Ethic Theory Moral Prac (2013) 16:879–897
DOI 10.1007/s10677-012-9396-x
Punishing ‘Dirty Hands’—Three Justifications
Stephen de Wijze
Accepted: 14 November 2012 / Published online: 29 November 2012
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012
Abstract Should those who get dirty hands be punished? There is strong disagreement
among even those who support the existence of such scenarios. The problem arises
because the paradoxical nature of dirty hands - doing wrong to do right - renders the
standard normative justifications for punishment unfit for purpose. The Consequentialist,
Retributivist and Communicative approaches cannot accommodate the idea that an
action can be right, all things considered, but nevertheless also a categorical wrong.
This paper argues that punishment is indeed appropriate for those who dirty their hands
and that there are three normative justifications that can be used to support this claim.
These are the justifications from ‘Catharsis’, ‘Recognition of Evil Suffered’ and
‘Causal Responsibility’. Together they provide the sui generis justifications for punishing
dirty hands.
Keywords Dirty Hands . Punishment . Justification . Michael Walzer
The notion of ‘dirty hands’ (hereafter DH) is a puzzling one. It essentially relies on a
paradoxical claim; namely, that it is possible to do wrong in order to do right. Expressed
more formally, DH situations are those where it is possible (necessary in some situations,
and all things considered, the justified and best option) to commit a moral wrong in order to
do what is morally required. This somewhat perplexing claim, if taken seriously, raises a
number of very difficult questions. Firstly, is there the conceptual space in which to
coherently claim that we can do wrong and right at the same time?1 Secondly, even if we
do manage to establish the philosophical space for DH, can we offer a set of necessary and
sufficient conditions for such a phenomenon so that we can distinguish DH scenarios from a
host of other kinds of ethical scenarios?2 Thirdly, which moral emotions do we properly
associate with this paradoxical notion of DH given that neither ‘regret’ nor ‘remorse’ is
1
See Stocker (1992): Chs 1 and 2 and de Wijze (1994)
2
I have in mind alternative scenarios such as acts of straightforward immorality, moral dilemmas, justified and/or
inescapable moral wrongdoing. For discussions of these notions see Gowans (1994) and Gardner (2005).
S. de Wijze (*)
Manchester Centre for Political Theory (MANCEPT), Politics, University of Manchester, Manchester
M13 9PL, UK
e-mail:
[email protected]
880
S. de Wijze
appropriate. I have argued for ‘tragic remorse’ given that we need to acknowledge genuine
wrongdoing but also recognise the bravery and good done by those who get genuine DH.3
There is yet another element of the DH puzzle which is the focus of this paper. It is the
question of how to justify (if at all) both punishing and praising (at the same time) those who
get DH. There has been very little written on this somewhat perplexing paradoxical
situation.4 The difficulties here are not simply pragmatic ones about who ought to carry
out the punishment, and under which conditions. Nor is it the related and much vexed
question of just what types of punishment and praise would be appropriate for those who get
DH. Rather, the problem is a conceptual one concerning the issue of justification itself. How
can we justify punishing (or praising) those who do wrong in order to do right, and are any
of the standard justifications in the philosophical literature fit for purpose?
This paper sets out to answer these questions and argues following Michael Walzer pace
Neil Levy and Tamar Meisels,5 that punishment is necessary for those who dirty their hands.
However, the justification for inflicting such punishment cannot be made by the standard
theories of punishment that dominate the philosophical literature; namely, the
Consequentialist, Retributivist and Communicative positions. Rather a novel way of understanding the purpose of punishment sets out the justifications needed and I argue for three
closely related accounts which I call the justifications from ‘catharsis’, ‘evil suffered’ and
‘causal responsibility’. These three justifications, whether taken severally or together provide the conceptual rationale for inflicting punishment on those who paradoxically do wrong
in order to do right. In it important to make explicit here that while those who get DH ought
to be both punished and praised at the same time, I only focus on the issue of punishing since
its infliction demands an especially strong justification given its unpleasant and harmful
nature. I begin this paper with an account of the paradoxical nature of DH actions and why it
raises the conundrum about punishment that it does. This leads to a brief discussion of the
three well trod influential approaches to justifying punishment which I argue are not suitable
for considering DH cases. I then outline and defend my three alternative justifications.
1 DH: a brief synopsis
DH scenarios are those situations where a conscientious moral agent does wrong in order to do
right. More formally, DH scenarios, following Stocker, are situations where there is an action
which is ‘justified, even obligatory, but none the less wrong and shameful’.6 This claim that DH
is part and parcel of our moral reality is strongly contested. The reason is that such claims appear
to be incoherent and confused at best and fly in the face of a moral metaphysics accepted by
nearly all consequentialist and deontological moral theorists. However, I shall assume (for the
purposes of this paper) that DH scenarios are conceptually possible. Furthermore, I shall also
assume that there is a set of necessary and sufficient conditions that identify DH scenarios and
that these conditions best reflect how we approach certain kinds of intractable moral conflict or
dilemmas. The defence of these assumptions against the counter claims of Consequentialists
and Deontologists I have discussed at length elsewhere.7
3
de Wijze (2005).
The literature available focuses almost exclusively on punishment rather than praise. For an extensive,
although not exhaustive, discussion of punishment and DH, see Walzer (1973), Levy (2007), Meisels (2008),
Garrett (1996): ch.2, Thompson (1987):ch.3, Arendt (1958), Digeser (1998).
5
See Walzer (1973), Levy (2007) and Meisels (2008).
6
Stocker (1992): 9.
7
See de Wijze (1994) and (2005).
4
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
881
The phrase ‘doing wrong to do right’ captures the paradoxical nature of DH but to
understand why such acts evoke both punishment and praise needs further discussion. There
is no single agreed upon definition of DH. Some theorists argue that DH are those actions
that result from the intractable ‘means-ends’ problem in politics.8 Others insist that DH arise
from a clash between the different moral guidance given by deontological and consequentialist moral reasoning.9 Yet others focus on the different moral duties and obligations found
in public and private moralities where the former expresses the duties of a particular public
role that sometimes necessitates actions which violate private moral convictions.10 I shall
use Stocker’s account which essentially sidesteps these different understandings but which is
compatible with any of the above definitions of DH that one finds most congenial.
Essentially then DH scenarios are circumstances where it is possible for an action to be
‘(1) justified, even obligatory, but (2) none the less somehow wrong’.11 The predicament of
DH arises for moral persons due primarily to the immoral and evil acts (or projects) of other
persons.12 When an autonomous moral agent is faced with choosing between the lesser of
two evils, or forced to act so that a much-cherished moral principle will be violated, she finds
that she is morally polluted by having so to act. In short, DH scenarios are those cases where
agents are motivated by moral considerations to commit moral violations. Agents experience
a loss of moral goodness due in part to the knowledge that in so acting they have voluntarily
become part of a causal process that aids or abets an immoral/evil project. DH scenarios are
particularly pernicious and morally vicious states of affairs since they co-opt good persons
into voluntarily committing immoral acts or participating in immoral projects. To claim that
one has DH in this context is not merely to offer a description of a feeling or sentiment that
may arise due to the distastefulness of an action. It is a claim that genuine wrongdoing has
taken place and that serious moral fall-out from such an action is inescapable.
