Global Journal of HUMAN-SOCIAL SCIENCE: A
Arts & Humanities - Psychology
Volume 21 Issue 1 Version 1.0 Year 2021
Type: Double Blind Peer Reviewed International Research Journal
Publisher: Global Journals
Online ISSN: 2249-460x & Print ISSN: 0975-587X
Martin Heidegger and his Way to Ontotheology
By Jacek Surzyn
Jesuit University Ignatianum in Krakow
Abstract- In this article I attempt to present Heidegger's conception of the ontotheology in his late
thought. I based mainly on his famous book “Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning).” In
ontotheology Heidegger needs the figure of “the last god” to show the very path to being itself. It
is not the God of religion, but the proper god of metaphysics, the god of other beginning, which
using a sign (Wink) points Dasein the right direction. It seems to be a key to the meaning of
ontotheology itself. The problem of ontotheology is presented against the backdrop of several of
the most important contexts of Heidegger's thought manifested in “Contributions...”: the problem
of being itself and the path to it or the problem of the last god and his sign.
Keywords: being, entity, the last god, heidegger, sign, ontotheology, enowning, essential swaying.
GJHSS-A Classification: FOR Code: 199999p
MartinHeideggerandhisWaytoOntotheology
Strictly as per the compliance and regulations of:
© 2021. Jacek Surzyn. This is a research/review paper, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons AttributionNoncommercial 3.0 Unported License http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/), permitting all non-commercial use,
distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Martin Heidegger and his Way to Ontotheology
Keywords: being, entity, the last god, heidegger, sign,
ontotheology, enowning, essential swaying.
I.
An Introduction
M
Author: Jesuit University Ignatianum in Krakow, Poland.
e-mail:
[email protected]
1
In this article, I always use the word “being” for the German terms
Sein, or Seyn. On the word Sein, especially in the context of
Heidegger's “Contributions to Philosophy” and in the Old German form
of Seyn, see the extensive Translation's Foreword to the English
translation of this book by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly: Heidegger,
Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), XXII-XXII.
2
I am convinced by the arguments of Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly
(Heidegger 1999: XIX-XXII) and in this text I use the English word
“enowning”.
II.
The Being
The disclosure of being from enowning is a
process that Heidegger describes in “Contributions...”
as an essential swaying (Seyn west). It is important to
remember that he uses the term wesen only in reference
to being. The verb translated as “to hold sway” is now
obsolete in German and we may say Heidegger
restored it in philosophical language. In the past,
German wesen was the equivalent of the verb sein – to
be, and Heidegger linked wesen with “being”
(Heidegger 1983: 76-77; Inwood 1999: 53). Generally,
wesen has been retained in past forms of the verb sein
as war and gewesen. However, in contemporary
German it is mostly used as the noun Wesen, which
means essence, in scholastic tradition referred to as
essentia. This form of entity (being) is expressly
mentioned by Hegel, who claims that the entity has
gone forever, its time has ended and it has become an
essence that has ceased to exist but has remained as
“something.” In this meaning, for Hegel the grasping of
existence is always late, because in the dialectic
process we can only explore what has already passed,
what has become the past, in other words, what has
transformed from “is” to something that “was,” i.e., to
essence-Wesen. This meaning is reflected in the past
form of the verb sein – the above-mentioned gewesen
3
There are two English translations of this book: Contributions to
Philosophy (From Enowning). Trans. by P. Emad, K. Maly. Bloomington
& Indianapolis: Indiana University Press 1999; Contributions to
Philosophy (Of Event). Trans. by R. Rojcewicz, D. Vallega-Neu.
Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press 2012. Both
translations differ significantly from each other. We can say that they
represent different visions of Heidegger's “Contributions...”. I prefer the
translation of P. Emad and K. Maly.
4
Heidegger's concept of “the last god” was strongly influenced by his
reading of Schelling's texts. For more on this topic, see: Seidel 1999:
85-98.
© 2021 Global Journals
27
-
artin Heidegger's philosophical effort is
conceived in the search for the way to being1.
His thought is commonly divided into two
periods. The first is connected with the publication of
“Being and Time” in 1927. This book was well-received
and its author intended for it to be the first part of a great
work related to a large-scale project involving the search
for the proper foundation of reality, that is, being (Sein).
According to Heidegger, being itself has been forgotten
in the history of philosophy, concealed by giving
attention to “what” (τoδe τi) rather than to “is” (ἔivai). In
“Being and Time” Heidegger tried to reverse this
process, beginning with the analysis of human existence
as Dasein. He called this attempt fundamental ontology
and it was intended to result in the discovery of being
through the study of the human entity revealing itself in
the context of being “there” (sein da).
