Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian
Philosophers
Volume 33
Issue 3
Article 6
7-1-2016
Reasons of Meaning to Abhor the End of the Human Race
Thaddeus Metz
Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy
Recommended Citation
Metz, Thaddeus (2016) "Reasons of Meaning to Abhor the End of the Human Race," Faith and Philosophy:
Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 33 : Iss. 3 , Article 6.
DOI: 10.5840/faithphil201633366
Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol33/iss3/6
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative
exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian
Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange.
REASONS OF MEANING TO
ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE*
Thaddeus Metz
In this review essay on Samuel Scheffler’s Death and the Afterlife, I focus on his
intriguing suggestion that we reasonably care more about the fate of an unidentifiable, future humanity than of ourselves and our loved ones. Scheffler’s
main rationale for this claim is that meaning in our lives crucially depends
on contributing to the well-being of the human race down the road, with
many commentators instead arguing that advancing the good of ourselves or
existing loved ones would be sufficient. In contrast, I argue for a different
kind of rationale for Scheffler’s conclusion, contending that it is our attachment to, not contribution towards, humanity’s flourishing that plausibly
constitutes a large part of the meaning in our lives.
1. Introduction
In a book based on his Tanner Lectures,1 Samuel Scheffler has purportedly become the first Western philosopher to systematically address the
issue of how the ending of the human species in the future would affect
the value of our lives in the present.2 In the first two major sections of
his lengthy essay “Death and the Afterlife,”3 on which I focus, Scheffler
argues for the claim that “the fact that we and everyone we love will cease
to exist matters less to us than would the nonexistence of future people
who we do not know and who, indeed, have no determinate identities.”4
Beyond making this interesting phenomenological point, Scheffler also
seeks to explain why we tend to care more about the fate of humanity
* A review of Death and the Afterlife by Samuel Scheffler, ed. Niko Kolodny (Oxford University Press, 2013). Pp. 224. $29.95 (paperback).
1
For audiofiles of the lectures, see Scheffler, “The Afterlife.”
2
Frankfurt, “How the Afterlife Matters,” 132.
3
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife.” For a summary of these sections from the horse’s
mouth, see Scheffler, “The Importance of the Afterlife.” Note that I set aside any discussion
of the third major section of the essay, in which Scheffler takes up the issue of how a person
ought to react to the prospect of her own death, not the death of the species.
4
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 45.
pp. 358–369
FAITH AND PHILOSOPHY Vol. 33 No. 3 July 2016
doi: 10.5840/faithphil201633366
All rights reserved
REASONS OF MEANING TO ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE
359
than of ourselves and our loved ones, an explanation that makes good sense
of those differential attitudes.5
In this review essay, I focus on Scheffler’s justificatory project, or at least
I read him as providing one.6 Supposing that we sensibly care more about
the fate of humanity than that of ourselves and our loved ones, should we
for the reason that Scheffler posits? Which considerations would best justify
a greater concern for the survival of the species—which is what Scheffler
principally means by “afterlife”—than of oneself and one’s beloveds?
I argue that if we sensibly care more about what happens after our
lives, it is not mainly for the reason Scheffler appears to offer, which is,
roughly, that our activities would lose substantial meaning if they were
unable to affect future generations. If this tendency is justified, it is more
likely so in virtue of other considerations, specifically about our attachment
to humanity, or so I contend.
Such a critical approach to Scheffler’s position differs from other discussions of it, which have instead focused on showing that much of what
we value in life could obtain in the absence of an orientation towards a
future humanity.7 I am more inclined to agree with Scheffler that such an
orientation matters crucially to us and rightly so, but not so much for the
central reason suggested in his essay.
I begin by clarifying the nature of Scheffler’s thesis that we sensibly
care more about the fate of humanity than that of ourselves, after which I
expound his central argument for it (§2). Next, I present objections to his
rationale (§3), and then advance a new account of why it would be reasonable to deem humanity’s future to matter more than one’s own, an account
that avoids and explains the objections I make to Scheffler’s account (§4).
