DOI: 10.1111/phin.12339
Philosophical Investigations : 2022
ISSN 0190-0536
Rule-Following and Objective Spirit
Thomas J. Spiegel, Department of Philosophy, University of Potsdam
Abstract
This paper deals with Wittgenstein’s rule-following paradox, focussing on
the infinite rule-regress as featured in Kripke’s Wittgenstein on Rules and
Private Language. I argue that one of the most salient and popular
proposed solutions (championed by John McDowell), which argues that
rule-following is grounded in “custom,” “practice” or “form of life,
remains unsatisfactory because part of this proposal is the rejection of
further “theory” (commonly attributed to Wittgenstein) which seemingly
makes it impossible to substantiate the claim of how customs, practices or
forms of life ground rule-following. I argue that this conundrum can be
solved by introducing Wilhelm Dilthey’s overlooked notion of objective
spirit as the objectivated sediment of historical human communality. This
proposal allows us to substantiate Wittgenstein’s hints at the connection
between rule-following and customs, practices, and forms of life without
introducing “problematic theories.” Combining Wittgenstein’s views
with Dilthey’s notion of objective spirit results in a solution that is
neither skeptical nor straight, but therapeutic.
The infinite regress of rules as it pertains to the rule-following problem
is one of the most comprehensively covered, yet enduring topics in 20th
century philosophy, now extending into the 21st century. In the shortest
of terms, the rule regress consists in the supposed problem that the application of any rule requires the addition of a further rule. Infinite ruleregresses are enabled by the nature of rules, or rather (as shall become
clear) a certain interpretation of that nature. Arguably, the most influential rendition of the rule-regress has been provided by Wittgenstein and
Saul Kripke’s infamous interpretation of Wittgenstein.1
A number of different solutions have been proposed since Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations were first published. One of the most
salient proposed solutions to the rule-following problem is John McDowell’s account. According to McDowell, Wittgenstein’s own solution
Open access funding enabled and organized by ProjektDEAL.
1. Kripke (1982).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution NonCommercial License,
which permits use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited and
is not used for commercial purposes.
2
Philosophical Investigations
(which he endorses) to the rule-following problem is that the correct
application of a rule is ultimately grounded in a “custom,” “practice,”
“institutions” or “form of life”.2 Yet, McDowell (like Wittgenstein) does
not specify what this could mean, something that might be viewed in
line with Wittgenstein’s rejection of explanations in philosophy that
McDowell shares. Hence, McDowell’s account has been called “quietist,” although McDowell himself eschews the label.3
This provides a certain unsatisfactory tension: on the one hand,
McDowell’s account stays as faithful as possible to Wittgenstein’s own
solution. On the other hand, this methodological parsimony results in
explanatory poverty: more simply needs to be said about how customs,
practices or forms of life ground the fact that rule-following is possible.
Or, in Wittgenstein’s own words, how exactly do these ultimately social
phenomena ensure that we can follow rules “blindly”,4 that this is where
the “spade” turns back?5
In this article, I propose a solution that aims to improve and expand
upon McDowell’s parsimonious account without violating the methodological and explanatory constraints set by Wittgenstein. The result ultimately aims at an elaboration of Wittgenstein’s own remarks, given that
McDowell’s reading seems largely faithful. This proposal essentially
involves the concept of objective spirit as developed by Wilhelm
Dilthey.6 More specifically, Dilthey’s conception of objective spirit
(objektiver Geist), which he appropriateness from Hegel for his own
views, and his idea of elementary understanding (elementares Verstehen) are
apt to further make intelligible how a subject-transcendent form of life
or collective-habitual ways of acting make it possible to follow a rule
without a further interpretation. This solution purports to be a straight
solution – a solution that demonstrates how rules can be followed without an infinite regress arising – rather than a mere skeptical solution
famously favoured by Kripke.7 The result is a solution that is
2. Wittgenstein (1953: §9: §24).
3. McDowell (2009).
4. Wittgenstein (1953: §219).
5. Wittgenstein (1953: §217).
6. This is salient also because some commentators from a hermeneuticalphenomenological standpoint have conceded, erroneously, that there can only be a skeptical solution (in Kripke’s terms) to the regress. “The Husserlian view I have been sketching
thus amounts to what Kripke calls a “sceptical solution” to the rule-following paradox, in
that it accepts that there is no straightforward, fully determined fact of the matter about
meaning in any single moment of my lived experience, [. . .]. As Kripke notes, instead of
refuting the sceptic in the manner of a “straight solution,” a “sceptical solution”—such as
that in Hume’s Enquiry—seeks to show how “our ordinary practice or belief is justified
be—contrary appearances notwithstanding—it need not require the justification the sceptic has shown to be untenable.” Rump (2020: 88).
7. Kripke (1982).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
3
explanatorily frugal, yet constitutes a satisfactory and straight solution to
the rule regress.
This paper is about rules only insofar as they engender an infinite
regress. The topic of rule-following more generally has been written
about from very different angles. It is therefore necessary to stress that
this paper focusses mainly on Wittgenstein’s framing of the issue and utilises his scattered hints at a (dis-)solution of the problem in order to
expand on those hints. While similar in nature, similar kinds of infinite
regresses are not considered for the purpose of this inquiry.8 Even
though the rule-following considerations are crucial to the philosophy of
the later Wittgenstein,9 I shall gloss over to its systematic relations to, for
example, the saying/showing distinction,10 their connection to normativity more generally,11 the private language argument,12 and the idea of
rules as rails to infinity.13 I shall furthermore not deal with more specialised questions concerning the (im-)possibility of a so-called “fullblooded” theory of meaning in relation to the rule-following paradox.14
The first section reconstructs the rule-following paradox and related
infinite regress of rules in the later Wittgenstein. The second part
focusses on McDowell’s elaboration of Wittgenstein’s own hints at a
solution; I argue that while McDowell’s account has merits, it ultimately
remains unsatisfactory due to unnecessarily strict self-imposed methodological restrictions. Section 3 in turn introduces Dilthey’s notion of an
objective spirit and elementary understanding as providing a solution
insofar as viewing rule-following grounded in objective spirit does not
let the regress arrive in the first place. Section 4 illustrates how this hermeneutic solution differs from the other available options by Kripke,
Brandom, Winch, and Ginsborg; rather than being straight or skeptical,
it is a therapeutic notion in the spirit of the later Wittgenstein himself.
