View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk
brought to you by
CORE
provided by PhilPapers
ISSN 1563-0307; eISSN 2617-5843
Философия, мәдениеттану, саясаттану сериясы. №1 (75). 2021
https://bulletin-philospolit.kaznu.kz
https://doi.org/10.26577//jpcp.2021.v75.i1.05
IRSTI 02.31.21
Jon Mahoney
Kansas State University, USA, KS, Manhattan,
e-mail:
[email protected]
LIBERALISM AND LIBERAL MUSLIMS
Three central ideas in contemporary liberal political philosophy include: 1) liberty and equality represent the most basic political values; 2) legitimate political authority must be exercised on the basis of
moral reasons that are compatible with liberty and equality; and 3) the burden of justification for political
authority is on the state, not the individuals subject to the state’s coercive authority. Notwithstanding
many different interpretations of liberalism that range from libertarian, egalitarian, and social democratic
formulations, liberal political philosophers base their various positions on these fundamental ideas (For
a good survey see “Liberalism,” S. Courtland and D. Schmidtz, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
2018: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liberalism/.). Religious freedom, toleration, and a guarantee of
equal treatment under law are among the widely shared convictions endorsed by liberal political philosophers.
In this paper I propose an approach to thinking about religion and politics that should inform how
we think about liberalism and religion. I also consider how the conception of political authority defended by the prominent Muslim public intellectual Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’im (Abdullahi Ahmed
An-Na’im, Islam and the Secular State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).) is a paradigm
example of liberalism. In Part I I consider two approaches to religion and politics. According to the reductionist view, whether values that are central to a religious tradition can be reconciled to liberalism
is more a matter of doctrine than practice. By contrast a non-reductionist approach emphasizes that the
relationship between political and religious values is influenced by a number of variables in addition
to religious doctrine, including ethnicity, historical memory, political economy, and local politics. On
this view, the path between religious and political convictions is anything but a straight line. In Part II I
examine central arguments in An-Na’im’s work that are central to his version of liberalism, with a focus
on liberty of conscience and religious freedom. To illustrate An-Na’im’s liberalism I focus on examples
of claims about morality and theology, politics, and history. I conclude in Part III by considering how
An-Na’im’s position is one example of what we would expect from a non-reductionist understanding of
religion and politics.
Key words: liberalism, religion, politics, secularism, Muslims.
Джон Махони
Канзас мемлекеттік университеті, АҚШ, Канзас ш., Манхэттен қ.
e-mail:
[email protected]
Либерализм және либералды мұсылман
Қазіргі заманғы либералды саяси философияның үш орталық идеясы мыналарды
қамтиды: 1) бостандық пен теңдік ең негізгі саяси құндылықтарды білдіреді; 2) заңды саяси
билік бостандық пен теңдікке сәйкес келетін моральдық негіздер негізінде жүзеге асырылуы
керек; және 3) саяси билікті ақтау ауыртпалығы мемлекеттің мәжбүрлі күшіне бағынатын жеке
тұлғаларға емес, мемлекетке жүктеледі. Либерализмнің либертарлық, эгалитарлық және социалдемократиялық тұжырымдардан тұратын әртүрлі түсіндірулеріне қарамастан, либералды саяси
философтар өздерінің әртүрлі ұстанымдарын осы іргелі идеяларға негіздейді. Дін бостандығы,
толеранттылық және заң бойынша тең қарым-қатынас кепілдігі – либералды саяси философтар
мақұлдаған кең таралған сенімдердің бірі.
Бұл мақалада мен либерализм мен дін туралы қалай ойлайтынымыз туралы түсінік беретін
дін мен саясат туралы ойлауға көзқарасты ұсынамын. Мен сондай-ақ белгілі мұсылман қоғамдық
зиялысы Абдуллахи Ахмед Ан-Наим қорғаған саяси билік тұжырымдамасы либерализмнің
парадигматикалық мысалы ретінде қарастырамын. I бөлімде дін мен саясатқа байланысты
екі көзқарасты қарастырамын. Редукционистік көзқарас бойынша, діни дәстүрдің басты
құндылықтары либерализммен татуласуы мүмкін бе деген сұрақ практикадан гөрі доктринаның
мәселесі болып табылады. Керісінше, редукционистік көзқарас саяси және діни құндылықтар
арасындағы қатынастарға этникалық, тарихи жад, саяси экономика және жергілікті саясатты қоса
алғанда, діни доктринадан басқа бірқатар ауыспалылар әсер етеді деп баса айтады. Осы тұрғыдан
42
© 2021 Al-Farabi Kazakh National University
Jon Mahoney
алғанда, діни және саяси нанымдардың арасындағы жол түзу емес, әр түрлі нәрсе. II бөлімде АнНаимнің жұмысындағы негізгі дәлелдерді қарастырамын, олар оның либерализм нұсқасы үшін
орталық болып табылады, ар-ождан мен дін бостандығына баса назар аударады. Ан-Наимнің
либерализмін суреттеу үшін мораль мен теология, саясат және тарих туралы шағымдардың
мысалдарына тоқталамын. III бөлімді қорытындылай келе, мен Ан-Наимнің ұстанымы дін мен
саясатты редукционистік түсініктен не күтуге болатынының бір мысалы ретінде қарастырамын.
