Private Incarceration – Towards a Philosophical
Critique
Yoav Peled and Doron Navot
Introduction
On November 19, 2009, Israel’s High Court of Justice (HCJ) ruled, by an eight to one majority,
that Amendment 28 to the Prison Ordinance (2004), which authorized the construction of the
first privately-run prison in the country, was unconstitutional. The main reason given by the
Court for its globally unprecedented decision was that the very fact of being incarcerated by
a private, for-profit corporation, regardless of the quality of service provided by that private
institution, was an excessive violation of the prisoners’ rights to freedom and to human
dignity and thus contradicted the provisions of Basic Law: Human Dignity and Freedom.
The main opinion in the case, written by Supreme Court President Dorit Beinisch, has
been criticized as incoherent, in that it confused the institutional argument – based on the
non-delegation doctrine – with the argument from human rights. Beinisch explicitly stated
that the concern that prisoners’ rights are more likely to be infringed in a private than in
a public prison was not sufficiently strong to warrant the finding that the amendment was
unconstitutional. Still, she concluded that the very fact that the power to deprive a person of
her liberty rested with a private for-profit entity was, in and of itself, an excessive violation
of the prisoners’ rights to freedom and to human dignity. She also argued that this finding
rendered considering the issue of the delegation of core governmental functions to a private
entity superfluous in this case.1
The Court’s liberal critics have pointed out that the president failed to provide a persuasive
argument for her decision. An argument from human rights, they claimed, should have been
able to show some reason to believe that the prisoners’ rights were more likely to be infringed
in a private than in a public institution. Alternatively, the president could have argued against
the delegation of core governmental functions.2 Having declined to take either of these
courses, her decision amounted to no more than an unsubstantiated assertion. Moreover,
while the Supreme Court spoke its lofty rhetoric, prisoners were languishing in public
prisons in awful conditions. To the extent that these prisoners may have preferred to be
housed in a more comfortable private prison, the Court could also be said to have violated
their rights of free choice and personal autonomy.3
In this paper, we argue that while Beinisch’s decision was indeed incoherent and unjustified when viewed from a liberal perspective, which was her avowed perspective, it is
perfectly coherent and justified from a civic republican perspective. We further argue that,
in general, a coherent moral argument against private incarceration must necessarily rest on
civic republican foundations.
The question of the relations between liberalism and civic republicanism, especially
between their respective conceptions of freedom, has become salient over the last three
decades following the renewal of interest in the civic republican tradition. An argument
heard with increasing frequency in recent years, however, claims that the differences between
the two conceptions of freedom are minor in reality and that every worthy moral position
Constellations Volume 19, No 2, 2012.
C 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford
OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
217
taken from within the civic republican tradition can also be sustained by liberal reasoning.4
Our main argument in this paper is that, at least with respect to the morality of private
incarceration, this is not the case. We contend that liberalism, with its negative conception
of freedom and its pre-political understanding of rights, cannot provide a coherent critique
of private incarceration. A sound philosophical basis for such a critique can, however, be
provided by civic republicanism.
We begin in Part I with a discussion of the non-delegation doctrine, in terms of which
the constitutional question of private incarceration is often formulated. We therefore seek
to address whether the state’s delegation of the function of criminal incarceration to private
entities is desirable, or at least tolerable, from the point of view of both liberalism and civic
republicanism. In Part II, we turn to liberal arguments concerning private incarceration. Our
analysis begins with the utilitarian paradigm, the liberal position most sympathetic to private
incarceration. We then deal with the libertarian perspective, which is of two minds on the
question of private incarceration. Finally, we examine the limits of the Rawlsian critique
of the privatization of incarceration. Part III offers arguments against private incarceration
drawn from the civic republican tradition based on a reconstruction of Rousseau’s Social
Contract and on the works of Michael Walzer. The final section analyzes the Israeli High
Court’s decision in light of the foregoing discussion of liberalism and civic republicanism.
I. The Liberal Social Contract and Non-Delegation
The non-delegation doctrine, which has been developed by the US Supreme Court since
1882, derives from Article 1 of the Constitution: “all legislative powers . . . shall be vested
in Congress.” On this doctrine, the legislative power was given to Congress and could not
be delegated to other branches of government or to private parties. The original use of the
doctrine was to limit the ability of Congress to delegate legislative powers to the President.5
According to the Supreme Court, the legislative branch may not abdicate its responsibility to
resolve “truly fundamental issues” by delegating legislative powers to others or by “failing to
provide adequate directions for the implementation of its declared policy.” Congress should
supply an “intelligible principle” to guide and limit executive discretion.6
Protecting the people from abuse of public power is most commonly seen as the underlying
objective of the non-delegation doctrine. The doctrine is intended to forestall two possible developments: the delegation of power by Congress to the executive branch and the executive’s
delegation of governmental powers to private bodies. By requiring public consensus during
the policy formation and design stages, the non-delegation principle increases the likelihood
that such powers will not be used to harm individual liberty. Additionally, by preventing the
delegation of power to non-elected entities, the principle keeps the responsibility for creating
public policy in the hands of Congress and hence helps buttress democratic control and the
rule of law. This enhances, or at least sustains, governmental accountability.7
The US Supreme Court has not articulated a theory of the principles that govern the
non-delegation doctrine and has not defined a precise test to distinguish between statutes
that properly delegate governmental powers and those that do not. In practice, the nondelegation doctrine has served to restrain neither privatization in general nor the privatization
of incarceration in particular. At the federal level, the Supreme Court has not invalidated
legislation on non-delegation grounds since the mid-1930s.8 Consequently, the doctrine has
been used in US debates over private incarceration, but without much success.9
Scholars have tended to explain the Supreme Court’s limited interpretation of the nondelegation doctrine in functional terms. It is common knowledge that in the modern
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
218
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
administrative state, wide-ranging delegations of legislative authority to executive branch
agencies are inevitable. A strict reading of the separation of powers doctrine is but a fiction.10 Many scholars therefore believe that the non-delegation doctrine is dead or practically
useless. For example, Paul Verkuil, an advocate of the doctrine and an opponent of the outsourcing of governmental functions, wrote that “non-delegation alone may not be a sufficient
instrument for constraining pervasive outsourcing.”11
The functionalist explanation of the judicial interpretation of the non-delegation doctrine
masks the fact that such interpretation is derived from fundamental normative assumptions
about the nature of politics and the role of the state in society. In order to argue why certain
governmental functions should not be delegated, we need a normative theory that explores
the role of the state and political institutions in a just and good society. In the next section,
we examine whether a number of liberal normative theories can provide such arguments. As
we shall see, without the assumption that our political rights are constituted through public
institutions or the belief that social institutions mold our preferences and our behavior in
fundamental ways, one cannot provide conclusive arguments as to why certain institutions
must remain public or why certain functions should not be delegated to private bodies. Thus
commenting on the legitimacy of private incarceration, Judge Richard Posner has remarked,
“A prisoner has a legally protected interest in the conduct of his keeper, but not in the
keeper’s identity.”12
II. Liberalism
1. Utilitarianism
Given the prominence utilitarianism continues to enjoy in western politics and governance,
it is unsurprising that much of the debate over private incarceration is couched in utilitarian
terms, even when participants adhere to other moral philosophies.13
With his Panopticon scheme – “the inspection house” – Jeremy Bentham was the forerunner of the ideology underlying private incarceration.14 Characteristically, Bentham’s scheme
was based on the principle of the conjunction of duty and interest. The Panopticon was to be
run by means of private contract management, and the profit motive operative in the process
would enhance the public interest by penalizing criminals at a lower cost.15 The contractor
was a key figure in the scheme, and Bentham intended himself to be the contractor of the
first prison to be built according to his principles.16
It is generally agreed that the failure to promote the Panopticon scheme led Bentham
to embrace the idea of representative democracy. He concluded that this failure resulted
from the influence of sinister interests on members of Parliament17 and saw representative
democracy as a measure with which to counter the influence of these interests and ensure
“the greatest happiness for the greatest numbers.”18 Thus, in the history of utilitarianism,
democracy and private incarceration came together into the world.
