This article is available open access under a CC BY-ND 4.0 license thanks to the generous support
from a global network of libraries as part of the Knowledge Unlatched Select initiative.
From Neo-Republicanism
to Socialist Republicanism
Antonio Gramsci, the European
Council Movements and the
‘Second Republican Revival’
Andreas Møller Mulvad and
Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
Abstract: This article engages with socialist republicanism, which is
preoccupied with extending freedom as non-domination, central to the
neo-republican revival, from the political sphere of formal democracy
to the economic sphere of capitalist production. Firstly, we discuss the
transition from neo-republicanism to socialist republicanism. Secondly,
we reconstruct the socialist republicanism of Antonio Gramsci, who
was involved in the council movements in Turin in 1919–20. We argue
that Gramsci applies the republican vocabulary of servitude to describe
the capitalist workplace and analyse the workers’ councils as republican
forms, allowing for popular self-determination in the economic sphere.
Consequently, we contribute to the ongoing exploration of the historical,
political, and conceptual affinities between republicanism and socialism
and inscribe Gramsci as a key thinker in this endeavour.
Keywords: Antonio Gramsci, non-domination, republicanism, socialism, workers’ councils
If democracy is justified in governing the state, then it is also justified in governing economic interests. What is more, if it cannot
be justified in governing economic enterprises, we do not quite
see how it can be justified in governing the state.
– Robert Dahl, A Preface to Economic Democracy
Theoria, Issue 171, Vol. 69, No. 2 (June 2022): 97-118 © Author(s)
doi:10.3167/th.2022.6917106•ISSN0040-5817(Print)•ISSN1558-5816(Online)
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 97
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
98
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
The democratic ideas of freedom, equality, and self-government
are realized only when . . . the self-government of the people finds
its basis in the self-government of workers in a republican economy.
– Otto Bamuer, Zwischen zwei Weltkriegen?, p. 199.
The opening epigraph is provided by the famous American political scientist Robert Dahl. Dahl was by no means a socialist, but as
a professor in democratic theory at Yale University, the distinction
between a public-political sphere in which citizens enjoy equal civil
and political rights and a private-economic sphere in which employers direct their employees, who in turn have few possibilities for
influencing their work, proved a logical and moral question. Why
is that equality, rights, and participation is taken as the sine qua non
in the political domain of society, whereas in the economic domain,
inequality and hierarchy are perceived as natural conditions? Who
draws the demarcation line between the public realm of freedom
and equality and the private realm of hierarchy and domination, and
on what grounds? If democracy is the all-important principle of our
political systems, why not expand it to economic enterprises?
The second epigraph by the Austrian socialist Otto Bauer, who
briefly held the office of Foreign Minister in Austria in 1918–19, as
socialist movements had been instrumental in the dissolution of the
Austro-Hungarian Empire after the First World War, expresses a
similar belief, but in a conceptual vocabulary, which this article will
seek to elucidate and expand. According to Bauer, the ‘democratic
idea’ of the ‘self-government of the people’ can only be realised
through the workers’ self-government in a republican economy.
What is a republican economy? As a conceptual term and historical experience, republicanism is most often associated with forms
of political government freed from monarchical elements and with
some degree of popular involvement, most often through mechanisms of representation (Pettit 1997). What does it mean to extend
this form of political government to the economy?
These questions have recently nurtured many different research
agendas in political theory, comparative politics and intellectual
history, and debates on the democratisation of the economy has
seen a revival post-2008, marking an increased problematisation
of neoliberalism. Some researchers have explored the ‘firm-state
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 98
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
99
analogy’, whereby the basic organisational comparability of firms
and states is demonstrated (González-Ricoy 2014; Landemore and
Ferreras 2015), other researchers have argued for the normative
justification of workplace democracy and new forms of cooperative
ownership (Anderson 2017; Breen 2015; Hsieh 2005), while intellectual historians have re-invigorated the idea of economic democracy (Currarino 2011; Kärrylä 2021). The workplace, as it was once
argued, is no longer a ‘forgotten topic of democratic theory’ (Ellerman 2009).
In this article, we shall engage with a contemporary strain of
political theory: socialist republicanism, which is preoccupied
with extending practices of democracy, cooperatism as well as the
idea of freedom as non-domination, made highly influential by the
neo-republican revival some thirty years ago, from the political
sphere of formal democracy to the economic sphere of capitalist
production. We are certainly not alone in this ambition, as scholars
have recently demonstrated the historical and conceptual affinities between republicanism and socialism (Muldoon 2019; O’Shea
2019), between republicanism and resistance to oligarchy (Vergara
2020), between republicanism, Karl Marx and Marxism (Gourevitch 2014; Leipold 2020), between republicanism and ‘the left’
(Kouris 2020; White 2007), and between republicanism and the
tradition of council democracy (Muldoon 2020; Thompson 2018).
This article, hence, contributes to an ongoing debate by focusing
on two specific elements. Firstly, we discuss the transition from
neo-republicanism to socialist republicanism, as we introduce the
idea of a ‘second republican revival’. Secondly, we reconstruct
the socialist republicanism of the Italian political thinker Antonio
Gramsci, who was briefly involved in the socialist council movement in Turin in 1919–20 – during Italy’s so-called biennio rosso.
He later became an influential Marxist and died in prison, sentenced
there by Benito Mussolini’s fascist regime. We do not claim that
Gramsci represents a distinct branch of socialist republicanism;
the ambition is instead to augment the ongoing ‘second republican
revival’ by adding a socialist republican reconstruction of Gramsci’s thought to the already existing analyses of key socialist intellectuals and activists of the early twentieth century, such as Karl
Kautsky (Muldoon 2020: 99–130), and Rosa Luxemburg (Vergara
2020: 168–183) as well as Karl Marx (Leipold 2020: 172–193).
