via a distributional approach (Cartwright and
J. Lin et al.
Brent 1997; Mintz 2002; Mintz et al. 2002; Redington et al. 1998). We upgrade the
conservative widening learning strategy by adopting Mintz (2002, 2003) and Mintz et
al. (2002) in that a distribution-based learning mechanism plays a crucial role in early
language acquisition. In the absence of innate knowledge about which expressions in
their target language are subject to certain distributional constraints, children’s first
attempt to analyse such items can only be guided by investigating positive evidence
available in the beginning of acquisition in terms of distributional properties, either
linguistic (such as semantic properties of licensing contexts) or statistical in nature
(e.g. frequency, or co-occurrence frequency in the input).
Conservative widening gives rise to three predictions when we look at the acquisition of distributionally restricted words such as English any, Dutch hoeven, and Mandarin Chinese shenme. First, we expect children not to overgeneralize these words in
those contexts that do not license them in the target grammar in any developmental
stage. Second, we predict the distribution of these words to be more restricted in early
than in late child language. This is because the set of the output of an analysis at a
certain stage is always a subset of the set of the output of its reanalysis in a subsequent
stage. Our third prediction is that these words in early child language are restricted
only to those types of semantic environment contexts that are most frequently attested
as their licensing contexts in the language input.
3 Methodology
For an overview of the acquisition of these different distributionally constrained
items, we carried out an extensive search in the CHILDES database (MacWhinney
2009). A total of 2940 CHAT files containing spontaneous speech data of monolingual children under the age of six have been analysed. For English any, a total of 1492
CHAT files containing spontaneous speech data of 145 monolingual children between
one and five years old were analysed. Data were collected from the following British
English corpora in CHILDES: Belfast (Henry 1995; Wilson and Henry 1998), Cruttenden (Cruttenden 1978), Fletcher (Crystal et al. 1989; Fletcher and Garman 1988;
Karmiloff-Smith 1986), Forrester (Forrester 2002), Howe (Howe 1981), Lara (Rowland and Fletcher 2006), Manchester (Theakston et al. 2001), Thomas-Heritage
(Lieven et al. 2009), and Wells (Wells 1981).
For Mandarin shenme, three subcorpora in CHILDES for data collection were
investigated: Beijing 2 (Tardif 1993, 1996), Zhou 1 (Zhou 2004a), and Zhou 2 (Zhou
2004b). This provided a total of 734 CHAT files including spontaneous speech data
of more than 40 monolingual Mandarin children aged between one and five.
As for Dutch hoeven, we examined spontaneous speech data of 59 monolingual
children between one and five years old recorded in a total of 710 CHAT files in the
following subcorpora: BolKuiken (Bol and Kuiken 1990),7 CLPF (Fikkert 1994; Levelt 1994), Groningen (Wijnen and Bol 1993), Schaerlaekens (Schaerlaekens 1973),
VanKampen (van Kampen 1994), and Wijnen (Wijnen 1988, 1992; Elbers and Wijnen
1992).
7 Only typically developing children recorded in this subcorpus were included.
Distributionally restricted items
Among the 59 Dutch children investigated, merely two of them were longitudinally recorded for the whole age range examined in the current research, namely
Sarah and Laura in VanKampen (van Kampen 1994). Out of the 145 English children
studied in this paper, only 16 children were longitudinally recorded from approximately one and a half years old to before their fifth birthday: the participants in Wells
(Wells 1981). As for the Mandarin children included in our research, no longitudinal
data were available. We therefore opted for a cross-sectional analysis of child data
for all three words.
The procedure of our corpus research is as follows. We first divided all children
in each language into different groups depending on their age of recording, creating
three age groups distinguished in the current study: AG I (one- and two-year-olds),
AG II (three-year-olds), and AG III (four-year-olds).8,9 Afterwards, we counted the
frequency of each target expression per age group in each language by employing the
freq-command of the CLAN program in the CLAN CHAT files. For any and shenme,
” (shenme in characters),
the target form searched in CHILDES was “any” and “
whereas for hoeven, all its three inflected forms of the present tense plus its infinitive
form were taken into consideration, namely hoef (HOEVEN -1 SG), hoeft (HOEVEN 2/3 SG), and hoeven (HOEVEN - PL / INF).
All utterances containing the target expressions were then judged for their grammaticality status by using the kwal-command. Generally, three lines of context preceding and following an utterance containing the target words were analysed to evaluate their grammaticality status (see below), by adding “+w3” and “−w3” to the
command. Contextual information was sometimes necessary because a child could
be interrupted by, for instance, another participant of the conversation when he or she
was uttering a sentence containing one of the target words. If a total of six lines of
context were not sufficient in such cases, more contextual data were checked manually. Five categories regarding grammaticality were distinguished in this respect:
grammatical use, ungrammatical use, self-correction, unclear use, and contrastive
use.
Grammatical use refers to child utterances in which the target expression appeared
in a proper context; the category of ungrammatical use covers utterances containing
the target words in the absence of a proper context. If children substituted the target
word by another word that is not subject to any distributional constraints after first uttering the target, it was counted as an instance of self-correction. If it was impossible
to analyse the grammaticality status of the target words after taking both linguistic
environment and available contextual information into account, it counted as unclear
use. Child utterances containing target expressions appearing in the scope of verum
8 The current study chose the chronological age at recording to benchmark children’s acquisition stages.
Another alternative would be the Mean Length of Utterance (MLU), in either morphemes or words. As far
as we understand, however, MLU is mainly employed to distinguish atypically developing children from
their typically developing counterparts (see, for instance, Bishop and Adams 1990; Nippold 1990; Nippold
and Schwarz 2002) or to indicate language proficiency of children in early language development, i.e.
before approximately three and a half years old (Leonard 2014, among others). Since all of our participants
were typically developing children up to the age of five, we chose not to use MLU. Moreover, MLU is not
a reliable indicator in cross-linguistic research due to its cross-linguistic differences.
9 We did not separate a distinct age group of children of one year old at the moment of recording, because
those children rarely produce the target words.
J. Lin et al.
focus (used to deny the previous assertion) were labelled as contrastive use. Examples of each category are given in Appendix 1; the category of contrastive use was
only applicable in the case of Dutch. See further Sect. 2.1.2.
Finally, the child utterances containing grammatically uttered target words were
further categorized for their semantic environments. Here we adopted the classification of different types of negative contexts introduced in Sect. 2. Since any is sometimes also assigned a FC interpretation, when appearing in, for instance, the scope of
an epistemic modal verb, we extend our semantic analysis by including such contexts
as well. Thus, the notions we employed for data categorisation are: anti-morphic contexts (AM), anti-additive but not anti-morphic contexts (non-AM, AA), downward
entailing but not anti-additive contexts (non-AA, DE), polar questions, WH questions, other non-veridical contexts that are not DE (non-DE, NV), and FC-inducing
contexts (FC).
In order to investigate the role of input, we investigated the distribution of the
three target expressions in the corresponding child-directed speech in the selected
CHILDES subcorpora as well. A similar procedure as described above was followed
when analysing the input data. Since the frequency of shenme and any was extremely
high in child-directed speech in the selected subcorpora, we decided, due to practical
limitations, to only analyse their distribution based on approximately 1000 utterances
containing these words, which were randomly selected in the adult speech towards
children of different ages.
4 Results and analysis
We start with the distribution of any, hoeven, and shenme in the child-direct speech.
Absolute and relevant frequency data of the language input are given in Table 2, per
language/expression. Since we do not find any instances of ungrammatically used
any, hoeven, or shenme in the child-direct speech, we only report their distribution
in the input depending on the semantic environments in which they are attested. Raw
input data are given in Appendix 2 (Tables 5, 6, 7).
As already introduced in Sect. 2.1, any, hoeven, and shenme differ in the exact
semantic environments that may license them. Their distributional differences are
clearly reflected by the input data in Table 2. Shenme is found in various NV contexts
including polar and WH-questions; whereas any is predominantly attested in different DE environments plus questions, and hoeven is only found in some AA or DE
contexts. In addition, the data collected in the child-directed speech also give rise to
different types of semantic contexts in which the NPIs are most frequently attested.
In child-directed English, the most frequently attested contexts in which any is uttered are AM contexts and polar questions. Dutch hoeven is most frequently attested
in AM contexts, and in child-directed Mandarin, shenme is most frequently attested
as a WH-term.
We proceed with presenting data collected in child speech. Frequency data of the
target expressions of investigation depending on the grammaticality status are presented per age group per expression in Table 3. These data clearly show that children
of all languages are aware of the restricted distribution of the relevant expressions.