Түйін сөздер: либерализм, дін, саясат, зайырлылық, мұсылмандар.
Джон Махони
Канзасский государственный университет, США, штат Канзас, г. Манхэттен,
e-mail:
[email protected]
Либерализм и либеральное мусульманство
Три центральные идеи современной либеральной политической философии заключаются в
следующем: 1) свобода и равенство представляют собой самые основные политические ценности;
2) законная политическая власть должна осуществляться на основе моральных оснований,
совместимых со свободой и равенством; и 3) бремя оправдания политической власти лежит
на государстве, а не на отдельных лицах, подчиненных принудительной власти государства.
Несмотря на множество различных интерпретаций либерализма, которые варьируются от
либертарианских, эгалитарных и социал-демократических формулировок, либеральные политические философы основывают свои различные позиции на этих фундаментальных идеях.
Свобода вероисповедания, веротерпимость и гарантия равного обращения по закону являются
одними из широко распространенных убеждений, одобренных либеральными политическими
философами.
В этой статье я предлагаю подход к размышлениям о религии и политике, который должен
дать представление о том, как мы думаем о либерализме и религии. Я также рассматриваю,
как концепция политической власти, защищаемая видным мусульманским общественным
интеллектуалом Абдуллахи Ахмедом Ан-Наимом, является парадигмальным примером
либерализма. В части I автор рассматривает два подхода к религии и политике. Согласно
редукционистской точке зрения, вопрос о том, могут ли ценности, которые являются
центральными для религиозной традиции, быть примирены с либерализмом, является скорее
вопросом доктрины, чем практики. В отличие от этого, нередукционистский подход подчеркивает,
что на отношения между политическими и религиозными ценностями влияет ряд переменных,
помимо религиозной доктрины, включая этническую принадлежность, историческую память,
политическую экономию и местную политику. С этой точки зрения путь между религиозными
и политическими убеждениями – это, что угодно, только не прямая линия. В части II автор
рассматривает основные аргументы в работе Ан-Наима, которые являются центральными для
его версии либерализма, с акцентом на свободу совести и свободу вероисповедания. Чтобы
проиллюстрировать либерализм Ан-Наима, я сосредоточусь на примерах утверждений о морали
и теологии, политике и истории. В заключительной части III автор рассматривает позицию АнНаима как один из примеров того, что мы могли бы ожидать от нередукционистского понимания
религии и политики.
Ключевые слова: либерализм, религия, политика, секуляризм, мусульмане.
Introduction
One benefit of the perspective defended in this
paper is that it shows how liberalism and Islam can
be reconciled. More generally the compatibility
of a religious tradition and liberalism is partly a
matter of interpretation. The terms of religious and
political doctrine are always in principle negotiable.
John Locke famously tried to reconcile Christianity
with liberalism by proposing an interpretation
of Christianity at odds with most of his 17th C
contemporaries for whom Christianity is the basis
for authoritarian monarchy. Liberal Muslims such
as An-Na’im are committed to a similar kind of
project (Andrew March, The Caliphate of Man:
Popular Sovereignty in Modern Islamic Thought
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2019);
and Nader Hashemi, Islam, Secularism, and Liberal
Democracy: Toward a Democratic Theory for
Muslim Societies (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2011).).
Justification of the choice of articles and goals
and objectives
I Approaches to Religion and Politics
There are multiple ways to consider whether
Islam or any religious tradition can or cannot be
reconciled to liberalism. A partial list includes those
that emphasize history (Michael Cook, Ancient
43
Liberalism and liberal muslims
Religions, Modern Politics: The Islamic Case in
Comparative Perspective (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2014).), regional and geopolitics
(Eric McGlinchey, Chaos, Violence, Dynasty:
Politics and Islam in Central Asia (Pittsburg, PA:
Pittsburg University Press, 2011).), post-colonial
politics (Elizabeth Thompson, Justice Interrupted:
The Struggle for Constitutional Government
in the Middle East (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2013).), the intersection of ethnic
and religious identity (Amartya Sen, Identity and
Violence: The Illusion of Destiny (New York: W.
H. Norton, 2007).), and ways that dominant values
in the background religious culture inform selfunderstandings about religion and politics (Michael
Walzer, The Paradox of Liberation: Secular
Revolutions and Religious Counterrevolutions (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015).). Each of
these approaches to religion and politics can yield
important insights. Yet they can also be misused for
sectarian political ends. We need to proceed with
care and open-mindedness when thinking about
ways that various forms of religious identity are
compatible or at odds with liberalism.