Since the effects of private incarceration (or of anything else for that matter) on the general
happiness of humankind, or just on a particular society bound by the borders of a specific
sovereign state, are impossible to calculate, the debate over social utility is often reduced to a
debate over the comparative economic efficiency of private versus public incarceration, and
sometimes even to the simple question of fiscal savings.19 By contrast, a more sophisticated
utilitarian analysis would have to not only consider fiscal savings, but must also be mindful
of more intangible factors such as the effects of private incarceration on state capacity and
legitimacy, democratic accountability, and so on. As the prominent Princeton University
penologist John DiIulio has stated:
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
219
Despite a variety of claims to the contrary, there is absolutely nothing. . . that would enable
us to speak confidently about how private corrections firms compare with public corrections agencies in terms of costs, protection of inmates’ civil rights, reliance on particular
management technologies, or any other significant dimension.20
This statement, made in the late 1980s, is no less true today, after a dramatic increase in the
number of prisoners incarcerated in private prisons and a plethora of studies on the matter.21
Nevertheless, utilitarian analysts, lured by the prospect of cutting government costs, still
attempt to find ways of making private incarceration more appealing on utilitarian grounds.
Thus, James Gentry has argued that “serious problems may arise in attempting to ensure
the fidelity of entrepreneurial jailers to societal preferences,” and that “significant factors
suggest that private prisons could be inferior to their public counterparts in both quality and
efficiency.” He also noted the difficulty of even ascertaining what societal preferences would
actually be in this particular case. Still, in a truly Benthamite fashion, he proceeded to offer
“a set of monitoring devices that . . . [would make it possible] to harness existing private
motivations to generate improvements in prison quality.”22
Gentry admits that under present conditions the state is likely to perform better as an
administrator of public prisons than as a monitor of private ones. The costs of effective
monitoring, he points out, would have to be deducted from the savings to state budgets that
justified privatization in the first place. As a result, the state would have an incentive to keep
monitoring costs as low as possible, inevitably reducing the quality of its oversight. Coupled
with the problems of hidden delivery, entrenchment, the monopolistic tendencies of the
private corrections market, and “capture” of the regulatory agency by the industry, this will
create a strong incentive for the state to be satisfied with the minimum standards stipulated
in legislation or ordered by the courts.23 (We would add that under these conditions, the state
would most likely be satisfied with the appearance of meeting such minimum standards.)
Gentry proposes to deal with this problem through a system of pecuniary incentives,
both positive and negative, that would make it the private jailer’s interest to provide quality
service in its prisons. His system consists of fines for any divergence from the standards
of service delivery, buttressed by transparency of the prison operation, monitoring by the
prisoners themselves, state ownership of the physical prison facilities, short contract terms
to avoid entrenchment, and so on. We do not wish to enter into a detailed critique of Genrty’s
proposals because his approach is one of trying to solve in practical ways the problems
of private incarceration and therefore offers little by way of theoretical relevance to our
inquiry. Nonetheless, it would seem that in order for Gentry’s system to work, he would have
to wish away many of the problems he himself identified with private prisons in the first
place.
Along with economic efficiency, accountability plays a prominent role in the utilitarian
private incarceration discourse.24 Governmental accountability is the key to ensuring that
public officials’ private interests do not dominate legislation and the policymaking process
to the detriment of the public good. It is for this reason that Martha Minow identified
governmental accountability as the central issue requiring inventive work and renewed public
involvement.25 Although she did not define accountability precisely, she emphasized the
role of the public, especially in establishing criteria for successful governmental activity.26
However, she also averred that insisting on public accountability does not require public
monopoly over the design and delivery of public services. Privatization could improve quality
and accountability, and it has a potential for innovation and increased efficiency. It may also
enhance pluralism and stimulate new knowledge and the construction of new infrastructure.27
On the other hand, privatization also risks reduced quality, unequal treatment, and outright
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
220
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
corruption.28 In sum, then, Minow neither supports nor opposes prison privatization in
principle, as long as public accountability is kept viable and dynamic.
Gillian Metzger has argued that the case against private prisons is easy to overstate and
that we must also confront the widespread problems and deficiencies present in many public
prisons. Moreover, she argues that private prisons are in some ways more accountable than
public ones. If private prisons lead to improved prison conditions and services, they enhance
the human dignity of the prisoners, a consideration that is relevant from a constitutional
point of view. The challenge posed by privatization is to determine how to devise the means
of preserving governmental accountability without sacrificing regulatory flexibility and its
associated benefits. The concrete concern is whether private delegation of governmental
power is adequately structured to preserve constitutional accountability.29 In sum, Metzger’s
discussion clarifies the connection between accountability and utilitarian calculation. It also
illustrates that the non-delegation principle cannot provide a conclusive basis for rejecting
private incarceration as long as the enhancement of accountability or democratic control
of policy is interpreted as the principle’s main objective. After all, one cannot dismiss the
possibility that private prisons will be more accountable than public ones.
2. Libertarianism
Libertarians, in general, face a painful dilemma. In principle, they believe in preserving the
state-of-nature right of private enforcement of one’s own and everybody else’s rights unless
such right has expressly been given up. If that right is to be given up in the state of nature, as it
must, Robert Nozick posits that it would be given up to private for-profit associations, whose
respect for the rights of their non-clients would be ensured by market forces. He further
argues that the market for private enforcement agencies would tend toward monopolization,
and once a monopolistic all-encompassing protection agency emerges, we are really in the
presence of what he calls the “minimal state.”30 So Nozick and other libertarian thinkers
accept, perhaps reluctantly, the monopoly of the state over law enforcement.
If the state is nothing but a private protective association that has gained monopoly status,
there is nothing essential that differentiates it from other private corporations. On this view,
there are no inherent state functions that cannot be delegated to others. The state derives its
authority from the consent of the governed, expressed through the delegation to it of their
right to judge their fellow human beings. If the coercive powers of the state are delegated
powers to begin with, there is no principled reason why the state could not delegate them
further, to either public or private entities. Barak Medina made a particularly blunt statement
of this position in the context of the Israeli debate over private incarceration:
According to the prevailing approach [sic], the private-public distinction is normatively
baseless, and is used, if at all, only for descriptive purposes. An activity is “private” if it
is free of limitations, such that the actor is free to employ her discretion regardless of the
interests of others, and it is “public” if the actor is subject to such limitations. The decision
whether an activity should be subject to limitations is based on substantial reasons, rather
than on some formal, pre-defined classification as “private” or “public.” The classification
is the outcome of the substantive consideration, not its source. Consequently, it is difficult
to make any meaningful distinction between prisons’ staff according to the formal status
of their employer, the state or a private corporation.31
The only issue that matters to libertarians of this kind is that individual rights be preserved
through due process, and they do not see any reason why they should be preserved any better
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
221
by public bodies than by private ones. On the contrary, they argue, everything else being
equal, due process is more likely to be observed by private bodies because market discipline
is more effective than administrative control. Having cleared this hurdle, libertarians proceed
to enter the utilitarian arena, where, naturally, they find the market to be much more efficient
than the state in providing correctional (and most other) services.32
Another strand of libertarianism, however, is suspicious of private incarceration, since it
does not believe that many of the “clients” of the private corrections companies – those who
committed “victimless crimes” such as drug use – should be imprisoned in the first place.33
Thus, for this brand of libertarianism, private interests should not take part in the illegitimate
incarceration of people who have not infringed on anyone else’s rights, the only legitimate
reason for interfering with personal liberty. According to Bruce Benson, prison privatization
may be seen as a Faustian bargain, resulting in a more efficient way to punish people for
victimless crimes or for breaking laws that may be unjust.34 Needless to say, Benson does
not view public prisons any more favorably than he does private ones. If anything, he still
considers private corrections companies to be a more benign force in society than the interests
that surround public correctional institutions such as prison guards’ unions.