I conclude by briefly addressing a related issue about how to value the
future that stumps Scheffler, with him being “open to suggestions” from
the field,8 namely, how to account for the intuition that it is reasonable to
exhibit strong negative reactions towards humanity’s demise when it is
imminent, but not when it is very far off (§5). I conclude by noting that
reflection on this issue provides extra reason both to doubt Scheffler’s central rationale for prizing the continuation of the human race and to favour
my alternative.
2. The Contribution View of Meaning in Life
With regard to Scheffler’s claim about how we (properly) value the continuation of the species, he can be read as defending both a weaker claim and
5
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 26, 31, 53–54. See also Scheffler, “Death, Value, and
the Afterlife,” 189.
6
As Susan Wolf remarks (“The Significance of Doomsday”), Scheffler “shies away from
this more prescriptive question” (115) and “seems to want to resist any questions of this sort”
(124), although he does clearly address it on the pages I have cited above.
7
See Frankfurt, “How the Afterlife Matters,” 132–136, 139–140; Wolf, “The Significance of
Doomsday,” 119–124; Belshaw, “Review: Death and the Afterlife”; Nagel, “After You’ve Gone.”
8
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 63.
360
Faith and Philosophy
a stronger one. In this article, I focus on the stronger claim, here spelling it
out and why Scheffler believes it.
The weaker claim regarding how we (are reasonable to) prize the future
of the human race is that “the survival of people after our deaths matters
greatly to us,” much more than we usually recognize.9 Much of the first
section of Scheffler’s essay aims to establish this point,10 and to note the
limits of not only psychological and ethical egoism, but also individualism
more broadly, that is, the view that the good life makes no essential reference to relationships with others, or at least others in the future.
To argue for this weaker claim, Scheffler contends that most modern
readers will share with him the sense that, in the face of our own mortality, we face “the problem of preserving our values and the problem of
establishing a personalized relation to the future.”11 The former problem
is that normally when we value something, we implicitly are committed
to the thought that it should continue to exist. If we expect no longer to be
around to sustain it, then we naturally form a desire that others will do
so in the future. The latter problem is that we often do not just want our
values to continue to survive, but also something of ourselves to do so.
And, on this score, we typically identify with people who will live beyond
us, children in the first instance, but also clubs, organizations, institutions
and traditions. Hence, finding it important to “defend and extend the coherence and integrity of our selves and our values over time,”12 we are
strongly drawn to “leave traces” on the lives of future human beings, to
use Robert Nozick’s elegant phrase.13 And, according to Scheffler, we often
fail to realize the extent to which our lives are geared around this interest.
Scheffler’s analysis and defence of the weaker claim is powerful and
revealing, and, as noted above, many interlocutors have focused on this
claim, considering the objection that human beings could still find substantial meaning, happiness and other key values despite a keen awareness of
the impending end of the human race. I, however, set the weaker claim
aside, in order to explore Scheffler’s stronger one, advanced mainly in the
second section of his essay. The stronger claim is that we reasonably “care
less” about our own survival than about the survival of humanity, or that
the latter sensibly “matters more” to us than the former.14
This strong claim pertains more to our attitudes than our actions. Scheffler’s view is not so much that we generally and reasonably do more for
humanity than for ourselves. Instead, by people “caring” more about future human beings than themselves, or deeming the former to “matter”
more than the latter, Scheffler in the first instance means something
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 54, 59–60, 80–81.
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 15–43.
11
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 35.
12
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 35.
13
Nozick, Philosophical Explanations, 582–585.
14
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 47, 72, 73, 77–81.
9
10
REASONS OF MEANING TO ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE
361
about our mental states. He remarks that we are “more dependent for
our equanimity”15 on our confidence in the survival of humanity than on
our confidence in our own survival; we aptly exhibit stronger negative
attitudes towards the prospect of the extinction of humanity than towards
that of our own death. Concrete examples include emotions such as distress, profound dismay, grief, sadness, horror, despair and depression,16
with Scheffler claiming that we are rightly more distressed, dismayed, etc.
upon anticipating humanity’s extinction than our own death.
