Progress in
Human Geography
http://phg.sagepub.com/
Violence as fetish: Geography, Marxism, and dialectics
James Tyner and Joshua Inwood
Prog Hum Geogr published online 28 January 2014
DOI: 10.1177/0309132513516177
The online version of this article can be found at:
http://phg.sagepub.com/content/early/2014/01/27/0309132513516177
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
Additional services and information for Progress in Human Geography can be found at:
Email Alerts: http://phg.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts
Subscriptions: http://phg.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
>> OnlineFirst Version of Record - Jan 28, 2014
What is This?
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
Article
Violence as fetish: Geography,
Marxism, and dialectics
Progress in Human Geography
1–14
ª The Author(s) 2014
Reprints and permission:
sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/0309132513516177
phg.sagepub.com
James Tyner
Kent State University, USA
Joshua Inwood
University of Tennessee at Knoxville, USA
Abstract
The study of violence has increasing academic purchase. However, the academic treatment of violence
imparts an ontological status that masks violence from critical scrutiny. We argue for the social sciences to
(re)theorize violence and to develop a dialectics of violence. Our purpose is to provide a space for dialogue,
to open a broader debate within the social sciences on the theoretical determination of violence. We
advocate for a new approach to violence that eschews the development of essentializing typologies or
generalized explanations of violence as an epiphenomenon of society.
Keywords
dialectics, direct violence, Marxism, ontology, structural violence
I Introduction
Violence, as Blomley (2003: 123) writes, has a
geography and for this reason, geography must
lie at the center of any discussion of violence
(Tyner, 2012: 14). To this end, various scholars
have forwarded particular workings of the intersectionality of violence, space, and place – contributing to what may be considered a ‘spatial
turn’ in the study of violence (cf. Loyd, 2012;
Springer, 2011, 2012; Tyner, 2012; Woon,
2011, 2013; Wright, 2011). Largely missing
from these discussions, however, has been a
critical engagement with ‘violence’ itself.
Although seemingly self-evident, violence is
not as it appears. Indeed, we argue that geography – but the social sciences more broadly – have
too often fetishized violence, thereby obfuscating
the fundamental sociospatial relations and processes that give ‘violence’ its meaning (though
see Loyd, 2012; Mitchell, 1996).1 As Harvey
(2009: 209) writes, ‘concepts and categories cannot be viewed as having an independent existence, as being universal abstractions true for
all time’. He continues: ‘concepts are produced
under certain conditions . . . [and] they also have
to be seen as producing agents in a social situation’ (p. 298). We contend that violence must
be approached from this same vantage point; that
violence must be theorized as not having a universal quality – but as being produced by, and
producing, sociospatially contingent modes of
production. In other words, violence has no
material reality.
Corresponding author:
James Tyner, Department of Geography, Kent State
University, Kent, OH 44242, USA.
Email:
[email protected]
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
2
Progress in Human Geography
On the surface, such a statement seems either
banal and/or counter-intuitive; violence, common sense holds, is self-evident. As Mitchell
(1996: 156) writes, ‘violence appears to be a
simple concept: it is the act of doing harm,
injury, or desecration through physical force’.
When a person is beaten, raped, or killed, we
know that violence has occurred. We suggest
otherwise. Not that these are not violent events
but that our assertion of violence is at the level
of the abstract. In other words, we all too often
acknowledge that violence has occurred; but
once established, we quickly move on to other
fields to tend. We study the aftermath of violence (Hupy, 2006, 2008; Inwood, 2012; Tyner,
2010), the legal response to violence (Blomley,
2003), crime and the criminalization of violence
(Garmany, 2011; Holloway and McNulty, 2003;
LeBeau and Leitner, 2011), the fear of violence
(Pain, 1991; Sandberg and Tollefsen, 2010;
Valentine, 1992), the representation of violence
(Gallaher, 2004), the landscapes of violence,
and the memorialization of violence (Inwood,
2012; Tyner et al., 2012). However, the act of
violence and the social conditions that produce
and are produced by violence in the first place
becomes a black box, assumed, acknowledged,
but rarely theorized in such a way that affords
a critical evaluation of its constitution. Such
treatments of violence miss the ‘common generative processes and relations’ (Harvey, 1996:
58) that give rise to a multiplicity of violences,
both through time and space, and thus fail to link
violence in time and space.
This is a serious lacuna because it gives the
appearance of violence as being natural and
aspatial to the human condition – and therefore
hiding many other forms of ‘non-physical’
forms of violence. Indeed, in many accounts
of violence, it is claimed that humans have
always been violent, and that violence is a natural part of human relations (cf. Daly and Wilson, 1988; Smith, 2007; Wrangham and
Peterson, 1996). Who among us, for example,
has not run into colleagues, family, or friends
that dismiss the pervasive and unrelenting violence of modernity as simply a natural fact of
life, to be tolerated, ignored, or utilized for their
own purposes? While we acknowledge that violence broadly conceived has played a large and
direct role in the development of our contemporary societies, we also assert that what counts as
violence is intimately associated with the modes
of production that both constitute, and are constituted by, society.
Likewise, we are concerned that the academic
treatment of violence imparts an ontological status that masks our subsequent understanding of,
say, the criminalization or memorialization of
violence. As Oksala (2012: 4) finds, ‘violence
is treated as an extremely wide-ranging term
that covers everything from the use of physical
force that damages bodies to the forms of
semantic exclusion involved in issuing a meaningful sentence’. Consequently we argue that
the time has come for the social sciences to
(re)theorize violence and specifically to
develop a dialectics of violence. Our immediate purpose therefore is to provide a space for
dialogue; to open a broader and more sustained
debate within geography on the theoretical
determination of violence, thereby enriching
our understanding of the ‘spatiality of violence’ and the ‘violence of space’. Building
on the work of Galtung (1969) and the concepts
of structural and direct violence, we advocate
for new understandings – not definitions – of
violence that eschew the development of
trans-sociospatial, essentializing typologies or
generalized explanation of violence as an epiphenomenon of society (cf. Cowling, 2008).
