Evolutionary Psychology
www.epjournal.net – 2012. 10(4): 714-719
¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯
Book Review
Morality Binds and Blinds
A review of Jonathan Haidt, The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by
Politics and Religion. Pantheon Books: New York, 2012, 448 pp., US$28.95, ISBN # 9780307377906 (hardcover).
John Klasios, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. Email:
[email protected].
Every so often a book is published which helps to connect the dots and provide a
synoptic overview of some topic of inquiry, whereby what was once understood in a
disjointed fashion suddenly becomes a coherent and intuitively understood whole—as if by
experiencing a sudden Gestalt switch. Social psychologist Jonathan Haidt’s The Righteous
Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion is one such book.
Stylistically and pedagogically, the approach taken in the book by Haidt parallels some of
its main messages. Haidt points to the evidence within social psychology and reasoning
psychology which demonstrates that humans possess a rueful knack for being more than a
bit impervious to reason and evidence that aims to convince them that they hold false or
inaccurate beliefs. Among the evidence adduced along the way is the confirmation bias and
motivated reasoning. Perhaps the lesser-known of the two, motivated reasoning occurs
whenever individuals deploy their reasoning either to concoct a justification in favor of
some belief they possess, or to counter an assertion or argument presented against one of
those very beliefs.
In connection with these findings from the literature, Haidt draws attention to the
provocative thesis recently advanced by Mercier and Sperber (2011), wherein they argue
that the best explanation of the collective findings within the social and reasoning
psychology literatures is that human reasoning, as deployed in social contexts, evolved not
so much as a means of ascertaining truthful propositions, but rather as a way of winning
arguments—as a way of persuading others. Perhaps relatedly, the character of Glaucon
from Plato’s Republic is used to convey a fundamental motive of humans in the moral
sphere: to appear moral and virtuous in the eyes of others, without necessarily actually
being moral and virtuous. Both the Glauconian thesis and the one advanced by Mercier and
Sperber will perhaps not be too surprising to those of an especially evolutionary-bent
reading Haidt’s book.
Given this rather bleak picture of human reasoning, the author declares his intention
to first attempt at persuading the reader by speaking directly to his or her ―elephant‖, the
Morality binds and blinds
metaphorical stand-in which he uses to refer to the intuitive and affective aspects of our
cognitive makeup. It is also these aspects which he thinks are ultimately what exert the
predominant influence on us so far as our moral psychology is concerned. Haidt concedes,
rather pessimistically, that if his tactics of persuasion cannot succeed at this level then the
follow-up arguments are quite likely to fall on proverbial deaf ears. Indeed, Haidt seems to
believe it when he says that humans are primarily guided by their intuitions in the fixation
of their beliefs. Lest Haidt’s view sounds like it paints too bleak a picture of human
reasoning, it should be noted that he does believe that processes of rational deliberation can
play a role in belief fixation, as well as reasoned input from others in one’s social milieu.
One of his more optimistic messages, therefore, is that the pursuit of truth is within our
capacity, but only insofar as a community of reasoners is able to recursively vet each
other’s reasoning — a condition which is seemingly best exemplified by scientific
communities.
The central views bestriding the field of moral psychology throughout the latter
part of last century are briefly sketched by Haidt near the outset of the book, namely the
Piagetian and Kohlbergian views. But rather than giving a dry, extended technical overview
of these paradigms, Haidt weaves the explication of their central tenets around his own
explorations of moral psychology, beginning with his days as a graduate student. His
exposure to the ethnographic work of Richard Shweder had lead him to eventually research
the moral psychology of individuals living in India, an experience which would ultimately
leave an indelible mark both on how Haidt came to see our moral psychology and on
himself personally. The rest of Haidt’s personal story leads to the central argument that the
rationalist view of humans’ moral psychology—with roots in Plato and as developed in the
field of moral psychology by Kohlberg and his proponents—is radically incomplete. In its
place, Haidt makes the case for his moral foundations theory. According to this view,
which is a keystone piece around which many of the other themes running throughout the
book revolve, morality is more than what rationalists like Plato and Kohlberg have made it
out to be. Rather, Haidt argues that the rationalist picture of moral psychology generally
only picks out two broad foundations of a larger complex which features at least three—
and probably four—others. These six moral foundations are given the names care/harm,
fairness/cheating, loyalty/betrayal, authority/subversion, sanctity/degradation, and
liberty/oppression. For instance, the liberty/oppression foundation, as its nomenclature
suggests, is sensitive to moral transgressions which curtail or oppress the liberty of some
individual or group, whereas placing more weight on the welfare of individuals in a foreign
nation is likely to activate the loyalty/betrayal foundation—the latter foundation being one
that conservatives score much higher on than liberals.
Indeed, one of Haidt’s central contentions in the book, backed up by the empirical
evidence he and colleagues have gathered, is that liberals primarily make use of only three
of these moral foundations—care/harm, fairness/cheating, liberty/oppression—whereas
conservatives utilize all six. Moreover, the cross-national data gathered by Haidt and his
colleagues show that this patterned divide between liberals and conservatives remains
consistent no matter which country one looks at. Along these lines, earlier work by Haidt
found that upper-class individuals in Brazilian cities distinguished moral violations from
conventional violations/taboos more like upper-class individuals in Philadelphia, whereas
Evolutionary Psychology – ISSN 1474-7049 – Volume 10(4). 2012.