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 99
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
100
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
The article proceeds in the following manner: Firstly, we introduce the idea of a ‘second republican revival’ by documenting the
turn from neo-republicanism to socialist republicanism, by stipulating the way contemporary proponents of socialist republicanism
argue for the feasibility of the neo-republican idea of freedom as
non-domination as a viable critique of capitalism and a well-suited
starting point for what Bauer called a ‘republican economy’. Secondly, we introduce the historical context for Gramsci’s political
thinking by turning to the European council movements during
and after the First World War, where workers’ councils acted as
key actors in the Russian, German, and Hungarian Revolutions.
Thirdly and lastly, we reconstruct Gramsci’s thinking by focusing
especially on his ‘pre-prison’ writings, which are more practical
and political than the philosophical Prison Notebooks, and where
Gramsci sought to establish the political, conceptual, and historical
links between the Russian soviets and the Italian factory councils
that appeared during the biennio rosso in 1919–20.
The ‘Second Republican Revival’:
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
Socialist republicanism, or what is otherwise named labour republicanism (Gourevitch 2014), radical republicanism (Leipold et
al. 2020) or plebeian republicanism (Vergara 2020), is a product
of what we call the ongoing ‘second republican revival’, which
extends the insights from the highly influential neo-republican
research programme inaugurated by Philip Pettit and Quentin Skinner thirty years ago from the political sphere and into the economic
sphere. To elucidate this ‘second revival’, we need to situate socialist republicanism within the broader landscape of republican political theory.
Republicanism is an ancient political philosophy, originating
from the political system of the Roman Republic. Its mixed constitution and vehement conflict with monarchy informed Renaissance city states and political thinking and influenced English
seventeenth-century revolutionaries and political philosophers like
Algernon Sidney and James Harrington. In addition, republicanism also influenced the French and American confrontations with
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 100
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
101
monarchy and colonialism (Honohan 2002) by criticising the denigration of the common good and civil liberty by the arbitrary power
of royal and colonial overlords. The overarching political principle
of the republican tradition is that of freedom – that is, to be a free
human being, a citizen, is to live in a free state, where power is not
exercised arbitrarily (Hammersley 2020).
Neo-republicans refer to an idea of freedom as non-domination.
Through a meticulous reconstruction of the republican tradition
from ancient Rome to modernity, and focusing especially on the
political thought of Machiavelli, Quentin Skinner has famously
argued – in what could be called the ‘first republican revival’ –
that beyond the two concepts of liberty compared in Isaiah Berlin
famous essay ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’ (1958), that is, negative
liberty as non-interference and positive liberty as self-realisation,
a third republican concept of liberty could be excavated from centuries of republican thinking (Skinner 1998; Pettit 1997). While
the liberal notion of negative freedom as non-interference argues
that people are simply unfree to the degree that someone (a public
power, a feudal lord, or a monarch) directly interferes with their
actions, the republican concept of negative freedom as non-domination claims that citizens are only free when they are not subject to
the arbitrary power of a master.
The vital distinction between interference and domination is
sometimes clarified with reference to slavery. In the liberal account,
a slave is claimed to be free to the degree that he has a benevolent slaveowner, who never directly interferes with his movements.
Consequently, the liberal concept of freedom has disjointed the
question of freedom from the question of the form of government.
Citizens can theoretically experience the same amount of freedom
in a tyranny as in a democracy – it depends on the concrete extent
of interference from the state or the tyrant. According to the republican account of freedom as non-domination, however, the slave
would never be free, even living under the most benevolent of slaveowners, as the slaveowner always has the possibility to hypothetically intervene arbitrarily in the slave’s life. The mere possibility
of arbitrary intervention would reduce the slave to an unfree life in
the republican account. As maintained by Skinner (2008: 86), ‘the
master’s power is said to be arbitrary in the sense that it is always
open to him to govern his slaves, with impunity, according to his
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 101
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
102
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
mere arbitrium, his own will, and desires’. Consequently, neorepublicans have joined together freedom and form of government,
as citizens are only free in a free state; that is, when the citizenry
has political channels of participation, influence, and representation, hereby rendering the domination and interference existing in
every polity unarbitrary (Pettit 2013: 187–238).
This republican idea of freedom as non-domination has been
incredibly successful in pointing to various domains of political
and social life where arbitrary domination exists and could thus be
understood as domains of unfreedom. But in some ways, the idea
that socialists have and should embrace the republican tradition and
its concept of freedom as non-domination might sound peculiar.
The republican tradition has often been labelled aristocratic, and the
freedom enjoyed by male citizens during the Roman Republic, and
all the way to the foundation of the American Republic has often
come at the cost of the subjugation of slaves and women (Gourevitch 2014; McCormick 2018). Beyond the aristocratic heritage of
republicanism, political theorists and intellectual historians have
argued that a popular, plebeian and radical tradition of republicanism can be identified, emanating originally with the political
practices and constitutional offices of the Roman plebs (McCormick 2011), re-articulated by Machiavelli (Lefort 2012; Vergara
2020) and re-emerging with the French Revolution (Breaugh 2013;
von Eggers 2016) as well as with the Paris Commune (Breaugh
2013; Leipold, 2020). The central claim of the ‘second republican revival’, hence, is that nineteenth- and early twentieth-century
socialism is the inheritor of a non-aristocratic, popular tradition of
republicanism.