We do so both to better understand the multifaceted ‘geographies’ of violence (Fluri, 2009;
Loyd, 2009; Mitchell, 1996; Tyner, 2009;
Wright, 1999, 2001, 2011), but also, we hope,
to begin the process that will engender a more
peaceful and meaningful human condition (e.g.
Inwood and Tyner, 2011; Loyd, 2012;
Megoran, 2010, 2011; Mitchell and Heynen,
2009; Ross, 2011).
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
3
Tyner and Inwood
II Ontologies and de-naturalized
discourses
The idea that human aggression (and violence)
has a biological and evolutionary basis is
long-standing and is an increasingly popular
explanation (Ray, 2011: 22). This holds particularly true for studies of murder (cf. Daly and
Wilson, 1988; Smith, 2007; Wrangham and
Peterson, 1996). Buss (2006), for example,
maintains that:
we must come to grips with the unpleasant reality
that murder has been a remarkably effective solution to many of the challenges we’ve faced in the
evolutionary trials of survival and reproductive
competition: ascending social hierarchies, creating a reputation that deters encroachers, protecting and keeping our families, escaping from
violently abusive relationships, gaining access
to new lovers. (Buss, 2005: 230–231)
Buss (p. 231) concludes that ‘our moral abhorrence of homicide should not cause us to reject
the compelling evidence that a deep psychology
of killing has been and is an essential component of human nature’.
Such an argument that violence is ubiquitous,
natural, and rooted in ‘human biology’ is especially problematic, for it renders geographic
variability moot.2 As Ray (2011: 42) contends,
‘to see violence as the product of neural capacity inherited through evolutionary development
ignores the social and cultural meanings and
significance of violence that expresses complex
forms of social organization, power and communication’. Indeed, evolutionary psychological models fail to consider that not all actions
that we may now consider ‘violent’ have in fact
been considered violent; nor do these models
say much about the legal constitution of what
counts as both ‘violence’ and ‘crime’. For it is
not simply to determine that any action is or is
not violent; it is rather a matter of understanding
whether such acts are considered justified or
legal. Following Knauft (1991) and Ray
(2011), it is not possible to draw conclusions
about an essential tendency for violence from
early human evolution; it is necessary instead
to situate our conceptualization of violence both
historically and geographically.
The argument that violence is ubiquitous is
mirrored by another limiting position, namely
that ‘violence’ has become an overburdened
concept, one that risks being crushed by its
own inclusivity and unspecificity. Our concern, and critique, is that scholars have for too
long afforded violence an ontological status
without critically engaging in the theorization
of violence. And similar to ongoing efforts
to de-naturalize other seemingly self-evident
concepts (i.e. space, ‘race’, sex, and gender)
it is necessary to critique our inherited ontology of violence (cf. McIlwaine, 1999, for an
extensive overview of typologies of violence).
Ontology has two distinct meanings. On the
one hand, it refers to the fundamental ‘nature’
of reality – of what exists; and, on the other, it
refers to the systematic study of this nature
(Oksala, 2012: 34; cf. Castree, 2005). With
regards to the first usage, ontology is understood
as the sedimented and normally taken-forgranted background of everyday life. It is, in
other words, the common world in which we
live. Realists, for example, argue that societal
conflict is unavoidable; that humans are by
nature competitive and aggressive. While these
arguments are most apparent in strands of evolutionary psychology – which premises that
there is a strong biological component to violence – there are many other epistemological
positions that presume that conflict and violence
are simply part of human nature. Violence, in
short, is given its own material reality: it simply
exists.
Here, we argue against the existence of a pregiven, pre-discursive reality. What we take as
the everyday – including our understanding of
the ‘reality’ of violence – is itself the outcome
of the political. In other words, as Oksala
(2012: 16) writes, the political ‘is not a distinct
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
4
Progress in Human Geography
realm of social reality, but its precondition’. She
explains that:
to be able to argue that entities such as homosexual, delinquent, and pervert are not natural phenomena which human sciences could simply
discover, describe, and refer to objectively, but
effects of power relations and political struggles,
requires a profound denaturalization of ontology:
we have to sever any direct, natural, or necessary
link between scientific concepts and their referents. (Oksala, 2012: 19)
Hence, just as progressive scholars have deconstructed, for example, the ontological status of
‘race’ and ‘sex’ (cf. Kobayashi and Peake,
1994), it is necessary to do likewise for the concept of violence.
Reality – or, rather, what we take as reality –
is an assemblage of political practices; it is
always and already the effect of power relations;
or, as Foucault (1979: 194) asserts, ‘Power produces; it produces reality; it produces domains
of objects and rituals and truth’. Consequently,
when we consider the ‘reality’ of violence, of
what is counted, classified, and criminalized
as violence, we must do so through an understanding of how power and difference are sedimented into society. We counter that violence is
not pre-given; violence is neither transhistorical
nor transgeographical; it has no pre-social existence but comes into being through political
practice.
This is not to deny the salience of violence
within any given society; nor is this to suggest
that violence is merely discursive. The shooting
deaths of over 80 people per day in the United
States are ample testimony to the materiality
of ongoing violence (see also Tyner, 2012).
However, we should not conceive of this violence as somehow determinate, as explained
by racist ‘cultures of poverty’ theories or simple
crime-mapping exercises. Rather, we suggest a
dialectic approach to the theorization of violence, an approach that highlights the embedded
subjectivities and sociospatial relations and
processes that are systemic to any given mode
of production.