-715-
Morality binds and blinds
their working-class compatriots tended to make no such distinction—that is, saw outright
moral violations as on a par with violations of a conventional sort. Thus, distinguishing
moral violations from taboos appears to cross-cut cultures, at least in the case of the upperclass subjects examined in Haidt’s work.
Comprising one of the central themes of the book, Haidt makes the case that moral
psychology has come to reveal human moralizing as primarily driven by intuitive
processes—a picture which mirrors the verdict with respect to our reasoning more
generally. According to the social intuitionist model developed by Haidt, intuitive cognitive
processes precede the more overt, conscious deliberations that are traditionally held to be
the hallmark of moral reasoning. Before formally introducing this model, however, Haidt
begins by tracing out how his own thinking gradually evolved into the model as it is
presented in the book. Three contrasting views of the relation between moral reasoning, on
the one hand, and intuitions and emotions, on the other, are presented: the
Platonic/rationalist view, the Humean sentimentalist view, and the Jeffersonian dualprocess view. Although Haidt at one stage acceded to the Jeffersonian dual-process view,
he ultimately came to abandon it in favor of Hume’s view. Evidence is marshalled to
support the view that, rather than human moral psychology being directed by cool,
calculated, off-line deliberation via the higher rational faculties—the Platonic view—and
contra it being shaped conjunctively by both reason and the passions—the Jeffersonian
view—it rather appears, according to Haidt, that we start with moral judgments infused by
intuitive flashes, with which our controlled reasoning then proceeds to concoct ex post
facto rationalizations for.
Undergirding Haidt’s moral foundations theory is an explicit endorsement of
evolutionary psychology’s modularity—specifically the construal proffered by Sperber and
Hirschfeld (2004). In conjunction with this construal of modularity, Haidt also cites the
treatment of developmental neurogenetics presented by Marcus (2004), utilizing Marcus’
terse definition of nativism as organized in advance of experience. Broadly speaking, Haidt
takes the view that the six moral foundations are modules inhering within our cognitive
architecture. These broadly construed modules are simultaneously taken to be malleable in
response to a wide array of cultural, social, and other factors, yet malleable in relatively
specific, constrained, systematic, and organized ways—ways which presumably have been
adaptively crafted by natural selection. Of course, this review is not the place to partake in
an extended and in-depth analysis of Haidt’s modular framework, or cognitive modularity
more generally, but his corpus of work on moral foundations theory and other topics is
definitely evolutionary-psychological in character, and unashamedly so.
The final part of the book looks at the groupish psychology of humans more
generally, and religion more specifically. The principle underlying this part of the book is
that morality binds and blinds. Roughly speaking, Haidt takes human groupishness and
moral psychology to have evolved chiefly to bind humans into in-groups. And it is within
these in-groups that rituals, norms, and customs—inter alia—facilitate group cohesion and
solidarity for the purposes of competing with rival out-groups. As has been pointed out by
others (e.g., de Waal, 2006) one of our most noble psychological dimensions, namely
morality, has its provenance in an evolutionary history of inter-group conflict. That said,
however, one should be cautious before necessarily conflating the underlying evolved
Evolutionary Psychology – ISSN 1474-7049 – Volume 10(4). 2012.
-716-
Morality binds and blinds
psychological aspects of our moral impulses with morality as it perhaps ought to be defined
as (Kitcher, 2006).
It is also at this point of the book where arguably the most controversial of Haidt’s
theses makes its entrance, namely that humans have been shaped to some non-negligible
extent by group selection, and that religion may possibly be an adaptation (perhaps, for
instance, an adaptation characterized by cultural complexes interfacing with an underlying
cognitive basis, forged jointly by gene-culture co-evolutionary processes). It is important to
take note, however, that Haidt is simply raising the possibility and not reaching any
definitive conclusions. Relatedly, his contention that humans are, metaphorically speaking,
90 percent chimp and 10 percent bee—that is, have been shaped partly by group
selection—will obviously be viewed skeptically by many. That said, whether humans have
or have not been shaped by group selection—and if so, the extent to which they have
been—remains an empirical question. At a minimum, much of the controversy at the
theoretical level has seemingly overlooked the fact that gene selection/inclusive fitness and
group selection/multi-level selection are equivalent formulations (e.g., Sterelny and
Griffiths, 1999, pp. 151-179; Wilson, 2012a, 2012b; Okasha, 2008). The question of
religion, too, still remains an open question. For instance, and in line with Haidt’s
suggestion that it may be an adaptation, recent arguments have been advanced in favor of a
framework that is both adaptationist and pluralistic—incorporating explanatory elements
such as spandrels and cultural group selection, inter alia (e.g., Atran and Henrich, 2010;
Powell and Clarke, 2012).