8. Plato’s Third Man argument, Agrippa’s trilemma, or even Bradley’s regress have arguably garnered much more attention than the rule-regress as it is found in Kant, Carroll,
and Wittgenstein. What sets those arguments apart from the rule-regress is, trivially, that
their infinite regresses are not enabled in virtue of the application of a rule or concept,
and hence will be omitted here.
9. Verheggen (2017) even states that it is the “centerpiece” of his Philosophical
Investigations.
10. cf. Wittgenstein (2001: 3.262, 4.1212, 4.122, 4.461).
11. Wittgenstein (1953: §224 & §225).
12. Wittgenstein (1953: §202 & 252).
13. Wittgenstein (1953: §218), Wright (2001).
14. E.g. Maher (2012).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
4
Philosophical Investigations
I. Rule-Following and the Pentalemmatic Rule-Regress
The later Wittgenstein wrangles with the phenomenon of rules as such,
but especially as they pertain to language, i.e., language as a game15 and
language as it pertains to conceptuality.16 Wittgenstein views language as
essentially rule-governed. Specifically, word usage is governed by rules.
The central issue Wittgenstein uncovers is that if language is essentially
governed by rules, correctly applying a rule requires another rule, leading
to an infinite regress. While there are some very similar infinite regresses
established in the work of other thinkers,17 the following reconstruction
will focus on Wittgenstein’s specific brand of the rule-regress, since it
has dominated large parts of the literature.
The infinite rule-regress is part of the wider rule-following problem.
The rule-following problem itself states that there never seems to be a
fact of the matter whether one has followed a rule correctly because any
(linguistic or mathematical) performance can be brought into accord
with that rule. The sections in which Wittgenstein most clearly formulates the problem are as follows:
Can’t we imagine a rule determining the application of a rule?18
Can we not now imagine further rules to explain this one?19
Now we get the pupil to continue a series (say +2) beyond 1000 —
and he writes 1000, 1004, 1008, 1012. We say to him: "Look what
you’ve done!" — He doesn’t understand. [. . .] Or suppose he pointed
to the series and said: "But I went on in the same way." [. . .]20
But how can a rule shew me what I have to do at this point? Whatever I do is, on some interpretation, in accord with the rule."— That
is not what we ought to say, but rather: any interpretation still hangs in
the air along with what it interprets, and cannot give it any support.
Interpretations by themselves do not determine meaning.21
This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a
rule, because every course of action can be made out to accord with
the rule. The answer was: if everything can be made out to accord
with the rule, then it can also be made out to conflict with it. And so
there would be neither accord nor conflict here.22
15. Wittgenstein (1953: §68, §80, §81, §125, §133).
16. Wittgenstein (1953: §71, 81, 84).
17. This refers most notably to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1998: B127) and Lewis
Carroll’s What the Tortoise said to Achilles (1895).
18. Wittgenstein (1953: §84).
19. Wittgenstein (1953: §86).
20. Wittgenstein (1953: §185).
21. Wittgenstein (1953: §198).
22. Wittgenstein (1953: §201).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
5
In conjunction, these quotes contain the central elements for the infinite
regress of rules. As is often the case, Wittgenstein‘s relatively unsystematic remarks regarding rules in general have been interpreted in various
ways and with different connections to other thematic clusters in his later
work. However, the most (in)famous construal of the rule-regress as a
problem has been supplied by Kripke. Regardless of whether it is a faithful interpretation of Wittgenstein, Kripke’s argument offers a substantially
useful discussion and reconstruction of the rule-following problem. The
focus is on the question: which rule is expressed by a given set of examples? Kripke elaborates that every finite set of examples is in accordance
with indefinitely many logically possible rules. So whatever rule a
speaker favours as the one explaining a set of examples, there are still
indefinitely many other possible rules that are equally compatible with
the same set of examples.
This rule-following problem entails an infinite regress of rules once we
ask for justifications regarding the use of a certain rule. This is often
exemplified using Kripke’s famous arithmetic example of the rule of
addition and the made-up rule of quaddition, but I prefer an exemplification that is closer to ordinary language. Consider any concept F. The
concept F is applied to things in the world by uttering statements like
“this is F,” like “this is a stone.” Since concepts can be phrased as rules
(according to thinkers like Wittgenstein and Kant), whenever one utters
a statement “this is F,” then she follows a rule which specifies which
things actually are F, and which are not F. A rule specifies F by specifying under which circumstances it is correct to utter “this is F.” The
question is: how exactly does the concept F determine the usage of
utterances like “this is F”? One may be inclined to give another rule that
specifies how the concept F ought to be used. For example: “only say of
a thing x ‘this is a stone’, if x is grey and hard.” But such a rule does
not solve the initial problem. It reiterates the problem because GREY and
HARD are just two more concepts of which one can ask for a rule that
specifies how they ought to be used, enabling an infinite regress.
In order to get a better analytical grip on the issue, we can formulate
a more general, perspicuous overview of the nature of the rule regress
that captures the essence of their different approaches. The rule-regress
can be represented through the following pentalemma:23
23. Following L€
owenstein (2017: 335) construction of a general and uniform account of
regress problems. While his version is mainly focussed on regresses of doxastic justification, the same pentalemma can be applied mutatis mutandis to the rule-regress, which I
have modified accordingly here.
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Philosophical Investigations
6
Phenomenon
Ground
Recurrence
Finity
Non-circularity
There are rules.
Every rule requires some form of interpretation.
Every interpretation is itself a rule.
No rule is a rule in virtue of an infinite chain of rules.
No rule is a rule in virtue of a circle of rules.
In the search for a solution or dissolution of the resulting paradox of
the infinite regress, the question arises what exactly enables the infinite
regress in the first place. It should be fairly obvious that the lemmata
Phenomenon, Finity, and Non-Circularity are (at least prima facie) unproblematic. This leaves the lemmata Ground and Recurrence as the ones
which seemingly enables the regress. In Section 3 below, the strategy in
this paper will be to argue that a proper solution to the rule-regress
offers a rephrasing of Recurrence and Ground. Before presenting that
strategy, however, the following section develops Wittgenstein’s own
attempts at a solution, including McDowell’s elaboration, arguing that it
ultimately remains unsatisfactory.
