Principles and Practices in Ancient Greek and Chinese Science by
G. E. R. Lloyd
Aldershot, UK/Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2006. Pp. xvi + 302. ISBN
0--86078--993--4. Cloth $114.95
Reviewed by
Georgia L. Irby-Massie
College of William and Mary
[email protected]
Since the early 1960’s, G. E. R. Lloyd has been a leading figure in
advancing the study and understanding of the history of Greek science, in large part effecting the metamorphosis of the discipline from
the fragmented and narrow focus on modern categories of ‘science’
to a holistic investigation of inquiry into the natural world within
the cultural, social, economic, and political milieu: compare Cohen and Drabkin [1948], Sarton [1952], and Clagett [1957] who excluded fertile but ‘non-rational’ fields of study, including astrology—
based, in Mediterranean antiquity, on rigorous rules of mathematical
astronomy—and alchemy, whence the modern discipline of chemistry.
In recent years, Lloyd, casting his intellectual net even more broadly,
has undertaken comparative studies of scientific approaches, particularly Greek and Chinese, in various foci of intellectual inquiry, especially mathematics and medicine [see Lloyd 2004].
For Principles and Practices in Ancient Greek and Chinese Science, Lloyd undertook the daunting task of choosing 15 of the most
important or influential articles from the approximately 90 articles
which he has penned over the last 20 years. These 15 articles (dating
from 1987 to 2003) are now conveniently collected and easily accessible to students of Greco-Roman antiquity and the history of science.
Principles and Practices falls into three parts. Part 1 includes five
articles exploring the interpretation of Greek medicine. Part 2 includes six articles exploring technical questions in Greek science and
philosophy. In Part 3 (four articles), Lloyd uses comparativist approaches to inquire into issues that may not occur to the specialist
in a single area [ix]. Lloyd’s comparativist studies succeed not only
in emphasizing the themes developed in the first two sections of the
2007 Institute for Research in Classical Philosophy and Science
All rights reserved
ISSN 1549–4497 (online)
ISSN 1549–4470 (print)
ISSN 1549–4489 (CD-ROM)
Aestimatio 4 (2007) 13--28
C
14
Aestimatio
volume (and throughout his publishing career) but also in revealing
new questions. Several of the articles were originally delivered orally
[I, XI, XIII, XV], and this collection generally exudes a readable and
intimate conversational quality. The articles are presented here as
originally published (including the original pagination); a dagger (†)
appears in the margin where Lloyd has altered or augmented his text.
The author provides a supplementary bibliography of recent publications at the end of each section, per se a valuable tool. Each article
is numbered sequentially [I--XV], with that number reproduced on
each page. Citations to the volume in this review include this Roman
article number and an Arabic page number.
Principles and Practices is underpinned by three major themes
[ix--x]:
◦ a continuing preoccupation with disciplinary boundaries and how
that fixation hinders rather than furthers exploration, interpretation, and understanding [XV.197];
◦ the polemical nature of Hellenic society which prejudiced Greek
investigations into the natural world and shaped the interrelationships between teacher and student as well as between competing
schools; and
◦ the open-endedness and unpredictability of scientific research.
Complex intellectual and institutional factors contributed to the development of rational interpretations of the natural world. Close textual readings show that divergent approaches and conflicting results
occurred not only between cultures (Chinese and Greek), but also
within cultures 1 and even within philosophical frameworks. 2 There is
nothing predictable or inevitable about how an institution or discipline develops, and full appreciation can be gained only through combining social, cultural, political and abstract considerations [I.118,
XI.1, XII--XV]. It is from this holistic approach to the philosophy
and history of science that the collected articles derive their thematic cohesion. Interpretations based on modern values and expectations reveal only the biases of the interpreter and lead to no true
1
For example, competing Greek explanations of the physical nature of the
cosmos such as the Stoic plenum theory v. Epicurean ‘atomic’ theory.
2 Disagreements about causes and different interpretations are noted within
both the Hippocratic [I.117] and the Herophilean medical traditions [von
Staden 1989].
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
15
understanding. Lloyd’s approach to such an ambitious program is farreaching, but his method is always cautious, detailed, and meticulous;
and he is the first to admit to conjecture [e.g., VII.178, VIII.171]. He
draws extensively from the sources, both ancient and modern, and
his arguments never fail to be axiomatic, deductive, and rational,
with Euclidean precision.