In sum, libertarians are of two minds on the question of private incarceration. Some favor
it because they support, in principle, the transfer of as many state functions as possible to
the market, independently of the calculus of economic costs and benefits involved. Other
libertarians, however, are opposed to private incarceration because they do not think private
interests should be involved in what they consider the illegitimate deprivation of liberty from
perpetrators of “victimless crimes” and the violators of other unjust laws such as income tax
laws.
3. Rawlsian Liberalism
In the context of private incarceration, the human dignity of prisoners is of crucial importance
for Rawlsians. When the state incarcerates offenders, it strips them of their freedom and
dignity and consigns them to conditions of severe regimentation and physical vulnerability
for extended periods. Before seeking to ensure efficient incarceration, therefore, it must first
be determined if the particular penal practice at issue is even legitimate. According to Sharon
Dolovich, penal policies must conform to two principles: the principle of humanity and the
principle of parsimony. The principle of humanity entails a prohibition on gratuitously cruel
and unusual punishment, and the principle of parsimony entails a prohibition on sentences
that are disproportionately long.35
On Rawlsian principles, inhumane treatment of convicts (which incarceration is by definition) would have to meet two criteria in order not to be considered gratuitous: proportionality
vis-à-vis the need to deter evildoers from harming others and efficiency subject to the difference principle, i.e. a reasonable guarantee that resources that could have been invested
in making the conditions of incarceration less inhumane will be invested in improving the
conditions of the least fortunate free members of society with respect to their most urgent
interests. Without such a guarantee, the state is obligated to invest the resources in making
the conditions of incarceration less inhumane.36
Dolovich argues, like all critics of private incarceration, that if left to their own devices,
private prisons, whose sole motive is the profit motive, would be tempted to cut costs in two
major ways: by providing for inmates’ needs at lower than satisfactory levels and by “hiring
fewer staff members, paying lower wages, and reducing staff training.” In both cases, costcutting would inevitably result in greater violations of the humanity principle. The standard
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
222
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
response to this argument is two-pronged: (1) have the contract specify exactly the kinds,
frequency, quality, and so on of the services to be provided to inmates, and the number,
qualifications, and training of prison guards; and (2) effective state regulation. However,
Dolovich argues that private prison contracts are “incomplete contracts” by their very nature
in that these requirements cannot be specified at a level of detail that could guarantee against
cost-cutting practices. Moreover, due to the nature of prisons as total, and potentially violent,
institutions, these incomplete contracts necessarily accord private prison officials “residual
control rights,” that is, the right to diverge from the agreed-upon standards and practices in
order to meet unexpected contingencies.37
As for state regulation, four regulatory mechanisms are usually proposed by proponents
of private incarceration as effective vehicles of state oversight – the courts, accreditation,
monitoring, and competition.38 Dolovich, once again like many other critics of private
incarceration, is skeptical of the effectiveness of these oversight mechanisms and provides
rich historical evidence in support of her skepticism. She concludes, on the basis of this
evidence, “that although much of the available data is inconclusive regarding the overall
quality of conditions in private prisons as compared with public facilities, meaningful data
do exist showing elevated levels of physical violence in private prisons.” And this is so despite
the fact that, in the United States, maximum security prisoners make up about ten per cent
of all prisoners in state-run prisons and only about four and a half per cent in privately-run
ones.39
In view of all this, Dolovich’s overall conclusion may sound surprising:
Certainly, nothing in the foregoing discussion goes to show that the state’s use of private
prisons could never satisfy the humanity principle. What it does show is that, when the
state looks to privatization to save money on the cost of corrections, there is reason to
expect conditions of confinement to fall below even that level of quality and safety that
can be reasonably expected of those charged with the difficult task of running the prisons.
When the state’s aim is saving money, it will be unwilling to undertake measures that will
substantially raise the cost of privatization, even when doing so could arguably ensure more
meaningful protections for vulnerable inmates.40
Dolovich argues that from a Rawlsian perspective, deficiencies of private incarceration stem
from two practices that are widespread in the prison system as a whole: outsourcing of various
non-security functions, such as food, laundry, medical care, and so on, in order to cut costs,
and the delegation to prison officials of considerable power over their essentially helpless
wards.41 Fully privatized prisons aggravate these problems, but such problems certainly are
not unique to them. In principle, if expenditures on prisoners’ needs could meet the standard
of Rawls’s difference principle, and if due process could guarantee that prison officials will
not abuse their power, Rawlsian liberals, like Dolovich, would find no reason to object to
private incarceration.
Indeed, the main point of Dolovich’s essay is to argue that the very institution of incarceration should be revisited, not that there is anything inherently unique to private incarceration.
From her perspective, private incarceration is merely a “miners’ canary” that illuminates the
problems of incarceration in general: “For liberal legitimacy . . . the current [dismal] state
of public prisons represents not a rejoinder to the foregoing critique of private prisons, but
rather an occasion for asking whether the insights gleaned from that critique help also to
explain failings in the public system.”42
More recently, Dolovich has expressed concern with the exclusive focus on efficiency
in the privatization discourse. She explained that comparing the efficiency of private and
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
223
public prisons operates as a rhetorical device that keeps the debate within particular bounds,
excluding some concerns altogether and reframing others in ways consistent with utilitarian
priorities. Since this issue is dominant in the debate over private prisons, it is unsurprising
that critics concerned with the normative implications of privatization have had “so little
success” in influencing the debate.43 However, Dolovich’s major concern is the humanity of
penal institutions and the quality of the public and scholarly debate about privatization, and
not private prisons as such. She does not take a stand against private incarceration, but uses
the debate to point out the issues she believes should be addressed and how the efficiency
argument stifles that debate.
If her Rawlsian premises are taken into account, Dolovich’s position is not at all surprising.
Firstly, as Michael Sandel has shown, Rawlsians are primarily concerned not with the
intrusion of private interests into spheres of social relations that, on the civic-republican
view, should be immune from such interests, but rather with the “background conditions”
under which such intrusion takes place. If this intrusion could occur under “fair background
conditions” that would guarantee respect for individual rights—as might be obtained through
sufficiently complete contracts and effective state oversight—Rawlsian liberals would not
consider it an act of coercion but rather of consensual contractual relations.44
Secondly, Rawls’ difference principle is problematic, not only in its application to concrete
social situations, but also in its essence. As Joshua Cohen has pointed out, the principle asserts
that no one should be less well-off than anyone “needs to be.” However, the actual meaning
of the term “needs to be” is ambiguous in that it is unclear whether people’s attitudes and
preferences should be taken into account in determining how well-off a person needs to
be. How, for example, should we treat the fact that many people in the US are vehemently
opposed to “socialized medicine” in considering that millions of Americans are very badlyoff in terms of their access to healthcare (or at least were badly-off prior to the recent
reform)? Cohen shows that it is possible (although, according to him, not desirable) to read
the difference principle as stating that given the American social ethos regarding publiclyprovided healthcare, millions of people are not worse-off than they “need to be.” By the same
token, given the American social ethos regarding “law and order” and private enterprise, it
may be just to spare the money required to make prison conditions less inhumane, even if that
money ends up as profit in the coffers of private incarceration companies rather than being
spent to improve the conditions of the least well-off free members of society (by providing
them with subsidized health insurance, for example).45
Other related aspects of Rawls’ theory that may be relevant to the discussion of private
incarceration are his conception of the self and his understanding of moral justification.