II. Wittgenstein’s and McDowell’s Incomplete Solution
This section provides an overview of Wittgenstein’s remarks regarding
possible solutions which uncovers the fact that, according to Wittgenstein, there must be an understanding of a rule which itself is not an
interpretation. This point essentially results in a rephrasing of the lemmata
Ground and Reccurence detailed above. In doing so, I follow McDowell’s reading of Wittgenstein’s rule regress insofar as his solution lies
with the suggestion that following a rule is ultimately grounded in custom, practice, or form of life. However, unlike McDowell, I contend
that just hinting at these ideas cannot result in providing a satisfactory
solution or dissolution of the infinite regress even when staying true to
Wittgenstein’s rejection of “theories” in philosophy.
While the writings of the later Wittgenstein can make it difficult to
parse and track his argument, the diagnosis of the central issue leading to
the rule regress is most succinctly expressed in the following passages:
"But how can a rule shew me what I have to do at this point? Whatever I do is, on some interpretation (Deutung), in accord with the
rule."— That is not what we ought to say, but rather: any interpretation (Deutung) still hangs in the air along with what it interprets, and
cannot give it any support. Interpretations (Deutungen) by themselves
do not determine meaning.24
24. Wittgenstein (1953: §198).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
7
It can be seen that there is a misunderstanding here from the mere
fact that in the course of our argument we give one interpretation
(Deutung) after another; as if each one contented us at least for a
moment, until we thought of yet another standing behind it.25
Wittgenstein states here that the problem is that the rule-regress is
enabled by following an interpretation of a rule (in other words: propositionally stating what a rule means) with yet another interpretation of a
rule. By “interpretation,” Wittgenstein accordingly means the “substitution of one expression of the rule for another.”26 This is essentially a formulation of the adjusted phrasing of two lemmata introduced in the last
section:
Ground
Recurrence
Every rule requires some form of interpretation.
Every interpretation is itself a rule.
Wittgenstein would have accepted Recurrence, since an interpretation
(Deutung) of a rule must be in the form of a rule. It would be difficult to
come up with a conceptually articulated interpretation of a rule that does
not itself qualify as a rule, such that it might perhaps even qualify as an
analytic truth that every interpretation is a rule.
Accordingly, Wittgenstein’s solution focusses on Ground and Recurrence. His focus on Ground can be read off such passages as the
following:
What this shews is that there is a way of grasping (Auffassung) a rule
which is not an interpretation [. . .].27
Is something that follows a rule itself a rule? And if not, - what kind
of proposition (Satz) am I to call it?28
Hence, the main requirement for stopping the infinite
that there be a form of understanding a rule that is not
tation (Deutung). If we return to L€
owenstein’s (2017)
expressed by Wittgenstein in these remarks results in a
lemma Ground:
Ground*:
regress of rules is
itself an interprediction, the idea
rephrasing of the
Every rule requires some form of understanding.
25. Wittgenstein (1953: §201).
26. Cf. Wittgenstein (1953: §201). The same diagnosis Wittgenstein affords us is already
present in nuce in Schleiermacher, who asserts that the rules of interpretation do not carry
the “certainty of their application within them” (Schleiermacher 1977: 81).
27. Wittgenstein (1953: §201).
28. Wittgenstein (1967: VI-31).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Philosophical Investigations
8
While perhaps not entirely necessary, the lemma Recurrence can also
be reformulated to suitably reflect the trajectory of Wittgenstein’s hints
at a solution:
There are ways of understanding a rule which are not
interpretations.
Recurrence*:
Ground* and Recurrence*, respectively, block the rule regress since
now not every rule requires another rule for interpretation. Rather, it
asserts that there are ways of understanding (or grasping, Auffassen) which
are not interpretations. Both Ground* and Recurrence* are intuitively
plausible. Yet, the decisive question then becomes what such understanding would look like (in contrast to an interpretation). In exploring
that idea, Wittgenstein offers different sets of terminologies in the Philosophical Investigations as well as minor remarks in Culture and Value and
Cause and Effect:
On the contrary; I have further indicated that a person goes by a signpost only in so far as there exists a regular use of sign-posts, a custom
(einen st€andigen Gebrauch, eine Gepflogenheit).29
[. . .] To obey a rule, to make a report, to give an order, to play a
game of chess, are customs (uses, institutions) (Gepflogenheiten
[Gebr€auche, Institutionen]).30
"How am I able to obey a rule?"—if this is not a question about
causes, then it is about the justification for my following the rule in the
way I do. If I have exhausted the justifications I have reached bedrock,
and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say: "This is simply
what I do."31
What has to be accepted, the given, is . . . forms of life32
no reason can be given why you should act (or should have
acted) like this, except that by doing so you bring about such and such
a situation, which again has to be an aim you accept33
[. . .] it is characteristic of our language that the foundation on which
it grows consists in steady ways of living, regular ways of acting34
These quotations – in different contexts – all deal with the same question, i.e., whether the rules governing language games, among them
propositional ones, necessitate some further interpretation. Wittgenstein’s
point to be extracted from these passages seems to be alluringly simple:
there is an “instant” way of grasping and applying a rule that simply
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
Wittgenstein
Wittgenstein
Wittgenstein
Wittgenstein
Wittgenstein
Wittgenstein
(1953:
(1953:
(1953:
(1953:
(1980:
(1976:
§198).
§199).
§217).
part II, p. 226).
16e).
397).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
9
“works” without adducing another rule. This is where one reaches his
famous “bedrock” where the “spade is turned.” Less metaphorically, this
kind of direct grasping of a rule which does not itself take the form of a
rule is characterised in four ways: as a custom,35 a practice,36 an institution,37 and a form of life.38 Furthermore, any such acting through an
understanding of a rule is seemingly “blind.”39
Wittgenstein does not say much more on this matter in his later philosophy. And according to McDowell’s reading – which I take to be
among those most faithful to Wittgenstein – this is where the story ends:
Readers of Wittgenstein often suppose that when he mentions customs,
forms of life, and the like, he is making programmatic gestures towards
a certain style of positive philosophy [. . .]. But there is no reason to
credit Wittgenstein with any sympathy for this style of philosophy.
When he says “What has to be accepted, the given, is - so one could
say - forms of life” [. . .], his point is not to adumbrate a philosophical
response [. . .].40
According to McDowell, there is no more to be said, and no mystery
about meaning or rules remains once we get clear on the idea that rulefollowing is grounded in customs.41 And while this general “quietist”
idea has been controversially debated, there is in fact some good textual
evidence that Wittgenstein eschewed “substantial” explanations of several
different philosophical issues.
