Symposium
John Rawls: An Introduction
Brooke Ackerly
The References for all articles in this Symposium have
been compiled and begin on page 128. Authors’ citations
include the following abbreviations for works by John
Rawls:
JAF
(1985) “Justice as Fairness: Political Not
Metaphysical”
JFR (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement
LP (1999) The Law of Peoples
PL (1996) Political Liberalism
TJ
(1999) A Theory of Justice
magine for a moment, that we—we in this liberal
democracy—want to design the basic institutions of our
economic and political interactions so that they are just.
In order that just institutions be designed fairly, we will
not be allowed to reason from our own particular circumstances. We are not to know our own race or religion, our
own material resources, or even our own personal abilities
and whether these abilities are valued by our society. Imagine that once this “veil of ignorance” about ourselves is
lifted, we might discover that we are the person least advantaged by racist social norms or least advantaged by the
relative value that our society places on skills (for example,
that we have the skills of a seamstress, not of a professional
basketball player). In this view of the bases for an agreement about first principles of justice, the things that we
think of as “ours”—our innate skills and those we develop
through education and commitment—do not entitle us
to the benefits of deploying them in our political economy. Instead, our personal endowments and the value that
society puts on them are morally arbitrary. From the moral
view of this “original position”, choosing the principles
used to guide the distribution of the benefits that accrue
from exercising these should be a political decision that we
make together. Yet, imagining that we might be a seamstress, a basketball player, or unemployable, each of us
reasons the same way. Because of the empathy required in
the original position, the original position describes a moral
and political position. Since we reason the same way, we
agree on principles that should guide the design of our
basic institutions. The institutions that distribute political, social, and economic costs and benefits in our society
will thereby be just and promote stability and continued
social cooperation.1 Imagining about what would be fair,
I
Brooke Ackerly is Assistant Professor at Vandervilt University (
[email protected]). She is the author of
Political Theory and Feminist Social Criticism (2000).
Special thanks to W. James Booth, to the participants in the
Vanderbilt interdisciplinary theory seminar Mark Brandon,
John Goldberg, Steve Hetcher, Bob Talisse, and John
Weymark and to Talisse, John Geer, and the anonymous
reviewers of Perspectives on Politics.
March 2006 | Vol. 4/No. 1 75
Symposium
|
John Rawls and the Study of Politics
we create the conditions for a just original social agreement and continued social cooperation, “justice as fairness”.
Through this device of the original position and other
methods of philosophical argument, John Rawls stimulated our discussions about the foundations of social
cooperation within liberal societies and among states.2
Consequently, when he passed away in 2002, he left legacies of inquiry and debate not only in philosophy but
also in other disciplines in which the study of social cooperation is foundational, including economics, education,
law, and political science.
In this symposium we ask to what extent is Rawlsian
liberalism informed by, or potentially informative in thinking about, issues in democratic and international politics.
Each of our authors has an answer. Simone Chambers
finds Rawls too accommodating of real world economic
inequalities. Iris Young finds Rawls’s justice as fairness insufficiently attentive to real world processes that generate
social inequalities. Russell Muirhead and Nancy Rosenblum argue that Rawls’s political liberalism is instructive
in thinking about political parties. Michael Doyle finds
Rawls’s account of international law and relations in one
sense appropriate to contemporary challenges regarding
global justice and in another sense disconnected from the
reality of international politics. Peter Berkowitz argues that
Rawls is insufficiently reflective on his own metaphysical
foundations for his theoretical argument to have the universal appeal to which he aspires.
Rawls would welcome this line of engagement. With
his method of philosophical inquiry, he sought to build
coherence among our deeply held convictions and our
familiar practices, yielding “reflective equilibrium” between
our ideas and our ability to justify them to ourselves and
to one another.
Not only do our considered judgments often differ from those of
other persons, but our own judgments are sometimes in conflict
with one another . . . Those who suppose their judgments are
always consistent are unreflective or dogmatic . . . The question
arises: how can we make our own considered judgments of political justice more consistent both within themselves and with the
considered judgments of others without imposing on ourselves
an external political authority? . . . The most reasonable political
conception for us is the one that best fits all our considered
convictions on reflection and organizes them in a coherent view.
At any given time, we cannot do better than that.3
However, in putting forward his account, Rawls challenges us to do better, and the contributors to this symposium each suggest ways in which we might.