To set parameters, I’ll start by contrasting two
general ways of framing questions about religion
and politics: reductionist and non-reductionist
conceptions. Someone who accepts a reductionist
approach to religion and politics holds that a religious
identity defined by religious doctrine is frequently
the primary variable that explains a person’s political
affiliation. Two familiar reductionist approaches to
thinking about liberalism and Islam include “the
clash of civilizations” (Bernard Lewis, “The Roots
of Muslim Rage,” The Atlantic, Sept. 1990; Samuel
Huntington, “The Clash of Civilizations?” Foreign
Affairs, Summer 1993.) thesis and what we might call
an authoritative texts approach. If there are essential
differences between the cultures of Orthodox or
non-orthodox Christianity, Confucianism, Islam
or Judaism among other traditions, then perhaps
Islam is the key variable which explains the relative
absence of liberal democracy in so many Muslim
majority societies. Likewise, if the New Testament
or the Qur’an contain passages which can or cannot
be reconciled to liberalism–we know the usual
examples about rendering to God and Caesar their
due, or killing apostates, adulterers and the like–we
might try to explain connections between dominant
religious identities, political affiliation, and religious
texts. These are reductionist positions in the sense
that they significantly deemphasize a number of
variables in order to first, isolate the correlation
between religious identity and political affiliation;
44
and second, to show that that religious affiliation
plays a more significant role than other variables,
such as ethnicity, local politics, or historical memory.
We can summarize reductionist approaches
by noting that they are variations on the following
argument:
Political identity tracks religious identity
Religious identity tracks authoritative texts as
well as paradigmatic civilizational identity markers
Therefore, we can reliably infer from
authoritative texts and paradigmatic civilizational
identity makers what members of the relevant groups
(e.g. Western Christianity, Islam, Confucianism,
etc.) will likely believe about politics, because these
texts and identity markers ground individual and
group conceptions of political values.
This is a tempting but unsound argument. It is
tempting because it purports to explain a complex
phenomenon, the intersection of religion and
politics, by studying values that are internal to
different religious traditions. Yet this is a simplistic
picture, in part because it affirms preconceptions and
imagined boundaries between religious and political
groups. Reductionist approaches also frequently
exhibit confirmation bias. Moreover, the argument
upon which these approaches to religion and politics
rest is unsound, because, as will be shown shortly,
there are clear counter-examples to both premises.
It is worth highlighting that there are some
approaches to religion and politics that have both
reductionist and non-reductionist versions. For
example, what we might call a history of ideas
approach to religion and politics can be cast in
either reductionist or non-reductionist terms.
Some anti-Muslim public intellectuals who write
on Islam and liberalism (Todd Green, The Fear of
Islam: An Introduction to Islamophobia in the West
(Minneapolis: MN. Fortress Press, 2015)) emphasize
texts such as Sayed Qutb’s Milestones (Islamic
Book Service, 2006.) which has inspired forms of
political Islam that are squarely incompatible with
liberalism.
Intellectual history of course is not an
objectionable enterprise. Yet the merits of individual
case studies cannot be assessed without considering
the political agendas that motivate them. In
contemporary Europe and N. America for example
there is a common strategy endorsed by what Todd
Green calls, “professional Islamophobia.” (Green,
The Fear of Islam: An Introduction to Islamophobia
in the West: 205-232.). By selecting passages
from the Qur’an, Sayed Qutb or other sources that
‘confirm’ the incompatibility of Islam and liberalism,
a selection bias reinforces a confirmation bias.
Jon Mahoney
In his more balanced intellectual history of
modern Islamic political thought, The Caliphate
of Man, March emphasizes the plurality of views
about sovereignty and political authority. The
diversity of views includes different conceptions of
the following options where political authority is
represented by the following models (the source of
authority is represented on the left, and the subject
of authority is represented on the right):
Theocracy: God–Ruler–People
Secular Democracy: People–Ruler
Islamic democracy: God–People–Ruler (March,
The Caliphate of Man: 182.)
Traditions in Islamic thought differ in which of
these options they endorse. March’s study focuses
on modern Sunni political thought, so in that
sense it is not intended to be an exhaustive survey.
The important purposes here is that the picture
that emerges is one of diversity not uniformity.
March presents a non-reductionist history of ideas
approach, because he examines considers ways that
post-colonial politics in India, North African Muslim
identity in Tunisia, and authoritarian and democratic
interpretations of Islam in Egypt influence different
conceptions of Islam and politics.
There are more and less extreme versions
of the thesis that there is some kind of essential
incompatibility between ‘liberal citizen’ and
‘Muslim’ but any version of the thesis is liable to rest
upon assumptions about religion and politics that
overlook the diversity of interpretations of religious
values. By analogy, one might invoke Robert
Filmer to illustrate how Christianity is incompatible
with liberalism, showcasing for example Filmer’s
famous defense of the diving right theory of
sovereignty. This characterization of Filmer is not
wrong, yet the dueling interpretations of religious
texts in Christianity shows that not all Christians
are anti-liberal (For an insightful comparison of the
Locke-Filmer debate and similar debates in modern
Shia political thought in Iran, see Hashemi, Islam,
Secularism, and Liberal Democracy, Ch 2, “Dueling
Scriptures: The Political Theology of John Locke
and the Democratization of Muslim Societies”: 67102.).