Like Rousseau, and at least partly under his influence, Rawls believes that social institutions affect the development of human propensities.46 He shares with Rousseau the thesis
that institutions “make a large difference to ethos”: “the character and interests of individuals themselves. . . are not fixed or given. . . . Now everyone recognizes that the institutional
form of society affects its members and determines in large part the kind of persons they
are.”47
But although Rawls believes that institutions could potentially change the way people
perceive of themselves and their society, their interests and the meaning of freedom,48 his
commitment to a certain type of respect and to personal autonomy as self-direction militates
against building social institutions that might curtail individuals’ abilities to form, revise,
and pursue individual life plans.49 As with other liberals, Rawls does not regard the state, and
public institutions in general, as a necessary component to achieving autonomy and liberty.50
Thus, although Rawls is aware of the important role institutions play in social relations
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
224
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
and of their constitutive effect on people, his support for political institutions is restrained,
and his philosophy does not supply the necessary arguments against delegation of state
power.
Finally, Rawls’ reasonable decision procedure and his conditions of justification have a
limiting effect on our ability to make principled arguments regarding constitutional issues,
such as the one we are dealing with in this paper. Already in his first published article,
when he was seeking “a reasonable decision procedure which is sufficiently strong. . . to
determine the manner in which competing interests should be adjudicated,” Rawls wrote
that “it is required that the judgment. . . should not be determined by a conscious application of principles so far as this may be evidenced by introspection. . . . What is required is
that the judgment not be determined by a systematic and conscious use of ethical principles.”51 Later on, the close connection between the way arguments are justified publicly
and their political validity became a central tenet of Rawls’ political philosophy. From the
perspective he developed since the 1980s, the truth claims of public arguments relating to
constitutional matters and to basic justice could not be based solely on the fact that they
derived from certain comprehensive doctrines which were firmly believed to be true. Such
truth claims had to be justified on the basis of beliefs grounded in the prevailing public
discourse:
[I]n discussing constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice we are not to appeal
to comprehensive religious and philosophical doctrine – to what we as individuals or
members of associations see as whole truth. . . . As far as possible, the knowledge. . . and
ways of reasoning that ground our affirming the principles of justice and their application
to constitutional essentials and basic justice are to rest on the plain truths now widely
accepted, or available, to citizens generally. Otherwise, the political conception would not
provide a public basis of justification.52
Incarceration, which involves the organized use of violence and the infringement of basic
rights, is clearly a matter of basic justice and constitutional essentials. Discussions concerning
it are therefore subject to these requirements of justification.
More generally, Rawls’ theory of justification privileges factual arguments and considerations of public policy over abstract principles: “the feasibility of the basic liberties depends
upon circumstances.”53 He believes that a decision that contradicts a basic principle could be
just if it is supported by the facts and if the reflexive balance counters the abstract principle.
A theory of morality should be free to rely on contingent assumptions and on general facts.
It is accordingly a mistake to believe that general principles and abstract conceptions always
override particular judgments. This is especially true with respect to alternatives having to
do with the situation of the less free members of society. We must acknowledge the fact that
it might be just to accept an alternative that is bad in itself if it improves the conditions of
the less free.
For example, when choosing between supporting or opposing the practice of enslaving
prisoners of war, it is not sufficient to consider whether enslavement is or is not just in
principle. We should also ask what the alternatives are. If the alternative is the execution
of these POWs, we should decide in favor of enslaving them, a practice less unjust in itself
and one that leaves the door open for a better future: “There may be transition cases where
enslavement is better than current practice.” Rawls emphasizes, however, that provisional
acceptance of slavery cannot “appeal to the necessity or at least to the great advantage of
these servile arrangements for the higher forms of culture. . . the principle of perfection would
be rejected in the original position.”54
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
225
In sum, a Rawlsian perspective may provide grounds for supporting private incarceration,
at least as a provisional measure, for the following reasons:
1. This issue must not be decided on the basis of one comprehensive doctrine (such as civic
republicanism), while ignoring other comprehensive doctrines (such as utilitarianism).
2. The issue cannot be decided solely on the basis of abstract conceptions, such as freedom
or human dignity. The decision should consider a whole array of factual matters as well,
such as the conditions of incarceration in public prisons, the prisoners’ own preferences,
the state’s ability to regulate the private corrections industry, and so on.
3. Given the existing beliefs and preferences of the public regarding public spending, it
might be just to privatize prisons, at least for a while, in order to improve the conditions
of the prisoners, who are the least free members of society.
Rawlsian arguments against private incarceration may thus be limited by Rawls’ commitment to individualism, by his anti-perfectionist moral philosophy, and by his theory of
justification.
III. Civic Republicanism
Michael Walzer, “politically. . . a liberal but also what Europeans would call a social democrat,”55 straddles the line between liberalism and civic republicanism and illustrates in his
own work the differences between these two perspectives on the question of private incarceration. In 1985, as prison privatization was getting under way in the US, Walzer wrote
an essay criticizing the new trend.56 In his essay, submitted later, with small changes, as a
brief in support of the plaintiffs in the Israeli prison privatization case,57 liberal and republican arguments, or arguments from the perspectives of both coercion and corruption, to use
Sandel’s terms, were intertwined.
Walzer argued that establishing private prisons was wrong because it “exposes the prisoners to private or corporate purposes, and it sets them at some distance from the protection
of the law.”58 He presented the legitimacy of the law as stemming from a Lockean social
contract, complete with tacit consent and the need for an impartial arbiter:
When we agree to the laws. . . we accept the proposition that if we ever break the law we
ought to be punished. Criminals are punished, then, with their own consent. And if this isn’t
active and explicit consent, then it is constructive and tacit: for the criminal has lived under
and enjoyed the benefits of the laws, and could have participated in the making of these
laws. . . . But if this is right, then it is crucial that the agents of punishment be agents of the
laws and of the people who make them. Though it may sound paradoxical, the criminal is
punished by his own agents – who are ours too. That’s why private punishment is ruled out.
We can’t be judges or police or jailers in our own name or for our own purposes. It is only
some public purpose, which the criminal could share – which, as a fellow citizen, he does
share – that justifies punishment.59
Later, Walzer imperceptibly slips into republican arguments: when the uniformed agents
of the state enforce the law as an expression of “the general will . . . they don’t oppress
us.” However, when private or corporate interests interfere in law enforcement, “justice is
corrupted.”60
The corruption of justice by the intrusion of private interests into the public sphere does
not seem to Walzer to be a sufficiently strong argument against private incarceration; in the
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
226
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
final part of his essay, he again resorts to liberal arguments – the difficulty of ensuring the
accountability of and oversight over private prisons. But these arguments, as we have shown,
do not address the essential problem of private incarceration and therefore cannot support
a coherent principled position against it. Indeed, Walzer concluded his essay, and his legal
brief, with what seems to be a conditional endorsement of private incarceration as long as the
corporations charged with the task are not-for-profit. This endorsement, we shall emphasize,
is not consistent with the reference he made in the legal brief (but not in the published
essay) to non-delegation, arguing that in privatizing law enforcement, “the state gives up on
what it cannot give up legitimately, which is its prerogative to punish or use coercive force
against violators of the law.”61 This inconsistency is a symptom of the difficulty faced by
liberal theory, which Walzer has remained committed to, in pointing out why private prisons,
whether for profit or not, should be forbidden.
