Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
Volume 6 Issue 2 December 2016
Research Article
___________________________________________________________
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein*
İkinci Dönem Wittgenstein'da Kural Takibinin Septisizmden Korunması
YURDAGÜL KILINÇ ADANALI
Necmettin Erbakan University
Received: 03.12.16Accepted: 26.12.16
Abstract: Whether the later Wittgenstein succeeded in destroying
“the mythologized” and abstract theories of rule following is still a
matter for debate. The question is important because it grounds
Wittgenstein’s position against a Platonist, idealistic, conventionalist, relativist and even skeptical views regarding the concept of
rule following. It has been argued that Wittgenstein’s views on rule
following does not succeed in giving a comprehensive theory.
Some even argued that Wittgenstein’s views even leads to a skeptical conclusion that there are no rules to be followed. In this article,
I argue that when Wittgenstein rejects necessary conditions that
determinate the application of rules, he does not slip into a skeptical position. Rather, he introduces a concept of rule following
based on practice, rejecting classical objectivist approaches.
Through this concept, in fact, Wittgenstein wants to overcome
certain
dichotomies
such
as
objectivity/subjectivity,
socie-
ty/individual, and mind/body. His views on rule following emphasizes the role of individual in following a rule and thereby his or
her moral responsibility.
Keywords: Rule-following, skepticism, normativity, criterion, moral responsibility.
*
This paper is partially based upon my master thesis How to Follow a Rule: Practice Based
Rule Following in Wittgenstein, which is fulfilled at the METU.
___________________________________________________________
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı, Öğr. Gör.
Necmettin Erbakan Üniversitesi Sosyal ve Beşeri Bilimler Fakültesi Felsefe Bölümü
42140, Meram, Konya, TR
[email protected]
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
___________________________________________________________
2
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
Introduction
Language is a rule-based system and a proper understanding of language entails a comprehensive investigation of its grammar. However, we
are not concerned here with the kind of grammar that linguists have in
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
mind, when they say that language is a rule- governed system. It is rather
the philosophical aspects of grammatical rules not examined or explained
in ordinary grammar books. A native speaker does not need to consult
grammar each time she speaks, since she already has an intuitive grasp of
grammatical rules. Most people, however, if asked to formulate the rules
which they use, would be hard pressed to know what to say. They might
perhaps offer examples, but these examples are not rules and they do not
explain to us how to follow a rule. If rule following is not properly understood, then the lack of understanding may generate confusions concerning logical and grammatical aspects of linguistic practice, and this may
have further implications for the relations between external grammatical
rules and their mental representations. This article discusses some of
these confusions as pointed out by Ludwig Wittgenstein and examines
how he tried to “dissolve” them.
Despite the fact that rules are discussed extensively throughout the
history of philosophy, the concept of rule following as a philosophical
problem has become prominent mainly because of Wittgenstein’s treatment of this topic in his Philosophical Investigations (1958a). Although
Wittgenstein does not give an explicit definition of what a rule is, his
analysis presupposes a basic understanding of this concept. He insists
that philosophy should not be concerned with hidden structures or foundations of language, since he thinks that there is nothing to be discovered
or explained metaphysically (1958a:§126). It is not the task of philosophy
to go beyond grammatical rules which underlie the usage of words and
sentences in ordinary language; it is, rather, to investigate and clarify how
these rules are used or applied in speech.
Contrary to Wittgenstein, if we accept that there is an independent
reality beyond the actual application of rules in language, then two possibilities arise: [i] either language reflects reality in the same way a mirror
reflects an image or [ii] language becomes arbitrary and it lacks any intrinsic link with reality. In the former case, language follows reality and
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
3
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
changes along with it. If language reflects reality, then there is no need
for any extra-linguistic means to understand and explain reality. However,
if language turns out to be arbitrary, as some would have argued, then it
cannot be taken as a reliable linguistic tool in understanding and explainfor example, conceptual analysis. Both positions have significant implications about us, language and reality. If language mirrors reality directly
and inevitably, then we face an arduous task of matching words with the
world. This also takes out the individual freedom from the equation. If
language, on the other hand, is arbitrary, this disconnects words from the
world, and cuts off us from reality as far as the language concerned. There
are, however, two main problems with these positions: [i] if language is
necessary, then how can we explain linguistic error? [ii] If language is
arbitrary, then how can we achieve truth?