Anti-reductionist approaches to religion and
politics share the common conviction that we must
attend to the intersection of many variables when
we are interested in correlations between religious
values and political convictions. A partial list
includes: ethnicity, language, historical memory,
religious texts, and the political economy of rentier
states. On this view, religious identity intersects with
these other variables and in many contexts, relevant
non-religious variables provide a better explanation
for political affiliation as well as why different types
of political regimes are more likely to emerge in
different contexts. The non-reductionist approaches
that inform my position all share a commitment to
the claim that we need to consider how a composite
of intersecting factors can explain why religious
values are invoked to support different views about
political morality. Many but not all non-reductionist
approaches are presented by social scientists who
work on religion and politics. Here I briefly highlight
just four of many examples of non-reductionist
approaches to religion and politics (Ahmet Kuru,
Secularism and State Policies Toward Religion:
The United States, France, and Turkey (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2009); and William
Cavanaugh, The Myth of Religious Violence:
Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).
Scientific research methodology
Consider first whether resource dependent
economies or prevailing religious identities can
better explain the persistence of authoritarian
regimes. In The Oil Curse: How Petroleum Shapes
the Wealth of Nations Michael Ross (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2013.) shows that in
some contexts when we look at correlations between
authoritarian governments and rentier states, the
ratio of oil rents to GDP is more relevant than
religion. On his view, a combination of factors such
as the following is crucial: lack of transparency,
success in profiting from oil rents in a global market
that rewards undemocratic regimes, patronage that
buys loyalty to the regime, reduced or non-existent
income taxation, and in some cases heavy reliance
on foreign guest-workers. The correlation between
abundant natural resources and authoritarian
regimes does have exceptions (e.g. Norway). Yet
the correlation is significant because it does hold
across many states in different regions and where
religious demography is very different. Resource
rich states from Equatorial Guinea–whose Muslim
population is less than 5%--to Russia–whose
largest religious group is Christian Orthodox, and
the oil rich Gulf monarchies are autocratic. What is
oftentimes characterized as a correlation between
Islam and authoritarian politics is in fact a multicausal phenomena whose variables (e.g., religious
demography; political economy, including the
ratio of resource wealth to total GDP; and geo
and global politics) interact in different ways.
Contingent factors matter to how people understand
45
Liberalism and liberal muslims
the relation between religious and political values.
The correlation between natural resource dependent
economies and authoritarianism is strong enough to
provide a number of counter-examples to what we’d
expect from a reductionist view about religion and
politics.
Moreover, as Leif Wenar shows in Blood Oil:
Tyrants, Violence and the Rules that Run the World
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.) global
oil markets incentivize authoritarian politics in part
because control over access to oil resources is a
sufficient condition for gaining enormous wealth.
Systematic violations of property rights, human
rights violations, and state oppression will not deter
buyers from purchasing vital natural resources. Oil
markets will remain indifferent to these atrocities
until those on the consumer side opt for regulatory
schemes that punish those with illegitimate control
over resources. On this specific point there is a tragic
irony: citizens in democratic societies consume
resources extracted by authoritarian governments
and thereby contribute to the success of authoritarian
regimes.
From a different perspective Asef Bayat shows
in, Making Islam Democratic: Social Movements
and the Post-Islamist Turn (Stanford University
Press, 2007.) that we need to separate the question,
‘how does a Muslim understand her political and
religious identity?’ from ‘what are the central tenets
of Islam?’ What matters on his view is how people
interpret their religious and political identities.
These interpretations vary both within and across
religions. We can characterize this as a bottom-up
approach to religion and politics, one that highlights
the role of agency exercised by individuals who
interpret their religious values in all manner of
different ways. Here are familiar examples. Thomas
Jefferson and Thomas Aquinas are both Christians
but they have considerably different views about
religious toleration, among other political values.
Aquinas advocated death for heretics (Summa
Theologica, Question II, Heresy, Article 3, Whether
Heretics Should Be Tolerated”) whereas Jefferson
insisted that we tolerate the religious beliefs and nonreligious beliefs of our fellow citizens. Likewise,
Sayyed Qutb and Abdullahi An-Na’im are both
Muslims; An-Na’im advances many positions that
can be reconciled to liberal political values; Qutb
not so much. The compatibility between a religious
tradition and democracy is a matter of interpretation
as much as it is a matter of authoritative religious
figures or texts.
A third perspective is offered by Amartya Sen in
his book on ethnic and communal violence in India,
46
Identity and Violence: The Illusion of Destiny (Op.