However, we can find a theoretical basis for a civic republican critique of private incarceration in Walzer’s own philosophical work, especially in Spheres of Justice. We will turn to
that book shortly, after first laying out the basic premises of civic republicanism as articulated
by Rousseau.
Civic republicans see a moral purpose common to all citizens, not contractual relations
among individuals, as the basis of society. Under the assumption that people do not necessarily
know what is just and best for them, republicans are not only concerned with the question
of what is just and good from each individual’s perspective, but are primarily interested in
the question of how to move people to do the good defined pre-institutionally, i.e. is not
based on consent but is rather accepted as given—“that is inherited” in Alisdair MacIntyre’s
term—by the political community.
Convinced that the bounds of possibility in moral matters are broader than liberals imagined, Rousseau aimed at forging all members of society into a greater whole. This, he claimed,
would reduce, not increase, interdependence among citizens, while making everybody dependent upon the collectivity itself. In order to reach that goal, people should give up all
their resources in entering the social contract and be given new ones by the state. “Only then,
when the voice of duty succeeds physical impulsion and right succeeds appetite, does man,
who until then had looked only to himself, see himself forced to act on other principles, and
to consult his reason before listening to his inclinations.”62
For Rousseau, law is not a procedure for regulating social relations in a society based
on conflicting individual interests. It is, rather, the supreme expression of the moral will of
the community. Violating the general will, which expresses the true will of the transgressor
himself as a citizen—whether he realizes it or not—means breaching a sacred trust, the
solidarity on which the very existence of the community depends. Such a breach endangers
the existence of the community and is therefore tantamount to treason.63 Moreover, since
freedom, for Rousseau, means living under the law one makes for oneself through one’s
membership in a community and through participation in its general will, the criminal
already rendered himself unfree in violating the law, since he has allowed his passions to
overcome his real interests (that can be perceived by his reason). Reason would also bring
him to the realization that the punishment imposed on him by the community is actually an
expression of his own free will as a citizen and thus not a deprivation, but an affirmation of
his freedom.64
It is this bond between the individual – be he a convicted criminal or not – and the
community that is corrupted by the introduction of mercenary relations into the criminal
justice system. In Spheres of Justice, Walzer argues that this bond cannot be conceptualized
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
227
through the liberal idea of social contract, based as it is on the notion of the “unencumbered
self.” In an obvious allusion to Rawls’s original position, he argues:
Even if they are committed to impartiality, the question most likely to arise in the minds of
the members of a political community is not, What would rational individuals choose under
universalizing conditions of such-and-such a sort? but rather, What would individuals like
us choose, who are situated as we are, who share a culture and are determined to go on
sharing it? And this is a question that is readily transformed into, What choices have we
already made in the course of our common life? What understandings do we really share?65
Historically, Walzer argues that an important part of this shared understanding is the idea that
each sphere of social activity has its own distinct good, that these goods are not interchangeable, and that by its very nature the good associated with each social sphere determines what
is the right distribution of it (hence “spheres of justice”).
Walzer’s “theory of goods” harks back to Karl Marx’s distinction between the use value
of commodities, which is particular to each commodity and is therefore not interchangeable,
and their exchange value, which is measured universally by units of labor time, and therefore
is interchangeable. Walzer’s theory of goods has six points:
1. All goods are social goods.
2. Human beings draw their identities from the ways in which they relate to goods (as
producers, consumers, owners, and so on).
3. There is no single set of “primary goods” (as Rawls avers). Each type of good is, or
should be, autonomous of the others.
4. Different social goods possess distributive criteria and arrangements that are intrinsic to
them (a particular manifestation of the priority of good over right).
5. The social meanings we attach to goods are historical.
6. Every set of goods constitutes a separate distributive sphere.66
For civic republicans, the intrusion of a good that belongs to one social sphere into
another constitutes corruption. Liberals would partially agree with that position – they also
see corruption in the intrusion of certain kinds of monetary relations into politics or the
judicial process as well as in the intrusion of politics into the market (hence their principled
opposition to state ownership of economic enterprises, and so on). Liberals, however, have
always considered exchange value as the primary good, the good into which all other goods
are ultimately reducible. In the words of Thomas Hobbes, “The value or WORTH of a man
is, as of all other things, his price, that is to say, so much as would be given for the use of
his power; and therefore is not absolute, but a thing dependent on the need and judgment
of another.”67 Later on, liberals added certain individual rights to their definition of primary
goods, but the contradiction between exchange value and individual rights makes it difficult
for them, as we have argued, to take a principled stand against the intrusion of monetary
relations into many social spheres.
Walzer rejects the idea of a primary good, and for him, as for civic republicans more
generally, each social good should stay within the confines of its own social sphere. The
social good specific to the political sphere is not, as in the liberal view, protection of individual
rights that are antecedent to it, but rather citizenship – membership in a solidary community
based on a commonality of moral purpose which is prior to any notion of individual rights.
This social good determines its own system of distribution – based on desert (or civic virtue) –
and this cannot be exchanged for the good of the market, money: “Private trading is ruled out
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
228
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
by virtue of what politics, or democratic politics, is – that is, by virtue of what we did when
we constituted the political community and what we still think about what we did.”68 This
is so because “[t]he market doesn’t recognize desert,” the nature of which stands in tension
with the idea of supply and demand.69 By the same token, the main legitimating principle of
market relations is free exchange, in the negative sense of freedom, while political relations,
on the civic republican view, are legitimated by a positive notion of freedom, as the capacity
to contribute to the promotion of the overriding moral purpose of the community.
Criminal punishment, and above all incarceration (as well as capital punishment, where
this institution still exists), is based on coercion. On the civic republican view, this coercion
is legitimated by social solidarity, which the offender violated. The good of social solidarity
determines its own mode of distribution, from bestowing high rewards to those who possess
great civic virtue to dispensing severe punishment to those whose actions undermine the
community. The principle of free market exchange is totally foreign to this sphere of social
activity, and introducing it would corrupt both spheres: the intrusion of private interest would
corrupt the political sphere, where the criminal justice system belongs, while the intrusion of
coercion would corrupt market relations, which are legitimately based only on free exchange.
(The “clients” of private incarceration are not free to choose their jailers, and so on.)
When placed in a private, for-profit prison, prisoners no longer live under the law they
made for themselves, but become subjects to the will of an alien power. In Walzer’s words,
The critical exposure is to profit-taking at the prisoners’ expense, and given the conditions
under which they live, they are bound to suspect that they are regularly used and exploited.
For aren’t the purposes of their private jailers different from the purposes of the courts that
sent them to jail? All the internal rules and regulations of their imprisonment, the system
of discipline and reward, the hundreds of small decisions that shape their daily lives, are
open now to a single unanswerable question: Is this punishment or economic calculation,
the law or the market?70
When they lose their autonomy in this way, convicts lose their capacity as moral agents, so
that rehabilitation and re-entry into the normal life of the community become impossible.
Thus, on the civic republican conception, the corrupt practice of private incarceration is both
illegitimate by its very nature and counter-productive in terms of the real interests of the
community.