III Towards a dialectics of violence
Within geography, our understanding of dialectics is uneven, with multiple and contradictory
interpretations (Castree, 1996: 343; see also
Doel, 2008). This is partially a result of the fact
that Marx never outlined his principles in a systematic and concise way; instead, it has been left
to scholars to decipher Marx’s method from his
myriad and sometimes contradictory writings
(Harvey, 1996). As a consequence, we turn to
the work of Ollman (2003) to outline our understanding of dialectics.3
According to Ollman (2003: 12), ‘dialectics
is a way of thinking that brings into focus the
full range of changes and interactions that occur
in the world’. This is counter to more conventional and pervasive epistemologies – of which
empiricism is exemplary – that disaggregate the
world into discrete and unrelated entities. So
conceived, a disaggregated epistemology limits
analysis to the surface appearance of objects.
Dialectics, conversely, opens space for a deeper
and more profound analysis. Reality, from a dialectical vantage point, consists not simply of
disparate ‘things’ but rather processes and relations. In other words, reality is more than the
epiphenomenon that can be counted, classified,
and mapped; it is more than the ‘observation’
that strikes us immediately and directly, which
masks the underlying structures and social
relations.
Dialectics restructures our thinking and our
understanding of reality by replacing the commonsense notion of ‘thing’ with notions of ‘process’, ‘relation’, and ‘change’. This allows us to
reconsider ‘how something works or happened
while simultaneously developing [an] understanding of the system in which things could
work or happen in just this way’ (Ollman,
2003: 15). As Harvey (1996: 51) writes, ‘dialectics forces us to ask the question of every ‘thing’
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
5
Tyner and Inwood
or ‘event’ that we encounter: by what process
was it constituted and how is it sustained?’
So how might a dialectical approach to violence proceed? Consider the following situations:
Scenario 1: Person X raises a hand and
strikes person Y in the chest. Person Y falls
to the ground in pain.
Scenario 2: Person A raises a hand and
strikes person B in the chest. Person B falls
to the ground in pain.
On the surface the actions in both scenarios
appear identical; and on a certain level both may
be understood as acts of violence. Such a
surface-level understanding appears to hold
true, even if the first scenario occurred, for
example, in France during the Middle Ages and
the second scenario occurred in Cambodia last
week. Indeed, it is the equivalence of these two
actions – separated, in our example, by hundreds of years and thousands of miles – that
gives weight to the argument that violence is
ubiquitous, unproblematic, and contains a transgeographical and transhistorical essence.
What is missing in this fetishization of violence, we contend, are those factors that actually constitute our conception of violence. If
we were to abstract from these scenarios we
would see that both cases are relational, that
is the subjects in both scenarios are internally
related: X strikes Y and A strikes B. These acts,
moreover, are intended to be transformative.
One might say that both X and A are attempting
to impose their will on Y and B. If we return to
the concrete, however, we would find that the
scenarios are qualitatively different. For example, how is X related to Y? Are they partners,
are they father and son, or strangers? Where
does this act occur – in a bar, on a battlefield,
or during a sporting event? We readily see that
even though acts of violence may give the
appearance of being identical, the underlying
social and spatial relations and processes are
masked. To simply label both events as violent
is to fetishize violence and possibly to remove
the underlying processes and relations for why
this violence occurs from our analysis. In our
attempt to move beyond a theorization of violence as an epiphenomenon and to provide a
de-ontology of violence, we argue that it is first
necessary to think through the concepts of
abstract and concrete violence; and second to
situate concepts of violence within the dominant mode of production.
IV Abstract violence and concrete
violence
Dialectics, following Ollman (2003: 60), begins
with the ‘real concrete’ (the world as it presents
itself to us) and proceeds through ‘abstraction’
(the intellectual activity of breaking this whole
down into the mental units with which we
can think about it) to the ‘thought concrete’
(the reconstituted and now understood whole
present in the mind). In other words, the ‘real
concrete’ is the world in which we live, with all
of its contradictions, and social, economic, and
political processes and relations. By disaggregating the world into its constitutive parts
through the process of abstraction and then
by reconstituting the world back to a whole
we are able to understand the underlying relations that give rise to phenomena in the first
place.
In Capital, Marx made a distinction between
‘abstract’ and ‘concrete’ labor; he did so in
order to focus attention on the valorization of
capital: the generation of surplus-value. Here,
Marx uses ‘abstraction’ to:
refer to those units whose ties with reality are
fully obscured, where the particular society in
which they exist has been completely lost sight
of. Thus labor – which, as labor in general, Marx
takes to be a special product of capitalism – is
spoken of as an ‘abstraction’ because most people
consider that it existed in all social systems.
(Ollman, 1976: 62)
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
6
Progress in Human Geography
Labor, in other words, and outside of a Marxist
perspective, is taken as given, as something that
is ubiquitous to humanity and is natural.
Within geography there is a tendency to
focus on measurable, map-able, concrete acts:
rapes, murder, famine, suicide. This is readily
viewed in the various empirical studies of
‘crime’ and ‘violence’ that are, in actuality,
indirect studies of how certain acts defined as
‘criminal’ or ‘violence’ are counted.4 Violence
assumes the form of a static, independent variable (e.g. the likelihood of any given individual
either perpetuating an act of ‘violence’ or of
becoming a victim of an act of ‘violence’). In
turn, other abstractions such as poverty, education, ‘race’, and so forth are held as dependent
variables. The relationship among these surface
appearances assumes the form of causality.
However, such studies provide insufficient
attention to the hidden totality that internally
relates the supposed disarticulated variables.
By falling into this analytic trap, scholars make
the mistake of conflating ‘real’ concrete acts
with specific abstractions, instead of seeing
such acts for what they are, namely acts that are
historically and geographically contingent and
dialectically related to the society from which
they emerge. For example, during the 18th century, certain actions we now classify as ‘domestic violence’ were, from a legal standpoint,
considered neither violent nor criminal, but an
accepted part of marital relations; likewise, rape
during the 16th century was not only ‘not’
necessarily viewed as violent, but was encouraged as part of broader processes of primitive
accumulation (Federici, 2004).
