PHILOSOPHY & GEOGRAPHY, VOL. 4, NO. 2, 2001
ARTICLE
The city and the philosopher:
on the urbanism of phenomenology
EDUARDO MENDIETA
Department of Philosophy, University of San Francisco, San Francisco, CA, USA
Abstract Philosophy projects a certain understanding of reason that is related to the ways in
which the city gures in its imaginary. Conversely, the city is a practice of spatialization that
determines the ways in which agents are able, or unable, to live out their social agency. This
essay focuses on the ways in which philosophy and the city’s spatializing practices and
imaginaries inform differential ways of living out social agency. The thrust of the investigation
is to discern the ways in which sexism—differential engendering—results from the relationship
that exists between philosophy and the city. To illustrate this link between philosophy, the city,
and differential engendering, the work turns to a consideration of Jean-Paul Sartre’s phenomenology, which is taken as an exemplary illustration of the entwinement between the
philosophical imaginary, and the perception and reception of the city.
Introduction
The history of philosophy can be, and has been, written as the history of philosophical
systems, currents, schools, great philosophers, even as the story of the succession of
geopolitically hegemonic empires.1 A history of philosophy as the history of its sites of
production, however, has yet to be undertaken.2 Why this project has not been
undertaken is certainly related to the fundamental prejudice that orients most, if not all,
philosophy. This prejudice assumes that philosophy is about thinking the absolute, the
universal, in a way that transcends, effaces and erases the traces of the origin and site
from which or out of which such thinking is thought. Philosophy, to use an expression
of Merleau-Ponty, does not project a shadow, because it is no where. Another reason
why the archeology of the sites of the production of philosophy has yet to be undertaken
is related to the prima facie plurality of such sites. One may in grosso modo suggest the
following parallels: Greek philosophy to Agora, Roman philosophy to Imperial City,
Christian philosophy to Monastery and/or Church, Modern philosophy to European
urban centers of mercantile, colonialist, and later, imperialist capitalism, and so on.
There is a way in which if we think of philosophy as a practice, the practice of thought,
this practice must have been and continues to be determined by the place in which and
out of which it is practiced. And in this realization there lies perhaps the most
fundamental reason why the archeology of the sites of the production of philosophy has
ISSN 1090-3771 print/ISSN 1472-7242 online/01/020203-16 Ó 2001 Taylor & Francis Ltd
DOI: 10.1080/10903770120067043
204
E. MENDIETA
not been undertaken. The links between thought and place, thinking and space, remain
elusive, if not mutually exclusionary. To think is to be where one is not, and to be, in
body and soul, is to focus on the moment, on what is present at hand. Yet, thinking is
conditioned by space, just as how a space, a place, in turn, is made accessible by a way
of thinking.3 This paper is about how philosophy thinks, images, and projects space,
thus contributing to the consolidation, legitimation, and normalization of certain spatial
practices. At the same time, it is also about how certain social practices, once solidied
and coagulated into topographies and geographies that map social relations, in turn
condition the ways space is to be represented, experienced, and lived, i.e., to be thought
by philosophy. The central claim of this essay is that philosophy has been most
fundamentally determined by the city, and conversely, that the city is related to the
project, or production, of philosophy.
In the rst part of the essay, I combine the insights of Lefebvre and Appadurai in
order to develop a method of analysis that will render the internal relations between
philosophizing and the city evident and graspable. This method I call chronotopology, or
the study of spatial-temporal regimes. Here, however, I want to focus on the elements
that such a method entail.4 Thus, this essay is not an exercise in either reconstruction
or exegesis. It has a generative telos, namely to offer insight into those tools, or
categories of analysis, that we would have to take into account were we to develop a
comprehensive analysis of the co-determination of the city, as perhaps the paramount,
although not only, locus of the actualization of space, and philosophy.5 Chronotopology
would be the method. Lefebvre and Appadurai would be two precursors. The central
thesis that this essay seeks to illustrate and defend is that the city as a site in which one
may nd the traces of practices, representations, and experiences of space is inescapably
a product of the philosophical imaginary. Philosophy thinks the city, be it in the form
of an image, a utopia, even a conceptual grid. At the same time, however, precisely
because the city is the site of the sedimentation of practices, representations, and lived
experiences, it enacts a particular philosophical imaginary. Philosophy is enabled as a
practice of the imagination but also of the body itself (philosophers have homes and
sometimes they walk or drive to their places of teaching) by the city. One may even say
that the city imagines/images philosophy.
The second half of the essay turns to a case study of Jean-Paul Sartre. Again, the
idea is not to develop a comprehensive analysis of Sartre’s concept of space. Nor is it
to illustrate how Sartre changes his ideas about space as he progresses from phenomenology to Marxism.6 Rather, the point is to illustrate how Sartre’s phenomenological investigations exhibit the kind of co-determination that exist between philosophy
and the city. Many other philosophers would have been equally appropriate as litmus
tests. Heidegger comes to mind immediately, but also Plato and his Academy, and
Aristotle, whose school was called the peripatetics, because they used to walk around
while philosophizing.7 By the same token, if the general approach of this paper is to be
credible at all, we should be able to nd correlations between cities and philosophers,
if not entire philosophical systems, not just in the 20th century, or at the so-called dawn
of Western philosophy, but throughout its entire history.8
The philosophizing of the city
In order to approach the question of the relationship between the city and philosophy,
I will avail myself of the framework developed by Henri Lefebvre. I will complement his
framework with Arjun Appadurai’s work on the imagination in the age of globalization,
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
205
which I think is pertinent to the discussion of spatialization and philosophy’s relationship to the practices and technologies of embodiment that are allowed and called for by
the city. I think that this synthesis of Lefebvre with Appadurai allows a discussion of the
political economy of the production of space that, hopefully, will neither slide back into
Marxist economism and ideological reductivism, nor, just as importantly, simply regurgitate Eurocentric spatialities.
