the author(s) 2015
ISSN 1473-2866 (Online)
ISSN 2052-1499 (Print)
www.ephemerajournal.org
volume 15(3): 513-535
Laughing for real? Humour, management power
and subversion
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
abstract
Management and humour are becoming more closely interlinked in contemporary
organizational life. Whereas humour was conventionally viewed as a deleterious, alien
element at the workplace, it is now increasingly viewed as a valuable management tool.
This development raises the question of whether humour can still be regarded as having
critical or subversive potential. This article discusses three research approaches to
management and humour: the instrumental, the ideological critical, and contemporary
critical organization studies, giving particular emphasis to extending the last tradition.
Hence, the article situates itself in the critical debate on the function of humour in the
workplace and on ‘cynical reasoning’ recently initiated in organization studies. It seeks to
contribute to this debate by defining the features of a critical humoristic practice in a
post-authoritarian management context. The point of departure is primarily Žižek’s
critique of ideology and its application in recent organization studies.
Introduction
In a comedy sketch broadcast on Danish television, employees of a company are
called in for a meeting in the company canteen. ‘Today I have good and bad news
for you,’ announces the well-dressed female manager to the anxious employees,
‘The bad news is that, unfortunately, we have to reduce staff by 35 per cent’. The
camera shows the fear in the employees’ faces before the manager continues:
‘The good news is that we have teamed up with the company clown from
Companyclown.com, who is here to help us all through the difficult time’. Next
to the manager enters a clown who uses over-dramatic body language, affected
facial expressions and a yellow balloon to mime the manager’s message of
article | 513
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
dramatic decline in the company’s earnings and the extremely unpleasant
1
consequences for the staff, all while the employees look on incredulously.
Now why is this TV sketch funny? The immediate answer is that it is funny
because, like any good comedy, it undermines the familiar by turning things
upside down. The sketch depicts one of life’s most serious situations (workers
about to lose their jobs) in an unserious way (it’s a clown who tells them). But
perhaps the sketch is also funny because at another level it depicts and identifies
something familiar, or something that is about to become part of the familiar.
Perhaps it is not simply because of the sketch’s unexpected, unrealistic nature (a
clown present at a company crisis meeting) that it is funny, but also because it in
fact contains aspects that are not completely unrealistic. In other words: the
sketch may also be funny because it points to something recognizable in our
contemporary context. It displays, in an exaggerated, distorted and parodic
manner, how leadership has become interconnected with humour and a selfironic attitude.
It is precisely this linkage between management, irony and humour that is being
2
mocked by the Danish TV sketch. And more specifically, a particular aspect of
this linkage. The amusing aspect of the sketch is not only that the serious
message is not communicated by a serious manager, but by a clown. That which
we thought was serious, the layoff announcement, was in fact funny. Indeed,
1
2
Eschewing the dichotomy between ‘lived reality’ and more or less true
‘representations’ of it (as criticized by Derrida, 1978), we contend that popular culture
such as films are just as much a part of our reality than anything else, and that they
contribute to the symbolic coding of social reality like other discursive or material
artefacts. Žižek justifies studying cultural products, including films, jokes and
commercials by arguing that art is the site of cultural conceptions and symbolic
coordinates ‘expressed at their purest’ (Žižek, 2000: 250). Broadly similarly, Foucault
discarded the duality of the ‘purity of the ideal’ versus ‘the disorderly impurity of the
real’ (Foucault, 1991: 80). We follow his assertion that the fact that a particular
‘statement’, however utopian or grotesque, could be uttered at a particular juncture
inevitably takes part in diagnosing our culture. The sketch, broadcast on the comedy
program
Krysters
Kartel
(DR2),
is
available
(in
Danish)
at:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=2Xr4KfByT5g.
The American comedy series The Office contains a similar sketch in the episode
‘Halloween’. On the day of a long awaited Halloween celebration the local manager
Michael Scott, played by Steve Carell, is called up by the main office who reminds
him that he needs to dismiss an employee by the end of the day. Scott, who likes to
think of his employees as ‘his friends’, strives hard to avoid taking the decision about
who he has to dismiss – a struggle that culminates in him pretending that the extra
head (his Halloween costume) on his shoulder is telling him to let go of his assistant
regional manager. The latter refuses to resign, and now tragically comic games begin
in which employees successfully pass on the dismissal to another person. See The
Office; 2nd season; Episode 5 (2005/06).
514 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
what makes the sketch funny is that it shows us that something that we thought
could only be just for fun, the clown, is in fact deadly serious. The sketch makes
us laugh not (only) because it shows us a difference where we expected similarity
(the clown appears instead of the manager), but (also) because it shows us
likeness where we expected a difference (the clown, like the manager,
3
communicates something serious). What is really funny, and which in our view
gives the sketch a critical potential, is the humour that we normally associate
with something provocative and subversive here appears on the same side as
management. Management is not laughing ‘at’ the employees but in a way ‘with’
them. The sketch thus emphasizes that humour is not inherently opposed to
power, as we might think, and as the literature on humour has so far tended to
assume. On the contrary, there seem to be situations in which humour is quite
well-suited as a tool for exercising power in the contemporary context.
As already indicated, it is of course not realistic to imagine a situation exactly like
the Danish comedy sketch above, where a clown appears as part of a mass layoff
announcement. Nevertheless, the intertwinement of leadership and humour, we
shall argue, is quite realistic. Hence, over the last two decades, we can discern a
new trend in not only the instrumental leadership literature, where humour has
been promoted as a useful management tool (e.g. Malone, 1980; Caudron, 1992;
Barsoux, 1996), but also discussed in critical management research, where
humour at work has received increased attention (Kunda, 1991; Rodrigues and
Collinson, 1995; Collinson, 2002; Fleming and Spicer, 2003; Taylor and Bain,
2003; Bolton and Houlihan, 2009; Sørensen and Spoelstra, 2012; Westwood and
Johnston, 2012; Butler, 2015). The interest in humour as a managerial
instrument reflects a broader trend in which positive psychology and a new
discourse on happiness is gaining a growing influence as a guideline for the
organization of both our personal life and our work life. It promises to help us
live in ’wealthier’, ‘healthier’ and more ‘productive’ ways, and thus happiness
functions as an ethical standard, if not a moral obligation (Zupančič, 2008;
Ehrenreich, 2009; Cederström and Grassman, 2010; Binkley, 2011).
Considering the above developments we will raise two main arguments. First, we
believe that the Danish comedy sketch reflects something significant about the
relationship between power and humour in contemporary organizational life.
Our starting point is that humour – as pointed out in the sketch – does not stand
3
A paradigmatic example of this point is the well-known joke by from the Marx
Brothers: ‘This man looks like an idiot and he acts like an idiot, but don’t be fooled,
he is an idiot’. See Žižek (2006: 109) for a discussion of this distinction between a
form of humour which produces difference where one expects sameness, and a form
for humour which produces sameness where one expects difference.
article | 515
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
in an inherently critical opposition to management, but has begun to lend itself
to management, including humour’s ironic, cynical and subversive qualities.