You must bear in mind that the language-game is so to say something
unpredictable. I mean: it is not based on grounds. It is not reasonable
(or unreasonable). It is there – like our life.42
One can only describe here and say: thus is human life.43
One is inclined to say: this and that event transpired; laugh if you
can.44
In these and other passages, Wittgenstein asserts that many such questions
or contexts cannot be further explained, there is nothing more to be said
but simply to accept that human practice, by and large, works. Even if
we assume that McDowell’s interpretation of these and similar remarks is
35. Wittgenstein (1953: §198, §199).
36. Wittgenstein (1953: §54, §197).
37. Wittgenstein (1953, §199).
38. Wittgenstein (1953: §241, part II, p. 226).
39. Wittgenstein (1953: §219).
40. McDowell (1992: 50f.), cf. also McDowell (1984).
41. He has also reiterated this sentiment in McDowell (2009) and McDowell (2015).
42. Wittgenstein (1969: §559).
43. Wittgenstein (1995: 180). Translation mine. „Nur b e s c h r e i b e n kann man hier
und sagen: so ist das menschliche Leben.“
44. Wittgenstein (1995: 181). Translation mine “Man m€
ochte sagen: Dieser und dieser
Vorgang hat stattgefunden; lachˈ, wenn Du kannst.”
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
10
Philosophical Investigations
faithful, such methodological constraints understandably leave even sympathetic readers befuddled. And of course some Wittgenstein scholars
have not followed Wittgenstein’s (or McDowell’s) request to abstain
from further attempts to develop his notions of customs, practices, and
the idea of a form of life, respectively.45
There is a tension internal to the Wittgensteinian-McDowellian solution. On the one hand, there is reason to take Wittgenstein’s eschewal
of “theories” seriously (at least when considering his own solution), and
therefore not to engage in further “theory” about customs and practices
(as a quietist reading would have it, as it were). On the other hand, it
seems clearly not enough to simply state that following a rule is
grounded in a custom or form of life. There are legitimate questions to
be asked. For example, in what way does a custom, practice, institution,
or form of life enable rule-following? Or how can a mere customary
determination of the correctness of rules be lined up with thoughts about
how the world truly is? An apodictic reference to such social phenomena
just seems too thin to be satisfactory. This is a legitimate grievance that
any solution to the rule regress has to rule out. The central problem of
their proposed solution is that it seems incomplete. What Wittgenstein
(and McDowell, channelling Wittgenstein) provide are hints at a solution,
but not a complete solution that would be satisfactory.
In what follows, I shall try to demonstrate that there is a via media
between these two extremes. This middle-way consists in expanding on
Wittgenstein’s solution to the regress without offering theories of the
problematic kind which Wittgenstein is critical of. I have argued elsewhere46 that this is a live possibility. In other words, there ought to be a
way to say more than what Wittgenstein states without saying anything
45. Cf. e.g. Schatzki & Knorr-Cetina (2000) who developed a full-grown “practice theory” on the back of the later Wittgenstein.Some readers of Wittgenstein further offer a
very deflationary reading of his idea of custom and practice. For example, Lin (2019: 17)
suggests that a custom merely implies that a certain act of rule-following “cannot be performed only once” and that this makes it a practice since practices are “something which
cannot happen just once”. While this assertion is not incorrect, it does not seem to be
sufficient to get to the heart of how customs, practices, and the idea of a form of life
ground rule-following. This is because practices and customs being carried out a number
of times is not sufficient for solving the logical problem of how they guarantee a correct
application of a rule. The mere frequency of acts that constitute a custom which grounds
a rule cannot be the reason why that custom grounds a given rule, for principled reasons.
46. I have argued in Spiegel (2021a) and Spiegel (2021b) that Wittgensteinian quietism is
properly understood as the rejection of those theories in philosophy that try to emulate a
natural-scientific mode of explanation. Accordingly, Wittgenstein is obviously not against
philosophical theories as such. McDowell himself points this out in a later paper, writing
that Wittgenstein would obviously not have an issue with philosophical reflections on the
proper shape of a political community, McDowell (2009) and McDowell (2015).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
11
methodologically problematic. The rest of this investigation is dedicated
to working out what such a solution could look like.
III. Objective Spirit as a Hermeneutic Treatment of the Regress
This section argues that Dilthey’s concepts of understanding and objective spirit can be utilised in this context to provide such an unproblematic elaboration of Wittgenstein’s hints at a solution to the rule-regress,
i.e., it can provide a reason to reject the lemma Ground in the pentalemma. A first starting point lies in noticing that Wittgenstein states in
his Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics that we always already understand rules:
If you want to understand [verstehen] what it means to “follow a rule,”
you have already to be able to follow a rule.47
Wittgenstein here expresses a fundamental idea of the hermeneutic tradition, namely the idea that one is always already engaged in understanding.
This point rarely comes up in debates about the rule regress. As an
exception, Bowie offers some remarks on how these ideas can be
brought together (albeit without explicit reference to the section of
RFM just cited):
The argument prevents a regress of rules for the application of rules, by
grounding rules in pre-theoretically constituted practices that are inherent in our “being in the world.48
If one has not always already understood, how could what one is
doing in understanding be grounded by an explanation of
understanding?49
Bowie’s general remarks here are helpful in expressing the general direction in which an appropriate answer to the rule regress can be found:
what grounds rules has to be a certain form of understanding which is
not itself rule-like but wholly different from rules, at least nontheoretical in a certain sense; and this understanding somehow has to do
with practices of our “being in the world” (Heidegger). This is certainly
an extended reformulation of Wittgenstein’s own admission that rule following cannot be grounded in rules, i.e., a rejection of the aforementioned lemma Ground. Yet, Bowie’s remarks, too, leave us with
questions about what these non-theoretical practices are and how they
47. Wittgenstein (1967: V-32).
48. Bowie 2016: 48.
49. Bowie 2016: 49.
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
12
Philosophical Investigations
relate to following rules, other than that they are explanatorily prior to
rules.