In order to be able to explicate how space is produced, in a non-reductivist way,
Henri Lefebvre distinguishes between: spatial practice, representations of space, and
representational spaces. Every social system is legitimated through an ideology. This
ideology is “primarily a discourse upon social space.”9 This discourse upon social space,
however, must be differentiated in terms of the practices that undergird it and produce
it, the way it is actually projected as an idea or image, and how it is lived. Ideology, after
all, is a matter of lived experience. Thus, for Lefebvre, to disentangle the ideology of a
particular system requires that we discern the ways in which the spatial practices of a
social system “secretes that society’s space.”10 Spatial practices consist of, for instance,
the processes of contemporary gentrication that displace some through the valorization
of certain spaces; the localization of educational institutions within certain neighborhoods which are also within the reach of sport, transportation, and scientic training
facilities; the gentrication of areas through access to loans and mortgages that results
in ghettoization, the displacement and emplacement of spaces of production either far
away or very close to spaces of living, which might not stand close to places of mass
public transportation. But spatial practices, and here I am expanding on Lefebvre, also
consist in the constitution of what I would like to call lustscapes or pornscapes that match
the consumptionscapes that gentrify civic agents.11 These, in turn, are also to be differentiated from powerscapes, and entertainmentscapes (or to mutate Benjamin Barber’s
term, infotainmentscapes12) that further map the city. Red zone districts, like ghettos
of power and powerless, mark bodies by marking zones for the consumption and
production of desire, the abjection and policing of the other.13
Spatial practices are not by any means driven solely by economic imperatives. They
are driven by the imaginary of power, and by the power of the imagination. The
monumentality of a Paris, Rome, or New York are all defaced, challenged, and
contested by the grafti of the people, the murals that give voice to the power of the city,
and the contestation of civic space through loitering, walking, festivals and commemorations.14 Indeed, cities are sites of struggle between classes, ethnicities, and genders.
Cities, in turn, are gatherings of places which are memories of wars and battles, conicts
and victories. Cities are also the testament, if not the bequest, of both real and
metaphorical struggles between cities that stood or stand now for certain ideas,
ideologies, or imaginaries: Athens versus Jerusalem, Paris versus Berlin, Washington
versus Moscow, etc.15
Two different and famous but illustrative examples of the ways in which a society’s
spatial practices secretes that society’s space are Los Angeles and New York. The former
is a city of distances to be broached by cars and highways. The latter is a city of
closeness in the midst of a concrete, steel, and beroptics jungle. The former is linked
by a network of asphalt and cement, the latter by its famous subway system. Their daily
and ceaseless ows of peoples through its arteries is the most highly obvious way in
which a city’s spatial practices condition civic agents. One reaches horizontally, the other
vertically. Both claim, gather, produce, and secrete space differently. Both, however, are
but different versions of the same quest for the eternal West, the eternal frontier.16
Every spatial practice is accompanied by its representations of space. There is no
206
E. MENDIETA
absolute space, except as a representation of an abstracted, reied social space. These
representations are generally produced by “scientists, planners, urbanists, technocratic
subdividers and social engineers” by identifying “what is lived and what is perceived
with what is conceived.”17 Absolute, abstract space is function of a particular way of
representing space that corresponds to the rise of mercantilism, capitalism, and the
centrality of the city as a site for the exchange of commodities, and the quantication
of all interchange. The classic examples of representations of space are the development
of perspective in painting by the Renaissance painters, which was catalyzed by the new
role of cities in Western societies, and the development of non-Euclidian geometries at
the turn of the century, which might have been catalyzed by the de-centering of Europe.
These are arguments that require sustained and careful illustration, one which is beyond
the scope of this circumscribed space. Still, Lefebvre devotes a sizeable part of his book
The Production of Space to substantiating these claims.18
Representations of space and spatial practices determine the coordinates within which
social agents live their space. Spatial practices, as Lefebvre puts it, secrete a society’s
space.19 When this secretion converges or dialectically interacts with the representations
of space produced by society’s engineers and technocracts, it also enters into dialectical
tension with the lived space of agents. This lived space is what Lefebvre calls representational spaces. These spaces are “directly lived through [their] association with images and
symbols.”20 These are the space of inhabitants and users, but also of artists and perhaps
even philosophers who “aspire” to do more than merely describe.21 It is from such
representational spaces that subjects are emplaced and embodied as social agents. It is
from these representational spaces that agents peer outward to the civic landscape, and
inward to their psychic life. A representational space always acts as a horizon from which
we are allowed to or prevented from surveying our localization in social space.22 The
inside of the body, and the outside of the mind, to paraphrase a wonderful formulation
of Elizabeth Grosz, are circumscribed by these spaces.23 In other words, how the look
from outside towards the inside, and conversely, from inside towards the supposedly
legible surface of the body, condition each other is determined by these representational
spaces. Sexism, as well as racism, are functions of the representational spaces that allow or
disallow one to occupy one’s own body, and one’s civic space.24 Sexism denies one
access to a representational space of one’s body that is free from the colonizing gaze of
another.25 Sexism constitutes those representational spaces that condition the ways in
which one is able to localize one’s body in social space.26 The same holds for racism.
Frantz Fanon’s famous discussion of racism is easily translatable into the language of the
spatializing that is allowed by representational spaces, that is, racism is nding oneself
in a world in which no space is one’s own, and all spaces are commandeered by a
supreme master race.27 To be black, like being female, means not being allowed, and
not being able to think oneself, in certain spaces, or places, at certain times, or hours
of the night (or day, depending).
For Lefebvre, spatial practices, representations of space, and representational
spaces stand in direct relation to the dialectical triad: the perceived, the conceived, and
the lived. A spatial practiced is perceived, a representation of space is what is conceived,
and a representational space is what is lived. The point of this analytical model,
however, is not to establish a formal schematic, but rather to grant us the tools to ascend
to the most concrete forms of the historical production of space. One might therefore say that an archeology of subjectivity can be pursued through an archeology of
the production of space.28 How a social agent lives, conceives, and perceives their
social existence is related to the spatial practices, the representations of space, and
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
207
the representational spaces that together offer us a cartography of a particular
society.29
In order to establish better the links I want to elucidate between philosophy, the
city, and differential gendering embodiments, I would like to synthesize Lefebvre’s
analysis of the production of space with Arjun Appadurai’s discussion of the imaginary.