My aim in this article is not so much to evaluate directly Scheffler’s
strong claim that our negative attitudes towards the demise of the human
race are sensibly stronger than those towards our own death. Instead, I
appraise the rationale he advances for this claim. Has he advanced the
most compelling argument for it?
Scheffler contends that we sensibly care more about the lives of future
strangers than our own lives because the worth of much of what we find
most valuable doing now would not obtain if humanity’s demise were
imminent.17 For Scheffler, much of what we most value doing depends
on its having some positive effect on the human race in the future. When we
talk of “meaning in life” or “what matters,” we are centrally referring to
“things we can do to promote the survival and flourishing of humanity
after our deaths.”18 I call this the “Contribution View,” since it deems contributing to humanity’s good in the future to be crucial for one’s life to
be meaningful. This view underlies Scheffler’s specific examples of the
kinds of activities that would become meaningless were humanity to die
out: working on cancer research;19 developing seismic safety techniques;20
engaging in creative projects;21 tackling climate change;22 and preventing
nuclear proliferation.23
In his reply to critics, Scheffler at one point appears to disavow the Contribution View, when he says that “even very modest academic or creative
efforts can have a point or value that is independent of their individual
merits or causal influence.”24 Instead, Scheffler suggests that their point
“depends on seeing oneself as a participant in a collective, temporally extended project.”25
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 77.
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 20, 21, 22, 23, 38, 40, 43.
17
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 24–26, 53, 72, 76, 78.
18
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 78.
19
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 42.
20
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 42.
21
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 42.
22
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 78.
23
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 78.
24
Scheffler, “Death, Value, and the Afterlife,” 185.
25
Scheffler, “Death, Value, and the Afterlife,” 185.
15
16
362
Faith and Philosophy
Here are three reasons why, despite this once-off distancing from the
Contribution View, it is apt to focus on it here. First, Scheffler’s defence
of the strong claim that we sensibly care more about humanity’s future
than our own becomes weaker in the absence of the claim that the meaningfulness of a project depends crucially on the prospect of it affecting
humanity’s future. After all, one already has a good 10,000 years or so of
human civilization into which one’s academic and creative efforts can fit
so as to see oneself “as a participant in a collective, temporally extended
project.” In order to defend the strong claim about the relevance of the
future, Scheffler needs to show that we must understand ourselves as more
than, say, the final, crowning achievement to human enquiry or creativity.
There is a second consideration of coherence among Scheffler’s claims
that prescribes holding the Contribution View. Recall that he believes that
we modern folk typically want to “act in ways that will help preserve and
sustain the things that we value” and to “personalize our relation to the
future.”26 And in the face of our own mortality, Scheffler contends that
we often seek “to create a future in which the value we have historically
shared with other members of the group will continue to endure” and
“to create a future whose inhabitants will share with us some of the commitments that matter most to us.”27 In short, these claims indicate that in
order to satisfy desires to extend our selves and our values, we must create
a future, i.e., act in ways that are going to contribute to what comes after
we are gone.
Finally, even if, upon reflection, Scheffler would change the phrasing
of the many passages that I quote and cite in this article, the Contribution
View is at least a fair way to read the first two sections of his essay, and,
moreover, is a view that is philosophically important and merits critical
investigation.
In sum, according to Scheffler, we sensibly prize the continuation of
the species more than our own continuation since the meaningfulness of
our lives substantially depends on helping to create a desirable future for
it. We are reasonably inclined to lose our equanimity more upon losing
faith that the species will continue than upon losing faith in our surviving
the death of our body, since “we need humanity to have a future for the
very idea that things matter to retain a secure place in our conceptual
repertoire.”28 This is an original, fascinating suggestion, one that is underexplored in the literature on life’s meaning.29
3. Criticisms of the Contribution View
I have two major objections to what I have identified as Scheffler’s rationale for valuing the lives of future, currently non-existent human beings
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 32.