In what follows, I shall suggest that Dilthey’s hermeneutical version of
objektiver Geist (or “objective spirit”) offers a further elaboration of this
idea, which sheds light on Wittgenstein’s sparse hints at a solution and
offers a more thorough application that one has always already understood in the context of the rule regress. The general form of a solution
to Wittgenstein’s rule-regress remains that there must be something which
licenses or mediates the correct usages of a rule directly, without requiring an interpretation. And this criterion can be fulfilled by (some form
of) the idea of an elementary understanding and objective spirit.
The idea of objective spirit is due to Hegel. In the simplest of terms,
objective spirit is the whole of normative mindedness as it is sedimented
or expressible in morality, law, Sittlichkeit, sciences, art, religion, philosophy, and generally “mundane aspects of human life.”50 Objective spirit is
to be contrasted with subjective spirit, i.e., the whole of phenomena as
they pertain to an individual mind.51 Although the idea of an objective
spirit may now not be part of the canon of anglophone analytic philosophy, it has had wide influences on different traditions of thought, especially sociology and social philosophy. Dilthey critically engaged with
Hegel’s idea of objective spirit throughout his career,52 arguably culminating in his late Aufbau. A full reconstruction of Dilthey’s grappling
with the idea of objective spirit would require its own treatment. For
the present context, it is sufficient to focus on the crucial properties
Dilthey ascribes to objective spirit:
On Dilthey’s view, objective spirit is the “medium” of our sociohistorical situation and all our interaction; it is the frame which enables
understanding and in which all understanding takes place,53 similar to
how water allows fish to breathe and swim. Objective spirit is the objectivated sediment of historical human communality (das Allgemeinmenschliche), i.e., the whole of mental phenomena as they figure in history
become objective in practices, meanings, and institutions. Dilthey puts it
like this:
A basic experience of commonality permeates the whole conception of
the world of human spirit.54
50. Makkreel (2021): 28.
51. Objective spirit is also to be contrasted with absolute spirit which, however, is not
pertinent to the issue at hand. One of the most crucial differences between Dilthey and
Hegel here is perhaps that, on Hegel’s account, religion, philosophy, and art make up
absolute spirit, whereas Dilthey includes them in objective spirit.
52. Starting with Dilthey (1990).
53. Makkreel & Rodi (2002: 3).
54. Dilthey (2002: 163).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
13
At every stage, there is an implicit understanding of the world of
human spirit, from its general idea to methods of criticism and individual investigations, that is uniform or homogeneous.55
The social institutions that make up objective spirit are socially constituted extensions of our own cognitive practices, which are historically
solidified and enduring. As such, objective spirit is always already there:
people are “born into” objective spirit which informs every individual
mind since its inception.56 In other words, there is no escaping objective
spirit, as it accompanies human life from its very beginning. Objective
spirit encompasses
the manifold forms in which a commonality existing among individuals
has objectified itself in the world of the senses,” allowing the past to
become “a continuously enduring present for us.57
This kind of objectified commonality has always been historical, that is,
the whole of practices which are objectified into objective spirit simultaneously present a way of keeping a history of human conduct present in
a certain sense.58
But how does objective spirit relate to both Dilthey’s wider philosophical contentions and the rule-regress at hand? Wilhelm Dilthey has
incorporated the idea of objective spirit into his hermeneutic theory of
the human mind. Without going into too much detail, his account, as it
pertains to the topic at hand, can be summarised as follows. Dilthey’s
overarching goal – at least of his unfinished late philosophy – was to
provide a theoretical foundation of the human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften). Perhaps the most crucial part of this foundation is his conception of
understanding (Verstehen). Appropriating Vico’s verum factum principle
and Schleiermacher’s idea that “I understand nothing which I cannot
apprehend as necessary and which I cannot construct myself,”59 Dilthey
posits that the complement to and object of understanding is life (Leben),
or rather, manifestations of life (Lebens€außerungen). Manifestations of life
themselves are divided into three categories: propositional items (concepts, judgments, thoughts), actions (Handlungen), and expressions of
lived experience (Erlebnisausdruck; i.e., emotions like joy or sadness, but
also gestures and art.60 Expressions of life as the object of understanding
are, of course, all mental items that can be understood rather than
explained.
55.
56.
57.
58.
59.
60.
Dilthey (2002: 167).
Dilthey (2002: 229).
Ibid.
Ibid.
Schleiermacher (1959: 31).
Dilthey (1962: 205–207)/Dilthey (2002: 205).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
14
Philosophical Investigations
Dilthey’s concept of understanding is further bifurcated into elementary understanding and higher-level understanding.61 Elementary understanding is a kind of direct, non-inferential, usually unconscious
understanding directed upon single instances of manifestations of life. For
example, if I see a woman lying by the roadside with a distorted facial
expression next to a damaged bicycle, it is elementary understanding that
allows me to directly see that the woman is in pain. Accordingly, if
someone yells “fetch” and throws me a ball, it is elementary understanding (next to biological reflexes) that is operative in my understanding
that I am to fetch the ball instead of, say, deflecting it with the stick in
my hand. Higher-level understanding, on the other hand, is an inferential, explicit kind of understanding which is based upon elementary
understanding and is directed upon more general, “objective” elements
like context, situation, meaning, and reasons. To stick with the same
example, it is higher-level understanding that enables me to understand
that the woman who is clearly in pain most likely had a car accident and
is in need of immediate assistance. Thus, elementary understanding is
foundational, and instances of higher-level understanding require
instances of elementary understanding, according to Dilthey.
Dilthey is aware that his overall account of understanding retains a
crucial explanandum couched in the question what makes understanding
possible in the first place. This is highly analogous to Wittgenstein’s diagnosis of the rule-regress, albeit in different terms. In other words, what
makes it possible that two different people can understand one another?
This question is answered by his introduction of objective spirit. He puts
it like this:
lndividuals do not usually apprehend manifestations of life in isolation,
but as filled with a knowledge about commonalities and as encompassing a relation to something inner.62
According to Dilthey, it is objective spirit that enables understanding in
the first places, specifically the immediacy of elementary understanding is
enabled by having always already partaken in objective spirit. And in
turn, elementary understanding enables higher understanding.63 The relation between elementary and higher understanding is such that higher
understanding becomes necessary if the contents of elementary
61. Dilthey (1962: 207–213)/Dilthey (2002: 228f.). This description of higher versus elementary understanding is borrowed from Spiegel (2021c).