As I mentioned above, the claim that it is possible to do wrong and right at the same time
is strongly rejected by both consequentialist and deontological moral theorists. They insist
that the right application of the appropriate moral theory (rule utilitarianism, or Kantian
ethics etc.) dissolves this apparent paradox and the very existence of moral conflict/dilemmas of this kind are shown to be chimerical. However I shall simply assume that this attempt
to ‘dissolve’ the problem fails and agree with Bernard Williams who points out that our
moral reality throws up cases where for some actions, we ‘have reason to approve of the
outcome, and …an agent who is able to make that choice, while conscious that there has
been a “moral cost”’.13 The existence of genuine moral conflict, the incommensurability of
cherished values, the conflicting personal and role based moral claims that press on agents
seeking to act morally, sometimes give rise to moral conflict situations where it is impossible
to avoid getting DH. In such situations, as Stocker points out, ‘even if morality requires that
that the injuries and deaths of innocents must be endured, they are matters of moral moment
and matters for extreme regret’.14 When this happens, we admire and praise those who acted
in this way and also we acknowledge that they must bear the moral pollution that such acts
bring with them. By so acting, good persons have compromised their moral integrity and it
8
See Machiavelli (1997); Hampshire (1983):Ch.5 and (1978): 1–22; and Galston (1991):175–197.
See Walzer (1973), Nagel (1972) and Nielsen (1996).
10
For DH as a clash between the public and private, see Weber (1948), Hollis (1982) and Williams (1981a, b)
‘Utilitarianism and moral self indulgence’: 41–42.
11
See Stocker (1992): 10.
12
Whether or not DH scenarios can arise from natural events I leave aside here. For a view that natural events
do give rise to DH see Goodwin (2009): ch. 7.
13
Williams (1981a, b) ‘Moral Luck’: 37.
14
Stocker (2000), ‘Dirty Hands and Ordinary Life’: 28.
9
882
S. de Wijze
ought to affect how we think of them and what they think of themselves for what they have
become. They ought not just to feel regret since this would trivialise terrible actions and
undermine the moral revulsion of the harms done. However, neither can such agents
properly feel remorse, the emotion appropriate to immoral behaviour with no justification
or redeeming factors. Rather, as I have argued elsewhere, they ought to feel ‘tragic-remorse’;
the appropriate way of characterising the moral emotion that arises from getting DH.15
This brings us to the issue of punishment and praise for those who dirty their hands. As I
mentioned earlier, I will concentrate on punishment because the infliction of punishment
involves the imposition of a burdensome action such as harsh and unpleasant treatment of
some kind that results in discomfort or the curtailment of rights. These are things we and the
State may only do to others when properly justified.16 While praising inappropriately
without proper justification also has deleterious consequences they are ceteris paribus less
morally problematic.17
2 Punishment
The key questions that require answers with respect to a theory of punishment are:
1) why punish?
2) who do we punish?
3) What kinds of punishments should we inflict and what quantity would constitute the
appropriate punishment for a particular action?
For the purposes of this essay I am primarily interested in (1) above since this paper
argues that the standard justifications for punishment are not appropriate in DH cases and
that we must and can find better alternatives. Consequently, I am not concerned with offering
anything like a comprehensive overview of justifications for punishment with the different
variations and nuances that have been developed in the extensive philosophical literature
available.18 Even if it were possible to do this in a short paper, it would take me too far away
from my present purposes. Rather, I shall argue that existing approaches are inapplicable to
the DH scenarios because of the sui generis nature of such acts and I shall then seek to offer
three alternative justifications for punishing the dirty.
Punishment then, according to Duff, ‘is typically, something intended to be burdensome
or painful, imposed on a (supposed) offender for a (supposed) offence by someone with
(supposedly) the authority to do so; and that punishment, as distinct from other kinds of
penalty, is typically intended to express or communicate censure’.19 Different theorists
tweak this definition in different ways or focus on different aspects of it but incorporate
many if not all of Duff’s main points. Tasioulas, for example, endorses Duff’s definition but
15
de Wijze (2005): 463–471.
For an extended account of why punishment needs to be justified see Bedau et al. (2010).
17
I need to be clear here that I am not suggesting that finding a justification for praising those with DH is
easier than finding one for punishment. The former task might prove even more difficult than a justification
for punishment. However, I leave this task to another paper.
18
The literature on punishment is extensive, complex and subtle. There are the different strands of consequentialism, retributivism, and communicative theories in addition to hybrids that seek to combine the
different justifications. Punishment can also be justified from a purgative or incapacitative rationale. For a
taste of some of the central texts on punishment see Bennett (2008), Duff (2001), Feinberg (1970), Garvey
(1999), Hart (1968), Kramer (2011), Matravers (2000), McDermott (2001): 403–432, and Von Hirsch (1998).
For a useful discussion on the problems with defining punishment see Lacey (1988): 4–8.
19
Duff (2001): xiv-xv.
16
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
883
focuses on the communicative aspect insisting that ‘the hard treatment is intended to
communicate to the wrong-doer justified censure for their wrong-doing.’20 Tasioulas insists
that this communicative aspect is not just a condition for something to be properly called
punishment, but rather that it ‘is the over-arching justifying ‘point’ of punishment. Or to put
it slightly differently, it is ‘the justifying ground of punishment’.21
All justifications for punishment of whatever stripe presuppose that there has been a
crime (in the legal context) and/or some form of moral wrongdoing. The philosophical
literature offers three broad and different theoretical approaches to justifying punishment
which are either forward or backward looking or a combination of the two.22 These
approaches are roughly the Consequentialist (forward-looking), Retributivist (backwardlooking) and the Communicative approaches.23
Consequentialists justify punishment in purely instrumental terms. Punishment is justified only if it brings about certain goods or prevents certain evils. A penal system, for
example, is justified if it reduces crime by reforming or incapacitating offenders and
deterring possible future offenders. For Consequentialists, punishment always remains an
evil and it is to be used only if it brings about a lesser evil. Retributivists, in contrast and in
both their ‘desert’ and ‘rights-based’ forms, argue that those who have committed a crime (or
who have acted immorally) necessitates punishment that is proportionate to the wrong
done.24 Punishment is an end in itself; the reassertion of the correct and legitimate moral
order which has been violated by the wrongdoing. Punishment in the appropriate proportion
re-establishes the moral order and needs to be administered even if from a consequentialist
perspective it would not bring about certain goods or prevent certain evils.
20
Tasioulas understands punishment to be ‘a practice that involves (a) the deliberate infliction of hard
treatment, (b) on an alleged wrong-doer, (c) because of the alleged wrongness of their conduct, (d) by
someone who claims the authority to inflict it for that reason, where (e) the hard treatment is intended to
communicate to the wrong-doer justified censure for their wrong-doing.’ See Tasioulas (2006): 283.
21
Tasioulas (2006): 284. Although Duff includes an expressive element to his account he focuses on
punishment as reparation or atonement. Duff insists that condemnation itself is sufficient to justify punishment
on the grounds that it ought to take place even if the offender cannot repeat the violation or has already
repented or is unlikely to be persuaded to act otherwise by the communicative or deterrent nature of
punishment. See Duff (1998): 162. (I am indebted to Kimberly Brownlee for this point.)
22
There is a fourth approach which favours the abolition of punishment altogether but I shall not include this
position largely because its focus is mostly on the abolition of legal sanctions and my focus is on the
normative. As Cohen points out, ‘for abolitionists … punishment is not a solution to be justified by
philosophers, allocated by lawyers and measured by criminologists. It is a problem to be solved by an
imaginative quest for alternatives.’ Cohen (1991): 733. For a far reaching debate on the abolitionist position
and alternative to punishment see the ‘Alternative to Punishment’ section of the Israeli Law Review 1991. 25
(3–4).
23
I say ‘roughly’ as I am not claiming that this threefold categorisation exhausts the different philosophical
approaches to justifying punishment. What I do contend is that these three significant approaches cannot be
used to justify punishing DH.
