This art icle was downloaded by: [ Murzban Jal]
On: 30 April 2012, At : 02: 16
Publisher: Rout ledge
I nform a Lt d Regist ered in England and Wales Regist ered Num ber: 1072954 Regist ered
office: Mort im er House, 37- 41 Mort im er St reet , London W1T 3JH, UK
Critique: Journal of Socialist Theory
Publicat ion det ails, including inst ruct ions for aut hors and
subscript ion informat ion:
ht t p:/ / www.t andfonline.com/ loi/ rcso20
Reflections on Violence
Murzban Jal
Available online: 20 Apr 2012
To cite this article: Murzban Jal (2012): Reflect ions on Violence, Crit ique: Journal of Socialist
Theory, 40:2, 235-259
To link to this article: ht t p:/ / dx.doi.org/ 10.1080/ 00111619.2012.664729
PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTI CLE
Full t erm s and condit ions of use: ht t p: / / www.t andfonline.com / page/ t erm s- andcondit ions
This art icle m ay be used for research, t eaching, and privat e st udy purposes. Any
subst ant ial or syst em at ic reproduct ion, redist ribut ion, reselling, loan, sub- licensing,
syst em at ic supply, or dist ribut ion in any form t o anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warrant y express or im plied or m ake any represent at ion
t hat t he cont ent s will be com plet e or accurat e or up t o dat e. The accuracy of any
inst ruct ions, form ulae, and drug doses should be independent ly verified wit h prim ary
sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, act ions, claim s, proceedings,
dem and, or cost s or dam ages what soever or howsoever caused arising direct ly or
indirect ly in connect ion wit h or arising out of t he use of t his m at erial.
Critique
Vol. 40, No. 2, May 2012, pp. 235259
Reflections on Violence
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Murzban Jal
This essay is on Marxist theory of violence, keeping in mind Marx’s idea of Gewalt that
he first drew in his 18431844 critique of Hegel. Gewalt, an almost untranslatable term,
is translated as force, sometimes also as violence. But Marx’s Gewalt is immediately
related to humanity in ferment, which is in the grips of revolutionary theory. Gewalt
becomes an ethical idea, a revolutionary categorical imperative. Later Marx in Capital
brings in again the idea of Gewalt, this time as the midwife of revolutions. We are taking
these two readings of Gewalt and attempting to understand whether Gewalt as
revolutionary violence has meaning in the contemporary era of the imperialist Empire, or
whether the Stalinist and imperialist counter-revolutions devour this revolutionary
repertoire. In the background of this problem we are also reflecting on Marx’s idea of the
human essence as also psychoanalytic deliberations on these themes, deliberations carried
out in the epochs of Lenin’s reading of imperialism and Negri’s understanding of the New
Imperial World Order: the (dis)order of Empire-ism where the warfare economy has
monopolized politics and henceforth rendered unnecessary the process of critical and
revolutionary thinking.
Keywords: Violence; Empire-ism; Just War; Alienation; Lenin; Psychoanalysis
War is not only a continuation of politics. It is the epitome of politics. (V.I. Lenin,
‘Report to the 7th All Russian Congress of Soviets, December 5, 1919’)
If we are to use force, it is because we are America. We are the indispensible nation.
(Madeline Albright, Today, NBC interview with Matt Lauer, 19 February 1998)
Politics itself is increasingly becoming war conducted by other means. (Michael
Hardt and Antonio Negri, Multitude)
Violence as Technological Reason
Reflections on violence take us back, not only from the contemporary age of the global
state of perpetual war to Auschwitz and the gas chambers, nor merely to the pickaxe
that smashed Trotsky’s skull, or to the Stalinist massacre of the Bolsheviks. One goes
further back to colonialism and the primitive accumulation of capital where Western
Europe was able to stamp its footprints all over the world. Even these antecedents have
ISSN 0301-7605 (print)/ISSN 1748-8605 (online) # 2012 Critique
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00111619.2012.664729
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
236
M. Jal
a prehistory that itself is quite long. Just as European fascism has a history that
could be located both in the dictatorship of finance capital and in what Wilhelm Reich
called the ‘orgone’ that we transcribe after the young Marx as the estranged human
condition,1 so too the new policeman turned emperor, Uncle Sam, has a history that
cannot be located merely to William Casey and Robert Gates, nor simply to the Platt
Amendment of 1901, to the colonial policy of John Quincy Adams, or to George
Washington and Franklin Pierce. Instead one will understand the histories of violence
unleashed by Auschwitz and Uncle Sam in a different and deeper context.
A certain sense of philosophical reflection necessitates going back to the origins of
the problem. In this sense reflections on violence necessitate reflection on four
simultaneous themes: (1) the questions of the genesis of class societies with the
breakdown of primitive communist societies and the emergence of the state as the
organ of coercion; (2) the dominance of capitalism, imperialism and the warfare
economy over our contemporary life-worlds;2 (3) the classical philosophical
question: ‘What is humanity?’, added with a very Marxist question, ‘How is free
humanity possible?’; and (4) the very important political question, ‘Is revolutionary
violence possible when one is talking of communism as being classless, stateless and
nationless realized as the ‘union (Verein) of free individuals’?3 Keeping these
questions in mind, one further asks: ‘Would these free individuals be violent
individuals and the union a violent union?’ Or, ‘Is revolutionary violence inexorably
caught in a bourgeois trap where the liberator would inevitably imitate the
oppressor?’ It is with these intertwined themes that reflections on violence can
proceed.
There are three basic structures in this essay: the first on violence, and wars as a
manifestation of violence; the second on the historical conjuncture of class struggles,
the nature of transition to socialism, universal suffrage, mass action and the need for
armed struggle against imperialism; and the third on Marx’s critique of alienated
humanity. Let us see the first part: violence, so the classical socialist texts of the 20th
century went, is of two types*the bourgeois predatory type of imperialist violence
where, for the sake of gold, imperialism kills and maims millions of people and brings
in devastation, starvation and death; and the proletarian liberating type that brings
peace, bread and freedom, and ‘uses gold for the purpose of building public lavatories
in the streets’.4
1
The term ‘cell-form’ we have taken from Marx’s Capital, Vol. I, transl. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling
(Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1983), p. 19, whilst the estranged human essence appears in his early works, most
notable the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. In order to understand the orgone, see Charles Kelly,
‘What is Orgone Energy?’ in The Creative Process, Vol. II, Nos 23 (September 1962). However it is important to
note that, whilst we are using this Reichean term, we do not subscribe to Reich’s almost metaphysical inversion
of his early research, especially his pioneering work on fascism.
2
In philosophical terms, this dominance of capitalism implies studying the etiology of the alienated human
essence and the dominance of the reality principle of capital accumulation over the pleasure principle of labor,
love and life.
3
Marx, op. cit., p. 83.
4
V.I. Lenin, ‘Importance of Gold Now & After Complete Victory of Socialism’ in Lenin. Selected Works
(Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1977), p. 649.
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
237
To understand the various Marxists on the use of revolutionary violence, one needs
to understand that there are no smooth curves, but zigzags, contradictions and breaks
in the theories of violence. One also needs to understand the dialectics of Aufhebung
(an uprising of preservation and abolishment) and Auflösung (dissolution) of the
state, and thus the abolishing and dissolution of the state as an instrument of
violence, and the consequent transfer of power (Gewalt) to the Soviets and the
proletarian communes. The abolishing of the state is intrinsically tied down to the
immediate abolishing of commodity production and the money economy, which
directly involves the abolishing of the imperialist cartels and the Military Industrial
Complex as the raison d’être for imperialist wars. Thus when Lenin talked of ‘violent
revolution’ and claimed that Engels wrote a ‘panegyric on violent revolution’,5 the
dialectic of abolishing and dissolution of the state, commodity production and classes
governed his philosophy, where the abolishing and dissolution of the state was
translated into the dictum: ‘convert the imperialist war into a civil war’.6
Since the abolishing of the state and commodity production is the practical reason
for the Marxist theory of violence, it must be kept in mind that the post-Lenin
Bolsheviks (from Trotsky to Bukharin, Kamenev, Zinoviev, et al.) became trapped in
the bourgeois cycle of violence and counter-violence, primarily because commodity
production and the state (the cause sui of violence) were reinforced as the essential
aspects of socialist society. It is this feature that is the main cause of the Stalinist
counter-revolution, the restoration of capitalism in Soviet Union in 1928, the return
of the Oriental Despot in the USSR and the collapse of Marxist critique into
bourgeois theory of violence. Not only was Preobrazhensky wrong about his theory
of ‘primitive socialist accumulation’, and not only were Stalin and Mao outrageously
incorrect in keeping commodity production and value as the essentials of socialist
economy,7 but so too was Trotsky wrong in talking of the ‘gradual dying away’ of
state and money.8 It is in this materialist perspective that we shall be able to reflect on
violence. To reflect on violence, one needs to reflect on the political economy of
violence, and as we shall see in the course of this essay, to reflect on the etiology of
alienation.