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 35.
28
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 60.
29
For an overview of the field, see Metz, “The Meaning of Life.”
26
27
REASONS OF MEANING TO ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE
363
over one’s own life and the lives of one’s beloveds. The first objection to
the Contribution View starts from the point that very few people are able
to make much, if any, progress towards ends that would benefit human
beings unrelated to themselves in the future. Some large percentage of current human beings is made up of “non-contributors,” those who, by virtue
of lack of talent, bad upbringing or unfortunate circumstance, are not able
to engage in projects that are likely to leave traces. Neither cleaners, insurance salespeople, advertisers, television actors, comedians, farmers,
firefighters nor general medical practitioners, let alone the unemployed,
can be “contributors” through their careers, on which they spend the bulk
of their time.30 They can do a lot of good for people currently alive, but
they are unlikely to do much for “future people who we do not know and
who, indeed, have no determinate identities.”31 Not many people engage
in the kinds of contributory activities Scheffler discusses as key examples,
which, recall, include fighting cancer, climate change and nukes.
The main way that most people affect future generations is by creating
them. However, procreation is of course not a relevant way to have a
positive influence on people “who have no determinate identities,” something that Scheffler claims should matter to us more than ourselves and
“everyone we love.”32 After all, one point of Scheffler’s essay is that we
would no longer continue to have children if we knew the species would
die out, implying that procreation cannot count for him as a way to positively influence the future of the species in a way that would confer much
meaning on life.33
Now, suppose I am right that relatively few people are currently in a
position to count as “contributors.” Then, it probably is not the inability
to have some beneficial effect on future human beings that explains most
people’s negative attitudes towards the prospect of the extinction of the
species. Humanity’s extinction would take no opportunity away from the
large majority of us “non-contributors,” and yet we would still reasonably
be very upset were we to learn that humanity were soon to die out. Hence, there
must be some important reason for mourning humanity’s doom more
than one’s own besides the fact that the death of the species would occlude
one’s ability to help human beings down the road; again, few of us could
have helped anyway.34
30
My point, that these folks are unlikely to be able to help future generations but would still
sensibly be upset were they to discover there would soon be no more of them, differs from Nagel’s
point that it would not be natural “for an electrician, a waitress, or a bus driver to think of
what they are doing as essentially part of the collective history of humanity, stretching far
into the future” and hence that most people are focused on obtaining meaning in life from
the present. See his “After You’ve Gone.”
31
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 45.
32
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 45,
33
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 25; cf. 39.
34
Notice that this objection also applies to the alternate construal of Scheffler’s view
mentioned above, that meaning in life depends not essentially on contributing towards the
future, but rather “on seeing oneself as a participant in a collective, temporally extended
364
Faith and Philosophy
Here is a second objection to Scheffler’s central explanation of why we
are reasonable to be more distraught by the prospect of humanity’s end
than that of our own. Consider, now, the small group of those who are in
a position, by virtue of talent, upbringing and circumstance, to make a
long-term contribution to humanity’s good. Of those who can contribute to
the flourishing of future generations (however many or few they may be),
most will be able to make a difference for, say, at most three generations.
Imagine, now, that humanity would die out upon the fourth generation. By
the logic of the argument occasioned by Scheffler’s text, those who have in
fact contributed to the next three generations would have much less reason
to be upset than non-contributors. However, I suspect the negative reactions
of contributors and non-contributors towards the prospect of humanity’s
extinction would be comparable, and reasonably so. Those who can and will
make progress towards ends that will benefit strangers in the future would
be sensible to be about as upset at the impending death of the species as
would those who could not or did not, but the logic of Scheffler’s argument
entails that these two groups ought to have substantially different degrees
of negative reactions, since one group has succeeded in its “determination
to act in . . . behalf”35 of future generations and the other has not.