We suggest, therefore, that in order to theorize the broader salience of violence in society
one must abstract violence from dominant
modes of production that give rise to particular
acts; we encourage scholars, therefore, to use
violence as a theoretical vantage point for a
more comprehensive and sustained analysis of
social and spatial relations. It is necessary,
accordingly, to address the ‘thought concrete’
forms of violence that are systemic to particular
modes of production: to acknowledge that ‘real
concrete’ violence is neither transhistorical nor
transgeographical, but the ‘appearance’ of different social relations vis-à-vis access to the
means of production.
V Marx’s second condition of
capitalism
By engaging in dialectics we begin from the
premise that to understand society we need to
grasp the character of its relations of production,
or its particular ‘mode of production’ (Lebowitz,
2003: 2). Simply put, as Rees (1998: 99)
explains, ‘theoretical concepts arise from and
relate to the real world, but not in a direct and
simplistic way’. We must therefore acknowledge
that a direct reflection of reality – including our
conception of violence – can only lead to the
mental reproduction of the most misleading
appearances of society (cf. Rees, 1998: 98).
Lefebvre (1991: 46–47) postulated that every
‘society to which history gave rise within a
framework of a particular mode of production,
and which bore the stamp of that mode of
production’s inherent characteristics, shaped its
own space’. In other words, the mode of production is crucial to understanding not only
how space is produced, but also how social relations – including those conceived as violent –
are produced. We do not, however, suggest that
human subjectivities or actions (i.e. violence)
are determined by the dominant mode of production with no room for autonomy; instead
we suggest that what constitutes violence, and
our understanding of violence, is linked to
and flows from the dominant modes of production in a given society.
The term ‘mode of production’ is somewhat
contested (Harvey, 2010). Here, we follow Fine
and Saad-Filho (2010) who write that:
patterns of life are determined by existing social
conditions, in particular the places to be filled in
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
7
Tyner and Inwood
the process of production. These relations exist
independently of individual choice, even though
they have been established in the course of the
historical development of society. (Fine and
Saad-Filho, 2010: 3)
Capitalism, for example, is a specific historical
form of the social process; its foundation is the
separation of direct producers from the means
of production, which is why workers – although
formally free – are forced by material circumstance to sell their labor-power to the capitalist,
who owns the means of production (Heinrich,
2012: 181). Capitalism, in this sense, appears
as a system whereby a person’s capacity to work
becomes a commodity that can be bought and
sold on the market. This has a tremendous bearing on the theorization of violence. For just as
each mode of production is structured according
to its class relations, for which there are appropriate corresponding categories of analysis (Fine
and Saad-Filho, 2010: 5), so too will each mode
of production structure the abstraction of violence in particular concrete forms.
For Marx, capitalism was predicated upon
two key conditions. The first is that ‘laborpower can appear on the market as a commodity
only if, and in so far as, its possessor . . . offers it
for sale or sells it as a commodity’ (Marx, 1990
[1867]: 271). The condition, however, holds
only if a second condition is met, namely that
‘the possessor of labor-power . . . [must] be
compelled to offer for sale as a commodity that
very labor-power which exists only in his living
body’ (p. 272). It was through the satisfaction of
these two conditions that workers appear free in
a double sense: as legally ‘free’ individuals who
are ‘free’ to enter into the waged-labor market.
The worker, of course, is anything but free.
As Peck (1996: 27) writes, ‘in capitalist societies, the preparedness of workers to offer their
labor on the labor market is largely secured by
the systematic erosion of possibilities of subsistence outside the wage system’. It is, consequently, Marx’s second condition that assumes
prominence in our understanding of violence
in capitalism.
Consider the well-documented, if still debated,
transformation from feudalism to mercantilism to
capitalism. A Marxist perspective begins from
the standpoint of ‘primitive accumulation’, a term
also subject to much recent debate both within
and beyond geography (Glassman, 2006; Harvey,
2003; Li, 2009; McIntyre, 2011). In general, however, this entails the historical process of separating workers from the means of production; this
may be accomplished via the usurpation of common property, enclosures of ‘common’ land, and
the destruction of domestic, artisanal production.
In an oft-cited passage, Marx (1990 [1867]:
926) says of primitive accumulation: ‘capital
comes dripping from head to toe, from every
pore, with blood and dirt’. Marx’s point is not
simply that capitalism is violent; rather, his critique lies in the assertion that as long as capitalism exists, systemic inequalities are both
necessary and unavoidable. That these structural
conditions are not necessarily considered criminal or necessarily violent is a reflection of how
crime and violence are also ‘historically and
morally determined’. For, as Marx recognizes,
the standards of ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ are not transhistorical or transgeographical but rather conditioned by the dominant economic (and hence
legal) relations of society. This, certainly, is the
point raised by Engels, who, in The Condition
of the Working Class in England, writes:
When one individual inflicts bodily injury upon
another, such injury that death results, we call the
deed manslaughter; when the assailant knew in
advance that the injury would be fatal, we call the
deed murder. But when society places hundreds
of proletarians in such a position that they inevitably meet a too early and an unnatural death, one
which is quite as much a death by violence as that
by the sword or bullet; when it deprives thousands
of the necessaries of life, places them under conditions in which they cannot live – forces them,
through the strong arm of the law, to remain in
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
8
Progress in Human Geography
such conditions until that death ensues which is
the inevitable consequence – knows that these
thousands of victims must perish, and yet permits
these conditions to remain, its deed is murder just
as surely as the deed of a single individual; disguised, malicious murder, murder against which
none can defend himself, which does not seem
what it is, because no man sees the murderer,
because the death of the victim seems a natural
one, since the offence is more one of omission
than of commission. But murder it remains.