Although post-Lenin Marxists claimed to predicate their theories of violence on
this materialism of commodity production, class struggle and the state, in the last
resort they would forget the dialectics and historicity of commodity production and
the state, and thus in the last resort be determined by the old theories of war*from
Sun Tzu’s The Art of War to Clausewitz’s On War. Since Marxist critique of political
economy was confused with bourgeois economics, and since one forgot the
5
V.I. Lenin, ‘State and Revolution’ in Lenin. Selected Works, op. cit., pp. 275277.
V.I. Lenin, Socialism and War (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1977), p. 23.
7
J.V. Stalin, ‘Problems of Socialism in the USSR’ in J.V. Stalin Selected Writings, Vol. II (Calcutta: National
Book Trust, 1976), p. 301; Mao Tse Tung, A Critique of Soviet Economics (London: Monthly Review Press,
1977), p. 144.
8
Leon Trotsky, The Revolution Betrayed. What is the Soviet Union and Where is it Going? (Delhi: Aakar
Books, 2006), p. 78.
6
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
238
M. Jal
dialectical materialist dictum*money economy determines (bestimmte) war*one
not only made violence a free-floating signifier, but one also confused the bourgeois
and Marxist theories of violence. Mao would be, in a certain sense both the
culmination of these pre-Marxist theories of violence and war and the author of the
left-messianic theory and practice of violence. Consider his most bourgeois and
almost Clausewitzean understanding: ‘Military action is a method used to attain a
political goal’.9 One will see in the course of this essay how the fetishism of war and
violence is deeply rooted in this type of discourse, a discourse that would not merely
give way to the Maoist school of protracted war, but also appropriate the George
Sorel school of violence (realized best in the Shining Path movement and the
contemporary Indian Maoist movement that celebrates the ‘annihilation of class
enemies’). It must be noted that the metaphysics of violence that Sorel theorized gave
way to the right-wing school of Italian fascism, which would then be taken over by
messianic Islamism of the Hezbollah type.10 Since Maoism talks of ‘liberation’, but
does not critique commodity production and the state, one will also see how there is
more of Sun Tzu in Maoism and thus more of the discourses of Oriental Despotism
and the ‘Moral Law (which) causes the people to be in complete accord with their
ruler, so that they will follow him regardless of their lives, undismayed by any
danger’,11 than Marx’s philosophy of human liberation. As Mao’s politics-incommand replaces Marx’s union of free individuals, and since the Stalinist and
Maoist state replaces the free activity of the multitude, one must note that, not only
are the Stalin and Mao schools wrong, but they are essentially counter-revolutionary.
If for Mao there was the fetishism of messianic wars deeply etched in his theory
and practice, for the Soviet school there was the fetishism of class reductionism. It
seemed as if the Soviet bourgeoisie had never read Lenin’s critique of ‘economism’.
Yet, it must be noted that there is a difference in these two fetishes: the Maoist fetish
was a movement for a united China independent of both Japanese occupation and
the rule of the Chinese comprador, whilst the Soviet fetish of violence was built on
the fear of revolutionary Marxism, the decomposition of revolutionary Bolshevism
and the triumph of the Stalinist counter-revolution. What one finds in the Chinese
and the Soviet decomposed schools was a Faustian dilemma that could never be
resolved. For just as two souls dwelt in Faust’s breast and just as two hostile classes
exist in contemporary society, so too we were told by the Soviet and Chinese
apparatchiks that two types of violence inexorably exist in the breast of capitalism.
The militarization of socialism and consequently the bourgeoisiefication of socialism
would be the necessary consequence.
Since violence was articulated as a mimicking superstructure of a given historical
class, and since classes are the fundamental reality of capitalism, violence was also
noted as being an inevitable part of Marxist discourse. Violence was henceforth
9
Mao Tse Tung, On War (Dehradun: Natraj Publications, 2008), p. 79.
It must be noted that, for Shiite Islam (especially for the Hezbollah), the concept of the oppressed
(Mostazafin) in messianic war with the oppressor (Moztakberin) is fundamental.
11
Sun Tzu, The Art of War, ed. James Clavell (New York: Delta, 1983), p. 9.
10
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
239
articulated merely as a type of technique, or technological reason wielded by a
particular class, and if violence was to be understood as a technique or as
technological reason, then reflections on violence as technological reason implied
that reason as violence was basically nonhuman reason and nonrational reason, if not
antihumanist and irrational altogether.
In this case one has to stress that rigorous Marxism has to theorize in the terrains
of Classical German Philosophy that demarcates the zones of technological reason*
which exists in the site of understanding (Verstand)*and humanist reason*which
exists in the site of reason (Vernunft) itself. One is thus claiming that there is a site
that lies beyond violence itself*the site of Vernunft*a site that seems to be
concealed despite the works of Marx, Lenin, Freud, Reich, Erich Fromm and Raya
Dunayevskaya. After all, as Habermas says, technological reason is both ideological
and domineering, for it does not seek to know, but seeks to control both nature and
humanity.12 In this case one has to seek a type of reason that goes beyond
technological reason. It seems that the type of post-technological reason was found,
but because of the lack in the understanding of Hegelian dialectic, this was
submerged in a Faustian dilemma. This led to a certain type of tragedy that haunts
the left movement even today.
So in addition to these two types of rationale of violence (the real bourgeois one
and the mythical messianic one), a third type of reason emerged with the
emergence of a nonviolent action type, reminiscent however not of revolutionary
Marxism, but of pacifism and the radical utopians. The pacifist forgot Lenin’s
dictum: ‘wars are inevitable as long as class rule exists’.13 Here the two souls in
oblivion to class society take an altogether different course, recalling the celebrated
Faustian dilemma:
Two souls, alas, are housed within my breast,
And each will wrestle for the mastery there.
The one has passion’s craving crude for love,
And hugs a world where sweet the senses rage;
The other longs for pastures fair above,
Leaving the murk for lofty heritage.14
We are thus left with three types of action types: the two types of violent ones
followed by the tragic Gnostic-pacifist one, a type reminiscent not only of Faust but
also of Hamlet, the bourgeois existentialist par excellence and the Modern Prince of
late imperialism in crisis, who not only abjures from reflecting on Gewalt, but falls
down before the state machine contemplating: ‘to be or not to be . . .’. Yet one will not
be dismissive of any one of them, neither the bourgeois one, nor the proletariat one,
nor even the FaustianHamletean one. To these three types one will have to recall the
12
See Jürgen Habermas, ‘Technology and Science as Ideology’ in Towards a Rational Society, transl. Jeremy
Shapiro (London: Heinemann, 1971), p. 82.
13
V.I. Lenin, ‘The Fall of Port Arthur’ in Lenin. Collected Work, Vol. 8 (Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1962), p. 54.
14
Johann Wolfgang Goethe, Faust, Part One, transl. Philip Wayne (London: Penguin Books, 1949), p. 67.
240
M. Jal
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
most important one that Marx theorized in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts
of 1844 as the appropriation of humanity as humanity15 and then christened in the
Theses on Feuerbach as revolutionary praxis of authentic humanist society, or
‘socialized humanity’.16 It must be noted that the classical theorizing on violence in
20th-century Marxism from Trotsky to Mao and Che Guevara seemed somehow to
lack this Marxist dialectic of the philosophy of praxis.17
Our thesis is based on the radical idea of praxis that transcends the reductionist
and a-historical ideas of violence. It also transcends the ideologies of pacifism.
Although pacifism is itself a wide and complex field of operation, it inevitably gets
caught up in the fetishism of capital accumulation and in the last resort serves the
capitalist class. Consider Gandhi, the classical pacifist:
I am working for the co-operation and co-ordination of capital and labor and of
landlords and tenants . . . Class war is foreign to the genius of India which is
capable of evolving a form of communism broad-based on the fundamentals of all
and equal rights of all. The Ramrajajya of my dream ensures the rights alike of
prince and pauper. You may be sure that I shall throw the whole weight of my
influence in preventing class war . . . I know, however, that no member (of the
Parliamentary Board) will talk of expropriation and extinction of private property . . . Our socialism and communism should therefore be based on
non-violence and on the harmonious co-operation of labor and capital and the
landlord and tenant.18
In this essay we shall take five themes in order to reflect on Marx’s idea on
violence: (1) the classical 20th-century Marxist texts on violence derived from
Clausewitz’s theory of war, especially his theory that war is a continuation of
policies by other means and that war is business and commerce carried out with
bloodshed;19 (2) the continuation and reversal of the first proposal where capital
accumulation becomes war carried out with violent means; (3) the pacifist theme of
violence as being the other side (namely the Hamletean side) of violence; (4)
Lenin’s theory of war as the epitome of politics, which has to be differentiated from
15
Marx’s words are ‘the appropriation of the human essence’ (die Aneignung des menschlichen Wesen). See
Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1982), p. 109 and Karl
Marx, ‘Nationalökonomie und Philosophie’ in Karl Marx. Die Frühschrifte (Stuttgart: Alfred Kröner,
1964), p. 264.
16
Karl Marx, ‘Theses on Feuerbach’ in Marx. Engels. Selected Works (Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1975), p. 30.
17
Yet one must note that the first generation of 20th-century revolutionaries did not have access to the
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, which were published only in the mid 1920s by David Ryazanov.