I believe these problems were at the background, when Wittgenstein claimed that rules are not conceived independently of human linguistic practices. He proposed an external justification which grounds
rules non-transcendentally, and in fact he saw no justification for rules
beyond rules themselves. It is true that we justify our linguistic actions by
appealing to rules, but justification of linguistic practice cannot be
achieved by assuming a transcendental status for the rules that ground
these actions.
Rules do not correspond to reality, that is, they are not means
through which we reach at reality. Indeed, they are part of the reality so
far as the language is a part of the world. For some authors this view of
Wittgenstein leads to skepticism. In contrast, I will argue that Wittgenstein rightly makes a distinction between “in accordance with a rule” and
“following a rule.” Following a rule is not just matter of doing what accords with the rule; one must also do it because the rule requires it. The
rule must be one’s reason for acting. This means that following a rule
involves understanding the rule and grasping what it requires. One can
act in accordance with a rule, doing what the rule requires without understanding it. So, for Wittgenstein, “accordance with a rule” brings rule
skepticism as a threat to possibility of correct and meaningful speech not
his concept of rule following.
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
ing reality as it is, and we may need other ways of investigating the world,
4
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
1. Rule-Following
In Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein considers language as a
game which does not operate necessarily according to well-defined rules.
When one speaks, one does not have to employ well defined grammatical
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
rules in speaking, since these rules do not follow any given structure of
the world. Yet, the rules imply that language is a practice and is a part of
human behavior that governed by social regularities (Alpyağıl, 2002: 133).
The idea of a rule resting on the association of words with transcendental
forms or ideas is incoherent for him, since it is a mythologized concept of
rule and furthermore it is not clear how the mind grasps these forms or
ideas and follows accordingly (Wittgenstein, 1958a: §218-219). The distinction between correct and incorrect applications of words cannot be
made a priori by invoking abstract or transcendental concepts, since there
is no realm beyond and outside language and its actual usage (Baker and
Hacker, 1985:12).
In contrast to Platonism, Wittgenstein does not invoke a connection between rules and words which permits infinitely many applications
and contains a whole series of possibilities in linguistic practice (Rees,
1967: 333). He rejects Platonic position due to its commitment to transcendental abstract entities such as ideas, concepts or meanings independently of human practice of language. The individual mind cannot
have an access to a transcendental ideal world and neither can it find a
structure in language that reflects that the forms of this world. Rather, if
there is such a structure, it is practical and dynamic relations of people in
certain regularities and patterns of action over time (Verheggen, 2003:
285).
Many modern commentators of Wittgenstein point out the sharp
contrast between early and later Wittgenstein and argued that the model
of an ideal language that is the main project of Tractatus LogicoPhilosophicus is rejected by later Wittgenstein since he no longer believed
that language is governed by a set of specifically defined rules or logical
syntax. In the Tractatus, language is compared to a model with exact
meanings and fixed rules (Wittgenstein, 1961). The idea is that it is possible to draft an artificial language which represents abstract conditions
underlying every natural language. Later Wittgenstein, however, objects
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
5
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
to the idea that ordinary usage is determined by specifically define and
fixed rules. He claims that we use language without prior definitions or
fixed rules. Rules do not mirror the logical forms of reality and one
should look for “the harmony between thought and reality…in the gramever, the existence of linguistic rules and rules of usage people commonly
apply in their daily communication and interaction, but he rejects the
possibility of isolating and describing them at an abstract level independently of their actual usage in specific contexts. Thus, a rule does not
count as a standard of correctness independently of linguistic practice.