Distributionally restricted items
Table 2 Distribution of any,
hoeven, and shenme in
child-directed speech
Contexts
any
hoeven
shenme
AM
600
299
0
57.7%
80.8%
Non-AM, AA
Non-AA, DE
Polar questions
15
57
1.4%
15.4%
0
46
14
8
4.4%
3.8%
0.8%
336a
0
3
32.3%
0.3%
5b
WH-questions
0
976
0.5%
97.7%
Non-DE, NV
0
0
12
FC
38
0
0
370
999
1.2%
a Among these 336 utterances,
there are 36 instances containing
any in embedded polar questions
b Two of these instances were
3.7%
Total
1040
embedded WH-interrogatives
Table 3 Distribution of any, hoeven, and shenme in child language by grammaticality status
any
Grammatical use
Ungrammatical use
hoeven
AG II
AG III
AG I
AG II
AG III
AG I
AG II
AG III
328
196
150
107
72
49
55
176
386
98.4%
100%
100%
92.5%
88.8%
96.1%
100%
99.4%
100%
2
0
0
1
1
0
0
0
0
0.9%
1.2%
2
1
1
0
0
0
1.7%
1.2%
1.9%
3
4
1
1
0
2.6%
4.9%
1.9%
4
3
0
0
0
0
3.4%
3.7%
117
81
51
55
177
386
0.6%
Self-correction
0
0
0
Unclear
3
0
0
use
1%
Contrastive
0
0
0
use
Total
shenme
AG I
333
196
150
0
0.6%
This awareness appears to be present already at the onset of language acquisition,
as there are virtually no utterances containing ungrammatically used any, hoeven, or
shenme even in Age Group I. Ungrammatical appearance does not even add to more
than 2% of the overall cases in all age groups and languages. This finding confirms
our first prediction: children make no overgeneralization errors of the distributionally
restricted words (see Sect. 2.2).
We now continue with the distribution of the three target expressions in child language development in terms of their semantic licensing environments. Results are
summarized in Table 4.
J. Lin et al.
Table 4 Distribution of any, hoeven, and shenme in child language by semantic contexts
any
AM
Non-AM, AA
Non-AA, DE
hoeven
AG II
248
152
108
101
67
42
1
5
15
75.6%
77.6%
72%
99%
98.5%
85.7%
1.8%
2.8%
3.9%
0
1
0
5
0
0
0
2
3
0.6%
1.5%
0
0
AG III
AG I
WH-questions
Non-DE, NV
AG II
1%
7
0
67
37
25
20.4%
18.9%
16.7%
7
1
1
2.1%
0.5%
0.7%
0
0
0
AG III
AG I
AG II
AG III
10%
1
2
1
1
3
1.5%
4%
1.8%
0.6%
0.8%
0
0
0
0
0
0
0
0
0
53
170
335
96.4%
96.6%
86.8%
0
0
4.7%
Polar questions
shenme
AG I
0
0
0
30
7.8%
FC
Total
4
3
10
1.2%
1.5%
6.7%
328
196
150
N.A.
N.A.
N.A.
N.A.
N.A.
N.A.
102
68
49
55
176
386
Based on the raw data presented in Table 4, we carried out a two-sided Fisher’s
Exact Test to examine any significant differences in the distribution of each of the
three target words in different age groups, under the assumption of no individual
difference with respect to children’s employment of any, hoeven, and shenme.10 We
used this test since there were quite a number of cells in Table 4 (based on which a
contingency table was generated) containing a frequency value smaller than 5.
Results of the significance tests show that the distribution of all the three target
expressions attested in different semantic environments does not significantly differ
between AG I (one- and two-year-olds) and AG II (three-year-olds) (p = .487 in
English; p = .638 in Dutch; and p = .662 in Mandarin). This means that we have
no statistical evidence showing that the two chronological age groups, i.e. AG I and
AG II, represent two distinct developmental stages in the acquisition of the three expressions. We therefore group AG I and II together and compare the data of children
younger than the age of four and those of their older counterparts with the same kind
of statistic test. In all three languages, we find a significant difference (p = .000 in
English; p = .001 in Dutch; and p = .000 in Mandarin) between children under the
age of four and their older counterparts. This result suggests a development in how
they use any, hoeven, and shenme when older than four years.
10 Fisher’s exact test is a statistical test for significance in analyzing contingency tables, which is used
when one or more cells of the contingency table contains a value smaller than 5. This test is employed
when one aims to examine any significant relationships between categorial variables, for example. In our
research, we would like to find out whether the distribution of the NPIs attested at different ages were
related to each other, which can shed light on any significant development in the child’s knowledge of the
NPIs. Therefore, we employed this test.
Distributionally restricted items
Fig. 2 Distribution of any in early and late child English
Fig. 3 Distribution of hoeven in early and late child Dutch
Such results provide evidence for two distinct phases in the acquisition of the
three expressions, all with age four as a boundary, which further suggests that the
development of children’s knowledge of any, hoeven, and shenme has two stages:
an early stage and a late stage. Given this finding, we re-report the corpus data in
Table 4 in Figs. 2 to 4. The bars in each graph stand for the two distinct stages in child
language development. The different shades and patterns in these bars represent the
different semantic environments in which the words are attested. 11
As is clearly illustrated in Figs. 2 to 4, the acquisition of the three distributionally restricted items all turn out to have two developmental stages. Moreover, we
find that in early child language, all of the three expressions are only used in one
or two semantic contexts, whereas at the subsequent stage, they are systematically
used in more types of semantic environments. This is evident when we compare the
shaded/patterned areas in the two bars in each of the figures. The significant differences attested between children under the age of four and those above this age in
all the three languages mean that older children utter any, hoeven, and shenme in
significantly more types of semantic contexts than at the early stage. These findings
11 As a critical reader may notice, there is a drop of the total frequency of any and hoeven from the initial
stage to the subsequent stage. This drop of N in the relevant languages is explained by grouping AG I and
II together and also by the fact that there were a lot more chat files available of 2- and 3-year-olds than 4and/or 5-year-olds in the investigated English and Dutch corpora in the CHILDES database.
J. Lin et al.
Fig. 4 Distribution of shenme in early and late child Mandarin
confirm the second prediction that we motivated under the hypothesis of conservative
widening.
When we zoom in at the shade/pattern of the bars in one figure to those in another, we see that the semantic environments in which the three target expressions
are attested in early and late child language differ from expression to expression. Figure 2 shows that English children below the age of four systematically use any in
the scope of not (AM contexts) (78.6%); they also show evidence for polar questions
in any-licensing (18.7%) (see Tieu 2010 for a similar developmental pattern). Older
children are capable of using any in more types of semantic contexts, such as in FCinducing contexts with an FC interpretation (6.7%), and various DE contexts that are
not not-sentences or polar questions (5%), such as conditional clauses.
As for Dutch hoeven, its acquisition pathway is different. As illustrated in Fig. 3,
hoeven is only attested in the scope of sentential negation niet ‘not’ (AM contexts;
98.9%) at the early stage, whereas in late child Dutch, it is also used in the scope of
a number of non-AM, AA operators (10.2%), such as negative indefinites like niks
‘nothing’ or geen ‘none’ (see also Lin et al. 2015).
Compared to English any and Dutch hoeven, shenme in Mandarin Chinese exhibits a very distinct learning path (see Fig. 4). At the early stage, Mandarin children
virtually only use shenme as a WH-term (96.5%), whereas their older counterparts
also use shenme in different non-DE, NV contexts (13.2%), like the ones introduced
by an epistemic modal adverb (see also Lin et al. 2014).
Zooming in on the distributions of any, hoeven, and shenme in child language
with their distribution in the language input (Table 2), it is clear that at the early
stage of acquisition, these three words are all restricted to those semantic contexts in
which they are most frequently attested in the language input. This confirms our third
prediction made under conservative widening (see Sect. 2.2).
5 Interpretation
Our presentation and description of the corpus and statistical results in the previous section confirm all the three predictions made under the hypothesis of conservative widening. We therefore conclude that children, cross-linguistically, employ the
conservative widening learning strategy (Berwick and Weinberg 1986; Manzini and
Distributionally restricted items
Wexler 1987; see also Snyder 2002, 2007, 2008, 2011) in their acquisition of distributionally restricted words. The adoption of a distribution-, frequency-based learning
model (Cartwright and Brent 1997; Mintz 2002; Mintz et al. 2002; Redington et al.
1998) at the early stages helps children make the first step in acquiring distributionally restricted items. Moreover, the results reported and analysed in Sect. 4 give rise
to two distinct stages in the acquisition of any, hoeven, and shenme. By assuming
these two stages to be associated with two distinct analyses of these words in child
language, namely an initial analysis and a reanalysis at the early and the late stage,
respectively, we discuss in this section what these analyses can be. Note that although
conservative widening learning is generalizable to other distributionally constrained
expressions (in other languages), we do not presume there to necessarily be a twostage acquisition process for every such word.