18
M.K. Gandhi, ‘Answers to the Zamindars, 25 July, 1934’ in Radungshu Mukherjee (ed.), The Penguin
Gandhi Reader (New Delhi: Penguin, 1993), pp. 238239.
19
‘War is neither an Art nor a Science in the real signification . . . War belongs not to the province of Arts
and Sciences, but to the province of social life. It is a conflict of great interests which is settled by bloodshed . . .
It would be better, instead of comparing it with Art, to liken it to business competition, which is also a conflict
of human interests and activities; and it is still more like State policy, which again, on its part, may be looked
upon as a kind of business competition on a great scale’. Carl Von Clausewitz, On War, transl. J.J. Graham,
Book I, chap. 3 (London, 1909). Also see his Principles of War, transl. and ed. Hans W. Gatzke (Stackpole
Books, 1942).
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
241
his theory of insurrection, which is to be treated as art;20 and (5) Marx’s
revolutionary humanism that emphasizes that ‘an end which requires unjustifiable
means is no justifiable end’,21 which is in direct contrast to Clausewitz’s justification
of war as ‘an act of violence to compel our opponent to fulfill our will’.22 Drawing
thus the line of demarcation between the sites of violence and wars as commerce
(thus ‘wars as violent commerce’ and ‘violence as war-like commerce’) and
insurrection as art*thus differentiating commerce from aesthetics*one will be able
to understand the nature of violence and whether revolutionary violence is possible
at all in the Marxist repertoire. Keeping these points in mind and then cogitating
over the concerns of the young Marx, it could be said that there could be no
greater critic of violence than Marx himself. Reflections on violence would then
transcend the old socialist idea of differentiating bourgeois violence from the
proletariat one. Instead one could say that, according to Marx’s problematic of
alienation, violence (both violence as business and business as violence, not to forget
nonviolence itself) could be said to emanate from the alienated human condition, a
condition that is perfected by late imperialism in permanent crisis. Violence is the
raison d’être of estranged society and the spectacle of estranged society. However, as
our argument goes, so is nonviolence another spectacle. It is in this context that we
begin the classical readings of violence and question how they need to be put in the
dialectics of suspicion. Consider Lenin:
After expropriating the capitalists and organizing their own socialist production,
the victorious proletariat of that country will arise against the rest of the world*
the capitalist world*attracting to its cause the oppressed classes of other countries,
stirring uprisings in those countries against the capitalists, and the case of need
using even armed force against the exploiting classes and their states. The political
form of a society wherein the proletariat is victorious in overthrowing the
bourgeoisie will be a democratic republic, which will more and more concentrate
the forces of the proletariat of a given nation or nations, in the struggle against
states that have not come over to socialism.23
Two important issues emerge: firstly, Lenin’s reading of insurrection as art that is
differentiated from the business of war and how this proposition would be compatible
with Marx’s philosophy of liberation; and secondly, how this Leninist articulation is
applicable in today’s changed world, from combined and uneven development to
combined and destroyed development, from nation states to post-nation states, and from
imperialism to the imperial-ism of the Empire. Here it must be stated that the alleged
Leninist opposition (just and unjust wars) was a Stalinist invention. The Leninist
opposition is wars vs insurrection, the philistine vs the revolutionary.
20
V.I. Lenin, Marxism and Insurrection (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1977), pp. 354358. One may call
insurrection the realization of humanism and naturalism of the young Marx.
21
Karl Marx, ‘Debates on the Freedom on the Press’, in Marx. Engels. Collected Works, Vol. 1 (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1975), p. 175.
22
Von Clausewitz, On War, op. cit.
23
V. I. Lenin, ‘On the Slogan For a United States of Europe’ in Lenin. Selected Works, op. cit., pp. 155156.
242
M. Jal
Thinking about Gewalt
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
In order to understand the art of insurrection as the realization of humanism, let us
begin with Marx’s philosophical reading of Gewalt. Now the Gewalt that Marx drew
in his A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Introduction
implies a polysemy of meanings: from power, authority and force to violence.24 That
Gewalt in the German also has idealist connotations*almost a biblical reading of the
‘act of God’ that should not be forgotten. Marx’s Gewalt is on the other hand the
exact inversion of the idealizing messianic meaning common to salvation ideologies.
Note the humanist motif in Marx and note also how Gewalt is intrinsic to the
question of humanity as humanity. Note also how Marx talks of weapons (Waffen) in
his philosophical discourse:
Clearly the weapon of critique (die Waffen der Kritik) cannot replace the critique
of weapons (die Kritik der Waffen), and material force (die materielle Gewalt)
must be replaced by material force. But theory also becomes a material force once
it has gripped the masses. Theory is capable of gripping the masses when it
demonstrates ad hominem, and it demonstrates ad hominem as soon as it
becomes radical. To be radical is to grasp things by the root. But for humanity
the root is humanity itself.25
It is from this humanist moment that I propose to read the notion of Gewalt in Marx,
keeping in mind Marx’s second reading of Gewalt: ‘Force (die Gewalt) is the midwife
of every society pregnant with a new one. It itself is an economic power (ökonomische
Potenz)’.26 Now it is well known that this extract has been used in left-wing literature
almost without trying to fathom what Marx was trying to say. The immediate picture
that one draws is that of the socialist baby that is almost refusing to be born (or its
birth is being blocked by the bourgeoisie) and the violent communist midwife trying
to ply the baby from the womb of the aging capitalist mother. It is tempting for
Marxists to dream of enacting the role of this midwife, but did Marx want to become
this violent midwife? Recall the context that Marx is locating the problem*of the
genesis of the industrial capitalist and of primitive accumulation. According to Marx,
modern capitalism (the baby) emerges like the barbarian with ‘brute force’ (brutalster
Gewalt) with ‘the power of the state’ (die Staatsmacht) and with the ‘organized force
of society’ (organisierte Gewalt der Gesellschaft).27 Capitalist Gewalt, so Marx claims,
is the barbarism of the Christian race, seeping in treachery, bribery, massacre and
meanness.28 The theater of this Gewalt is the secret prison.29 We live in the prison
24
See Etienne Balibar, ‘Gewalt’ in Wolfgang Fritz Haug (ed.), Historisch-Kritisches Wörterbuch des Marxismus
(Berlin: Argument, 2001), p. 1271. Also see his Politics and the Other Scene, transl. Christine Jones, James
Swenson and Chris Turner (London: Verso, 2002).
25
Karl Marx, ‘A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right.Introduction’ in Karl Marx.
Early Writings, transl. Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton (New York: Vantage Books, 1975), p. 251.
26
Karl Marx, Capital, op. cit., Vol. I, p. 703.
27
Ibid.
28
Ibid., pp. 703704.
29
Ibid., p. 704.
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
243
house of capitalist violence. How is one to escape from it? Which type of Gewalt will
one have to use?
The response could be both a type of cynicism and economism on the one hand
and the realist type of explanation on the other. Both the cynic and realist will say:
‘You want to be a Marxologist, a type of philologist deciphering meanings behind
words. But how would one deal with the Kolchaks, Denkins, Hitlers and Khomeinis?
Most certainly not with the book of the metaphysics of morality in hand!’ To this
cynical response there is yet an opposite response*this time from the liberal who will
quote Kant: ‘war is bad in that it produces more evil people than it destroys’.30 To
understand both the socialist realist as well as the Kantian response one has to move
from the realm of ‘evil’ to the bourgeois Garden of Eden, where one sees this Kantian
‘evil’ nestled in the delicacies of bourgeoisdom: bourgeois freedom, the rights of man
and abstract humanity.31 Here the primarily ‘evil’ is not so much the destruction of
human rights, but the transfiguration of these rights into the rites of humanity, where
Monsieur Capital does his danse macabre over the body of Madame Earth.32 As good
historical materialists one will have to see this macabre dance, scripted now in the
biblical text of the birth, life, death and resurrection of this very strange and
grotesque Monsieur Capital. According to this biblical reading of the resurrection of
Monsieur Capital, the good Christian philanthropist was crucified, and after going to
the house of his beloved Lord, returned again as the propagandist of the bourgeois
warfare economy.
Since Monsieur Capital has become Prophet Capital accompanied by the holy
warriors of God, gripped by an epidemic of overproduction, we have now become
momentary barbarians governed by a ‘universal war of devastation’ that cries out:
‘there is too much civilization!’33 And why is there surplus civilization governed by
the momentary barbarians? It is because there is ‘too much means of subsistence, too
much industry, too much commerce’.34 We were once humans. Now we are waiting
to be barbarians once again. In order to understand the genealogy of the momentary
barbarians, and also to understand the birth, life, death and resurrection of Monsieur
Capital, one needs to see the inner structure of capital accumulation. Here one also
understands that the bourgeoisie cannot maintain the capitalist system. Instead
violent convulsions are the orders of the day:
The commodities which emerge anew from the sphere of production find the
market still occupied by the old ones, then it becomes overcrowded, a stoppage
occurs, the market is glutted, the commodities decline in value, there is overproduction. Where, therefore, the intermediate stage of circulation acquires
independent existence so that the flow of the stream is not merely slowed down,
where the existence of commodities in the circulation phase appears as storing up,
30
Immanuel Kant, ‘Eternal Peace’ in The Philosophy of Kant. Immanuel Kant’s Moral and Political Writings,
ed. and transl. Carl J. Friedrich (New York: The Modern Library, 1949).