More precisely, our thesis is that the managerial use of humour in contemporary
society not only seeks to instrumentalize humour’s positive effects for
management purposes, but also its critical effects. By this move, management
humour very often takes on a self-critical character. Our suggestion is particularly
inspired by Fleming and Spicer’s pioneering work on resistance, irony and
‘cynical reasoning’ in organizational life (Fleming and Spicer, 2003; 2004),
which we wish to contribute to here. In the first part of this article, we pursue our
argument on the basis of examples from the management literature. We thus
discuss and evaluate three major research approaches to the managementhumour relationship: 1) the instrumental, 2) ideology critique, and 3) critical
organization studies. Our goal is to assess the strengths and limitations of each
approach in understanding the increasing use and reception of humour in
contemporary management practices.
Second, we believe that sketches like the one above raise an important question
regarding humour’s potential for resistance: if management itself uses humour
and actually benefits from its effects in its exercise of power, is it still possible to
regard humour as critical, subversive or emancipatory? In the second part of this
article, we address this problem and offer some theoretical reflections on how a
critical, subversive humour can be conceptualized in these circumstances. We do
this by drawing on concepts originating from Lacanian psychoanalysis and
developed by Slavoj Žižek.
Hence, the object of this article is not to provide an empirical analysis, but to
assess existing approaches and help expanding the framework for analysing the
relationship between power and humour in contemporary management.
Accordingly, our assessments and contributions are primarily situated at a
theoretical and conceptual level. Furthermore, when we use the term
‘management’ here, we refer to the contemporary prevalent view of management
as activities of facilitating, stimulating, coaching and sparring, or in Foucault’s
words to perform ‘an action upon the actions of others’ (Foucault, 1982: 790).
This view of management contrasts with (the increasingly controversial)
hierarchical management, which takes the form of instructions, commands or
sanctions. In this light we may better understand the emergence of management
humour that aims precisely to stimulate, inspire or promote ‘team spirit’ and
organizational unity by mobilizing the employees’ own cultures, attitudes and
values.
516 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
Humour as gain, critique or uncontrollable surplus?
If – following Simon Critchley (2002) – we approach the matter
‘phenomenologically’, humour can be described in very broad terms as a specific
social practice, and the easiest way to identify this practice is by its impact. On
this view, the fundamental characteristics of humour are specific physiological
effects such as laughing, giggling, grinning and smiling, and emotional affects
including joy, relief, surprise, excitement and enthusiasm. Humour is not per se
these effects and affects, but rather that which causes them. These apparently
positive effects and affects are also invoked to ascribe to humour a certain
therapeutic power. However, this is not the only thing that humour is supposed
to cause. Sometimes, at least, humour is also believed to produce new
perceptions of the surrounding world as well as of oneself (Critchley, 2002: 9-11);
it makes creates a distance to the immediacy of things (including oneself), which
implies a certain critical potential (Critchley, 2002: 18). Thus, in brief, humour
can be defined as a social practice that produces certain bodily effects, emotional
affects and psychological perceptions.
Within modern management, humour, irony and laughter have altered their
status from having been perceived as fundamentally dysfunctional for
management goals and organizational effectiveness to humour being
increasingly viewed as a potential positive force (Malone, 1980; Barsoux, 1996).
In traditional management discourse, humour in the workplace was principally
viewed as undermining productivity and subverting the maintenance of
authority. Humour had therefore to be restricted, as part of the necessary
separation between job and leisure, work and pleasure. Within the last few
decades, however, we have seen the emergence of management practices that
explicitly seek to use humour as a tool for achieving various objectives. Humour
is used to promote the integration of employees and groups, to break up fixed
roles and hierarchies, contest prejudices, to get through crises such as budget
cutbacks and layoffs, and it is assumed to promote creativity and innovation in
the organization. Concrete examples of the use of humour in management
include ‘ice-breakers’, organizational theatre, corporate clowns, dress-up games
and recommendations to leaders to recognize (hidden) workplace humour as a
source of non-acknowledged knowledge about the organization.
We divide the research on humour and management into three main groups,
while recognizing that such a division can only be schematic and tentative
considering the extensive literature on humour within and beyond work life (for
a historical overview of theories of humour, see Bremmer and Roodenbrug,
1997). In the place of a detailed examination that pretends to exhaustive
article | 517
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
categorization, we will offer brief readings of three examples that represent
distinct approaches to humour in relation to management and work life.
Humour as gain
The first group is characterized by an instrumental, positive approach, which
enthusiastically sees humour as a useful and not fully exploited management
tool. This approach perceives humour solely from the management perspective:
humour can be enrolled and used as part of an optimization and streamlining of
management tasks. Here, our example is an early article by Paul Malone (1980:
357) in which he presents humour as a ‘possible tool that could assist in getting
people to get things done’. Malone recounts his own experience as a recruit in
the US Army where, after a 60-hour exercise, he and his unit were completely
exhausted. To their great frustration, however, the group received an order to
prepare for another exercise, and at that moment, the commanding officer who
had delivered the message appeared as their enemy, as a torturer. But when the
commander added a joke to the order, the mood suddenly turned to one of
hysterical laughter, creating an entirely new energy in the group, which forgot its
fatigue and could get on with the task: ‘Suddenly, the environment changed: the
Ranger instructor became a fellow man, not a torturer, the men who had laughed
together became a team with a revitalized common cause’ (Malone, 1980: 357).
The article depicts several key features that characterize the instrumental
approach to humour in management: humour is regarded as a means of
releasing built-up tensions in a moment of redemptive energy discharge, ‘a
comic relief’; humour is a way to break down stifling roles and hierarchical
positions; humour can soften the social conflicts; humour can even help
managers and others to see the world in a clearer light, avoiding the rigid
categories or simplifying performances. Most of these features echo the modern
canonical literature on laughter and humour (see Spencer, 2005). Malone’s
article is paradigmatic for the instrumental approach, in that it bluntly considers
how humour can best be appropriated by management. The principle questions
for this approach include: which leaders can utilize humour, under which
conditions can humour be used, and which forms of humour are most effective
in a management context? Malone (1980: 360) says that
It is my contention that humour is a virtually undeveloped resource that can
contribute to enhancing the satisfaction and productivity of human beings at work.
The tool has been around for quite a while, but it is used as a toy because no one
ever developed a set of instructions.