In the first article, ‘The Transformations of Ancient Medicine’,
Lloyd explores the changes in our perception of ancient medicine and
shows how the shifting post-antique reception of Greek medicine in
fact parallels ancient approaches: even in antiquity there was a selection and distortion of medical texts. Lloyd traces the history of the
modern reception of ancient Greek medicine from the persistence of
the canonical authority of Hippocrates, 3 Aretaus, Galen, and Celsus
well after challenges to their expertise in anatomy, physiology, and
pathology had been successfully mounted [I.114], to the debunking
of that authority, and, finally, to a shift in recent inquiry regarding what cultural insights can be gleaned from the study of Greek
medicine with an aim to restoring ‘the wholeness and complexity of
Greek medicine’ [I.130]. Drawing from a wide range of medical and
philosophical evidence, Lloyd illustrates the heterogeneous scope and
aims of Greek ‘scientific’ (e.g., non-magical, non-ritualized) medicine.
Medicine in antiquity was not institutionalized and medical ‘schools’
in the modern sense were lacking. There was no unified approach,
theory, or understanding of the fundamentals or of the details within
the medical sects, much less between them: consider the conflicting
Hippocratic theories of humors [I.126] and the Herophilean articulations of pulse theory [von Staden 1989]. Rational disciplines in Hellenic Greece—and medicine was no exception—were influenced by
the paradigm of rhetoric and the ideal of citizen participation in government and politics. Plato had the sophist Gorgias [Gorgias 456b ff;
Lloyd 1979, 254; I.128] pride himself on his rhetorical skills which rendered him more persuasive on medical issues than even his brother,
a trained and practicing physician. Even Hippocratic treatises, including Precepts, Decorum, and On Diseases, advise practitioners on
how to debate with a patient, family member, or fellow-physician
3
Littré [1839–1861] was motivated by his own conviction of the contemporary
value of the Hippocratic corpus [I.114].
16
Aestimatio
[I.128]. A physician’s success was measured by his ability to convince patients and peers of his authority and of his claim to the right
answers via debate and dialogue [I.129--131].
Lloyd, who has long been interested in articulating the scope
of science in general and natural philosophy in particular [XV.195:
cf. Lloyd 2004, 33], takes up an ancient Greek debate on the precise
parameters of ‘medicine’, the investigation of which can do much
to elucidate how the original thinkers perceived and understood the
issues. The polemical nature of Greek intellectualism and the plurality of medical traditions gave rise to debates over the definition
of medicine, whether medicine constituted a rational discipline (skill
or τέχνη as opposed to luck, experience, or knack [II.259]), and who
had the authority to practice the medical τέχνη. These questions are
explored in the second article, ‘Definition, Status, and Methods of
the Medical Techne in the Fifth and Fourth Centuries’. It was the answers to these questions which distinguished physicians (ἰατροί) from
imposters, laymen, and midwives, who nonetheless served important
functions. 4 Lloyd’s scrutiny of three Hippocratic treatises (On the
Art, On Regimen in Acute Diseases, and On Ancient Medicine) reveals wide-ranging and conflicting views of the definition, aims, scope,
methodology, and limits of medicine and medical practitioners. The
author of On the Art expansively defines medicine as the complete
removal of suffering from illness and the ‘alleviation of violences of
diseases’, but nonetheless allows the physician to refuse to treat a
patient ‘where the disease has already won the mastery’ [I.253]. 5 To
the author of On the Art, medical τέχνη involves doing or not doing
something to effect a cure, even if a patient cures himself without
consulting an expert. The author of On Regimen in Acute Diseases
suggests that the debate is waged because of the incompetence of
some practitioners and disagreement among others [II.254--245]. 6 On
Ancient Medicine attests the conservative and traditional nature of
4
Although male physicians did oversee normal and abnormal births [[Hippocrates], De nat. mul. 1.34, De nat. puer. 30], a midwife was more likely
than a ἰατρός to attend at a birth [Dean-Jones 1994, 34--35, 212--213: cf.
Euripides Hipp. 293--296].
5 τέχνη cannot in all cases be expected to secure a cure; success proves the
power of the τέχνη, but failure does not belie its authority.
6 Interestingly, Lloyd points out the frustration noted even in the primary
sources over Greek medical pluralism.
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
17
the discipline. Its author attacks those who tried to apply ‘the newfangled method of postulates (ὑποθέσεις)’ to medical diagnosis as if
they were undermining the status of medicine as a τέχνη ‘since there
is no criterion to which one should refer to obtain clear knowledge’
[II.256], thereby oversimplifying the questions [IX.263] and reducing
the art to chance.