31
Marx, Capital, op. cit., Vol. I, p. 172.
32
Ibid., Vol. III, p. 830.
33
Karl Marx, ‘The Manifesto of the Communist Party’ in Marx. Engels. Selected Works, op. cit., p. 40.
34
Ibid.
244
M. Jal
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
then this is not brought up by a free act on the part of the producer, it is not the
aim or an immanent aspect of production, any more than the flow of blood to the
head leading to apoplexy is an immanent aspect of circulation of the blood. Capital
as commodity capital . . . must not become stationary, it must only constitute a
pause in the movement. Otherwise the reproduction process is interrupted and the
whole mechanism is thrown into confusion.35
In order to understand how Monsieur Capital got into a state of confusion leading to
apoplexy, and how he suddenly got cured; one has to see the metamorphosis of
Monsieur Capital, who as an infant promised to be a good fellow, but after getting
diseased became a fascist and died, only to be reborn as a liberal draped in the stars
and stripes. If we were once momentary barbarians living in Auschwitz, we have now
become eternal savages by converting the entire world into Auschwitz. Kant and the
early liberals have moved on to let Robert Gates and the postmodern mercenaries
script the new scene of history. What do we find in this new site? We find that
violence as business and wars is understood in the site of the general contradictions
of capital described above. Not only is violence important for imperialism*from
Robert Oakley and Nasserudin Babbar (the CIA creators of the Taliban) to Robert
Gates and Cameron (the born again Bushes and Blairs)*but violence as imperialist
wars now forms the essential political economy of global capitalism. The postmodern
mercenary as the bricoleur-technocrat has taken power. If modernity was governed by
universal suffrage with periodic coups, the age of Empire-ism is governed by the
technocrat mercenary as eternal savage. Democracy has given way to these eternal
savages, to the Bushes and Ahmadinejads. In this sense one is compelled to say that
‘there is no such thing as non-violence’.36 Nonviolence is pure fiction, authored not
so much by Gandhi, but by Hamlet. Nonviolence becomes the other half of both
violence and the warfare economy. Here we are faced with a new problem:
We are faced with a global state of war in which violence can erupt anywhere at any
time. And most important from the perspective of sovereignty, there is no secure
means of legitimating the use of violence today and no stable groupings of that
violence into friend and enemy camps . . . Modern sovereignty, we should be clear,
does not put an end to violence and fear but rather puts an end to civil war by
organizing violence and fear into a coherent and stable political order. The
sovereign will be the only legitimate author of violence . . . The current state of war,
which has become continuous police activity that supports the regulative
foundation of administration and political control, similarly demands the
obedience of subjects who are plagued by violence and fear.37
We then come back to our main question: ‘What does Marx’s Gewalt do when the
Pentagon, NATO and the international mercenaries have replaced Kant’s three
Critiques?’ It is here that we ask the following questions: ‘Is there any way of
35
Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, Part III (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1978), p. 282.
Etinne Balibar, Politics and the Other Scene, transl. Christine Jones, James Swenson and Chris Turner
(London: Verso, 2002), p. 145.
37
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire (London: Penguin
Books, 2004), pp. 238239.
36
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
245
delivering mankind from the menace of war?’, and, ‘Why is it that every attempt at its
solution has ended in a lamentable breakdown?’38 Since we shall not be enamoured
by the theories of good wars and bad wars (the earlier just and unjust wars), we will
simply say that ‘a person filled with hate and destructiveness and incapable of loving
is not healthy’.39
Yet this humanist thesis of Marx’s radical ‘practical subversion’ (practischen
Umsturz),40 of the New Sovereign of Global Empire-ism takes a different form that
cannot be predicated on the old logic of ‘revolutionary war’,41 or a ‘bourgeoisprogressive war of national liberation’ where the Kurds fight the Turks, the
Palestinians fight the Zionist occupiers, just as once Persia, China and India were
told to fight Russia, the Japanese and Britain.42 In this sense one is questioning not
only the classical Leninist thesis of revolution in the age of early imperialism. One is
also questioning Gramsci’s theories of the wars of maneuver and position, as also
Mao’s idea of protracted wars. In this understanding of violence and wars in the age
of Empire-ism of late imperialism in permanent crises, one transforms Marx’s idea of
the phantom commodity into the concept of phantom wars.
Just as the commodity negates its material form as use values to posit a hyper-ideal
form of value, so too wars in the age of the Empire of late imperialism negate the
materialspatial forms of classical modernity. Phantom wars are wars fought by
hyper-technologies. Phantom wars are not only bodiless (from the view of Yankee
imperialism). They are primarily mindless. The old (modernist) concept outlined by
Machiavelli and Clausewitz where people rule over technology and not vice versa is
transcended by phantom wars, wars that are not restricted to material geographical
spaces. Like Marx’s value, these new wars are hyper-spatial wars. The problem is not
only historical*namely understanding new material conditions, new subject
positions and consequently new states of conflicts*but also one that has to be
understood within the problematic of Marxist theory that differentiates wars (as
business) from insurrections (which are primarily aesthetical in nature). One cannot
mimic the bourgeois. One cannot state that, just as the bourgeois has its own wars,
the proletariat can have its own.
Instead the New International, the International of the 21st century, denounces all
types of all wars and subscribes to the very ethical and aesthetical question: how to
treat insurrection as art. We thus differentiate wars from insurrection. One cannot
collapse one into the other. Now it is well known that just before the 1917 Bolshevik
Revolution Lenin had posed this question. One needs to treat insurrection as art, just
as one treats Beethoven’s music or Goethe’s poetry as works of art. Just as the works
38
Albert Einstein, ‘To Sigmund Freud, Caputh near Potsdam, July 30, 1932’ in The Sigmund Freud Penguin
Library, Vol. 12, Civilization, Society and Religion, transl. James Strachey (London: Penguin, 1985), p. 345.
39
Erich Fromm, The Crisis of Psychoanalysis (London: Penguin, 1973), p. 40.
40
Karl Marx and Fredrick Engels, The German Ideology (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1976), p. 61.
41
For ‘revolutionary war’ see V.I. Lenin, ‘The Tasks of the Proletariat in the Present Revolution’ in Lenin.
Selected Works, op. cit., p. 29.
42
V.I. Lenin, Socialism and War, op. cit., p. 15.
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
246
M. Jal
of Beethoven and Goethe cannot become works of business, so too insurrection
cannot be reified into a commodity that can be controlled by the global monopoly
capitalists. Yet the reification of insurrection is continually manufactured by Global
Empire-ism, and in the reified shadows of insurrection stands the figure central to
Marx’s politics*the figure of the boheme, the pretender revolutionary that lives with
the proletariat, but always conspires against it. Those familiar with Marx will
recognize the figure of Louis Bonaparte behind this strange character. One will also
note how the original Bonapartes went to let Stalin enter the scene of history, and
how Stalin went to let the Iranian mullahs dance their macabre dance. The boheme is
everywhere. One has to understand this strange character. One also has to understand
that the act of this strange character in early 21st century is actually the ‘revolt of the
mercenaries’43. In this drama Puccini is not there. Neither are Rudolphe or Mimi
present. Instead one will see the boheme marching alongside the Hamas and the
Hezbollah. The boheme preaches redemptive violence, and since violence maintains
Empire-ism*although pretending to fight the Empire*one will have to look
carefully at this scene.
Redemptive Violence and Nonviolence: Both as Swindle
Let us first mention the so-called radical enemies of the Empire, the Hamas,
Hezbollah, the Iranian quixotic mullahs, not to forget other postmodern theologians,
and then let us turn to the young Marx’s reading of the boheme as the professional
conspirator. This postmodern boheme is like the alchemists of the revolution44
of classical modernity. He conjures images of revolutions. He fantasizes that the ‘real’
revolution is the Islamic revolution. Just as Charles Baudelaire once shouted: ‘Long
live revolution!’, ‘Long live destruction!’, ‘Long live penance!’, ‘Long live death!’,45 so
too the postmodern boheme celebrates the theological ‘revolution’ of destruction and
death. Consider Marx’s portrayal of this conspirator:
The chief characteristic of the conspirators’ way of life is their battle with the police,
to whom they have precisely the same relationship as thieves and prostitutes. The
police tolerate the conspiracies, and not just as a necessary evil: they tolerate them
as centers which they can keep under easy observation and where the most violent
revolutionary elements in society meet, as the forges of revolt, which in France has
become a tool of government quite as the police themselves, and finally as a
recruiting place for their own political mouchards. Just as the most serviceable
rogue-catchers, the vidocqs and their cronies, are taken from the class of greater
and lesser rascals, thieves, esrocs (swindlers) and fraudulent bankrupts, and often
revert to their old trade, in precisely the same way the humble political policemen
are recruited from among the professional conspirators. The conspirators are
43
Hardt and Negri, op. cit., p. 48.