IV. Human Rights Division v. Minister of Finance
To recapitulate, President Beinisch’s opinion dismisses the non-delegation argument as unnecessary for deciding the case because she deems the violation of the prisoners’ rights to
freedom and to human dignity attendant upon their very placement in a private prison sufficient for finding Amendment 28 to the Prison Ordinance unconstitutional.71 And since such
violation of the prisoners’ rights was established independently of whether their treatment
was likely to be better or worse in a private prison than in a public one, the issues of oversight,
accountability, and so on were also found irrelevant to the case. Liberal critics have found
her decision incoherent and argued that a persuasive case against the constitutionality of the
amendment had to be based either on the non-delegation doctrine or on the claim that the
inmates’ rights were more likely to be violated in a private than in a public institution, or on
both.72
In this section of the paper, we argue that the president’s decision was correct but that she
could have made a more persuasive case for it had she relied explicitly on republican rather
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
229
than liberal reasoning. To make this argument, we wish to distinguish between not-for-profit
and for-profit private prisons and claim that from a civic-republican perspective, placing
prisoners in the former type of institution violates their right to freedom, while placing them
in the latter kind violates their right to dignity as well. (Beinisch did not make this distinction
because the issue of private not-for-profit prisons was not before the Court.)
As is well known, the civic republican tradition understands freedom as living under laws
that one has made for oneself as a member of the political community. Being unfree, says
Philip Pettit,
does not consist in being restrained; on the contrary, the restraint of a fair system of law
– a non-arbitrary regime – does not make you unfree. Being unfree consists rather in
being subject to arbitrary sway: being subject to the potentially capricious will or rather
potentially idiosyncratic judgment of another.73
Walzer, while maintaining the distinction between for-profit and not-for-profit private prisons, actually provides an argument why any kind of private coercive authority is harmful to
freedom:
The policeman’s uniform symbolizes his representative character. When he puts on his uniform, he strips himself bare, so to speak, of his private opinions and motivations. . . . When
the police behave in this way, impersonally enforcing the general will, their coercive powers
are justified. They may annoy us or frustrate us and even, sometimes, frighten us, but they
don’t oppress us.74
This representative quality, which enables coercion to be non-oppressive because it stems
rightfully from the law that the prisoner has made for himself as a citizen, is lost when the
police officer or prison guard is employed by a private corporation on contract to the state,
whether or not that corporation seeks to profit from that contract. The very fact that the
prisoner is made dependent on a private will that mediates between him and the law makes
the prisoner unfree because a free person is a person who is not subordinated to an alien
private will. Regulation, oversight, accountability, and so on can mitigate the manifestations
of this problem, but they cannot affect its essence.
In the brief he submitted to the HCJ, Walzer limited his argument to the question of
freedom, but Beinisch, echoing Walzer’s argument, went on to argue that incarceration in a
private for-profit prison constituted a violation of the prisoners’ right to human dignity as
well:
There is . . . an inherent and natural concern that imprisoning inmates in a privately managed
prison that is run with a private economic purpose de facto turns the prisoners into a means
whereby the corporation that manages and operates the prison makes a financial profit. . . the
very existence of a prison that operates on a profit-making basis reflects a lack of respect
for the status of the inmates as human beings, and this violation of the human dignity of the
inmates does not depend on the extent of the violation of human rights that actually occurs
behind the prison walls.75
Beinisch also emphasized that the violation of the prisoners’ right to human dignity in a
private prison did not depend on the inmates’ subjective feelings. In a plainly non-liberal
fashion (that raised the ire of some of her liberal critics),76 Beinisch implied that it did not
matter whether the prisoners agreed, or even preferred, to be incarcerated in a private prison;
the violation of their human dignity was inherent in the very institution of a private for-profit
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
230
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
prison, because they rendered prisoners into a means for someone else’s financial gain.
According to Beinisch (alluding, perhaps, to Rawls’ theory of justification), this was also
the common understanding of the notions of freedom and human dignity in Israeli society.77
Reformulated in liberal terms, Beinisch’s argument was that the rights to freedom and to
human dignity necessarily implied the right to be incarcerated only by public power and that
such right therefore could not be given up.
Conclusion
Almost two hundred years ago, Alexis de Tocqueville and Gustave de Beaumont wrote that
“[w]hile society in the United States gives the example of the most extended liberty, the
prisons of the same country offer the spectacle of the most complete despotism.”78 Until the
1920s, it was common for public prisons in the US to contract prisoners out as workers to
the private sector. This practice ended due to the pressure from labor unions, which saw this
form of slave labor as a threat to their members’ jobs.79 The last three decades have seen
a change in the opposite direction – against the welfare state and the social costs that are
needed, inter alia, to sustain a sense of common citizenship in prisoners and their guards. In
this paper we have suggested that it is not by mere coincidence that the liberal conceptions of
liberty, freedom, and autonomy have led the US in this direction, while in Israel, where the
republican conception of citizenship still maintains a hold in the political and legal culture,
private incarceration has been declared unconstitutional.80
President Beinisch relied on Hobbes, Locke, and the liberal conception of the social
contract in order to argue that the state itself must perform law enforcement functions. As we
saw, these authors could provide only a weak foundation for this argument, and her reliance
on them led her to a correct decision that lacked persuasive power. Theoretically, Beinisch
could have presented a clear and explicit non-delegation argument based on the importance
of public institutions, particularly in the area of law enforcement, for social solidarity, and
on the inherently corrupting influence of private interests when they encroach on the public
sphere. Such an argument, however, might have led to the conclusion that public institutions
are crucial for citizenship and that, therefore, much of the privatization that has taken place
in Israel over the last three decades has been destructive of social solidarity. This would have
been a conclusion that few people would have liked to hear, even in semi-republican Israel.
NOTES
This paper originated in a seminar on law and the free market conducted by Prof. (now District
Judge) Ofer Grosskopf at the Buchman Faculty of Law, Tel Aviv University. We would like to thank Judge
Grosskopf and the members of the seminar for their thoughtful and inspiring comments and suggestions.
Earlier versions of the paper were presented at the conference on “Private Power and Human Rights” held
at the Academic Center of Law and Business in Ramat Gan, Israel and at the conference on “Nationalism
and Human Rights: Law and Politics in the Middle East and Europe” held at Tel Aviv University, both in
December of 2009.
1. Human Rights Division v Ministry of Finance, HCJ 2605/05, para 19. Two other justices, Procaccia
and Naor, based their concurring opinions on the greater potential for abuse inherent in private incarceration.
2. Barak Medina, “Constitutional Limits to Privatization: The Israeli Supreme Court Decision to Invalidate Prison Privatization”, SSRN, accessed August 30, 2010, http://ssrn.com/abstract=1700190. Daphne
Barak-Erez has offered a slightly different critique. While supporting the Court’s decision, she argued, correctly in our view, that “although the justices refrained from directly deciding the question of ‘core’ executive
functions, their view that the very idea of operating imprisonment functions by private actors infringes rights
implied they considered these functions to be part of this core.” In addition, she argued that the Court’s
analysis of private imprisonment should have distinguished between three distinct spheres of discussion: the
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
231
boundaries of privatization, the privatization process, and the regulation of privatized actions. See Daphne
Barak-Erez, “The Private Prison Controversy and the Privatization Continuum,” Law and Ethics of Human
Rights 5 no. 1 (2011): 138, 150.
3. Michal Tamir and Assaf Harel,”On Human Dignity and Privatization,” unpublished manuscript
(on file with the authors).
4. Alan Patten, “The Republican Critique of Liberalism,” British Journal of Political Science 26 no.
1 (1996): 25; Melvin Rogers, “Republican Confusion and Liberal Clarification,” Philosophy and Social
Criticism 34 no. 7 (2008): 799; Eric Ghosh, “From Republican to Liberal Liberty,” History of Political
Thought 29 no. 1 (2008): 132; J. Kimpell, “Neo-Republicanism: Machiavelli’s Solutions for Tocqueville’s
Republic,” European Political Science Review 1 no. 3 (2009): 375.
5. Cass Sunstein emphasizes that the US Constitution grants legislative power to Congress, but that
it does not do so in terms that forbid delegation of that power. According to him, there is no evidence that
such delegations were originally thought to be out of bounds. See Cass Sunstein, “Nondelegation Canons,”
The University of Chicago Law Review 67 (2000): 315, 322.