5.1 English any
In order to understand the children’s initial analysis of any, restricting its appearance
to sentences containing not and polar questions, more needs to be said about the
semantics of polar questions in the grammar of a young child. More concretely, what
do polar questions containing any represent in early child language? We therefore
analysed the polar questions containing any uttered by English two- and three-yearolds (i.e. children at the early stage), and the context in which such polar questions
are attested. All together, we find 96 polar questions with any in early child language,
of which at least 72.9% seem to convey a negative bias: 15.6% exhibit a negative
answer indicated by the child her/himself, and 57.3% are responded to by parents
or investigators with either a negative answer (27.1% direct; 17.7% indirect) or a
positive answer with counterevidence (12.5%)—two kinds of felicitous responses
associated with negatively biased polar questions (Krifka 1995; van Rooij 2003; see
Table 9 in Appendix 4 for the detailed categorisation and frequency data).
At the same time, polar questions without any do not tend to convey such a bias in
early child language. An investigation of 103 polar questions without any randomly
selected in early child English shows that in only 25.2% of the cases are such questions possible with a negative bias (see Table 10 in Appendix 4 for relevant data).
A comparison of the response patterns observed with polar questions with and
without any (i.e. Tables 9 and 10 in Appendix 4, respectively) leads us to conclude
that polar questions containing any express a negative bias in early child language.
This gives rise to an assumption that the early child grammar (not the adult grammar)
associates polar questions containing any only with a negative meaning.12 Following
12 This assumption may raise a question of where the negative bias of polar questions containing any in the
early child grammar comes from. We do not have an explicit answer or a detailed proposal here. However,
we assume that the emergence of the negative bias in polar questions containing any is triggered by an
interesting characteristic of the input data directed towards English children under the age of four. We find
that about one in every five negative statements containing any in the scope of the sentential negation not
in the input, i.e. 78 out of 408, is marked by a positive tag question as shown below. The ages given in the
examples below indicate the ages of the children towards which the utterances were addressed.
(i)
You don’t like any fruit, do you?
(Theakston et al. 2001:joel09b.cha: line 1598)
(02;01.23)
J. Lin et al.
the semantics of polar questions proposed in Hamblin (1973) and the analysis of
polar questions with a negative bias proposed in Asher and Reese (2005), we assume
that the meaning of a negatively biased polar question with any uttered by English
two- and three-year-olds is the set {¬(. . . any . . . ), ¬¬(. . . any . . . )}.13 Under this
assumption, we see that any stays in the scope of a logical negation in each element
of a negatively biased polar question, just like when it appears in the scope of not—
the phonological realisation of ¬. In the first stage any must thus be analysed as an
element that is required to take immediate scope under a semantic negation.
Now the question arises as to how children reanalyse any to an element that is
restricted to DE contexts, including polar questions, as we attested in late child language. The occurrence of any in other kinds of DE contexts triggers the reanalysis
but it does not explain what alternative analysis must be invoked. Here, we focus on
another property of any, namely its competition with other indefinites. Although the
children’s initial analysis of any only allows the indefinite to appear in the immediate
scope of not, this position is not restricted to any in early child English. As indicated
by the child utterances below, next to any (as in (20a)), bare NPs (as in (20b)) and
NPs modified by a plain indefinite (as in (20c)) are also good in negative clauses
introduced by not.
(20)
a.
b.
c.
They don’t have any chairs, that’s why!
(Fletcher and Garman 1988:spdav.cha: line 2016)
I don’t want bubbles.
(Theakston et al. 2001:liz34b.cha: line 682)
Haven’t got a racing car.
(Fletcher and Garman 1988:spkev.cha: line 2139)
(3;02.23)
(2;10.18)
(3;00.00)
The pattern illustrated in (20) is far from unfamiliar in adult language. What determines whether any is used in the environments where other indefinites can be used as
well? Following Kadmon and Landman (1993), the semantic difference between an
any-NP and an a/an/ø-NP in utterances such as (20) is that any is a domain widener
whereas a/an/ø are not. Chierchia (2006, 2013), pointing out that any can but does
not have to act like a domain widener, argues that any obligatorily introduces domain
alternatives that have to be exhaustified. Occurrences with any will this way always
(ii)
You are not making any effort to eat them, are you?
(Lieven et al. 2009:2-02-04.cha: line 2961)
(2;02.04)
Tag questions have a reduced form of generic polar questions. However, due to the preceding negative
statement, positive tag questions are not analysed as generic or neutral polar questions but as a pragmatic
tool to emphasize the preceding negative statement, inducing a negative meaning (Van Rooij and Šafářová
2003; among others). We thus assume that it is the presence of tag questions in children’s communication
with parents, for instance, that triggers the emergence of negative bias in polar questions with any.
13 Other approaches to negatively biased polar questions are Guerzoni (2003) and Van Rooij (2003). From
a syntactic perspective, Guerzoni argues that polar questions with a negative bias are negative assertions,
i.e. ¬p, rather than questions. Van Rooij, however, analyses negatively biased polar questions as true
questions denoting {p, ¬p} but differing from their neutral counterparts in that they necessarily carry a
strong negative presupposition or implicature. It is not our goal to participate in the debate on the semantics
and/or pragmatics of polar questions with a negative bias. We therefore refer the reader to Asher and Reese
(2005) and the references therein for a related discussion.
Distributionally restricted items
be subject to strengthening. This strengthening may but does not have to trigger a
semantic effect, which a/an/ø lack standardly. Further analysis of the pattern in (20)
suggests that usage of any instead of its plain counterparts in early child language
does not manifest itself at random but already mirrors adult use of any, namely that
children only employ an any-NP in those contexts where all stronger domain alternatives are false.
Experimental findings by Tieu and Lidz (2016) support this conclusion. They show
that English children, at least those four- and five-year-olds, are aware of the interpretational difference with respect to domain widening between any and its plain counterparts. Could younger children perhaps also be sensitive to the domain widening
effect of any? A further qualitative analysis of the context containing the utterance of
any chairs in the scope of the sentential negation, (20a), and that containing the utterance containing a racing car in the scope of the sentential negation, (20c), suggests
a positive answer.
The reason the child utters (20a) is to explain why James and his sister, two cartoon figures from a storybook, could not reach the biscuits on the kitchen table: they
did not have chairs on which they could stand to reach the biscuits, not even a chairlike thing that could fulfil the same function. On the other hand, after uttering (20c)
as an answer to the question of the adult Have you got a racing car?, the child continues their conversation by telling the adult that he actually has a little racing car,
somewhere downstairs in his house. Given this contextual difference, we tentatively
assume that children have acquired the knowledge of any having a strengthening effect before the age of four.
But what does it mean, then, for any to have a strengthening effect? Adopting
Chierchia’s framework (Chierchia 2013; see also Xiang 2017 for a recent summary
of his system), this is the semantic consequence of the fact that any obligatorily introduces domain alternatives and that it carries an uninterpretable feature [uD], which
must be checked by a covert exhaustifier. The acquisition of the knowledge that any
obligatorily introduces domain alternatives by English three-year-olds may thus form
evidence that any carries such an uninterpretable D-feature. This means that by the
end of the initial stage, right before the age of four, English children have already
assigned an uninterpretable [uD] to any. Once, a child has acquired that utterances
containing any introduce domain alternatives and must be exhaustified, he or she has
captured its adult-like distribution.
Following up on Kadmon and Landman (1993) and Krifka (1995), Chierchia argues that any carries an uninterpretable feature [uD] that needs to be checked in the
syntax by a covert exhaustifier (O). Feature checking by O gives rise to exhaustification of a proposition p in which any appears. Consequently, an exhaustive reading
of p is achieved that p is true and all non-weaker (domain) alternatives are false.
This restricts any to DE contexts. In such contexts, e.g. under sentential negation as
illustrated in (21a), the proposition containing any is already the strongest statement
among possible alternatives since (21b) necessarily entails (21c) (Kadmon and Landman 1993; Krifka 1995; Lahiri 1998; Chierchia 2006, 2013). Exhaustification takes
place vacuously.
(21)
a.
b.
John did not read any book.
λW. ¬∃X ∈D [bookw (x) ∧ readw (John, x)]
J. Lin et al.
c.
λW. ¬∃X ∈D′ [bookw (x) ∧ readw (John, x)], where D′ ⊆ D
However, checking-off any’s [uD]-feature in contexts that are not DE, for instance, in
simple affirmative contexts as shown in (22a), yields a semantic contradiction. Suppose that when a speaker utters (22a), s/he would mean (22b). Exhaustifying (22a)
would mean that only (22b) is true and all non-weaker (domain) alternatives in (22c)
are false. Then, a semantic contradiction arises: John read a book in a domain D but
he does not read a book in any subdomain D′ of D, rendering (22a) a logical contraction. Following Gajewski (2002), such contradictions trigger ungrammaticality
judgements.
(22)
a.
b.
c.
John read any book.