Karl Marx, ‘Review of Chenu’s les Conspirateurs’, in Marx. Engels. Collected Works, Vol. 10 (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1978), p. 318.
45
See Walter Benjamin, Charles Baudelairre. A Lyric Poet in the Era of High Capitalism, transl. Harry Zohn
(London: Verso, 1992), p. 14.
44
Critique
247
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
constantly in touch with the police, they come into conflict with them all the time;
they hunt the mouchards, just as the mouchards hunt them. Spying is one of their
main occupations. It is no wonder therefore that the short step from being a
conspirator by trade to being a paid police spy is so frequently made facilitated as it
is by poverty and prison, by threats and promises.46
It is here that we need to ask: what is the relation between violence (even so-called
‘revolutionary violence’) on the one hand (knowing that the police spy as advocate of
so-called ‘revolutionary violence’ is always present at the scene of revolution), and
barbarism and cruelty on the other hand? I am tempted here to recall Horkheimer’s
and Adorno’s Dialectic of Enlightenment that seeks the origins of the metaphysics of
violencebarbarismcruelty in the very structure of class societies. Thus, to overturn
the rather fashionable concept ‘Western Reason’, we need to inject the very scientific
term ‘Class Reason’, and thus to look at violence in this space of Class Reason. We
shall keep this question in mind and proceed to the question of whether redemptive
violence is necessarily realized in the theater of cruelty. We shall pick up this theme
from Kevin Anderson’s Marx at the Margins47 and recall what Marx called the ‘rule of
historical retribution, that its instrument be forged not by the offended, but by the
offender himself ’.48 There are two different themes of revolutionary violence that one
picks up from Anderson’s text:
(1) The anticolonial movement by the Indian masses against British imperialism, a
revolt that was, however, bathed in cruelty. Marx notes the ‘cutting of noses and
breasts . . . [and] the horrid mutilations committed by the sepoys’.49 Whilst
these anticolonial actions horrified the British, European refinement was not
affected by ‘the throwing of red-hot shells on canton dwellings by a secretary of
the Manchester peace society, or the roasting of Arabs pent up in a cave by a
French marshal’.50 So how does one understand the many sides of cruelty? Marx
answers: ‘cruelty, like every other thing, has its fashion, changing according to
time and place’.51
(2) The second part is more focused on the terror unleashed by the oppressed.
Sometimes it appears as a process of destruction ‘without any nucleus of
construction . . . [where] a human head means no more than a cabbage to a
Taiping’.52 Sometimes it is ‘only negative action . . . merely the rage and fury of
46
Karl Marx, ‘Review of Chenu’s les Conspirateur’s’, in Marx. Engels. Collected Works, Vol. 10 (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1978), p. 319.
47
Kevin Anderson, Marx at the Margins. On Nationalism, Ethnicity, and Non-Western societies (Chicago, IL:
The University of Chicago Press, 2010).
48
Karl Marx, ‘The Indian Revolt’ in The First Indian War of Independence (Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1978), p. 79.
49
Ibid., p. 81.
50
Ibid.
51
Ibid.
52
Karl Marx, ‘Chinese Affairs’ in Marx. Engels. Collected Works, op. cit., Vol. 19, pp. 216217; Anderson,
Marx at the Margins, op. cit., p. 37.
248
M. Jal
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
destruction . . . no more significant than cleaving a head of a cabbage or
swallowing a draught of water’.53
Whilst one does note the grotesque in these forms of violence and also notes the
undialectical fashion of violence, one also agrees with Anderson, who says that, whilst
the so-called ‘mystical east’ was involved in revolutionary action (even of the violent
type), the bourgeoisie of the ‘rational west’ was (Hamlet-like) obsessed with the
fetishism of commodities and its magic and necromancy emanating thereon.54 Yet if
this magic and necromancy was noted by Marx in the first volume of Capital as some
sort of psychological disorder, it has now become the ideology-in-dominance with
imperialism actively transforming the politics of class and multitude into the politics
of crowd with Human Rights Watch, the International Republican Institute, National
Democratic Institute, Freedom House, the National Endowment for Democracy
playacting Bonaparte and Stalin, the magician and necromantic artist, not to forget
the mouchard conspirator cum police spy. Look everywhere*to Afghanistan, Iraq,
Palestine, Pakistan, and now West Asia*and one will see this mouchard conspirator
cum police spy, negating the multitude as class struggle and positing the crowd as
nonclass mass, and advocating both redemptive violence as well as nonviolent
conflict resolution despite being financed by the Empire and the warfare economy.
The site for the operation of this conspirator is the crowd, a technique that was
developed by the Nazis, later taken over by the Shiite mullahs in 1979, and now used
with great efficiency by Yankee imperialism. The crowd is almost a sort of
metaphysical entity, as against class which is dialectical. The crowd has no shared
code, no ‘commonness’, no common interest. That is why the ‘crowd or the mob or
the rabble can have social effects*often horrible destructive effects*but cannot act
on their own accord. That is why they are susceptible to external manipulation’.55
So in contrast to this delight in swindle and advocacy of both redemptive violence
and nonviolence*the Empire-ist claiming to be anti-Empire-ist, the conspirator
turned police spy*there is a counter delight, a more authentic one may I say, and
that is the delight in what we know after Hegel’s Science of Logic as the delight in the
Begriff (Notion) where the praxis of Revolutionary Internationalism as the vehicle of
human emancipation is able to free itself from the discourses of capitalism. Let us
briefly look at the logical structure of Hegel’s Logic. According to the Logic there is a
three-tiered structure*Being (Sein), Essence (Wesen) and Notion (Begriff)*where
Being is the basic structure, Essence is the deep structure and Notion is the deep
deep structure. Now what exactly is this Hegelian Notion and how does it help us in
understanding violence in the age of late imperialism? At this juncture one will briefly
53
G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, transl. J.B. Baillee (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1966),
pp. 604605; Anderson, Marx at the Margins, op. cit., p. 37.
54
‘The irony is that ‘‘rationalist’’ Europe had in the 1850s lost its revolutionary drive and was instead swept
up by mysticism, while ‘‘mystical’’ China was engaged not so much in mysticism as in social revolution’.
Anderson, Marx at the Margins, op. cit., pp. 3637.
55
Hardt and Negri, op. cit., p. 100.
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
249
move on to the two reflections on Hegel: the one inspired by Raya Dunayevskaya56
and then taken up by contemporary American Marxist Humanists, especially Kevin
Anderson’s reading of Hegel’s ‘Idea’,57 where the Idea is no longer read in the
Engelsian fashion as the culmination of speculative idealism and world history
itself.58 Instead the ‘Idea’ as the prime mechanism of the Notion grasps reality in root
form where Marx’s statement ‘to be radical is to grasp things by the root, but for
humanity the root is humanity itself ’59 is located in this Hegelian dialectics of world
history. One has to grasp this root*that poses these questions ‘What is humanity?’
and ‘How is communism as the appropriation of humanity possible?’*in order for the
revolution to flow. To grasps things by the root requires knowledge of both the
Hegelian dialectic and humanist anthropology. Once one has grasped this authentic
structure of dialectical and revolutionary humanism, one is able to define the core
historicist and humanist structure of Marxism.
It is here that one is able to clearly demarcate the sites of communism and
capitalism, of insurrection on the one side, and violence and wars on the other
side. The first treats humanity as species being, and the second treats humanity as
sadomasochism. This ‘invitation to intoxication’ (to borrow Adorno’s phrase)60 is
sketched in the site of the sadomasochistic character that has lost its human
essence. What Einstein called ‘the dark places of human will and feeling’61 are
grounded in this very site. One will understand not only bourgeois violence, but
also violence as such in this very site. One also understands Martin Heidegger’s
passion of ‘the complete Europeanization of the world and all mankind’
(vollständige Europäisierung der Erde und des Menschen) in this site of sadomasochism of Bourgeois Reason.
Marxist Strategies: The Weapon of Critique and the Critique of Weapons
A cursory glance at the classics of early European liberal literature shows that even
abstract propositions like the Kantian moral imperative that goes ‘Act only on that
maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a
universal law’,62 whereby the practical imperative should be read as ‘Act in such a
56
Raya Dunayevskaya, Philosophy and Revolution: From Hegel to Sartre and from Marx to Mao (New York:
Colombia University Press, 1989).
57
‘Lenin tends to view the absolute idea chapter as a final grand exposition of Hegel’s revolutionary dialectic
rather than a closure’. See Kevin Anderson, Lenin, Hegel, and Western Marxism. A Critical Study (Urbana, IL:
University of Illinois Press, 1995), p. 87.
58
‘The absolute idea*which is only absolute in so far as he has absolutely nothing to say about it . . .’;
Fredrick Engels, ‘Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy’ in Marx. Engels. Selected Works, op.
cit., p. 589. On Engels’s critique of the alleged Hegelian ‘end of history’, see ibid., p. 592.
59
Karl Marx, ‘A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Introduction’, in Karl Marx.
Early Writings, transl. Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton (New York: Vantage Books, 1975), p. 251.
60
Theodor Adorno, In Search of Wagner (London: New Left Books, 1981), p. 100.