Socialist republicanism, accordingly, emerges as an extension
of republican freedom into the economic realm, to relations in the
workplace and as a critique of capitalism itself. The ‘second republican revival’ – as phrased in the introduction to a newly published,
edited volume on the subject – ‘seek to extend the concept’s [i.e.,
freedom as non-domination] application from political domination
(historically the main focus of republicanism) to social and private forms of domination’ (Leipold et al. 2020: 2). Whilst neorepublicanism has been interested in relations of domination and
dependency in the political realm, it has often stopped short of investigating and criticising such relations in the economic sphere – to
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 102
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
103
such a degree that the workplace has been deemed ‘a forgotten topic
in democratic theory’ (Ellerman 2009). This is where the opening
epigraphs by such different figures as the American Ivy League
professor Robert Dahl and the Austrian Marxist Otto Bauer become
relevant: If living under arbitrary power has detrimental effects on
freedom, arbitrary power in all social domains must come under
scrutiny and critique. As also highlighted by Nancy Fraser (2014:
64), a ‘division that is constitutive of capitalist society’, and reified
ideologically by liberalism, we might add, is ‘that between polity
and economy’. Such a constitutive division is part of the explanation why one crucial site of arbitrary domination in contemporary
Western societies is the workplace, where conditions of inequality, hierarchy and domination are taken as natural conditions, even
though such relations have long been formally abandoned in the
political sphere (Anderson 2017). Neo-republicanism’s ‘blind spot’1
towards economic relations of domination and unfreedom testify to
the fact that many republican thinkers incorporated in Skinner’s
and Pettit’s genealogy of republicanism (thinkers like Aristotle,
Cicero, Rousseau, Madison, Tocqueville) often displayed an aristocratic or elitist attitude, whereby constitutional design ought to
tamper the passions of the plebs and the popular classes. In short,
while republicanism is a staunch critic of monarchy and arbitrary
power, it is not inherently democratic, or at least not inherently in
favour of a popular understanding of democracy. Socialist republicanism, instead, holds that freedom as non-domination is, firstly,
an adequate concept of freedom to combat contemporary relations
of domination and exploitation (Anderson 2017; O’Shea 2019);
secondly, this concept of freedom has actually animated workingclass struggle since the emergence of capitalism in the eighteenth
and nineteenth centuries (Domènech 2004).
Socialist republicanism hinges on the idea that wage labour in
a capitalist society is a form of wage slavery. In privately owned,
capitalist corporations, workers are exposed to the arbitrary domination of managers and superiors without the right to participation (Hsieh 2005), and such domination is structural, as workers
deprived of productive assets might reject one workplace, but such
workers cannot refrain from selling their labour power if they seek
to uphold their livelihood (Anderson 2017; Fraser 2014: 57; Wood
2002). Capitalism, as seen through the eyes of a socialist republican,
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 103
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
104
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
is consequently a modern form of slavery, as ordinary workers, in
their attempt to survive, live under the arbitrary will of their managers. Such argument was aptly phrased by the nineteenth-century
American trade unionist Georg E. McNiell, who argued that ‘there
is an inevitable and irresistible conflict between the wage-system
of labour and the republican system of government’, and that it was
thus essential ‘to engraft republican principles into our industrial
system’ (McNiell in Gourevitch 2014: 6, 116). Distinctive methods
to ‘engraft republican principles into our industrial system’ have
been investigated by current socialist republicans stemming from
‘workplace constitutionalism’ (i.e., state regulation), ‘workplace
democracy’ (i.e., giving employees formal influence in the corporation), and forms of cooperative ownership (i.e., worker co-ownership and co-direction of the business) (Leipold et al. 2020: 10–14).
Gramsci’s European Context: A Brief Overview
of the Interwar Council Movements
To situate the reconstruction of Gramsci’s socialist republicanism
in historical context, it is necessary to introduce the European council movements as they appeared from 1917–1921. After the Russian
Revolution, workers’ councils emerged across multiple European
countries. Countries across Europe developed comparable organs
of economic self-management, and workers’ control such as the
Russian soviets, the German arbeiterräte, the British factory committees, and the Italian commissioni interne. Moreover, the council
movements were a vital force in the dissolution of the large empires
of Russia, Germany, and Austria-Hungary, and would be the leading actor in creating revolutionary transformations (Anweiler 1974;
Carsten 1972; Gombin 1978). Even though the council systems
across Europe seldom existed more than a couple of months,2 a
rather similar institutional structure emerged across countries.
Firstly, the workers’ councils operated as self-managing institutions, taking decisions on several questions (factory councils on
economic production and organisation of the workflow, army regiments on political and military support to the revolutionary movements, neighbourhood councils on food supply and infrastructure
in local districts). Secondly, the councils chose their own delegates
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 104
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
105
from the factory shop floor, the neighbourhood, the army regiment
to represent them in municipal, regional, and national councils.
Thirdly, the relation between the local councils and the central council was often structured by instant recall and imperative mandate.
These mechanisms of instruction, delegation, and recall, which also
in some form or another were establish in clubs and popular societies during the French Revolution, and in the Paris Commune, were
instruments through which the local councils could retain power at
the bottom of the federal council systems (Tomba 2015).
In Italy, which was Gramsci’s immediate political-historical ‘rawmaterial’ for his socialist republicanism, factory councils appeared
in many northern cities during the biennio rosso in 1919–20, most
forcefully in Turin, Milan, and Genoa. The biennio rosso was characterised by intense social conflict due to the economic crisis after
the First World War. As a result, the entire associative network on
the Italian Left – trade unions, the Italian Socialist Party (PSI), the
anarchist movement and syndicalist groups – experienced popular
support. In this political environment, especially influenced by the
strong Italian anarcho-syndicalist movement associated with Errico Malatesta, workers in the Fiat automobile plants around Turin
in particular began to occupy the factories and established internal
councils that ran the factories and established links to councils of
other factories. In the weeks after the establishment of the first factory council, councils were created across whole industries, quickly
representing approximately 50,000 workers (Di Paola 2011). Instrumental in disseminating information about the practicalities of the
council form, its historical significance, and political principles
was the newly created journal L’Ordine Nuovo (The New Order),
headed by Gramsci himself, the later founding member of the Italian Communist Party (PCI) Angelo Tasca, and long-term leader of
PCI Palmiro Togliatti. The factory councils in northern Italy never
developed into a nationwide structure as in Russia and Germany,
and never acquired the political power as their Russian and German
counterparts. Eventually the socialist activity of the biennio rosso
ebbed out, as another political force appeared on the Italian national
scene – the fascist Blackshirts and their rise to power. They were
eventually led by Benito Mussolini in the 1922 March on Rome.
