DOI: 10.1111/jmcb.12664
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI
NOEMI NAVARRO
(In)Efficient Interbank Networks
We study the efficiency properties of the formation of an interbank network.
Banks face a trade-off by establishing connections in the interbank market.
On the one hand, banks improve the diversification of their liquidity risk
and therefore can obtain a higher expected payoff. On the other hand, banks
not sufficiently capitalized have risk-shifting incentives that expose them to
the risk of bankruptcy. Connecting to such risky banks negatively affects
expected payoff. We show that both the optimal and the decentralized networks are characterized by a core-periphery structure. The core is made
of the safe banks, whereas the periphery is populated by the risky banks.
Nevertheless, the two network structures coincide only if counterparty risk
is sufficiently low. Otherwise, the decentralized network is underconnected
as compared to the optimal one. Finally, we analyze mechanisms that can
avoid the formation of inefficient interbank networks.
JEL codes: D85, G21
Keywords: interbank network, core-periphery, liquidity coinsurance,
counterparty risk.
IT IS WELL ESTABLISHED THAT banks have incentives to form
bilateral lending relationships. The most intuitive reason is to coinsure future and
uncertain idiosyncratic liquidity shocks (Allen and Gale 2000, Freixas, Parigi, and
Rochet 2000). There is robust evidence that documents how interbank lending plays a
crucial role in providing liquidity insurance both in normal times (Furfine 2001, King
We thank Martin Brown, Sandro Brusco, Fabio Feriozzi, Jiro E. Kondo, Emanuela Sciubba, and Wolf
Wagner for helpful comments. We are also grateful to seminar participants at Bank of England, Universidad
Carlos III, Bank of Italy, 1st Swiss Conference on Banking and Financial Intermediation (Champery),
Society for Economic Dynamics (Boston), European Finance Association (Athens), and Association for
Public Economic Theory (Galway) annual meetings where an earlier version of this paper was presented.
The usual disclaimer applies. Castiglionesi acknowledges financial support from the Marie Curie Intra
European Fellowship and Navarro from the Spanish Ministry of Economics, grant ECO2014-53767P.
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI is at Tilburg University (E-mail:
[email protected]). NOEMI NAVARRO is at
Université de Bordeaux. (E-mail:
[email protected]).
Received July 5, 2018; and accepted in revised form April 29, 2019.
Journal of Money, Credit and Banking, Vol. 52, Nos. 2–3 (March–April 2020)
C 2019 The Authors. Journal of Money, Credit and Banking published by Wiley Periodicals,
Inc. on behalf of Ohio State University
This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License,
which permits use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work
is properly cited.
366
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
2008, Cocco, Gomes, and Martins 2009) and in times of crisis (Furfine 2002). The
overall amount of these bilateral links that banks establish forms what is generally
known as the interbank network.
The 2007/2008 financial crisis witnessed a prominent role played by the interbank
market in initiating and spreading the turmoil. This event prompted a surge of empirical evidence about the actual shape of the interbank network. Soromäki et al. (2007)
and Bech and Atalay (2010) find that the interbank networks formed by U.S. commercial banks is quite sparse. It consists of a core of highly connected banks, while
the remaining peripheral banks connect to the core banks. An almost identical feature
is found in interbank networks in countries like the UK, Canada, Japan, Austria, and
Germany (see, respectively, Boss et al. 2004, Inaoka et al. 2004, Embree and Roberts
2009, Craig and von Peter 2014, Langfield, Liu, and Ota 2014).
The aim of this paper is to establish under which conditions, if any, a core-periphery
interbank network may be optimal. We then study the decentralized endogenous
network formation game. That is, we investigate if banks have the right incentive
to mimic the optimal network and under which conditions this may occur. Overall,
the objective of the paper is to rationalize the stylized fact on the core-periphery
shape of the interbank networks, and to understand when such a structure may
entail inefficiencies.
We model an interbank network composed of several banks that anticipate how the
structure of the network affects their payoff. Participating in the interbank network
is beneficial because it allows banks to increase the expected payoff. We posit that
such expected payoff is increasing in the number of links that a bank establishes
in the network. The rationale behind this assumption is the ability of the interbank
network to reduce liquidity risk by coinsuring future idiosyncratic liquidity shocks.