λW. ∃X ∈D [bookw (x) ∧ readw (John, x)]
λW. ∃X ∈D′ [bookw (x) ∧ readw (John, x)], where D′ ⊆ D
Hence, once a child has acquired that any carries a feature [uD], he or she only utters
any in DE contexts, including those introduced by the sentential negation not (as
shown in (21)) and questions (Guerzoni and Sharvit 2007; see also Mayr 2013 and
Nicolae 2013).
Finally, let’s turn to any’s appearance in FC-inducing contexts, which emerges at
the late stage of acquisition after the age of four (see Tieu et al. 2016 for experimental
findings showing that the FC-use of any is acquired later than its NPI usage). Here
we propose two scenarios in which English four-year-olds may undergo a reanalysing
process, as a consequence of which they allow any to appear in FC-inducing contexts
with an FC interpretation in addition to various DE contexts as assumed above (see
Tieu 2010 for similar proposals). One possibility is that children develop a second
lexical entry for any, namely an FC any next to the any that is exclusively restricted
to DE contexts. This suggests that the late child grammar consists of two anys: one
functions as domain widener indefinite, restricted to DE contexts only, and the other
functions as a FC item that give rise to FC interpretations, restricted to FC-inducing
environments only.
Instead of assuming a second any, one can alternatively opt for a unified analysis
of any at the late stage, i.e. a unified reanalysis of any, which explains its appearance
in both DE and FC-inducing contexts. Chierchia’s treatment of any is an example
of such a
unified analysis. In particular, he proposes that any in fact carries a feature
complex = [uσ , uD]. Next to its uninterpretable D-feature, any also bears an uninterpretable σ -feature. This uninterpretable scalar feature explains any’s FC interpretation when appearing in FC-inducing contexts, such as in the scope of an epistemic
modal verb. Thus, we may assumethat the reanalysis that children develop for any is
that it carries the feature complex . However, our corpus findings cannot provide insight into whether FC any is a different lexical item, and if so, how children probably
acquire any’s uninterpretable scalar feature [uσ ]. We therefore leave this for further
research and schematically summarize the acquisition pathway of NPI any in Fig. 5.
A critical reader may however wonder that the development observed in children’s
production of any, namely that they utter these words in significantly more types of
semantic contexts after four years old, can also be attributed to the booming vocabulary in four-year-olds. This vocabulary-based explanation suggests that there is no
Distributionally restricted items
Fig. 5 Acquiring any as a Chierchia-type of NPI
reanalysis at the later stage since the analysis that children establish at the early stage
(i.e. the initial analysis) already explains all the input evidence that they encounter.
It is only children’s underdeveloped vocabulary rather than the strict, narrow initial
analysis that restricts the distribution of any to a limited range of semantic environments at the early stage. However, this explanation is rejected by the data in Table 8
in Appendix 3 showing that negative environments introduced by various negative
indefinites and conditional clauses introduced by the connective if are frequently
attested already with English two- and three-year-olds. This means that any’s distribution to not-sentences and polar questions only is explained by children’s restricted
analysis of any at the early stage.
5.2 Dutch hoeven
The developmental pattern of hoeven in child Dutch is first discussed and explained
in Lin et al. (2015) (see Lin et al. 2017 for an experimental validation). In order to
explain why niet is virtually the only licenser for hoeven in early child language,
Lin et al. (2015) assume that children below the age of four analyse the two lexical
items as having a lexical dependency, represented by one single lexical unit [HOEVEN
NIET ]. As for the emergence of [ HOEVEN NIET ], Lin et al.—following the conservative widening learning hypothesis—assume a crucial influence from the language
input. As reported in Table 2 in Sect. 4, hoeven is attested in the scope of niet more
than 80% of the time in child-directed speech. The authors assume that this massive
co-occurrence of hoeven and negation triggers the development of the lexical unit
[HOEVEN NIET] in early child Dutch, reflecting a strong frequency effect in early
language acquisition.
The lexical representation of the Dutch modal verb as [HOEVEN NIET] gives rise
to hoeven’s appearance under the scope of the negative marker niet, but cannot generate its appearance in the scope of, for instance, negative indefinites such as niks
‘nothing’ or geen ‘no(ne)’. This means that [HOEVEN NIET] cannot explain hoeven’s
appearance in the scope of another negative operator, such as geen or niks, which
contribute to almost 20% of the language input (Table 2 in Sect. 4). Children thus
need to develop a reanalysis to explain such input.
In order to explore what this reanalysis can be, Lin et al. adopt Jacobs’ decomposition analysis of negative indefinites (Jacobs 1980). Jacob’s analysis is originally
proposed for German but also applies to Dutch. According to this analysis, negative indefinites (at least in the Germanic languages) can be analysed as containing in
their underlying representation an abstract negation (NEG) on the one hand and an
J. Lin et al.
Fig. 6 Decomposition analysis of negative indefinites in Dutch
existential quantifier on the other, as illustrated in Fig. 6 (see also Rullmann 1995;
Zeijlstra 2011; among others), motivated by the existence of so-called split-scope
readings of negative indefinites (see further Rullmann 1995; Penka and Zeijlstra
2005; Penka 2012; Zeijlstra 2011; Iatridou and Zeijstra 2010, 2013; Klima 1964;
Szabolcsi 2004).
If the sentential negative marker, niet in Dutch, is the specific phonological realization of the abstract negation NEG, then AA contexts can also be analysed as containing a decomposable negation NEG. Then, Dutch children can reanalyse hoeven
as being lexically dependent on NEG, instead of its specific phonological form niet.
Therefore, Lin et al. propose that [HOEVEN NEG] is the reanalysis of hoeven that children develop at the late stage. Since the abstract negation NEG can be spelled out as
the sentential negation niet or be incorporated in negative indefinites, hypothesizing
[HOEVEN NEG] as the representation of hoeven in late child language explains why
children above the age of four can utter hoeven both in negative contexts introduced
by niet and negative indefinites.
As Lin et al. point out, [HOEVEN NEG] gives rise to a distributional pattern of
hoeven in all contexts that contain a decomposable negation. In addition to the AA
(including AM) contexts discussed above, some DE contexts can also be analysed
as containing a decomposable abstract negation as well. Examples are semi-negative
operators like zelden ‘seldom’, negative universal expressions like niet iedereen ‘not
everybody’, or exclusive adverbs like alleen ‘only’ or slechts ‘merely’ (von Fintel and
Iatridou 2003; Penka 2011; Iatridou and Zeijstra 2010; 2013, Klima 1964; Szabolcsi
2004). As exemplified in Sect. 2.1, hoeven is indeed attested in such contexts in adult
language. AA and DE contexts that cannot be analysed as containing NEG, such as
conditional clauses or in the restrictive clause of a universal, are indeed non-licensers
of hoeven. Once children have established [HOEVEN NEG] as an analysis for hoeven,
we may therefore say that they have acquired its adult-like distributional restrictions,
a conclusion also supported by experimental findings in Lin et al. (2017).
A reader may now wonder what the difference is between bearing a lexical dependency with an abstract negation NEG and bearing an immediate scope relation with a
semantic negation ¬. To what extent may we consider any in early child grammar to
have the same underlying representation as hoeven in child Dutch? We here present
two pieces of evidence from our acquisition data that bearing a lexical dependency
with the abstract negation NEG does not apply to any. First, although both hypotheses
generate any’s appearance in the scope of the sentential negation, the hypothesis that
hoeven bears a lexical dependency with NEG predicts that it cannot occur in polar
questions with a negative bias. The NEG-hypothesis requires a context in which the
abstract negation NEG is phonologically realized. Second, if any were represented as
[ANY NEG ] in early child grammar, we may expect any to be attested not only in AM
(in the scope of not) but also in AA contexts that are not AM, such as negative quan-
Distributionally restricted items
Fig. 7 Acquiring hoeven as a Postal-type of NPI
tifiers like no or nobody, once the children understand that negative indefinites need
to be decomposed into abstract negation NEG and an existential. However, although
children at the early stage are already able to use such negative quantifiers systematically in their spontaneous speech (Table 8 in Appendix 3), they do not utter any in the
corresponding non-AM AA contexts. The absence of any in non-AM AA contexts in
early child English is easily captured by the hypothesis that any bears an immediate
scope relation with a logic negation ¬: in these contexts, any no longer lies in the
immediate scope of a logic negation, as the existential quantifier would take scope in
between the two.
The reanalysis of hoeven as [HOEVEN NEG] in fact echoes Postal’s treatment of
unary NPIs (Postal 2004, see also Collins and Postal 2014). In their view, the reason
why NPIs are restricted to negative contexts only is that they carry a negation (NEG) in
their underlying lexical structure that raises to a higher position in the structure. Our
exploration of Dutch children’s acquisition of hoeven provides a possible scenario
of how such an NPI may have emerged in language-acquiring children, which we
represent schematically in Fig. 7.14
5.3 Mandarin Chinese shenme
Given the overwhelming usage of shenme as a WH-term in both the language input
and early child Mandarin, we assume that the children’s initial analysis of shenme
is that of a WH-word, similar to English what. However, this initial WH-analysis
of shenme cannot explain the distribution attested for late child Mandarin, in which
shenme is also attested in a variety of NV contexts outside WH-questions, including
negative, imperfective and epistemic modal contexts. How do children above the age
of four analyse shenme, such that it can appear in this wider range of NV contexts?