In order to set up the reader for the substantive essays
to follow, I introduce the key concepts Rawls uses in developing his political thought and the principle political obstacles to social cooperation which were the political context
in which he developed his account of liberalism.4 Rawls’s
assumptions, his central concepts, his method of political
theory, and his arguments have generated intense and often
76 Perspectives on Politics
fertile controversy. My principal purpose is to introduce
the terrain of Rawlsian inquiry. The contestation over the
content and the boundaries of this terrain has been extensive and deep, a limited sampling of which can be found
in the footnotes.5
In asking to what extent the Rawlsian project is informed
by contemporary political problems, we might be inclined
to think that where his work is responsive to politics, it is
good and where it is seemingly oblivious to political obstacles, it is bad. However, it may be that we need political
philosophers to challenge us to think past the limits within
current politics. Thus, as we ask the first question, we
should also ask: to what extent should a political theorist
constrain his imagination by what has already been foreshadowed in political life and to what extent should we
expect political philosophers to offer us normative reasons
for thinking beyond the boundaries of present practices?
In “Justice as Fairness” (1958), Rawls wrestled with the
foundational questions of U.S. liberal society, while the
civil-rights movement brought these questions to our political attention. In A Theory of Justice (1971), Rawls developed a perspective from which to reason about justice—
“the original position”—that would base liberal democracy
on the capacity of individuals to reason about justice, empathizing with those least well-off in society and choosing
principles of justice that would be considered just from
the perspectives of the least well-off and everyone else in a
society.6 Using what he asserts are weak and few assumptions about human nature 7 —that individuals are mutually independent,8 that more is preferred to less,9 that
individuals are risk averse 10 —he argues that the principles
chosen under such conditions would support liberalism:
political liberty, equal opportunity, and an egalitarian economics defined by the “difference principle” according to
which differences in distributions would be considered
just only if they resulted in an improved condition of those
least advantaged by the inequality.11
According to the difference principle, some inequalities
are not unjust. It is not unjust for basketball players to
earn more than seamstresses. If basketball players get paid
well to develop fan support for their team such that fans
buy T-shirts, thereby increasing demand for seamstresses’
skill, the difference in player and seamstress wages would
not be unjust. The difference in wages could also be justified as necessary to encourage someone to go into a career
where so few are successful. For these and possibly other
reasons, some difference in wages is justified, but the difference principle also constrains how much inequality is
just. We could increase the inequality in their wages only
to the extent that the increase in inequality would make
the seamstress better off.
While this example may be helpful for illustrating the
concept of the difference principle, it is not the kind of
question to which Rawls expects us to apply the difference principle in the original position. Instead, Rawls is
interested in designing a just “basic structure”—the foundational institutions of government and economics.12
Questions that focus our attention on the basic structure
are: Would a proportional representation or quota system promote political equality? Is an income, property,
or sales tax a more appropriate means for funding public
expenditures for collective goods? 13
In the 1980s and 1990s the identity-defined movements for gay rights and for multicultural education and
accommodation animated political and theoretical discussions about what was good for citizens and communities
and drew political attention away from the distributive
questions that animated Rawls’s earlier inquiry.14 In “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical” (1985), Rawls
argued that the principles guiding liberal understandings
of liberty, opportunity, and just economic distributions
should be understood as politically, not morally or metaphysically, justified.15 Despite our holding differing metaphysical views about what is good for human beings and
our community, we should agree that liberty, opportunity,
and fair economic distributions are just. As he further
developed it in Political Liberalism, Rawlsian liberalism
should be understood as a political agreement achievable
by those holding a range of incommensurable, but not
unreasonable, metaphysically based views.16 In Political
Liberalism Rawls assumes that “a continuing shared understanding on one comprehensive religious, philosophical,
or moral doctrine [even if the doctrine is liberalism] can
be maintained only by the oppressive use of state power” 17.