In article III, ‘Scholarship, Authority, and Argument in Galen’s
Quod Animi Mores’, Lloyd further explores the primary themes of the
first two articles: the effect of rhetoric in medicine and the aims and
definition of the art. In Quod animi mores, Galen inverted Gorgias’
argument to claim that a physician is in a better position than a
philosopher to make patients better and more intelligent: since the
soul follows the body, the physician can suggest changes in diet and
regimen to improve a patient’s character and intelligence—‘the best
doctor is also a philosopher’ [IX.260: Kühn 1821, 1.53--63]. 7 Galen
drew extensively, but selectively, from medical, philosophical, and
poetic sources. He simplified Plato’s arguments in support of his
own thesis on, for example, the nature of the soul and immortality
[III.19]; and he also misinterpreted or misapplied Aristotle on, e.g.,
the correlation between physical features and character or intelligence
[III.25--26]. Galen’s purpose in Quod animi mores, as was the aim
of the protreptic and apologetic Hippocratic treatises evaluated in
article II, was to advocate the importance and prestige of the medical
art as a τέχνη. Lloyd shows how Galen’s judicious and sometimes
distorted use of sources attests to the perceived and real connections
between the medical τέχνη, rhetoric, and philosophy.
Philosophy, modern as well as ancient, shares with medicine a
plurality of approaches and interests as well as a lack of consensus
on its definition, scope, and aims: definitions and understandings of
terminology were far from concrete [IV.262, IX.261, X.1]. Philosophers were admired by some, but reviled by others, e.g., the author
of On Ancient Medicine [X.3]. Medicine and philosophy, with their
7
See also van der Eijk 2005 for the circumvolutions of philosophy and medicine.
18
Aestimatio
own theoretical and practical agendas, developed sometimes conflicting, sometimes harmonious, epistemological models. Lloyd scrutinizes the interrelations and rivalries between medicine and philosophy more broadly in articles IX (‘Philosophy and Medicine in Ancient Greece’) and X (‘Pluralism of Intellectual Life Before Plato’).
As Galen relied upon the authority of Hippocrates of Cos, so too did
Plato have Socrates enlist Hippocrates as an ally [Phaedrus 270c] on
the connection between ethics, morality, and the study of nature and
the human body. Lloyd rightly points out the ambiguity in Plato’s
text: What precisely is meant by the study of ‘the whole nature’
[IX.258]? Like Lloyd, ancient thinkers pursued wide-ranging interests. Plato drew analogies between justice and health in opposition
to disorder and disease [Gorgias 504b--d: cf. Republic 564b--c], as Aristotle sketched analogies between health and morality [IX.259]; and
Galen argued that the ‘philosopher-doctor’ was in the best position to
help his patients physically, intellectually, and morally. Medical texts
are replete with discussions of language, nature, convention, cosmology, and elemental theories: the author of Airs, Waters, Places even
includes an ethnographic survey [X.5--6: cf. Herodotus, Hist. 3.106;
Strabo, Geog. 6.4.1]. Among the Greeks, specialists were rare, excepting Euclid, Euctemon probably, and Meton; and epistemological
approaches and explanations in all rational disciplines were pluralistic and heterogeneous [XV.199]. 8 Lloyd, while sceptically attempting
to define what constitutes philosophy before Plato, emphasizes that
Presocratic philosophers cannot be made to fit into artificial modern categories, that those thinkers whom we thus categorize hardly
shared a methodology or an interest in all the points which might
constitute philosophy (e.g., cosmology, the relationship between language and reality) [X.10], and that insight can be gained only through
caution and an appreciation for the complexity of their polymathic
interests [X.12].
The criticism of the application of ὑποθέσεις to medicine meted
by the author of the Hippocratic On Ancient Medicine [II.256] points
to an early connection between medicine and mathematics, and Lloyd
scrutinizes this link specifically in two articles chosen for Principles
and Practices. Galen prided himself on his mathematical training
8
For the extensive and flexible scope of Greek ‘scientific’ writers, see Rihll
1999, esp. 7, 89--90.