After the council movements were dissolved everywhere in
Europe during the first years of the 1920s, the organisational form
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 105
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
106
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
and political principles of the councils were broadly discussed in the
socialist movements across Europe. The councils developed into a
hallmark for those socialist activists and political thinkers, who
sought to advance alternative ideas of democracy than the parliamentary version and who wanted to democratise the capitalist economy, but simultaneously sought to distance themselves from the
development of state communism and planned economy in Soviet
Russia. Deliberations on council democracy created an alternative
strain of left-wing political thinking, which placed the councils
beyond the distinction of social democratic parliamentarianism and
Leninist one-party rule. Council communists, as advocates of workers’ councils were called to distinguish themselves from Bolshevikstyle party communism, specifically attacked the hierarchisation
of the social democratic parties, the trade union movement and the
communist leadership, the absence of real participation of workers and peasants, and the social democratic and Bolshevik obsession with the power of the state. In contrast, council communists
rejected the parliamentarianism of social democrats as well as the
elitism and discipline of the Bolshevik vanguard, and instead, in the
apt phrasing of Geoff Eley, ‘they defended democratic values that
socialists . . . tended to forget – local control, direct participation,
small-scale community, and federative corporation’ (Eley 2002:
95). Rather than democratising the economy through the power of
the state, advocates of the councils cherished the ordinary workers
and shop floor activity; rather than respecting the parliamentary
process they preferred direct action and strikes; and rather than a
vanguard of professional revolutionaries, they stressed mass insurgency. This, we belief, is the appropriate historical-political context
necessary for reconstructing Gramsci’s socialist republicanism.
Gramsci’s Socialist Republicanism
Today, Antonio Gramsci stands out as one of the key Marxist
thinkers of the twentieth century. His most vital contribution to
the analysis of capitalism is his concept of hegemony developed
in the Prison Notebooks (1947), that is, the cultural and ideological underpinnings of capitalist economic exploitation. Whereas
orthodox readings of Marx’s historical materialism privileged
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 106
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
107
the economic base, Gramsci’s concept of hegemony pointed to
the ongoing ‘superstructural’ function of ideology in maintaining
capitalist relations of production. Such a reorientation had lasting
influence on Western Marxism, as thinkers associated with the first
generation of the Frankfurt School as well as thinkers like Louis
Althusser repeatedly analysed how bourgeois culture and the ‘ideological state apparatuses’ contributed to the ongoing hegemonic
renewal of the capitalist status quo. The success of Gramsci’s concept of hegemony positioned him throughout the twentieth century
as something resembling a master strategist for Western communist
parties, which fought for communism in the distinct condition of
capitalist, bourgeois cultural and ideological hegemony. Such a
condition required a special role for the ‘organic intellectuals’ of
the labour movement who were responsible for creating and disseminating a cultural counterhegemonic narrative during a gradual
and clandestine ‘war of positions’ before an eventual direct ‘war of
manoeuvre’ could be undertaken. The suitability of these Gramscian concepts to analyse the strategic situation of twentieth century,
Western European communist parties, though, have also to some
extent obscured the historical context and acute political conflicts,
which influenced Gramsci’s thinking (Bellamy 1994: ix). Therefore, by returning to his pre-prison writings, especially to the writings in L’Ordine Nuovo during the emergence of workers’ councils
and factory committees during the Italian biennio rosso, we can
reconstruct Gramsci’s concrete political programme of socialist
republicanism during the years of trans-European revolutionary
upheaval.
Central to such a reconstruction of Gramsci’s socialist republicanism is (a) his critique of capitalist factory production as a form
of despotic rule, (b) his critique of the liberal division between a
public, political sphere and a private, economic sphere, (c) his critique of parliamentary democracy and trade unionism has central
enforcers of this distinction between politics and economics, (d) his
understanding of freedom as political autonomy and economic selfmanagement, and (e) his insistence on workers’ councils and factory committees as pivotal organisational forms of what Otto Bauer
in the opening epigraph called a ‘republican economy’. Before surveying each of these elements of Gramsci’s socialist republicanism, it is worth stressing how they together provide an exemplary
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 107
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
108
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
illustration of what we have called the ‘second republican revival’,
insofar as Gramsci seeks to extend the historical legacy of a republican imaginary focused on political domination, arbitrary government, and freedom into the economic realm of capitalist relations
of production, in order to qualify the ideal of republican freedom
beyond the liberal divide between politics and economy.
The Despotism of the Modern Factory and the
Liberal Divide between Politics and Economics
A key starting point is the text ‘Red Sunday’ published in L’Ordine
Nuovo in September 1920, on the Sunday following the largest
factory occupations in Turin during the biennio rosso. The text
begins with Gramsci’s proclaiming the significance of the events,
insofar as ‘social hierarchies have been smashes, historical values
turned upside down. The “implementing” classes, the “instrumental
classes” have become the “managerial classes”: they have become
their own bosses’ (Gramsci 1994j: 198). The factory occupations
and creation of workers’ councils entails a reversal of hierarchies,
insofar as workers are no longer ‘instruments’ that ‘implement’ the
orders of distant bosses but are instead their own bosses capable of
managing the production circuits of a modern factory. The reason
such a reversal of hierarchy is significant relies on a distinct republican analysis of the modern factory system. ‘The factory’, according
to Gramsci, ‘under the capitalists, was a miniature State, ruled by a
despot. The ruler enjoyed a singular suffrage – a single man with a
single vote . . . The factory was a despotically organized State, with
all power resting in the hands of proprietor’ (Gramsci 1994j: 199).