6. Ronald Krotoszynski, Jr., “Reconsidering the Non-Delegation Doctrine: Universal Service, the
Power to Tax, and the Ratification Doctrine,” Indiana Law Journal 80 no. 2 (2005):260; Victor Flatt, “The
‘Benefits’ of Non-Delegation Doctrine,” William and Mary Bill of Rights Journal 15 no. 4 (2007): 1092;
Joseph E. Field, “Making Prisons Private: an Improper Delegation of a Government Power,” Hofstra Law
Review 15 (1987): 656; Sunstein, “Nondelegation Canons,” 318.
7. Ira P. Robbins, “The Impact of the Delegation Doctrine on Prison Privatization,” UCLA Law
Review 35 (1988): 915; Sunstein, “Nondelegation Canons,” 318; George I. Lovell, “That Sick Chicken
Won’t Hunt: The Limits of a Judicially Enforced Non-Delegation Doctrine,” Constitutional Commentary
17 no.1 (2000): 79. (Sunstein and Lovell criticize what they consider to be the common interpretation of the
non-delegation doctrine.)
8. Krotoszynski, Jr., “Reconsidering the Non-Delegation Doctrine,” 262, 267.
9. See for example: Joseph E. Field, “Making Prisons Private,” 649; Robbins, “The Impact of the
Delegation Doctrine on Prison Privatization,” 925; Paul Verkuil, “Public Law Limitations of Privatization
of Public Functions,” North Carolina Law Review 84 (2006): 397.
10. Sunstein, “Nondelegation Canons,” 318; See also, Flatt, “The ‘Benefits’ of Non-Delegation
Doctrine,” 1094. (Flatt is an advocate of the non-delegation doctrine but thinks that the reason for the limited
use of the doctrine is related to governmental reality. He does not consider the normative assumptions of
the discourse); Krotoszynski, Jr., “Reconsidering the Non-Delegation Doctrine,” 267. For the most recent
statement of this position see: Eric A. Posner and Adrian Vermeule, The Executive Unbound: After the
Madisonian Republic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
11. Paul Verkuil, “Outsourcing and the Duty to Govern” in Government by Contract, ed. Jody
Freeman and Martha Minow (Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 2009), 317. For a critique,
see Sunstein, “Nondelegation Canons,” 318 (Sunstein argues that the doctrine is alive and well).
12. Pischke v. Litscher [7 th Cir. 1999] 178, F. 3D 497, 500, cited in James Blumstein, “A Commentary
from an America Constitutional Perspective on HCJ 2605/05 Human Rights Division v Minister of Finance,”
unpublished manuscript (on file with the authors), 19.
13. Until the publication of Rawls’ Theory of Justice (TJ), utilitarianism had been the dominant liberal
moral philosophy. Its prominence declined with the publication of TJ, but the rise of neo-liberalism has
restored it to a position of honor. According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “the influence of the
Classical Utilitarians has been profound — not only within moral philosophy, but within political philosophy
and social policy”, accessed March 14, 2011, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/utilitarianism-history.
14. James T. Gentry, “The Panopticon Revisited: the Problem of Monitoring Private Prisons,” The
Yale Law Journal 96 (1986): 353; Janet Semple, Bentham’s Prison (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), 134.
For details of the Panopticon, see Semple, ibid., 134. For a shorter description and much more critical
evaluation of the Panopticon scheme, see Gertrude Himmelfarb, “The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham,”
in Minds (New York, Evanston, and London: Harper Torchbooks, 1952), 32.
15. “I would do the whole by contract. I would farm out the profits, the non-profits, or if you please
the losses, to him who, being in other respects unexceptionable, offered the best term,” wrote Bentham.
Himmelfarb, “The Haunted House,” 42. See also Semple, Bentham’s Prison, 134.
16. Gertrude Himmelfarb, “The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham,” 58; L. J. Hume, Bentham and Bureaucracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981),111; Semple, Bentham’s Prison,
136–137.
17. On the connection between the failure to promote the Panopticon and the development of the
concept of sinister interests, see Phillip Schofiled, Utility and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2006), 111.
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
232
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
18. Ibid., 137–170, 344–346.
19. See for example, James E. Blumstein et al., “Do Government Agencies Respond to Market
Pressures? Evidence from Private Prisons,” Virginia Journal of Social Policy and the Law 15 (2008): 446.
20. John DiIulio, “The Duty to Govern: A Critical Perspective on the Private Management of Prisons
and Jails,” in Private Prisons and the Public Interest, ed. Douglas McDonald, (New Brunswick: Rutgers
University Press, 1990), 155, 156. Even Charles Logan, a prominent libertarian advocate of private incarceration, concedes that “a fundamental insight in regard to state capacity and privatization is that it is wrong
for the state to divest itself of powers if this action would later prevent the state from playing its role, be
it the protection of rights, the advancement of equitable distributions, or the enforcement of democratic
accountability,” Charles Logan, Private Prisons: Pros and Cons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990),
60.
21. See, for example, Sharon Dolovich,”State Punishment and Private Prisons,” Duke Law Journal
55 (2005): 523; Ahmed A. White, “Rule of Law and the Limits of Sovereignty: The Private Prison in
Jurisprudential Perspective,” American Criminal Law Review 38 (2001): 111, 135.
22. Gentry, “The Panopticon Revisited,” 353–355, 356.
23. Ibid., 359–360.
24. For the importance of the concept of accountability in utilitarianism, see David Held, Models of
Democracy, 3rd ed. (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2006), 75. To illustrate, there are 194 instances of the word
“accountability” in 137 pages of Gilian E. Metzger, “Privatization as Delegation,” Columbia Law Review
103 (2003) and 63 times in 41 pages of Martha Minow, “Public and Private Partnership: Accounting for
the New Religion,” Harvard Law Review 116 (2003). For the sake of comparison, in Sharon Dolovich’s
article, “How Privatization Thinks,” which we classified as belonging to the Rawlsian perspective, there is
only one instance of the word “accountability” (in 24 pages). See in Jody Freeman and Martha Minow, ed.,
Government by Contract (Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 2009).
25. Minow, “Public and Private Partnership,”1237.
26. Ibid., 1259.
27. Ibid., 1242–1246.
28. These dangers are grouped by Minow under three heading: dilution of public values; potential
mismatch between competition and social provision; and divisiveness and loss of common institutions (Ibid.,
1246–1255).
29. Metzger, “Privatization as Delegation,” 1394, 1410, 1502.
30. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974).
31. Medina, “Constitutional Limits to Privatization,” 28.
32. Logan, Private Prisons, 236–259.
33. According to the Justice Policy Institute, “between 1980 and 2006, the number of people incarcerated for drug offenses in state and federal prisons [in the US] increased 1,412 percent from 23,900 to 361,276. In 2006, 24 percent of the people in state and federal prisons
were there because their most serious offense was a drug offense,” accessed April 24, 2011,
http://www.justicepolicy.org/uploads/justicepolicy/documents/punitive_response_to_drug_use.pdf.
34. Bruce L. Benson, “Do We Want the Production of Prisons Services to Be More ‘Efficient’?” in
Changing the Guard: Private Prisons and The Control of Crime, ed. Alexander Tabarrok (Oakland: The
Independent Institute, 2003),163. This volume was published by the libertarian Independent Institute and
its general tenor is very favorable towards prison privatization.
35. Dolovich, “State Punishment and Private Prisons,” 441, 463.
36. Ibid., 470–471.
37. Ibid., 475–480; Cf. Avio, “when some outputs are unobservable and contracts are thus necessarily
incomplete, the profit motive can have negative implications.” Kenneth L. Avio, “The Economics of Prisons”
in Changing the Guard.