Ct.). On his view, the intersecting identity markers
of ethnicity, language, religion and culture show
that religious identity by itself is generally not a
useful predictor of political values, especially when
the religious identity marker is stated in general
terms, such as ‘Muslim’ or ‘Hindu’. The interethnic
violence that arose shortly after independence from
Britain, as well as in continuing conflicts such as
that over the disputed Kashmir region, illustrate
the significance of multiple intersecting identity
markers, including ethnicity and religion. As in
many post-colonial contexts, independence meant
that a formally colonized multi-ethnic and multireligious population faced deep uncertainties about
nation building and national identity. This in turn
played a role in post-independent conflicts between
Hindus and Muslims. Though circumstances are
not exactly analogous, Sen’s observations about
post-independent inter-ethnic and inter-religious
violence are also apt for post-Soviet central Asian
republics–where conflicts between ethnic groups
such as Kyrgyz and Uzbek in Kyrgyzstan have
shaped contemporary politics. Additional parallels
might be drawn in Armenia and Azerbaijan where
conflicts between Christians and Muslims and
interethnic conflicts between Armenians and Azeri
play a significant role in post-independence politics.
A fourth perspective is provided by Robert
Pape (Dying to Win: The Strategic Logic of Suicide
Bombing. University of Chicago Press. 2006.) in his
research on suicide bombing campaigns. Pape offers
a social science perspective on religious identity
and politics by showing that in many cases suicide
bombing campaigns require the presence of two
variables: first, political occupation; and second a
difference in religious identity between occupier and
occupied. Though not a necessary condition, Pape’s
research purports to show that in some contexts the
presence of these variables are political conditions
that give rise to suicide bombing campaigns. Religion
is relevant but in conjunction with other factors,
including especially, differences between groups in
conflict along ethnic, or national, and religious lines.
For obvious reasons, no one expects a battle slogan
that goes, ‘we shall fight the Christians, because we
are Christians!’ Yet what Pape offers is a compelling
model for identifying underlying conditions that
motivate suicide bombing campaigns and what this
model shows is that religion is not the key variable.
As a rule, suicide bombing campaigns are motivated
by an underlying political grievance.
Likewise, Grim and Finke report data in their
book, The Price of Freedom Denied (Brian Grim
Jon Mahoney
and Roger Finke, The Price of Freedom Denied:
Religious Persecution and Conflict in the 21st
Century (New York, NY: Cambridge University
Press, 2011.), which show that repressive state
religion policies correlate with an increase in social
hostilities between religious and ethnic groups; the
data also show that this correlation obtains across
religious and regional contexts. On this view,
we’d expect, for example, the occasional violence
between Muslim Uyghurs and the Chinese state to
correlate with state repression; and in this instance,
repression against an ethnic and religious minority
is official state policy.
The abovementioned studies provide support
for the following verdict: data from multiple
disciplines that investigate religion and politics
provide compelling reasons to reject reductionist
approaches. One way that such work can assist
political philosophy is the following: how religious
values impact political convictions is dependent upon
many variables, too many to maintain a reductionist
position which holds that the dominant variable is
in general religious tradition or authoritative texts.
Furthermore, if the correlations identified by Pape,
Grim and Fink track causation, then the causes of
violence in the name of religion are often political. I
will treat the anti-reductionist view as provisionally
settled and frame the claims that follow from a nonreductionist standpoint.
Before examining the position of An-Na’im
I want to highlight two points. First, the idea that
violence and social hostilities are more likely to
be rooted in political grievances than in religious
fanaticism is a familiar idea in the history of
liberalism. Second, it is possible to understate ways
that religious values matter to politics, especially
when one has political or religious convictions
that motivate doing so. Those of us who defend
an anti-reductionist approach are no less prone to
confirmation bias than our reductionist counterparts.
This is a reason for humility when we try to draw
political and policy implications from a data set.
Though the social science data is on the side of
the anti-reductionist, complex phenomena such as
religion and politics should inspire skepticism about
easy answers.
Regarding the first point, consider Locke’s
remarks in A Letter Concerning Toleration:
…if men enter into Seditious Conspiracies ‘tis not Religion
that inspires them to it…but their Sufferings and Oppressions….
Oppression raises Ferments, and makes men struggle to cast
off an uneasie and tyrannical Yoke (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett,
1983): 52.).
The idea that religiously motivated violence can
be mitigated by an official state policy of religious
freedom and toleration is not a new idea and it is
worth keeping this traditional liberal perspective in
mind when asking whether a religious tradition is
or is not compatible with liberalism. On the other
hand, a rentier state can offset, at least partly, the
destabilizing effects of religious repression. Loyalty
to a repressive regime is easier to foster when the
regime can distribute wealth from its oil rents to
citizens. Those in the liberal tradition of Locke,
James Madison, and Rawls who emphasize that
religious freedom is a just and practical means
to manage conflicts that spring from religious
pluralism, might predict that a rentier state with
repressive state religion policies is exercising its
authority on borrowed time. Political philosophy
can offer a moral frame within which to evaluate
proposed policy responses to religious-political
conflicts. But the merits of this empirical hypothesis
are better addressed by social scientists than by
political philosophers.
Secondly, a qualification is in order regarding
non-reductionist approaches to religion and politics.