Although the transition from a pre-capitalist to capitalist economy
entails the formal-juridical liberation of labour from direct forms
of extraction (Wood 2002), Gramsci argues that the capitalist factory is still ruled like a despotic state, where the capitalist enjoys
absolute power over his subjects. Everywhere throughout his biennio rosso writings, Gramsci uses the language of unfreedom, slavery, and tyranny so central to republicanism to describe the social
relations of capitalism: the factory is permeated with the ‘tyranny
of private ownership’ (1994b: 113), as ‘the salaried worker [is]
the slave of capital’ (1994c: 117), and the entire working class is
subjected to ‘industrial servitude’ (1994h: 172), as they toil ‘in
the darkness of the factory’ as part of ‘the countless multitude that
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 108
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
109
capitalism subjects to its laws’ (1994g: 164) via the power of ‘the
new and pitiless feudal lords of capitalism’ (1994a: 89). Once we
leave the so-called free sphere of market exchange, and enter into
the ‘hidden abode’ of capitalist production (Fraser 2014), the lives
of the working masses, according to Gramsci, are permeated with
arbitrary power, slave-like conditions and tyrannic commands – in
short, with unfreedom.
What idea of freedom can be excavated from Gramsci’s early
writings during the biennio rosso period? In the short text ‘The
Sovereignty of the Law’, published in the daily newspaper of the
Italian Socialist Party Avanti! in 1919, Gramsci discusses the kind
of freedom enjoyed by the Italians since the first liberal constitution, the so-called Staturo Albertino of 1848. At first glance,
Gramsci argues, the Italians have since 1848 ‘no longer been at the
mercy of the irresponsible state. Rule by whim, by arbitrary decree,
have disappeared from our social scene: our society has become
a society of ‘citizens’, equal in their rights and duties, which are
equally watched over and protected by the founding Charter of the
realm’ (1994a: 87). Gramsci’s description of the Italians’ liberty
entails many elements of the classical republican understanding of
freedom as non-domination. As the state is now governed by standing laws, and in accordance with a basic constitution that treats
and protects citizens equally, arbitrary decree – the cornerstone of
republicanism’s critique of monarchical government – has been
substituted for a ‘society of citizens’, that is, by free men, who
cannot be governed by an alien, arbitrary will. But according to
Gramsci, the constitution’s liberal instantiation of an equal and
free ‘society of citizens’ hides the fact – or rather justifies it ideologically – that unfreedom exist in the economic sphere due to the
sanctity of private property, as ‘this “freedom” immediately turns
into the disadvantage of the proletariat’, insofar as ‘the conditions
of the salaried worker become worse than those of the slave or the
serf’ (Gramsci 1994a: 89). The central divide between the ‘free’
political sphere and ‘unfree’ economic sphere has overall detrimental effects on society, as collectivities are broken up, and – in
the phrasing of economic historian Karl Polanyi (2001: 136–140) –
and economic activities are ‘dis-embedded’ from social bonds and
communal practices. According to Gramsci, ‘society is cut loose
from any kind of collective bonds and reduced to its primordial
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 109
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
110
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
element of the citizen-individual. And society begins to dissolve,
eaten away by the corrosive acids of competition’ (Gramsci 1994a:
88). As such, the modern liberal divide between politics and economics reifies the ongoing capitalist domination, despite the civil
liberties inscribed in a liberal constitution, insofar as ‘on the terrain
of production, in the factory, where relations are those between the
oppressor and the oppressed, the exploiter and the exploited, where
there is no such thing as liberty for the worker and no such thing as
democracy’ (Gramsci 1994g: 164).
This also means that the working-class organisations, which have
emerged under conditions of capitalism, such as for example trade
unions, are inherently insufficient, because they themselves contribute to the division between politics and economy. The trade
union ‘organizes workers not as producers, but as wage-earners:
that is, as creatures of capitalist private ownership’ (Gramsci 1994e:
128). Trade unions might a provide a ‘constitutionalisation’ of the
workplace, but they accept the basic premises of capitalism, namely
wage labour (Domènech 2004: 248). Instead, Gramsci looks to
the newly established workers’ councils in the factories of Turin,
Milan, and Genoa for his institutional socialist republicanism.
The ‘Proletarian Republic’, Workers’
Councils and Republican Economy
In the same article – Red Sunday – in L’Ordine Nuovo, published
after the huge factory occupations in Turin in 1920, where Gramsci
at length discussed the despotism and tyrannical unfreedom of the
capitalist factory, he also described the newly occupied and selfmanaging factories as ‘proletarian republics’ (Gramsci 1994j: 199).
Such ‘proletarian republics’ were governed by a general assembly –
‘the organ of power and sovereignty of the proletarian factoryrepublics’ (Gramsci 1994j: 201) – which would decide on overall
matters relating to the inner life of the factory. As also argued by
Antoni Domènech (2004: 248), such ‘proletarian factory-republics’ would introduce republican practices of deliberation, collective decision-making, and contestation into the productive sphere.
The general assembly, moreover, would also elect representatives
to administer the factory’s daily affairs, but unlike parliamentary
representatives, who are only bound by their own conscience, the
daily administers of the ‘proletarian republics’ would be under
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 110
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
111
imperative mandate and subject to instant recall by the sovereign
general assembly. Through these institutional mechanisms – which
were also found in the other socialist republican institutional formations such as the Paris Commune and the Russian soviets (Gramsci
1994i: 180; Popp-Madsen 2021) – political power would (theoretically) be retained at the popular level, and delegates would not turn
into a new bureaucratic elite as was the case of trade unions and
parliamentary parties (Gramsci 1994j: 201; 1994e: 128).