62. Dilthey (1962: 209)/Dilthey (2002: 209).
63. “Higher understanding is only needed when this self-evident context of commonality
breaks down and pits particulars against each other.”, Makkreel & Rodi (2002: 13).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
15
understanding are “called into question,” e.g., if some “ambiguity [. . .]
needs to be resolved.”64
How do these aspects of Dilthey’s own view relate to Wittgenstein’s
version of the rule regress? To get this into view, we first have to consider structurally analogous aspects of their views, more specifically, how
Dilthey’s conception of understanding and Wittgenstein’s treatment of
rule following overlap.
My suggestion is that Dilthey’s concept of higher understanding
accords with an explicit interpretation of a rule in the rule-following
problem, and that Dilthey’s elementary understanding accords with the
direct understanding that is proposed by McDowell as foundation of following rules. In other words, Dilthey’s points can be taken as a further
substantiation of the lemmata Ground* and Recurrence* that were left
insufficiently explained on McDowell’s account. With the help of
Dilthey’s account of understanding, we can now state that explicit interpretations of rules are a special case of a direct, more fundamental understanding of a rule, i.e., the kind of understanding Dilthey calls
“elementary.”
The ensuing question, then, is what makes elementary understanding,
in turn, work. This is where Dilthey’s conception of objective spirit
becomes relevant. The enabling condition for our being able to follow
rules at all is the embeddedness in objective spirit. Elementary understanding is in turn grounded in objective spirit as the historically grown
whole of objectified modes of manifestations of life, especially social
institutions. This is because objective spirit is the frame, context, or
medium through which we “communicate with each other, and interact” as it “embodies elementary knowledge as passed down to us by the
reality of the past.”65 Objective spirit is that which provides the meanings that are understood in discourse as a supra-personal, historical entity.
Due to its being supra-personal, objective spirit underwrites the meanings that can be understood in elementary understanding such that the
kind of meaning skepticism alluded to by the rule-following problem
does not arise in the first place. The rule-regress only arises if we stay on
a relatively surface level of higher understanding which does implicate
some form of interpretation of a certain intentional context given in elementary understanding. The rule-regress only arises if one rules out the
possibility of elementary understanding in the first place.
In other words, this explains why explicit rules have to figure as
means of interpretation; they become necessary when elementary understanding is insufficient. In Wittgenstein’s rule-regress, this is represented
64. Makkreel (2021: 28).
65. Makkreel & Rodi (2002: 3).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
16
Philosophical Investigations
by asking for a justification of a certain rule. Yet, the very usage of
explicit rules in order to interpret a given hermeneutic context aims at
making the use of further rules obsolete: Using an explicit rule to interpret another rule aims at enabling the interlocutors to return to an
implicit understanding (in more Wittgensteinian terms) or to elementary
understanding (in Dilthey’s terminology).
Recalling the pentalemma structure of the regress, Dilthey’s notion of
elementary understanding offers a substantiation of how understanding a
rule – specified by Ground* and Recurrence* – can work without such
understanding taking the form of another interpretation. The Diltheyian
“defusing” of the rule-regress grounds rules in a form of immediate noninferential understanding that is itself grounded in objective spirit. The
relation between singular thinker and objective spirit is conceived in
such a way that objective spirit grounds or “guarantees” understanding.
While a full dive into this topic is way beyond the scope of this
paper, it is important to note that the concept of objective spirit features,
at least implicitly, a conception of sociality broader and richer than the
kind of sociality adumbrated in the usual treatments of the rule-regress.
The difference can perhaps be elucidated by introducing the more wellknown distinction between holist and individualist conceptions of the
social. Different conceptions of objective spirit have been traditionally
associated with a holist conception of the social. In the briefest of terms,
holism claims that social entities are sui generis, i.e., something over and
above conglomerates of individuals, such that social entities are a fundamental part of the “inventory” of the world.66 Holist social entities are
supra-individual or supra-personal entities.
Ontological individualism, on the other hand, claims that social entities are nothing over and above suitably arranged conglomerates of individuals, such that those social entities can be reduced67 to individuals. It
would be inappropriate to ascribe a full-blown commitment to any of
these positions to either Wittgenstein or to those who aim to provide a
straight or skeptical solution to the regress. However, the framework in
which social relations are discussed in their respective solutions tends to
lend itself to something like individualism, or something close enough.
This is because Kripke, Brandom or Ginsborg (whose accounts are introduced in the following section) mainly consider social relations as
individual-to-individual; the frame of what is considered as a social
66. Archer (1995), Elder-Vass (2010), Panzarasa & Jennings (2006).
67. There are forms of individualism according to which social entities supervene on sets
of individuals. While I cannot argue for this here, this is not a claim that could be rendered suitably distinct from holism insofar as a holist might subscribe to a global supervenience claim, yet still hold that social entities are ontologically sufficiently distinct, cf.
Epstein (2009).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
17
relation is as something between individuals who are in each other’s
vicinity or community. In a different context, Stoutland has even provocatively (and ironically) labelled such approaches anti-social. While
there are exceptions,68 the paradigmatic cases of social interaction in
Wittgenstein’s later philosophy tend to be in such narrower confines of
one’s immediate social vicinity, e.g., the famous slab case69 or the “unorthodox” wood sellers.70 The grander point is that these more restricted
notions of sociality do not run counter to the idea of an objective spirit,
they are simply episodes of social interaction within the whole of objective spirit, the objective spirit being something that only comes into
view once we broaden the gaze onto such concrete cases to the wider
vicinity.
IV. Neither Straight nor Skeptical, but Therapeutic
Kripke’s construal, despite its infamy, offers a helpful frame for assessing
solutions to the rule-regress as it comes up in Wittgenstein. While
Kripke is foremost concerned with the “paradox” of rule-following itself,
it can be applied to the implied rule-regress. He differentiates between
straight and skeptical solutions. A straight solution to the rule-regress
argues that there is a fact of the matter – social or non-social – that
determines the meaning of linguistic items such that a rule-regress is prevented. A skeptical solution suggests that the paradox is genuine, i.e.,
that there is in actuality no deciding whether a certain performance
accords with a given rule, but that this need not affect our ordinary practice. While Kripke himself is perhaps the only major proponent of a
skeptical solution, there are a number of different accounts that propose
a straight solution, three of which will shortly be presented here.