Rather it is a matter of its use in a certain context, in a certain practice,
and in a certain language which is interwoven with the world (Aliy, 2005:
167). If that is how it is, then the crucial question regarding the rule following is “how can we apply a rule?”
This question brings us to two main issues: first whether there is any
need for interpretation between a rule and its application, and second
whether there is or can be a criterion for the application of a rule.
2. Is There any Gap between Rule and Its Application?
There can be many interpretations for the application of a rule, some
of which are mutually coherent and furthermore, any action or application can be characterized both in a way that accords with a given rule or
conflicts with it. And this constitutes the source of the paradox; in other
words, even if the application of a rule is correct, there can be an interpretation of this application that contradicts to it. The paradox stems
from the idea that grasping a rule always involves an interpretation and
interpretation works both ways, in accordance with the rule and in contrast to it. The second problem with the application of a rule and the
interpretation provided for it is its regression. It is true that we may provide an interpretation, but how do we know that this interpretation corresponds to the meaning of that word? Can this interpretation also have
“a meaning” which requires a further interpretation? If so, this interpretation will require another interpretation. That is, if a rule needs to be supplemented with another interpretation, then the interpretation of the
rule needs a further interpretation and so on. So, the appeal to interpreta-
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
mar of the language” (Wittgenstein, 1974: §162). He does not deny, how-
6
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
tions leads to an infinite regress. Thus, one may never know whether the
interpretation of a rule is correct or not.
To avoid these problems, Wittgenstein rejects the idea that all instances of rule following must involve interpretations. He does not, how-
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
ever, deny that rules guide actions. Since a rule can be interpreted in
many and sometimes contradictory ways, interpretation can be conceived
as prescribing any course of action whatsoever. In fact, his critique of
interpretation is an attack on the assumption that interpretation is an
inner process (Delice: 2013, 104). Wittgenstein denies that following a
rule involves an inner process of interpretation and claims that if we do
not give up interpretation as mediator between rule and its application,
then “whatever is going to seem right to me is right. And that only means
that here we cannot talk about ‘right’” (Wittgenstein, 1958a: §258). In
order to avoid these two problems, the requirement of a “mysterious”
mediation between a rule and its application must be given up.
Interestingly enough, Saul Kripke takes Wittgenstein’s remarks on
problem of interpretation to establish a skeptical conclusion. According
to him, first, there is no criterion how we distinguish correct from incorrect applications. Second, the justification of understanding and rulegoverned behavior is ambiguous; we can only justify a rule with a community consensus (Williams, 1999: 162). So, for Kripke, rule following consists in doing as community does: “Ultimately we reach a level where we
act without any reason in terms of which we can justify our action. We
act unhesitatingly but blindly” (Kripke, 1982: 87). In that regard, community determines what justifies rule following actions. Since meaning is
determined by appealing to communal practice, Kripke assumes that
Wittgenstein agrees with the skeptic that there is neither an “internal”
nor an “external” fact which guarantees any meaning (Kripke, 1982: 69).
Kripke’s view involves one important point: he thinks that, for Wittgenstein, meaning and rule following have a correlation with a community.
Meaning is possible because we are living in a society and the community
determines the correctness of an application.
However, does Wittgenstein really accept community standards as
correct? Can we say that Wittgenstein believes in that there is homogeneity in the application of a concept in a community? If we take community
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
7
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
as a standard, then we should accept that disagreements would arise in
the community. If that is the case, then we have to accept that each culture is enclosed within its standards of correctness. Consequently, meaning becomes completely culture-dependent. Is this the relativist account
If we consider communities as bedrock, since all of them will be enclosed within their rules, this would cause a problem of communications:
how can different communities understand each other? As Wittgenstein
points out, “the common behavior of mankind is the system of reference
by means of which we interpret an unknown language” (Wittgenstein,
1958: §206). Nevertheless, the basis of rules does not depend upon our
verbal agreement on the nature of things; on the contrary, it depends on
human practice, because this is common to all mankind. So, we can understand each other regardless of our cultural differences. If this is true,
then meanings arise from our acting in the world. Grammatical rules and
their applications are merged in a melting pot or rather they emerge together in a social context. This implies that Kripke’s account is mistaken,
because rule-application cannot be justified by appealing to the community. We cannot say that “this is blue” is correct by appealing to a community, but by only consulting to the examples of “blue” in a linguistic
community. What is important here is that the agreement of the color
with the sample determines the usage of this concept. Of course, there is
an agreement in community, but this agreement belongs to the framework.