In addition, the self-governing workers’ councils would socialise
the economy, as the popular take-over of factories ‘eliminated all
masters’ and based ‘a new order of production . . . on the collective
interests of the social community’ (Gramsci 1994f: 144; 1994d:
124). Crucially, these institutional innovations are by Gramsci continually cast in the language of freedom – not equality, emancipation, or justice. With the emergence of workers’ councils and
‘proletarian factory-republics’ across northern Italy, ‘the “citizen”
is displaced by the “comrade”; social atomism by social organisation . . . the worker wins a degree of autonomy for himself, a degree
of real, effectual freedom’ (Gramsci 1994a: 89). What Gramsci
here displays is a distinctively republican meditation on the meaning of freedom. It might be case that Enlightenment understandings
of individual rights and citizenship, emanating from the more moderate strains of the French Revolution, provide an abstract, formal
ideal of freedom – the type of freedom, which like the liberal, negative freedom of non-interference is divorced from concrete forms of
government. The preambles of the late eighteenth-century declarations of the rights of men and declarations of independence speak of
natural, self-evident freedom and equality, separated from the concrete, material realisation of such freedom. But in the ‘proletarian
republics’, this abstract freedom is substituted with a ‘real, effectual
freedom’, grounded on the one hand in the worker’s autonomy (the
condition that the worker, not an external master, gives himself his
own laws – auto nomos), but on the other hand that such ‘real, effectual freedom’ can only attained in common through ‘social organisation’. We regard this second requirement for the realisation of
republican freedom as a distinct contribution by the ‘second republican revival’ of socialist republicanism. Crucially, for neo-republicans such as Skinner and Pettit, freedom as non-domination refers
predominantly to a legal-constitutional status, which is acquired
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 111
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
112
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
through the individual status as a citizen of a free republic. In the
phrasing of Pettit, for republicanism ‘enslavement and subjection
are great ills, and independence and status the supreme goods’ (Pettit 1997: 132). Once we extend the republican ideal of freedom as
non-domination into the economic sphere, which we have argued
is the key ambition of socialist republicans, this type of freedom
requires collective, social organisation and concrete institutional
mechanisms. As such, ‘the Factory Council’, which according to
Gramsci is ‘the only proletarian institution, which, springing up, as
it does, in a sphere outside the political relations of one citizen to
another, a sphere in which freedom and democracy for the working class do not exist, where all that does exist in all its harshness
and cruelty, is the economic relation between the exploiter and the
exploited, the oppressor and the oppressed, represents the endless
striving for freedom that the working class is engaged in’ (Gramsci
1994h: 174).
Conclusion: Antonio Gramsci and the
‘Second Republican Revival’
In a recent, important intervention in the debate on workplace
democracy, the philosopher Elisabeth Anderson has shown the
effects of the Industrial Revolution and the historical emergence
of capitalism on progressive political thinking. Her argument, in
short, is that progressive, pre-nineteenth-century political thinking
to some extent looked to the market as a model of free and equal
social organisation. The market, by dispensing with earlier hierarchical relations of serfdom, apprenticeship and tenancy associated
with estate-based society, provided in eyes of pre-capitalist progressives ample opportunity for small-scale property ownership, and
self-employment – in short, the market was thought to be one main
road for gaining the independence associated with being ‘masterless
men’ (Anderson 2017: 7–17). The market – in Anderson’s narrative – for pre-Industrial Revolution progressives, hence, was thought
to be integral for the realisation of republican freedom (i.e., to be an
‘independent masterless man’). Thomas Jefferson’s radical republicanism is founded upon small-scale, agrarian self-ownership, and
Thomas Paine’s influential advocacy of popular sovereignty during
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 112
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
113
both the American and the French Revolutions went hand in hand
with the promotion of small-scale independent producers3 (Anderson 2017: 22–33). Although, critiques of the market as a place of
domination and exploitation were already present in the eighteenth
century (in particular during the French Revolution), Anderson’s
central argument (2017: 33–36) is that the Industrial Revolution
of the nineteenth century completely shattered the centrality of the
market for progressive thinking. Instead of being a model of free
and equal social exchange, the market became the central site of
domination and exploitation. The reason being that economies of
scale and the amount of capital and labour needed for industrial production, along with the closing of the American frontier, made the
progressive ideal of small-scale independent producers impossible
for the many. As highlighted continually by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels throughout The Communist Manifesto (1848), industrial
capitalism inaugurated a descent of the small artisans, craftsmen,
and petty bourgeois shopkeepers into the proletariat. In short, selfemployment became a rarity for the masses, wage labour the norm.