I turn to him for two reasons. First, because I read his work as an attempt to theorize
the positive dimensions of ideology, that is, I read his work as an illustration of how
control, hegemony, and in tandem, resistance and contestation, are not just a negative
operation but also a positive production. In other words, his work illustrates how
ideology produces images, and excites the imagination, thus controlling the imaginary.
Ideology does not just obfuscate, conceal, and mask, it also makes us see in certain ways,
or allows us only to see what we can see when we are looking at it. Ideology controls
by allowing and disallowing what is imaginable and unthinkable, and to this extent, it
is not just negative, or constraining, it is also positive and creative. I think that this
aspect of Appadurai’s work can serve as a corrective to some elements of Lefebvre’s
work that may sound too deterministic. The second reason why I turn to Appadurai is
because I nd that most contemporary discussions of postcolonial issues and of
globalization seem to be proceeding as if globalization and postcoloniality happen
somewhere else on the map. Someone else is postcolonial, just as someone else is the
victim of globalization. Appadurai’s work contests this unilateral and anatropic perspective. For Appaduari, who develops his discussion explicitly from within the context of
a confrontation between postcolonial and globalization theories, what distinguishes
globalization, or our contemporary life, is the new role imagination has attained not just
in relationship to some putative center, but to the entire planet. I nd this sensibility and
approach to be not just apropos, but also theoretically necessary. It helps correct the
Eurocentric or North Atlantic focus of Lefebvre’s political economy of the production
of space.
In order to grasp the new role of the imagination in global society, Appadurai brings
together three approaches: that of the Frankfurt school with its focus on images,
especially those that have been mechanically produced and reproduced; that of social
historians informed by Benedict Anderson’s idea of the imagined community; and that
of French social thought that focuses on the idea of the imaginary (Lacan, et. al).
Together, these approaches allow us to bring together the image, the imagined, and the
imaginary. In synergy, they allow us to discern the dialectic of the new global cultural
process, which in Appadurai’s terms signals the recognition of imagination as social
practice. Globalization, thus, could be understood as the new cultural process in which
the imagination has become an organized eld of social practices, a form of
work (in the sense of both labor and culturally organized practice), and a form
of negotiation between sites of agency (individuals) and globally dened elds
of possibility … The imagination is now central to all forms of agency, is itself
a social fact, and is the key component of the new global order.30
I want to suggest that there is a relationship between Lefebvre’s spatial practices,
representations of space, representational spaces, and Appadurai’s image, the imagined,
and the imaginary. A spatial practice is always perceived as an image, as in the image
of a cityscape, the sky-line of a city, the congested highways extending and vanishing in
the horizon, the monstrous snakes of people being vomited from the entrails of the city,
etc. A representation of space is always an imagined space. We project from an image
of what is perceived, an ideal, extreme, claried imaged. The empty space of science, the
208
E. MENDIETA
absolute space of mathematics, and the abstract space of transcendental reection all
reect the empty space of the city square, the space of power that the state occupies, and
the space of sociality that civic participation both represents and requires. Finally, a
representational space is to lived space what the imaginary is to the images and
imagination that we develop from a given social space. The social imaginary is
conditioned by the images and imagination allowed or not by specic, historically
produced spatial arrangements. Agents are able to conceive of themselves as either
enabled or proscribed from engaging in certain praxes depending on the representational
spaces that accompany a social imaginary. One must wonder, for instance, why one
almost never sees a woman in a red light district as a consumer, but always as a
commodity of consumption. Where in social space is the space reserved for the
production and consumption of women’s desire? This question need not entail a
justication of either pornography or prostitution. It questions a seemingly objective fact
and points to the way in which the feminine imaginary is circumscribed or excluded
from certain incursions and is thus relegated to certain stealth acts of trespassing.
With these prolegomena, I have prepared the territory for the following arguments.
Philosophy thinks the city, as the city imagines philosophy. Philosophy, in other words,
emerges from a spatial practice that conditions and is conditioned by particular
representations of space and representational space. Philosophy is always the work of an
image of the city, the imagination of the city, and the social imaginary of a demos.
Conversely, the city is produced by philosophy insofar as philosophy offers an imagine
of the city, calls for a particular urban imagination, and determines the frontiers of a
social imaginary that either excludes or includes the city as its locus.
To illustrate the co-determination of image, imagination, and the imaginary, as
correlatives of a spatial practice, a representation of space, and a representational space,
I would like to turn to a contra-punctual reading of Sartre. Through an analysis of
Sartre’s phenomenological writings, I hope to make patent the ways in which his
philosophical project is parasitic on the city and philosophy’s long-standing relationship
to it. At the same time, barely submerged under his verbiage of ontological and
phenomenological philosophizing operates a determining and continuous differential
gendering. The Pour-Soi is ineluctably and uncircumventably emplaced, true. Sartre’s
being-in-the-world, however, is always a gendering emplacement. How space is produced by philosophy, and how philosophy is produced by a certain social space, but how
both are gendering, is what I hope to illustrate next.31
The look of the city and looking in the city: Jean-Paul Sartre
Simone de Beauvoir once characterized Jean-Paul Sartre as someone who
abhors—the word isn’t too strong—the seething life of insects and the profusion of plants … he feels at home only in towns, at the heart of an articial
universe consisting of man-made objects. He likes neither raw vegetables nor
milk which has come straight from the cow. Nor oysters—nothing but cooked
food, and he always asks for bottled fruit rather than the natural product”32
With him, indeed, we are confronted with an inveterate city dweller who lived, loved,
philosophized, and politicized in the middle of the city square, in the café, in the street,
in plain view of everyone. His whole life is in fact marked by a profound aversion to
privacy, secrecy, to the bad faith of concealment, inhibition, masquerading, and posturing. Ronald Hayman, his biographer, wrote that Sartre was a refugee from la vie
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
209
intériuere.33 This is not hyperbole, even if a bit misleading. More appropriately, Sartre
was a demolisher, deler, deconstructor of the delusions of subjectivity, of a life that is
lived alone, away, concealed from the look of the other. Self-consciousness is a
nothingness, it thus cannot have its own space, or place. Its place is outside itself,
beyond itself. Man [sic] is a creature of distances, as he liked to quote from Heidegger,
but of social distances. His distaste for psychoanalysis was partly motivated by this
phobia and distrust of privacy, of the dark recesses of a subjectivity not penetrable by
analysis, not liable to objectication. Sartre’s philosophy is as much his attempt to
disentangle the folding upon itself of the subject enshrined in idealism, psychologism,
and objectivism, as it is his personal quest to extinguish privacy in his own life. His life
became so much grist for his literature, as his philosophy was to be lived, by him, his
friends, his lovers, a public credo.