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
19
and applied its principals to his medical philosophy [IV--V]. In article IV, ‘Theories and Practices of Demonstration in Galen’, Lloyd explores Galen’s application of axiomatic-deductive reasoning to demonstrations in medicine. The strengths of such an approach are selfevident: it is orderly, systematic, and methodical; a clear logical
structure is demanded; and refutation must be guided by the application of logical analysis. This approach, however, is overly idealistic
[IV.264] and inappropriate to medicine [IV.276], which is hardly an
exact science. Galen certainly made no claim to conclusive knowledge, yet he repeatedly claimed that parts of medicine could be made
the subject of rigorous geometrical-style demonstrations [IV.274]. Galen recast empirical observations in a geometrical mold ‘with deductions stemming from starting points for which axiomatic indemonstrable status is claimed’ [IV.277]. Galen’s application of axiomaticdeductive reasoning was contentious and rhetorical; by appealing to
the prestige and incontrovertibility of his method, Galen sought to
establish his own authority [IV.273--274].
In articles V (‘Mathematics as a Model of Method in Galen’) and
VII (‘The Meno and the Mysteries of Mathematics’), Lloyd considers the status of mathematics, its connections to other rational fields
of inquiry, and how Galen [V] and Plato [VII] invoked mathematics to establish their éclat and persuade the audience of the truth
of their opinions, theories, and conclusions. Despite the difficulty
and unpopularity of mathematics amongst physicians, 9 Galen valued
the prestige and exactitude afforded by mathematically linked examples 10 and demonstrations, and so he used mathematics to persuade
his readers of his own expertise and incontestability. Like Galen,
Plato may have used mathematics for its prestige without fully understanding its complex nuances in Meno 86e--87b [VII]. 11 As the use
of mathematics in Galen may have served a non-mathematical purpose (to establish irrefutability), so Plato’s aim may have been one of
investiture. Plato under-described his hypothesis regarding whether
9
According to Galen, his readership considered mathematical explanations
obscure and unduly lengthy [V.113].
10 E.g., the geometrically informed explanation of the cone of vision: see On
the Usefulness of the Parts 10.12: V.124--125.
11 Gregory 2000 does not address this passage and assesses Plato’s geometry
only in the context of his astronomy, atomism, and ideals of philosophical
education.
20
Aestimatio
an ‘area can be stretched out as a triangle in this circle’, thus making
it unnecessarily obscure [VII.177--178] by withholding essential information [VII.180], in antithesis with orthodox Greek mathematical
practice wherein the teacher would logically and methodically lead
the student step-by-step through a proof until arriving at the conclusion by whose indisputability the student would be overwhelmed
[XIV.136]. Lloyd suggests that Plato’s geometrical obliquity may
have served a non-mathematical purpose, that of initiation: a guide
(Plato’s Socrates) attempts to facilitate a student’s (Meno’s) exploration of various possibilities of the problem’s resolution [VII.180].
Lloyd guardedly suggests that the obscurities of the mathematical
problem point to ‘the need of initiation—not, of course, into the
method but in the fields to which it is applied’ [VII.181]. The deliberate obscurity and Lloyd’s cautious suggestion of a context of
initiation bring to mind Pythagoreanism which has been connected
to Orphism, which was itself characterized by mystery and initiation
rites [Kerényi 1950; Kahn 2001, 19--22; Assmann 2002]. De Zwarte
[2004] argues intriguingly that in the Heraeum at Paestum, a temple
possibly created by the Pythagorean community and wherein there
seems to be embedded much mathematical knowledge, the placement
of at least three columns of the naos may have been selected for the
sake of (perhaps secret) mathematical wisdom, to which only members of the community would have had easy access. That is, the
columns may have been so placed for reasons other than aesthetics.
Worshippers of Hera at Paestum may have understood the mathematical implications of the temple under guidance similar to that which
Socrates attempts to proffer to the intractable Meno. Plato’s partially presented mathematical problem further bears some interesting
resemblance to Chinese educational dynamic (as well as Druidical, if
Caesar is to be believed: see Bell. gall. 6.14), wherein the student is
expected to memorize and internalize texts (often marked by rituals
of initiation in Chinese culture [XIV.136]) before coming to understand them, and then to conserve and transmit the corpus [XIII.162].
In article VI, ‘The Alleged Fallacy of Hippocrates of Chios’,
Lloyd evaluates an ancient debate about whether Hippocrates of
Chios engaged in paralogism in his quadrature of lunes. The debate underscores one of Lloyd’s underpinning themes: the desire to
establish incontrovertibility and to challenge the credibility of a rival.