61
Albert Einstein, ‘To Sigmund Freud’, op. cit., p. 345.
62
Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, transl. H.J. Patton (London: Hutchinson
1966), p. 66.
250
M. Jal
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person
of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an ends’,63 are
both more meaningful and humane than the standpoints of both the contemporary
neo-conservatives and Obama’s reinvention of the just war theory. Let us for the
time being bracket the Marxist question of Gewalt and now turn to the question
raised by Kant: how is ‘eternal peace’ possible? The 1795 essay Eternal Peace. A
Philosophical Sketch, like his 1785 text Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten
(Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals), is of crucial importance for the
understanding the modern concept of peace. His moral precept guiding his notion
of practical reason shall also be the guiding force for the implementation of the
peace program. Now with this discovery of the ‘kingdom-of-ends’, the Kantian
notion of moral politics and the peace program follows. Kant claimed to have
discovered six preliminary articles of an eternal peace between states. They are:
(1) No treaty shall be held to be such, which is made with a secret reservation of the
material for a future war.
(2) No state having an independent existence, whether it be small or great, may be
acquired by another state through inheritance, exchange, purchase or gift.
(3) Standing armies shall gradually disappear.
(4) No debts shall be contracted in connection with the foreign affairs of the state.
(5) No state shall interfere by force in the constitution and government of another
state.
(6) No state at war with another shall permit such acts of warfare as must make
mutual confidence impossible in time of future peace, such as the employment
of assassins, of poisoners, the violation of articles of surrender, the instigation of
treason in the state against which it is making war, etc.64
Now there are three definitive articles of eternal peace:
(1) The civil constitution in each state should be republican.
(2) The law of nations (Völkerrecht) should be based upon a federalism of free states.
(3) The Cosmopolitan or World Law shall be limited to conditions of universal
hospitability.65
A number of points come up in the reading of the Kantian text. Firstly the
foundations of the principles of peace are grounded on the metaphysics of morals. Here
the issue of peace is linked to the ideas of moral politics and the idea that people can
unite to form a state in accordance with the principles of ‘freedom’ and ‘equality’, which
itself is based on ‘duty’ and not on ‘prudence’.66 One must note that Kant’s Christian
63
Ibid.
Immanuel Kant, ‘Eternal Peace’ in The Philosophy of Kant. Immanuel Kant’s Moral and Political Writings,
ed. and transl. Carl J. Friedrich (New York: The Modern Library, 1949), pp. 431434.
65
Ibid., pp. 437448.
66
Ibid., pp. 466467.
64
Critique
251
morality interpreted according to the principles of the enlightenment is the dominant
feature of this type of liberal inspired political philosophy. Note this metaphysics of
peace: ‘Seek ye first the kingdom of pure practical reason and of its righteousness, and
your end (the well being of eternal peace) will be added unto you’.67 In contrast is Marx’s
categorical imperative: revolution. The oppressor must be overthrown.
Whilst an immediate contrast of these Kantian precepts with contemporary neoconservative ideology is obvious, there is also a sharp line of demarcation between
Kantian moral philosophy and Marxist revolutionary élan. On the international scene
these three lines of demarcation will be the fault lines drawn between imperialism of
the Empire, liberalism and Marxism. It is from this juncture that we can recall
contemporary reflections on the questions of war and peace:
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
War and peace: in its classical form, the conjunction of war and peace preserves the
disjunctive value implied in the chiasm of these two common notions, whilst
showing the impossibility of producing*both historically and conceptually*a
positive definition of peace. Peace, as disarmament, negatively designates the social
state of affairs characterized by the absence of war. This is Raymond Aron’s peace
by disarmament: ‘it is said that peace reigns when commerce among nations does
not entail the military forms of struggle’ (as Aron says in Peace and War among
Nations, 1962). Being neither essential nor existential, peace does not exclude
struggles and conflicts (it demilitarizes them) from the moment its principle has
become ‘no different than of wars: instances of peace are based on power’ (ibid.) in
a world that the imperative of public security already requires us to consider in its
entirety (totus orbis). With security at its core, this secular form of political
globalization is indissociable from the antinomy: War/Peace, which submits the
‘law of peoples’ (jus gentium) to the universal perspective of power (potestas).
Antinomy: this is the term used by Proudhon to explain that ‘peace demonstrates
and confirms war’, whilst ‘war in turn is a demand of peace’ (as noted by Proudhon
in his 1861 War and Peace, Inquires into the Principle and the Constitution of the Law
of Peoples). Despite the striking actuality of this formula, Proudhon is describing
here what he calls ‘the alternative conditions of the life of the peoples’, who are
subjected to the historical, ‘phenomenological’, alternation states of peace and
states of war in a world in which the national logic of state centralization both
implies and explains the propensity toward military confrontations.68
The first question is how should one be emancipated from the state of perpetual
war*remembering that capitalism is in itself a state of perpetual war? Second, how
does one deal with the Empire now having taken the empirical form of the American
state, which claims absolute, in fact, divine sovereignty and divine right to declare
war on any nation state in order to declare an illusory peace? Negri and Alliez ask
further questions that are relevant to this issue:
(1) Has Peace become the postmodern label for War?
67
68
Ibid., p. 466.
Antonio Negri and Eric Alliez, ‘Peace and War’, Theory, Culture and Society, 20:2 (2003).
252
M. Jal
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
(2) Is it necessary to arm war with the thought of desire of peace ‘so as to lead the
enemy, by victory, to the advantages of peace’ (St Augustine, Letter189 to Count
Bonifacius)?
(3) Can there be a ‘war against war’?
(4) What is the difference between ‘the living labor of the world’ which is ‘the
globalization of living labor’?
(5) How does this transcendental dead labor ‘recompose itself only through war’?69
Now it is this aufgehoben (literally ‘an uprising’) against dead labor and the
appropriation of living labor that shall concern us. We call this uprising ‘the
appropriation of the human essence’ (die Aneignung des menschlichen Wesens).70
Recall Marx: because capital as dead labor governs living labor, humanity (like
Hamlet) is haunted by the ghost of the dead.71 And so it is this difference*the
difference between the ontology of dead labor (recomposed as the ideology of death
that is transmitted through the culture industry and warfare economy) and the
ontology of living labor*that shall concern the investigations on war and peace.
A methodological note on the older left theories of war is necessary. Since the
theory of alienation and the ontology of dead labor were never taken by both
the Second and Third Internationalists, a certain form of cynicism is found in the
orthodox Marxist reflections on both violence and war, based more on Clausewitz
than on Marx’s repertoire. Recall here both Lenin and Trotsky. Just as there can be
nothing called ‘wars in general’, there can be nothing called ‘violence in general’.
There are bourgeois wars, the wars waged by the imperialists to loot weaker nations
and subjugate them, and revolutionary wars; the wars waged by the oppressed
nations to ward out the aggressive imperialists; and the wars of the revolutionary
proletariat against the world bourgeoisie. These are what we get from the 20thcentury understanding of war. Thus one must distinguish just wars from unjust wars,
a difference that is spelt out not in the site of a phantasmagorical superstructure that
advocates Kantian types of moral responses, but in the social structure of class
conflict. This has hitherto the raison d’être of the Marxist theory of wars in the 20th
century. Whether it has been Lenin, Trotsky, Giap, Fanon, Satre, Merleau-Ponty or
Che Guevara, this line of demarcation differentiating just wars from unjust wars runs
through 20th-century revolutionary Marxism, because it is grounded in the
difference between a predatory capitalist economy and the communist proletariat
that actively fights against this predator. But then does the communist proletariat
fight with old weapons of not only the bourgeois, but of all class societies? What does
Marx’s Gewalt do?
That is why we are saying that, besides this political site, there is also the Marxist
philosophical site*the site that Marx had seen as the site of free humanity having the
69
Ibid.
Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, op. cit., p. 109; Marx, ‘Nationalökonomie und
Philosophie’, op. cit., p. 264.
71
Karl Marx, Das Kapital, Erster Band (Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1981), p. 15.
70
Critique
253
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
ability to live without classes and nations, and most certainly able to live without the
Repressive State Apparatus. It is this philosophical site that grasps the difference
between the zones of living and dead labor, the life-world of the sensuous human
essence (das menschliche Wesen), and the death-world of capitalism. This philosophical site is now not only related to the old theory of just and unjust wars, but
related to the transcendence of the theory of just wars. After all, if one ponders with
the aid of Hegelian logic, one will notice that the just wars/unjust wars binary is
related to the old Aristotelian logic and has nothing to do with dialectics. But then
did Lenin, who chided the comrades of the Second International for not having
understood Marx,72 himself regress into the pre-Hegelian framework when reflecting
on violence and wars? Or did his idea of insurrection transcend the just/unjust
theories of war?