Gabriel Marcel, for whom the philosopher was truest to his calling by being in
solitude, wrote that “Sartre’s world is the world as seen from the terrace of a café.”34
This is a very accurate description, for Sartre’s philosophy peers into the city from inside
the city. His tenacious phenomenological eye and pen are constantly trained on the life
of persons, moving, sitting, talking, reecting, objectifying, deceiving and trusting
others, always under the look of others. Interestingly, despite the recent upsurge of
interest in philosophers who paid attention to the city, Sartre shines in his absence. This
is disconcerting since Sartre wrote extensively on the city, city life, buildings, and
crowds. His numerous letters are sprinkled with incisive phenonemological explorations
of cities: Berlin, Paris, Rome, London, etc. One letter in particular merits attention. It
is a letter written from Naples during the summer of 1936 to Olga Kosakiewicz. This
is a letter, an essay in fact, that goes on for twenty printed pages (!) describing at rst
Neapolitans, and then their city.35 The physiognomy of Neapolitans, their sartorial
customs, carnality, and habitus are noted down with acumen: the unabashed and
unaffected display of bodies, the pervasiveness of inrmities, physical trauma, suffering
and marked esh. The bodily composure and comportment of Neapolitans, however, is
mirrored in the morphology of Naples:
They drag their chairs and tables out into the street or to the doorways, half
in, half out, and it is in this intermediate world that they perform the principal
acts of their lives. So there is no longer any inside or outside; the street
becomes the extension of their rooms, they ll it with their intimate odors and
their furniture. With their history, too. Imagine, walking down a street in
Naples, we pass a clump of people sitting outside, busy doing in public
everything the French do in private … And the outside is organically connected
to the inside, it always gives me the feeling of a slightly bloody membrane
pushed outside, accomplishing their numerous little gestations.36
Of the Neapolitan balcony, which is contrasted to that of Paris, an ornament, or Rouen,
a luxury, Sartre writes that it is a respiratory organ. In fact, it is the street in the air.37
The streets in Naples, thus rise and descend, simultaneously. There is a transverse, a
horizontal and vertical trajectory, a continuous mixing of outside and inside, up and
down that gives the city its unique phenomenology. Neapolitan streets hang, rather than
extend, distend, project, or wind.
Almost a decade latter, Sartre is going to write about “American Cities.” In contrast
to the European city, a shell, a fortication built by men to hold in abeyance nature, the
American city is seen as an outpost in the wilderness, the desert. The city does not so
much separate itself from nature as it moves and ows with the currents of man’s
210
E. MENDIETA
interaction with nature. The American city is a moving landscape, just as the European
city is an incrustation in nature that has become part of the history of nature itself.38
Whereas the European city is solid, stable, a monument of history, wherein people
change while being outlived by their habitats, the American city is a perennially
changing, transforming site, where its inhabitants are the carriers of the memory of cities
but also of their hope for renewal and transformation. Nothing, however, betrays more
starkly the contrast between both types of cities than the different worldviews that are
disclosed by the streets of European and American cities. Sartre writes:
In Europe, a street is half-way between the path of communication and the
sheltered “public place.” It is on a footing with the cafés, as proved by the use
of the “terrasses” that spring up on the sidewalks of the cafés in ne weather.
Thus it changes its aspect more than a hundred times a day, for the crowd that
throngs the European street changes, and men are its primary element. The
American street is a piece of highway. It sometimes stretches over many miles.
It does not stimulate one to walk. Ours are oblique and twisting, full of bends
and secrets. The American street is a straight line that gives itself away
immediately. It contains no mystery.39
In the last instance, however, these outposts, waiting to be overrun by nature or the
shifting thrusts of social forces, ciphers of impermanence, newness, even impatience,
reveal the other side of the United States: “Here everyone is free—not to criticize or to
reform their customs—but to ee them, to leave for the desert or another city. The cities
are open, open to the world, and to the future.”40
The attempt to understand a people through a morphology of the city, to read the
physiognomy of a culture through and in the habitus of a city, remained a central
concern for Sartre. Among his notes for the second volume of the Critique of Dialectical
Reason, for instance, we nd sketches for a history of Venice.41 These phenomenological
investigations of the city, however, are not episodic or aleatory to Sartre’s philosophical
corpus. They are extensions, not to say the other side, of his concern with the
spatializing/spatialized character of the For-Itself. The For-Itself, which is always the
object of the look of another For-Itself, ascends to self-consciousness through its being
and having been temporalized and spatialized by this other For-Itself. This is Sartre’s
solution to the conundrum of modern philosophy. For Sartre, modern philosophy
shipwrecked on the reefs of solipsism. Here one must speak of reefs, for solipsism
manifested itself not only in the form of the self-referential and self-granting subject
which cannot relate to others without falling into some aporetic circularity, but also in
the impossibility of relating the subject to its world. Sartre’s Being and Nothingness is a
philosophical solution to the question of the philosophical scandals of the world and
others.42
For Sartre, consciousness is rst and foremost a derivative mode of existence. It
is an objectied For-Itself. In other words, a For-Itself which has been made into an
object for someone else’s consciousness. The other is not discovered after we have
ascended to consciousness of ourselves. Rather, the other is the necessary presupposition of my own consciousness. The other is prior to my self-consciousness. In
fact, the transcendental unity of apperception, Kant’s transcendental I, is substituted by
Sartre for the Other. The other is “an a priori hypothesis with no justication save the
unity which it permits to operate in our experience, an hypothesis which can not be
thought without contradiction.”43
The other, however, is not a consciousness, disembodied or even localized in the
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
211
eyes of its gaze or its look. The other is part and parcel of the world. One may even say
that the look is the world. The world envelopes the other, and the other appears with
the world. The world and the other are given simultaneously and anteriorly to our
self-consciousness. 44 For our purposes, this co-originary givenness of both the other and
the world is what grants us place as it also bestows it on other things in the world. The
Pour-Soi is in the world by being placed in the world by the look of the other. “The
Other’s look confers spatiality upon me.”45 Thus, the En-Soi, a thing, is in the world in
terms of my distance from it. It is placed in the world in relation to a specic orientation
that arises from a project and its practical references. Human reality is what grants place
to others and things. “Human-reality is the being which causes a place to come to
objects. Human reality alone, in so far as it is its own possibilities, can originally take
a place.”46
To be in the midst of the world, however, is not something ethereal, abstract, or
without material consequences. To be the object of someone else’s look is to be a body
which is seen. The look of the other makes us blush and we are thus corporealized. To
be in the world is to have a body. To take a place in the world, is to live out our bodies
in that distended space that has become our place; of course, insofar as we assume it.