24
The ‘desert-based’ approach argues that those who do wrong deserve to be punished while the ’rightsbased’ approach argues that punishment is due since those who have been wronged have had their rights
violated and the punishment is necessary to correct this injustice. It is useful to examine Kant’s justification for
punishment as a paradigmatic Retributivist account. Kant argues that there is a ‘principle of equality’ which
must be enforced. If a wrong is committed, this upsets the balance of the scale of justice. The person who has
committed the wrong has inflicted suffering on another, and so now is herself deserving of suffering to rectify
the balance. Consequently, it is necessary to punish the offender. The notions of justice and desert are clearly
fundamental to Kant’s justification of punishment and he does this to ensure that the punishments are
proportionate and directed only at those who properly deserve such treatment. Punishing the innocent is
strictly prohibited in stark contrast to what may be justified under a Consequentialist justification. Also see
Kemp (1968): 89.
884
S. de Wijze
However, both the Consequentialist and Retributivist approaches (notwithstanding the
various sophisticated adjustments made by supporters) face serious criticisms.
Consequentialists fail to provide the empirical evidence that punishment does indeed bring
about the lesser evil and it always remains something of a speculative affair. Furthermore,
since a Consequentialist justification depends on the predicted effects of the punishment, it
opens up the possibility that punishing the innocent or punishing in a disproportionate
manner could be justified. For many this is unacceptable and opens the Consequentialist
approach to the serious charge that it does not take the distinction between persons seriously
allowing (at least in principle) for the use of persons as means to some other end.25
Retributivists similarly face powerful criticisms. Essentially Retributivists of all stripes face
the difficulty of adequately explaining the relationship between punishment and guilt. What
is it precisely about guilt that makes punishment an appropriate and necessary response? All
the explanations offered seem to require either a disputed appeal to intuitions or deeply
controversial metaphysical claims or are really consequentialist arguments in disguise.26
Given these and many other problems faced by the Consequentialist and Retributivist
justifications for punishment (despite each having considerable intuitive appeal), there have
been attempts to develop the so called ‘Communicative’ approach which draws on both the
forward and backward-looking views. The Communicative approach, in essence, justifies
punishment as the way to convey deep disapproval toward those who have acted immorally
and/or criminally. Punishment conveys the message that their actions are unacceptable
(backward-looking aspect of the justification) and that there needs to be repentance for
acting in this way with the foregoing of similar actions in the future (the forward-looking
influence). Needless to say, the Communicative approach is not without its trenchant critics
either. It is not clear, for example, why the Communicative approach needs to employ
punishment as such to send a message to the transgressor rather than some other means of
communication. What is more, the attempt to incorporate both the forward and backwardlooking aspects of the justification may result in a self-cancelling incongruity where
registering disapproval undermines the aim of preventing future wrongful actions.27
3 Punishing DH
My concern in this paper is not to assess the superiority or plausibility of any one of the three
different philosophical justifications vis á vis each other. There is a rich and subtle literature
already available that seeks to do this. Rather, my focus is primarily on an aspect of DH
theory, specifically whether we can establish a plausible philosophical justification for
punishing those who genuinely get DH. What I hope will become clear is that the three
standard approaches outlined in the previous section are not capable of providing the
normative justification for doing so if indeed we think that punishment is necessary. DH,
as stated above, are peculiar and sui generis situations where autonomous agents deliberately
do wrong in order to do right. For DH scenarios, the forward-looking or Consequentialist
25
John Rawls famously makes this criticism of consequentialist accounts of distributive justice in his A
Theory Of Justice. See Rawls (1971): 27–33.
26
See Duff (2001): Ch. 2.
27
There are different variants of the Communicative theory. Duff, for example, formulates a Monastic
approach that is essentially backward-looking as it is desert based. The Communicative aspect affords no
independent justification for punishment. Pluralistic variants, such as Tasioulas’, are not purely desert based
since justified punishment is not necessarily the same as deserved punishment. For example, the former can be
reduced if the offender repents. (I am indebted to Kimberley Brownlee for bringing this to my attention).
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
885
justification is deeply problematic since punishment is defensible in order to change future
behaviour and bring about the less deleterious consequences. But genuine DH scenarios are
always cases where an agent has done what was needed in the circumstances to bring about the
least bad consequences and if such a situation were again to arise in the future we would hope
that the agent repeats her actions even though it involves (sometimes serious) wrongdoing.
Indeed we are grateful for the wrongdoing as it brought about the lesser evil and we need to
praise the agent for so acting in a difficult moral situation. The backward-looking or
Retributivist justification does no better with cases of DH. This approach (in both its desert
and rights-based forms) punishes because a wrongdoing has been committed and the agent
deserves the proportionate punishment. However, the peculiarity of the DH scenario is that the
agent did the wrong thing because it was also the right thing to do in the circumstances. Recall
that central to DH scenarios is that a good person is motivated by moral reasons to commit
moral violations. So to punish an agent for doing the wrong thing here means also punishing
that person for doing the right thing with the right motive. To do this, it seems, is to punish an
innocent person; something that is both deeply counter-intuitive and without proper justification
also morally repugnant. Finally the third approach to justifying punishment, the
Communicative approach, is problematic if not simply incoherent with DH situations at least
as it is usually understood when applied to ordinary wrongdoing. In DH cases we need to
simultaneously praise/honour and blame/punish the agent for so acting and, as Levy puts it,
‘what punishment is also an expression of our honouring attitude?’28 In short, despite the fact
that DH acknowledge that a categorical wrong has been committed it seems that the standard
justifications for punishing wrongdoers are unsuitable in such situations.
While this problem has not been widely addressed by DH theorists, in large part due to a
prior concern with whether such a notion is even possible and coherent, there are two theorists,
Michael Walzer and Neil Levy,29 who have endeavoured to bring some clarity to this issue.
While both theorists support the existence of genuine cases of DH they differ sharply on
whether punishment can be justified. Walzer argues that it is both necessary and important to
punish DH while Levy emphatically rejects the idea as both incoherent and immoral.
3.1 Walzer on punishing dirty hands
Walzer’s contribution in his groundbreaking article ‘Political Action: The Problem of Dirty
Hands’ vividly and enigmatically sets up the problem and is clear on at least this much; those
who get DH ought to be punished.30 However his justification to support this view runs the
gamut of all three approaches to justifying punishment. In different places when discussing
28
Levy (2007): 43.
See Walzer (1973) and Levy (2007).
The issue of whether it would be possible to find a legal basis for punishing DH is a difficult one. As far as I am
aware, there is no room in existing criminal law theory for a case where an agent commits a justified wrong and is
also the object of legal punishment. Wrongdoing accompanied by an adequate justificatory defence attracts no
punishment and wrongdoing that proffers an excusatory defence is either not punished or draws a lesser
punishment. DH scenarios fall between the cases of wrongdoing that ought to be punished and those with a
justificatory defence that ought not to be punished. In legal terms the latter category renders the wrong done
defeasible, one trumped by an undefeated reason. I am concerned with the normative rather than legal basis for
punishment in this paper and my justifications for punishing DH seek to find that space which is not available in
the legal framework. However this does not mean that DH can avoid legal sanction. In some cases and especially
for public figures, it may be necessary. However, the legal issues raise further complications even if we could find
the legal space for the idea of a justified action that nevertheless violates a categorical wrong. There is an additional
problem that if such acts are committed by the legitimate authorities (politicians, police, army etc.) there may be no
one (short of the priest and the confessional) to whom we could entrust with the task of punishing those with DH
even if we could find the legal space for such punishment. See Walzer (1973): 179.