This request has been well received in the management literature. In the decades
after Malone’s article, numerous studies have appeared which provide precisely
518 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
these kinds of instructions for applying humour. They have focused on how
humour can dissolve barriers between managers and employees to produce
innovative ideas and learning (Barsoux, 1996); how theatre and play can break
down rigid stereotyping among employees (Corsun, et al., 2006), and how
‘cultures of fun’ can be used to get people to produce more by binding their
private life and entire identity to the workplace (Fleming and Spicer, 2004). In
the instrumental approach, humour is perceived as a means of freeing up the
energy and potential of managers and employees, while humour’s potentially
uncontrolled and subversive aspect is very seldom touched upon. Viewing
humour as a ‘tool to be appropriated’ by management, the instrumental position
generally ignores the ambiguities and critical potential that humorous practices
may involve.
Humour as critique of power
The second group takes a critical approach to humour, insofar as humour is
viewed as a potentially critical expressive form that employees can apply in
relation to management. This interpretation of humour’s role amounts to a
critique of power, or an ‘ideology critique’, if we understand critique as
uncovering and displaying the hierarchies, symbols and structures of domination
in work life. We write ‘potentially’ critical because many of the contributions see
humour as fundamentally subversive and difficult to control due to its informal,
hidden and often metaphorical character. Yet they often demonstrate how
humour in many cases is controlled by management or fails to achieve the
critical effect in relation to existing power structures. An objection to this
approach to humour is that it works with a too-rigid opposition between the
‘malicious’, dominant and exploitative management on the one side and a space
of playful and rebellious creativity on the other (Fleming and Spicer, 2003: 304).
An illustrative study of humour’s critical potential is a description of a union’s
satirical resistance strategies in a Brazilian telecommunications company
(Rodrigues and Collinson, 1995). The authors express a general feature of critical
studies of humour in work life: the assertion that humour can act as a resistance
strategy because of its ability to reproduce real conflicts and contradictions in
metaphorical terms. Metaphors and satire are typically ambiguous and
identifying a precise author behind them is difficult; therefore, they are
particularly useful when there is a risk of retaliation by management. The
Brazilian telecommunications company, Telecom, had an autocratic and
militaristic reputation, as illustrated by the sacking of the author of a satirical
cartoon in the union members’ magazine (Rodrigues and Collinson, 1995: 756).
The magazine had for years operated as a medium for employees and trade
union representatives’ resistance strategies, especially through anonymous
article | 519
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
cartoons. Here, the Telecom management was depicted as money-fixated,
exploitative and militaristic. Real conflicts and events could be represented in the
form of fictional characters and events that succeeded in highlighting
contradictions and paradoxes in the organization’s management practices and
caused momentary breakdowns in the managerial authority structures
(Rodrigues and Collinson, 1995: 757). In this case, the employees, through
relatively organized humour, obtained a platform to exercise leadership criticism
and gained some gradual improvements in their own working conditions.
Other contributions within this humour-as-critique approach stress that humour
as a medium (e.g. anti-authoritarian, able to display contradictions, spontaneous
and uncontrollable) does not guarantee its progressive effects. These features do
not prevent humour from being able to support or be incorporated into
management strategies. Kunda’s (1992) oft-cited study of middle managers’
ironic role-distancing in an American computer company shows just how such
behaviour can easily be appropriated by managers. The ironic attitude was
unorganized, and its occurrence was easily redefined as a demonstration of
management’s tolerance, openness and commitment to freedom of expression
(Kunda, 1992). Other critical contributions argue that humour, such as coarse
jokes, can serve to sustain hierarchies of power or subordination between the
sexes (Collinson, 2002).
In summary, this approach is critical in two ways: first, by maintaining humour’s
intrinsic subversive potential in relation to exposing power-holders and
domination; second, by considering how humour in practice is often
instrumentalized as a management technology or partakes in more or less
explicit strategies of domination. While this ideology critique perspective
provides a powerful view into the managerial appropriation of humour, it has
limitations conceptualizing in more detail the inherent ambiguities of humoristic
practices.
Humour as an indefinite surplus
The third group is subsumed under the term critical organization studies. This
group draws on post-structuralist, neo-functionalist and neo-Marxist theories in
examining humour and management (Du Gay and Salaman, 1992; Fleming and
Spicer, 2003; Sørensen and Spoelstra, 2012). The studies in this group
acknowledge the difficulty of making a clear distinction between criticalsubversive and instrumentalized humour. They do not start from a clear verdict
as to whether humour is by nature essentially subversive; instead, they
problematize the dichotomous thinking that positions the ‘good’ humour against
a ‘bad’ management that seeks to appropriate it. Hence, critical organizational
520 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
scholars often emphasize forms of interplay, reversibility and circularity between
power and humour. These studies recognize that the norms informing
management in modern organizations are not irrevocably fixed but under
continuous contestation and reconstruction. In this context, provocative and
immediately subversive behaviours may be assigned – at least momentarily – a
productive role in managerial practices.
Critical organizational scholars generally share an assumption of a circular, coproductive relationship between management and humour, although they
explore it in different ways. Some studies highlight play as a ‘doubling’ of reality.
In play, a virtual world is created where identities, relationships and values can
be put at risk and be redefined. Our example is a recent study by Sørensen and
Spoelstra (2012) who are interested in the production of virtual reality by play and
humour, yet they seek to retain humour’s autonomous character. They argue that
humour has its own logic, its own telos and its own performances that prevent it
from being appropriated completely for functional purposes (Sørensen and
Spoelstra, 2012: 2). Humour can indeed operate functionally for organizations,
exhibiting organizational difficulties, shortcomings and paradoxes, which can
then be mitigated. But Sørensen and Spoelstra (2012: 12) highlight – on the basis
of empirical evidence – that humour’s auto-logical nature makes it
fundamentally uncontrollable, in that it produces a residual surplus that breaks
with organizational needs and narrow managerial interest. In fact, humour can
become such a strong self-propelling power that it ‘usurps’, i.e. saturates the
processes and relationships of working life.
Sørensen and Spoelstra come close to our present concern, insofar as they
precisely address the interlacing of humour, management and power. However,
what is lacking in their contribution is more detailed clarification of when
humour can be said to have critical, ‘usurping’ qualities and effects, since no
precise normative or analytical criteria are given which would enable us to make
such an assessment. The remainder of the article turns to this task.
Psychoanalysis and ideology
Seeking to expand the framework for studying the role of humour in
contemporary organizations, we will offer some considerations on what
subversive humour can consist of, mainly inspired by Žižek. Žižek’s central
thesis concerning ideology – and his main contribution to the renewal of
ideology critique – is that in order for ideology to work, it always requires a
minimum degree of dis-identification in the interpellated subject: ‘An
interpellation succeeds precisely when I perceive myself as “not only that”, but a
article | 521
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
“complex person who, among other things, is also that” – in short, imaginary
distance towards symbolic identification is the very sign of its success’ (Žižek,
1999a: 258-259). Zupančič (2008: 4) underscores this insight in relation to the
relationship between humour and power:
Indeed, one can easily show that ironic distance and laughter often function as an
internal condition of all true ideology, which is characterized by the fact that it
tends to avoid direct ‘dogmatic’ repression, and has a firm hold on us precisely
where we feel most free and autonomous in our actions.