3. Criterion: How do You Know That So and So is the Case?
The second discussion concerning the concept of rule following is
related to the criterion of its application. Although Wittgenstein uses the
term criterion in a somewhat different, technical way, his views indicate
that its meaning may ultimately be derived from everyday usage. He
claims that no mental picture, image or concept, could serve as our ultimate criterion for whether a descriptive expression “fits” an object. If we
do not relate a word to the observable characteristics of an object in the
external world through some mediating mental picture, how is, then, the
connection between a word and an object is established? The answer is
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
which Wittgenstein adheres?
8
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
not by some “mysterious” relation, but by all particular connections that
consist in the actual usage of a word in a language.
Wittgenstein says that criteria are specified by giving an answer to
the question “How do you know that so and so is the case?” The answer conBeytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
sists in giving a criterion for saying that “so and so is the case” (Wittgenstein, 1958b:24). This means that there may be more than one criterion
for each case. Whether or not a word is correctly applied may depend
upon various criteria which may be present and may even conflict with
one another. Which criteria are relevant to the use of a term in one case
depends on its actual uses. Therefore, a criterion “determines” the meaning of words and sentences by the usage. If one does not know the criterion for the use of an expression, then she does not understand its meaning. A term has no meaning until it is connected with the characteristics
of the objects which it applies to. Thus, criterion for the use of an expression is central to its meaning, and it is mentioned in any definition of that
expression. Wittgenstein writes “one cannot guess how a word functions,
has to look at its use and learn from that” (1958a:§109). Then to learn the
use of a sign we look to ordinary language to discover the function it has,
or the purpose it serves there. In that sense, the rules of usage are not
only public, but are also a part of our application.
A person cannot follow a rule unless he or she is in conformity with
a common way of acting that is displayed in the behavior of everyone who
has had the same training, instruction, and guidance. This means that the
concept of rule following implies practice of rule followers which Wittgenstein called form of life: “the speaking of language is part of an activity
or form of life” (1958a: §23).
Some authors argued that form of life as a background and criterion
for rules leads to skeptical conclusions, since there is no normativity for
rules in form of life. They further asserted that a rule should be normative
so that it may let us evaluate the use of concepts and practical regularities. Since mere regularity in practice is not sufficient for the manifestation of a rule, Wittgensteinian rule-following cannot be a normative theory (Medina, 1998, 295). Despite the claims, Wittgenstein’s views on rule
following cannot be considered as skeptical because of his account of
normativity, which will be explained in the following section.
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
9
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
4. Normativity
The notions of correctness and incorrectness play an essential role in
the concept of normativity. I argue that this goes for Wittgenstein’s concept of rule following as well. Rules involve various concepts and certain
phenomena, but also embody a way of acting within the world. Furthermore, these practices require the possession of various norms that relate
to certain skills such as teaching, explaining, criticizing and justifying
(Wittgenstein 1958a: §197-202). If rules do not function in guiding, criticizing, etc. an action, they cannot be considered as rules in any sense.
