zyx
zyxzy
AQUINAS LECTURE 1985
Practical Reasoning, Human Goods
and the End of Man
John Finnis
Given at Blackfriars, Oxford, on 29 January, 1985. *
Our practical reasoning goes well and attains its truth when we
identify ways of adequately getting or realising really desirable
objectives. And our objectives are really desirable (good) when they
either are really desirable in themselves, or are steps on the way to
getting or realising some such intrinsically desirable objective or
objectives. If there is but one such intrinsically desirable objective, our
practical reasoning cannot go well unless we know what it is. If, as
seems much more plausible, there are a number of intrinsically
desirable objectives, our practical reasoning cannot go well unless we
know whether there is some further objective to be attained or realised
by or in the pursuit of some or all of these intrinsically desirable
objectives, i.e. whether there is some further point to pursuing them;
and if so, what that further point or objective (‘last end’) actually is.
Some say that the true last end is some one of the intrinsically
desirable human goods, say, the highest instantiation of the highest
good attainable in this life, thus contemplation of God to the extent
that God is knowable through His creatures. Others agree that it is
some one human good, but place it beyond this life, and beyond
merely human capacities, in the beatific vision and contemplation of
God. Others again deny that it is any one of these goods, and say that
it is integral human fulfilment, a manifold of goods; and that, given
human capacities as we know them, such fulfilment can now be for
practical reasoning no more than an inadequately attainable value, an
ideal of practical reason, but could in a divinely completed realm and
household of God be shared and enjoyed, by each member of that
realm and household, as an attained and realised goal.
The last is the position I wish to defend.
A word about method. As St. Thomas very plainly says, the task
of philosophically ‘considering and determining the ultimate end of
438
zyx
z
zyx
zy
life and human affairs’ belongs to the principal practical science’;
Aristotle called it ethics and Thomas moral philosophg, but both
agreed that it is practical, from beginning to end’. This, then, is
philosophising to be done (if done intelligently) for the sake of
realising or getting intrinsically desirable human good(^)^. Such
philosophising is thus (if one can only get one’s act together) all of a
piece with the rest of one’s practical reasonings.
I
In Nicomachean Ethics I,2, Aristotle launches an argument that many
have understood as the following mere fallacy: If any chain of choices
must end somewhere, there must be a single place where all chains of
choice stop. Aristotle’s text5, however, is not so simple-minded:
If. ..
(1) We do not choose everything for some further thing
(for that would be to begin an infinite regress, in which
case desire would be empty and pointless),
and
(2) there is some one end of acts, which we want for its own
sake while we want the others for it,
then it is clear that
(3) that one end will be the good and indeed the highest
good.
Now this is no fallacy. Step (1) does not assert that there must, if
choice is not to be vain, be one place in which all chains of choice end.
It simply asserts that every chain of choice does have a point, its own
point or end or final good (not necessarily the same point as other
chains of choice). One chain of practical reasoning ends, Aristotle will
suggest6, in a good such as honour, another in a good such as
pleasure, another-in the good of understanding, and others in one or
other of the excellences or virtues.
And now step (2) comes in to say that if even these “other” final
goods or ends-for-their-own-sake’ are chosen not only for their own
sake but also for the sake of some one end, then (3) that one end will
be the highest good or indeed, as Aristotle puts it (elliptically and at
considerable risk of misleading), the good simpliciter.
In NE I, 7 Aristotle is going to explain both this conclusion (step
(3) and his reason for affirming what is supposed in step (2), i.e. for
affirming that there is indeed ‘some one end of acts, which we want
for its own sake while we want the others for it’. Take the conclusion
first.
To understand something possible or actual as good is to
understand it as having or giving point, as a ‘that for the sake of
which.. .’, as end. And the good without qualification will be, he says,
zyxw
zyxwvu
z
z
439
zyxwv
whatever is most an end. The good will be most final by making one’s
life (A) lacking in nothing, i.e. ‘self-sufficient’ (autarches) and (B)
thoroughly desirable (choiceworthy, aireton, eligibilis).
Now self-sufficiency and unqualified desirability are both
definitive of eudaimonia, a concept more ordinarily familiar to
Aristotle’s hearers than the technical concept of the good. So ‘the
good’ is eudaimonia, provided we understand by eudaimonia a state
(whatever it may turn out to be) which (A) makes one’s life selfsufficient, i.e. lacking in nothing, i.e. satisfying all desires’, and (B) is
unrestrictedly final in that it is the point of all choices, even of choices
for goods which are themselves final in that they are chosen for their
own sake, as ends in themselves.
Troels Engberg-Pedersen has recently argued forcefully that in
Book I of the NE, eudaimonia is, in fact, a purely formal concept, the
concept of a satisfactory life: an indeterminate state which (A)
involves the satisfaction of all desires and (B) is the point of all choice.