29
30
886
S. de Wijze
the three traditions of thinking about the interaction between politics and morality,31 Walzer
helps himself to the Retributivist, Consequentialist and Communicative accounts insisting
that while we uniquely and paradoxically both honour and punish those with DH, we also
punish them for ‘the same reasons we punish anyone else’. Walzer makes it clear that he is
not defending any particular view of punishment and even introduces a fourth possibility
which justifies punishment as a form of self-punishment and expiation.32 So when discussing the ‘Ticking Bomb scenario’ and other DH cases in his 1973 article, Walzer explicitly
invokes all three philosophical approaches. Firstly, Walzer offers a Retributivist account
insisting that in those rare circumstances where a politician, for example, was justified in
ordering torture, he nevertheless ‘committed a moral crime and he accepted the moral
burden’.33 The committing of a moral crime leaves him a guilty man and ‘we can expect
more than melancholy from him now’.34 Those who commit a determinate moral crime
‘must pay a determinate penalty’.35 Secondly, Walzer draws on the Communicative account
when he acknowledges that punishment of DH sometimes requires a social expression and
social limitation since one of its main purposes is to remind us that certain actions are always
wrong no matter the justification.36 Thirdly, Walzer makes use of the Consequentialist
approach when he argues that to prevent DH scenarios from occurring too often and too
hurriedly, punishment is necessary to ensure that the stakes for so acting remain high. This
serves to protect the moral (and legal) code.37
Walzer’s use of the different philosophical justifications for punishing DH fails to
acknowledge the critical question that needs addressing; namely, how do we justify punishing DH given its sui generis and paradoxical nature.38 The standard approaches for justifying punishment assume that actions are either right or wrong and punishment is appropriate
and justified only for wrongful actions. But with situations where the action was both wrong
and right, these theories of justification are no longer suitable. The very basis on which the
justification rests in each of the different approaches is fundamentally undermined.
Retributivists cannot punish those who did right, Consequentialists cannot punish to change
31
Walzer explores three traditions of thinking about the interaction between politics and morality and each of
these offers an account of the costs for getting DH; namely, the Neoclassical, Protestant and Catholic perspectives.
These three approaches draw on the works of Machiavelli (1997), Weber (1948) and Camus (1958) respectively.
These traditions do not offer normative justifications for punishment but rather illustrate the different ways in
which the costs of DH could be experienced. The Neoclassical tradition focuses on the consequences to the
individual of success and failure. There is no reward for good motives if the actions undertaken fail. A politician
dirtying her hands does not risk her goodness but rather glory and power. The Protestant tradition focuses on
individual suffering for committing wrongs. A politician who gets DH lives by an ‘ethic of responsibility’ and
loses her soul becoming a tragic hero and suffering servant. She pays the price so that others do not need to do so.
The Catholic tradition, which Walzer is inclined to endorse, rejects the Protestant approach as it focuses entirely on
the inner life of the politician. Political crimes need to be socially acknowledged and the punishment socially
limited. For a more detailed account of these traditions see Walzer (1973): 174–180.
32
Walzer (1973): 178. I return to this justification when I examine my justification from ‘Catharis’ below.
33
Walzer (1973): 167.
34
Walzer (1973): 167.
35
Walzer (1973): 178.
36
Walzer (1973): 177 puts it this way: punishment needs to be socially expressed as ‘it confirms and
reinforces our sense that certain acts are wrong’.
37
Walzer (1973): 179/180.
38
While Walzer hints at this problem his main focus is on the politician’s role and the fact that those who get DH
(especially for reasons of state) are highly unlikely to be punished for so acting. Walzer enigmatically states that if
such punishment was consistently and reliably applied so that politicians could acknowledge their responsibility
for violating a moral or legal rule, then DH would not be a problem. (Walzer 1973: 179.) It is not clear to me why
Walzer thinks that this would solve the problem of seeking a normative basis for punishing DH. The issue of who
punishes and the institutional problems with enforcing or administering punishment are practical questions that
need to be considered after the justification for so acting has been settled.
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
887
future behaviour and the Communicative approach needs significant adjustment since the
complexity of DH scenarios requires a different and subtle message to those who dirty their
hands and the society at large. If we accept the reality of DH, then genuine cases are
significantly different to cases of unjustified wrongdoing and so will be the justifications for
punishment that may be warranted.
If I am correct here then that leaves two possible routes to travel. Either we can agree with
Walzer that punishment of DH is necessary and seek alternative justifications, or we could adopt
a different strategy and reject any need for punishment. The latter approach, with which I
disagree, is championed by Neil Levy and Tamar Meisels. They accept that there are genuine
cases of DH but argue that such scenarios do not require that agents be punished. I now turn to
outlining and then rejecting this position in favour of seeking alternative normative justifications.
3.2 Levy (and Meisels) on DH and punishment
Apart from Walzer, Levy offers the most extensive analysis of the problem of DH and
punishment. In his ‘Punishing the Dirty’39 Levy devotes a great deal of his article to
outlining Walzer’s position discussed above and then comprehensively rejecting it. Levy’s
arguments against the standard Consequentialist and Retributivist justifications for punishing DH focus on the paradoxical nature of DH. For example, the Consequentialist justification that punishment is needed to prevent future adverse consequences in DH situations
serves to undermine itself. If the consequentialist justification is true then, as Levy points
out,40 we are committed to a wider consequentialism. And if we are committed to wider
consequentialism, one that rejects the possibility of doing wrong to do right, then the DH
problems disappears. So it seems that the Consequentialist approach is simply self-defeating.
Walzer would clearly find this conclusion unpalatable and contrary to his core argument that
those who dirty their hands ought to be punished.
Concerning the Retributivist justification, Levy argues that it is both incoherent and immoral. The incoherence arises due to an erroneous understanding of the relationship between
wrongdoing and blameworthiness.41 Levy correctly points out that the wrongness of an action
and the blameworthiness of the agent who so acted are not always inextricably linked. In some
situations an agent who is ignorant of particular rules or who could not have reasonably
predicted the outcome of her actions, may have acted wrongly but is not blameworthy.
Conversely, a person can be blameworthy for acting in a certain way even if through luck her
intended malevolent action resulted in a good or neutral outcome. What is important to stress
here is that in order to be blameworthy, an agent must have had the option to act differently in
the circumstances. If this were not possible as is the case in DH scenarios then, even if one acts
wrongfully, one cannot be properly blamed for so acting. If ‘one cannot avoid blame’, then ‘by
the principle of the avoidability of blame’, one is blameless.42 And, if one is blameless, then one
does not, pace Walzer, deserve punishment. Levy sums his position as follows:
In dirty hands cases, therefore, blame is not appropriate, and responsibility is widely
distributed, at least in democracies. If our representatives employ dirty means for our
39
Levy (2007).
Levy (2007): 40–41.
41
Levy relies on the distinction between first-person and second-and-third-person ascriptions of responsibility. The former is identified by the moral emotions of guilt, shame and pride. The latter are associated with
blame and praise. In DH scenarios the agent is right to feel guilt and pride for having so acted but ascription of
blame and praise rests with others who benefited from the action. See Levy (2007): 40.
42
Levy (2007): 45.
40
888
S. de Wijze
benefit, and they truly have no better alternative, they are not blameworthy, any more
than we are.43
Levy agrees with Walzer that we need to acknowledge the violation of important rules
and values that we violate due to the ‘complex of immorality’44 which sets the parameters
for DH scenarios. But this is done by ‘confronting the events’ and ‘compensating the
wronged’.45 If there is any blame for so acting, it is widely distributed (at least in
democratic societies) among all of us who benefited from the dirty acts. It is a short step
to see why Levy now sees the Retributivist justification as immoral. If the Retributivist
approach is indeed incoherent, then there is no justification for punishing the dirty. To do
so would be an immoral practice with no redeeming qualities. Indeed, as Meisels insists,
punishing an agent who has acted in good faith with the appropriate caution and with all
the incumbent risks to career and reputation would be ‘not only unjustifiable…but inexcusable’. It would be equivalent to punishing the innocent and it is not ‘an irony or a
paradox: it is simply wrong.’46
Since Levy presumably does not believe it is possible to establish any alternative
normative justifications for punishing the dirty, he takes the second route and rejects outright
the imposition of punishment for DH actions. Levy of course may ultimately be correct
about this but, it seems to me, that his (and Meisels’) decision to not look for alternative
justifications rests on the uncritical acceptance of certain assumptions that underlie the
standard justifications for punishment. I hope to show that there are alternative normative
justifications which are available to justify punishing DH but to do this requires that we
reevaluate our understanding of the relationships between responsibility, guilt, blame and
punishment. (See Appendix 1). Levy holds that a necessary condition for punishment is
blameworthiness and a necessary condition for blameworthiness is that an autonomous
agent was able to choose otherwise. However, just as Levy is right to think that in
some situations blameworthiness and responsibility can pull apart, so can punishment
and our inability to avoid acting in a particular way. DH scenarios are just such cases
where due to the immoral circumstances created by others, good persons are forced
for moral reasons to commit moral violations. These violations are categorical wrongs
and even if blame is not appropriate, there is still a need for punishment as I hope to
make clear in section 4 below.