(Engels, 2005 [1845]: 127)
What both Marx and Engels understood is not
just that ‘violence’ assumes a central role in the
accumulation of capital; rather, they understood
that capitalism is a particular historical (and
geographical) mode of production; and that
social relations, such as the relationship to the
means of production, must be described with
categories that retain their validity only with
regard to these modes of production (cf. Heinrich,
2012: 32). From Marx we recognize that ‘labor’
is not a transhistorical concept; likewise, we
understand that ‘race,’ sex, and gender appear
in different forms in different times and different places. This suggests, therefore, that any
understanding of ‘violence’ as a relational process must take seriously the argument – put
forth most prominently by feminist geographers – that violence is first and foremost experienced, embodied, and deeply personal (cf.
England and Simon, 2010; Fluri, 2009; Kedir
and Admasachew, 2010; Koopman, 2011; Pain,
1991, 2001, 2010; Woon, 2011; Wright, 2010).
It is necessary therefore to refocus future analyses to that of, for example, violence in feudal
Japan, or violence in neoliberal United States,
rather than a search for universal, essentialist
origins and explanations.
VI The unity of structural and
direct violence
In 1969, Johan Galtung forwarded an especially
powerful conceptual understanding of violence.
He began by noting six dimensions to ‘violence’,
provisionally defined as being ‘present when
human beings are being influenced so that their
actual somatic and mental realizations are below
their potential realization’ (Galtung, 1969: 168;
see also Galtung, 1990; Galtung and Höivik,
1971). Galtung (1969: 170) argued that a key distinction among different forms of violence is
‘whether or not there is a subject (person) who
acts’. Direct violence is said to occur when there
is an identifiable actor who commits an act of
violence – defined, again, by Galtung as any
action that impinges on or reduces human potential; structural violence (also termed ‘social
injustice’ by Galtung) occurs when no such actor
is identifiable. Galtung elaborates that:
whereas in the first case these consequences can
be traced back to concrete persons or actors, in the
second case this is no longer meaningful. There
may not be any person who directly harms
another person in the structure. The violence is
built into the structure and shows up as unequal
power and consequently unequal life chances.
(Galtung, 1969: 170–171)
Structural violence, in other words:
occurs as inequalities structured into a society so
that some have access to social resources that foster individual and community well-being – high
quality education and health care, social status,
wealth, comfortable and adequate housing, and
efficient civic services – while others do not.
(Opotow, 2001: 151; see also Gilmore, 2002)
Consequently:
to understand who is made most vulnerable where
and how socially produced harms are naturalized
discursively and materially, it is necessary to
theorize specific economic, political, and social
relations of oppression and domination and how
they articulate (or intersect) in particular historical, geographic moments. (Loyd, 2009: 865–866)
It is such an understanding, indeed, that typifies
many so-called Marxist accounts of violence,
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
9
Tyner and Inwood
for the historical transformation of social relations embedded in and stemming from practices
of primitive accumulation are heralded as a transition from ‘direct’ to ‘structural’ violence. As
Marx (1990 [1867]: 899) explains, ‘the silent
compulsion of economic relations sets the seal
on the domination of the capitalist over the
worker. Direct extra-economic force [i.e. direct
violence] is still of course used, but only in
exceptional cases’. Such a sentiment is found in
a recent report published by the World Health
Organization, albeit without an explicit critique
of capitalism: ‘Poverty wields its destructive
influence at every stage of human life, from the
moment of conception to the grave. It conspires
with the most deadly and painful diseases to
bring a wretched existence to all those who suffer
from it’ (WHO, 2005: 5).
The theoretical separation of ‘direct’ and
‘structural’ violence is both pervasive and, we
argue, misleading (cf. Farmer, 2004, 2009;
Scheper-Hughes and Bourgois, 2004). What
appears as a clear dichotomy between ‘direct’
and ‘structural’ violence, like all such polar
opposites in Marxism, is really not one (Ollman,
1976: 66). Instead of focusing on the uncritical
distinction between structural and direct violence, as though each of these forms has its own
a priori existence in and of itself, we need to
unite these seemingly opposite abstract forms
into their historical and geographical totalities.
Critical for understanding a dialectical
approach, as stated, is how one moves from real
concrete events, to abstract concepts, and back
to the thought concrete. Throughout each of
these transformations it is necessary to abstract
out particular ‘types’ and ‘relations’ of violence
and to begin to think through how they are interconnected, and take particular form, at any
given moment. For example, various state apparatuses (e.g. those institutions that constitute the
criminal justice system) routinely collapse a
litany of specific, real concrete acts into the concept of violence: killings, beatings, bullying,
rape, and so on.
However, we would ask: how is it possible to
equate such seemingly disparate, qualitatively
different acts? A starting point to equate these
different (and selected) real concrete forms of
violence is to abstract from them, to ask what
relations are manifest among these acts. Thus,
through a process of abstraction, violence
becomes relational and transformative – a statement aligned with Galtung’s provisional definition. However, if we abstract violence as any
action that affects the material conditions of
another, thereby reducing one’s potentiality, the
distinction between ‘direct’ and ‘structural’ collapses. For should not the continued inequalities
as manifest in differences in life expectancy, for
example, in the United States count as violence?
Should not the elimination of welfare programs
and health care constitute acts of violence – acts,
it should be stressed, that are legislated by
knowable, nameable members of the US Congress? The false dichotomy between direct and
structural violence no longer holds purchase as
we move from the level of the abstraction to that
of the ‘thought concrete’. This has tremendous
bearing, given that intentionality serves as an
additional key distinction for Galtung.
According to Galtung, this:
distinction is important when guilt is to be
decided, since the concept of guilt has been tied
more to intention, both in Judeo-Christian ethics
and in Roman jurisprudence, than to consequence
(whereas the present definition of violence is
entirely located on the consequence side). (Galtung, 1969: 171)
More specifically, a focus on ‘intention’ as
opposed to ‘guilt’ risks understating the level
of violence within any given society. As Galtung (1969: 170) explains, ‘ethical systems
directed against intended violence will easily
fail to capture structural violence in their nets’.