The higher the number of connections in the network are, the higher the probability to
find coinsurance is, the less resources have to be invested in liquid low-return assets,
and the more resources can be invested in illiquid high-return investment projects
thus increasing depositors’ payoff (Castiglionesi, Feriozzi, and Lorenzoni 2019).
The benefit however has to take into account the potential cost of participating in the
interbank network. Such cost is captured by assuming that banks face a standard moral
hazard problem (Holmström and Tirole 1997). Each bank is financed by depositors
and shareholders. The former supply their funds and expect to break even, the latter
provide capital and decide the type of investment the bank chooses. Shareholders
have two types of investment projects in which they can invest the bank’s resources.
Although one project is risk-free, that is, it guarantees a certain return, the other project
is risky because it has the same payoff of the safe project if it succeeds but it delivers
nothing if it fails. The risky project however gives private benefits to the bank’s
shareholders, therefore it represents a gambling project from the depositors’ point of
view.1 Shareholders are protected by limited liability, so they find it convenient to
invest in the gambling project when the bank is poorly capitalized. We assume that a
1. Throughout the paper, we use the expressions risk-free and safe bank (or project) as synonymous.
Similarly for risky and gambling bank (or project).
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
367
bank, by establishing a link with banks that invest in the risky project, reduces the ex
ante probability of serving its own depositors. In particular, we assume that the higher
the ratio between the number of neighboring banks that invest in the risky project
over the total neighboring banks, the lower the probability to serve the depositors is.
We refer to the risk of making connections in the interbank network as counterparty
(or solvency) risk.
We analyze the trade-off of participating in an interbank market in which the benefit
of a reduced liquidity risk has to be weighted against the counterparty risk. First, we
characterize the optimal interbank network as the solution of the planner’s problem.
The planner can avoid the moral hazard problem in all banks only if a sufficient
amount of bank capital is available in the economy. In this case, the first-best network
is characterized by a fully connected structure. Otherwise, if bank capital in the
economy is scarce, the planner has to allow some banks to gamble and a constrained
first-best (CFB) network is obtained.
The presence of banks investing in the risky project implies that the CFB network
does not necessarily coincide with the fully connected one. Indeed, the CFB network is characterized by a core-periphery structure. The core includes all the banks
that invest in the safe project and form a complete network structure among themselves. The periphery includes all the gambling banks that can be connected among
themselves and/or with the core banks according to the parameters’ value. With an
additional assumption on the benefit of participating in the network, we are able to
fully characterize the conditions under which risky banks should or should not be
connected among themselves and with the core (safe) banks.
Second, we analyze the decentralized interbank network formation adopting the
equilibrium notion of pairwise stability. Also in this case a core-periphery structure
emerges as an equilibrium outcome. Nevertheless, the connectivity in the decentralized network does not necessarily coincide with the CFB network. We show
that the structure of the decentralized interbank network is the same as the CFB
one if the counterparty risk is sufficiently low. Otherwise, when the counterparty
risk is not low enough, the decentralized network does not coincide with the CFB
network. The reason is that the planner finds it optimal to link a safe bank with
a gambling bank when the expected losses of the former (because of counterparty
risk) are lower than the expected gains of the latter (represented by the higher expected payoff due to a higher liquidity coinsurance). However, these expected gains
are not internalized by the safe banks that severe the link with the gambling banks
even when this is not efficient. The decentralized network has an inefficiently low
degree of connectivity compared to the CFB network when counterparty risk is
sufficiently high.
Finally, we analyze possible mechanisms that could prevent the formation of inefficient networks. In particular, we allow for decentralized bank capital transfers
before the shareholders take the investment decision. Banks investing in the safe
project may find it convenient to transfer part of their bank capital to the neighboring gambling banks to change their investment decision and therefore to achieve
a higher expected payoff. We show that if the probability of success of the bank’s
368
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
risky project is sufficiently high, then banks do not have incentive to initiate any
bank capital transfer. More generally, we show that the decentralized network formation does not induce banks to form the CFB network also when bank capital
transfers occur.