Aristotle here makes no decision amongst the competing conceptions
of this concept; the state is left wholly undetermined. Even when the
argument leads Aristotle to affirm that the state is one of activity, ‘it is
left absolutely open whether just one thing or activity or more things
or activities than one should in the end be said to fill in e~daimonia’.~
Now the formal property of eudaimonia in NE I, 7 (1095b5) is
this: when we stop our chains of choice (practical reasoning) at other
ends or goods which are final, we do so not only because of the
goodness of such ends-for-their-own-sake but also because we believe
that through these goods we will secure eudaimonia.
So here, at last, we find ground for asserting what was
hypothesised in step (2). Precisely because the concept of eudaimonia
simply is the concept of the fully satisfactory life-i.e. a state
(whatever it may be) which is the point of all choices and the
satisfaction of all desires-it can be said that final goods such as
(Aristotle supposes) honour, pleasure, understanding and virtue are
chosen not only for their own sakes but also for the sake of
eudaimonia. Thus eudaimonia is the ‘one end’ Aristotle was
envisaging.
But one may wish to test the matter. Are the various final goods
in fact chosen for the sake of eudaimonia? Aristotle says so, but offers
no argument to prove it. The missing argument must, I think, be that
suggested by St. Thomas”. For Thomas, this fact is not a mere
happenstance, which sometimes is the case and sometimes not; it is a
necessity, a natural necessity and (since will simply is the power of
intelligent and rational choosing) a rational necessity. Why? Surely
because about every specific human good, however thoroughly and
independently and non-derivatively good (and thus capable of
terminating a chain of practical reasoning and rendering otiose the
440
zyx
z
zyxw
question ‘What for?’), there can nonetheless be raised the further
question: ‘Is the state of affairs in which this good, or this set of
goods, is realized by my choice a fully satisfactory state of affairs?’
The question is meaningful, and successful in relativising even
our most successful attainments of basic human goods; the question
remains meaningful, and forceful, even though we remain quite
unable to identify a practicable ‘fully Satisfactory life’, or an
attainable ‘perfect good’, a ‘practicable state of affairs lacking
nothing’, ‘perfectum et sufficiens’“.
Specific basic goods, i.e. goods which are underived and chainof-choice-ending, have both a critique and a support in this category,
this inescapable further question. They have a critique because no one
of them can plausibly pose as itself the fully satisfactory object of
choice. They have a support because each of them has its attraction
not merely as ‘a good in itself‘ but also as a component in,
contribution to, the fully satisfactory, whatever that may be.
But how are the basic human goods in fact related to a ‘fully
satisfactory’? The ‘fully satisfactory’ that Aristotle and Aquinas have
in mind is ‘practicable’. But, Aquinas quite reasonably points out, it is
simply impossible to attain the fully satisfactory (‘excluding all evil
and fulfilling every desire’) in this life”. Only an ‘imperfect’
beatitude, he says, is within our powers”.
But is ‘imperfect beatitude’ a coherent concept? After all, the ‘perfect’,
the ‘fully satisfactory’, is what the concept of eudaimonia/beatitudo is
about; an ‘imperfect beatitude’ is, by definition, a state that is not
‘adequate to the aspirations of human nature’. The notion certainly
seems paradoxical.
To see whether it is a worthwhile paradox, we can first inquire
what Aquinas thought his beatitudo imperfecta consists in. I begin
with the most illuminating of his various answers: ‘beatitudo
imperfecta consistit in operatione virtutis’, imperfect beatitude
consists in the workings of virtue (virtue in a ~ t i o n ) ’ ~ .
Now virtue is whatever renders good its possessor and his acts.
Take the moral virtues, for example. They have, says Aquinas, a
point: bonum humanum, human good’’; and recognition and love of
this good is necessary for virtueI6.
And here we come to a matter decisive for my whole argument.
This bonum humanum, the point or good of virtue, is a manifold; for
there are, says St. Thomas, a plurality of fines rnoraliurn virtuturn,
ends of the moral virtues”. These ends are identified by practical
understanding working according to the natural disposition which he
calls synderesis‘*. The understanding of these final or basic goods is
441
z
zyxwvu
zyxw
formulated in the prima principiu of practical reasoning, principles
which Aquinas calls the prima principiu of natural law or natural
rightIg. The goods identified in these principles are naturally wanted;
they are the appropriate objects of the inclinations which pertain to
each of the human capacities and a human being’s natural integrity”.
As such they are included under the will’s natural object, complete or
universal good2’; but each is final, good-for-its-own sake, as Aquinas
most plainly affirms by describing the manifold of corresponding
practical principles as per se notu and prima. Yet none of these basic
goods is absolutely or simply or (as Aristotle would say) ‘most’ final.
Let me here interpose three summary remarks:
(i) Aquinas has arrived at a rather better list of final or basic goods
than that off-hand itemisation in Nic. Eth. I,7 (‘honour, pleasure,
intelligence and the various virtues’).