Furthermore, rules must be repeatable, and not something which is done
only once, since a language is normative insofar as its rules can be both
correctly and incorrectly applied repeatedly in a form of life. The origin
of norms, then, lies in their agreement to form of life that creates standards. This relation between normativity of rule following and form of life
implies that private language has no normativity (Rızvanoglu, 2016: 24). If
meanings are determined by one person, then there is no intelligible way
to understand rightness or wrongness of an action (Wittgenstein, 1958a:
§202). Unless a rule has various applications, it cannot actually possess a
normative value; a language whose rules are applied only once is not a
genuine language. This means that rule can possess a normative value,
only if it has various applications. That is, practical regularities have to be
accompanied by expression of acceptance, or rejection, or criticism. Of
course, mere regularity in practice is not sufficient for the application of a
rule. Wittgenstein’s account of normativity cannot be reduced to mere
regularities, since the normative attitudes are an essential competent of
continuing practices.
Wittgenstein moves the discussion toward the ground of grammar
that establishes the possibilities for continuing practices. The rules are
realized or manifest in practice and are not held as external objects for
determining meanings. Rather the relation between a rule and its application is internal, and its instantiation is in practice. There are no external
standards for the justification of grammatical rules since they are standards for the correctness of using an expression: “Grammar describes the
use of words in a language. So it has somewhat the same relation to the
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
complex practices that govern meaning and use. They not only report
10
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
language as a description of a game, the rules of a game, have to the
game” (Wittgenstein, 1974: §23). This is a considerable principle that
there is no such thing as justifying grammar by reference to reality. Rules
of grammar are not suitable to any external justification and cannot be
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
true or false by reference to reality, since the rules of grammar are antecedent to truth or falsity. That is why the rules are considered as arbitrary
(Alpyağıl, 2003: 100). They describe the framework within which ascriptions of truth or falsity can meaningfully be made. Since any rule cannot
meaningfully articulate without grammar, grammar is to be seen as a
framework of rules. Therefore, grammatical rules are standards for the
correct use of an expression which determine its meaning: to give the
meaning of a word is to specify its grammar (Wittgenstein, 1969: §61-62).
“Correct” here does not necessarily mean “true,” since one may use a term
in accordance with rules without saying something true. The “truth” of a
grammatical proposition consists not in stating how things are, but in
accurately expressing a rule, that is, grammar governs but do not determine (O’Neill, 2001: 1). However, this does not mean that Wittgenstein
abandoned the idea that language is rule-governed. This becomes clear
when we stop comparing language to a calculus and began to see it as a
game:
As long as we remain in the province of the true-false games a change in the
grammar can only lead us from one game to another, and never from something true to something false. On the other hand if we go outside the province of these games, we don’t any longer call it “language” and “grammar”
and once again we do not come into contradiction with reality. (Wittgenstein, 1974: §68)
Therefore rule following has two dimensions: on the one hand, there
is a form of life, which provides a background for rule following, and on
the other, there are individuals who interact with others in a form of life.
Individuals are free to give a new meaning to concepts or rules; however,
this does not mean that they have no responsibility over the application
of a rule correctly. By rejecting private language, Wittgenstein avoids
subjectivity, and by rejecting external criteria for rule following, he avoids
objectivity. So, Wittgenstein’s view of rule following advocates a position
neither of pure subjectivity nor of pure objectivity. It may be said there is
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
11
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
a balance concerning subjective and objective aspects of linguistic acts in
Wittgensteinian account. Moreover, even though there are no necessary
rules that force people to act in certain ways, we still have the concept of
correct application: doing right thing in action, not just in theory. This is
So, he develops a theory of practice that does not reduce the normative
to the empirical or psychological. On this account, what grounds the
normativity of a practice is an agreement in action. The source of normativity does not spring from a set of symbolic rules belonging to an autonomous domain, independent of actual uses; it is rather immerged in practice or praxis.
5. Moral Responsibility and Rule Following
When we suggest that praxis is the fundamental phenomenon for
the concept of rule following, it seems we may set up a relation between
rule following and responsibility in a moral sense. Here, I do not claim
that Wittgenstein provides a new moral theory. It is fair to say that he is
not constructing a theory of moral judgment. Since his concept of rule
following does not dismiss normativity, I believe there must be a link,
however indirect, between rule following and moral responsibility. To
establish that link, first I will show the conceptual interdependence of
rule following, practice, and responsibility. Second, I will examine whether Wittgenstein’s concept of rule following imply moral responsibility for
individual as it stands in opposition to the Platonist and Tractarian concepts of rules.