As Sartre notes:
Thus my being-in-the-world, by the sole fact that it realizes a world, causes
itself to be indicated to itself as a being-in-the-midst-of-the-world by the world
which it realizes … Thus to say that I have entered into the world, “come to the
world,” or that there is a world, or that I have a body is one and the same
thing. In this sense my body is everywhere in the world.47
My body, which is both placed and placing, spatialized and spatializing, is lived rather
than encountered, just as the world is lived rather than discovered as already constituted. In so far as we live our bodies, we oscillate between having been spatialized and
spatializing ourselves. Similarly, we live our bodies by oscillating between having been
temporalized and temporalizing ourselves. The body, therefore, is something continuously being surpassed. It becomes the continuous trace of a consciousness reaching out
for itself.48 Like the world is realized, as something which is testimony of a project that
has been attained, the body is a “transcended transcendence.”49 I lived, and thus
abandoned my body, in order to reach out to my self-consciousness, to live out the
nothingness that I am. My body, a place in social space, is thus pure relationality:
“… this place which I am is a relation. A univocal relation, to be sure, but a relation all
the same. If I am limited to existing my place, I can not at the same time be elsewhere
in order to establish this fundamental relation.”50 The body is relationality in and
through the world, with the past, our present and future. Time and space, therefore, are
given as the temporalizing and spatializing of a particular and contingent emplacement.
This is facticity. Sartre writes, “… since the body is the facticity of the transcendencetranscended, it is always the body-which-points-beyond-itself; it is at once in space (it
is the situation) and in time (it is freedom-as-object).”51
Thus far these phenomenological reections and insights into the ontological
structure of human existence have neither betrayed nor concealed presuppositions and
exclusions concerning gender and sexuality. This would seem to be consonant with the
general thrust of Sartre’s project, namely that we choose ourselves, and that we are our
freedom. As Sartre puts it:
We have seen that human reality, far from being capable of being described as
212
E. MENDIETA
libido or will to power, is a choice of being, either directly or through appropriation of the world. And we have seen—when the choice is expressed through
appropriation—that each thing is chosen in the last analysis, not for its sexual
potential but depending on the mode in which it renders being, depending on
the manner in which being springs forth from its surface.52
Curiously, Sartre’s reections on the body also do not seem to presuppose or prejudge
insights into the “sexed” or “gendered” ways in which we are emplaced, even if the
En-Soi, the pure In-Itself, seems to be revealed to us by the qualities and adjectives of
slime, viscosity, uidity, the undifferentiated, all of which he also associates with
women. In other words, Sartre seems to be implying that gender and sexuality are not
pertinent at the level of ontological determination, even if that which most patently
discloses to us facticity is highly gendered and sexed. In terms of the basic categories of
his ontological analysis, Sartre must reject the gendered or sexual body as examples of
bad faith, as attempts to erode the ways in which we choose even our bodies. This
rejection is similar to his rejection of Freudian psychoanalysis. The fact, however, is that
while Sartre does not explicitly deal with the sexed and gendered nature of our assuming
a place in the world, his entire philosophical system is informed by a “philosophical
imaginary” that exploits crudely, parasitically, and even atavistically, a profound metaphysical sexism. A seemingly neutral, that is “foundational,” project that hopes to raise
above the mundane is seriously compromised by its reliance upon a gendered, not to say
“masculinist,” view of consciousness.53
The question of sexuality is raised explicitly by Sartre at the end of the book, at the
very end of section III of part four, which is entitled “Quality as a Revelation of
Being.”54 In this section, Sartre illustrates the ways in which his existential psychoanalysis interprets certain phobias and visceral reactions as examples of the ways in which
being is disclosed through the qualities attributed to it. Here Sartre talks about slime,
holes, and the sugary as so many ways of disclosing the docile, uid, evasive, engulng,
and pliant character of the En-Soi. In this chapter, however, we also nd some
statements so surprisingly offensive that one wonders how they escaped the censure of
readers. One can quote these passages only after having resisted interjecting with
objections, counter-examples, expletives, lest one give them any respectability or
credibility. For instance, Sartre writes:
But if we consider the slimy, we note that it presents a constant hysteresis in
the phenomenon of being transmuted into itself. The honey which slides off
my spoon on the honey contained in the jar rst sculptures the surface by
fastening itself on it in relief, and its fusion with the whole is presented as a
gradual sinking, a collapse which appears at once as a deation (think for
example of children’s pleasure in playing with a toy which whistles when
inated and groans mournfully when deating) and as display—like the
attening out of the full breasts of a woman who is lying on her
back … Actually we have here the image of destruction-creation … The slimy
is docile.55
The slimy is that which both foils and resists the projecting forward of an existential
project. It haunts the For-Itself perpetually, always frustrating its attempt to become that
which is not and to cease being what it is. Slime:
It is a soft, yielding action, a moist and feminine sucking, it lives obscurely
under my ngers, and I sense it like a dizziness; it draws me to it as the bottom
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
213
of a precipice might draw me. There is something like a tactile fascination in
the slimy … Slimy is the revenge of the In-Itself. A sickly-sweet, feminine
revenge which will be symbolized on another level by the quality of the
“sugary.”56
Furthermore, holes, like slime, are on the same level of disclosure. Holes, for instance,
reveal to us the relationship between the In-Itself and the For-Itself, what Sartre called
earlier the “feminine and masculine poles of the world.”57 The hole is a unique mode
of being through which existential analysis elucidates the character of human existence.