What is more, even if we were to agree with Levy that punishing the dirty is incoherent
and immoral his alternative ‘solution’ for recognising the violation of categorical wrongs is
puzzling. He puts it this way:
Walzer is right to insist that we must seek a way to affirm the values that necessity
forced us to ignore. We best do that by confronting the events, not by ignoring them.
Society should compensate the wronged, if possible, and should do so in the name of
all those who bear responsibility for it. In the final analysis that means all of us.47
43
Levy (2007): 50.
By ‘complex of immorality’ I mean those situations in which good persons find themselves facing options
where they cannot avoid committing a categorical wrong. These situations are brought about by the immoral
or evil projects of other persons.
45
Levy (2007): 50.
46
Meisels (2008): 173. Meisels argues that Walzer acknowledges the immorality of punishing the dirty when
he states that when we so act we too get dirty hands. See Walzer (1973): 180. ‘Meanwhile he lies, manipulates,
and kills, and we must make sure he pays the price. We won’t be able to do that, however, without getting our
own hands dirty, and then we must find some way of paying the price ourselves.’
47
Levy (2007): 50.
44
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
889
But what does it mean to ‘confront the events’ rather than ignore them? One of the ways of
doing just this is to recognize that punishment is needed and seek a justification that does not rely
on the standard normative approaches to justifying punishment. Levy’s rejection of punishment
raises more questions than it solves. For example, how does one acknowledge those wronged?
How do we compensate the tortured terrorist in Walzer’s Ticking Bomb scenario? Does this
involve giving him his freedom, a public apology, a monetary reward or some combination of all
three? To be fair to Levy, these questions would be the subject of another paper but this said it is
too easy to dismiss punishment in favour of alternatives without giving some clearer idea of what
these alternatives would involve. What is more, since Levy does acknowledge the reality of DH,
how would the wrongdoing be properly acknowledged if not by punishing those who so acted?
Even if those who did get DH are not blameworthy, we may need to punish for other reasons
because ‘blameworthiness’ is only one important aspect of how we understand our moral reality
and how we best respond to it. The peculiar case of DH forces us to abandon the standard
approaches to justifying punishment and if we are not to abandon the idea of punishing the dirty,
then we need to find justificatory replacements. In section 4 I turn to three possible justifications
for imposing punishment on those with DH. My hope is that each justification alone offers
sufficient reason for punishing the dirty and when they are taken collectively make the argument
for such punishment irresistible to those who accept the reality of such scenarios.
4 Three alternative justifications
As stated repeatedly above the standard justifications for punishment are not fit for purpose
when applied to DH scenarios. The key difficulty is that all the standard justifications
assume that it is impossible to do wrong and right in the same action. They further assume
that punishment only attends to actions that are wrong and/or do harms. This standard view
also rests on the idea that there is a body of accepted rules or values which are capable of
guiding the ordinary conduct or behavior of rational autonomous agents. These agents are
able to follow these rules should they choose to do so and are aware of the consequences of
not doing so. The various theories of punishment then take off with either a forward looking,
backward looking, communicative or some hybrid approach that justifies inflicting the
punishment.48 But some of the above assumptions are not operative in cases of DH. In such
scenarios we do wrong and right in the same action, and the rules are confusing if not silent
in the face of intractable moral conflicts or dilemmas. Consequently, we need to look
elsewhere and the best place to begin is with what we want punishment to convey to those
who commit dirty acts and those who benefit and suffer from them. Given this approach
there are three possible justifications49 which I shall call the justifications from ‘catharsis’,
‘recognition of evil suffered’ and ‘causal responsibility’.
48
See Davis (2009): 75–77. I have borrowed and modified what Davis refers to as the ‘Flew-Benn-Hart
definition’ where punishment is concerned with institutions inflicting penalties on individuals who fail to
follow a body of rules.
49
There may be a fourth justification, which I call the justification from ‘metaphysical concerns’, where
punishment acknowledges the complexity and moral pluralism underlying our ethical lives. One way of
understanding DH is to see such acts as the inevitable consequence of unavoidable conflicting pluralist values
where punishment is necessary for proper acknowledgment of this reality. For example the value of punishing
those who violate categorical wrongs is pressing yet we also balk at punishing those who are blameless. (DH
scenarios, for example, involve conflicting values in the same way that freedom and equality conflict in
theories of justice. Too much freedom undermines equality whereas too much equality unacceptably restricts
freedom.) However I decided to leave ‘metaphysical concerns’ aside as it is less a justification as one
particular way of understanding the structural background of our moral reality of which DH is a part.
890
S. de Wijze
1) Justification from catharsis
In his discussion of DH and punishment Walzer raises, albeit rather briefly, what I have called
the ‘cathartic’ justification.50 Here punishment for those who get DH, especially for those who
commit terrible acts such as murder or torture, serves as a means to wash the blood from their
hands, to enable them to pay the price for what they have done. In so doing the agent is forgiven
her wrongdoing (and she can forgive herself to become morally whole once more). To use
Walzer’s terminology, she will be able to regain her soul as punishment in these circumstances
enables a form of atonement through self-punishment and expiation. While I argue that the
justification from ‘catharsis’ is a proper and persuasive normative basis from which to justify
punishing DH, it has been proposed by others as a justification for ordinary wrongdoing. Stephen
Garvey outlines and defends a similar normative justification for punishing wrongdoers in an
ideal community.51 This justification is based on the view that wrongdoers need to undergo a form
of secular penance in order to expiate their guilt and enable reconciliation with the community in
which they live.52 Garvey argues that under ideal circumstances, wrongdoing leads to guilt for
which the wrongdoer can and should atone. This atonement occurs when the offender undergoes
expiation for her wrongdoing which involves four stages: repentance, apology, reparation and
penance. When the victim of the wrongdoer sees a genuine attempt by the offender to expiate her
guilt, she forgives the offender and enables reconciliation. The expiation and reconciliation
together bring about atonement and heal the rift within the community caused by the wrongdoing
and importantly brings the offender back into the community as a member of good standing.
While Garvey’s ‘punishment as atonement’ theory focuses solely on straightforward
wrongdoing it has insights that underlie my justification as catharsis. Here punishing those
with DH is justified as it provides the best means for the DH agent to reconcile herself with
having committed a categorical wrong. Through a process of expiation she can acknowledge
the moral pollution of the DH action, cleanse herself and become a member of good standing
in the community once again. Here punishment serves as a ritual of cleansing and when the
DH act was committed in a public or professional role, the punishment needs to be a public
one and enforced by the appropriate authorities. Part of the process of expiating the guilt
arising from a wrongdoing committed in the public sphere is to publicly acknowledge the
wrongness of what has been done and publicly pay the appropriate and proportionate price
for so acting. In short, a public punishment enables public forgiveness. This is especially
important for politicians engaged in ‘noble cause’ corruption53 or for acts which necessitated
serious moral violation yet are highly praised by those who benefited from them. It is very
easy for politicians to erroneously believe that the wrong they committed has no moral
import because it was done for the right reasons.54
50
See Walzer (1973):178. Walzer refers to this cathartic purpose of punishment as ‘self-punishment and
expiation’.