To claim that violence in the name of religious
values always springs from causes that are more
central than religious convictions would entail that
religious values are epiphenomena, always caused
by non-religious variables but never themselves
causing intentions. In summarizing Pape’s research
Jonathan Haidt offers an appropriately nuanced way
of thinking about religion and violence when he
writes: “[r]eligion is…often an accessory to atrocity,
rather than the driving force of the atrocity.” (The
Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by
Politics And Religion (New York: Random House,
2012): 268.). This cautious way of framing a nonreductionist approach to religion and politics is
appropriate given the complexities and our limited
understanding of human agency. Moreover, criteria
for sorting variables into ‘religious’ and ‘nonreligious’ slots are not well-defined. The answer
to, ‘was she motivated by her religious or by her
non-religious convictions?’ is just as likely to be
unknown to the observer as to the agent herself.
This is not a reason to jettison talk of religious and
non-religious motivations, although it is a reason for
humility in how we impute motives in the context
of religion and politics. Talk of religious and nonreligious motivators remains essential to policy
considerations, in part because we know that in
many contexts states that repress religious freedom
generate conflict and states that do not are often able
to diffuse such conflict.
47
Liberalism and liberal muslims
II Liberal Muslims: The Case of An-Na’im
With a non-reductionist view about religion
and politics as background, I now discuss ideas
from one prominent contemporary Muslim public
intellectual. We can sort central theses in AnNa’im’s work into three categories: 1) theological
and moral, 2) political, and 3) historical. Of course,
these categories cannot in fact be so neatly divided–
their intersectionality is something we emphasize
if we take a non-reductionist approach to religious
identity and politics. Yet for analytical purposes
we can sort theses in this way, with the caveat that
any person’s religious and political convictions
are influenced by a composition of these and other
identity conferring commitments.
One qualification is in order here. I select AnNa’im work for examination in order to illustrate
an approach to religion and politics that useful for
those interested in the compatibility of a religious
tradition to liberal political morality. My primary
aim is not to establish that liberalism and Islam
are in principle compatible. That has already
been amply demonstrated, for instance in Andrew
March’s work (Islam and Liberal Citizenship: The
Case for an Overlapping Consensus.). Rather, I will
examine An-Na’im’s work because his conception
of religious identity is especially instructive for
thinking about liberalism outside the frame of
standard analyses.
Standard discussions by liberal political
philosophers on religion and political authority often
take for granted that most citizens are Protestant or
some other denomination of Christianity. This is
exemplified for example by Rawls’ discussion of
the origins of religious toleration in early liberal
thought (Political Liberalism (New York, NY:
Columbia University Press, 1990): xxv-xxvii.). As
a history of liberalism there is nothing wrong with
the standard view. However, when we ask about the
applicability of liberal ideas about political authority
in other contexts, we cannot take for granted that a
set of ideas that emerged in the unique context of
17th C Europe can simply be extended to contexts
in which religious-political conflicts may differ in
significant respects. Claims about compatibility
between liberalism and various conceptions of
religious authority and religious traditions need to
be adjudicated case by case.
In Islam and the Secular State An-Na’im defends
the thesis that a secular liberal state is required by
his conception of Islam:
In order to be a Muslim by conviction and free choice,
which is the only way to be a Muslim, I need a secular state.
48
By secular state I mean one that is neutral regarding religious
doctrine, one that does not claim or pretend to enforce Shari’a…
simply because compliance with Shari’a cannot be coerced
by fear of state institutions or faked to appease their officials.
This is what I mean by secularism…, namely, a secular state
that facilitates the possibility of religious piety out of honest
conviction (Loc 63, Kindle Version.).
As evidence in support of this claim An-Na’im
invokes a number of considerations from within his
conception of Islam. Three such considerations may
be categorized as theological and moral, political,
and historical. In deciding to classify claims by
putting them into one of these three categories I have
been guided by what I take to be points of stress
or emphasis. Many of his claims emphasize more
than one of these dimensions but in what follows I
highlight claims that place more stress on one over
the others.
Here are three theological and moral claims:
The power to decide who is qualified to exercise ijtihad
[i.e. an interpretive judgment] and how it is to be exercised is
part of the religious belief and obligation of every Muslim (Ibid,
Loc 256, Kindle Version.).
By its nature and purpose, Shari’a can only be freely
observed by believers; its principles lose their religious
authority and value when enforced by the state (Ibid, Loc 103,
Kindle Version.).
…coercive enforcement promotes hypocrisy (Loc 109,
Kindle Version.).
I call these theological and moral claims because
they purport to rest upon an authority or source which
is naturally construed as theological and moral. To
make an obvious connection on this point, there is
textual support in the Qur’an for the second claim:
“Let there be no force (or compulsion) in religion.”
(The Quran (Trans. Syed Vickar Ahamed. Book
of Signs Foundation, 2007): 2.256: 22). Likewise,
there are longstanding traditions within Islamic
jurisprudence which emphasize ijtihad or the
permission to draw analogies or to make deductive
inferences from what is explicitly stated within the
Qur’an. So An-Na’im is drawing upon very familiar
positions on hermeneutics within Islam.
Here is a set of political claims:
The premise of my proposal is that Muslims everywhere,
whether minorities or majorities, are bound to observe Shari’a
as a matter of religious obligation, and that this can best be
achieved when the state is neutral regarding all religious
doctrines and does not claim to enforce Shari’a principles as a
state policy or legislation (Islam and the Secular State: Loc 93,
Kindle Version.).