Despite being tailored to fit Lewis Carroll’s regress paradox pertaining
to rules of inference71, Peter Winch’s straight solution can be applied
here as well.72 His straight solution interprets the rule regress as pointing
towards the idea that inferring itself is not something that can be stated
as a rule, but is rather a kind of doing, i.e., an ability, “it is learning to
do something.”73 This solution is straight insofar as a capacity that is
68. Stoutland (1997). Wittgenstein’s notion of sociality in his Culture and Value, Remarks
on Frazer’s Golden Bough, or his Lectures on Aesthetics may sometimes appear to be somewhat ‘wider’. Yet, fully establishing this point would take its own inquiry.
69. Wittgenstein (1953: §6).
70. Wittgenstein (1967: §149).
71. Carroll (1895).
72. Winch (2003).
73. Winch (2003: 57).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
18
Philosophical Investigations
either innate or acquired accounts for whether a given linguistic or conceptual performance is in accordance with a given rule.
As part of his so-called normative pragmatics, Robert Brandom has
developed a straight solution to the rule-regress that aims to ground
meaning (and concept use as such) in doings.74 Invoking Ryle’s wellestablished notion of knowing-how (in contrast to knowing-that), Brandom argues that the rule-regress is stopped once we adduce that apprehension of rules is not grounded in further explicit, propositional rules,
but rather in norms implicit in practice.75 He calls this the “pragmatist
conception of norms [as] primitive correctnesses.”76 His solution is
straight insofar as meaning is determined by norms that implicitly govern
practice, as it were.
More recently, Hannah Ginsborg has developed an account of primitive normativity as a straight solution to the rule regress. Her solution
from primitive normativity posits that there are certain, more fundamental states of consciousness which are fraught with normativity as a sense
of appropriateness,77 a “consciousness for appropriateness.”78 Ginsborg’s
proposed solution is a straight one insofar as meaning (and concept use)
is ultimately grounded in such states of consciousness, as it were.
In contrast to such skeptical and straight solutions, the hermeneutic
solution purports to be different. The hermeneutic solution is not
straight since it does not provide an account of meaning, at least not in
the sense that Ginsborg, Brandom or Winch do. Introducing the idea of
objective spirit does not amount to an account that would allow us to
determine the meaning of a given term, at least not in the same way
that, say, allusion to primitive normativity does. Neither is the hermeneutic solution a skeptical solution, since it does not deny that there is
meaning in the first place.
More specifically, the hermeneutic solution is more of a dissolution of
the problem rather than a solution. As such, it can be viewed in line
with Wittgenstein’s own metaphilosophical convictions, parts of which
famously espouse philosophy as therapy most commonly associated with
the following key quotes:
74. Brandom (1994).
75. Brandom (1994: 46, 62).
76. Brandom (1994: 21).
77. “[I]t is plausible that she does so with a sense that this is the appropriate thing to do.
She takes it that the green spoon ‘belongs’ in the box containing the previously sorted
green things and that the blue spoon does not.”, Ginsborg (2011: 235).
78. Ginsborg (2011: 237).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
19
The real discovery is the one that makes me capable of stopping doing
philosophy when I want to. – The one that gives philosophy peace
[. . .].79
The philosopher’s treatment of a question is like the treatment of an
illness.80
What is your aim in philosophy?—To shew the fly the way out of
the fly-bottle.81
The metaphilosophical conviction expressed in quotes like these states
that the goal of at least some philosophy is to identify certain faulty
(“pathological”) underlying theoretical commitments which entail a
given philosophical problem. The therapeutic reading of Wittgenstein
has been championed by, for example, Baker and Hacker.82 This kind of
philosophical therapy consists in a diagnosis and reconception of the matter in question.83 In the case of the hermeneutic solution, the diagnosis
lies in recognising that the setup that leads to regress, i.e., the pentalemma, is faulty. The reconception lies in offering a rephrasing of the
two lemmata Ground and Recurrence, both of which include the
acknowledgment that grasping a rule does not have to be an interpretation (Deutung) but can also consist in elementary understanding. In this
way, the hermeneutic solution does not offer a way out of the regress. It
instead contends that the regress does not even arise once we bring elementary understanding and its relation to objective spirit into play. The
“paradox” about rules is thus not solved, but dissolved. If we take Wittgenstein’s own metaphilosophical remarks seriously, the hermeneutic
solution is more faithful to his own views. While this is not a requirement for an appropriate systematic solution to the regress, it does have
the added bonus of being a solution that is closer to the Wittgensteinian
spirit.
V. Conclusion
This paper argued for a hermeneutic solution to the rule regress as it is
entailed by Wittgenstein’s rule-following problem. The hermeneutic
solution consists in adducing Dilthey’s concepts of objective spirit and
elementary understanding not as the bedrock, but as the grand social
structure in which rule-following happens in the first place. The hermeneutic solution is neither straight nor skeptical, but therapeutic insofar as
79.
80.
81.
82.
83.
Wittgenstein (1953, §133).
Wittgenstein (1953: §255).
Wittgenstein (1953: §309).
Baker and Hacker (1984).
Macarthur (2008).
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
20
Philosophical Investigations
it offers a reconception of the assumptions – Ground and Recurrence –
which enable an infinite regress in the first place, such that the regress
does not even arise.
The hermeneutic solution walks on a tightrope. On the one hand, it
avoids saying too much, i.e., something that would go against Wittgenstein’s own methodological constraints, and that some other accounts are
guilty of (Kripke, Ginsborg, Brandom, Winch). On the other hand, it
avoids saying not enough, which both Wittgenstein and McDowell’s elaboration of Wittgenstein are guilty off. Simply put, it states that rulefollowing is grounded in objective spirit, i.e., in a relation of a speaker
to their socio-historical environment that is more profound and more
intimate than the mere social “‘environment” that Wittgenstein himself
evokes in his elaborations.
While there is some fairly well-established research that links Wittgensteinian philosophy with the idealist, phenomenological, and pragmatist
traditions (as well as his relation to other thinkers like Heidegger), there
has been surprisingly little work on how Wittgenstein’s thought relates
to Post-Hegelian hermeneutics. This paper is an attempt to demonstrate
one way in which these two traditions can relate. The intersection presented here lies in the idea that intentionality and concept use as such
are ultimately grounded in a fundamental form of understanding which
itself is intimately connected to a historical, social, subject-transcendent
whole.84
Department of Philosophy
University of Potsdam
Am neuen Palais 10
14469 Potsdam
Germany
[email protected]
References
Archer, M. (1995). Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach.