The type of inefficiency that our model highlights likely arose during the 2007/2008
financial crisis, where banks feared losses in their counterparts. Our model predicts
that when the risk associated with the lending of funds is too high, connections become
too costly relative to their benefits and safe banks inefficiently sever their interbank
links. Nevertheless, our paper also stresses the fact that safer banks still have incentive
to maintain their links among each other. These predictions are supported by Afonso,
Kovner, and Schoar (2011) who find that interbank lending in the United States
decreased substantially during the 2007/2008 crisis but it did not freeze completely.
They find that riskier banks were cut off from the interbank market, whereas safer
banks would be still active.2 Moreover, consistent with our model, they show that the
interbank market stress was likely coupled with inefficient provision of liquidity to
the risky banks.
The reminder of the paper is organized as follows. As part of the Introduction, we
discuss the related literature. Section 1 sets up the model and then it posits the benefit
and cost of the interbank network and how they affect agents’ expected payoff.
Section 2 analyzes the planner’s problem, characterizing the constrained first-best
solution. Section 3 studies the decentralized network formation and its efficiency
properties. Section 4 concludes. The Appendix collects the proofs.
Literature Review
Our paper is inspired by the strand of literature that models contagion as the
outcome of links established by banks. In particular, banks are connected through
interbank deposits that are desirable ex ante, but the failure of one institution can
have negative effects on the institutions to which it is linked (Allen and Gale 2000,
Freixas, Parigi, and Rochet 2000, Brusco and Castiglionesi 2007). The common
feature of all these models is to assume an exogenous and very stylized interbank
network. The present model captures the features of the banking models such as
the benefits stemming from liquidity coinsurance (Allen and Gale 2000) and the
gambling behavior of low capitalized banks (Morrison and White 2005, Brusco and
Castiglionesi 2007), but it directly addresses the issues of the optimal design and the
decentralized formation of the interbank network.
Even if the theory of network formation has been successfully applied to several
economics fields, only recently there have been attempts to use such theory to understand the working of financial systems (see for a survey Allen and Babus 2009).
Among the first attempts, Leitner (2005) and Babus (2016) consider models of network formation, where banks form links in order to reduce the risk of contagion.
2. Note that theoretical explanations of the liquidity dry-up based on adverse selection arguments
predict that only the risky banks (i.e., the “lemons”) remain in the market (Malherbe 2014, Heider,
Hoerova, and Holthausen 2015).
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
369
These models rationalize the interbank network as an insurance mechanism. The
idea is that banks can be surprised by unexpected liquidity shocks that can make
bankrupt at least one bank in the system (like in Allen and Gale 2000). We provide
an alternative rationale for the existence of interbank networks that is based on banks
that fully anticipate the trade-off between the benefits and the costs of participating
in the network.
Similarly to us, Farboodi (2017) provides an analysis with the aim of rationalizing
the existence of a core-periphery banking network. She exogenously assumes two
types of banks: those that do not have any investment opportunity and those that may
have a good but risky investment opportunity. The interbank market is rationalized as a
tool that channels resources from the former banks to the latter banks. In equilibrium,
banks without the possibility to invest are on the periphery lending money to the
core banks that instead may have the risky investment opportunity. The core banks
that turn out to have the risky investment opportunity will then invest, and the core
banks that do not have such investment will intermediate between the safe periphery
banks and the risky core banks. In our model instead, the interbank market is viewed
as a tool that provides risk sharing (that is, liquidity coinsurance) among banks. In
our model, all banks invest and we endogenously determine the banks that either
invest in the safe project or the risky project. Banks that invest in the safe project are
part of the core because they provide the liquidity coinsurance service in the safest
way. Banks that invest in the risky project will be part of the periphery because their
provision of liquidity coinsurance is not safe. This is the reason of the two diametric
results between her and our model.
A related fast-growing literature studies the propagation of negative shocks in
financial networks. Contrary to our approach, this literature takes the structure of
the network as given (Caballero and Simsek 2013, Elliott, Golub, and Jackson 2014,
Acemoglu, Ozdaglar, and Tahbaz-Salehi 2015, Castiglionesi and Eboli 2018). A
different approach is taken by Acemoglu, Ozdaglar, and Tahbaz-Salehi (2014) and
Zawadowsky (2013) who analyze the strategic link formation among banks located
however on a given network shaped as a ring. Although the former paper predicts
that the equilibrium network can exhibit both under- and overconnection, the latter
provides a rationale for underinsurance. Allen, Babus, and Carletti (2012) analyze the
interaction between financial connections due to overlapping portfolio exposure and
systemic risk. Cabrales, Gottardi, and Vega-Redondo (2016) investigate the optimal
properties of a network of firms that trade-off risk sharing and risk of contagion.