(ii) Aquinas’s list includes knowing truth about God. But it is clear
that no item in the list is highest in the sense that the others are merely
means to it, or are more dispensable than it, or can rightly be directly
attacked for the sake of securing it2’.
(iii) We began with a proposition about the moral virtues and looked
for their point; but there are also the intellectual virtues or excellences,
all of which (leaving aside prudentiu) can exist without moral virtue23.
St. Thomas, intellectualist though he may be, will point out that one
can make bad use of an intellectual, but not of a moral, virtue24;
indeed, he will say that, if we are considering their relationship to
human activity, the intellectual virtues are less noble than the moral2’.
There is, we may say, no single, privileged perspective from which
such a human good as theoretical knowledge grasped and enjoyed
contemplatively is simply and in all respects highest, particularly if by
‘highest’ we mean most choice-worthy.
To return now to Aquinas’s ‘imperfect beatitude’; we can now
see why one might think it consists in the workings of virtue. For we
can envisage a life in which each of the basic goods is somehow in
place; none is suppressed; none is arbitrarily emphasised or
contemned; reasonableness regulates their interrelations as it regulates
the emotions and inclinations of the individual and the relations
between individuals in friendship and other forms of community.
These ‘virtue-in-action’ aspects of this person’s flourishing do not add
t o the value of the basic components in that flourishing, the basic
goods26. But they do constitute a further intelligible and worthwhile
good which is simply an intelligible and worthwhile aspect of the
realization of the other goods (derivative and non-final or underived
and final/basic), a good in relation to which every other good takes its
place, or under which each of them falls.
That is surely why St. Thomas could helpfully speak of imperfect
beatitude, even at the cost of some paradox: imperfect beatitude is
442
z
zyxw
zy
zy
worthy of the name just because, in some respect, i t plays the same
role in practical thinking and choosing as the natural and inescapabie
notion of (perfect) beatitude or euduimoniu, the notion of the fully
(not imperfectly) satisfactory (whatever that may be). ... Being
imperfect, imperfect beatitude is neither the fully adequate point of all
choices nor a state lacking nothing that we could desire. But specific
goods-for-their-own-sake and ends-for-their-own-sake can and should
be ‘placed’ (both critically and supportively) under some wider good,
‘imperfect beatitude’, a good somehow constituted by the realization,
in some appropriate way, of basic human goods”.
But there is also a rather different story, perhaps more prominent in
St. Thomas’s account, and certainly more well-known. In its starkest
form, this tells us that ‘the imperfect human felicity which is
attainable in this life consists in knowledge of the separated substances
by the hubitus of wisdom”x. With more formality:
‘as is stated in (Aristotle’s) Ethics, the imperfect beatitude
which we can have in this life first and principally consists
in contemplation, and secondarily in the activity of
practical understanding governing our actions and
emotions’*’.
The question, therefore, is this: Why does St. Thomas say that in the
imperfect beatitude available in this life, contemplation has ‘first
place’? (Whatever that may in practice amount to...). Various reasons
are offered”’, but the decisive one seems to be that in contemplation,
and in the intellectual virtues, ‘we have a kind of beginning of that
(true) happiness which consists in the knowledge of truth’.”.
To test the adequacy of this characterisation of true beatitude and
thus, by anticipation, of ‘imperfect beatitude’, we need to enquire
whether our true and unrestricted fulfilment or flourishing would
indeed consist only in contemplation, even contemplation of God’s
essence in the beatific vision.
Aquinas’s statements to the effect that human beatitude is to be
found ‘on@ in the vision of
are to be understood in the same
sense as his statement that ‘Deus est forum hominis b o n u ~ n ’ Each
~ ~ . is
highly elliptical; they run the same risk of being taken literally (and
thus being misunderstood) as Aristotle ran when he said that
euduimoniu is ‘the good’ (a statement conjoined by Aristotle,
however, with the statement that there are many human ends-inthemselves). ‘Deus est totum hominis bonum’ is compatible with
Aquinas’s statement that to love God
is an ‘inadequate and
imperfect love of God’, and actually inferior to love of neighbour for
God’s sake. God’s goodness is our ‘whole good’ just in the sense that
zyxw
zy
z
443
zy
it is (a) the self-sufficiently adequate object of our love and (b) the
cause of all other goods (including persons and including, too, the
good constituted by our love of goods including persons). But God’s
goodness is also ‘not our whole good’, for God, by unnecessitated
choice, has created a universe of other goods distinct from Himself,
including goods available to and worthy of our love-of-friendship
(amor amicitiae) among human persons.
It is necessary, says St. Thomas, that there be but one ultimate
end of man in so far as he is man, because human nature is a unity”.