In sum, it appears that it would be reasonable to be more upset upon
anticipating humanity’s demise than one’s own death, even if one had no
ability to contribute towards humanity’s good, and furthermore that it
would be reasonable to be more upset about the prospect of humanity’s
demise than that of one’s own death, even if one in fact did so contribute.
If so, then it cannot be that such attitudes are best justified by the idea that
humanity’s demise would undercut our opportunity to contribute to its
flourishing in the long term.
4. An Alternate Explanation: The Attachment View
In this section, I advance a novel account of why it would be reasonable
to care more about humanity’s survival than one’s own, an account that
rivals what I find in Scheffler’s essay. After spelling it out, I note how it
avoids, and also plausibly explains, the objections I have made to the Contribution View.
I suggest that our negative attitudes towards humanity’s extinction
would reasonably be stronger than those towards our death and the
deaths of our loved ones if and because: (a) humanity over time is capable
of much greater things than an individual, where (b) a given human being
is sensibly “attached to” humanity’s achievements.36 Call this the “Attachment View,” the two clauses of which I now spell out.
project” (Scheffler, “Death, Value, and the Afterlife,” 185). It is far from clear that, say, bus
drivers are able to see their job in this way.
35
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 79.
36
And perhaps (c), with Seanna Shiffrin, that these great things would come to an end for
no good reason, i.e., either for no reason or for a bad one. See her “Preserving the Valued or
Preserving Valuing?,” 152–153.
REASONS OF MEANING TO ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE
365
The (a) clause should not be controversial. It says merely that what the
species can do over time with regard to many of the highest final values is
much more than what a single person can do in her lifetime. Picasso was
amazing, no doubt, but still more striking is the entire rise of the modern
art movement. Einstein was one of the greatest scientists ever to live, but,
again, what the scientific community as a whole has accomplished with
regard to insights into the workings of nature is even more impressive.
The existence of a future humanity promises not merely more collective
accomplishment down the road, but also the continuation of various narratives that the species has begun.
Such a perspective about what is good for its own sake should not
worry champions of human rights, individual dignity and related moral
perspectives that deny that persons may be treated merely as a means to
a greater, collective good. It is coherent to contend that an individual has
a superlative non-instrumental value that means that she may not be used
as a mere tool for the promotion of culture, and also to acknowledge that
the degree to which an individual can contribute to culture, which can be
great, is small relative to what many people can over time.
The (a) condition, or something like it, is essential to explain the difference in negative reactions to the demise of our species if it were, on
the one hand, capable of lives worth living, and, on the other, incapable
of such lives. If future human beings were destined merely to live in a
state of permanent coma, it is not clear that we would reasonably have
extremely negative attitudes towards their extinction, let alone attitudes
that are more negative than those towards our own death. For these attitudes to be reasonable, humanity must be at least capable of living well
in the medium term.
The (b) condition is not as intuitive as (a). According to this second
clause, part of the explanation of why we would be so inclined to lose
our equanimity upon learning that humanity is soon to die out is that
we are attached or close to its accomplishments. Roughly, one is more attached or closer to something, the more one’s propositional attitudes are
positively oriented towards it. One is attached to a thing to the extent that
one’s cognitive, emotive, affective and related mental states are contoured
towards it.37
With regard to humanity’s accomplishments, one kind of attachment to
them would be that on which Scheffler often focuses, namely, the intentional action of helping to bring them about. However, that is not the only
kind, with most people instead exhibiting a variety of others. For example,
many people are pleased by cultural achievements or appreciate them.
For another, many people identify with the cultural output of the species,
so that, even though they themselves did not produce it, they tend to think
37
For a related conception of attachment, interestingly cast in terms of personal identity,
see Joseph Mintoff, “Transcending Absurdity.” See also Metz, Meaning in Life, 222–225.
366
Faith and Philosophy
of it as “ours.” For yet another, many people take pride in what humanity
has done in aesthetic and intellectual spheres.