This third section of the book also integrates the other two main principles
comprising the organizing themes of the first two sections. According to Haidt, our welldocumented foibles of reasoning are especially evident with respect to those beliefs which
individuals take to be sacred —i.e., religious, political. If one follows the sacredness—that
is, ascertains what an individual or group holds to be a sacred value, cause, precept, etc.—it
is likely that they will discover where an individual or group becomes blind to any reasons
or counter-evidence that speak against that which is sacralized. As Haidt puts it:
Morality binds and blinds. This is not just something that happens to people on the
other side. We all get sucked into tribal moral communities. We circle around
sacred values and then share post hoc arguments about why we are so right and they
are so wrong. We think the other side is blind to truth, reason, science, and common
sense, but in fact everyone goes blind when talking about their sacred objects. If
you want to understand another group, follow the sacredness. (pp. 311-312)
Apart from the obvious relevance that the book has to human political cognition and
behavior—which is especially apropos given the polarized nature of the current political
climate in the United States—many of its central messages will also be applicable to
academic and scientific discourse. As Haidt (2012) has made salient elsewhere, social
psychologists, for instance, and social scientists more generally, may collectively as a
group be inadvertently or advertently discriminating against conservative colleagues in
ways which conform to the tribalistic moral psychology he has outlined. Indeed, a recent
survey of social psychologists found them to be overwhelmingly socially liberal, but more
Evolutionary Psychology – ISSN 1474-7049 – Volume 10(4). 2012.
-717-
Morality binds and blinds
to the point many openly conceded that they would likely discriminate in various ways
against conservative colleagues (Inbar and Lammers, 2012). Such a finding certainly
supports Haidt’s contention that social psychology—if not academia more broadly—can be
a hostile climate for conservatives (the out-group). Alarmingly, Inbar and Lammers found
that more than one out of three of their respondents would discriminate against
conservative colleagues when making hiring decisions, which indicates that major
personnel decisions occurring within the field of social psychology are being executed in a
discriminatory fashion.
The pervasive manner in which individuals form tribal moral communities that
sacralize certain values (e.g., egalitarianism) may also seemingly explain why certain topics
and lines of investigation in the human sciences are met with such strong resistance—e.g.,
adaptationism applied to human psychology, sex differences, race differences. These
resistances may very well be the manifestations of an underlying moral psychology
sculpted by natural selection, a psychology that enabled our ancestors to form moral teams
that perceived the world in terms of an idiosyncratic moral matrix, and who circled around
the sacred values and objects of the tribe—at once delineating the in-group and juxtaposing
it against all others. Haidt’s book is an important, eye-opening work of synthesis that is as
broad as it is topical, and for which it should deservingly gain a wide and interdisciplinary
readership.
References
Atran, S., and Henrich, J. (2010). The Evolution of Religion: How cognitive by-products,
adaptive learning heuristics, ritual displays, and group competition generate deep
commitments to prosocial religions. Biological Theory: Integrating Development,
Evolution, and Cognition, 5(1), 18-30.
De Waal, F. (2006). Morally evolved: Primate social instincts, human morality, and the rise
and fall of "Veneer Theory". In S. Macedo, and J. Ober (Eds.), Primates and
philosophers: How morality evolved (pp. 1-82). Princeton, N.J: Princeton
University Press.
Haidt, J. (2012, February 5). Post-partisan social psychology. Retrieved from
http://people.stern.nyu.edu/jhaidt/postpartisan.html
Inbar, Y., and Lammers, J. (2012). Political diversity in social and personality psychology.
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 496-503.
Kitcher, P. (2006). Ethics and evolution: How to get here from there. In S. Macedo, and J.
Ober (Eds.), Primates and philosophers: How morality evolved (pp. 120-139).
Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press.
Marcus, G. F. (2004). The birth of the mind: How a tiny number of genes creates the
complexities of human thought. New York: Basic books.
Mercier, H., and Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an
argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 57-111.
Okasha, S. (2008). Units and levels of selection. In S. Sarkar, and A. Plutynski (Eds.), A
Companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 138-156). Oxford: Blackwell.
Powell, R., and Clarke, S. (2012). Religion as an evolutionary byproduct: A critique of the
Evolutionary Psychology – ISSN 1474-7049 – Volume 10(4). 2012.
-718-
Morality binds and blinds
standard model. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 457-486.
Sperber, D., and Hirschfeld, L. (2004). The cognitive foundations of cultural stability and
diversity. Trends in Cognitive Science, 8, 40-46.
Sterelny, K., and Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to philosophy of
biology. Chicago, Ill: University of Chicago Press.
Wilson, D. S. (2012a, May 29). Richard Dawkins, Edward O. Wilson, and the consensus of
the
many.
Retrieved
from
http://www.thisviewoflife.com/index.php/magazine/articles/richard-dawkinsedward-o.-wilson-and-the-consensus-of-the-many
Wilson, D. S. (2012b, July 12). Clash of paradigms. Retrieved from
http://www.thisviewoflife.com/index.php/magazine/articles/clash-of-paradigms
Evolutionary Psychology – ISSN 1474-7049 – Volume 10(4). 2012.
-719-