Very well. But must we not acknowledge that the unity of human
nature is a unity in complexity? For a start, ‘Anima mea non est
ego’’‘. For another thing, human nature is known through its
capacities, and they are known through their acts, and these are
known through their objects”, and those objects are, for the most
part, precisely the basic goods identified in the prima principia of
practical understanding”. And as these are plural, so the human
nature they disclose is complex. So: the last end, if it has the unity of
human nature, must have the complexity which is unified in that
nature.
Let me dwell on just one aspect of this complexity. Among the
capacities (potentiae animae) intrinsic to human nature is our capacity
for love-of-friendship“, the richest of the human objects of the basic
inclination towards living in societale‘”. No-one understands human
nature who does not understand that a human being is deprived and
stunted in his own being if he has no participation in the love-offriendship. No-one understands love-of-friendship who does not
understand that it involves a mutual and reciprocal will that the other
person flourish more fully, i.e. share more fully in goods, among
which goods must therefore (precisely because the other has the same
desire that one be more fully flourishing oneself) be, now for the sake
of that other, the fuller flourishing of oneself. Self-love, in due
measure, is intrinsic to the fullest, most generous love-of-friendship;
love-of friendship, seeking true goods for another even at the hazard
of one’s own well-being, is intrinsic to one’s own well-being. So: noone can understand the unity of human nature who does not
understand this complexity of union-without-absorption, this
irreducible duality (indeed, multiplicity) of the goods which must be
realized if that nature is to be most fully actualized.
Hence we find Aquinas concluding that the socielas amicorum is
of the ‘bene esse of (perfect) beatitude’“. But why ‘of the bene esse’?
Because, he says, it is not absolutely necessary to beatitude, since it is
possible to envisage a universe in which there were but one soul in
communion with God, and that one would have beatitude; but the
actual universe is one in which we each have neighbours.. ..
Still we should press our question about Aquinas’s references to
444
zyxw
zyxwv
zy
zyxw
zy
the ‘complete’ perfection, or ‘bene esse’, of perfect beatitude. For we
find him using such expressions not only in relation to friendship but
also in relation to bodily life: “beatitude which is perfect in all
respects (beatitudo omnibus modis perfecta) requires the well-being of
one’s own body42.Such expressions are as paradoxical as ‘imperfect
beatitude’ and are tantamount to conceding what in other places
seemed to be denied: that the goods attained and realized in full
beatitude are not one but many, in due orderJ3 This requirement of
loving the goods in beatitude in due measure does not differ in its
intelligible structure from the measure of practical reasonableness that
we discern and use in this life.
St. Thomas himself draws the necessary conclusion: in the state
of perfect beatitude, when faith and hope will have ceased to be
virtues, practical reasonableness (prudentia) and justice will still,
therefore, be needed virtues-along with that charity which includes
with love of God a love of self (including one’s body) and of
neighbours in patria“.
At the outset of this lecture, I said that man’s true last end is
integral human fulfilmentJ‘. In this life, that is not a practicable goal
at all; its place in practical reasoning is rather as the ideal that provides
the content of the first principle of morality4‘. It is faith, not
philosophy, that proposes that that ideal may be realised, by divine
power and grace. Its realisation would be, 1 suggest, a state of affairs
that would not be, formally, a human act, nor, formally, a human
possession, though it would involve both activity and enjoyment. St.
Thomas himself from time to time overcomes the limitations of the
Aristotelian categories in which he usually conceives the last end of
human life: the categories of act and perfection, and the vocabulary
which draws no distinction between ideal and goal, or between
‘means’ which are merely instrumental and means which are actually
constitutive of a good. Often he says that the point (object) of our
beatitude is divine good”, and sometimes he will add that that good,
precisely as object of our beatitude, must be understood not as
something to be had or possessed but rather as the common good of a
whole society, that heavenly city whose citizens are the saints“.
To bring the whole matter to a head: we can now assess Aquinas’s
argument that ‘imperfect beatitude’ consists ‘first and principally’ in
contemplation because perfect beatitude ‘consists in’ contemplation.
Even on the rather relentlessly ‘intellectualist’ account in Aquinas’s
later writings, perfect beatitude consists not only in the contemplative
vision which illuminates the being and worth of all else49,but also in
an exercise of the virtues of practical understanding and
reasonableness, and of justice; and in love-of-friendship; and in
enjoyment of one’s own bodily personal life in its fullness. Hence,
even when one accepts the primacy within perfect beatitude of the
zyxwv
445
z
vision of God, the argument from anticipation provides one with
weak ground for according primacy t o contemplation within
imperfect beatitude; for the virtues of the active life, too, are, on St.
Thomas’s own account, anticipations.
zy
zyxwvu
zyxw
zy
z
IV
Under the ever-present influence of empiricist images of knowing, we
tend to think of the vision of God as if it were a gazing at a scene, a
much more beautiful and satisfying scene than one we’ve ever seen”.