They find that when big shocks have low probability to occur, the complete network
with uniform exposure among firms is the optimal one. When the likelihood of big
shocks is large enough, it is optimal to severe links and to form disjoint components.
Core-periphery structures are never optimal. However, they consider firms either
with homogenous risk-return characteristics or heterogenous characteristics but only
with respect to risk. We instead consider banks with heterogenous expected returns
due to the presence of moral hazard. This turns out to be the main reason for the
core-periphery structure to emerge both as the optimal and decentralized network.
370
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
1. THE MODEL
There are three dates t = 0, 1, 2 and one divisible good called “dollars” ($). The
economy is divided into n regional banks, and let N = {1, 2, . . . , n} be the set of
such banks. Each regional bank has the same (large) amount of depositors that
consume at t = 2. Depositors have to deposit at t = 0 in their regional bank to access
the investment opportunities of the economy. The endowment of deposits received
at t = 0 is normalized to 1$ in each regional bank. Besides deposits, banks are
funded also through capital. Each regional bank i randomly receives an endowment
ei ∈ [0, e] of dollars, which represents the bank capital and it is owned by the bank’s
shareholders. The vector e = (e1 , e2 , . . . , en ) represents the realization of the bank
capital endowments. The pair (N , e) is called an economy.
Let K i ⊆ N be the set of banks to whom bank i is directly linked, then the
number of banks connected to bank i is ki ∈ {0, 1, . . . , n − 1}. The vector K =
(K 1 , K 2 , . . . , K n ) captures the interdependence among the banks, and it represents
the interbank network. We restrict ourselves to undirected networks, that is bank i is
related to bank j if and only if bank j is related to bank i. Let K denote the set of all
possible interbank networks for a given economy (N , e) .
We also allow for transfers of bank capital across neighboring banks. Let xi =
ei + ti be the bank capital for bank i ∈ N after transfers have been made (i.e.,
ti is the transfer and can be positive or negative). A vector of bank capitals x =
. . , xn ) is called
(x1 , x2 , .
feasible for a given economy (N , e) if (i) xi ≥ 0 for all i,
and (ii) i∈N xi = i∈N ei . Let X denote the set of all feasible vectors of bank
capital for a given economy (N , e).
After the transfers are made, each bank i has 1 + xi dollars to invest. Banks may
choose to invest between two types of project that mature in t = 2:
(i) The risk-free, or safe, project r f with an expected return of R > 1 dollars per
dollar invested.
(ii) The risky, or “gambling,” project r that yields an expected return of R > 1
dollars with probability ξ , and 0 dollars with probability (1 − ξ ) per dollar
invested. This type of project yields also a private benefit B > 0 to bank’s
shareholders. Private benefits are realized at the moment of the investment (so
they do not have dollar value, consider them as perks or investment in family
business).
We refer to si ∈ {r f, r } as the project’s choice of bank i at t = 1 . The vector s
denotes the investment strategy profile, that is, s = {si }i∈N . Let S denote the set of
all possible investment profiles for a given economy (N , e). The sequence of events
is reported in Table 1.
The timing represents the interbank network formation game. In t = 0, once bank
capitals are realized, the banks choose the network structure. In t = 1, bank capital
transfers are made and the shareholders choose the type of project. Accordingly, the
expected payoff in t = 2 will depend on the structure of the financial network chosen
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
371
TABLE 1
SEQUENCE OF EVENTS
Time
Events
t=0
t=1
t=2
Bank’s capital is realized and interbank network is chosen.
Bank’s capital transfers are made and projects are chosen.
Projects cash flows are realized and depositors are paid.
in t = 0 and on the type of project chosen by the banks in t = 1. The timing captures
the fact that bank decisions about which interbank link to establish are long term,
while the type of the investment is a decision with shorter time horizon.