In other words, an artificial distinction between
‘direct’ and ‘structural’ violence serves to
reproduce existent inequalities in society; formal and official accountings of violence fail to
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
10
Progress in Human Geography
capture those actions that reduce one’s potentiality because the fundamental social relations
remain hidden. Farmer (2004: 307), for example, forwards the idea that structural violence
‘is violence exerted systematically – that is,
indirectly – by everyone who belongs to a certain social order’. However, the violence in
capitalism – imminently visible in the form of
primitive accumulation – becomes fetishized
beneath the supposed free exchange of labor.
Any given capitalist is no longer viewed as
intentionally or personally inflicting violence
upon his or her workers; and ‘direct’ violence
magically appears as something ‘natural’ if
not extraordinary, while ‘structural’ violence
appears as an unfortunate and unforeseen consequence of individual and free decisions.
There is a further complication to the false
dichotomy between ‘structural’ and ‘direct’ violence as manifest in capitalism, one that exists
because of what we term the social and spatial
immediacy of violence. Consider, for example,
acts of ‘real’ concrete violence, such as rape.
In these acts, there is an immediacy that is
clearly present: a man, for example, raping a
woman. In structural violence, however, such
as the social conditions that lead to famine, this
immediacy is missing. Those individuals
‘responsible’ for the creation of such conditions
are neither readily identifiable nor necessarily
in the immediate vicinity; and indeed, many
accounts do not, or cannot, attempt to ascertain
those responsible. Consequently, ‘structural’
violence simply happens; it is part of the existing structure of society with no individual to
hold accountable. Critical for us as geographers
is the way these relations are often obscured
through the production of space. It is necessary
to move beyond treating violence as simply
existing and instead to materially ground it
within the mode of production of a particular
society. This has the possibility to expand our
geographic understanding of the interconnectivity of myriad social, economic, and political
processes. In so doing it will be possible to help
our colleagues and students to see, for example,
how the unfettered capital accumulation that
occurs in the West has life-altering possibilities
for billions of untold peoples around the world
and undergirds much of our contemporary
understanding of violence.
As a consequence we refuse to abide by the
distinction between structural and direct violence. Concrete forms of structural violence
(e.g. lack of adequate health care or housing)
are manifest in capitalism not as ‘unfortunate’
by-products but because of the particular social
relations that constitute the production, circulation, and exchange of capitalism. However,
given our understanding of the sociospatial dialectic, these economic relations remain hidden;
so too are associated forms of violence. Concrete forms of violence, such as rape and beatings, are individuated and thus counted; those
concrete forms that perpetuate inequalities in
society – inequalities that facilitate the valorization of capital – are discounted and remain
veiled from critical scrutiny. It is incumbent
therefore to conceive of ‘structural’ violence
as just as ‘direct’ as other concrete actions; to
dismiss inequalities in society as unintended
consequences is to make disappear the systemic
inequalities that are inherent in capitalist
exchange.
VII Conclusions
In the wake of the US War on/of Terror, Butler
asks:
Are we not, strategically speaking, interested in
ameliorating this violence? Are we not, ethically
speaking, obligated to stop its further dissemination, to consider our role in instigating it, and to
foment and cultivate another sense of a culturally
and religiously diverse global political culture?
(Butler, 2004: 8–9)
We answer an unequivocal yes! Treating violence dialectically, in short, is about working
towards a more just future in which those who
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
11
Tyner and Inwood
defend their privileged position through the illconceived dichotomy of structural versus direct
violence can no longer obscure the fact that their
lives are possible because of, not in spite of, violence. Our argument is born out of a frustration
that current concepts and understandings of violence do very little to transform the fundamental
social relations that undergird society. We contend instead that considerations of violence
must be grounded in a sociospatial dialectic that
has its roots grounded in historical-materialist
understandings. In short, we argue by treating
violence dialectically we can begin to move
beyond the geographically confined and threadbare narratives of ‘us versus them’ to the more
important and potentially transformative questions that constitute the multiplicity of subjectivities that are dealt with violently.
It is therefore diversionary to seek either a
‘naturalized’ reality or preciseness of violence.
The attempt to decipher the ‘origins of violence’
is akin to searching for the ‘origins’ of space;
such a quest presumes the existence of a material entity that, frankly, does not exist. While
in recent years we have witnessed a flurry of
academic activity directed toward the study of
violence, a repeated fallacy of such studies is
to begin with a provisional definition of violence, and then to proceed to study (and map)
the causes of violence, the consequences of violence, or the fear of violence. As Harvey (2009:
144) notes, such an approach fails to fundamentally transform the very social and spatial relations that constitute violence. He goes on to
note that:
mapping even more evidence of man’s patent
inhumanity to man is counter-revolutionary in the
sense that it allows the bleeding-heart liberal in us
to pretend that we are contributing to a solution
when in fact we are not. This kind of empiricism
is irrelevant. There is already enough information
in congressional reports, newspapers, books, articles, and so on to provide us with all the evidence
we need. Our task does not lie here . . . [Instead
the] immediate task is nothing more nor less than
the self-conscious and aware construction of a
new paradigm for social geographic thought
through a deep and profound critique of our existing analytical constructs. This [as academics] is
what we are best equipped to do. (Harvey, 2009:
144)
In other words, if we continue down the royal
road of giving violence a naturalized existence
it does not possess, or deserve, and if we continue to attempt to locate ‘violence’ outside of
social – and spatial – relations, the progressive
praxis of promoting non-violence will continue
to elude our grasp. For if violence remains
fetishized – promoted as something natural
and normal – it will forever serve the interests
of those who seek to profit through oppressive
and exploitative practices. However, if we
acknowledge that sociospatial relations transform with, as well as transform, the mode of
production, and if we acknowledge that ‘violence’ is relational, it follows that ‘violence’
will likewise transform over time and space.