And under the ever-present influence of empiricist models of
experience, we tend to think of the satisfying of desires as the bringing
about of effects in a subject which is passive but for the excitement of
its own sensations under the influence of the cause.
The critique of the empiricist model of experience is accomplished
in ethics. ‘Ethics’ is the name given by Aristotle and St. Thomas to a
pursuit which I have mentioned more than once in this lecture. In and
by this pursuit one comes to understand human nature more
adequately. How? By understanding the goods which are the objects of
human acts, acts which one comes to understand as realizing human
capacities, capacities which one comes to understand as constituting
that nature”. So one rejects the option of living as a contented cow
(Aristotle’s example) or as a brain plugged into an experience machine
(Grisez’s and then Nozick’s more vivid and adequate thoughtexperiment), and one rejects it precisely as unworthy, an inadequate
and unsatisfactory (even though in itself wholly ‘satisfying’) form of life
for oneself or any person’’.
Similarly, the empiricist model of the visio Dei is overcome by a
reflection on practical understanding. To see God in His essence would
be to see Him not merely as cause but also as Person(s), and not merely
as Person(s) but as personally causing all the goods (including persons)
of the universe. And, knowing our own action practically, we know
that personal causing is not like the billiard-ball-colliding push-pull
causing of empiricism. In personal causing, the achieved effect which
comes last is the good envisaged from the first in the intelligent process
of practical understanding and reasoning, choosing and acting. To see
God would be to really understand, and for the first time, the point (the
good) of all created goods, including created persons and the love-offriendship between them. To love oneself and others like one, in full
measure, would thereby become not less possible, not less appropriate,
but more possible and more appropriate than in this life.
And we can go further. Speculative questioning and understanding
in contemplation disclose to us, already in this life, the existence of a
God who is not Aristotle’s purely contemplative noesis
446
zyxwvu
zy
noeseos but rather the domintis suorum actuum and free creator and
activator and governor of the universe. To attain the beatitude of a
perfected human knowledge and love of God would be to attain the
fullness of the image of GodS3.So the imaging of God in this life (a life
in which a very imperfect but real knowledge and love of God is
possible) would be an imitation not of the Aristotelian divine
contemplative, but of the fully practical (as well as contemplative)
intelligence and will of the true God, creator of irreducibly many forms
of good.
One understands that truth is a good, and one’s intelligence leads
one on by questions that call for (and thus dimly envisage) answers but
cannot be answered, and thus by the incomparably desirable prospect
of a fuller truth that is no mirage but remains simply unattainable in
this human life. To be aware of these questions, and of the unattained
good of answering them, is to have a notion of transcendence and our
openness to it54.But intelligence also grasps that friendship, or practical
reasonableness, or human life itself, are goods, and this understanding
lures us on to the intelligent realisation of those goods as best we can, as
well as to the incomparably desirable prospect and ambition of ever yet
more fully understanding their goodness and its source and of ever
more adequately realising and enjoying them.
Empiricism tempts us to think of our inclinations as blind i!rges,
pushing or pulling us from within. But, for us, things are in fact desired
because they seem desirable, i.e. because they appear and appeal to our
intelligence as good5’. The grasp of basic goods, and the intelligent
assessment of their implications, and the immediate direction of their
realisation in choice and execution, are all the work of one’s single
intelligence. If one’s intelligence opens one towards transcendence, it
does so not just by the pursuit of speculative truth but also and equally
by the pursuit of the truth of human goods and human actions (the
truth which Thomas relentlessly calls practical). If our hearts are
restless, it is not only for speculative truth but also for the practical
truth that consists in (satisfaction of intelligent desire for) the
realization, the making actual, of goods such as life, play, friendship....
It cannot be doubted that neither the full understanding of those goods
nor their sufficiently satisfactory realization is possible otherwise than
by a participation in God’s creative understanding and personal life far
fuller than any participation we can envisage or accomplish.
z
zy
V
A simplistic catechesis taught (or was fragmentarily remembered as
teaching) that man has one end, the vision of God, and treated that
vision simply as the reward for forms of virtue which have no
447
zyx
zyxwv
zyxwv
apparent tendency to fit a person for a life of exclusive ont temp la ti on'^.
Such a presentation has never been adequate to Christian faith.
That faith is conveyed more amply by Vatican 11, when (following the
scriptures and the liturgy) it identifies the ultimate end of mankind, not
simply as a vision of truth, nor even simply as a participation in holiness
and grace, but as a participation by a plurality of persons in a plurality
of goods, the goods of human dignity, brotherhood and freedom and
thus all the good fruits of our nature and our choices: ‘a kingdom of
truth and life, holiness and grace, justice, love and peace’”.