1.1 Interbank Network: Benefit, Cost, and Expected Payoffs
In order to model the benefit and cost of establishing connections in the interbank
market, we assume the following. On the one hand, establishing interbank lending
relationships is beneficial because it allows banks to coinsure small idiosyncratic
liquidity shocks that can hit the investment project before it matures. Such liquidity
shocks can be smoothed out by holding a liquidity buffer and therefore do not
jeopardize the survival of the bank. On the other hand, the cost of linking is given by
the failure of the gambling project that represents a big shock that cannot be insured.
Therefore, it may affect the survival also of the connected banks.
The benefit: liquidity coinsurance. We assume that the benefit of the interbank network is to increase the expected payoff that bank i can obtain by investing its resources
1 + xi . Let us indicate with i the expected payoff that bank i obtains for each unit
of investment conditional on its survival, and with R the return that bank i reaches
when it has no interbank connections. We posit that
i = f (ki )R
with f (ki ) increasing in ki . We assume that f (0) = 1, that is, if bank i has no
interbank connections (ki = 0), then it gets the lowest return R ∈ (1, R) for each unit
of investment. The return R can be interpreted as the “regional” (or autarky) return
that bank i obtains if it has no links with any other bank. On the other extreme, if bank
i is linked to all the other regional banks (ki = n − 1), we assume f (n − 1) = R/R.
That is, bank i gets the highest return R that can be regarded as the “global” return.
For simplicity, we assume an upper bound on R given by 2R ≥ R > R. By defining
R/R ≡ ρ, we have f (ki ) ∈ [1, ρ] , with ρ ≤ 2.
The modeling choice of f (ki ) captures that, all else equal, the higher the number
of neighboring banks ki is, the higher the bank i’s ex ante probability to find a
suitable counterparty. This reduces the liquidity risk that bank i is facing, allowing
372
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
it to obtain, conditional on its survival, a higher return.3 Among the many, one
possible interpretation of our assumption is provided by Castiglionesi, Feriozzi, and
Lorenzoni (2019). They show that a higher ex ante probability of finding coinsurance
in the interbank market reduces the liquidity buffer that banks hold, allowing them
to invest a higher amount of resources in illiquid and more profitable projects. When
ki = 0, bank i is therefore bearing fully the idiosyncratic liquidity risk with its own
liquidity buffer. When the number of linked banks increases, bank i can coinsure the
idiosyncratic liquidity risk with other regional banks and its liquidity buffer decreases.
In this paper, we abstract from analyzing banks’ liquidity holding, and we take as
given the positive relationship between the ex ante liquidity insurance provided by
the interbank network and the expected payoff.
The cost: counterparty (solvency) risk. The cost of belonging to an interbank network
is represented by the exposure to counterparty (or solvency) risk that determines the
bank’s survival. A bank indeed may end up lending money to a neighboring bank
that is actually investing in the risky project. Only if the risky project succeeds, the
risky bank is able to pay back the borrowed money. Otherwise, the lending bank is
negatively affected by the default of the gambling neighboring bank and it may not
serve its depositors either. We capture this solvency risk by assuming that the higher
the number of risky banks among the neighboring banks ki is (i.e., the higher the
bank i’s probability ending up lending to one or more risky bank), the lower the
probability bank i will serve its depositors. Although before we abstract from banks
liquidity holding, here we abstract from the amount of liquidity exchanged in the
interbank network.
Formally, let pi (K , s) be the probability that bank i survives. Let gi ∈ [0, ki ] denote
the number of gambling neighbors of bank i. Then the probability pi (K , s) is defined
as
gi
η ki
if si = r f,
gi
pi (K , s) =
(1)
ξ η ki otherwise.
When bank i and all its neighbors are investing in the risk-free project (i.e., si = r f
and gi = 0), then bank i serves its depositors with pi (K , s) = 1. In this case, no matter
which bank (or banks) will lend money to, bank i will be paid back and then surely
serve its depositors. If instead gi > 0, bank i will serve its depositors with probability
gi
less than 1, namely pi (K , s) = η ki . There is now a possibility that bank i will lend to
one (or more) of the gi banks that cannot repay after borrowing money. This would
spill over to bank i, reducing its ex ante probability of being able to serve its own
depositors.4 The worse case is when all bank i’s neighboring banks invest in the
3. In more abstract settings, Bloch, Genicot, and Ray (2008) and Bramoullé and Kranton (2007) offer
strategic analyses of informal coinsurance in networks. They characterize bilateral agreements that provide
coinsurance against income risk. We can interpret these works as microfoundation of the function f (k).