As Heidegger quickly realized, the project was a
failure. Consequently, in the second half of the 1930s,
the famous “turn” (Kehre) occurred in his thought,
leading to the rejection of fundamental ontology in favor
of something that the author called the “enowning”
(Ereignis) of being2. Heidegger carefully described this
process in his work „ Contributions to Philosophy (From
Enowning) [“Contributions to Philosophy (Of Event)”]”,
which remains one of his most mysterious works 3.
In Contributions... Heidegger tries to carry out
probably only one possibility of opening up to being
itself, through the “passing of the last god.” This is a
radical departure from the previous ontology, but also
from the previous thinking of God. The last god is
fundamentally different from the gods of the past. In
Heidegger's idea of the last god, there is no reference to
the God of faith, but the “theological” problem remains
hidden as “ontotheology” 4. In this article, I try to briefly
show what is the meaning of god for revealing being
itself and how Heidegger tries to go to ontotheology.
Year
conception of the ontotheology in his late thought. I based
mainly on his famous book “Contributions to Philosophy (From
Enowning).” In ontotheology Heidegger needs the figure of
“the last god” to show the very path to being itself. It is not the
God of religion, but the proper god of metaphysics, the god of
other beginning, which using a sign (Wink) points Dasein the
right direction. It seems to be a key to the meaning of
ontotheology itself. The problem of ontotheology is presented
against the backdrop of several of the most important contexts
of Heidegger's thought manifested in “Contributions...”: the
problem of being itself and the path to it or the problem of the
last god and his sign.
Global Journal of Human Social Science ( A ) Volume XXI Issue I Version I
Abstract- In this article I attempt to present Heidegger's
2021
Jacek Surzyn
Year
2021
Martin Heidegger and his Way to Ontotheology
-
Global Journal of Human Social Science (A) Volume XXI Issue I Version I
28
(Hegel 2010: 337). Whatever is – and first of all,
whatever will be – is subject to the process of becoming
and existing, which Hegel understood as a dialectical
process of transition from thesis to antithesis, then to
their synthesis, etc.5.
Heidegger, however, uses the verbal function of
the word wesen, which is no longer used in German. As
a verb, it should be translated as “to hold sway,”
because it refers to the presence or appearance of
something. This is quite important, because it is closely
related to the word das Anwesen and its derivatives: die
Anwesenheit, abwesen, das Unwesen, so it alludes to
“presence,” “appearance,” or their opposites (Inwood
1999: 54). Thus, essential swaying must refer to making
present, appearing or becoming, at the same time
pointing to the dynamic character of the phenomenon
with the used verbal form (Heidegger 1994: 484; See
Emad 2007: 29; Esposito 1995: 41). We can briefly say
that on this basis Heidegger presents his critical
assessment of traditional philosophy, which in his
opinion is based on forgetting its ground, its proper
foundation. In language it is manifested in the
discontinuation of the verbal form wesen in favor of the
static, non-dynamic nominal form Wesen. Thus,
according to Heidegger it is possible to approach the
whole history of philosophy as process in which there
was a transition from the verbal form wesen, expressing
movement, to stability and constancy expressed by the
noun das Wesen. Philosophy has become the
metaphysics of entity (actually, its static, constant
essence – das Wesen), abandoning the reflection on
being, the process of being, sein, wesen, i.e., on the
swaying and presence of entity. Metaphysics has
become the reflection on a “what” of that which is and
not on the “is” of that which is.
III.
The Way to Being
According to Heidegger, the swaying of being
is the core and return to doing “authentic” philosophy; it
is the key to building a proper ontology, which will
overcome the metaphysical crisis of the false – because
ontic – approach to what is the beginning, ground and
foundation of everything. The philosopher stresses that
the swaying of being (since it is being that holds sway or
is present) is performed through a sign (Wink). It is the
enowning (Ereignis) and it is disclosed to human beingDasein – in this we can see a clear distinction between
entity and being (Esposito 1995: 41-42). For Heidegger,
entity is the expression of departing from and forgetting
being. But this forgetting is not absolute, as even in
forgetting the visage of being is revealed, flashing
through the entity though remaining hidden. This is
based on the Parmenides’ postulate of the unity
5
“Die Sprache hat im Zeitwort Sein das Wesen in der vorgangenen
Zeit “gewesen” behalten; denn das Wesen ist das vergangene, aber
zeitlos vergangene Sein”. Hegel 2003: 3. See Hegel 2010: 337.