Thus the relationship between moral virtue in this life and the
integral human fulfilment of beatitude is affirmed to be, not of
instrumental means to extrinsic end, nor mere merit to sheer extrinsic
reward, but rather a striking form of participation: the good works and
virtues go to building up here and now the supernatural kingdom. And
‘afterwards’, in the fulfilled kingdom, those good works and virtues
‘will be found again’ as intrinsic to its heavenly life and constitution5*.
This underlines that the reward so insistently proposed by Scripture is
intrinsically connected to the rightful pursuit of the goods: it is not like
the prospect of a beach holiday rewarding long hours of work, but
more like (mutatis multis murandis) an orchestra’s prospect of
performing, really satisfactorily, a symphony after years of selfdiscipline, study, works9.
VI
zyx
In the theory of practical reason advanced by Grisez and Boyle and
myself and others, a number of goods are identified as basic. Against
this, it has been objected that ‘the pluralism implied in ... eight basic
goods ... is diametrically opposed to St. Thomas’s teaching that there is
but one ultimate good for all humans’60. But, as we have seen, one
should be slow to speak of diametrical opposition to a theory which is
as complex as Aquinas’s on the one ultimate good for all human
persons. St. Thomas can best be understood as holding to a conclusion
often obscured in his discourse. This conclusion, defended by Grisez
and myself as valid apart from the authority of St. Thomas, is: Any
state which could count as the ‘one ultimate good for all humans’ must
involve a plurality of goods, such is the irreducible complexity of
integral human fulfilment.
Philosophical argument alone cannot conclude to the faith and
hope re-expressed by the Council. But consider a philosophically
elaborated treatment: (i) of the basic aspects of human flourishing, the
basic human goods; (ii) of practical reasonableness as the architectonic
good which, transparent for the master ideal and
448
principle of integral fulfilment, provides the standards for good
realization of those basic human goods; (iii) of human self-constitution
by free choices which last indefinitely unless repented and which thus
might conceivably go, intrinsically, to fit or unfit a person for full and
eternal participation in the not merely contemplative life of God in the
not merely speculative-truth-centred Kingdom; and (iv) of the
possibiIity that practical reasonableness has a point beyond itself as a
participation in God’s free play, the play of creating and bringing-tofulfilment, a fulfilment of Creation which would include the actual
realization of integral human fulfilment. Can it reasonably be said, as
some claim6’, that all this amounts to ‘a conscious rejection of the
finality of man’s nature’? To me it seems rather to be, from beginning
to end, precisely an exploration and explication of that human finality
(if you like, that metaphysical finality), in its irreducible complexity.
zy
zy
*
zyxwvu
zyxw
zyxwvuts
zyxwv
zyxwv
zyxwvutsr
A similar version of this Aquinas Lecture appears in the Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association (The Catholic University of
America, Washington, D.C. 20064).
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
in Efh. I, lect. 2, (ed. Spiaui) n. 31; see also VI, lect. 8, n. 1233, with note 3 below.
See Gauthier and Jolif, L’Ethique d Nicomuque (Louvain and Paris, 2nd. ed:
1970), vol. 11, pp. 1-2; St. Thomas, in Eth., I, lect. 1, nn. 2, 3, 7.
For Aristotle, see Eth. Nic. I, 3: 1095a5-6; 11, 2: 1103b 27-9; VI, 8: 1141b23;
and the arguments of Teichmuller amply summarised and defended in T. Ando,
ArLsfofle’s Theory of Pructicul Cognifion (3rd. ed., Martinhus Nijhoff, The
Hague: 1971). pp. 121,168-74. For St. Thomas, see in Pol., proem., (ed. Spiazzi)
nn. 5-8; in Efh. 11, lect. 2, 11.256; lect. 9, n. 351; in Lib. Boef. de Trin., q. 5 , a.lc
& ad 4. It is clear that Aquinas has no interest in drawing a significant distinction
between ‘moral philosophy’ and ‘prudentiu’;he will introduce the treatise on moral
philosophy with the words ‘sapientis est ordinare’ (in Eth. I, lect. 1, n. I), and the
supienfiu in question, as the development of the whole commentary makes clear, is
that supientia in rebus humanis which is prudentia and ‘pertains solely to practical
reason’ (S.T. 1 1 4 , q. 47, a.2).
See Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (Georgetown U.P., Washington, DC;
Clarendon Press, Oxford: 1983), ch. I.
Nic. Efh. I, 2:1094a18-22, re-arranging the sentence-order.
Nic. Eih. I, 7:1097b2.
For this interpretation of the term ‘the others’, see St. Thomas, in Eth. I, lect. 2, n.
19. The recognition that basic goods can be desired and valued both for their own
sake and as components in a completely final good (eudaimoniu) is reached by
Plato in his critique of Socrates: see Irwin, Pluto’s Moral Theory (O.U.P.: 1977),
p. 167.