4. Our assumption allows us to analyze the contagious effect of the direct links that connect banks,
ruling out indirect contagion and systemic effects. Our results point out that the only presence of
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
373
risky project (i.e., gi = ki ). In this case, counterparty risk is maximal; therefore, the
probability of bank i to serve its depositors is minimal and equal to η. The parameter
η then captures, all else equal, the exposure to counterparty risk: the higher the η,
the lower the counterparty risk is.5 Finally, note that counterparty risk represents a
conditional probability (i.e., the bank that invests in the gambling project has to fail
and the bank linked to it has to be a lender of the failing bank). It is then natural to
assume η > ξ .
Expected payoffs and the choice of the investment project. Depositors in bank i
invest one dollar in the bank and perfectly anticipate the bank’s risk. Then the deposit
contract that allows depositors to break even has to promise an amount equal to
Di =
1
≥1
pi (K , s)
(2)
and the depositors’ expected payoff Mi (K , s) is
Mi (K , s) = pi (K , s)Di = 1.
Shareholders in bank i are residual claimant and are protected by limited liability.6
Accordingly, they expect the following payoff
m i (K , xi , s) =
pi (K , s)[(1 + xi ) f (ki )R − Di ]
pi (K , s)[(1 + xi ) f (ki )R − Di ] + B
if si = r f,
otherwise.
Considering the expressions for Di in (2) and for pi (K , s) in (1), we have
gi
η ki (1 + xi ) f (ki )Rxi − 1
gi
m i (K , xi , s) =
ξ η ki (1 + xi ) f (ki )Rxi − 1 + B
if si = r f,
otherwise.
(3)
Shareholders decide in which type of project to invest. Therefore, for given f (ki ) and
s−i , shareholders in bank i invest in the safe project if and only if
gi
gi
η ki (1 + xi ) f (ki )Rxi − 1 ≥ ξ η ki (1 + xi ) f (ki )Rxi − 1 + B,
“one-step” contagion is able to generate inefficient networks. Most likely, systemic effects would magnify
the inefficiencies present in our analysis.
5. The assumed monotonicity of pi (K , s) implies that solvency shocks are not perfectly correlated.
That is, risky banks default in different states of the world. If solvency shocks would be perfectly correlated
(i.e., risky banks fail together in the same state of the world), then we would have pi (K , s) = ξ if si = r .
That is, adding a risky bank does not affect bank i’s probability of default. Such alternative assumption
would undermine the core-periphery result because it would make it convenient to link all gambling banks.
6. All the results of the paper are independent of how the bank’s profits are shared between shareholders
and depositors. This fact implies that our model could be relevant also to contexts where institutions
operating in the network have different profit sharing rules and similar benefits and costs in establishing
links. Indeed the core-periphery structure is not an exclusive feature of the interbank market, but it is
observed also in other market as well (for example, how inter dealers are positioned in OTC markets).
374
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
which implies
B
xi ≥
(1 − ξ )η
gi
ki
− 1 ≡ I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η).
f (ki )R
Accordingly, banks with sufficiently high level of bank capital have incentive to invest
in the risk-free project, whereas relatively low capitalized banks find it convenient
to invest in the risky project. The threshold I ∗ is strictly positive whenever B is
sufficiently high.
Note that two banks i and j having the same amount of capital xi = x j = x̄ could
invest in different projects. Assume
B
(1 − ξ )η
gi
ki
B
− 1 ≤ x̄ <
f (ki )R
gj
− 1,
(1 − ξ )η k j f (k j )R
then shareholders in bank i choose the safe investment, whereas shareholders in
bank j choose the risky investment. The previous inequality necessarily implies
g /k
η g j /k j f (k j ) < η i i f (ki ). This can occur either when bank i has more connections
than bank j with the same proportion of risky counterparties, or when banks i and
j have the same number of connections but bank i has fewer risky counterparties.
What cannot occur is that bank j has more connections and a smaller proportion of
risky counterparties than bank i.
2. CONSTRAINED FIRST-BEST INTERBANK NETWORK
Let us define an allocation as a vector (K , x, s), where x ∈ X , K ∈ K and s ∈ S.