The (b) condition, or something like it, is essential to explain the difference in negative reactions to the demise of our own species as opposed to
reactions to the demise of some other, distant intelligent species. Imagine
that we received a communiqué from a species in another part of the
galaxy, which provided a description of their civilization and an indication that they are doomed because their sun will soon explode. Many of
us would reasonably feel some dismay, but not nearly as much as what we
would feel upon learning that our own sun would explode in a few generations. The difference is plausibly explained by the fact that our selves
are closer to humanity’s civilization, even if we did not help to create it or
will not further it in the future.
Return, now, to the objections facing Scheffler’s main account of why
we reasonably care more about future strangers than ourselves. As I read
Scheffler’s essay, the best explanation of why we are reasonable to care in
this way is that the meaningfulness of our lives crucially depends on the
ability to make progress towards ends that would benefit human beings
in the future. I argued that this cannot be much of the explanation, since
we would reasonably care more (or at least no less) about future strangers
than ourselves even if we could not in the first place make such progress,
and since we would reasonably care more about future strangers whom
we could not affect than about ourselves, even upon having actually made
such progress with regard to others whom we could affect.
I submit that the deep problem with the Contribution View is that
while having a productive, causal connection between oneself and future
others is probably sufficient to make sense of having much greater negative reactions towards the death of the species than of oneself, it is not
also necessary. Basically, other, intensional relations with future others are
also sufficient to make sense of these reactions. Since the Attachment View
does not make contributing to future humanity’s quality of life a necessary
condition for sensibly having negative reactions towards its extinction, it
avoids, and well explains, the counterexamples to the rationale that because the meaningfulness of our lives depends on “things we can do to
promote the survival and flourishing of humanity after our deaths,”38 we
sensibly deem humanity’s survival to matter more than ours.
5. Future Reflection on the Future: A Remaining Puzzle
I close this review essay by considering another problem that faces the
Contribution View. Scheffler himself raises the concern at one point when
he poses this question: “If the end of human life in the near term would
make many things matter less to us now, then why aren’t we similarly
affected by the knowledge that human life will end in the longer term?”39
38
39
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 78.
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 62–63.
REASONS OF MEANING TO ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE
367
Upon learning that humanity will die out in four generations, we would
be sensibly upset and deem it to be a catastrophe in a way we would not
upon discovering that it will die out in 10 billion years. The field has yet
to work through a number of explanations of the difference.40 I maintain
that Scheffler’s available explanations are implausible, and that the Attachment View grounds a more promising line.
Consider, first, the actual explanation that Scheffler gives, namely, that
“we simply don’t know how, in these contexts, to work with or even fully
to grasp concepts like ‘the end of the universe’ or ‘billions of years.’”41
The point might be true, but I suspect it is not relevant. Even if we cannot
grasp what these things mean, they are not essential to the matter at hand;
for we would continue to sensibly have different degrees of negative reactions to the prospect of humanity dying out in 100 years and to that of it
dying out in 1500, where we presumably have some reasonably firm grasp
of what the latter might mean.
There is another explanation that Scheffler does not offer but that
would dovetail neatly with the Contribution View. What Scheffler probably ought to say is that although our actions could make no difference
to humanity after a long time (even 1500 years), they could to humanity
in the near term. This explanation is powerful, and, on the face of it, the
ability to provide it enhances the credence of Scheffler’s general position.
However, upon reflection, the present explanation does not go the distance. Return to the thought experiment above, where I had the reader
imagine that we can influence only the next three generations of human
beings, and that the fourth would coincidentally be the last one. Although
the Contribution View account can make sense of why we would be much
less upset about the demise of humanity 75 generations from now than
about its demise three generations from now, it cannot make sense of our
negative feelings about the demise of the fourth generation. Any generation beyond our influence should also be beyond our care, by the logic
of the Contribution View. However, I presume that we would sensibly
be much more upset about the death of the fourth generation that we, by
hypothesis, could not influence than about the 75th generation. And so
there is more reason to doubt the Contribution View.