51
Garvey (1999): 1810–1845 offers a secular version of punishment as atonement. This justification for
punishment is one that is developed for an ideal community. By ‘ideal community’ Garvey means those
groups of persons who identify with each another as members of a community but also sometimes act in ways
that wrong others in the community.
52
Justice as atonement clearly has a theological heritage and we find religious justifications of this kind at least as
far back as St Anselm in the 11th Century. (Garvey (1999): 1802–3.) Recent theorists who offer secular accounts
are Duff (1991) who argues for a communicative account of punishment where punishments are understood as
penances. Also see Adler (1991) and Hershenov (1999) for similar approaches to justifying punishment.
53
See Miller (2007).
54
The view that doing the right thing all things considered or that the overall good (or least evil) was achieved
and hence no moral violation has occurred is the standard view of deontological and and consequentialist
moral theories. The justification from ‘catharsis’ is designed specifically to reject this approach by acknowledging the paradoxical nature of DH.
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
891
The catharsis justification for punishing those with DH largely (but not exclusively)
focuses on the needs of those with DH, in particular their need to atone for what they have
done and cleanse their hands. Note that in such cases punishment is neither required to
prevent future genuine cases of DH, nor is it an attempt to change the character of the person
who committed the actions.55 Here, as pointed out above, is where the sui generis nature of
DH is recognized. The DH actions were the right actions all things considered and we
admire the agent that took the difficult decision to so act. But what the justification from
catharsis also recognizes is that in committing a categorical wrong the agent needs a way of
atoning for such an action and be seen to do so by the community for whom she so acted.
The catharsis emerges from the penance that is undergone by the person who gets DH.
The penance also serves to communicate to the victim of the DH act that despite the
necessity for so acting there is a recognition that dishonour and disrespect of their rights
has occurred. This may seem odd given that the person harmed may have created the
circumstances which required a good person to commit a moral violation for moral reasons.
But good persons recognize that the violation of categorical wrongs must be properly
acknowledged even when forced by necessity to so act. It is what enables others to recognize
their goodness in such situations.56 For example, engaging in an act of justified targeted
killing may be unavoidable in order to save many lives but the recognition that such an
action is morally polluting and that penance is needed for so acting is one important way to
distinguish them from cases of cold blooded assassination and other forms of extra judicial
killing.57
The justification as catharsis requires punishment of DH in order to enable the agent to
publicly acknowledge the moral violation, do penance and cleanse themselves. Here punishment acts as a form of therapy for the person who dirties their hands.58 There is a
retributive element as those with DH pay a proportionate price for having so acted. This
justification also provides a communicative element where those who benefited from the DH
action are made aware that moral violations had occurred and that atonement (albeit in a
different way from ordinary wrongdoers) is being made. It also acknowledges the victims of
55
Garvey argues that the process of expiation involves four processes: repentance, apology, reparation and
penance. Of these four processes only penance applies to DH scenarios in an uncomplicated manner.
Repentance for getting DH cannot be the same as repentance for the wrongdoer who ought to repudiate that
aspect of their character that led to such acts accompanied by the resolve to never so act again. Similarly, the
apology given is of a different order to that given by the wrongdoer who by apologising acknowledges her
wrongdoing and simultaneously disowns it thereby dissociating the true self from the guilty self. (See Garvey
1999: 1816). An apology in the DH scenario is one which apologises for committing a categorical wrong in
order for the community to observe that the politician (or public servant) is aware of the violation of a
cherished value/rule and is aware of the moral pollution that results from such an action. Reparation for the
ordinary wrongdoer involves two aspects: the material harms done and the moral wrong committed. In DH
scenarios reparation is complicated by the fact that the violation of another person’s rights and the material
harm inflicted were the right thing to do in order to bring about the lesser evil. But the need for reparation,
especially for the moral wrong committed, is important to uphold the inviolability of certain central and
cherished moral values.
56
This view is echoed by Walzer when he argues that we want a politician that is ‘not too good for politics and
that he is good enough’. That is, a politician who will be willing to get DH (not too good) and also be willing
to pay the price for doing so (good enough). See Walzer (1973): 167–8.
57
See de Wijze (2009) for an analysis of targeted killing as a case of DH.
58
If the justification from catharsis does indeed act as a form of therapy is it punishment rightly understood?
Does it fit with the definition of punishment offered, for example, by Duff? It seems to me that it does and that
the punishment meted out to those who have DH will be burdensome or painful and imposed by an
appropriate authority expressing or communicating censure. Imposing such burdens on agents with DH
works as a form of therapy precisely because it is understood to be a form of punishment for so acting.
892
S. de Wijze
such actions by conceding that they have been morally wronged even though this was
caused by the complex of immorality in which the agent found herself.
2) Justification from Evil Suffered
The second justification draws on insights taken from Raimond Gaita 59 by focusing on
punishment for DH scenarios that properly illustrate the uniqueness of this situation and
‘capture the evil in it’.60 The justifications for punishment offered by the Consequentialists
and Retributivists are underpinned by a rather narrow understanding of our ethical lives. From
this perspective, the primary and sole task of moral theory is to provide a reliable decision
procedure on how to act in all conceivable situations.61 The moral theory establishes the right
action (or demonstrates why an act is impermissible) and if agents fail to do what they ought to
do, then they have committed a moral violation and punishment is the fitting, necessary, and
justified response. However, this view of our moral commitments is inappropriately reductionist which undermines our moral reality and diminishes the ethical domain of our lives.
There is another important aspect to understanding human actions that are immoral or
evil. An evil or immoral action, as Gaita points out, is sui generis in that it does ‘not remain
solely with the deed or with the character of the evil-doer: it spreads beyond them to their
victim.’62 When we correctly feel remorse for our immoral actions, what this recognises is
‘the shock of the acknowledgement of the sacred in ourselves and in our victims’.63 We
acknowledge the ‘special dignity’ or ‘special authority’ of the ethical. To put it in Kantian
terms, we recognize that persons are ends in themselves and by acting immorally we have
failed to treat them as such. The acceptance of punishment for having done wrong is the best
way to demonstrate that we understands the ‘evil in the situation’ and that we recognise the
humanity and importance of other human beings – even those who have sought to harm us.64
It is noticeable that politicians and especially revolutionaries have been driven by a need to
fight injustice and relieve suffering, what Arendt called a ‘passion for compassion’ (Arendt
1990)65, have themselves often perpetrated terrible crimes. Typically, such persons dismiss the
reality of DH scenarios, that there are situations, especially in politics, where some actions are
justified and necessary yet also terribly wrong. They fail to see the evil in the situation they have
brought about due to an adherence to a simplistic reductionist ‘right or wrong but never both’
approach. Such moral decisions can lead to the loss of humanity and the committing of terrible
moral crimes even when pursuing justice or the lesser evil. For this reason the need to punish
those with DH is especially important. Good persons can erroneously and too readily assuage
their guilt by believing that the moral (and legal) violation was unavoidable given the choices
available. It is also tempting for agents to feel no moral responsibility for such acts because those
59
Gaita (1991): Chs. 4and 5.
Gaita (1991): 74. By drawing on Gaita’s work I don’t mean to imply that he would endorse my use of his
ideas for justifying punishment in DH cases. Given Gaita’s views on the relationship between ethics and
politics, I suspect he might find the very notion of DH (at least as I have construed it) problematic and so too
the justifications for punishment that I offer here. (See Gaita’s ch.14 but especially his comments on Walzer’s
notion of DH on 261–262.)
61
This belief in part explains why the standard deontological and consequentialist moral theories deny the
existence of genuine moral dilemmas. The correct application of the preferred moral theory dissolves the
prima facie moral conflict. It has been pointed out to me that hybrid and pluralist theories of morality and their
attending views on punishment would not need to be reductionist about our ethical lives. I agree and expect
that such theories are likely to be sympathetic to my account of DH and my justification from ‘evil suffered’.