As in article I [117--118], the question remains, ‘Who has the right to
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
21
speak with authority about “science”?’ Hippocrates’ original text is
long lost, and the argument and proof have been mediated through
Aristotle, Themistius, Eutocius, Eudemus, Alexander of Aphrodisias,
and Simplicius. Simplicius, Lloyd suggests, used the issue to undermine the credibility of his rival Alexander of Aphrodisias by representing him as having attributed a fallacy to the esteemed Hippocrates
[VI.12]. Lloyd’s methodically crafted examination of the language in
the extant evidence shows that Hippocrates must have made some unreconstructable rhetorical remark about his quadrature of the lunes
which subsequently misled Aristotle. Lloyd asks an important question on VI.118: To what extent does Simplicius offer ‘verbatim quotations from Eudemus’? This query raises a fundamental issue regarding the survival of scientific texts, here hinted at but not fully
explored. In essence, Lloyd asks, How reliably has Simplicius represented Eudemus’ original ideas? Although some scientific treatises
have been transmitted intact, many are distilled only through later
commentators and encyclopedists (e.g., Iamblichus and Simplicius).
The modern scholar is handicapped in working with later interpretations of scientific ideas rather than with the original formulations
of those ideas. 12 Simplicius’ presentation, eclectically compiled from
12
The problem arose early in the transmission of the texts: Plato and Aristotle
(both valuable sources for extracts and testimonia of earlier philosophers)
engaged in the exegesis of earlier natural philosophers, and Galen’s compendious corpus is an invaluable but selective and biased source of earlier medical theory and practice. Galen, for example, levels vicious attacks against
the Methodists, claiming that he had succeeded where they had failed, taking over their cases and exposing their murderous ignorance [De meth. med.
10.31--38, 162--173, 204--205, 316--357, 390--391]. Galen, furthermore, had
only secondhand access to many texts through Andromachus, Asclepiades,
Criton, and others. The fragmentary and piecemeal nature of scientific texts
brings to the fore even deeper problems , as Lloyd palpably demonstrates
in his cautious attempts at reconstructing the argument. Lack of textual
context and continuity (just as a lack of cultural and social context) lead
to tentative resolutions of philosophical problems, especially as regards the
particularly fragmentary survival of Presocratic texts whose disputed details
stimulate debate rather than engender resolution: this issue is particularly
brought to bear on Lloyd’s discussion of Empedocles’ ‘theory of evolution’
[XI.6--7]. Interestingly, though hardly surprisingly, the same problems are
noted in other traditions, including Chinese. In his investigation into the
cosmological and heterogeneously compiled Huainanzi [XXX.148--149, 153],
22
Aestimatio
remote sources, drew upon the authority of one source (Eudemus) to
undercut the influence of another (Alexander). Likewise, Galen selectively relied upon the authority of Hippocrates of Cos, Plato, and
Aristotle, although passages he cited from these authors and others
‘for support of his general thesis [did] not do so to the full extent he
requires nor in quite the way he represents’ [III.12, 18--31].
In Article VIII, ‘Plato and Archytas in the Seventh Letter’,
Lloyd delves into the debate of the authorship of that letter. Of the
letters attributed to Plato, the seventh is the most substantial and
most philosophical [VIII.159]; and, although inconsistencies and unPlatonic statements are evident [VIII.60], Platonic authorship should
not be discounted [VIII.171]. Lloyd conjecturally posits that a careful reading of the seventh letter reveals subtle criticisms of Archytas
as a mediator or interpreter of Plato’s philosophy to Dionysius II. A
close reading of the letter also undercuts the king’s claim to understand ‘the most important things’ (τὰ μέγιστα) [VIII.164, 168--169].
Despite (or perhaps because of) his professed enthusiasm for mathematics, Pythagoras, and Archytas, Plato may have viewed Archytas
as a rival, and so, eschewing the heavy-handed tactics observed in
Lloyd’s assessment of the use of the rhetorical arts by the medical
writers, he (if Plato is the author of Epist. 7) may have applied subtle
but persuasive language to secure ‘the independence and originality’
of his philosophy, thereby elevating his own status and weakening a
potential rival [VIII.172].
The need to understand ancient texts within their cultural context has remained one of the core themes in Lloyd’s considerable
scholarly corpus, and he commends, on the side of Hellenic studies,
recently fashionable scholarship on attitudes to and beliefs about the
human body (Greek assumptions are not the same as our own): ‘attitudes to the body often provide a key to much else in the belief
systems, the values, the cosmology, of the society in question’ [I.118].