© 2021 Global Journals
(identity) of being and thinking, strongly emphasized by
Heidegger: when we think and express “thinking”, we
think and express being (Heidegger 1994: 432-434; see
Esposito 1995: 40-41; Herrmann 1989: 48-54; Herrmann
1994: 64-84). For example, phrases such as: entity
“is departing” or entity “is forgetting” refer to being,
since the “is” used in these phrases expresses “being.”
But in this very thinking (and expression) being is
hidden, camouflaged, we might say disguised as a link
or a connect occurring in a judgement or sentence.
Heidegger suggests that we should see the primacy of
being over entity, the primacy of concealed being whose
essence lies in remaining in this state and which can
only be disclosed by the proper approach to what entity
really “is” (Heidegger 1994: 255-256). We can
understand it as the process of disclosing being or
making it come to light, which is the dynamic enowning,
acceptance, authenticity of “is” and also the authenticity
of human being as Dasein 6. This process also involves
the relationship with one more important element, since
according to Heidegger it holds sway or is ownmost in a
sign (Wink). The function of the sign seems to be
unquestionable, because the sign is necessary. It
seems to be the essential sway of being itself. Being is
revealed in a sign (or through it) – although being
remains closed, concealed, in the sign it stimulates
Dasein to reflect on (not as intellectual reflection but as
motivation to think and ponder) and experience itself.
The sign is also something like a beckon or summoning
gesture, so it includes some dynamism, which manifests
itself in calling the last god, even if it is unclear whether
the last god is coming nearer or moving further away
(Heidegger 1994: 385, 409). It is the experience of
evanescence: with help of the sign, man recognizes and
realizes that entity conceals being, or – we may say –
that being hides itself behind entity, which seems a
complete abandonment of being (Nancy 2008: 169).
IV.
A Sign of the Last God
As I have already mentioned, Heidegger refers
to being itself in his thinking. He criticizes the earlier
metaphysical tradition whose object was entity as entity
(ens inquantum ens). In that tradition, nothing is
considered the opposite, an absolute exclusion of entity
– it is its logical negation. Heidegger stresses that in the
6
We must understand what means “authenticity”. Heidegger uses the
term Eigentlichkeit, which in German is related to the root eignen, i.e.,
all that is included in enowning, owning, or property. The English term
authenticity does not include this relationship at all. Still, I use it,
following K. Sipowicz, who explains in detail why he suggests using
this term with reference to Heidegger’s thought. Thus, authentic
Dasein would mean Dasein that is gifted, enowned, and actually
(eigentlich) existing (i.e., ontologically) in contrast to the ever-present
inauthenticity of Dasein in an ontic (i. e. entity) context. Cf.: Sipowicz
2007: 9-13. In English, authenticity is related to value, for example W.
J. Richardson writes: “So I suggest that Heidegger does propose
authenticity as a value. And he has two main ways of defending or
justifying this value to us”. Richardson 2012: 168 (See more: 168-172).
© 2021 Global Journals
Year
29
Global Journal of Human Social Science ( A ) Volume XXI Issue I Version I
last god gives a sign to such a move, such a transition.
He passes by Dasein and reveals to him – through a
sign – this openness to possibility. History occurs, so it
reflects movement, transformation and readiness to
disclose being (its truth). Disclosure of being in history is
enowning, gifting Dasein with the truth, i.e., what is notconcealed, unconcealed, aletheic in its essence, i.e., in
entity. Preparation and readiness of history to enowning
being is the transformation and readiness of man and is
connected with the coming of the last god. Heidegger
writes: “Preparation for the appearing of the last god is
the utmost venture of the truth of be-ing, by virtue of
which alone man succeeds in restoring beings”
(Heidegger 1999: 289; see McGrath 2008: 117). The last
god also discloses the truth of being to man, what
consequently seems to be decisive for him, since he
obtains his entity; his own entity is restored to him, i.e.,
the awareness that he is something and in this context
the realization of being-there (Sein da), i.e.,
transformation into the essence in which being has been
disclosed: transformation into Dasein. Man with this
attitude encounters being through the passing/
evanescence of the last god (Nancy 2008: 170).
Heidegger points out that the greatest nearness of the
last god occurs in the situation of refusal-resistance.
Karol Tarnowski tries to cast some light on the
Heideggerian sense of refusal in the presented context.