One possible learning scenario of Mandarin Chinese shenme is inspired by Giannakidou’s work (Giannakidou 2002, 2011, 2016; see also Giannakidou and Quer
2013; Giannakidou and Yoon 2011). For Giannakidou, expressions that, like shenme,
are restricted to a variety of NV contexts exhibit lexical referential deficiency. Referentiality can be informally understood as the ability to refer. Most DPs, for instance,
exhibit this ability and can therefore make existential commitments; the indefinite
DP a robin in John saw a robin yesterday refers to an entity in the world that meets
the description of this indefinite DP given by the context. By contrast, referentially
14 Note that here, a vocabulary-based explanation as we previously speculated for English any cannot
apply, either. van der Wal (1996) already showed in her corpus research that some AA operators, which
can give us proper semantic environments to use hoeven, such as negative indefinites weinig ‘few’ or
niemand ‘nobody’, and exclusive adverbs like alleen ‘only’, are acquired by Dutch children as early as
three years old (see also Lin et al. 2018).
J. Lin et al.
deficient indefinites lack this ability and can therefore only appear in those contexts
that do not force such indefinites to refer. Given that NV contexts are defined as contexts that do not entail the truth of the embedded proposition, referentially deficient
indefinites only survive in NV contexts (see also Lin 1996, 1998).
As for the transition from a WH-term to a referential deficient item hypothesized
for the acquisition of shenme, we further adopt Giannakidou’s approach by assuming
that referential deficiency of shenme it the result of a dependent variable part of its
lexical semantics (see also Giannakidou and Lin 2016). According to Giannakidou
(2011), both WH-terms and non-referential indefinites contain a dependent variable,
as neither can be assigned a fixed value from the context and thus must be constrained
in contexts where there is an operator they can be bound by and be in the scope of.
This means that the analysis of shenme as having a dependent variable is automatically made when children make their first step in acquisition to take shenme as a
WH-term. Reanalysing shenme as exhibiting referential deficiency is then triggered
by language input containing shenme in other (non-WH) expressions, in which only
a dependent variable survives (see Lin et al. 2014 for a previous version of the hypothesized learning path). Children then reanalyse that shenme’s dependent variable
can also be bound in non-interrogative contexts.15
Another possible scenario in which children may acquire both usages of shenme
is inspired by Chierchia and Liao (2015). Based
on Chierchia’s earlier work on any,
which he takes to carry a feature complex
= [uσ , uD] (see also Sect. 5.1), Chierchia and Liao (2015) apply an extension to Mandarin shenme. Any for them introduces both scalar alternatives, due to the uninterpretable feature [uσ ], and domain
alternatives, due
to its uninterpretable feature [uD]. As outlined in Sect. 5.1, this feature complex
needs to be checked by a covert exhaustifier. When this exhaustifier
applies to a proposition p, exhaustification takes place, yielding a reading that takes
p to be true and all non-weaker alternatives false.
Chierchia and Liao argue
that shenme is similar to any: for them, it also comes
with the feature complex , i.e. [uσ , uD]. This accounts for its appearance as an
existential indefinite or pronoun in various DE contexts, as sketched along the lines
for any in his earlier work. As for shenme’s usage as a WH-term, Chierchia and Liao
propose that, unlike any, shenme also carries an unconstrained WH-feature, which
can be valued either positively or negatively. When positively valued, it acts like a
WH-term, otherwise not. This unconstrained WH-feature, represented as [U-WH] in
their system, would thus explain the possible but not necessary appearance of shenme
as a WH-word (see further Chierchia and Liao 2015:(55) and (59)). Children would
then initially assign shenme a positive WH-feature ([+WH]) and later they would reanalyse this feature to an unconstrained feature [U-WH], which then allows shenme’s
usage as a non-WH, existential NPI.
However, this approach to shenme faces a non-trivial problem. As we showed
in Sect. 5.1 for the acquisition of English any, in order to acquire the [uD]-feature,
children need to be systematically confronted with input evidence containing any
15 Note that NV contexts in Giannakidou’s framework in fact describe those contexts that satisfy the non-
entailment-of-existence condition proposed in Lin (1996, 1998). This paper adopts Giannakidou’s terminology, as her approach has been applied cross-linguistically rather than just to Mandarin Chinese (see e.g.
Giannakidou and Quer 2013; Giannakidou and Yoon 2011).
Distributionally restricted items
Fig. 8 Acquiring shenme as a Giannakidou-type of NPI
appearing in a context of which no stronger alternatives are true, such as in the scope
of the sentential negation. This means that Mandarin children also need to receive
systematic input in which shenme is uttered in such contexts before they are ready
and able to develop the [uD]-feature. However, zooming in at the input evidence that
Mandarin children receive (Table 7 in Appendix 2), we see that shenme, when not
used a WH-term, is never attested in the scope of a sentential negation in the input,
although it is perfectly fine in this context (see (12a) and (12b) in Sect. 2.1). Such
a difference between any and shenme with respect to their input distribution makes
it problematic to assume that children are able to acquire a [uD]-feature on shenme.
Moreover, under Chierchia and Liao’s approach it would follow why shenme can be
used as a WH-term and as a weak NPI. However, as shown in Sect. 2.1.3, shenme can
also appear in some non-veridical contexts in which any cannot survive. This cannot
be explained by assuming that shenme is similar to any modulo the WH-feature.
Hence, we conclude this section by assuming that Mandarin-speaking children
acquire shenme a la Giannakidou: they start with the narrow analysis that shenme is
a WH-term and recategorized it as a particular type of non-referential indefinite later
on, as schematically presented in Fig. 8.16,17
6 Conclusion
This paper explored the learnability of any, hoeven, and shenme, which are all restricted to certain negative contexts in English, Dutch, and Mandarin Chinese, respectively, but show differences in their distributional patterns from each other. Our results
obtained in a corpus study using the CHILDES database show that children employ
one and the same conservative widening learning strategy in their acquisition of the
three target words, irrespective of their syntactic category, their functions/meanings,
or the differences between their distributional patterns in adult language. We therefore conclude that conservative widening is a learning strategy that children use in
acquiring expressions which are subject to restricted distributions.
16 There is counterevidence against a vocabulary-based explanation. By showing that Mandarin two- and
three-year-olds are already able to systematically and frequently produce a variety of NV operators (Lin
2017:Appendix B), the author argues that it is highly unlikely that shenme’s appearance as a WH-term in
the early stage is explained by younger children’s underdeveloped vocabulary. When it comes to NV operators, which are relevant to shenme-licensing, her data show that these are already acquired by Mandarin
two- and three-year-olds.
17 We would like to mention that one may alternatively assume two lexical entries for shenme in Mandarin
Chinese, namely a WH-shenme and an NPI-shenme, which, based on our corpus findings, should then be
acquired at the initial and the later stage, respectively. However, the current type of acquisition findings
cannot tear apart the two options. Further exploration is therefore needed, even though a unified approach
is to be preferred on the grounds of scientific parsimony.
J. Lin et al.
Although the same learning strategy is confirmed for all of the three expressions
investigated in the current research, we find distinct learning pathways, which we
further interpret as evidence showing different reasons or properties underlying the
limited distributions attested with each of the words in adult language. In particular, our hypothesized acquisition
path of any seem to lead to an analysis of the word
bearing a feature complex
= [uσ , uD], along the lines of Chierchia’s approach
(Chierchia 2006, 2013). As for the Dutch modal verb hoeven, the analysis that children eventually establish requires a lexical dependency between the verb and an abstract negation: [HOEVEN NEG], which we take as evidence for Postal’s treatment of
unary NPIs (Postal 2004; see also Collins and Postal 2014). Finally, for Mandarin
Chinese shenme, our interpretation and discussion of the corpus data suggest that it
is its non-referentiality, inspired by Giannakidou (2002, 2011; see also Giannakidou
and Lin 2016), that restricts its distribution to various NV contexts only.
The acquisition findings reported and interpreted in this paper strongly suggest
different reasons or properties underlying the restricted distributions of any, hoeven,
and shenme. This further suggests that NPIs do not form a homogeneous grammatical category, although they all show limited distributions in certain negative environments. It is essentially some kind of coincidence that NPI-hood manifests itself as
a homogeneous phenomenon. This is a crucial theoretical implication of the current
acquisition study.
However, one may question whether acquisition research is indeed necessary in
arguing that some expressions are restricted in their distributions due to different
underlying reasons. This is because the different distributional patterns of the three
investigated words in adult language may already be evident for different reasons
underlying the constrained distribution of each NPI. What does acquisition research
then tell us more than what we may already observe and infer from their distributions
in adult language?