Compared to the agreement on liberal principles possible
behind the veil of ignorance in A Theory of Justice, the
agreement in Political Liberalism is less comprehensive,
the pluralism more challenging.18
The “fact” of “reasonable pluralism” is the central political concern challenging political liberalism.19 For Rawls,
the fact that reasonable people may disagree about the
metaphysical bases for principles of freedom, opportunity,
and equality is not a platitude but rather, a challenge. In
the words of Stephen White, pluralism is “a continual
source of ferment in our lives, since engagement with this
phenomenon will involve a richer, more complex experience . . . we are constrained to an ever deeper and more
extensive engagement with pluralism” 20
However, Rawls puts boundaries on the political problem of difference with the qualifier “reasonable” and the
expectation of “public reason”.21 The distinguishing feature of reasonable views is that they can exist alongside
other views; they are not “aggressive” 22 ; they do not require
the defeat of incompatible views. Public reason requires
more of us. It requires us to give reasons for our views of
basic justice without making reference to our comprehensive religious or philosophical doctrines 23. Rawls writes,
“Our exercise of political power is proper only when we
sincerely believe that the reasons we offer for our political action may reasonably be accepted by other citi-
zens” 24 even though they hold different metaphysical views
from our own. Following the theme of this symposium
we might ask: what political problems—for example,
debates about health care or the environment—are the
result of people disagreeing over what constitutes a reasonable argument? We might wonder how Rawls might
deal with social norms that influence the relative respect
accorded to various speakers such that certain arguments
become inaudible to some audiences. We might also ask
whether in certain political debates—such as those over
abortion or stem cell research—there is a political view
that does not reflect a metaphysical commitment. Perhaps some political life is outside the bounds of Rawlsian
reasonable pluralism.
Within these boundaries on how much difference we
must engage politically, Rawls expects a lot of citizens. We
must come to an “overlapping consensus” on principles of
justice not as a way of getting along (not as a modus vivendi ), but rather because our reasonable views themselves
support the political conception of political liberalism.25
The same demands that he makes on citizens in his work
on justice within states are made of states themselves in
his work on a law of peoples, and many of the same
concepts—overlapping consensus, reasonable pluralism,
and public reason—are essential to its exposition.
In The Law of Peoples (1999), the book-length treatment of his 1993 Oxford Amnesty essay on human rights,
Rawls offers principles of international law that he argues
can be politically agreed to by societies living under a
range of political institutions and sustained by a range of
cultural beliefs. Rawls argues that the fact of reasonable
pluralism among peoples is addressed by liberal democratic states and human rights-respecting hierarchical states,
using the idea of public reason to develop an overlapping
consensus on principles of international relations. Written
while the U.S. faced challenging human rights-related foreign policy questions regarding famines, conflicts, and
genocides in Somalia, Brundi, Rwanda, and the former
Yugoslavian states, and while academics and policymakers debated whether the post-communist era would
usher in an age of democratization or a the clash of civilizations, Rawls identified principles of international law
around which states that respected human rights—liberal
or not—would form an overlapping consensus.
In Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (2001), Rawls rearticulates as a political theory (in the sense developed in
Political Liberalism) the theory first set out in 1958. The
restatement is interesting in part for the tone it takes when
he recognizes that contemporary political agreement is
not in support of the difference principle:
We should recognize, though, that the difference principle is not
often expressly endorsed; indeed, it may prove to have little support in our public culture at the present time. Nevertheless, I
believe it worth studying; it has many desirable features and
formulates in a simple way an idea of reciprocity for a political
March 2006 | Vol. 4/No. 1 77
Symposium
|
John Rawls and the Study of Politics
conception of justice. I think that in some form this idea is
essential to democratic equality once we view society as a fair
system of social cooperation between free and equal citizens from
one generation to the next.26
The political problem Rawls raises here is that “we” do
not conceive of ourselves as engaged in social cooperation.
Although his work has focused on the terms of cooperation among both citizens and states, he comes to realize
the political obstacles to getting the members of a political
collective to conceive of themselves as engaged in social
cooperation.27
It may be that aspects of Rawls’s theory are too reflective of contemporary social norms and power dynamics to
challenge them.28 It may be that other aspects are too
challenging of accepted social norms and power dynamics
to be sustainable.29 As we reflect on this issue, we might
ask ourselves to what extent we think that justice is about
social cooperation. Rawls ask us to consider that it should
be, and in so doing, rescues the liberal democratic tradition from the metaphysical claims of other liberals. He
offers the world a version of liberal democracy seemingly
disconnected from its historically and culturally Western
roots.30 In conferring on Rawls the National Humanities
Medal, then-President Clinton said, “A Theory of Justice
. . . placed our rights to liberty and justice upon a strong
and brilliant new foundation of reason. . . .[Rawls] has
helped a whole generation of learned Americans revive
their faith in democracy itself ”.31
Rawls’s theoretical development follows developments
in contemporary and international politics. The authors
of this symposium offer a snapshot of the contemporary
political problems for which reflections on Rawls’s insights
(and shortcomings) may be stimulating. In 1975 the American Political Science Review published a collection of nine
reviews of A Theory of Justice. While relating their
arguments to politics, its authors focus on key philosophical moves in the Rawlsian project. In this symposium,
we focus on the political moves of the Rawlsian project.