Aristotle’s explanation of the existence and function of females—that
females are failed males because of their inability to concoct blood
[I.124: Lloyd 1983, 94--105, esp. 95n139]—brings to the fore Aristotelean (and Hellenic) gender biases. The cultural milieu is especially
Lloyd raises precisely the same problems noted in his discussion of the ‘Presocratic’ philosophers and the transmission of Hipparchus’ claim regarding
the quadrature of lunes.
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
23
important in the question of Greek theories of evolution, the topic
of article XI, ‘The Evolution of Evolution: Greco-Roman Antiquity
and the Origin of Species’. Lloyd sets the debate securely in the
ancient world, surveying the documentary evidence within the larger
philosophical dialogue about, e.g., coming-to-be and passing-away, 13
teleology, 14 and popular and traditional beliefs such as that in the
Minotaur. Xenophanes recognized substantial changes in the configuration of land and sea [Kirk, Raven, and Schofield 1983, §184], but
the extant fragments of his writings suggest no theory of the extinction of species or changes (‘evolution’) in species. Aristotle, in fact,
rejected the notion of the evolution of species [XI.11]. Investigations
into the natural world of animals and animal species were fueled
not exclusively by zoological interest but also by philosophical and
moral interests (especially in cases of Epicurus and Lucretius). The
ancient discussion was ‘not in anticipation of modern ideas’ [XI.1]
but was far different in scope, purpose, and resonance. The Greeks
adhered to no cosmological dogma (in contrast with the modern cultural backdrop of continuing debates on the merits of Darwinism) but
looked to the animal world for ethical and moral exempla. Lacking
in Greek antiquity were explosive population growth, the dogmatic
theory of creationism, and new information about the dissimilarities
between species and varieties which informed Darwin’s work [XI.14].
As tempting as it may be to interpret the charming tales in Xenophanes and Empedocles through a 21st-century filter, the conclusions
reached would reveal more about the intellectual biases of the modern
scholar than the philosophy of species developed by ancient thinkers.
Over the span of the past two decades, Lloyd has devoted much
of his substantial intellectual energy to questioning the comparisons
between scientific traditions, recognizing that no cross-cultural universals (or even scientific universals) exist. In the three comparative
articles [XII--XIV] chosen for the Ashgate collection, Lloyd applies a
multidisciplinary approach to explore the nexus between science, philosophy, tradition, and mythology, advancing his earlier researches
13
Even among proponents of an eternal versus a created cosmos there was a
wide acceptance of large scale cyclical change [XI.3].
14 Advanced by Aristotle, but denied by Epicurus as producing animals useless
and hostile to humans [XI.8--12].
24
Aestimatio
[Lloyd 1979, 1983, 1987]. He delves into variant aspects of intellectual approaches to unravel and note important cultural diversity in
the expectations about the nature of wisdom, the purpose of scientific
texts, how cultures thought about science and philosophy and used
various categories, and the very purpose of the act of philosophizing
within distinct cultures.
Lloyd explores how social and political constructs shape intellectual approaches in article XII, ‘Appearance vs Reality: Greek and
Chinese Comparisons and Contrasts’. All cultures recognize hidden
realities, but for the Greeks the question of seeming v. being played
a crucial role in the development of Greek philosophical thought
[XII.306--310]. An essential component of the Greek discussion was
the debate regarding change, that is, whether change—coming-to-be
or passing-away—is possible. Divergent conclusions of competing
schools and thinkers, working within the framework of the debate defined by the dichotomy between the intelligible and the perceptible,
were often agonistically motivated in the competition for prestige and
in attempts to persuade peers and students. Such pressures did not
exist within Chinese intellectual society, where the role of the philosopher was to transmit (not alter) the canon and the goal was to advise
benign rulers who provided the primary source of employment and
patronage [XII.314, XIV.133], which was antithetical to the independent and self-sustaining existence of the Hellenic Greek philosopher.
Within this social framework, Chinese philosophers, since their work
was addressed not to peers or potential students but rather to the
benign patron-ruler, felt no pressure to engage in polemic; and, although they questioned the difference between appearance and reality and acknowledged hidden forces [XII.311], Chinese scholars recognized no fundamental ontological dichotomy and posited no ultimate
truth that was acquired only through reason. The Chinese explained
physical, social, and moral change [eventually, XII.312], through the
workings of yin yang and they accounted for the five phases (wu xing)
as governing cycles of mutual change not dependent upon the sharp
contrast between reality and appearance [XII.315].