The point is that any ideological identification, if it is to function, always involves
a degree of dis-identification, since no mature, modern individual (who
understands himself or herself as free and critical thinking) will completely
4
submit to an ideological identity. As Žižek points out, ideology functions such
that ‘we perform our symbolic mandates without assuming them and “taking
them seriously”’ (2002: 70). This insight has consequences not only for our
analysis of ideology, but also for our conception of resistance: ‘One has to
abandon the idea that power operates in the mode of identification…A minimum
of disidentification is a priori necessary if power is to function’ (Žižek, 2000:
218).
Žižek usually stresses the implicit self-distancing in the ideological interpellation
5
by using the following formula: ‘I know very well, but still...’. Following this
formula, he describes contemporary ideology – borrowing from Peter Sloterdijk
– as a form of ‘cynical reason’ (Žižek, 1991: 29). The ‘cynical’ refers, first, to the
ideological subject acting against better knowledge. Žižek likes to illustrate this
point with the following anecdote about the Danish physicist Niels Bohr. Bohr
was once visited at home by a famous scientist. The latter noticed a horseshoe
hanging over the door and asked Bohr indignantly: ‘Well, my dear Niels Bohr,
you don’t think that this kind of thing brings good luck, do you?’. ‘No, no, of
course I don’t’, Bohr reassured him, ‘but I’ve heard that it also brings good luck
4
Whether Žižek understands the ‘cynical’ or ‘fetishist’ character of ideology as a
historical specific (in contrast to for instance a ‘symptomatic’) mode of ideology or as
a general feature of ideology as such remains unclear. However, he tends to relate
ideology as form of cynicism that relies on dis-identification to a diagnosis of
modernity as a ‘crisis of investiture’, most evident in the impasse of the paternal
figure, which results in a general reluctance against identifying with received
symbolic mandates (Žižek, 2004: 148).
5
Žižek borrows this formula from a famous article by the Lacanian psychoanalyst
Octave Mannoni for whom it summarizes the logic of the perversion of fetishism,
which, according to Freud, is precisely a simultaneous recognition and disavowal of
the trauma of castration (the phallus is both renounced and kept in the form of a
fetish object) (Mannoni, 2003; Freud, 1955c).
522 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
even if you don’t believe in it’ (Žižek, 2008: 300). Second, the cynical refers to
ideology admitting to its ideological character, such as when an advertising
executive shamelessly says, ‘Yes, of course we try to manipulate you into buying
our product’. However, ideology can only put its cards on the table in this way
because it works – paradoxically, not in spite of but because of our critical
distance to it and to that part of ourselves partaking in the ideology. One might
say, then, that ideological interpellation only succeeds when it does not succeed
6
completely.
This self-distancing (dis-identification), which is the precondition for ideology, is
reinforced by ideology’s invitation to criticize, ridicule and create ironic distance
to it. When we criticize the ideological interpellation and distance ourselves from
it ironically, we thereby confirm the idea that we are in reality different – more
valuable, authentic and free – than that very self who acts in accordance with the
ideology (Žižek, 2001: 13-14). In other words, when Žižek asserts that it is not
through our identification with ideology but precisely through our more or less
conscious distancing from it that ideology is maintained, his point is that
‘ideology’ is itself the perception that there is a dividing line between reality (a
true self) and ideology (our ‘everyday self’); this dividing line reveals itself in our
ironic and critical distancing from ideology.
‘Ideology’, therefore, is not an illusion that conceals reality from us. For Žižek,
ideology is instead the very act of designating something as ideology, i.e. as an
illusion, by adding ‘critical distance’, ‘revealing’, ‘transgressing’ and ‘freeing
ourselves’ from it. Hence, as mentioned earlier, we maintain ideology precisely
through perpetuating the notion that we can avoid, breach, eliminate, emancipate
or separate ourselves from ideology. Žižek’s point, therefore, is that it is this very
procedure, of stepping out of ideology, i.e. the very distinguishing of ideology
(illusion) from non-ideology (reality), that constitutes the fundamental
mechanism of ideology (Žižek, 1999b: 71).
6
Readers familiar with Žižek’s work might hear in this formulation an echo of his
well-known description of the Lacanian subject in terms of the failure of
subjectivation, the remainder or gap that resists symbolization. However, we must
avoid such conflation. Žižek emphasizes: ‘For Lacan the dimension of subjectivity
that eludes symbolic identification is not the imaginary wealth/texture of experience
which allows me to assume an illusory distance towards my symbolic identity: the
Lacanian “barred subject” (s) is “empty” not in the sense of some psychologicoexistential “experience of a void” but, rather, in the sense of a dimension of selfrelating negativity, which a priori eludes the domain of lived experience’ (Žižek,
1999a: 259; emphasis in original; see also Dolar, 1993).
article | 523
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
Fantasy and cynicism
This distinguishing operation is based on fantasies, or more precisely
unconscious fantasies, about the ‘genuine thing’; ‘the subject who is supposed to
know’ in contrast to the ignorant, ‘the subject who is supposed to believe’ in
contrast to the enlightened, ‘the subject who is supposed to loot and rape’ in
contrast to the good law abiding citizen. In other words, fantasies are fantasies of
wholeness, completeness, fullness (e.g. of the omnipotent primordial father)
covering up a basic impasse (in psychoanalytical terms: castration, sexual
relationship, the desire of the Other, the Real, etc.). Or, as Žižek formulates it:
‘Fantasy is basically a scenario filling out the empty space of a fundamental
impossibility, a screen masking a void’ (Žižek, 1989: 126). In fact, fantasies have
a double function insofar as they both shape our desires and protect us against
our desires: ‘In this intermediated position lies the paradox of fantasy: it is the
frame co-ordinating our desire, but at the same time a defence against ‘Che
vuoi?’, a screen concealing the gap, the abyss of desire of the Other’ (Žižek, 1989:
118). Fantasies structures our social reality (our desires) in a way that ‘fills out its
empty space’, and this is what is concealed by ideology, not reality (Žižek, 1989:
32-33). In regard to cynicism, Žižek (1989: 33) asserts: ‘Cynical distance is just
one way – one of many – to blind ourselves to the structuring power of
ideological fantasy’.
That Žižek’s conception of ideology has consequences for the analysis of the
relationship between power, humour and resistance can be illustrated with a
short reference to Critchley’s book On humour. Here, Critchley briefly touches
upon the theme of humour as a management tool. Part of his account is an
anecdote about a group of employees staying at the same hotel as him. He
observes them one morning engaged in playing kick-ball, ping pong and Frisbee,
or as he calls it ‘structured fun’. After breakfast, he meets some of them outside
for a cigarette exchanging a few words. He writes:
I was enormously reassured that they felt just as cynical about the whole business
as I did, but one of them said that they did not want to appear to be a bad sport or
a party pooper at work and that this was why they went along with it. (Critchley,
2002: 13)
In Critchley’s (2002: 13-14) view, the cynical stance of the employees was an
indication of their resistance, or as he puts it:
I think this incident is interesting for it reveals a vitally subversive feature of
humour in the workplace. Namely, that as much as management consultants
might try and formalize fun for the benefit of the company […] such fun is always
capable of being ridiculed by informal, unofficial relations amongst employees, by
backchat and salacious gossip.