The hole is nothingness that presents to us a perennial challenge. Holes do not so much
invite as they compel. Their seduction is ineluctable and unavoidable.
Thus to plug up a hole means originally to make a sacrice of my body in order
that the plenitude of being may exist; that is, to subject the passion of the
For-Itself so as to shape, to perfect, and to preserve the totality of the
In-Itself … A good part of our life is passed in plugging up holes, in lling
empty spaces, in realizing and symbolically establishing a plenitude.58
With these observations, according to Sartre, we are now ready to pass over into a
proper discussion of sexuality. Now that we understand that one of the most fundamental tendencies of our existence is to sacrice our bodies to the slime and viscosity of the
world, and that we must do so by sacricing ourselves to accomplish an unachievable
plenitude of being; only now, purportedly, can we turn to sexuality,
It is only from this standpoint that we can pass on to sexuality. The obscenity
of the feminine sex is that of everything which “gapes open.” It is an appeal to
being as all holes are. In herself woman appeals to a strange esh which is to
transform her into a fullness of being by penetration and dissolution. Conversely woman senses her condition as an appeal precisely because she is “in
the form of a hole.” … Beyond any doubt her sex is a mouth and a voracious
mouth which devours the penis—a fact which can easily lead to the idea of
castration. The amorous act is the castration of the man; but this is above all
because sex is a hole.59
As with slime, holes, and the female sex, so with cities and their sociality, their
crowds. To come fully around to where we began, we should note that Sartre
experienced a dual fascination and repulsion of cities and urbane life. He could not live
without it. His philosophy would not have been possible without his voyeuristic gazing
upon unsuspecting epitomes of existential psychoanalysis. Cities also represented the
materiality of human existence, and to this extent they approximate in Sartre’s lexicon
the slime and viscosity of the En-Soi. Note for instance the following passage from the
1936 letter discussed above:
Everywhere mothers are nursing their babies in front of everyone, chatting with
the neighbors. Of course, they do that in Rome too. But in Rome it was nastier,
more fascist: it was the matron’s chaste immodesty, the lesson to the celibate,
the severe reminder of motherhood’s precious role. Here, it’s animal, it ts in
with all the rest, with that all too contingent esh digesting and breathing as
one, all those bodies freely exchanging their eas and their microbes … Yet
Neapolitans don’t look at all proletarian. Taken as a whole, they seem not a
class but a ock.60
214
E. MENDIETA
Of course, as proletariat, they would have been a project. As a ock, however, they are
inert, pure immanence. In What is Literature?, Sartre disapprovingly says something
similar of the contemporary relationship between an author and his audience:
To-day the public, in relation to the writer, is in a state of passivity: it waits for
ideas or a new art form to be imposed upon it. It is the inert mass wherein the
idea will assume esh. Its means of control is indirect and negative; one can
not say that it gives its opinion; it simply buys or does not buy the book; the
relationship between author and reader is analogous to that of male and
female: reading has become a simple means of information and writing a very general
means of communication.61
The writer, in other words, writes on the eshy surface of society; his subjectivity is
sacriced and projected upon an inert mass, a ock, just as the male projects himself
upon the pliant and viscous, supplicant and metaphysically inviting, materiality of the
woman. The scientist is no different. Knowledge and scientic investigation, which are
modes of appropriation, are described as penetration and supercial caress: “The scientist
is the hunter who surprises a white nudity and rapes it with his gaze.”62 All surfaces,
whether esh, paper, or sociality, represent an En-Soi to be written over by an autarkic
demi-god whose project of authenticity must always be foiled by the inert and intractable eshiness of a world that is female and is disclosed as such in her sex which is a
hole. In Sartre, image, imagination, and imaginary—that is, spatial practice, representations of space, and representational spaces—converge in the dual images of the city and
the female body. His philosophizing is not only motivated by the city, and the way it
places one as a subject, but it also, in turn, projects certain images and imaginaries of
space. For Sartre, in the last instance, the city, like the female body, is a surface upon
which to project the male, masculine, autarchical project of freedom. In his existential
psychoanalysis and ontological phenomenology the male is to the female, as philosophy
is to the city: projecting self-consciousness and freedom on one side, passive receptacle
and conniving adversity on the other.
Conclusion
The phenomenological method seeks to circumvent the paradoxes produced by the
extremes of rationalism, which gives primacy to ahistorical and disembodied concepts,
on the one hand, and empiricism, which gives primacy to brute facts and an already
established world, on the other. It tries to do this by demonstrating how the body is
always already conceptual and how thought is always already embodied. There is no way
in which concepts are not made possible by an embodied experience and practice, and
these later in turn remain obscure and meaningless unless they are formalized into
concepts. Sartre’s ontological phenomenology took the method a step further and both
spatialized and sexualized the embodied practices from which any investigation was to
proceed. In fact, much of Sartre’s success as a phenomenologist resided in his ability to
concretize the embodied practice from which the phenomenological reduction was to
proceed. This keen ability, doubtlessly related to his skill as a writer, has allowed him
to be appropriated by critics of racism.63 Racism, and sexism, are practices that affect,
nay, regiment, torture, manipulate, auction off, trade, and last but not least exterminate
and excise, the body of agents that have been racialized.64 Nonetheless, the agency, i.e.,
ability to act in social space, of these agents is enabled by certain spatial practices,
representational spaces, and spaces of representation, to use Lefebvre terminology again.