It is reasonable to suppose that there is a moral aspect in every step
of rule following, since the concept of rule following implies both that
there is individual freedom in actions and that there is a need for evaluation of the application of rules with regard to their correctness. In replying to the question “what is it to follow a rule” Wittgenstein says that “it
would be more correct to say not that an intuition was needed at every
stage but that a new decision was needed at every stage” (Wittgenstein,
1958a: §186). This answer stresses the need for “decision” that implies
that there is a relation between normativity of rule following and responsibility of individual. When we see the concept of rule following from this
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
what Wittgenstein means by practice or “praxis” when he uses the term.
12
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
point of view, we may conclude that Wittgenstein’s thoughts have some
implications for moral evaluation.
It is possible to talk about an application of a rule as correct or incorrect, since the concept of rule following would have no meaning unless
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
normative values are assumed. The fact that rule following activities are
not always determined by rules, and they rely on practices for their meaning, and they can be performed correctly or incorrectly, etc., all these
suggest that there are some aspects of Wittgenstein’s concept rule following that need to be studied further from a moral point of view. In that
regard, rule following is a special sort of activity; it may involve decisions
that do not appeal to a rule as a set of formulated instructions. Moreover,
when making decisions in new cases, the lack of precision involved in rule
following suggests that a type of flexibility is needed to solve problems.
The lack of precision in rule following may make application of a rule
easier particularly in problematic contexts, where our decisions involve
complex scenarios, have certain consequences or even made in the face of
moral dilemmas. Thus, we need moral responsibility as an ingredient in
reaching to a suitable application through correct decisions.
Another implication concerning moral responsibility takes place in
difference between being in accordance with a rule and following a rule
(Baker and Hacker, 1985: 155). When one follows a rule, she accords to it;
on the other hand, when one accords to a rule, she may or may not follow
it. The difference between following a rule and merely according to that
rule has implications concerning moral responsibility of individual. One
can follow a rule only if she has the freedom of not following it. Thus,
only free individuals can follow rules and only they can fulfill epistemically normative activities such criticism, justification, and so on. That is, rule
following is manifest in the manner in which individual uses rules, refers
to rules in acting, evaluates and corrects what others do (Baker and
Hacker, 1985: 45). This means that only individuals, who are free and
capable of acting, can follow rules and give reasons for their actions; machines or robots, for example, are not free and cannot give reasons for
their actions. (Wittgenstein, 1958a: §193) We can generalize that people
as oppose to machines can both accord and follow rules; machines on the
other hand can only accord to rules. Therefore, the only way we can
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
13
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
meaningfully speak of rule following is reserved to human beings, because
following a rule is praxis and only human beings can have praxis. In addition, only human beings can pursue which beliefs, decisions, and actions
are required to follow a rule. This internal connection between rule folThen, what does it mean to conceive of rule following as a moral responsibility? We learn to engage in complex practices through learning,
practice, and respond creatively to new situations and make mistakes, and
learn from them. We learn to be good and to do well; we come to a form
of life that values these activities and supports us in fulfilling them. Practices provide a framework of social expectations that establish norms to
determine what judgments and actions are appropriate. Even if we are
entirely freeing acting, we could not have been capable of required praxis
without interacting with others. In this sense, moral responsibility develops with practices in a form of life. These practices identify actions and
events that correspond to certain concepts. Hence, they enable individuals to act and judge with responsibility. Then, moral responsibility is also
a normative enterprise for the concept of rule following. It is normative
because it is concerned with how we ought to follow a rule and be in a
relation to one another (O’Day, 1998: 61).