Thirty years later, the contributors demonstrate that the
theoretical ideas Rawls developed are useful for reflecting
on political problems of contemporary relevance.
Notes
1 For discussion of Rawls as continuing a Rousseauian
tradition, see Chapman 1975, cf. Moon 2003. On
stability in Rawls, see Barry 1995 and those cited in
notes on social cooperation (notes 2, 6, 29), the
overlapping consensus (notes 19, 21), and Rawlsian
constructivism (note 11) below.
2 Rawls refers to “Peoples”. As Allan Buchanan
(2000a) argues, his Peoples are very similar to contemporary states. On social cooperation within
states, see Hardin 2003. On social cooperation
between states, see Beitz 1999 [1979] and 2000,
Pogge 2001b, and D. Miller 1995.
78 Perspectives on Politics
3 JFR, 30–31.
4 Other valuable introductions to Rawls include Daniels 1989b, Pogge 1989, Arneson 1989, Kukathas
and Pettit 1990, Talisse 2001, Freeman 1999 and
2003, and Laden 2003.
5 The resigning of controversy to the footnotes is
problematic for many theorists including myself
(2000) and Berkowitz in this symposium. See also
Bloom 1975. However, such marginalization must
also be read in context. In 2002, Political Theory did
a symposium, “What is Political Theory”, in which
no representative of the Rawlsian perspective was
included (though in the book version—White and
Moon 2004—one was added). Further, as Pogge
1989 notes in Realizing Rawls (1, fn1) any attempt
to provide reference to all of the secondary scholarship on Rawls will either be incomplete or render
the text unreadable. For a rich collection of some of
the secondary literature on Rawls, see Richardson
and Weithman 1999.
6 The device of the original position is an attempt to
create a social contract basis for social cooperation.
The idea is introduced in “Justice as Fairness”
(1958) and developed in A Theory of Justice. For an
introduction and discussion, see Nagel 1989 [1973],
Dworkin 1973, Fisk 1989, Kukathas and Pettit
1990, Habermas 2001, Shapiro 2003, Gauthier
1977, and Freeman 1990. Some argue that the
social contract theory is an exclusionary basis for
social cooperation; see Pateman 1988, Mills 1997,
Foster 2004. Others argue that social conflict not
social cooperation should be the starting point of
democratic inquiry (R. Miller 1989 [1974], Shiffman 2002). Still others emphasize that liberal contractarianism, by fabricating a distinction between
public and private power, belies the ways in which
patterns of hierarchies in private lives reinforce and
are reinforced by patterns of hierarchy in public life
(Okin 1989a, 2004, Pateman 1988, Smiley 2004).
7 For discussions of Rawls’s psychological assumptions, see Harsanyi 1975, Benhabib 1988, Okin
1989b.
8 Sandel 1982 criticizes Rawls for characterizing the
individual as one whose most important characteristic is her ability to choose her ends. In addition to
challenging Rawls’s characterization of the individual, the implication of this criticism is that we must
reexamine Rawls’s characterization of the project of
social justice: “Justice is the first virtue of social
institutions, as truth is of systems of thought”
([1971] 1999: 3). Honig 1993 offers a critique of
the Rawlsian self that is more attentive to power
than either Rawls or Sandel. For their communitarian critiques and own theoretical proposals see also
Rorty 1979 and 1983, MacIntyre 1981; Sandel
9
10
11
12
13
1984. See also Walzer 1983, which offers an account
of liberal democracy that is sympathetic with certain
aspects of the communitarian critique (cf. Larmore
1987). Walzer 1984 and 1990, Buchanan 1989, and
Wallach 1987 offer important reviews of the liberalcommunitarian terrain. Benhabib 1992 offers a
different way of mapping and traversing this
landscape.
Rawls characterizes individuals as having different
life plans, but each of these can be pursued more
successfully with more rights, liberties, opportunities, income, wealth, and social basis of self-respect.
According to Rawls, social institutions need to distribute these “social primary goods” fairly. Dworkin
1981a, 1981b argues that justice should be determined based on the distribution of resources
whereas Sen 1990 argues that primary goods and
resources are means to freedom, and that justice
should be concerned with not these but with the
extent freedoms. See also Phillips 2004. On Barber’s
reading, Rawls’s definition of primary goods itself
includes both ends and means 1975.
On Rawls’s assumption that parties in the original
position will be extremely risk averse, see Arrow
1973, in which he reviews some of the work in
economics on risk aversion. See also Sterba 1977.