What happened to the ideal of republican freedom as non-domination, independence and ‘masterlessness’ under these new conditions? The argument that is gradually emerging from what we have
called the ‘second republican revival’ is that the socialist movements of the nineteenth and twentieth century inherited and further developed the republican ideal of freedom as non-domination
under these markedly new conditions of capitalist production.4 The
ambition of this article has been, firstly, to substantiate the recent
turn from neo-republicanism to socialist republicanism; that is, to
demonstrate the recent theoretical preoccupation by political theorists and intellectual historians by extending the neo-republican
concept of freedom as non-domination from the formal, political
sphere to the sphere of economic life. Many recent interventions on
workplace democracy, common ownership, and cooperativism as
ways of taming – or transcending – capitalism is directly applying
the political language of republicanism to understand and challenge
domination and hierarchy in the economic sphere. Secondly, and
as a way of amending and contributing to this ‘second republican
revival’, we have aimed at inscribing the influential Marxist thinker
Antonio Gramsci into the tradition of socialist republicanism. By
discussing his pre-prison writings in the historical context of Italy’s
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 113
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
114
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
biennio rosso, where workers’ councils and factory committees
partly managed the heavy industry in major northern cities, we
have highlighted how Gramsci applies a distinctively republican
conceptual vocabulary in his critique of the despotism, tyranny, and
lack of freedom in the capitalist factory, as well as how Gramsci
envisioned the workers’ councils emerging throughout Europe from
the Russian Revolution and onwards as the basis of the new institutional form of proletarian republics. In these proletarian republics,
freedom as non-domination could be enjoyed due to novel institutional mechanisms such as imperative mandate and instant recall,
as well as due to the socialisation of production through common
ownership and factory democracy – or what Otto Bauer called a
‘republican economy’. By stipulating how republican freedom
can be realised under industrial conditions, where the traditional
republican ideal of small-scale, independent producers is unviable,
Gramsci also puts forward a distinct socialist republican understanding of freedom as non-domination. Whereas neo-republicans
like Skinner and Pettit understand republican freedom as a legalconstitutional, individual status, Gramsci highlights how social
organisation, class solidary and ongoing deliberative practices are
necessary conditions for a free state. If one wants to be a republican,
Gramsci could be taken to argue, one must be a socialist.
Andreas Møller Mulvad is an independent researcher. His research
focuses on the relationship between capitalism and democracy. He
has worked on China’s unfinished journey towards democracy and
is currently studying the cooperative roots of the success of ‘the
Nordic Model’. In Denmark’s public arena, he is an advocate for
sortition, having published the popular audience monograph Tæm
Eliten, which proposes a second chamber selected by lottery, as
well as the use of sortition to form recruitment committees for positions as board members representing the civic interest in major
private companies. E-mail:
[email protected]
Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen is a Postdoc at Copenhagen Business School. His research focuses on democratic theory, history of
political thought, civil society and Nordic politics. Benjamin has
published on these issues in Political Theory, Polity, Thesis Eleven,
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 114
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
115
Constellations: An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory, Contemporary Political Theory, Critical Horizons
and Management and Organizational History. His book Visions of
Council Democracy: Castoriadis, Lefort, Arendt was published in
2021 by Edinburgh University Press in 2021 in the series Taking on
the Political. E-mail:
[email protected]
Notes
Epigraphs: Dahl 1986: 134–135; Bauer 1936: 199.
1. Pettit sometimes discusses the relationship between republicanism and economic
domination, for example, in relation to universal basic income. See Pettit (2007).
2. In Berlin, during the German Revolution of 1918–19, the councils were in power
from November to December 1918 (Hoffrogge 2011: 84–103), in Hungary the
councils only exercised power from March to August 1919 (Carsten 1972: 50–59),
and in countries such as Austria, Italy and Britain, the various council formations
never reached considerable power in national politics (Di Paola 2011: 130–147;
Gluckstein 1985; Haumer 2015: 120–156). In Russia, where the workers’ council
first appeared, a system of workers’ councils shared power with the Provisional
Government – the ‘dual power’ situation – from February to October 1917, after
which the Bolsheviks seized power. See also Muldoon (2020) and Popp-Madsen
(2021).
3. In addition, Thomas Paine also argued in the pamphlet Agrarian Justice (1797),
that those owning land through self-ownership ought to pay a rental fee for the land
to the general community, in order for the community to fund old-age and disability pensions and basic income for all adult citizens. Hence, Paine was aware that
the non-universal spread of self-ownership would necessitate economic redistribution.
4. For further historiographical documentation of this argument, see Domènech
(2004), Gourevitch (2014), and Roberts (2017).
References
Anderson, E. 2017. Private Government: How Employers Rule Over Our Lives
(and We Don’t Talk about It). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Anweiler, O. 1974. The Soviets: The Russian Workers, Peasants, and Soldiers
Councils, 1905–1921. New York: Pantheon Books.
Bauer, O. 2017. Zwischen zwei Weltkriegen? Die Krise der Weltwirtschaft, der
Demokratie und des Sozialismus [Between two world wars? The crisis of the
world economy, democracy and socialism]. Bratislava: Europaverlag
Bellamy, R. 1994. ‘Introduction’. In Antonio Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ix–xxviii.
Berlin, I. 1958. ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’. In Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 115
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
116
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
Breaugh, M. 2013. The Plebeian Experience: A Discontinuous History of
Political Freedom. New York: Columbia University.
Breen, K. 2015. ‘Freedom, Republicanism, and Workplace Democracy’, Critical
Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 18 (4): 470–485.
Carsten, F. 1972. Revolution in Central Europe, 1918–1919. London: Maurice
Temple Smith Ltd.
Currarino, R. 2011. The Labor Question in America: Economic Democracy in
the Gilded Age. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.
Dahl, R. 1986. A Preface to Economic Democracy. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Di Paola, P. 2011. ‘Factory Councils in Turin, 1919–1920: “The Sole and
Authentic Social Representatives of the Proletarian Class”’. In I. Ness and
D. Azzellini (eds), Ours to Master and to Own: Workers’ Control from the
Commune to the Present. Chicago: Haymarket Books.
Domènech, A. 2004. El Eclipse de la Fraternidad: Una Revisión Republicana
de la Tradición Socialista [The eclipse of fraternity: A republican revision of
the socialist tradition]. Barcelona: Crítica.
Eley, G. 2002. Forging Democracy: The History of the Left in Europe, 1850–
2000. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ellerman, D. 2009. ‘The Workplace: A Forgotten Topic in Democratic
Theory?’, Kettering Review (Summer): 51–57.