Cambridge: CUP.
Baker, G. and P. Hacker (1984). Scepticism, Rules and Language. Oxford:
Blackwell.
84. I am grateful to Johannes Haag, Hans-Johann Glock, Richard Raatzsch, Mehdi
Ranaee, Luz Christopher Seiberth, Simon Sch€
uz, Gustav Melichar, and Jonathan Reiser
for helpful commentary on draft versions of this paper.
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
21
Bowie, A. (2016). “Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy. The Art of
Understanding” In K. Nelson (ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Hermeneutics, New York: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 45-53.
Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit. Cambridge, MA: HUP.
Carroll, L. (1895). “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles.” Mind 104(416):
691–693.
Dilthey, W. (1962). Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften, Gesammelte Schriften, vol. VII, ed. Berlin, Germany: B.
Groethuysen.
Dilthey, W. (2002). The Formation of the Historical World in the Human
Sciences, Selected Works, vol. III, eds. R.A. Makkreel and F. Rodi,
Princeton, NJ 1985–2010.
Dilthey, W. (1990). In H. Nohl (ed.), Die Jugendgeschichte Hegels und
andere Abhandlungen zur Geschichte des Deutschen Idealismus. Gesammelte
Schriften, Vol. 4, G€
ottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Elder-Vass, D. (2010). The Causal Power of Social Structures. Cambridge:
CUP.
Epstein, B. (2009). “Ontological Individualism Reconsidered.” Synthese
166: 187–213.
Gallagher, S. (2019). “Dilthey and Empathy”, In E. Nelson (ed.), Interpreting Dilthey, Cambridge: CUP, pp. 145-158.
Ginsborg, H. (2011). Primitive Normativity and Skepticism about Rules.
The Journal of Philosophy, 108(5), 227–254.
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason, Guyer & Wood (eds.), Cambridge: CUP.
Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge,
MA: HUP.
Lin, F. (2019). “Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Following a Rule
only once.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28(1): 134–154.
https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2019.1604314
L€
owenstein, D. (2017). “A Uniform Account of Rule-Regress Problems.” Acta Analytica 32: 333–354.
Macarthur, D. (2008). “Pragmatism, Metaphysical Quietism and the
Problem of Normativity.” Philosophical Topics 36(1): 193–209.
Maher, C. (2012). The Pittsburgh School of Philosophy. Sellars, McDowell,
Brandom. London & New York: Routledge.
Makkreel, R. (2021). “Wilhelm Dilthey.” In E. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
spr2021/entries/dilthey/, last viewed 28.04.2021.
Makkreel, R. and F. Rodi (2002). “Introduction.”, In W. Dilthey (ed.),
The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 1–22.
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
22
Philosophical Investigations
McDowell, J. (1984). “Wittgenstein on Following a Rule.” Synthese 58:
325–363.
McDowell, J. (1992). “Meaning and Intentionality in Wittgenstein’s
Later Philosophy.” In P. French, T. Uehling and H. Wettstein (eds.),
Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Vol 17. Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press, pp. 40–52.
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and World, New edition. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
McDowell, J. (2009). “Wittgensteinian ‘Quietism’.” Common Knowledge
15(3): 365–372.
McDowell, J. (2015). “Philosophical Method.” Journal of Philosophical
Research, Special Supplement 25–29.
Panzarasa, P. and N. Jennings. (2006). “Collective Cognition and Emergence in Multi-Agend Systems.” In R. Sun (ed.), Cognition and Multiagent Interaction, Cambridge, MA: CUP, pp. 401-408.
Rump, J. (2020). “Husserlian Phenomenology, Rule-Following, and
Primitive Normativity”, In C. Engelland (ed.), Language and Phenomenology, London & New York: Routledge, pp. 74-91.
T. Schatzki and K. Knorr-Cetina (eds.), (2000). The Practice Turn in Contemporary Theory. London & New York: Routledge.
Schleiermacher, F. (1959). Hermeneutik, ed. H. Kimmerle, Heidelberg.
Schleiermacher, F. (1977). Hermeneutik und Kritik, ed. Manfred Frank,
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Slaby, J. (2021). “Expanding the Active Mind.” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 1–17. https://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.2021.
1905487
Spiegel, T. J. (2021a). Naturalism, Quietism, and the Threat to Philosophy.
Basel: Schwabe.
Spiegel, T. J. (2021b): “What is Philosophical Quietism?” In K. Pathak
(ed.), Quietism, Agnosticism, and Mysticism, London & New York:
Springer.
Spiegel, T. J. (2021c). “Wittgenstein and Dilthey on Scientism and
Method.” Wittgenstein-Studien 12(1): 165–194.
Stoutland, F. (1997). “Why are Philosophers of Action so Anti-Social?”
In L. Alanen (ed.), Commonality and Particularity in Ethics. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 45–74.
Testa, I. (2009). “Second Nature and Recognition: Hegel and the Social
Space.” Critical Horizons 10(3): 341–370.
Verheggen, C. (2017). “Davidson’s Treatment of Wittgenstein’s RuleFollowing Paradox.” In C. Verheggen (ed.), Wittgenstein and Davidson
on Language, Thought, and Action, Cambridge: CUP, pp. 69-96.
Winch, P. (2003). The Idea of Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy.
London & New York: Routledge.
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Thomas J. Spiegel
23
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations, transl. Anscombe,
Oxford: Blackwell, p. 1953.
Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, ed.
von Wright, Rhees & Anscombe, Cambridge: MIT Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty, eds. Anscombe & Wright, transl.
Paul & Anscombe, Hamilton, New Zealand: Harper.
Wittgenstein, L. (1976). ““Cause and Effect: Intuitive Awareness”, ed.
Rush Rhees, transl.” Peter Winch, Philosophia 6: 392–445.
Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Culture and Value, ed. von Wright, transl.
Winch. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1995). “Philosophische Bemerkungen.” In M. Nedo
(ed.), Wiener Ausgabe, Vol. 3, Manuskript 110, New York: Springer.
Wittgenstein, L. (2001). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, transl. Pears &
McGuinness, London & New York: Routledge.
Wright, C. (2001). Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s
Philosophical Investigations. Cambridge, MA: HUP.
© 2022 The Authors. Philosophical Investigations published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.