Jon Mahoney
I am calling for the state to be secular, not for secularizing
society. I argue for keeping the influence of the state from
corrupting the genuine and independent piety of persons in their
communities (Ibid, Loc 175, Kindle Version.).
The first claim is more demanding than what
some liberals will insist upon as a condition for
political legitimacy. Notwithstanding intra-liberal
debates about the status of neutrality, such as
whether it is fundamental to the liberal conception
of political authority, or whether liberal neutrality
applies just to the intent rather than also effect
of state policy, An-Na’im’s position is clearly a
liberal one.
The second claim advocates the position that
religious identity will play a role in a society’s
culture, regardless of whether the state purports to
rule on the basis of secular values. On this point AnNa’im himself defends a conception of public reason
that permits the introduction of religious values in
public deliberation (“Islamic Politics and the Neutral
State: A Friendly Amendment to Rawls?” Rawls and
Religion (Eds. T. Bailey and V. Gentile, New York:
NY: Columbia University Press, 2015): 242-266.).
Here An-Na’im defends what he terms civic reason,
which, does not advocate excluding religious claims
on behalf of political positions. In practice this
means that on his view it is acceptable for citizens
to invoke religious values for their political claims,
provided they do so without demanding of other
citizens that they accept the religious premises. The
forms of public discourse and public deliberation
that An-Na’im has in mind here are more aligned
with a political culture informed by the American
First Amendment paradigm, in contrast with the
strict secularism of France or the Turkish Republic
(For an excellent survey see Kuru, Secularism and
State Polities Towards Religion.). On his view,
‘secular state’ does not equate to ‘laicist state’.
Yet as we’ll see in the next paragraph, An-Na’im
emphasizes that context matters to how we think
about secularism and state power.
Finally, here is a central historical claim that informs AnNa’im’s position:
…it is more productive to discuss secularism as it is
actually understood and practiced by different societies, each
in its own context. All societies are in fact negotiating the
relationship between religion and the state over many issues at
different times, rather than applying a specific or rigid definition
or model of secularism(Islam and the Secular State: Loc 582,
Kindle Version.).
In Islam and the Secular State An-Na’im supports
this claim with extended discussions of secularism,
religion and politics in a variety of contexts,
including Indonesia, Turkey, and India. There is a
lot of evidence that supports an-Na’im’s claim here,
some that comes from social science studies on the
variables that explain why different conceptions of
secularism, such as laicism as opposed to inclusive
state religion policies, take root in different contexts
(Kuru, Secularism and State Policies Towards
Religion.). Other evidence comes from comparative
studies such as An-Na’im’s which demonstrate that
there are multiple paths to building a democratic
secular state (Alfred Stepan, “Religion, Democracy,
and the ‘Twin Tolerations,’” Journal of Democracy.
Vol. 11. No. 4. 2000: 37-57.).
Results and discussion
There are too many considerations in An-Na’im’s
lengthy study to adequately capture in such a short
summary. Yet in highlighting three types of claim,
I have distilled one major thread in the extended
argument he presents. Each type of claim is invoked
to support his position as a liberal Muslim. It is true
that throughout the book much stress is placed on
the religious grounds for his position. In this respect,
there is an interesting parallel between Locke’s
Christian Natural Law defense of liberalism and
An-Na’im’s Islamic defense of liberalism. Locke
famously defended limited government and liberal
values such as liberty of conscience by invoking a
Christian moral framework. Most contemporary
liberal philosophers endorse a secular view about
the basis for political morality, yet this does not
exclude the views of Locke and An-Na’im from the
many forms of liberalism.
Conclusion
When we adopt a non-reductionist conception
of religion and politics, we are not surprised by the
conception of religious identity developed by AnNa’im. His position on religion and politics cannot
be straightforwardly deduced from central principles
of Islamic theology. And that is because religion
does not strictly limit options for self-understanding.
This is not unique to Islam. Religious values are
interpreted by agents; agents are influenced by many
variables, including those emphasized in Part I. We
should expect any longstanding religious tradition
with large populations to produce reformers, antireformers, liberals, anti-liberals, and those who
accept and those who reject scientific claims that
conflict with some traditional religious values.
At the beginning of this paper I highlighted
three ideas from contemporary political liberalism:
49
Liberalism and liberal muslims
1) liberty and equality represent the most basic
political values; 2) legitimate political authority
must be exercised on the basis of moral reasons
that are compatible with liberty and equality; and
3) the burden of justification for political authority
is on the state, not the individuals subject to the
state’s coercive authority. If we claim that AnNa’im defends a position on religion and politics
that is compatible with this picture of liberalism, a
full account would require examining his views on
each of these central features of liberalism. In that
respect, the picture I present here represents just one
aspect to An-Na’im’s liberalism; namely, his view
on religious liberty and the secular state.