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
215
That Sartre could not see his own misogyny is partly related to his philosophy, and the
way in which his love of cities is intimate with his penchant, if not obsession, with
exposure, confession and objectication. Sartre’s phenomenology, as well as his later
existential dialectics, illustrate excellently the central thesis of this essay: that the city
imagines philosophy, and conversely, that philosophy thinks the city. Paris, Naples, and
so on, were the cities from, and out of, which Sartre thought about the other as primarily
the object of a gaze, a look. Sartre’s phenomenology, whether ontological or existential,
became the crystallization of a series of cosmopolitan cities. Phenomenology became a
way in which certain cities thought and imagined their own modus vivendi and ethos,
namely as being always at the mercy of someone else’s look. Through Sartre’s key hole,
through this act of philosophical voyeurism, we can being to see things like: Heidegger’s
hut, and his dislike for big cities, and the way in which his philosophy was about a
monastic purism that dreads the touch of the other, Das Man. Kant, in Köningsberg,
thinking about the a priori, people setting their clocks to the rhythm of Kant’s daily
walks to and from the university, and the way in which he thought he could produce an
anthropology without having to ever leave his beloved Köningsberg. A history of
philosophy as a history of the relationship between the city and its different schools,
currents, traditions, begins to prole itself in the horizon.
Acknowledgements
I want to thank Lois Ann Lorentzen for her extremely helpful comments, Andrew Light
for his comments, encouragement and patience, and the anonymous readers of
Philosophy and Geography, whose suggestions and questions have helped me ne tune my
argument, as well as Johannes Fritsche, who upon hearing my description of this project
immediately gave me textual examples to illustrate my thesis.
Notes
1. On the traditional forms of doing the history of philosophy, see the excellent discussion by Richard Rorty,
“The Historiography of Philosophy: Four Genres,” in his Truth and Progress, Philosophical Papers, Volume
3 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 247–73; for the latter type of history of philosophy, see
Walter Mignolo, Local Histories/Global Designs: Coloniality, Subaltern Knowledges, and Border Thinking
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).
2. Although clues and building blocks for such a history can be gathered from Pierre Ansay and René
Schoonbrodt, eds, Penser la ville: choix de textes philosophiques (Bruxelles: Éditions des Archives
D’Architecture Moderne, 1989).
3. Without question this insight, its exploration, its substantiation has to be attributed to the work of feminist
philosophers, in the Continental tradition. I will list only the ones that have most inuence my thinking
directly: Luce Irigaray, An Ethics of Sexual Difference, trans. Carolyn Burke and Gillian C. Gill (Ithaca,
New York: Cornell University Press, 1993); Elizabeth Grosz, Space, Time, and Perversion (New York:
Routledge, 1991); Michèle Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice: An Essay concerning Women, Philosophy, trans.
Trista Selous (Oxford, UK & Cambridge, USA: Blackwell, 1991); Nancy Duncan, ed., Bodyspace:
destabilizing geographies of gender and sexuality (London and New York: Routledge, 1996); Gillian Rose,
Feminism & Geography: The Limits of Geographical Knowledge (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1993); Doreen Massey, Space, Place, and Gender (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1994); Donna J. Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (New York:
Routledge, 1991); and of course, Simone de Beauvior’s The Second Sex (New York: Vintage Books, 1989).
4. See my “Chronotopology: Critique of Spatio-Temporal Regimes,” in New Critical Theory, eds Jeffrey Paris
and William Wilkerson (Lanham: Rowman and Littleeld Pubs., forthcoming).
5. Philosophy has its unconscious, and this is generally assigned a place: the horizon, the wild, the desert,
the sea, the darkness, the corner, the underground, the celestial heights. The other of reason: folds,
recoils, conceals, turns, pulls, circumvents, masks, unmasks, etc. Evidently, and according to my own
216
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
E. MENDIETA
proposal, a complete archeology of the sites of the production of philosophy would have to include not
just the city, but also the imaginary places against which the sovereignty and autonomy of philosophy
garrisons itself. See two seminal texts on this question: Michèle Le Doeuff, The Philosophical Imaginary,
trans. Colin Gordon (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1989), and Edward S. Casey, The Fate of Place:
A Philosophical History (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997).
The reason why I do not discuss, explicitly, his Critique of Dialectical Reason, is not a philosophical but very
mundane one. It is almost twenty years since I read the rst 250 pages of this dense book before I
abandoned it to not return to it. Still, I think that the Sartre most people are familiar with is the Sartre
or Being and Nothingness. Furthermore, in terms of the larger goal of the complete text of which this
present essay is a part, I wanted to focus on phenomenological readings (Sartre and Heidegger), and show
their opposite relationships to the city. This already disinclined me to read the later Sartre.
For a discussion of the use of the name Peripatetic for Aristotle’s school, see W.K.C. Guthrie, A History
of Greek Philosophy. Vol. VI. Aristotle: An Encounter (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981), 29.
I am thinking here of Umberto Eco’s claim about the relationship between Thomism and Gothic
Cathedrals, on the one hand, but also of Angel Rama’s claims about cities in the New World and the
Logic of Port Royal, see Umberto Eco, Art and Beauty in the Middle Ages, trans. Hugh Bredin (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), and Angel Rama, The Lettered City, trans. John Charles Chasteen
(Durham: Duke University Press, 1996).
Henri Lefebvre, The Production of Space, trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (Oxford UK & Cambridge USA:
Blackwell, 1991), 44.
Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 38.
See Henning Bech, “Citysex: Representing Lust in Public,” in Love & Eroticism, ed. Mike Feathersone
(London: Sage Publications, 1999), 215–42.
Benjamin Barber, Jihad vs. McWorld: How Globalism and Tribalism are Reshaping the World (New York:
Ballantine Books, 1995).
See the monumental and indispensable Gary Bridge and Sophie Watson, eds, A Companion to the City
(Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 2000), especially part III, “Cities of Division and Difference.”
See Mikhail Bakhtin, Rabelais and his World, trans. Hélène Iswolsky (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1984).
See the comments about cities and their representation as female by Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex,
trans. and ed. H.M. Parshley (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), 177 ff.
See Robert Hughes, American Visions: The Epic History of Art in America (New York: Alfred A. Knopf,
1997), especially chapters 5, 7.
Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 38.
See the incisive discussion of the historical production of views of space by Grosz, Space, Time, and
Perversion, 84–101. See also Stephen Kern, The Culture of Time and Space: 1880–1918 (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1983).
Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 38.
Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 39.
Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 39.
For a useful and succinct discussion of Lefebvre’s key concepts, see Andy Merrield, “Henri Lefebvre:
A Socialist in Space,” in Thinking in Space, eds Mike Crang and Nigel Thrift (New York and London:
Routledge, 2000), 167–82. See also Richard Peet, Modern Geographical Thought (Malden, MA: Blackwell
Publishers, 1998), 100–6.