62
Gaita (1991): 80.
63
Gaita (1991): 80.
64
Some might consider the scope of this recognition to be wide enough to encompass most higher sentient
beings.
65
Arendt (1990): 71
60
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
893
transgressed against are of lesser concern or because they created the circumstances which
necessitated an immoral response. Punishing those with DH offers the appropriate corrective to
these sorts of misunderstandings ensuring that the necessary harms done and the wrongs
committed are properly understood and kept to an absolute minimum.
3) Justification from Causal Responsibility
The third justification challenges the widely accepted link between responsibility, guilt
and blameworthiness which underlies Levy’s rejection of punishment for those who get DH.
This justification draws on a Retributivist sense of why punishment is necessary but does so
without holding to certain assumptions about the link between blameworthiness and intentionality of an action. It draws on Williams’ insight that we can be held responsible for
actions we did not intend but which nevertheless formed an important part of the causal
chain of events that resulted in some terrible harm or serious rights violation. We have an
impact on the world through both our intended and unintended actions and we ought to feel
the weight of our unintended actions especially if they bring about a terrible state of affairs.
This is Williams’ point in his ‘Lorry Driver’ example where he argues for a species of moral
emotion he calls ‘agent-regret’.66 This is a species of regret that one can only feel towards
one’s own actions and it is not restricted to intentional actions. As Williams makes clear:
It can extend far beyond what one intentionally did to almost anything for which one
was causally responsible in virtue of something one intentionally did.67
The Greek tragic plays, such as Sophocles’s King Oedipus, certainly understood and explored the
impact of non-intentional actions.68 Oedipus, as is well known, had no intention of killing his father
Laius and marrying his mother Jocasta - but he did and that made all the difference. He was guilty of
patricide and incest, both terrible crimes which need to be severely punished. But how is one to
respond to the dreadful knowledge that one has unintentionally killed one’s own father and married
one’s mother? For Oedipus it was self blinding and exile. He punishes himself for actions he did not
intend because he properly feels the moral weight and pollution of what he has done. Oedipus need
not be seen as acting irrationally, or as holding an inappropriate sense of moral pollution based on a
primitive moral sensibility. Punishment may be appropriate and necessary even when one finds
oneself involuntarily part of a causal chain that ends in a terrible state of affairs.69
If this is true, then it has important implications for those who get DH. When we dirty our
hands we ought to feel ‘tragic-remorse’ since in addition to feelings of guilt and shame we
also feel anguish, pride and a strong sense of moral pollution. We feel the pollution of being
complicit with the immoral actions of others and from acting in ways that violate much
66
Williams (1981a, b) ‘Moral luck’: 27–29.
Williams (1981a, b) ‘Moral luck’: 28.
By ‘non-intentional’ here I do not mean that the each specific action was compulsive or due to outside
forces that could not be resisted. Oedipus does not act like an automaton. Rather, what is meant here is that his
chosen actions were inevitable given his destiny foretold by the prophesy at his birth, one which Oedipus did
not choose nor could he change.
69
Williams (1994): ch. 3 points out that any conception of responsibility for actions has four different
elements: cause, intention, state and response (55.) Our actions are sometimes caused by events outside our
control or knowledge. But our actions cause things to happen, and some of these outcomes were intended but
often they are not. Certain outcomes that are involuntarily brought about might be regretted by the agent and/
or by those who suffer from such outcomes. When this happens there is a demand for a response – a demand
from the agent herself and/or by those who suffer from the action. Williams’ crucial insight here is that it is
entirely plausible to have such situations where there is responsibility for actions which were not intentional
but brought about outcomes that are regrettable. Consequently, if our actions caused by circumstances beyond
our control result in unintended harmful outcomes, we can still be held responsible for them. And if this is
true, then we can justifiably punish such persons for their actions.
67
68
894
S. de Wijze
cherished categorical moral principles. Pace Levy’s (and Meisels’) claim that punishment in
these circumstances is incoherent and unjust, it is necessary to acknowledge the wrong done
and pay a proportionate price. Blameworthiness in such contexts is not dependent on the
view that the agent could have done otherwise or that the responsibility for wrongful actions
presupposes intended or voluntary actions. Doing something horrendous and wrong, even if
unintended or strenuously but unsuccessfully resisted, leaves a moral remainder and the need
for some price to be paid. While this justification for punishment rests on a retributivist sense
of desert, it does not link blame and intentionality in the same way marking a significant
modification from the standard retributivist justification outlined in section 2.
4) Final thoughts on the three justifications for DH
The three justifications above when taken together contain forward, backward and
communicative elements but also differ significantly from the standard justifications. In
DH cases punishment does not seek to rehabilitate the agent but it does attempt to provide a
process which expiates the guilt and removes the moral pollution for violating a cherished
and categorical moral prohibition. Secondly, punishing the dirty has a retributivist element to
it because since the agent has committed a serious moral wrong or crime (even if they had no
alternative given the options) they deserve punishment for so acting. This protects the
dignity and majesty of the moral realm (and the legal system) which even when violated
for the right reasons needs to be paid for through punishment. Thirdly, punishment for DH
violations are not intended to prevent future occurrence of the specific moral violation given
that it was the right thing to do and brought about the lesser evil. Rather, it seeks to
communicate the seriousness of such violations and make agents carefully evaluate the
necessity and wisdom of future DH actions given that so acting brings with it a serious moral
cost. As Walzer points out rather vividly using religious imagery, when a good moral agent
gets DH the choices are hard and painful and he pays the price not only while making them
but forever after. A man doesn’t lose his soul one day and find it the next.70
This is the communicative element warning of the gravity of such acts and reminding
agents to so act only when absolutely necessary.
5 Conclusion
Those who get dirty hands should be punished. I have argued pace Levy who holds that it is
both inconsistent and immoral to punish those with dirty hands. I then offered three
justifications why those with DH ought to be punished.71 Many of these arguments,
70
Walzer (1973): 177.
If my justifications for punishing DH are persuasive there remains the separate and difficult question of
what kinds and how much punishment would be appropriate. The justifications in themselves do not give
guidance concerning the specific nature and severity of appropriate and reasonable punishments. However,
there are moral boundaries constraining the nature and extent of punishments in a just liberal society which
can be stated as useful general principles. (Bedau et al. 2010: section 4 , for example, offer four principles for
constraining the use of punishment in a just liberal society. ) While this is not the place to examine these issues
at length I simply state three principles that constrain punishment for DH in a liberal democratic society. To
this end we can say that punishment for getting DH cannot be cruel and gratuitous nor violate the rights of
agents. Secondly, it must be proportionate to the immoral or criminal act committed. And, thirdly, it must be
open to an even greater degree of discretion and flexibility than cases of punishment for ordinary wrongdoing.
Beyond this there is a wide variety of punishments for political agents ranging from criminal trials, electoral
retaliation, social ostracism and removal of office. In some cases self-punishment such as resignation would be
appropriate. For a more detailed account of such punishments see Garrett (1996): ch 2.
71
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
895
especially concerning the justification of punishment for DH scenarios, are uncomfortable
ones requiring a deep revision of what we have long taken to be unassailable assumptions
about the purpose of moral theories and the place of guilt, responsibility and punishment
within them. But for all that, I contend that the justifications for which I have argued offer a
better fit with our deep intuitions and reflective understanding of our moral reality of which
DH scenarios are a part.