According to him, Heidegger first of all assumes that the
truth of being is revealed in the other beginning and
disclosed in several degrees of difficulty. Hence, it is a
quasi-mystical path that needs to be gone through in
philosophical experience, which ultimately leads to the
proper foundation, but also to the construction of a
proper attitude by the philosopher (Tarnowski 1990:
348). So, in his view, the essence of truth might first be
read as “the clearance for concealment,” because
Heidegger understands truth “aletheically,” i.e., as nonforgetting, a reminder, or discovering what is covered or
concealed. The sign (Wink) is revealed here, originally
pointing to the relationship between divinity and being,
and basically their association, i.e., to the disclosure of
aletheic divinity and being. For Heidegger, metaphysical
tradition understood the truth of being as a ground,
which gave him reason to assume that in the proper
understanding, the truth of being must be Ab-grund,
which may be translated as abyss. But identifying the
truth of being with the abyss does not explain much. The
meaning becomes clearer when we dig deeper into the
German original, which better shows what signifies the
“abyss,” or Abgrund. The key seems to be the German
ab- usually means “un-,” but it may also be used to add
power to the activity it is linked with. For example, we
have ab-arbeiten, which originally means to execute,
handle or process something, but also to slave away,
work extremely hard. The first dictionary meaning of
Abgrund is abyss or chasm, but when connecting “ab”
with ground, we would get meanings such “to prepare a
-
area of the proper, other question as part of other
beginning, contesting the positive nature of nothing
cannot be justified. In his opinion, for philosophical
reflection to be accurate, it must involve insight into “the
most essential finitude of be-ing.” To enter this area, one
needs to be prepared for accepting the last god.
Heidegger calls this process connected with attitude
“the long-term inkling of the last god,” this state being
the effect of a specific situation: entity, the traditional
God and everything connected with him must be
rejected (Crownfield 2001: 218: Gall 2013: 30).
According to Heidegger, the God of tradition is mostly
the God of Judeo-Christian monotheism. But for him
such a God has died. The death of God reflects the
condition of the metaphysical and religious tradition and
all the “-isms” connected with it. Monotheism, theism, or
atheism are the effect of conceptualization and a
metaphysical approach to the God of religions
(Heidegger 1999: 288-289). For Heidegger, the
bankruptcy of this tradition is an obvious fact. The God
of religions, the revealed God, the only Creator of the
world has been logicized and reduced to the content of
entity. Thus, God was linked to entity. Obviously, such a
God has died, lost his importance, left mankind and
man, is dead just like the whole metaphysics of entity
(Greisch 2008: 247). Heidegger diagnoses: “With the
death of this god, all theisms collapse. The multitude of
gods cannot be quantified but rather is subjected to the
inner richness of the grounds and abgrounds in the site
for the moment of the shining and sheltering-concealing
of the hint of the last god” (Heidegger 1999: 289). He
attributes the fundamental historic role to the last god.
The last god ends the former “history” and initiates other
beginning (andere Anfang) – actually, he is part of an
other beginning, entry to an other history. This entry
related to the passing of the last god as a “unique
uniqueness” opens history to a new possibility it gives
man the possibility of being as a disclosed possibility.
Heidegger stresses that the last god makes the previous
history come to its absolute end, but this does not
exhaust it, merely transforming it into a closed, past
history. He uses the word Verenden to describe this
state. In German it means finishing or ending, but at the
same time, it connotes certain inexhaustibility, making
the term signify something askin to an infinite process of
approaching the end. Thus, the metaphysics of entity
gives way to the metaphysics of being, and the last god
announces this breakthrough. It is the breakthrough of
disclosing/revealing of being, which must always be
connected with the end or completion of the history of
entity. Disclosing itself, being opens “other” possibilities;
it also opens the proper history for man as Dasein. The
disclosing being includes the fullness of absolute
possibility with all the positively approached contents,
as well as openness to the possibility of “what is,” “what
is-not,” “what is not-yet” - all which is connected with
transition and movement. (Crownfield 2001: 221). The
2021
Martin Heidegger and his Way to Ontotheology
Year
2021
Martin Heidegger and his Way to Ontotheology
-
Global Journal of Human Social Science (A) Volume XXI Issue I Version I
30
good, solid ground.” This, however, is only one
possibility. Another one is an opposite process, i.e.,
separation from the ground, getting rid of the
foundation, remaining without ground, that is, in a way
becoming immersed in the open abyss. The role of the
last god could therefore be reduced to the following:
passing by Dasein the last god gives him a sign, which
in turn leads to a groundless-abground. And it should
be opening to the truth of being (Emad 2007: 37-40).