Elizabeth Grosz, Space, Time, and Perversion, 104.
See Gail Weiss, Body Images: Embodiment as Intercorporeality (New York and London: Routledge, 1998).
See Gloria Anzaldúa, Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza (San Francisco: Aunt Lute Foundation,
1987), and Jacqueline M. Martinez, Phenomenology of Chicana Experience & Identity: Communication and
Transformation in Praxis (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littleeld, 2000).
In addition to the works already cited in note 3 above, I have in mind here the work of Judith Butler,
Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity (New York: Routledge, 1990), and Kelly Oliver,
Subjectivity without Subjects: From Abject Fathers to Desiring Mothers (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littleeld,
1998).
Frantz Fanon, Black Skin, White Masks, trans. Charles Lam Markmann (New York: Grove Weidenfeld,
1967), especially chapter 5: “The Fact of Blackness,” 109 ff., see also Albert Memmi, Racism, trans. Steve
Martinot (Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press, 2000).
This is what David Harvey’s work does, see David Harvey, The Condition of Postmodernity (Cambridge,
MA: Basil Blackwell, 1989), and The Urban Experience (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press,
1989).
THE CITY AND THE PHILOSOPHER
217
29. See Michel Foucault, “Different Spaces,” in Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology. Essential Works of
Foucault. 1954–1984. Volume Two, ed. James D. Faubion, trans. Robert Hurley et al. (New York: The
New Press, 1998), 175–86. See Edward Casey’s discussion of this text in The Fate of Place, 296–301.
30. Arjun Appadurai, Modernity at Large: Cultural Dimensions of Globalization (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1996), 31.
31. In a chapter long version of this essay, I illustrate the relationship between philosophy, the city, and
gendering through a comparison and contrast between Sartre and Heidegger. Both thinkers represent
almost diametrically opposed attitudes to the city, to the body, and to society. Yet, their work is marked
by the same quest for the ontological through the lens of the phenomenological, albeit with different
emphases and obviously with different results. While one is urbane, positively a creature of the city,
crowds, seeking and thriving in the public eye, the other is a recluse, not to say phobic of public spaces,
especially those involving crowds. One could not imagine a more jarring apposition. Indeed, it is their
contrast, their almost radical difference that makes more stark the ways in which they both are parasitic
on the city and philosophy’s relationship to it. The full chapter will appear in my work The Geography of
Utopia.
32. Quoted in Ronald Hayman, Sartre: A Biography (New York: Carroll & Graf Publishers, Inc., 1992), 110.
33. Hayman, Sartre, 110.
34. Gabriel Marcel, The Philosophy of Existentialism, trans. Manya Harari (New York: The Citadel Press,
1967), 59; compare with his own views on philosophy, 124.
35. Some of the observations in this letter made it into a small piece of ction Sartre published in 1938:
Jean-Paul Sartre, “Foods,” in The Writings of Jean-Paul Sartre. Volume 2: Selected Prose, eds Michel Contat
and Michel Rybalka, trans. Richard McCleary (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1974), 60–3.
36. Simone de Beauvoir, ed., Witness to My Life: The Letters of Jean-Paul Sartre to Simone de Beauvoir
1926–1939, trans. Lee Fahnestock and Norman MacAfee (New York: Scribner’s Sons, 1992), 64.
37. de Beauvoir, Witness to My Life, 68–9.
38. Jean-Paul Sartre, Literary and Philosophical Essays, trans. Annette Michelson (New York: Collier Books,
1965), 117.
39. Sartre, Literary and Philosophical Essays, 123.
40. Sartre, Literary and Philosophical Essays, 125.
41. See Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason: Vol. 2 (Unnished) The Intelligibility of History, trans.
Quintin Hoare (London. New York: Verso, 1991), 442 ff.
42. Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology, trans. Hazel E. Barnes
(New York: Philosophical Library, 1956), 223 ff.
43. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 227.
44. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 351.
45. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 266.
46. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 278.
47. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 318.
48. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 326.
49. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 347.
50. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 491.
51. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 351.
52. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 602.
53. The texts that have guided me most in the following reections are Le Doeuff’s Hipparchia’s Choice, and
Margaret Collins and Christine Pierce, “Holes and Slime: Sexism in Sartre’s Psychoanalysis,” in Women
and Philosophy: Toward a Theory of Liberation, eds Carol C. Gould and Marx W. Wartofsky (New York:
G.P. Putnam’s Sons, 1976), 112–27. Also Toril Moi, Simone de Beauvoir: The Making of an Intellectual
Woman (Oxford UK & Cambridge USA: Blackwell, 1994), chapter 5: “Freedom and Flirtation: The
Personal and the Philosophical in Sartre and Beauvoir,” 125–47.
54. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 600 ff.
55. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 608.
56. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 609.
57. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 601.
58. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 613.
59. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 613–14.
60. de Beauvoir, Witness to my Life, 54–5.
61. Jean-Paul Sartre, What is Literature?, trans. Bernard Frechtman (New York: Harper Colophon Books,
1965), 81. My italics.
62. Sartre in Being and Nothingness, quoted by Le Doeuff, Hipparchia’s Choice, 79.
218
E. MENDIETA
63. The classic case is Frantz Fanon’s, The Wretched of the Earth, trans. Constance Farrington (New York:
Grove Press, 1963), but see also Lewis R. Gordon’s Bad Faith and Antiblack Racism (New Jersey:
Humanities Press, 1995).
64. See my “The Modernity of Race and the Race of Modernity: Foucault’s Genealogy of Racism,”
forthcoming, and Michel Foucault, ,, Il faut défendre la sociéte .. (1975–1976) (Seuil: Gallimard,
Février, 1997).
Note on contributor
Eduardo Mendieta is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of San Francisco. He is the author
of From Hermeneutics to Semiotics: Adventures of Transcendental Philosophy (Rowman & Littleeld, forthcoming),
and is at work on a book about Utopia.
Copyright of Philosophy & Geography is the property of Carfax Publishing Company and its
content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the
copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email
articles for individual use.