38. In the US, accreditation is by the American Correctional Association, an independent “organization of correctional professionals dating to 1870.” Dolovich,”State Punishment and Private Prisons,”
488–489.
39. Ibid., 502.
40. Ibid., 505 (emphasis added). Dolovich believes, however, that it is well-nigh impossible that
private prisons will ever stand up to the principle of humanity. See ibid., 505–506.
41. Ibid. We have summarized Dolovich’s argument regarding the humanity principle only. She
offers a similar analysis with regard to her other principle, the parsimony principle, and reaches the same
conclusions: the profit interests of private prison contractors lead them to lobby (effectively) for harsher
sentencing policies in order to avail themselves of a larger pool of “clients” for longer periods of time.
However, she points to similar practices by interests connected to the public prison system as well, such
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Private Incarceration: Yoav Peled and Doron Davot
233
as prison guards’ unions. For our purposes in this paper, there is no need to analyze in detail both parts of
Dolovich’s argument.
42. Ibid., 507.
43. Sharon Dolovich, “How Privatization Thinks,” in Government by Contract, ed. Jody Freeman
and Martha Minow (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009), 129.
44. Michael Sandel, What Money Can’t Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets (The Tanner Lectures on
Human Values) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 94.
45. Joshua Cohen, “Taking People as They Are?” Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 no. 4 (2001): 366.
For another criticism of the difference principle, see G.A. Cohen, Rescuing Justice & Equality (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 2008), 315.
46. John Rawls, Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy (Cambridge and London: The
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2007), 207, 214; John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge
and London: Harvard University Press, 1999), 7.
47. John Rawls, Political Liberalism: Expanded Edition (New York: Columbia University Press,
2005), 269, cited in Joshua Cohen, “Taking People as They Are?” 381. See also Cohen, Rescuing Justice &
Equality, 376.
48. “No doubt even the concepts that we use to describe our plans and situation, and even to give
voice to our personal wants and purposes, often presuppose a social setting as well as a system of belief and
thought that are the outcome of the collective efforts of a long tradition. . . human beings have in fact shared
final ends and they value their common institutions and activities as good in themselves.” John Rawls, A
Theory of Justice: Revisited Edition (Cambridge and London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University
Press, 1999), 458.
49. Michael Titelbaum, “What Would a Rawlsian Ethos of Justice Look Like?” Philosophy and
Public Affairs 36 no. 3 (2008): 289, 310. (Respect for religious belief forbids public policy and institutions
that seriously curtail individuals’ abilities to form, revise, and pursue it.) See also: Stephen Mulhall and
Adam Swift, “Rawls and Communitarianism” in Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge and London:
Cambridge University Press, 2007), 476.
50. For self-transformation and liberal theory, see Mark Warren, “Democratic Theory and SelfTransformation,” American Political Science Review 86 no. 1 (1992): 8.
51. John Rawls, “Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics” in John Rawls’ Collected Papers, ed.
Samuel Freeman (Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 1991), 1, 6.
52. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 224–225. For the suggestion that the requirement of justification by
appeal to political values applies only to questions regarding constitutional essentials and matters of basic
justice, see T. M. Scanlon, “Rawls on Justification” in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. Samuel
Freeman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 162–163. (We should emphasize that Scanlon
did not refer to the privatization of prisons in this essay.) We agree with Freeman’s explanation that “[I]t
is because of the failure of the argument for stability of a well-ordered society as defined in A Theory of
Justice, and within Kantian constructivism that Rawls is driven to make the revisions in the justification
of justice as fairness that result in Political Liberalism.” Samuel Freeman, Justice and the Social Contract
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 6.
53. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 217–218.
54. Ibid., 218. See also, A. John Simmons, “Ideal and Non Ideal Theory,” Philosophy and Public
Affairs 38 no. 1 (2010): 23.
55. David Miller, introduction to Thinking Politically by Michael Walzer (New Haven and London:
Yale University Press, 2007) xi; cf. Seyla Benhabib, “Walzer . . . represents the civic-republican voice in
debates around citizenship and immigration,” Transformations of Citizenship: Dilemmas of the Nation State
in the Era of Globalization (Van Gorcum, 2001), 56.
56. Michael Walzer, “Hold the Justice,” New Republic, April 1985, 12.
57. A copy of the brief Walzer submitted in support of the plaintiffs in the Israeli prison privatization
case (HCJ 2605/05) is on file with the authors.
58. Walzer, “Hold the Justice,” 12
59. Walzer, “HCJ 2605/05 Brief,” 3.
60. Walzer, “Hold the Justice,” 11.
61. Walzer, “HCJ 2605/05 Brief,” 4.
62. Jean Jacques Rousseau, “The Social Contract” in The Social Contract and Other Later Political
Writings, ed. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997), 52.
63. Ibid., 64–65.
64. Ibid., 122–126.
65. Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books, 1983) 5 (emphasis added).
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
234
Constellations Volume 19, Number 2, 2012
66. Ibid., 6–10, 18–19; Cf. Sandel, What Money Can’t Buy, 101.
67. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994), 51 (emphasis in the original).
68. Walzer, Spheres of Justice, 22.
69. Ibid., 108–109.
70. Walzer, “HCJ 2605/05 Brief,” 11.
71. HCJ 2605/05, Beinisch Opinion, para 10, 18, 19, 63.
72. Alon Harel has criticized Beinisch’s arguments, although not her decision, based on an interesting
liberal variation of the non-delegation doctrine. He argued that (1) as autonomous human beings, the
employees of a private corrections company must exercise their own moral judgment before they can
carry out the sentence determined by the state; (2) public servants are forbidden to make such independent
judgments and are bound by the moral considerations of the state; (3) therefore only public servants should be
entrusted with carrying out judicial decisions. Alon Harel, “On the Limitations of Privatization,” Mishpatim
al Atar 2 (2010): 12–13. See also his “Why Only the State May Inflict Criminal Sanctions: The Vices of
Privately-Inflicted Criminal Sanctions,” Legal Theory 14 (2008): 113
73. Philip Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1997), 5.
74. Walzer, “Hold the Justice,” 11 (emphasis added); cf.HCJ 2605/05, Beinisch Opinion, para 26,
citing DiIulio: “The badge of the arresting police officer, the robes of the judge, and the state patch of the
corrections officer are symbols of the inherently public nature of crime and punishment.”
75. HCJ 2605/05, Beinisch Opinion, para 36.
76. See, for example, Tamir and Harel, “On Human Dignity and Privatization”.
77. HCJ 2605/05, Beinisch Opinion, para 24–27, 37, 39.
78. Cited by Marie Gottschalk, “Hiding in Plain Sight: American Politics and the Carceral State,”
Annual Review of Political Science 11 no. 1 (2008): 236.
79. Field, “Making Prisons Private,” 652.
80. Ethno-republicanism had been the dominant element within Israeli political culture for many
years, but its power has seriously eroded since the 1980s. The Supreme Court, on the other hand, has always
been a bastion of liberal thinking; Gershon Shafir and Yoav Peled, Being Israeli (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002).
Yoav Peled is Professor of Political Science at Tel Aviv University. His most recent book,
co-authored with Gershon Shafir, is Being Israeli: The Dynamics of Multiple Citizenship
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), which won the 2002 Albert Hourani Award
of the Middle East Studies Association of North America.
Doron Navot is a Lecturer in the Department of Political Science at the University of Haifa.
His most recent book is Political Corruption in Israel (Israel Democracy Institute, 2012) (in
Hebrew).
C
2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.