Wars as the Metaphysics of the Cruel Geist
Let us take the two statements with which we began our essay: the first one from
Lenin that says that war is the epitome of politics and the other from Negri and Hardt
that claims that politics is war by other means. Relate these to Marx’s theory of
communism as the appropriation of humanity as humanity73 and we further deduce
that, not only is the transcendence (Aufhebung) of wars (both just and unjust)
important, but the transcendence of politics (as we know it at least since the days of
Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Politics) combined with the transcendence of the state
(Aufhebung des States) itself.74 That is why one needs to state that Marx discovers an
entirely different problematic that postulates the world of authentic humanity (to
borrow his phrase), ‘the real, corporeal human being’ with its ‘real objective essential
powers’ (wirklichen gegenständlichen Wesenkräfte)75 at the center of revolutionary
politics. Instead of just wars, we have ‘human essential powers’ (menschlichen
Wesenkrafte)76 of the international multitude on this new scene of revolution. The
theme of violence and wars is now transcended for a theory of human essential powers.
This is why we insist that, when 20th-century Marxism repeatedly claimed that
Marx’s fundamental revolution in the domain of human thinking is the sighting of
the continents of knowledge*dialectical and historical-humanist materialism*it
was getting to the root of the question of Marxist theory itself, as well as getting at
the root of the question of violence without being obsessed with theories of war. It
literally laid bare the black hole of alienation where Gewalt as humanist Intifada was
degraded as the sadomasochism of so-called just wars. It is here that we pose the
very important questions: ‘Are just wars at all possible when we have said that the
72
V.I. Lenin, Philosophical Notebooks (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1980), p. 180.
Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, op. cit., p. 109; Marx, ‘Nationalökonomie und
Philosophie’, op. cit., p. 264.
74
Ibid., pp. 90, 235.
75
Ibid., pp. 135136.
76
Ibid., pp. 96, 111, 136.
73
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
254
M. Jal
humanist discourse of human essential powers (menschlichen Wesenkrafte) replaces
the theory of redemptive violence?’ ‘Does one agree with Mao’s theory that the aim
of war is to eliminate war and that one has to oppose war with war?’77 ‘Does one say
that the banner of mankind’s just war is the banner of mankind’s salvation?’78 Or is
it the case that one needs to cease being obsessed with Clausewitz’s theory of wars
and move to Marx’s critique of human alienation, reification and sadomasochism?
Or are we claiming that Mao was himself caught in the bourgeois phantasmagoria
and thus unable to replace the weapons of capitalism with the critique of
weapons?
Since we insist that violence is a form of alienated act and some sort of a false
consciousness, and since we have said that the doctrine of just and unjust wars is
replaced by Marx’s theory of essential powers (Wesenkräfte)79 and vital powers
(Lebenskräften)80 of the masses, we are likewise saying that at the center of
revolutionary politics lies the doctrine of natural powers (naturlichen Kräften) of
the proletariat. One therefore goes into the young Marx’s site of the dialectics of the
‘estrangement of the human essence’ (Entfremdung des menschlichen Wesens),81 and
‘the transcendence of the estrangement’ (die Aufhebung der Entfremdung)82 in order
to understand the genealogy of violence. After all, revolutionary praxis is possible
only through a critique of alienation. That is why one states that to appropriate this
human essence is the leitmotiv of understanding Gewalt as the realization of
communism as humanism and naturalism. What one gets is the principle of left-wing
solidarity where we have ‘a philosophical basis for socialism . . . the unity of human
with human, which is based on the real differences between people, the concept of the
human species brought down from the heaven of abstraction to the real earth.’83
By keeping the concepts of alienation and reification at the basis of Marxist theory,
one is able to understand how reification as ‘thingification’ (Versachlichung,
Verdinglichung) implies that people have lost their humanity and literally become
monstrous things, machines devoid of feelings*thus violent machines. I will pick up
this theme of reification as the maker of monstrous machines and link it up with the
first of the Theses on Feuerbach, where human activity is noted as being distorted into
schizophrenic binaries that even the great philosophers could not fathom. There
are two basic parts in this schizoid dualism*the passive-contemplative and
voluntaristic-phantasmagorical types. In this schizophrenic process one forgets the
essence*human sensuous activity, revolutionary praxis*and instead treats humanity
in the form of the terrible object that is confined to pure contemplation.84 It is literally
sachliche Gewalt, or ‘violence of things’.
77
Mao Tse-Tung, On War, op. cit., pp. 67.
Ibid., p. 7.
79
Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, op. cit., pp. 135136.
80
Ibid., p. 136.
81
Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, op. cit., pp. 127, 134; Marx, ‘Nationalökonomie und
Philosophie’, op. cit., pp. 251, 271.
82
Ibid., pp. 109, 264.
83
Karl Marx, ‘To Ludwig Feuerbach in Bruckberg’ in Marx. Engels. Collected Works, op. cit., Vol. 3, p. 354.
78
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
255
In locating the schizophrenic condition of capitalism, we thus move from the
sites of the politics of violence to the ontology of violence itself. We understand how alienation creates private property, which further re-creates human
alienation.85 It is at this specific site (of the alienationprivate property combine)
that we would be able to inquire into the origins of wars and violence. Not only are
private property and estrangement created, but also alongside these are created the
notions of ‘having’, ‘possession’ and ‘ownership of private property’. To be a
member of bourgeois society is firstly to ‘have’, to ‘possess’ and to be an ‘owner of
private property’. What one needs to stress is that violence directly emanates from
this trio of possession, ownership and private property. Violence first emerged in
human civilization to protect and defend private property, and over the centuries
has both played this role and perfected it. Violence cannot be removed from private
property. It is located in the sites of the ‘loss of objectivity’ and ‘loss of realness’.86
There is no violence innate in ‘human nature’. Human nature in the abstract is pure
fiction. One dictum follows: remove private property and violence ends. As we will
need to state, the Maoist messianic ideology of ‘wars that will end all wars’ will not
be the ideal solution.
On the Onto-genesis of Violence
Let us for the time being refrain from dwelling on the so-called ‘science of wars’ and
instead turn to Marx’s historicism and humanism and locate his problematic of the
human essence. Instead of concentrating on wars (just and unjust), let us firstly state
that the human essence (das menschliche Wesen) is defined as the fullness of
humanity, a fullness that is brought about by the overthrow of capitalism. This
fullness of humanity is also understood as the pleasure principle of humanness and
naturalness, which is directly in opposition to the reality principle of possession and
ownership. Let us proceed into the radical idea of the human essence whereby we can
have a philosophical basis for socialism as well as maintaining a rigorous critique of
the spectacle of violence continuously generated by global capitalism.
Let us thus turn to historical materialism and note how, with the breakdown of the
original (the so-called ‘primitive’) communist societies and the formation of human
estrangement, private property, class-stratification and the subjugation of humanity
by humanity arose. This period laid fertile ground for the growth of the state,
standing armies and institutional religions as ideologies of violence, primarily in the
defense of private property. We saw that, for Marx, the human being is directly a
‘natural being’ (Naturwesen), endowed with ‘natural powers’ (natürlichen Kräften)
and ‘vital powers’ (lebens Kräften), and we also saw how humanity has to be
understood as an ‘active natural being’ (tatiges Natürwesen).87 We now see that, with
84
Karl Marx, ‘Theses on Feuerbach’ in Marx. Engels. Selected Works, op. cit., p. 28.
Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, op. cit., pp. 6162, 7273, 8388, 90, 112114,
116119, 120.
86
Ibid., p. 143.
85
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
256
M. Jal
the birth of class societies, these human powers have been distorted. This disturbance
of the original human powers and potentialities (similar to Freud’s disturbance of the
pleasure principle) one classifies as the reality principle of the triumvirate of
estrangementreificationfetishism. This triumvirate is located in the black hole of
alienation in which the love of death (necrophilia) overpowers the love of life
(biophilia).88 The dominant ideologies and realities of late imperialism in permanent
crises are located at this very site. I would go with Fromm here and proceed into the
understanding of how humanity as a natural being is reified into the modern war
machine. What one will find is a combination of the male Apollonian life-world
combined with the Abrahamic one, as opposed to the life-world of humanity as
humanity.
In opposition to the Clausewitz-inspired theory of wars, let us have a brief look at
the origins of violence in the origins of the master/slave relation, and how the
authoritarian figures of Apollo and Abraham yet govern both the policies of the
imperialism of the Empire and modern human personality that consumes these
ideologies. Here it is necessary to reflect on Marx’s views on noncapitalist societies,
especially on his readings of the Iroquois and the early Greek, Roman and German
gens (nonstate societies) and contrast these with societies that have private property,
the state (as an alien and brutal organization for macrorepression) and the
monogamic family (as an institution for microrepression). This is the classical state
of the enforced union of enslaved individuals that is governed by the dialectic of
lordship and bondage. It is important to locate both enslaved individuals in the
master/slave relation, as well as the origins of violence in the birth of private property,
patriarchy and the state. With the victory of patriarchyprivate propertystate
combine, one witnessed (what Engels called) ‘the world-historic defeat of the female
sex’,89 where the monogamic family as the institution for the breeding of children and
the promotion of masculine lust and violence was born. Now what the modern
family does is that it contains ‘not only slavery (servitus) but serfdom also, since from
the very beginning it is connected with agricultural services . . . [where it] contained
within itself in miniature all the antagonisms which later develop on a wide scale
within society and its state’.90 One thus seeks the origins of violence much deeper, in
the family apparatus (the miniature form of the state), where man and woman are no
longer equal and interdependent, but unequal like master and slave. After all,
famalus, as Engels mentions, means ‘a household slave and familia signifies the
totality of slaves belonging to one individual’.91 Consequently for free individuals to
emerge, one does not abolish only private property and the state, but also the family
system, which is the cell-form of the violent state itself.