To understand and address contemporary violence, therefore, we must concern ourselves
with ‘real’ concrete forms of violence, and
abstract these forms into constituent ‘thought
concrete’ forms of violence.
Acknowledgements
The authors’ wish to thank the editors at Progress in
Human Geography, Derek Alderman, Alex Colucci,
Samuel Henkin, Dave Stasiuk, Rachel Will, and
three anonymous reviewers for providing helpful
and insightful critique of our original manuscript.
Omissions and shortcomings are entirely our own.
Funding
Portions of this research were funded through the
National Science Foundation (Grant 0961117 and
Grant 1262736).
Notes
1. Our purpose in this article is not to name and remark on
specific authors or studies, but instead is intended to
outline a way for social scientists to conceptualize violence more broadly and – we hope – to begin a process
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
12
Progress in Human Geography
that will engender a more just and equitable world. Far
from seeing this manuscript as a direct critique of these
previous approaches, our intent is to outline a different
way forward and to bring attention to the fact that as
social scientists we must move beyond description to
focus on processes that will ultimately be transformative to our institutions, communities, and world.
2. It is significant that many histories of violence utilize
homicide rates as a proxy for violence. See, for example, Eisner (2003, 2008).
3. Among the various approaches to dialectics, we find in
Ollman an approach that most effectively highlights
the inner relations between the ‘abstract’ and the
‘concrete’.
4. Flint (2003), for example, details that geographic patterns of hate crimes reflect more the various strategies
in which crime is defined and counted than the ‘actual’
number of incidents.
References
Blomley N (2003) Law, property, and the geography of violence: The frontier, the survey, and the grid. Annals of
the Association of American Geographers 93: 121–141.
Buss DM (2005) The Murderer Next Door: Why the Mind
is Designed to Kill. New York: Penguin.
Butler J (2004) Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning
and Violence. London: Verso.
Castree N (1996) Birds, mice and geography: Marxisms
and dialectics. Transactions of the Institute of British
Geographers 21: 342–362.
Castree N (2005) Nature. New York: Routledge.
Cowling M (2008) Marxism and Criminological Theory: A
Critique and a Toolkit. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Daly M and Wilson M (1988) Homicide. New Brunswick,
NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Doel MA (2008) Dialectics revisited: Reality discharged.
Environment and Planning A 40: 2631–2640.
Eisner M (2003) Long-term historical trends in violent
crime. Crime and Justice 30: 83–142.
Eisner M (2008) Modernity strikes back? A historical perspective on the latest increase in interpersonal violence
(1960–1990). International Journal of Criminal Violence 2: 288–316.
Engels F (2005 [1845]) The Condition of the Working
Class in England. New York: Penguin Books.
England M and Simon S (2010) Scary cities: Urban geographies of fear, difference and belonging. Social and
Cultural Geography 11(3): 201–207.
Farmer P (2004) An anthropology of structural violence.
Current Anthropology 45: 305–325.
Farmer P (2009) On suffering and structural violence: A
view from below. Race/Ethnicity: Multidisciplinary
Global Contexts 3: 11–28.
Federici S (2004) Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body
and Primitive Accumulation. New York: Autonomedia.
Fine B and Saad-Filho A (2010) Marx’s Capital, fifth
edition. New York: Pluto Books.
Flint C (2003) Spaces of hate: Geographies of discrimination and intolerance in the USA. In: Flint C (ed.) Spaces
of Hate: Geographies of Discrimination and Intolerance in the USA. New York: Routledge, 1–20.
Fluri JL (2009) Geopolitics of gender and violence ‘from
below’. Political Geography 28: 259–265.
Foucault M (1979) Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the
Prison, translated by Sheridan A. New York: Vintage
Books.
Gallaher C (2004) Teaching about political violence: A
primer on representation. Journal of Geography in
Higher Education 28: 301–315.
Galtung J (1969) Violence, peace, and peace research.
Journal of Peace Research 6: 167–191.
Galtung J (1990) Cultural violence. Journal of Peace
Research 27: 291–305.
Galtung J and Höivik T (1971) Structural and direct violence: A note on operationalization. Journal of Peace
Research 8: 73–76.
Garmany J (2011) Drugs, violence, fear, and death: The
necro- and narco-geographies of contemporary urban
space. Urban Geography 32: 1148–1166.
Gilmore RW (2002) Fatal couplings of power and difference: Notes on racism and geography. The Professional
Geographer 54: 15–24.
Glassman J (2006) Primitive accumulation, accumulation
by dispossession, accumulation by ‘extra-economic’
means. Progress in Human Geography 30: 608–625.
Harvey D (1996) Justice, Nature and the Geography of
Difference. Oxford: Blackwell.
Harvey D (2003) The New Imperialism. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Harvey D (2009) Social Justice and the City, revised
edition. Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press.
Harvey D (2010) A Companion to Marx’s Capital.
New York: Verso.
Heinrich M (2012) An Introduction to the Three Volumes
of Karl Marx’s Capital, translated by Locascio A.
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
13
Tyner and Inwood
Holloway S and McNulty TL (2003) Contingent urban
geographies of violent crime: Racial segregation and
the impact of public housing in Atlanta. Urban Geography 24: 187–211.
Hupy JP (2006) The long-term effects of explosive munitions on the WWI battlefield surface of Verdun,
France. Scottish Geographical Journal 122: 167–184.
Hupy JP (2008) The environmental footprint of war. Environment and History 14: 405–421.
Inwood J (2012) Righting unrightable wrongs: Legacies of
racial violence and the Greensboro Truth and Reconciliation Commission. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 102: 1450–1467.
Inwood J and Tyner (2011) Geography’s pro-peace agenda:
An unfinished product. ACME: An International
E-Journal for Critical Geographies 10: 442–457.