Our answer to this question is straightforward. Whatever a theoretical approach
may be, this approach must be learnable from the child’s perspective. As far as we understand, the different approaches proposed to account for the restricted distributions
of any, hoeven, and shenme are all developed exclusively based on adult language use
or patterns. As such, these approaches provide us with little information on whether
language-acquiring children are able to develop these approaches as well during the
acquisition trajectory. But such information from acquisition is crucial and necessary
when evaluating a theoretical approach that is established based on adult language
observations. If children, provided with typically developing cognitive abilities, are
not able to acquire this approach, it can only be considered inadequate. And this is
exactly what we have examined in the current paper.
Acknowledgements We would like to thank Gennaro Chierchia, Anastasia Giannakidou, Larry Horn,
Sabine Iatridou and Lyn Tieu for their insightful and constructive feedback during the preparations and
revisions of the manuscript. We owe also many thanks to the anonymous reviewers for their useful comments, which helped to improve the article. Earlier versions of this work were presented and discussed
at the 39th Incontro di Grammatica Generativa (University of Modena and Reggio Emilia, Italy), the 6th
Semantics and Philosophy in Europe Colloquium (St. Petersburg State University, Russia) and the 29th Annual Meeting of the Israel Association of Theoretical Linguistics (The Hebrew University of Jerusalem,
Israel). Many thanks go to the audiences at these conferences as well. Also, we thank Sible Andringa for
his help with statistics, and Caitlin Meyer for proofreading.
Distributionally restricted items
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps
and institutional affiliations.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as
you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons
licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material.
If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted
by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the
copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
Appendix 1: Examples of different categories of grammaticality
status18
Grammatical use:
(i) xx hoef geen suiker.
xx need no sugar
‘xx does not need sugar.’
(Wijnen and Bol 1993:abe21000.cha: line 24)
Ungrammatical use:
(ii) Ik hoef drinken.
I need drink
‘I want to drink something.’
(Wijnen and Bol 1993:mat30113.cha: line 515)
Self-correction:
(iii) Deze hoe(f t) deze moet @ op.
this need(s) this should @ on
‘This needs, this should be here.’
(Wijnen and Bol 1993:daa20910.cha: line 436)
Unclear use:
(iv) (I)k hoef . . .
I need
‘I need . . . ’
(Wijnen and Bol 1993:jos30110.cha: line 1275)
Contrastive use:
(v) Nee, hoeft wel.
no needs surely
‘No, it is necessary.’
(Wijnen and Bol 1993:mat30603.cha: line 1467)
18 Since our Dutch results contained all the defined categories, we choose to present here examples from
Dutch.
J. Lin et al.
Appendix 2: Distribution of the target words in child-directed speech
Table 5 Any in child-directed
English (based on
approximately 1000 randomly
selected utterances)
a Among these 336 tterances,
there are 36 instances containing
any in embedded polar questions
b Two of these instances were
embedded WH-interrogatives
Table 6 Hoeven in
child-directed Dutch
Table 7 Shenme in
child-directed Mandarin (based
on approximately 1000
randomly selected utterances)
Semantic context
Count (percentage)
In the scope of sentential negation
In (embedded) polar questions
In epistemic modal contexts or subtrigging
In conditional clauses
In the scope of without
In the scope of negative indefinites
In the scope of semi-negative expressions
In the scope of only
In before-clauses
In (embedded) WH-interrogatives
In the complement of emotive verbs
In the restriction of a universal quantifier
Others
Total
600 (57.6%)
336a (32.3%)
38 (3.7%)
32 (3.1%)
3 (0.3%)
12 (1.2%)
7 (0.7%)
0
7 (0.7%)
5b (0.5%)
0
0
0
1040
Semantic context
Count (percentage)
In the scope of sentential negation
In the scope of negative indefinites
In the scope of DE licensers containing NEG
In contrastive contexts
Others
Total
299 (80.8%)
57 (15.4%)
14 (3.8%)
0
0
370
Semantic context
Count (percentage)
In WH-interrogatives as a WH-word
In the scope of sentential negation
In the restriction of a universal quantifier
In conditional clauses
In imperfective aspects
In donkey constructions
In epistemic/inferential/subjunctive/modal
contexts
In polar questions (incl. X-NEG-X questions)
In imperatives
In WH-interrogatives with a non-WH
interpretation
In veridical contexts
In the scope of a negative indefinite
In other minimally negative contexts
Unclear
Total
976 (97.7%)
0
2 (0.2%)
0
6 (0.6%)
6 (0.6%)
4 (0.4%)
3 (0.3%)
2 (0.2%)
0
0
0
0
0
999
Distributionally restricted items
Appendix 3: Different any-licensers in child English development
Table 8 Frequency of different
any-licensers at the early and the
late stage
Any-licensers
Age: <4
Age: 4–5
no
nothing
nobody
nowhere
few
only
if-conditionals
37873
377
164
14
35
281
286
2689
80
8
7
9
186
412
Appendix 4: Response patterns to polar questions with and without any
uttered by children below the age of four
Table 9 Responses to polar questions with any uttered by children below the age of four
Answer type
Category
Count (percentage)
Positive
A direct yes-answer given by the parent/investigator
Indicated by the child her/himself
An indirect positive answer given by the parent/investigator
A positive answer with counterevidence marked by well, etc.
11 (11.5%)
5 (5.2%)
1 (1%)
12 (12.5%)
29
26 (27.1%)
15 (15.6%)
17 (17.7%)
58
1 (1%)
8 (8.3)
96
Total
Negative
Total
“I don’t know.”
Unclear
Total
A direct no-answer given by the parent/investigator
Indicated by the child her/himself
An indirect negative answer given by the parent/investigator
No bias or answers can be derived
Table 10 Responses to polar questions without any uttered by children below the age of four
Answer type
Category
Count (percentage)
Positive
A direct yes-answer given by the parent/investigator
Indicated by the child her/himself
An indirect positive answer given by the parent/investigator
A positive answer with counterevidence marked by well, etc.
42 (40.1%)
6 (5.8%)
16 (15.5%)
10 (9.7%)
74
10 (9.7%)
1 (1%)
5 (4.9%)
16
3 (2.9%)
10 (9.7%)
103
Total
Negative
Total
“I don’t know.”
Unclear
Total
A direct no-answer given by the parent/investigator
Indicated by the child her/himself
An indirect negative answer given by the parent/investigator
No bias or answers can be derived
J. Lin et al.
References
Asher, Nicholas, and Brian Reese. 2005. Negative bias in polar questions. In Proceedings of Sinn und
Bedeutung 9, 30–43.
Baker, C. Lee, and John Joseph McCarthy. 1981. The logical problem of language acquisition. Cambridge:
MIT Press.
Beck, Sigrid, and Hotze Rullmann. 1999. A flexible approach to exhaustivity in questions. Natural Language Semantics 7: 249–298.
Berwick, Robert C. 1985. The acquisition of syntactic knowledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Berwick, Robert C., and Amy S. Weinberg. 1986. The grammatical basis of linguistic performance: Language use and acquisition. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Bishop, Dorothy V. M., and Catherine Adams. 1990. A prospective study of the relationship between
specific language impairment, phonological disorders and reading retardation. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 31: 1027–1050.
Bol, Gerard, and Folkert Kuiken. 1990. Grammatical analysis of developmental language disorders: A
study of the morphosyntax of children with specific language disorders, with hearing impairment and
with Down’s syndrome. Clinical Linguistics & Phonetics 4: 77–86.
Braine, Martin D.S. 1971. On two types of models of the internalization of grammars. In The ontogenesis
of grammar 153–186.
Cartwright, Timothy A., and Michael R. Brent. 1997. Syntactic categorisation in early language acquisition: formalizing the role of distributional analysis. Cognition 63: 121–170.
Cheng, Lisa Lai-Shen. 1991. On the typology of wh-questions. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Cheng, Lisa Lai-Shen. 1994. Wh-words as polarity items. Chinese Languages and Linguistics 2: 615–640.
Cheng, Lisa Lai-Shen. 1995. On dou-quantification. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 4: 197–234.
Chierchia, Gennaro. 2006. Broaden your views: Implicatures of domain widening and the “logicality” of
language. Linguistic Inquiry 37: 535–590.
Chierchia, Gennaro. 2013. Logic in grammar: Polarity, free choice, and intervention. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Chierchia, Gennaro, and Hsiu-Chen Liao. 2015. Where do Chinese wh-items fit. In Epistemic indefinites:
Exploring modality beyond the verbal domain, eds. Luis Alonso-Ovalle, Paula Mene’ndez-Benito, C.
Lee Baker, and John McCarthy Joseph, 31–59. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chiu, Bonnie. 1990. A case of quantifier floating in Mandarin Chinese. In The Second North America
Conference on Chinese Linguistics (NECCL-2), Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania.