It goes without saying that ‘desires’, throughout, is to be taken in the Aristotelian,
not the Humean sense: see Finnis, Fundamenrols of Ethics, p. 44,also pp. 30-7,
44-5; ‘Natural Law and the “1s”-“Ought” Question: an Invitation to Professor
Veatch’ (1981) 26 Catholic Luwyer 266 at pp. 266-70.
Engberg-Pedersen, Aristotle’s 712eory of Moral fnsight (O.U.P.: 1983), p. 31; see
also pp. 12, 17-18, 20, 31-2.
See S.T. 1-11, q. 5 , a . 8 ~ see
; also q. 5 , a.8 ad 2; q. 5 , a.4 ad 2; q. 13, a. 6c;I, q. 19,
a. 3c & a. I&; q.60, a. 2c; 82, a. Ic & a. 2c; q. 94, a. Ic; debfalo, 3, 3c; in Efh. 111,
lect. 2. n. 403.
S.T. I h , 5 , 3c, C,quoting Nic. Eth. I, 7: 1097b8.
449
12
13
14
I5
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
zyxwvuts
zyxwvutsr
zyxwvut
zyxwvut
zyxwvutsrqp
zyxwvut
zyxwvut
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
3s
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
S.T. 1-11. 5 , 3c; also in Eth. nn. 129, 202, 2103, 2136, 21 10.
S.T.l-II,q.3,a.2ad4;a.5canda.6c;q.5,a.3ad2;a.5~.
1-11, 5 , 5c.
11-11. 47, 6c.
Q.D. de Caritate, a. 2c.
S.T. 11-11, 47, 6c.
11-11, q. 47, a.6 ad I & ad 3; 1-11, q. 58, a. 4c; 1, q. 79, a. 1%.
S.T. 1-11. q. 94, aa. 2, 4c;a. 3c = q. 63, a. Ic = 11-11, q. 47, a. 6c = 1-11. q. 58, a.
4c; de Malo, 3, 12 ad 13.
S.T. 1-11, q. 10, a. 1; q. 9, a. 1; q. 18, a. 7c; q. 94, a. 2c.
1-11, q. 8, a. 2c & a d 1; q. 9, a. 1; q. 19, a. Ic & ad 3.
1-11. q. 94, a. 2c (the main list); 11-11, q. 64,a. 5 ad 3; a. 6 ad 2; 111, q. 68,a. I 1 ad 3.
1-11, 58, SC.
1-11, 57, Ic.
1-11, 66, 3c. See also Joseph Buckley, Man’s Last End (Herder, St. Louis 81
London: 1949). pp. 208-10.
See Nic. Eth. 1, 7: 1097b17-19.
Notice that there is no reason at all to suppose that this as yet indeterminate
‘aspect’ of the realization of basic goods is instantiated by only one ‘appropriate
way’ of so realizing them; there may be many such ways that have in some
measure the relevant intelligibility and worth, and there is no reason to suppose
that the measure must be capable of commensuration and measurement. See
Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford U.P.: 1980). ch. 5 .
in Lib. Boet. de Trin. q. 6, a. 4 ad 3.
S.T. 1-11, 3, SC.
St. Thomas will appeal (11-11, 182, lc) to the seven reasons set forth by Aristotle
in Nic. Eth. X , 7: 1177all-bI3. The weakness of these reasons, and their
incompatibility with so much of the Ethics, is well exposed by Jon Moline,
‘Contemplation and the Human Good’ (1983) 17 Nous 37 at 40-5 (though
Moline’s own thesis about Aristotle’s ironical intent fails to convince).
S.T. 1-11. q. 66, a. 4 ad 1; q. 3, a. 6c; q. 57, a . 1 ad 2.
sola visio Dei; cf also ‘in solo Deo beatitudo hominis consistit’: 1-11, q. 2, a. 8c;
q. 3, a. 8c.
11-11, 26, 13 ad 3. Beatitude, the fully satisfactory, must surely include such a
vision, since without it our concern to understand would be unsatisfied. Indeed,
that vision could be said to be central to integral human fulfilment, because the
goodness that would be revealed in it must be such that all other goods will then be
understood (‘seen’) and appreciated as having their goodness as participations
(likenesses and effects) of that primary and original goodness. See further section IV.
11-11, 27, 8c: ‘dilectio Dei accip(i)tur secundum quod solus diligitur’.
‘propter unitatem humanae naturae’: see in Eth. I, lect. 9, n. 106.
St. Thomas, in I Cor., c. 15, lect. 2.
S. T. I, q. 26, a. 2 ad 2; q. 87, a. 3c; etc; see Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics. pp.
21-2, 25.
Supra n. 19; for the order of thought in St. Thomas on this key issue, read S.T.
1-11, q. 94, a. 2c with I, q. 80, a. 1 ad 1; q. 82, a. 4c and 1-11, q. 10, a. Ic.
1-11, q. 26, a. 4; 11-11, q. 25, a . 2c.