Kedir A and Admasachew L (2010) Violence against
women in Ethiopia. Gender, Place and Culture: A
Journal of Feminist Geography 17(4): 437–452.
Knauft BM (1991) Violence and sociality in human evolution. Current Anthropology 32: 391–409.
Kobayashi A and Peake L (1994) Unnatural discourse:
‘Race’ and gender in geography. Gender, Place and
Culture: A Journal of Feminist Geography 1: 225–243.
Koopman S (2011) Alter-geopolitics: Other securities are
happening. Geoforum 42: 274–284.
LeBeau JL and Leitner M (2011) Introduction: Progress in
research on the geography of crime. The Professional
Geographer 63: 161–173.
Lebowitz MA (2003) Beyond Capital: Marx’s Political
Economy of the Working Class, second edition. New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Lefebvre H (1991) The Production of Space. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Li TM (2009) To make live or let die? Rural dispossession
and the protection of surplus populations. Antipode 41:
66–93.
Loyd J (2009) ‘A microscopic insurgent’: Militarization,
health, and critical geographies of violence. Annals
of the Association of American Geographers 99:
863–873.
Loyd J (2012) Geographies of peace and antiviolence.
Geography Compass 6: 477–489.
McIlwaine C (1999) Geography and development: Violence and crime as development issues. Progress in
Human Geography 23: 453–463.
McIntyre M (2011) Race, surplus population and the Marxist theory of imperialism. Antipode 43: 1489–1515.
Marx K (1990 [1867]) Capital: A Critique of Political
Economy Volume 1, translated by Fowkes B. New
York: Penguin.
Megoran N (2010) Towards a geography of peace: Pacific
geopolitics and evangelical Christian crusade apologies. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 35: 382–398.
Megoran N (2011) War and peace? An agenda for peace
research and practice in geography. Political Geography 30: 178–189.
Mitchell D (1996) Political violence, order, and the legal
construction of public space: Power and the public
forum doctrine. Urban Geography 17: 152–178.
Mitchell D and Heynen N (2009) The geography of survival and the right to the city: Speculations on surveillance, legal innovation, and the criminalization of
intervention. Urban Geography 30: 611–632.
Oksala J (2012) Foucault, Politics, and Violence. Evanston,
IL: Northwestern University Press.
Ollman B (1976) Alienation: Marx’s Conception of Man in
Capitalist Society, second edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ollman B (2003) Dance of the Dialectic: Steps in Marx’s
Method. Urbana-Champaign, IL: University of Illinois
Press.
Opotow S (2001) Reconciliation in time of impunity:
Challenges for social justice. Social Justice Research
14: 149–170.
Pain R (1991) Space, sexual violence and social control:
Integrating geographical and feminist analyses of
women’s fear of crime. Progress in Human Geography
15: 415–431.
Pain R (2001) Gender, Race, Age, and Fear in the City.
Urban Studies 38: 899–913.
Pain R (2010) The new geopolitics of fear. Geography
Compass 4: 226–240.
Peck J (1996) Work Place: The Social Regulation of Labor
Markets. New York: Guilford Press.
Ray L (2011) Violence and Society. London: SAGE.
Rees J (1998) The Algebra of Revolution: The Dialectic
and the Classical Marxist Tradition. New York:
Routledge.
Ross A (2011) Geographies of war and the putative peace.
Political Geography 30: 197–199.
Sandberg L and Tollefsen A (2010) Talking about fear of
violence in public space: Female and male narratives
about threatening situations in Umea, Sweden. Social
and Cultural Geography 11: 1–15.
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014
14
Progress in Human Geography
Scheper-Hughes N and Bourgois P (2004) Introduction:
Making sense of violence. In: Violence in War and
Peace, edited by Scheper-Hughes N and Bourgois P.
Oxford: Blackwell, 1–27.
Smith DL (2007) The Most Dangerous Animal: Human
Nature and the Origins of War. New York: St Martin’s
Griffin.
Springer S (2011) Violence sits in places? Cultural practice, neoliberal rationalism, and virulent imaginative
geographies. Political Geography 30: 90–98.
Springer S (2012) Neoliberalising violence: Of the exceptional and the exemplary in coalescing moments. Area
44: 136–143.
Tyner JA (2009) War, Violence, and Population: Making
the Body Count. New York: Guilford Press.
Tyner JA (2010) Military Legacies: A World Made by
War. New York: Routledge.
Tyner JA (2012) Space, Place, and Violence: Violence and
the Embodied Geographies of Race, Sex, and Gender.
New York: Routledge.
Tyner JA, Brindis Alvarez G, et al. (2012) Memory and
the everyday landscape of violence in post-genocide
Cambodia. Social and Cultural Geography 13:
853–871.
Valentine G (1992) Images of danger: Women’s sources
of information about the spatial distribution of male
violence. Area 24: 22–29.
Woon C (2011) Undoing violence, unbounding precarity:
Beyond the frames of terror in the Philippines. Geoforum 42: 285–296.
Woon C (2013) For ‘emotional fieldwork’ in critical geopolitical research on violence and terrorism. Political
Geography 33: 31–41.
World Health Organization (WHO) (2005) Bridging the
Gaps. Geneva: WHO.
Wrangham R and Peterson D (1996) Demonic Males:
Apes and the Origins of Human Violence. Boston,
MA: Mariner Books.
Wright MW (1999) The dialectics of still life: Murder,
women, and maquiladoras. Public Culture 11: 453–474.
Wright MW (2001) A manifesto against femicide. Antipode 33: 550–566.
Wright MW (2010) Geography and gender: Feminism and
a feeling of justice. Progress in Human Geography
34(6): 818–827.
Wright MW (2011) Necropolitics, narcopolitics, and femicide: Gendered violence on the Mexico-US border. Signs:
Journal of Women in Culture and Society 36: 707–731.
Downloaded from phg.sagepub.com at UNIV OF TENNESSEE on January 31, 2014