Chomsky, Noam, and Howard Lasnik. 1977. Filters and control. Linguistic Inquiry 8: 425–504.
Collins, Chris, and Paul M. Postal. 2014. Classical NEG Raising: An Essay on the Syntax of Negation.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cruttenden, Alan. 1978. Assimilation in child language and elsewhere. Journal of Child Language 5: 373–
378.
Crystal, David, Paul Fletcher, and Michael Garman. 1989. Grammatical analysis of language disability.
London: Cole and Whurr.
Elbers, Loekie, and Frank Wijnen. 1992. Effort, production skill, and language learning. Phonological
development: Models, research, implications 337–368.
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1978. Implication reversal in a natural language. In Formal semantics and pragmatics
for natural languages, 289–301. The Netherlands: Springer.
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1980. Pragmatic entailment and questions. In Speech act theory and pragmatics, eds.
John R. Searle, Ferenc Kiefer, and Manfred Bierwisch, 57–69. The Netherlands: Springer.
Fikkert, Paula. 1994. On the acquisition of prosodic structure. PhD diss., University of Leiden, the Netherlands.
von Fintel, Kai, and Sabine Iatridou. 2003. Epistemic containment. Linguistic Inquiry 34: 173–198.
Fletcher, Paul, and Michael Garman. 1988. Normal language development and language impairment: Syntax and beyond. Clinical Linguistics & Phonetics 2: 97–113.
Forrester, Michael. 2002. Appropriating cultural conceptions of childhood: Participation in conversation.
Childhood 9: 255–278.
Gajewski, Jon. 2002. L-analyticity and natural language. Ms., MIT.
Giannakidou, Anastasia. 1997. The landscape of polarity items. PhD diss., Rijksuniversiteit.
Giannakidou, Anastasia. 1998. Polarity sensitivity as (non) veridical dependency. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.
Distributionally restricted items
Giannakidou, Anastasia. 2001. The meaning of free choice. Linguistics and Philosophy 24: 659–735.
Giannakidou, Anastasia. 2002. Licensing and sensitivity in polarity items: from downward entailment to
nonveridicality. Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 38: 29–53.
Giannakidou, Anastasia. 2011. Negative polarity and positive polarity: Licensing, variation, and compositionality. In The handbook of natural langauge meaning, eds. Claudia Maienborn, Klaus von
Heusinger, and Paul Portner, 1660–1712. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Giannakidou, Anastasia. 2016. The myth of exhaustivity of all NPIs. In Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS),
Vol. 52.
Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Jing Lin. 2016. The Mandarin shenme is not exhaustive: A reply to Chierchia and Liao (2015). Ms., University of Chicago and University of Amsterdam. Available at
http://home.uchicago.edu/~giannaki/pubs/Final.LinGianna.Mar.11.2016.pdf.
Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Josep Quer. 2013. Exhaustive and non-exhaustive variation with anti-specific
indefinites: Free choice versus referential vagueness. Lingua 126: 120–149.
Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Suwon Yoon. 2011. Referential vagueness and negative polarity: evidence
form Greek and Korean. In Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS), Vol. 48.
Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Frans Zwarts. 1999. Temporal, aspectual operators and (non) veridicality.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Grimshaw, Jane. 1981. Form, function and the language acquisition device. In The logical problem of
language acquisition, eds. C. Lee Baker and John Joseph McCarthy, 165–182. Cambridge: MIT
Press.
Gropen, Jess, Steven Pinker, Michelle Hollander, and Richard Goldberg. 1991. Affectedness and direct
objects: The role of lexical semantics in the acquisition of verb argument structure. Cognition 41:
153–195.
Guasti, Maria. T. 2017. Language acquisition: The growth of grammar. Cambridge: MIT press.
Guerzoni, Elena. 2003. Why even ask?: On the pragmatics of questions and the semantics of answers. PhD
diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Guerzoni, Elena, and Yael Sharvit. 2007. A question of strength: On NPIs in interrogative clauses. Linguistics and Philosophy 30: 361–391.
Hamblin, Charles L. 1973. Questions in Montague English, Foundations of Language 10(1): 41–53.
Heim, Irene. 1994. Interrogative semantics and Karttunen’s semantics for know. In Annual meeting of the
Israeli Association for Theoretical Linguistics (IATL), Vol. 1, 128–144.
Henry, Alison. 1995. Belfast English and Standard English: Dialect variation and parameter setting.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hoeksema, Jack. 2000. Negative polarity items: Triggering, scope and c-command. In Negation and polarity: Syntactic and semantic perspectives, eds. Laurence Horn and Yasuhiko Kato, 115–146. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Hogeweg, Lotte. 2009. The meaning and interpretation of the Dutch particle wel. Journal of Pragmatics
41: 219–239.
Horn, Laurence R. 1996. Exclusive company: Only and the dynamics of vertical inference. Journal of
Semantics 13: 1–40.
Horn, Laurence R. 2000. any and (−)ever: Free choice and free relatives. In Annual meeting of the Israeli
Association for Theoretical Linguistics (IATL), 71–111. Jerusalem: Akademon.
Horn, Laurence R. 2005. Airport ’86 revisited: Toward a unified indefinite any. In The Partee effect, eds.
Pelletier Francis Jeffry, and Gregory Carlson, 179–205. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Howe, Christine. 1981. Acquiring language in a conversational context. London: Academic Press.
Huang, James C-T. 1982. Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. PhD diss., Massachusetts
Institute of Technology.
Iatridou, Sabine, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2010. On the scopal interaction of negation and deontic modals. In
Logic, Language and Meaning, 315–324. Berlin: Springer.
Iatridou, Sabine, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2013. Negation, polarity, and deontic modals. Linguistic Inquiry 44:
529–568.
Jacobs, Joachim. 1980. Lexical decomposition in Montague Grammar. Theoretical Linguistics 7: 121–
136.
Kadmon, Nirit, and Fred Landman. 1993. Any. Linguistics and Philosophy 16: 353–422.
Karmiloff-Smith, Annette. 1986. From meta-processes to conscious access: Evidence from children’s metalinguistic and repair data. Cognition 23: 95–147.
Klima, Edward. 1964. Negation in English. In The structure of language 245–323.
Krifka, Manfred. 1995. The semantics and pragmatics of polarity items. Linguistic Analysis 25: 209–257.
J. Lin et al.
Ladusaw, William A. 1979. Negative polarity items as inherent scope relations. New York and London:
Garland Publishing.
Ladusaw, William A. 1996. Negation and polarity items. In The handbook of contemporary semantic
theory, ed. Shalom Lappin, 321–341. Oxford and Malden: Blackwell Publishers.
Lahiri, Utpal. 1998. Focus and negative polarity in Hindi. Natural Language Semantics 6(1): 57–123.
Lee, Thomas Hun-Tak. 1986. Studies on quantification in Chinese. PhD diss., University of California.
Leonard, Laurence B. 2014. Children with specific language impairment. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Levelt, Clara Cecilia. 1994. On the acquisition of place. PhD diss., Holland Institute of Generative Linguistics.
Li, Audrey Ye-Hui. 1992. Indefinite Wh in Mandarin Chinese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 1: 125–
155.
Lieven, Elena, Dorothé Salomo, and Michael Tomasello. 2009. Two-year-old children’s production of
multiword utterances: A usage-based analysis. Cognitive Linguistics 20: 481–507.
Lin, Jo-Wang. 1996. Polarity licensing and wh-phrase quantification in Chinese. PhD diss., University of
Massachusetts, Amherst.
Lin, Jo-Wang. 1998. On existential polarity WH-phrases in Chinese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 7:
219–255.
Lin, Jing. 2015. Acquiring negative polarity items. PhD diss., University of Amsterdam
Lin, Jing. 2016. On the distribution and acquisition of the West Germanic ‘Need’-verbs: German between
Dutch and English. Journal of Germanic Linguistics 28(4): 349–369.
Lin, Jing. 2017. Distributionally constrained items in child language: The acquisition of superweak
NPI shenme ‘a/some’ in Mandarin Chinese. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 2(1): 15
https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.173.
Lin, Jing, Fred Weerman, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2014. Mandarin SHENME as a superweak NPI. In Black
book: A festschrift in honor of Frans Zwarts, eds. Jack Hoeksema and Dicky Gilbers, 229–251.
Lin, Jing, Fred Weerman, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2015. Emerging NPIs: The acquisition of Dutch hoeven
‘need’. The Linguistic Review 32(2): 333–374.
Lin, Jing, Fred Weerman, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2017. Acquisition of the Dutch NPI hoeven
‘need’: From lexical frames to abstract knowledge. Language Acquisition. https://doi.org/10.1080/
10489223.2017.1348097.