When moral responsibility is viewed as an important component of
the concept of rule following, deeper dimensions of the rule following are
revealed. One is that each act, even the simplest one, has the features of
learning, understanding and teaching. It can be questioned how these
features affect the development of one’s own character and identity. In
that regard, there is a need for moral responsibility for acquiring and
performing the right acts. Similarly, we should consider the influence of
our acts upon others who might observe or become aware of it. Another
dimension of moral responsibility relates to human existence, since without rules there can be neither society nor culture (Sidnell, 2003: 429).
That is to say, we cannot imagine that a society in which there are no
recognizable rules, judgments, justifications and criticisms. These two
dimensions guide actions and provide a ground on which practice become
regular and predictable. Further they involve one’s self-perception and
that of others in the process of how we reflect upon them and decide
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
lowing and praxis has an important implication for moral responsibility.
14
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
what to do particularly what we do have consequences for others (Arici,
2015: 70).
We are born into a world in which we learn from others how to act
in certain ways in certain circumstances, and we teach others how to act
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
when it is our turn to convey this information. Even if one becomes autonomous in one’s choices eventually, the capacity to be such a free and
autonomous individual is grounded in our relations with others. This
interrelation is as much social as individual in an obvious way; we communicate with others as a way of clarifying what we intend to, would,
should do. Clarity means that we work with moral responsibility until we
reach a decision about what action is right. Thus, the ability to act with
moral responsibility is realized in individual’s relations to others.
Since all practices are never entirely private or personal, they are
learned, and taught in a social context; they are part of a shared form of
life. It is only through experiences of interacting with others that we
master the abilities of rule following. Nevertheless, this does not mean
that practices share necessarily a single common feature. Rather, they
involve different responses, choices, and actions as situations demand. It
is obvious that there is a balance in rule following concerning personality
and sociality. That is, rule following does not only concern an individual
but that individual in fundamental respects with other people as well.
This makes us as responsible individuals. Here moral responsibility
emerges from how we treat others, how they treat us, and how we treat
each other. This network of relations represents the inseparability of rule
following and of moral responsibility.
Conclusion
In this article, I argued that even though Wittgenstein rejects necessary criteria for rule following, he does not support a skeptical or relativist position. Based on preceding considerations, Wittgenstein’s concept
of rule following can be summarized in five points:
First, the idea of rule resting on the association of words with transcendental concepts is incoherent, since it is unclear how the mind grasps
these concepts. This view only produces a “mythologized” concept of
rule.
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
15
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
Second, since a rule can be interpreted in countless ways, and interpretation can be conceived as prescribing any course of action whatsoever, this makes interpretation unnecessary at best and contradictory at
worst. Rejecting that rule following must involve an interpretation does
Third, the rules of usage are not only public, but also a part of the
world and us as language users. A person cannot follow a rule unless she
or he is in conformity with a common way of acting that is displayed in
the behavior of others who have the same training, instruction, direction,
and guidance, etc.
Fourth, individuals can interpret rules freely. However, this does not
mean that they have no constrains or that they are dismissed of responsibility of applying a rule correctly. Since practices are not entirely private
and personal, they are part of a shared form of life; they are learned, practiced and taught in a given society.
Fifth, it is obvious that we must strike a balance in following rules
between private and public, between individual and social. This makes us
as morally responsible individuals. Here moral responsibility emerges
from how we treat others, how they treat us, and how we treat each other. This network of relations represents the inseparability of rule following from moral responsibility in Wittgensteinian context.
References
Arıcı, M. (2015). Zihinsel Alanda “Ben Hissi” Neye Karşılık Gelir? Dört Öğe, 7, 6576.
Aliy, A. (2005). Wittgenstein Felsefesinde Din Dili ve Dinî İman. Çukurova Üniversitesi İlahiyat Fakültesi Dergisi, 1, 158-176.
Alpyağıl, R. (2003). Gramer Olarak Teoloji: Din Felsefesinde Yeni Bir Ufuk.
Tezkire, 31-32, 89-105.
Alpyağıl, R. (2002). Wittgenstein ve Kierkegaard’dan Hareketle Din Felsefesi Yapmak.