When we punish those who do wrong to do right, we do this because it is right to do so
and it serves to protect us and the agent’s moral standing. However it always remains an
uncomfortable situation since we find ourselves in a grey zone where good persons do
wrongful actions in order to prevent terrible outcomes. This leaves them morally stained and
leaves us ambivalent about how we are to respond (and how the agent ought to respond) for
so acting. If this is right we have no way to offer more comfortable advice than that we need
to find a way to live with the duality of being both right and wrong at the same time. Martin
Hollis acknowledges the strangeness of the DH phenomenon. He states at the conclusion of
his article:
A paper on the art of the morally permissible cannot end tidily. If there were a
clear line which marked the limit of manoeuvre, then there would finally be no
Dirty Hands problem. .. It is an arena where the best is the enemy of the good,
where we license our agents to pursue the good and where they can succeed,
only if they operate partly beyond our ken and our control. Can some critic
please find me a more comfortable conclusion?72
I do not think there is a comfortable solution, something which consequentialists and
deontologists claim to have and seek to impose on us. To accept their views would require us
to ignore our complex moral reality and diminish our ethical lives. The price of doing that is
too high and even more uncomfortable than living with ambiguity and paradox. The puzzle
of DH demonstrates that sometimes our ethical lives can be complex, messy and difficult.
And from this there can be no escape.73
Appendix 1
The table below sets out the different ways in which the relationship between responsibility,
avoidability, guilt, praise, blame and punishment might be understood. The ‘Responsibility’
column refers to the chosen action taken by an autonomous moral agent who does so
knowing that her actions have violated an important moral value. The ‘Avoidability’ column
refers to whether the agent could have done otherwise given the circumstances in which she
finds herself (Table 1).
72
Hollis (1982): 398.
I am indebted to Jeremy Barris, Chris Bennett, Kimberley Brownlee, Eve Garrard, and Mark Reiff for
extensive comments on earlier versions of this paper. They have prevented me from making many elementary
errors. My thanks also to Tony Coady, David Rodin, Michael Neu, Jon Quong, and the participants attending
the MANCEPT one day conference on ‘Terrorism and Dirty Hands’ in 2011 for their useful comments. An
earlier version of this paper was also read at the weekly philosophy seminar at Virginia Tech University 2011,
and at the 2011 MANCEPT Political Theory Workshops. I am grateful to the participants of the philosophy
seminar and the ‘Dirty Hands’ workshop for the many helpful suggestions and comments. I am also indebted
to two anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments.
73
896
S. de Wijze
Table 1 Responsibility and Evaluation–A Summary of the Different Positions
Action
Responsibility Avoidability
Guilt Praise Blame Punishment
Ordinary wrongdoing Yes
Yes
Yes
No
Yes
Yes
Tragic dilemma
Yes
No (natural events and some
situations caused by
human actions)
No
No
No
No
DH scenario (Levy)
Yes
No (situations arise because
Yes
of a complex of immorality)
Yes
No
No
DH Scenario
(Walzer/ de Wijze)
Yes
No (situations arise because
Yes
of a complex of immorality)
Yes
No
Yes
References
Adler J (1991) The urging of conscience: a theory of punishment. Temple University Press, Philadelphia
Arendt H (1958) The human condition. Chicago University Press, Chicago
Arendt H (1990) On revolution. Penguin Books, London
Bedau, Hugo Adam and Kelly, Erin (2010) "Punishment", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring
2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/punishment
Bennett C (2008) The apology ritual: a philosophical theory of punishment. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge
Camus A (1958) The just assassins. In: Gilbert S (ed) Caligula and three other plays. Knopf, New York
Cohen S (1991) Alternatives to punishment- the abolitionist case. Isr Law Rev 25(3):729–739
Davis M (2009) Punishment theory’s golden half century: a survey of developments from (about) 1957 to
2007. J Ethics 13:73–100
de Wijze S (1994) Dirty hands—doing wrong to do right. S Afr J Philos 13(1):27–33
de Wijze S (2005) Tragic-remorse—the anguish of dirty hands. Ethical Theory Moral Prac 7(5):453–
471
de Wijze S (2009) ‘Targeted killing: a ‘dirty hands’ analysis’. Contemp Polit 15(3):305–320
Digeser P (1998) Forgiveness and politics: dirty hands and imperfect procedures. Polit Theor 26(5):700–724
Duff RA (1991) Punishment, Expression and Penance. In: Jung H, Müller-Dietz H, Neumann U (eds) Nomos)
Recht und Moral: Beiträge zu einer Standortbestimmung 235
Duff RA (1998) Desert and penance. In: Ashworth A, Von Hirsch A (eds) Principled sentencing. Hart,
Oxford
Duff RA (2001) Punishment, communication and community. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Feinberg J (1970) Doing and deserving. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Gaita R (1991) Good and evil: an absolute conception. Macmillan, Basingstoke
Galston W (1991) Toughness as a political virtue. Soc Theor Pract 17(2):175–197
Gardner J (2005) Wrongs and faults. Rev Metaphy 59(1):95–132
Garrett SA (1996) Conscience and power: an examination of dirty hands and political leadership. Macmillan,
London
Garvey SP (1999) Punishment as Atonement. Cornell Law Faculty Publications, Paper 264. http://scholar
ship.law.cornell.edu/facpub/264
Goodwin T (2009) The problem of dirty hands: examining and defending a special case of inescapable moral
wrongdoing. (PhD Thesis University of Manchester)
Gowans CW (1994) Innocence lost: an examination of inescapable moral wrongdoing. Oxford University
Press, Oxford
Hampshire S (1978) Morality and pessimism. In: Hampshire S (ed) Public and private morality. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge
Hampshire S (1983) Morality and conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Hart HLA (1968) Punishment and responsibility. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Hershenov DB (1999) Restitution and Revenge. J Phil 96(2):79–94
Hollis M (1982) Dirty hands. Br J Polit Sci 12(4):385–398
Kemp J (1968) The philosophy of Kant. OUP, London
Kramer M (2011) The ethics of capital punishment. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Lacey N (1988) State punishment: political principles and community values. Routledge, London
Punishing ‘dirty hands’—three justifications
897
Levy N (2007) Punishing the dirty. In: Primoratz I (ed) Politics and morality. Palgrave Macmillan, New York,
pp 38–53
Machiavelli N (1997) The prince. Wordsworth Editions Ltd, Ware
Matravers M (2000) Justice and punishment: the rationale of coercion. Oxford University Press, Oxford
McDermott D (2001) The permissibility of punishment. Law Philos 20:403–432
Meisels T (2008) Torture and the problem of dirty hands. Can J Law Jur 21(1):149–173
Miller S (2007) Noble cause corruption in politics. In: Primoratz I (ed) Politics and morality. Palgrave
Macmillan, New York
Nagel T (1972) War and massacre. Philos Publ Aff 1(2):123–144
Nielsen K (1996) There is no dilemma of dirty hands. In: Rynard P, Shugarman DP (eds) Cruelty & deception:
the controversy over dirty hands in politics. Broadview, Letchworth, pp 139–155
Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Stocker M (1992) Plural and conflicting values. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Stocker M (2000) Dirty hands and ordinary life. In: Rynard P, Shugarman DP (eds) Cruelty and deception: the
controversy over dirty hands in politics. Broadview, Letchworth
Tasioulas J (2006) Punishment and Repentance. Philosophy 81
Thompson D (1987) Political ethics and public office. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Von Hirsch A (1998) Proportionate sentences: a desert perspective. In: Andrew A, Andrew Von H (eds)
Principled sentencing. Hart, Oxford
Walzer M (1973) Political action: the problem of dirty hands. Philos Publ Aff 2(2):160–180
Weber M (1948) Politics as a vocation. In: HH G, and Wright Mills C (eds) From Max Weber: essays in
sociology. London, Kegan Paul Ltd
Williams B (1981a) Utilitarianism and moral self indulgence. In Moral luck—philosophical papers 1973–
1980. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Williams B (1981b) Moral luck. In: Moral luck—philosophical papers 1973–1980. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge
Williams B (1994) Shame and necessity. University of California Press Ltd, London