Likewise, as Lloyd shows in article XIII, ‘Mythology: Reflections from a Chinese Perspective’, the same cultural and political
phenomena—the Greek love of rhetoric and the competition for prestige, the Chinese favor of consensus and disdain for debate—explain
the absence of the dichotomy between mythic and rational accounts
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
25
(μύθος v. λόγος), so prevalent in Greek rational thought, in the Chinese understanding of cosmology. The cosmological Huainanzi includes etiological, empirical, mythical, and rational elements—‘an
extraordinary variety of material handled in a striking diversity of
ways’ [XIII.151--152] yielding a text which cannot be demarcated
into μύθος and λόγος but instead ‘quite simply presents itself as a
seamless whole’ [XIII.153]. Lloyd analyzes the Greek and Chinese
use of language and rhetoric to conclude that diverse technologies
of communication and linguistic idiosyncrasies themselves help to explain discrete intellectual approaches [XIV.133]. Similarly, cultural
and political factors (expectations of citizen participation), combined
with variant modes of writing and literacy (the Greek alphabetic
script), in part account for disparate mathematical and medical approaches. The axiomatic-deductive paradigm of Greek mathematics
begins with an indemonstrable premise, alphabetically building up a
diagram, as the student is led through a sequence of incontrovertible
steps, ending with an irrefutable conclusion [XIV.136]. The social
and political factors, as they affect Chinese intellectual institutions,
lack the dichotomy between perceptible and intelligible as well as
between μύθος and λόγος, further explaining the Chinese approach
to mathematics, which eschewed the axiomatic-deductive paradigm
in favor of consent, unity, and loyalty within the intellectual lineage
[XIV.136--138]. In China, ‘the negative models’ of ‘rhetorical debates’, so prevalent in Greek culture, were simply lacking [XIV.136].
In the last article of the collection (XV), ‘Is there a Future for
Ancient Science?”’ (his valedictory lecture marking his retirement
from teaching), Lloyd reflects on facets of both ancient and modern
rational inquiry, including how the study of ancient Greek science has
changed and how advances in modern science have been brought to
bear on the history and philosophy of science. E. R. Dodds’ seminal
The Greeks and the Irrational [1951] shifted the emphasis in classical
cultural studies away from ‘the triumph of Greek rationality’ and narrow inquiry, thereby encouraging the analysis of the whole culture.
Lloyd emphasizes the importance of examining both the successes
and failures of Greek science, philosophy, and culture as a means of
restoring the ‘the wholeness and complexity’ of Greek scientific pursuit [I.130, XV.197]. Comparativist studies reveal universal questions
raised by human thinkers (interest in the heavens, the nature and
health of the human body), but endemic cultural investigations into
26
Aestimatio
these same questions are inspired by assorted motives and yield contrastive explanations. The comparativist approach poses significant
demands, including the mastering of many (non-related) languages
and cultures [XV.208]; but, Lloyd argues, such an approach will be
most fruitful, as indicated by recent scholarship at Cambridge (and
elsewhere) in ancient science, which, though ‘not explicitly comparativist, had been animated by an awareness of alternative traditions’
[XV.208]. As Lloyd has rightly stated elsewhere [1991, 353], he reiterates the importance of inquiring into ancient science, the pursuit
of which far exceeds the technical details of mathematical, medical,
and philosophical explanations of the world: ‘For science in antiquity, read the ancient understanding of the world—and that takes you
straight to the heart of the values of the culture in question’ [XV.207].
The articles which Lloyd selected for Principles and Practices focus tightly on ancient texts and issues, but his interest in modern relevance [especially Lloyd 2004] does peep through on occasion. Specifically, he suggests that the modern physician can learn much from
the Hippocratic dialectical approach, which results in an open ended
discussion between physician and patient about health and disease
[I.32]. Epistemologically, Lloyd emphasizes that cognitive models
vary within and between cultures [IX.271--272], and that the pluralism of intellectual approaches reflects nothing less than the diversity
of human experience, as illustrated, for example, by anthropological studies into how human cultures classify animals, which habitat
stratum they occupy (air, forest canopy, and so forth), whether they
are domesticable, whether they are edible, and so on. [IX.266--268].
These queries have far-reaching implications for the philosophy of science as a whole in underscoring that there are no absolute answers
[IX.268--269].
It is clear that differences between Hellenic and Chinese culture resulted in divergent rational explanations of the natural world.