İstanbul: Anka Yayınları.
Baker, G. P. & Hacker, P. M. S. (1985). Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar, and Necessity.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Delice, A. (2013). Kural, Anlam ve Yorum Üçgeninde Wittgenstein. FSM İlmî
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
not mean to deny that rules guide an action.
16
Yurdagül Kılınç Adanalı
Araştırmalar: İnsan ve Toplum Bilimleri Dergisi, 2, 101-118.
Kripke, S. A. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Massachusetts:
Harvard University Press.
Medina, J. M. (1998). Wittgenstein in Transition: Meaning, Rules and Practices
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
(PhD. Thesis). Evanston: Northwestern University.
O’Day, K. (1998). Normativity and Interpersonal Reasons. Ethical Theory and
Moral Practice, 1 (1), 61-87.
O’Neill, M. (2001). Explaining ‘The Hardness of the Logical Must’: Wittgenstein
on Grammar, Arbitrariness and Logical Necessity. Philosophical Investigations,
24 (1), 1-29.
Rees, D. A. (1967). Platonism and the Platonic Tradition. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillian Publishing Co.
Rızvanoğlu, E. (2016). Wittgenstein’ın Özel Dil Eleştirisi Bağlamında Kartezyen
Geleneğe Itirazı. Posseible, 8, 22-32.
Sidnell, J. (2003). An Ethnographic Consideration of Rule-Following. The Journal
of the Royal Anthropological Institute Incorporating Man, 9 (3), 429-445.
Verheggen, C. (2003). Wittgenstein’s Rule Following Paradox and the Objectivity
of Meaning. Philosophical Investigations, 26 (4), 285-310.
Williams, M. (1999). Wittgenstein, Mind and Meaning: Toward a Social Conception of
Mind. London: Routledge.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958a). Philosophical Investigations (trans. G. E. M. Anscombe).
New York: Blackwell Publishers.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958b). The Blue and Brown Books (ed. R. Rhees) New York:
Harper & Row Publishers.
Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (trans. C. K. Ogden). London: Routledge & Keagan Paul.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty (trans. Denis Paul & G. E. M. Anscombe).
New York: Harper & Row Publishers.
Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical Grammar (trans. A. Kenny). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Beytulhikme 6(2) 2016
17
Saving Rule Following from Skepticism in Later Wittgenstein
Öz: İkinci dönem Wittgenstein’ın “mitolojik” ve soyut kural teorilerini ortadan kaldırmakta başarılı olup olmadığı hala tartışılagelen
bir konudur. Sorun mühimdir, zira kural takibi kavramı ile alakalı
olarak Wittgenstein’ın Platonik, idealist, konvansiyonalist, göreci
Wittgenstein’ın kapsamlı bir teori ortaya koymakta başarısız
olduğu ve hatta takip edilecek hiçbir kuralın mevcut olmadığı gibi
septik bir sonucuna vardığı uzun süredir iddia edilmektedir. Bu
makalede, kuralın uygulamasını belirleyen zorunlu şartları reddetse
dahi Wittgenstein’ın kural mevzusunda septik veya göreci olmadığını iddia etmeye çalışacağım. Bilakis Wittgenstein, pratik
temelli bir kural takibi kavramı geliştirir ve klasik nesnel yaklaşımları reddeder. Aslında o kural takibi kavramı ile felsefi
tartışmalardaki nesnellik/öznellik, toplum/birey ve zihin/beden gibi
temel bazı dikotomileri aşmak ister. Buna ilaveten bireyin kural
takibindeki rolünü ve dolayısıyla ahlaki sorumluluğunu vurgular.
Anahtar Kelimeler: Kural takibi, septisizm, normativite, kriter,
ahlaki sorumluluk.
Be y t u l h i k m e 6 ( 2 ) 2 0 1 6
Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy
ve hatta şüpheci görüşlere karşı duruşunu temellendirmektedir.