Given basic truisms about human identity
and agency (e.g. historical location, religious
demography, and diversity of viewpoints impacts
self-understandings in significant ways) we should
expect to find religious and political viewpoints that
are a composite of inferences from religious doctrine
and negotiations with others, including those with
different religious and political viewpoints. One of
the compelling features to An-Na’im’s work is how
he strives to reconcile his understanding of Islam
with liberalism. His position is a paradigm example
of liberal Islam.
In this paper I have focused on two main topics.
First, whether we should adopt a reductionist or nonreductionist approach to religion and politics. Second,
whether the position of a prominent public Muslim
intellectual provides insight into how non-reductionist
approaches to religion and politics are relevant to
questions about Islam and liberalism. The view that
emerges suggests something important about religion
and politics. Though I have not fully developed the point
here, I think what can be said of An-Na’im’s position
holds for many conceptions of religious and political
authority across many religious traditions. Whether
any given religious tradition can serve as the basis for a
religious identity that is compatible with liberalism is a
matter of interpretation. It is a matter of interpretation,
not in the trivial sense of, ‘anything goes’, but in the
more philosophically interesting sense that clusters of
identity markers and political variables compose a set
of features that intersect in many different ways.
Acknowledgement
I would like to thank Nurlykhan Aljanova and
students in Theories of Religion (Fall 2020) at
Al-Farabi Kazakh National University for many
discussions on the topics covered in this paper.
References
Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’im, Islam and the Secular State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).
Alfred Stepan, “Religion, Democracy, and the ‘Twin Tolerations,’” Journal of Democracy. Vol. 11. No. 4. 2000: 37-57.
Amartya Sen, Identity and Violence: The Illusion of Destiny (New York: W. H. Norton, 2007).
Bernard Lewis, “The Roots of Muslim Rage,” The Atlantic, Sept. 1990; Samuel Huntington, “The Clash of Civilizations?”
Foreign Affairs, Summer 1993.
Brian Grim and Roger Finke, The Price of Freedom Denied: Religious Persecution and Conflict in the 21st Century (New York,
NY: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
Dying to Win: The Strategic Logic of Suicide Bombing. University of Chicago Press. 2006.
Elizabeth Thompson, Justice Interrupted: The Struggle for Constitutional Government in the Middle East (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2013).
Eric McGlinchey, Chaos, Violence, Dynasty: Politics and Islam in Central Asia (Pittsburg, PA: Pittsburg University Press,
2011).
For an excellent survey see Kuru, Secularism and State Polities Towards Religion.
For an insightful comparison of the Locke-Filmer debate and similar debates in modern Shia political thought in Iran, see
Hashemi, Islam, Secularism, and Liberal Democracy, Ch 2, “Dueling Scriptures: The Political Theology of John Locke and the
Democratization of Muslim Societies”: 67-102.
For a good survey see “Liberalism,” S. Courtland and D. Schmidtz, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2018: https://plato.
stanford.edu/entries/liberalism/.
Green, The Fear of Islam: An Introduction to Islamophobia in the West: 205-232.
Ibid, Loc 103, Kindle Version.
Ibid, Loc 175, Kindle Version.
Ibid, Loc 256, Kindle Version.
(Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1983): 52.
Islam and Liberal Citizenship: The Case for an Overlapping Consensus.
Islam and the Secular State: Loc 93, Kindle Version.
Islam and the Secular State: Loc 582, Kindle Version.
Islamic Book Service, 2006.
50
Jon Mahoney
“Islamic Politics and the Neutral State: A Friendly Amendment to Rawls?” Rawls and Religion (Eds. T. Bailey and V. Gentile,
New York: NY: Columbia University Press, 2015): 242-266.
Kuru, Secularism and State Policies Towards Religion.
Loc 63, Kindle Version.
Loc 109, Kindle Version.
March, The Caliphate of Man: 182.
Michael Cook, Ancient Religions, Modern Politics: The Islamic Case in Comparative Perspective (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2014).
Michael Walzer, The Paradox of Liberation: Secular Revolutions and Religious Counterrevolutions (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 2015).
New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.
Op. Ct.
Political Liberalism (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1990): xxv-xxvii.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2013.
Prominent examples of work I do not discuss here but which add support to a non-reductionist approach to religion and
politics include: Ahmet Kuru, Secularism and State Policies Toward Religion: The United States, France, and Turkey (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2009); and William Cavanaugh, The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of
Modern Conflict (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).
See also Andrew March, The Caliphate of Man: Popular Sovereignty in Modern Islamic Thought (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2019); and Nader Hashemi, Islam, Secularism, and Liberal Democracy: Toward a Democratic Theory for Muslim
Societies (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).
Stanford University Press, 2007.
Summa Theologica, Question II, Heresy, Article 3, Whether Heretics Should Be Tolerated” (New Advent, Online Version:
http://www.newadvent.org/summa/3011.htm#article
The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics And Religion (New York: Random House, 2012): 268.
The Quran (Trans. Syed Vickar Ahamed. Book of Signs Foundation, 2007): 2.256: 22
Todd Green, The Fear of Islam: An Introduction to Islamophobia in the West (Minneapolis: MN. Fortress Press, 2015).
51