1-11, 94, 2.
1-11, 4, 8c and ad 3.
1-11, q. 4, a. 6c; also a. 5c.
11-11, 26, 13. This concession appears in other ways, too. In the state of perfect
beatitude, says Aquinas, the order of priorities in love, the ordo caritatis, will
remain the same ranked order as it is in this life. And in that state of beatitude,
all “the proper grounds of love” (honestae causae dilectionis) will remain as in
this life: a. 13c. But what is a causa dilectionis, a ground of love? It is a good,
which affords a ratio diligendi: 11-11, 26, 2 ad 1. So yet again we find Aquinas
formally recagnising the multiplicity of goods involved in beatitude, and the
zyxwvut
zyxwvutsrqpon
zyxwvu
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
zyxwv
51
52
53
54
zyxw
zy
zy
zyxwvutsr
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
necessity of loving and respecting each of those goods in due measure.
1-11, q. 67; 11-11, q. 26, a. 13; q. 52, a. 3; de Virt. Card. 4; de Car. a. 2c.
See also Finnis, Fundamentals of Efhiss, pp. 70-4, 120-1, 151-2.
For the contrast between ‘goal’, as attainable objective, and ‘ideal’, see Finnis,
Natural Law and Natural Rights, p. 61 and pp. 75-6. On ‘integral human
fulfilment’ as the first principle of morality, see n. 45 above.
S.T., 1-11, q. 2, aa. 7c, 8c; I, q. 65, a. 2; 1-11, q. 1, a. 8.
de Car., a. 2c.
S.T. 11-11, 25, 1.
Neo-Platonism such as Augustine’s can be regarded as employing this
inadequate model of knowing ‘in its sublimest form’: Bernard Lonergan, Insighf
(Longmans, London: 1958) p. 412.
See notes 1, 3, and 37 above. S i x conclusions about the relative epistemological
priority of ethics in our knowledge of human nature are reached by close students of St.
Thomas such as The0 G. Belmans 0.Praem., Le sem objectv de I’agir humain
(Libreria Editrice Vaticana: 1980). pp. 142-3,428, J. de Finance SJ, ‘Sur la notion de
loi naturelle’ (1969) 22 Lkxtor Comrnunk 201 at u)9-210. For an important and
neglected treatment of the way in which sciences can be interdependent without any
vicious Circle-preCiSely because each science (even one subalternated to another) can
call upon principles which are per se nota and thus not derived from the other sciencesee St. Thomas, in Lib. Boer. de Trin., q. 5, a. I ad 9.
Eud. Eth. I, 5: 1216a; Grisez and Shaw, Beyond the New Mora/ify(U. Notre Dame
P.: 1974), p. 26; Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: 1974), pp. 42-5;
Finnis, Fundamentak of Ethics, pp. 37-42,46,48, 89.
S.T. I, 93,4.
Here is St. Thomas principal argument for his famous assertion that every intelligent
being ‘naturally desires the vision of the divine substance’: Summa contra Genfiles
111, 57.
See note 8 above; Fundamentals of Ethics, ch. 2.
A deficient style of homily went further, reducing Christian moral life to a search for
‘happiness’. Ethics books could be found to follow suit. For example, Vernon
Bourke’s Ethics began: ‘(The) basic and natural urge for happiness is deep-rooted in
the being of every man. ... Each man’s moral problem ... is to select and do the kind
of actions which are conducive to true happiness.... Ethics may be defined as the
systematic study of human actions from the point of view of their rightness and
wrongness as means for the achievement of ultimate happiness.. .. For the present, we
can take right action to be that which should be done ... in order to achieve
happiness’ (1966 ed., pp. 3, 4). And happiness was located in an ‘intellectual
contemplation of the perfect good’ (ibid., p. vi). A more adequate exposition of
Christian faith sets aside t h k emaciated conceptionsof the moral life. The search for
one’s own happiness is displaced as the moral norm;in its place we find, in the words
of Vatican 11: ‘the norm of human activity is this: that in accord with the divine mind
(comiliurn)and will, human activity should harmonize with the genuine good of the
human race, and allow men as individuals and members of society to pursue and
fulfil their integral vocation’: Gaudium et S p , 35.
Gaudium et s p , 39.
Id.
cf. Eric D’Arcy, ‘The Withering-Away of Disbelief‘ (1983 18 Atheism and dialogue
(Secretariat for Non-Believers, Vatican) 158 at p. 163.
Vernon Bourke, ‘Justice as Equitable Reciprocity: Aquinas Updated’ (1982) 27 Am.
J. JurFFp. 17 at 25.
Ibid., at p. 24. Bourke added: ‘Finnis does not tie in this list of proximate human
goods with any consideration of an ultimate good’. But see Nafuralhw andNatural
Rights. pp. 49, 405--10.
zyxwvuts
zyxwvutsrq
451