524 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
From a Žižekian perspective, Critchley’s analysis is obviously problematic.
Critchley completely misses that it is precisely the informal cynical (self-joking)
attitude of the employees that makes up the basis of the formalized, structured
fun of the management: ‘We know very well (that this structured fun is the
company’s stupid attempt to manipulate us), but nonetheless (we go along with it
7
not to appear as a bad sport)’. Surely Critchley (2002: 14) is right when he
concludes that ‘[h]umour might well be a management tool but it is also a tool
against the management’. However, his more or less explicit claim that a cynical
distance – or as he points out later in the same book, humour as self-ridicule is
in itself a kind of resistance – is highly questionable. The same goes for his
distinction between (suppressive) formal and (subversive) informal humour.
Žižek can thus supplement critical organizational research on humour in several
regards, which we discuss in more detail below.
In this light, it is noteworthy that a number of recent critical organizational
studies and studies in the sociology of work demonstrate empirically how power
relations in work life are reproduced by employees by means of humour (Kunda,
1991; Willmott, 1993; Du Gay and Salaman, 1992). Kunda’s (1991)
aforementioned study describes how employees’ humorous mocking of official
business rituals were used as proof of the management’s liberal openness, while
at the same time employees actually performed their tasks to perfection. Du Gay
and Salaman’s (1992) article on ‘entrepreneurialism’ shows that even if
individuals do not take entrepreneurial discourse and its ideal of excellence
seriously and maintain an ironic distance towards it, they nevertheless practice it
to the fullest in their daily life. And Willmott (1993) demonstrates that people
interpret their possibilities to ironically challenge the corporate culture as proof
of their self-determination, and that this promotes a frictionless exercise of
organizational functions. Common to these studies is their demonstration that
‘cynical’ employees maintain the idea that they are autonomous agents who have
a distance from the management ideology, but they nevertheless perform the
company’s rituals to the maximum. None of these studies, however, address the
problem of which humorous strategies could transgress the demonstrated
(ideological) reproduction.
7
Žižek criticizes Critchley’s interpretation of Freud’s ‘humorous’ superego, which in
contrast to the classical ‘cruel’ superego that suppresses us by debasing our ego,
liberates us by enabling the ego to laugh at its own shortcomings (Critchley, 2002:
93-111; 2007: 77-84). Žižek argues that ‘[w]hat Critchley strangely leaves out of
consideration is the brutal “sadistic” aspect of humour itself: humour can be
extremely cruel and denigrating’ (2008: 341). The point is that the ‘humorous
superego’ might indeed be as cruel as the (straightforward) ‘cruel superego’ exactly
by exerting humour.
article | 525
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
Subversive humour?
Fleming and Spicer are pioneers in introducing the concept of ‘cynical reasoning’
into critical organization studies (2003; 2004), which constitutes a key lynchpin
for discussing how to conceptualize subversive practices of humour. Our initial
example with the ‘corporate clown’ poses a question in terms of the degree to
which cynicism fits into contemporary management: has it become legitimate to
accompany difficult management decisions like layoffs with humour so that they
may be more easily ‘swallowed’ by employees? (George Clooney’s ironic
performance in the film Up in the air is another example of accepted, blatant
cynicism consisting in the routine of bringing in an outsider to do
management’s dirty work).
In this situation, it is obvious that adding elements of self-caricature and
‘clowning’ to the management role may be strategically useful, as the clown is a
character against whom it is hard to exert serious critique: how do you mock a
character who is already clowning around? Faced with this kind of ‘fun-filled’,
self-ironic management, every form of irony and caricature seems destined to
fail, as it is already incorporated within the manager’s character, who can
effortlessly embrace the very distancing that supposedly forms the backbone of
humorous resistance. Management takes over the clowning around, and humour
becomes a leadership quality.
The question, then, is what kind of humour can operate critically and
subversively? Traditional forms of parody, irony and ridicule easily end up being
co-productive and supporting contemporary management practices, according to
the above research. With inspiration from Žižek and Zupančič, we will now
propose two possible analytical strategies for indicating practices of subversive
humour. These involve looking for:
I.
II.
Humour that is directed towards undermining the symbolic order by
targeting ‘master signifiers’ and practising ‘over-identification’.
Humour that exhibits and maintains incongruence.
Here, we follow Žižek’s premise that any power structure generates an excess of
resistance from within its inherent dynamics. The fact that resistance is thus
immanent to power in no way implies that every act of resistance is co-opted in
the structure, since ‘the very inherent antagonism of a system may well set in
motion a process which leads to its own ultimate downfall’ (Žižek, 1999a: 256).
Žižek asserts that our position becomes stronger if we claim that our resistance is
grounded in the system itself, articulating inherent antagonisms which may
undermine its unity and reproductive capacity. This is possible insofar as the
526 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
symbolic order is always by definition ‘decentred’ around a constitutive void or
impossibility. Fundamentally, it is a matter of generating confrontations with
‘the real’, which we understand as naming the failure of the symbolic order in
achieving its own closure. The real becomes the effects of the failure of
symbolization, evident as irruptions, impasses and impossibilities inherent in
the Symbolic itself (Laclau, 2000: 68).
Humour as over-identification
Our first suggestions concern humour that displays the inherent antagonisms of
the symbolic order, particularly targeting postulates of unity, cohesion and
homogeneity. Preventing full closure of the symbolic order, antagonisms are to
be understood not as objective social relations, but rather as ‘the point where the
limit of all objectivity is shown’ (Laclau, 2000: 72). Unifying concepts like
‘participatory management’, ‘cooperative values’, and ‘common rewards’ are
proliferating in contemporary management discourse. ‘Diversity management’,
on the contrary, invokes the idea that although our values and interests are
indeed divergent, we nevertheless benefit from ‘cooperation in difference’. In
both cases, the symbolic order is one in which all parties take their natural place
in a harmonious whole. Such a hegemonic articulation depends upon a rallying
of diverse identities to a reconciliatory representation of the organization or social
positions. In this process of contingent, partial fixation, one particular signifier
assumes the function of unifying representation. Developing Lacan’s notion of
‘Master Signifier’, Laclau (2000: 70-71) defines ‘the empty signifier’ as a
discursive element which achieves its unifying function by cancelling out its
specific content, thereby allowing diverse actors and groups to identify with it. Its
signifying content depends not on any non-discursive substance but on its
position within a chain of signifiers which endeavour to suture the empty
signifier, fixating its meaning (Laclau, 2000: 71). Sustaining its privileged
function requires that the signifier’s impossibility as a particular representing the
universal is not effectively exposed.