Fraser, N. 2014. ‘“Behind Marx” Hidden Above’, New Left Review 86: 55–72.
Gluckstein, D. 1985. The Western Soviets: Workers’ Councils Versus
Parliament, 1915–1920. London: Bookmarks.
González-Ricoy, I. 2014. ‘The Republican Case for Workplace Democracy’,
Social Theory and Practice 40 (2): 232–254.
Gombin, R. 1978. The Radical Tradition: A Study in Modern Revolutionary
Thought. London: Methuen & Co Ltd.
Gourevitch, A. 2014. From Slavery to the Cooperative Commonwealth: Labor
and Republican Liberty in the Nineteenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Gramsci, A. 1994a. ‘The Sovereignty of Law’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison
Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 87–90.
Gramsci, A. 1994b. ‘The Conquest of the State’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison
Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 108–114.
Gramsci, A. 1994c. ‘Unions and Councils’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 115–120.
Gramsci, A. 1994d. ‘The Trade Unions and the Dictatorship of the Proletariat’.
In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 121–126.
Gramsci, A. 1994e. ‘Syndicalism and the Councils’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison
Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 127–131.
Gramsci, A. 1994f. ‘The Italian State’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 141–145.
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 116
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
From Neo-Republicanism to Socialist Republicanism
117
Gramsci, A. 1994g. ‘The Factory Council’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 163–167.
Gramsci, A. 1994h. ‘The Communist Groups’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison
Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 172–177.
Gramsci, A. 1994i. ‘The Programme of L’Ordine Nuovo’. In A. Gramsci, PrePrison Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 178–186.
Gramsci, A. 1994j. ‘Red Sunday’. In A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 198–202.
Hammersley, R. 2020. Republicanism – An Introduction. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Haumer, P. 2015. ‘The Austrian Revolution of 1918–1919 and Working Class
Autonomy’. In D. Azzellini (ed), An Alternative Labour History: Worker
Control and Workplace Democracy. London: Zed Books.
Hoffrogge, R. 2011. ‘From Unionism to Workers’ Control: The Revolutionary
Shop Stewards Movement in Germany, 1914–1918’. In I. Ness and D.
Azzellini (eds), Ours to Master and to Own: Workers’ Control from
Commune to the Present. Chicago: Haymarket Books.
Honohan, I. 2002. Civic Republicanism. London: Routledge.
Hsieh, N. 2005. ‘Rawlsian Justice and Workplace Republicanism’, Social
Theory and Practice, 31 (1): 115–148.
Kärrylä, I. 2021. Democracy and Economy in Finland and Sweden since 2016.
London: Palgrave.
Kouris, Y. 2020. Radical Republicanism: The New Idea of the Left? ENA:
Institute for Alternative Policies. https://www.enainstitute.org/wp-content/
uploads/2020/05/ENA_Radical-Republicanism_Final-1.pdf.
Landemore, H. and I. Ferreras. 2015. ‘In Defense of Workplace Democracy:
Towards a Justification of the Firm–State Analogy’, Political Theory 44 (1):
53–81.
Leipold, B., K. Nabulsi, and S. White. (eds.). 2020. Radical Republicanism:
Recovering the Tradition’s Popular Heritage. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leipold, B. 2020. ‘Marx’s Social Republic: Radical Republicanism and the
Political Institutions of Socialism’. In B. Leipold, K. Nabulsi and S. White
(eds), Radical Republicanism: Recovering the Tradition’s Popular Heritage.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lefort, C. 2012. Machiavelli in the Making. Chicago: Northwestern University
Press.
McCormick, J. P. 2011. Machiavellian Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
McCormick, J. P. 2018. Reading Machiavelli: Scandalous Books, Suspect
Engagements and the Virtue of Populist Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Muldoon, J. 2019. ‘A Socialist Republican Theory of Freedom and
Government’, European Journal of Political Theory 21 (1): 47–67. https://
doi.org/10.1177/1474885119847606.
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 117
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM
118
Andreas Møller Mulvad and Benjamin Ask Popp-Madsen
Muldoon, J. 2020. Building Power to Change the World: The Political Thought
of the German Council Movement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
O’Shea, T. 2019. ‘Socialist Republicanism’, Political Theory 48 (5): 548–572.
Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Pettit, P. 2007. ‘A Republican Right to Basic Income?’, Basic Income Studies:
An International Journal of Basic Income Research 2 (2): 1–18.
Pettit, P. 2013. On the People’s Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of
Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Polanyi, K. 2001. The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic
Origins of Our Time. Boston: Beacon Press.
Popp-Madsen, B. A. 2021. Visions of Council Democracy: Castoriadis, Lefort,
Arendt. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Roberts, W. C. 2017. Marx’s Inferno: The Political Theory of Capital. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Skinner, Q. 1998. Liberty before Liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Skinner, Q. 2008. Hobbes and Republican Liberty. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Thompson, M. 2018. ‘A Theory of Council Republicanism’. In J. Muldoon
(ed) Council Democracy: Towards a Democratic Socialist Politics. London:
Routledge, 108–128.
Tomba, M. 2015. ‘1793: The Neglected Legacy of Insurgent Universality’.
History of the Present 5 (2): 109–136.
Vergara, C. 2020. Systemic Corruption: Constitutional Ideas for an AntiOligrachic Republic. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
von Eggers, N. 2016. ‘When the People Assemble, the Laws Go Silent: Radical
Democracy and the French Revolution’, Constellations 23 (2): 255–268.
White, S. 2007. ‘Is Republicanism the Left’s Big Idea?’, Renewal 15 (1): 37–46.
Wood, E. M. 2002. The Origins of Capitalism: A Longer Review. London:
Verso.
Theoria 171 June 2022.indb 118
6/2/2022 6:41:31 PM