Lin, Jing, Fred Weerman, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2018. Acquisition of the Dutch NPI hoeven ‘need’: From
lexical frames to abstract knowledge. Language Acquisition 25(2): 150–177.
MacWhinney, Brian. 2009. The childes project. Tools for analysing talk – electronic edition 2.
Manzini, M. Rita, and Kenneth Wexler. 1987. Parameters, binding theory, and learnability. Linguistic
Inquiry 413–444.
Marcus, Gary F. 1993. Negative evidence in language acquisition. Cognition 46: 53–85.
Marcus, Gary F., Steven Pinker, Michael Ullman, Michelle Hollander, T. John Rosen, Fei Xu, and Harald
Clahsen. 1992. Overregularization in language acquisition. Monographs of the Society for Research
in Child Development 57(4): i–178.
Mayr, Clemens. 2013. Downward monotonicity in questions. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 17,
eds. Emmanuel Chemla, Vincent Homer, and Grégoire Winterstein, 345–362. Paris: École Normale
Supérieure.
Mintz, Toben H. 2002. Category induction from distributional cues in an artificial language. Memory &
Cognition 30(5): 678–686.
Mintz, Toben H. 2003. Frequent frames as a cue for grammatical categories in child directed speech.
Cognition 90(1): 91–117.
Mintz, Toben H., Elissa L. Newport, and Thomas G. Bever. 2002. The distributional structure of grammatical categories in speech to young children. Cognitive Science 26: 393–424.
Nicolae, Andreea Cristina. 2013. Any questions? Polarity as a window into the structure of questions. PhD
diss., Harvard University.
Nippold, Marilyn A. 1990. Concomitant speech and language disorders in stuttering children: A critique
of the literature. Journal of Speech and Hearing Disorders 55: 51–60.
Nippold, Marilyn A., and Ilsa E. Schwarz. 2002. Do children recover from specific language impairment?
International Journal of Speech-Language Pathology 4: 41–49.
Pan, Haihua. 2006. Focus, tripartite structure, and the semantic interpretation of Mandarin dou. Research
and Exploration on Grammar 13: 163–184.
Penka, Doris. 2011. Negative indefinites. London: Oxford University Press.
Penka, Doris. 2012. Split scope of negative indefinites. Language and Linguistics Compass 6: 517–532.
Distributionally restricted items
Penka, Doris, and Hedde Zeijlstra. 2005. Negative indefinites in Dutch and German. In 20th Comparative
Germanic Syntax Workshop, Tilburg.
Pinker, Steven. 1984. Language learnability and language development. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Pinker, Steven. 1995. Language acquisition. Language: An Invitation to Cognitive Science 1: 135–182.
Pinker, Steven. 2013. Learnability and cognition: The acquisition of argument structure. Cambridge: MIT
press.
Postal, Paul M. 2004. Skeptical linguistic essays. New York: Oxford University Press.
Redington, Martin, Nick Crater, and Steven Finch. 1998. Distributional information: A powerful cue for
acquiring syntactic categories. Cognitive Science 22: 425–469.
Rowland, Caroline F., and Sarah L. Fletcher. 2006. The effect of sampling on estimates of lexical specificity and error rates. Journal of Child Language 33: 859–877.
Rullmann, Hotze. 1995. Geen eenheid. Tabu Squib Nummber Deel 2: 194–197.
Schaerlaekens, Anne Marie. 1973. The two-word sentence in child language development. The Hague:
Mouton.
Sharvit, Yael. 2002. Embedded questions and ‘de dicto’ readings. Natural Language Semantics 10: 97–
123.
Snyder, William. 2002. Parameters: The view from child language. Keynote address at Tokyo Conference
on Psycholinguistics (TCP) 3. Tokyo: Hituzi Shobo.
Snyder, William. 2007. Child language: The parametric approach. Oxford: OUP.
Snyder, William. 2008. Children’s grammatical conservatism: Implications for linguistic theory. In An
enterprise in the cognitive science of language: A festschrift for Yukio Otsu, 41-51, eds. Tetsuya Sano,
Mika Endo, Miwa Isobe, Koichi Otaki, Koji Sugisaki, and Takeru Suzuki. Tokyo: Hituzi Syobo.
Snyder, William. 2011. Children’s grammatical conservatism: Implications for syntactic theory. In Boston
University Conference on Language Development (BUCLD) 35: 1–20.
Szabolcsi, Anna. 2004. Positive polarity–negative polarity. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 22:
409–452.
Tardif, Twila Zoe. 1996. Nouns are not always learned before verbs: Evidence from Mandarin speakers’
early vocabularies. Developmental Psychology 32: 492–504.
Tardif, Twila Zoe. 1993. Adult-to-child speech and language acquisition in Mandarin Chinese. PhD diss.,
Yale University.
Theakston, Anna L., Elena V. M. Lieven, Julian M. Pine, and Caroline F. Rowland. 2001. The role of
performance limitations in the acquisition of verb-argument structure: An alternative account. Journal
of Child Language 28: 127–152.
Tieu, Lyn Shan. 2010. The acquisition of NPI any in English: A case study. In 34th Boston University
conference on language development.
Tieu, Lyn. 2011. On the tri-ambiguous status of ‘any’: The view from child language. In Proceedings of
Semantics and Linguistic Theory, eds. David Lutz and Nan Li. (SALT) 20:19–37. Ithaca, NY: CLC
Publications.
Tieu, Lyn. 2013. Logic and grammar in child language: How children acquire the semantics of polarity
sensitivity. PhD diss., University of Connecticut.
Tieu, Lyn, and Jeffrey Lidz. 2016. NPI licensing and beyond: Children’s knowledge of the semantics of
any. Language Acquisition 23(4): 311–332.
Tieu, Lyn, Jacopo Romoli, Peng Zhou, and Stephen Crain. 2016. Children’s knowledge of free choice
inferences and scalar implicatures. Journal of Semantics 33(2): 269–298.
van der Wal, Sjoukje. 1996. Negative polarity items and negation: Tandem acquisition. PhD diss., Rijksuniversiteit Groningen.
Van der Wouden, Ton. 1994. Polarity and ‘illogical negation’. Dynamics, Polarity and Quantification 17:
16–45.
van der Wouden, Ton. 1997. Negative contexts: Collocation, polarity and multiple negation. London: Routledge.
van Kampen, Jacqueline. 1994. The learnability of the left branch condition. Linguistics in the Netherlands
199: 83–94.
van Rooij, Robert. 2003. Negative polarity items in questions: Strength as relevance. Journal of Semantics
20: 239–273.
van Rooij, Robert, and Marie Šafářová. 2003. On polar questions. Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT)
13: 292–309.
von Fintel, Kai. 1999. NPI licensing, Strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics
16: 97–148.
J. Lin et al.
Wells, Gordon. 1981. Learning through interaction: The study of language development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wijnen, Frank. 1992. Incidental word and sound errors in young speakers. Journal of Memory and Language 31: 734–755.
Wijnen, Frank. 1988. Spontaneous word fragmentations in children: Evidence for the syllable as a unit in
speech production. Journal of Phonetics 16(2): 187–202.
Wijnen, Frank, and Gerard Bol. 1993. The escape from the optional infinitive stage. Language and Cognition 3: 105–118.
Wilson, John, and Alison Henry. 1998. Parameter setting within a socially realistic linguistics. Language
in Society 27: 1–21.
Wu, Jian-Xin. 1999. A minimal analysis of dou-quantification. Ms., University of Maryland College Park.
Xiang, Ming. 2008. Plurality, maximality and scalar inferences: A case study of Mandarin dou. Journal of
East Asian Linguistics 17(3): 227–245.
Xiang, Yi-Mei. 2017. ONLY: An NPI-licenser and NPI-unlicenser. Journal of Semantics 34(3): 447–481.
Xie, Zhi-Guo. 2007. Nonveridicality and existential polarity wh-phrases in Mandarin. In Proceedings of
Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS), eds. Malcolm Elliott, James Kirby, Osamu Sawada, Eleni Staraki,
and Suwon Yoon. Vol. 43, 121–135. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zeijlstra, Hedde. 2011. On the syntactically complex status of negative indefinites. Journal of Comparative
Germanic Linguistics 14: 111–138.
Zhou, Jing. 2004a. The Zhou 1 corpus. The CHILDES database. childes.talkbank.org.
Zhou, Jing. 2004b. The Zhou 2 corpus. The CHILDES database, childes.talkbank.org.
Zwarts, Frans. 1981. Negatief polaire uitdrukkingen I. Glot 4: 35–132.
Zwarts, Frans. 1986. Categoriale grammatica en algebraïsche semantiek: een onderzoek naar negatie en
polariteit in het Nederlands. PhD diss., Rijksuniversiteit.
Zwarts, Frans. 1995. Nonveridical contexts. Linguistic Analysis 25: 286–312.
Zwarts, Frans. 1998. Three types of polarity. In Plurality and quantification, 177–238. Berlin: Springer.