Humour, which demonstrates the empty signifier’s fragility and fictive
universality, has subversive potential because it reveals how a postulated
wholeness covers primordial lack, antagonism and non-identity. More precisely,
humour can generate a process of contamination of the empty signifier by
infusing it with diverse, incongruent content, thereby ‘overburdening’ its
universalizing function. Such contamination may undermine the chain of
equivalences and open space for substitutions and whole new articulations: ‘a
certain meaning which was fixated within the horizon of an ensemble of
institutionalized practices is displaced towards new uses which subvert its
literality’ (Laclau, 2000: 78). Imagine, for instance, an organization in which the
article | 527
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
signifier ‘our corporate vision’ is equated with ‘team-spirit’, ‘individual
performance’, ‘achieving sector bench marks’ and ‘our unique qualities’ that all
endeavour to fill its void. Here, humorous interventions could insist on
simultaneously articulating these particular and incommensurable representations
of the organization. Such an insistence on incommensurable identities may overburden and contaminate the empty signifier and the entire hegemonic formation
that finds support in it.
A humorous attack on empty signifiers can also be directed towards moments of
irruption or collapse which are always inherent potentials of symbolic orders.
Returning to our initial example of layoff announcements that operate with the
help of a company clown, there is a momentary imbalance in the symbolic order,
whose hegemonic representation is unity – that management and employees are
part of a common, mutually rewarding project. However, the tragic-comedic
moment arises when the clown pops up and displays the impossibility of the
assertion of harmonious union and non-conflictuality.
Another possible strategy of humorous destabilization of the symbolic order
consists of over-identifying with it (see Fleming and Spicer, 2003: 172-173).
Rather than putting ironic distance to the positions and prescriptions directed at
employees, an effective strategy could consist of completely embracing and
overdoing them. Or, as Žižek asserts:
In so far as power relies on its ‘inherent transgression’, then – sometimes, at least
– over-identifying with the explicit power discourse – ignoring this inherent
obscene underside and simply taking the power discourse at its (public) word,
acting as if it really means what it explicitly says (and promises) – can be the most
effective way of disturbing its smooth functioning. (Žižek, 2000: 220)
The premise is that any power structure relies on its ‘inherent transgression’,
exemplified by the rule of law which relies on its inherent and continual
transgression without which it disintegrates (Žižek, in Contu, 2008: 368). The
fact that these acts of resistance and transgression are integral to power does not
make it untouchable, but renders it vulnerable to acts that simply take its claims
and propositions literally. This may include humour that fully identifies with
such claims, even excessively, and hence collapses the self-distance operative in
symbolic positions: ‘we touch the Real when the efficiency of such symbolic
markers of distance is suspended’ (Žižek, 2000: 223). Such over-identification
can be very humorous and can reveal the antagonistic kernel of a specific social
arrangement or position. For example, one might imagine that employees, in
introducing ‘lean management’, which requires continuous generation of ideas
from the rank and file, take advantage of this new position to drown
management in an abundance of impossible and mutually contradictory
528 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
proposals for new work routines, technologies, customer care, etc. This practice
is difficult to sanction, in that the employees are doing precisely what is officially
expected of them, although in a too literal manner. In our example with the
company clown, a strategy of over-identification could consist in the remaining
employees’ insistence on joking about the negative budget balance – a practice
that was sanctioned by management when it hired a clown to help inform
employees about this. By dissolving the distinction between humorous
representation and harsh reality, the employees effectively display both
managerial incompetence and the collapse of meaning. According to Žižek, no
amount of disguising such misfortunes with a joke or irony can prevent it from
having a hurtful effect: ‘This collapse of the distinction between pretending and
being is the unmistakable sign that my speech has touched some real’ (Žižek,
2000: 223). Again, this underlines the uncontrollable and potentially subversive
character of humour.
The minimal difference of humour
Our second proposal is based on a certain idea of humour, which in humour
literature is usually described as ‘the incongruence theory’ (e.g. Moreall, 1981;
Critchley, 2002; Billig, 2005). This humour theory has its roots in Kant and is
further developed by Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard. Also, both Zupančič’s and
Žižek’s reflections on humour, which we will rely on here, can be read as an
example of incongruence theory. According to this theory, humour is perceived
as misalignment or incongruity between the reality as we expect that it will look
like, and the reality as it is expressed, for example in a sketch, a comic story or a
practical joke (Critchley, 2002: 3). However, Morreall (1981: 245) emphasizes that
not all incongruence is comical since incongruence can also cause negative
emotions such as anger or fear. Freud (1955a: 246) remarked upon this aspect in
his famous text on ‘The uncanny’, discussing the intrinsic connection between
the comic and the uncanny:
Then the theme that achieves such an indubitably uncanny effect, the involuntary
recurrence of the like, serves, too, other and quite different purposes in another
class of cases. One case we have already heard about in which it is employed to call
forth a feeling of the comic.
It is the repetition that, according to Freud, links the uncanny and the comic.
More specifically, the repetition (of the same) may reveal that the same, i.e. the
identical, perhaps does not totally accord with itself, is non-identical, and thereby
8
create a situation where the repetition becomes comical (or uncanny). Here,
8
Another comic (and disturbing) aspect of repetition is the stubbornness or
steadfastness which it entails (this becomes especially clear when repetition is related
article | 529
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
humour exhibits, plays on and plays with this division in the heart of the same in
the core of any identity. Zupančič (2008: 58) also formulates this point with
reference to Lacan’s concept of the real:
[T]he Real ‘exposed’ by comedy is […] the structural Real (or impasse) the
suppression of which constitutes the very coherence of our reality. […] Comedy
succeeds in displaying the crack in the midst of our most familiar realities.
One of the places where humour, according to Zupančič, makes its presence felt
most clearly in this sense is in the question of ‘reality’. There is something
unrealistic about the reality of humour that creates an incongruence between the
reality of humour (where the realistic and the unrealistic tend to coincide) and
the realistic perception of reality, which we are presented with most of the time.
This unrealistic – or ‘real’, in Lacanian terms – element of the reality of humour
is for instance expressed partly in the form of a ‘blind’ insistence, such as when
the cat in a Tom and Jerry cartoon keeps on chasing the mouse, even though Tom
always ends up being beaten to a pulp. This insistence is unrealistic in the sense
that it does not take into account what is dictated to be practical, convenient or
realistic. Or, putting it differently, (good) humour involves a dimension that is
‘beyond the pleasure and the reality principle’. Zupančič (2008: 217-218) often
9
employs the psychoanalytic concept of (death) drive to illustrate this dimension.