What does the Attachment View entail about the puzzle? It does better.
According to this perspective, while we can expect that humanity would
be capable of great things in 1500 years, we are not acquainted with what
its achievements would be, are not as disposed to take pride in them, are
not as inclined to identify with them, and, yes, also cannot contribute to
40
For the view that we ought not to have differential reactions to humanity’s imminent
and far-off extinction, see Frankfurt, “How the Afterlife Matters,” 138; and Wolf, “The Significance of Doomsday,” 127–129.
41
Scheffler, “Death and the Afterlife,” 63–64; see also Scheffler, “Death, Value, and the
Afterlife,” 189.
368
Faith and Philosophy
them.42 However, we are so acquainted, disposed, etc. when it comes to
what humanity is likely or at least able to do in about 100 years.
In this review essay I have focused on evaluating Samuel Scheffler’s
particularly bold claim that, upon reflection, we can see that we reasonably tend to care more about the survival of the species than we do about
that of ourselves and our loved ones. More specifically, I have considered Scheffler’s apparent major reason for believing this claim, and have
argued that it has serious weaknesses, which have led me to articulate a
different account that avoids and explains them. As the reader will appreciate, a strong work of philosophy is not essentially one that is true or even
convinces; it can rather be one that makes a contribution to improving
humanity’s future reflection on the source of meaning in our lives.
University of Johannesburg, Auckland Park Campus
References
Belshaw, Christopher. 2014. “Review: Death and the Afterlife.” Philosophical Quarterly 64: 326–328. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqu004
Frankfurt, Harry. 2013. “How the Afterlife Matters.” In Samuel Scheffler, Death and
the Afterlife, ed. Niko Kolodny (Oxford University Press), 131–141.
doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.003.0006
Metz, Thaddeus. 2013a. Meaning in Life: An Analytic Study (Oxford University
Press). doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199599318.001.0001
Metz, Thaddeus. 2013b. “The Meaning of Life.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/life-meaning/.
Mintoff, Joseph. 2008. “Transcending Absurdity.” Ratio 21: 64–84.
doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9329.2007.00385.x
Nagel, Thomas. 2014. “After You’ve Gone.” New York Review of Books. http://www.
nybooks.com/articles/2014/01/09/thomasnagel-after-youve-gone/.
Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations (Harvard University Press).
Scheffler, Samuel. 2012. “The Afterlife” [audio recording of Tanner Lectures].
http://tannerlectures.berkeley.edu/2011-2012/.
Scheffler, Samuel. 2013a. “Death and the Afterlife.” In Samuel Scheffler, Death and
the Afterlife, ed. Niko Kolodny (Oxford University Press), 15–110.
doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.003.0009
Scheffler, Samuel. 2013b. “Death, Value, and the Afterlife: Responses.” In Samuel
Scheffler, Death and the Afterlife, ed. Niko Kolodny (Oxford University Press),
177–207. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.003.0009
42
Note that making this point does not undercut the one above that we can “grasp” what
it would mean for humanity to die out after 1500 years. We can “grasp” that in the sense of
having plausible descriptions of what humanity would be like then.
REASONS OF MEANING TO ABHOR THE END OF THE HUMAN RACE
369
Scheffler, Samuel. 2013c. “The Importance of the Afterlife. Seriously.” New York
Times, September 21, 2013. http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/09/21/
the-importance-of-the-afterlife-seriously/.
Shiffrin, Seana. “Preserving the Valued or Preserving Valuing?” In Samuel Scheffler, Death and the Afterlife, ed. Niko Kolodny (Oxford University Press), 143–158.
doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.003.0007
Wolf, Susan. “The Significance of Doomsday.” In Samuel Scheffler, Death and the
Afterlife, ed. Niko Kolodny (Oxford University Press), 113–129.
doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.003.0005