87
Ibid., p. 136.
Fromm, op. cit., p. 213.
89
Fredrick Engels, ‘Origins of Family, Private Property and the State’ in Marx. Engels. Selected Works,
op. cit., p. 488.
90
Ibid., p. 489. See also Anderson, Marx at the Margins, op. cit., p. 201.
91
Engels, Origins of Family, Private Property and the State, op. cit., p. 488.
88
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
257
For it is not merely in private property and the state, but in the family system as
the instrument of slave production where the humanist principle of love and life dies
and the patriarchalauthoritarian principles of calculation, control and domination
are born. Yet it is important that one must avoid the romanticism in Engels’s reading
of Morgan, where a singular epoch-moving ‘Event’ seemed to usher in ‘the worldhistoric defeat of the female sex’, as if stratification did not exist in early gentile
society.92 Despite the nuanced differences between Marx and Engels on the question
of the origins of social stratification, one will stress that the structured violence that
imperialism continuously appeals to is the patriarchal form of class-based, race-based
violence. Ironically, a similar form of violence is taken up by those claiming to oppose
the American project, namely al-Qaeda and the Iranian Shiites, just as in the last
century the same biblical-messianic ideology (grounded on the private property
patriarchystate combine) was the basis of both Nazi as well as Zionist ideologies.93
What it is important to note is that this contemporary (alleged ‘liberal’) imperialist
ideology of violence is both a continuation of the fascist theories of violence and
rooted in the biblical tradition of the territorialization of the earth, its division
between good and evil (similar to the bourgeois division between value and use
value), followed by the doctrine of ethnic supremacy, the chosen people and the
master race.
Let us have a look at the phylogenesis of this unhappy unconscious. In the
Babylonian myth of creation, for instance, Marduk, the patron god of Babylon,
becomes the supreme god. Yet Marduk does not totally eliminate the other male
gods, nor does ‘he’ become like Jehovah (who appears as the first monopolist
landlord and capitalist in the Bible), eliminating matriarchy and the tradition of the
mother goddess. In the biblical tradition, on the other hand, it is the ideology of
the violent male god that is prominent. Here the supremacy of the male (in the
form of the estranged ‘Holy Spirit’) not only eliminates mother rights and the
matriarchal elements of matrilineal societies, but usurps the feminine domain of
procreation. One could say that this is where male-centric violence is clearly
detected, where the male as estranged spirit launches a hostile attack on
womanhood itself by stating that she was the author of original sin. In this
biblical narrative the male god claims that the feminine principle is no longer
needed in procreation. Creation is depicted as emerging through the word of the
male god. It is not the womb, but the order of the male god whereby ‘creation’ (i.e.
a more brutal word for the mode of production) takes place. This will serve as the
first principle of the origins of male-centric exclusion and violence. Thus it is no
longer sexuality whereby procreation is possible, but through the speech-act of the
male. Note how the male robs sexuality from the woman (literally castrating her).
92
Anderson, Marx at the Margins, op. cit., pp. 203204.
The Zionists, like the Nazis, had their racist ‘theoreticians’ based on the discredited pseudo-science of
eugenics, and even more disgraceful ‘science’ of Bible studies. Some of these racist pseudo-theoreticians have
been Elias Auerbach (Bible scholar and the first German Zionist), Felix Theihaber (German sexologist) and
Ignaz Zollschan (German Zionist anthropologist and physician).
93
258
M. Jal
The vibrant mother goddess of matrilineal societies is killed. The virgin mother is
born. Probably the best-known picture of repression is painted here, and so is the
story of the enslavement of humanity. Recall the biblical story of creation again, the
castration threat, the monopoly of the male god, the sinful Eve, and the threat to
eternal damnation. The rigorous difference and conflict between father (god/state)
and son (Adam/civil society) is drawn here. God (the state) forbids the son (civil
society) to eat the forbidden fruit (the mother’s breast/surplus product). The son is
disobedient, attempts to seize the surplus it itself has produced and is exiled from
paradise. Since we are the disobedient and exiled sons and daughters of eternal
rebellion, the question remains: ‘what is to be Done?’
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Conclusion
To my mind one will need to mobilize Marx’s historicism and humanism for
understanding the processes of revolution in the 21st century. Firstly one will have
to note that this Marxist process is essentially antistate, just as it is essentially
humanist and thus antiviolence. It must be recalled that the proletariat ‘cannot
simply lay hold of the ready-made state machinery and wield it for its own
purpose’.94 Thus we claim that one cannot use the despotic instruments of class
societies and wield them for communist purposes. Secondly one will also need to
question the two stages of revolution*the so-called ‘lower stage’ (socialism) and
the ‘higher stage’. How one jumps the early stage should be the focus of attention,
since Stalinism with its totalitarian state power has totally monopolized all
discourses of this ‘early stage’.
What one needs to do is put the theory of state, force and violence on the
backburner and shift attention to the theory of human vital powers (Lebenskräften).
The bourgeois understands violence, not humanity. So what one does now is to
transform the Marxist theory of humanity as humanity into a new humanist theory of
materialist vitalism. Marx’s Gewalt is consequently written in this text of humanistvitalism. The process has started in West Asia. Soon it will engulf the entire world.
It will state that, just as the Narodnikis were incorrect in basing their politics on the
use of revolutionary violence (remember that Lenin and the Bolsheviks could emerge
as a revolutionary party only in the critique of the Narodnikis), so too one will have
to state that the romantic and anarchist versions of violence propagated by Sorel are
not only false but also outright reactionary. Marxism is not anarchism. Lenin was not
Nikolai Chernyshevsky, Petr Chaadev or Pyotr Tkachev. The Bolsheviks were not the
Zemlia i Volia (‘Land and Freedom’). The difference between communism and
anarchism is that the former insists that the masses make history, whilst anarchism
stresses violent acts against the authoritarian state performed by few heroic
individuals. Marx’s Gewalt is a search for revolutionary authenticity, a phenomenological process that moves from bourgeois-fetishized consciousness to class
94
Karl Marx, ‘The Civil War in France’ in Marx. Engels. Selected Works, op. cit., p. 285.
Downloaded by [Murzban Jal] at 02:16 30 April 2012
Critique
259
consciousness. Yet never does Marx’s Gewalt become sachliche Gewalt, or reified
violence. It always remains humanist Gewalt, Gewalt as insurrection. As it is not
sachliche Gewalt, it cannot become akin to a Dostoevsky-inspired act, where the chief
character of Crime and Punishment, Raskolnikov, playacts a messianic hero by
murdering a frail, old woman.95
That is why it is imperative to say that Marxism always concentrates on the issues
of people, and that is also why one needs to emphasize that Marxist politics is always
peoples’ politics, and its philosophy is necessarily humanism. Neither does Marxism
fantasize on some sort of metaphysical world peace, nor does it indulge in romantic
adventurism. On the contrary, Marxism claims that capitalism and imperialism have
to be overthrown, and with communism as the realization of the will of free
individuals and the establishment of classless society, wars can be seen as something
of the past. Humanity will be free at last, refusing to live in the nightmare of its own
prehistory. The dawn of classless society will light the morning of real peace. Freud’s
dictum*where there was id there shall be ego*is transformed into the Marxist
dictum*where there are capitalist wars, there shall be revolutions. It also must be
noted that revolutions in the 21st century shall not repeat themselves as that of 1789
or the 20th-century revolutions, where the theater of world history was dominated by
Dante and Robespierre, Monsieur Guillotine and Napoleon Bonaparte, accompanied
by Trotsky, Stalin and Mao. Instead one has to transcend the very structure of class
societies by looking into the human basis of society. As Marx says:
Communism as the positive transcendence (Aufhebung) of private property as
human-estrangement, and therefore as the real appropriation (Aneignung) of the
human essence (menschlichen Wesens) by and for humanity; communism therefore
as the complete return (Rückkehr) of humanity to itself as a social (i.e., human)
being*a return accomplished consciously and embracing the entire wealth of
previous development. This communism, as fully developed naturalism, equals
humanism, and as fully developed humanism equals naturalism; it is the genuine
resolution (Auflösung) of the conflict between humanity and nature and between
human and human*the true resolution (Auflösung) of the strife between existence
and essence, between objectification and self-confirmation, between freedom and
necessity, between the individual and the species. Communism is the riddle of
history solved, and it knows itself to be the solution.96
However, look closely at the solution of the riddle of history and one will find the
following words inscribed:
Combat or death, bloody struggle or extinction.
Thus the question is inexorably put.97
95
Fyodor Dostoyevsky, Crime and Punishment (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1985). I would also keep
Slavoj Žižek, Revolution at the Gates: Žižek on Lenin, the 1917 Writings (London: Verso, 2002) at this same
DostoevskySorel inspired plane.
96
Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, op. cit., p. 90.
97
Marx is quoting George Sand. See Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy (Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1978), p. 161.