A key feature of the death drive, as is well-known, is that it involves an obsession
to repetition (hence, Freud [1955b] describes it as ‘conservative’). However, any
repetition also entails a minimal displacement (and thus an element of novelty).
The concept of ‘drive’ encompasses a particular conception of the relationship
and interplay between identity (repetition) and difference (displacement) which
can be utilized in the analysis of humour. The theory of incongruence can thus
be refined by the distinction (borrowed from Žižek) between, on the one hand,
situations that are comical because they show us a difference where we expected
similarity and, on the other, situations that are comical because they show us
identity where we expected difference. Accordingly, we can distinguish between
two types of incongruence. First, the form of incongruence that can arise when
two fundamentally different things meet or are joined together (as in the initial
to failure) (see Zupančič, 2008: 29-20). Freud similarly pointed out that the
neurotic’s compulsion to repeat can have both a comic and a disturbing effect (Freud,
1955a: 236-238). See also Zupančič (2005).
9
Conversely, according to Zupančič (2008: 126), the comic constitutes a good
introduction to the psychoanalytic concept of drives. There is an important
interconnection between the (Freudian) concept of drive and the (Lacanian) concept
of the real: ‘drive involves the Real of compulsion to repeat that is by definition
“beyond the pleasure principle”’ (Žižek, 1999a: 295).
530 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
corporate clown example). And second, the kind of incongruence that may arise
when two similar things are united (such as the Marx Brothers’ ‘idiot’ joke
mentioned in footnote 2). In the latter case, the incongruity arises in that the
repetition of the same produces a ‘minimal difference’ between two identical
things. In this way, it is shown that at the foundation of every identity lies an
internal division. Or as Žižek explains: ‘This very lack of difference between the
two elements confronts us with the “pure” difference that separates an element
from itself’ (Žižek, 2006: 109). Hence, the difference and sameness on which
humour plays is, as suggested, not a difference between the reality and a more or
less unreal representation of reality, but rather a ‘pure’ or ‘minimal’ difference
incarnated in reality itself. It is a minimal difference which, according to
Zupančič, is expressed when humour displays that there is something in our life
that lives its own life, i.e. the drive, the Real (Zupančič, 2008: 218).
Attempts to bring the subject into contact with himself, e.g. in the form of
moments of ‘comic relief’, theatrical role transgression, or momentary openings
of authentic speech (Karlsen and Villadsen, 2008) all attempt to conceal this
unruliness, this fundamental lack of closure, and yet at the same time produce a
potential self-undermining excess. In other words: there is something
uncontrollable, something inherently disturbing, even self-sabotaging, about
humour. Managers who try to exploit humour as a tool for managerial control
will, paradoxically, always be introducing an element of something ambiguous
and uncontrollable into the organization.
Concluding remarks
Some researchers have emphasized that workplace humour, parodies, irony and
the like are easily absorbed by management and thus do not comprise any sort of
fundamental threat to the dominant organization of work life (Kunda, 1991;
Collinson, 1992; Du Gay and Salaman, 1992; Contu, 2008). Contu goes so far as
to propose that researchers tend to seek out hidden or carnivalesque forms of
resistance in order to convince ourselves that there are still pockets of resistance
in the undergrowth of workplaces which escape the iron grip of discipline. In this
way, hidden forms of everyday resistance are idealized. She relies on Žižek’s
assertion that inherent transgressions of the symbolic order in fact constitute the
ultimate support of this order. Much of the resistance that organizational
researchers observe is in fact ‘decaf resistance’, a resistance that threatens no one
and which has no real social costs. Even if humoristic forms of resistance takes a
carnivalesque or obscene character, they are ‘decaf’ insofar as they ‘do not
seriously challenge the economic reproduction of both producers and
consumers’ (Contu, 2008: 368). Instead, Contu seeks out genuine acts of
article | 531
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
resistance, the ‘impossible act of resistance’, impossible because it is not based
upon or contained within the official discourse and norms against which the act
is being exercised (Contu, 2008: 370). It should be acts of resistance which
fundamentally challenge and undermine the symbolic order (our meaningattributing structures of language and symbols) and, in this sense, entail high
costs.
We have attempted to demonstrate that humour (at least certain forms of
humorous practice) contains such a potential for resistance. It does not, however,
necessarily have to be forms of humour resistance that fundamentally alter the
symbolic order of the organization. More modest forms of distortions, exposures
and calling things into question can (also) open up spaces for confrontation with
the failure of closure of the symbolic. Above, we have sought to call attention to
the fact that while humour may be managerially useful, it always entails a form
of evasive excess, an unavoidable, uncontrollable dimension that makes it risky
for those in power to appropriate it, and which therefore endows humour
strategies with a subversive, critical potential.
Contu (2008: 379) encourages us to abandon the belief that there is an ultimate
authority that can justify the attitudes which guide our actions and take on the
full and terrifying responsibility for them:
The real act of resistance, the act proper, is an act where one assumes fully the
responsibility for the act itself, without ‘if’ and without ‘but,’ risking all and
effectively choosing the impossible, in this sense, ‘traversing the fantasy,’ as Žižek
put it.
While we sympathize with this idea of such a ‘genuine’ or ‘real act of resistance’,
it seems unrealistic as an imperative for the vast majority of subordinate
employees who find themselves in structures consisting of very real authorities,
responsibilities, and risk of sanctions. Therefore, apart from the future work of
theorizing a subversive humour, we need to begin investigating how humorous
practices interact with entirely different forms of dominance, resistance and
struggle (Fleming and Spicer, 2003: 171). It follows from our understanding of
humour as highly ambiguous and difficult to control that its concrete effects
must be studied in relation to other social practices and power relations and
situated in the context of specific organizational cultures, identities, languages,
and hierarchies. Hence, this contribution is an invitation to undertake both
further theoretical elaborations and empirical studies of the interlacing of
humour and managerial power in specific organizational contexts. In this way we
can begin to better understand corporate clowns and other ‘uncanny’ instances of
humour that allow management to negotiate (and re-negotiate) their relationship
532 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
with employees. And we can explore this game from the premise that its
outcome is hardly ever completely controllable or determined in advance.
references
Barsoux, J-L. (1996) ‘Why organizations need humour’, European Management
Journal, 14(5): 500-508.
Binkley, S. (2011) ‘Happiness, positive psychology and the program of neoliberal
governmentality’, Subjectivity, 4(4): 371-394.
Bolton, S.C., and M. Houlihan (2009) ‘Are we having fun yet? A consideration of
workplace fun and engagement’, Employee Relations, 32(6): 556-568.
Bremmer, G. and J. Roodenbrug (eds.) (1997) Cultural history of humour: From
antiquity to the present day. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Butler, N. (2015) ‘Joking aside: Theorizing laughter in organizations’, Culture and
Organization, 21(1): 42-58.
Caudron, S. (1992) ‘Humour is healthy in the workplace’, Personnel Journal,
71(6): 63-68.