Some theorists dispute whether these are the right
assumptions and others, whether these are the right
conclusions to draw from these assumptions (e.g.,
Nozick 1974, Sandel 1982, Hardin 2003, Arrow
1973, Waldron 1993 [1986]). Still others challenge
the construction of the liberal project itself for its
understanding of the political subject (Brown 1995)
or for its characterization of the privileged relationship between liberalism and democracy (Bell 2000,
Dallmayr 2001, Ackerly 2005). On the structure,
constructivism and method of Rawls’s argument, see
Nagel 1989 [1973], Dworkin 1973, McCarthy
1994, O’Neill 1996, Klosko 1997. On the priority
of liberty and the relationship between the Rawlsian
principles, see Scanlon 1989, Hart 1989 [1973],
Daniels 1989a. On the priority of the right over the
good, see Sandel 1982 and Kymlicka 1988.
Rawls does imagine that decision makers in those
institutions (specifically in the legislature) will often
use the device of the original position to help them
think through important distributive issues, but the
facts of which a legislator is ignorant in such circumstances are limited.
Okin added that the family and the gendered structure of the workplace should also be of interest to
the theorist of social justice (1989a, 1989b). The
ambiguities of his response are explored in Okin
1994 and 2005. Arrow and others raise the concern
that the difference principle, also known as the
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
“maximin” principle because it maximizes the position of the least advantaged person, would create
bizarre outcomes such as a preference for expensive
medical procedures that would offer minimum
additional benefit to a seriously ill person and that
would reduce the standard of living of the rest of the
population to poverty (Arrow 1973). Likewise we
may find it difficult to assess whether the primary
goods basis for determining the least advantaged
enable us to make interpersonal comparisons—of
the relative values that make up well-being (see the
discussion of primary goods in footnote 9).
Those who have taken other routes to theorizing the
implications for social justice of taking identity
concerns seriously include Kymlicka 1989, Taylor
1994 [1992], Young 1990, Connolly 1991, and
Fraser 1997.
In a 1989 article, Hampton looks at Rawls’s turn in
“Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical”
(1985) and “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus” (1987). See also Erin Kelly’s “Editor’s Forward”
to Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (2001). Habermas (2001, 59) traces the turn to “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory” (1980).
Ackerman 1994 avers that the arguments for the
veil of ignorance and the difference principle cannot
be sustained using the arguments of Political
Liberalism.
PL, 37.
For an account of comprehensive liberalism and
engagement with Rawls on the subject, see Galston
2002. For discussions of the shifts between A
Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism, see Ackerman 1994, Barry 1995, and Wolin 1996.
For a discussion of pluralism, public reason, and
moral conflict in Rawlsian liberalism, Habermasian
ethics, and democracy, see Bohman 1995. See also
Moon 1993, Gaus 1999.
White 2002, 475.
On the importance of reasonableness to the political legitimacy of political liberalism, see Cohen
1996; and for a criticism of this importance, see
Mouffe 2000. For a critical rereading, see Habermas
2001. One concern about the focus on reasonableness and public reasons is that it limits the role of
faith and metaphysically-supported values from
being part of public discourse (Wolterstorff 1997,
Fish 1999, George 2001, Galston 2002, Weithman
2002, Talisse 2005). On public reason and political legitimacy, see also Nagel 1987, Raz 1990, Cohen
1993, Wenar 1995, Reidy 2000, and Christiano
2001.
Public reason is important to Political Liberalism
but his statement of it in that book proves inadequate and he rearticulates in “The Idea of Public
March 2006 | Vol. 4/No. 1 79
Symposium
22
23
24
25
|
John Rawls and the Study of Politics
Reason Revisited”, which is reprinted in The Laws
of Peoples, as the argument is essential to that
work as well. Sections of “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited” appear verbatim in JFR, discussed below.
PL, 144.
PL, 224–225.
PL, xlvi.
PL, 147. For a discussion of modus vivendi in the
context of larger philosophical debates of which
Rawls’s work is a part, see Larmore 1987. See also
Neal 1993 and Scheffler 1994.
80 Perspectives on Politics
26 JFR, 132–133, emphasis added.
27 This is the concern originally raised by Chapman
1975 with references to TJ.
28 This was Allan Bloom’s accusation (1975).
29 On sustainable social cooperation, see note 2. On
pluralism and social cohesion see Galston 1989.
30 Of course, most political philosophers consider
those roots; the structure of the argument is an
attempt to disassociate from them.
31 Clinton 1999.