The same criteria of geographical location (e.g., Attica, and Ionia)
and variant political systems (e.g., democracy and aristocracy) could
perhaps be applied in scrutinizing differing Greek approaches to
philosophy, mathematics, medicine, and other rational disciplines.
Like Greek medicine, Greek cultural identity was hardly homogenous. The language, of course, was a unifying factor (although dialect and vocabulary varied regionally), and individual πόλεις worshipped many of the same gods and celebrated many of the same
GEORGIA L. IRBY-MASSIE
27
festivals (with local modifications). Nonetheless, there was no panHellenic political or philosophical concord, not even after Alexander.
It is agreed that certain social, cultural, and political factors were at
work to spark the scientific revolution in Ionia 15 Welcome would be a
study of geographical trends in Greek medicine and/or mathematics
to ascertain whether peculiar local factors (e.g., political, economic,
intellectual) affected the trends in the development of rational fields
of inquiry.
Principles and Practices in Ancient Greek and Chinese Science
is not a monograph, and this fact results in some minor inconsistencies. While most are carefully and thoroughly annotated, article
XI lacks citations (easily supplied by the advanced or talented intermediate student), and there are inevitable overlaps of evidence and
examples: Gorgias’ persuasiveness [I.128, II.252--253, X.7, XII.08,
XIV.131]; Plato’s attempt to educate Dionysius II [VIII.159--170,
172--173; XII.314; XIV.127]. Nonetheless, the volume is an invaluable collection, adhering to the mission of the Variorum Collected
Studies Series to bring together a ‘selection of articles by a leading
authority on a particular subject’ and to ‘make available research that
is scattered, even inaccessible in all but the largest and most specialized libraries’. The brief introduction is most helpful in establishing
the cohesiveness of the collection, and each essay follows from its predecessor. Lloyd’s treatment of manifold questions always engages the
reader, and each article rewards with insight and elucidation. The
anthology stands not only as a useful synopsis of recent trends and
discoveries in the history of Greek (and Chinese) science but also
as a testament to the continuing guidance and contributions to the
history of science and ideas by the indefatigable Geoffrey Lloyd.
bibliography
Assmann, J. 2002. ‘Pythagoras und Lucius. Zwei Formen „ägyptischer Mysterien“ ’. Pp. 58--75 in J. Assmann and M. Bommas
edd. Ägyptische Mysterien? Munich.
Cohen, M. R. and Drabkin, I. E. 1948. A Sourcebook in Greek Science. New York.
15
Graham 2006 is the most recent to affirm this.
Aestimatio
28
Clagett, M 1957. Greek Science in Antiquity. London.
De Zwarte, R. 2004. ‘Pythagoras’ Inheritance at Paestum in South
Italy: Number is the Substance of All Things’. Bulletin Antieke
Beschaving 79:41--50.
Dean-Jones, L. 1994. Women’s Bodies in Classical Greek Science.
Oxford.
Dodds, E. R. 1951. The Greeks and the Irrational.
Graham, D. W. 2006. Explaining the Cosmos: The Ionian Tradition
of Scientific Philosophy. Princeton.
Gregory, A. 2000. Plato’s Philosophy of Science. London.
Kahn, C. H. 2001. Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans: A Brief History. Indianapolis/Cambridge.
Kerényi K. 1950. Pythagoras und Orpheus. Zurich
Kirk, G. S., Raven, J. E., and Schofield, M. 1983. The Presocratic
Philosophers. 2nd edn. Cambridge.
Kühn, K. G. 1821. Claudii Galeni omnia opera. Leipzig.
Littré, E. 1839--1861. Oeuvres complètes d’Hippocrate. Paris.
Lloyd, G. E. R. 1979. Magic, Reason, and Experience. Cambridge
1983. Science, Folklore, and Ideology. Cambridge.
1987. The Revolutions of Wisdom. Cambridge.
1991. Methods and Problems in Greek Science. Cambridge.
2004. Ancient Worlds, Modern Reflections: Philosophical
Perspectives on Greek and Chinese Science and Culture. Oxford.
Rihll, T. E. 1999. Greek Science. Greece and Rome: New Surveys in
the Classics 29. Oxford.
Sarton, G. 1952. A History of Science: Ancient Science through the
Golden Age of Greece. Cambridge, MA.
van der Eijk, P. J. 2005. Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity. Cambridge.
von Staden, H. 1989. Herophilus. Cambridge.