Cederström, C. and R. Grassman (2010) ‘The unbearable weight of happiness’,
in C. Cederström and C. Hoedemaekers (eds.) Lacan and organization.
London: MayFly.
Collinson, D. L. (2002) ‘Managing humour’, Journal of Management Studies,
39(3): 269-289.
Contu, A. (2008) ‘Decaf resistance: Misbehaviour, desire and cynicism in liberal
workplaces’, Management Communication Quarterly, 21(3): 364-379.
Corsun, D. L., C. A. Young, A. McManus and M. Erdem (2006) ‘Overcoming
managers’ perceptual shortcuts through improvisational theatre training’,
Journal of Management Development, 25(4): 298-315.
Critchley, S. (2002) On humour. London: Routledge.
Derrida, J. (1978) ‘The theatre of cruelty and the closure of representation’, in
Writing and difference. Chicago: UCP.
Dolar, M. (1993) ‘Beyond interpellation’, Qui Parle, 6(2): 75-96
Du Gay, P. and G. Salaman (1992) ‘The cult(ure) of the customer’, Journal of
Management Studies, 29(5): 615-633.
Ehrenreich, B. (2009) Smile or die: How positive thinking fooled America and the
world. London: Granta.
Fleming, P. and A. Spicer (2003) ‘Working at a cynical distance: Implications for
subjectivity, power and resistance’, Organization, 10(1): 157-179.
Fleming, P. and A. Spicer (2004) ‘“You can checkout anytime, but you can never
leave”: Spatial boundaries in a high commitment organization’, Human
Relations, 57(1): 75-94.
Foucault, M. (1982) ‘The subject and power’, Critical Inquiry, 8(4): 777-795.
article | 533
ephemera: theory & politics in organization
15(3): 513-535
Foucault, M. (1991) ‘Questions of method’, in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P.
Miller (eds.) The Foucault effect: Studies in governmentality. Chicago: UCP.
Freud, S. (1955a [1919]) ‘The uncanny’, in The standard edition of the complete
psychological works of Sigmund Freud, XVII. London: The Hogarth Press.
Freud, S. (1955b [1920]) ‘Beyond the pleasure principle’, in The standard edition of
the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, XVIII. London: The Hogarth
Press.
Freud, S. (1955c) ‘Fetishism’, in The standard edition of the complete psychological
works of Sigmund Freud, XXI. London: The Hogarth Press.
Karlsen, M.P. and K. Villadsen (2008) ‘Who should do the talking? The
proliferation of dialogue as governmental technology’, Culture and
Organization, 14(4): 345-363.
Kunda, G. (1991) Engineering culture: Control and commitment in a high-tech
corporation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Laclau, E. (2000) ‘Identity and hegemony’, in J. Butler, E. Laclau and S. Žižek
(eds.) Contingency, hegemony, universality. London: Verso.
Malone, P. (1980) ‘Humor: A double-edged tool for today’s managers?’, Academy
of Management Review, 5(3): 357-36.
Mannoni, O. (2003) ‘“I know very well, but all the same...”’, in M.A. Rothenberg,
S. Žižek and D.A. Foster (eds.) Perversion and the social relation. Durham:
Duke University Press.
Morreall, J. (1981) ‘A new theory of laughter’, Philosophical Studies, 42(2): 243254.
Rodrigues, S.B. and D.L. Collinson (1995) ‘“Having fun?”: Humour as
Rresistance in Brazil’, Organization Studies, 16(5): 739-768.
Sloterdijk, P. (1988) Critique of cynical reason. Minnesota: University of
Minnesota Press.
Spencer, H. (2005) ‘The physiology of laughter’, in Illustrations of universal
progress. Boston: Adamant Media Corporation.
Sørensen, B.M. and S. Spoelstra (2012) ‘Play at work: Continuation, intervention
and usurpation’, Organization, 19(2): 81-97.
Taylor, P. and P. Bain (2003) ‘“Subterranean worksick blues”: Humour as
subversion in two call centres’, Organization Studies, 24(9): 1487-1509.
The Office (2005/06) Second season, episode 5: ‘Halloween’.
Westwood, R. and A. Johnston (2012) ‘Reclaiming authentic selves: Control,
resistive humour and identity work in the office’, Organization, 19(6): 787–
808.
Willmott, H. (1993) ‘Strength is ignorance; slavery is freedom: Managing culture
in modern organizations’, Journal of Management Studies, 30(4): 515-552
Žižek, S. (1989) The sublime object of ideology. London: Verso.
Žižek, S. (1999a) The ticklish subject: The absent centre of political ideology. London:
Verso.
534 | article
Mads Peter Karlsen and Kaspar Villadsen
Laughing for real?
Žižek, S. (1999b) ‘The spectre of ideology’, in E. Wright and E. Wright (eds.) The
Žižek reader. Oxford: Blackwell.
Žižek, S. (2000) ‘Da capo senze fine’, in J. Butler, E. Laclau and S. Žižek (Eds.)
Contingency, Hegemony, Universality. London: Verso.
Žižek, S. (2002) Welcome to the desert of the Real. London: Verso.
Žižek, S. (2004) Iraq: The borrowed kettle. London: Verso.
Žižek, S. (2006) The parallax view. Boston: MIT Press.
Žižek, S. (2008) In defence of lost causes. London: Verso.
Zupančič, A. (2008) The odd one in: On comedy. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Zupančič, A. (2005) ‘Reversals of nothing: The case of the sneezing corpse’,
Filozofski vestnik, 26(2): 176-186.
the authors
Kaspar Villadsen is Professor at the Department of Management, Politics and
Philosophy, Copenhagen Business School. He is the author of the books Power and
welfare: Citizens’ encounters with state welfare (co-authored with Nanna Mik-Meyer, 2013,
Routledge) and Statephobia and civil society (co-authored with Mitchell Dean, forthcoming,
Stanford University Press). Villadsen has published on Foucault, organizations,
biopolitics and welfare policy in Economy and Society, Theory, Culture and Society,
Organization, Constellations, Social Theory and Health, Culture and Organization and more.
His current research is on governmental technologies, health promotion, and the
problem of state and civil society.
Email:
[email protected]
Mads Peter Karlsen is Assistant Professor at the Department of Management, Politics
and Philosophy, Copenhagen Business School. He did his PhD thesis on Alain Badiou
and Slavoj Žižek. He is the author of the book Pastoralmagt: Om velfærdssamfundets kristne
arv (2008) and the editor (with Lars Sandbeck) of the books Religionskritik efter Guds død
(2009) and Kristendom og engagement: Peter Kemps teologi til debat (2014). Karlsen has
published on Foucault, Badiou and Žižek in New Political Science, Journal for Critical
Research on Religion and International Journal of Žižek Studies. His current research is on
the interrelationship between theology and psychoanalysis.
Email:
[email protected]
article | 535