In my opinion this is the core of Heidegger’s
understanding of the process of a transition from
metaphysics of entity to metaphysics of being. For in
this process, determined by the passing of the last god,
we – in a way – get rid of the foundation and become
immersed in the “abyss” of “something” (I have to use
this word, although, as we know, Heidegger does not
has in mind anything like an object) that is nongrounded, or groundless, so in this sense, ultimate and
near the end (Crownfield 2001: 222-223). This
“something” is disclosed but at the same time it is
always concealed, but yet not grounded by anything
else, holding sway in aletheic enowning. We receive
such a sign during the passing of the last god and a
path to being itself seems to be open. This process
becomes a bridge between being itself and Dasein, so it
is a way to ontotheology.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
References Références Referencias
1. Crownfield David. 2001. The Last God. In:
Companion to Heidegger's “Contributions to
Philosophy”, edited by Charles E. Scott, Susan M.
Schoenbohm, Daniela Vallega-Neu, Alejandro
Vallega, 213-228. Bloomington & Indianapolis:
Indiana University Press.
2. Emad, Parvis. 2007. On the way to Heidegger’s
“Contributions to Philosophy”. Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press.
3. Esposito Constantino. 1995. “Die Geschichte des
letzten Gott in Heideggers„ Beiträge zur
Philosophie”. Heidegger Studies, vol. 11: 33-60.
4. Gall Robert S. 2013. “Faith in Doubt in the End”.
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 73/1:
29-38.
5. Greisch Jean. 2008. The Poverty of Heidegger's„
Last God”. In: French Interpretations of Heidegger:
an Exceptional Reception. Edited by David
Pettigrew, Francois Raffoul, 245-264. New York:
State University of New York Press.
Gottfried
Friedrich
Wilhelm.
2003.
6. Hegel
Wissenschaft der Logik. Zweiter Teil. Berlin: Meiner
Verlag.
7. Hegel Gottfried Friedrich Wilhelm. 2010. The
Science of Logic. Translated and Edited by George
di Giovanni. Cambridge: University Press.
8. Heidegger Martin. 1983. Einführung in der
Metaphysik. Edited Peter Jaeger. Gesamtausgabe,
© 2021 Global Journals
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
Band 40. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klosterman
Verlag.
Heidegger Martin. 1994. Beitrӓge zur Philosophie
(Vom Ereignis). Gesamtausgabe, Band 65. Frankfurt
am Main: Vittorio Klosterman Verlag.
Heidegger Martin. 1999. Contributions to Philosophy
(From Enowning). Translated by Parvis Emad,
Kenneth Maly. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana
University Press.
Heidegger Martin. 2012. Contributions to Philosophy
(Of Event). Translated by Richard Rojcewicz,
Daniela Vallega-Neu. Bloomington & Indianapolis:
Indiana University Press.
Herrmann von Franz-Wilhelm. 1989. “Das Ende der
Metaphysik und der andere Anfang des Denkens.
Zu Heideggers „Kehre”. Freiburger Universitätblätter
104: 47-60.
Herrmann von Franz-Wilhelm. 1994. Wege ins
Ereignis. Zu Heideggers „Beiträge zur Philosophie”.
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann Verlag.
Inwood Michael. 1999. A Heidegger Dictionary.
Massachussetts:
Blacwell
Oxford-Maiden,
Publishers.
Maly Kenneth. 2001. Turning in essential Swaying
and the Leap. In: Companion to Heidegger's
“Contributions to Philosophy”, edited by Charles E.
Scott, Susan M. Schoenbohm, Daniela Vallega-Neu,
Alejandro Vallega, 150-170. Bloomington &
Indianapolis: Indiana Univeristy Press.
McGrath S. J. A. 2008. (very) Critical Introdution.
Michigan-Cambridge:
William
B.
Eerdmans
Publishing.
Nancy Jean-Luc. 2008. On a Divine Wink. In: French
Interpretations of Heidegger: an Exceptional
Reception. Edited by David Pettigrew, Francois
Raffoul, 167-186. New York: State University of New
York Press.
Richardson William. J. 2012. Heidegger. London
and New York: Routledge.
Schoenbohm Susan M. 2001. Reading Heidegger's
'Contributions to Philosophy': An Orientation. In:
Companion to Heidegger's “Contributions to
Philosophy”, edited by Charles E. Scott, Susan M.
Schoenbohm, Daniela Vallega-Neu, Alejandro
Vallega, 15-31. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana
Univeristy Press.
Seidel George J. 1999. “Heidegger's Last God and
the Schelling Connection”. Laval theólogique et
philosophique 55/1: 85-98.
Sipowicz Kamil. 2007. Heidegger: degeneracja i
nieautentyczność. Warszawa: Aletheia.
Tarnowski Karol. 1990. Der letzte Gott. “Heidegger
dzisiaj”. Aletheia 1(4). Edited by Piotr Marciszuk,
Cezary Wodziński.