An allocation (K , x, s) is an investment Nash equilibrium (INE) for a given economy
(N , e), with x = (xi )i∈N , if
m i (K , xi , s) ≥ m i (K , xi , (s−i , s̃i ))
for all i ∈ N ,
with s̃i ∈ {r f, r }. That is, an allocation is an INE for a given economy if taking the
financial network and capital as given there are no unilateral profitable deviations in
the shareholders’ choice of the investment project. Note that an allocation (K , x, s)
is an INE for a given economy if and only if for all i ∈ N
rf
si =
r
if xi ≥ I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η),
otherwise.
The constrained first-best solution is characterized by the social planner problem,
which objective function is to maximize the expected return of the agents in the
economy (i.e., depositors and shareholders). We assume that the planner is able to
(i) transfer the initial endowments of capital across banks, (ii) fix a financial network
and (iii) suggest to the shareholders of each bank the type of project to invest in.
Formally, the planner’s problem is as follows.
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
375
DEFINITION 1. Given an economy (N , e), an allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is a constrained
first-best (CFB) allocation if it maximizes
(4)
[Mi (K , s) + m i (K , xi , s)]
i∈N
subject to
xi ≥ 0
for all i ∈ N ,
(5)
(6)
xi =
i∈N
si =
rf
r
ei ≡ E,
i∈N
if xi ≥ I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η)
otherwise,
(7)
for all i ∈ N ,
m i (K , x, s) ≥ max{R(ei + 1) − 1, ξ R(ei + 1) + B − 1}
for all i ∈ N ,
(8)
The planner cannot assign a negative amount of capital to each bank (feasibility
constraint 5), and she can only reallocate by means of transfering the total amount
of bank capital E in the economy (feasibility constraint 6). We allow shareholders to unilaterally deviate from the planner’s investment suggestion, therefore the
incentive constraint (7) restricts the social planner problem in a way that moral hazard has to be taken into account. Finally, we impose the shareholders’ participation
constraint (8).7
First, note that if B ≤ (1 − ξ )ρ R, then the solution to the planner’s problem is the
first best. That is, the planner successfully proposes the shareholders in each bank to
connect to any other bank in the interbank network (k = n − 1) and to invest in the
risk-free project (g = 0). This is achieved without any reallocation of bank capital.
Choosing the risk-free project is indeed an INE given the complete and safe network
as the threshold I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η) is negative. Banks obtain a higher expected payoff
with the first-best network proposed by the planner than in autarky. By the same
reasoning, the planner achieves the first best if min ei ≥ I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η), whenever
B > (1 − ξ )ρ R (so that I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η) > 0).
Therefore, the CFB can be obtained when B > (1 − ξ )ρ R and min ei < I ∗ (n −
1, 0, ξ, η). Note that when the condition min ei < I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η) is satisfied, then
also the condition B > (1 − ξ )ρ R is satisfied. Let us define the following two thresholds for the total amount of bank capital E:
n−1 ∗
∗
I (0, 0, ξ, η) − n, n I (n − 1, 0, ξ, η)
E = max
ρ−1
and
E = I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η) =
B
− 1 < E.
(1 − ξ )ρ R
We have the following result.
7. Recall that depositors break even in expectation, so their participation constraint is satisfied.
376
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
PROPOSITION 1. A CFB allocation always exists. Assume min ei < E. Then: (i) if
E ≥ E, then any CFB yields a unique network structure K ∗ such that K i∗ = N \{i}
for all i and a unique strategy profile s ∗ such that si∗ = r f for all i; (ii) if E < E,
then any CFB yields a unique strategy profile s ∗ with si∗ = r for all i, and a unique
structure K ∗ such that either K i∗ = N \{i} for all i, if η ≥ 1/ρ, or K i∗ = ∅, otherwise.
The proof is in the Appendix. The existence of a CFB is guaranteed even if the
constraints in the planner’s problem do not define a compact set on R n because
of constraint (7). Nevertheless, by modifying the planner’s problem such that the
constraints define a compact set on R n , the solution to the modified maximization
problem exists and it turns out to be also the solution of the planner’s problem.
Proposition 1 also establishes the amount of total bank capital E that is needed to
achieve the first best. That is, all the banks in the interbank network are connected
and invest in the risk-free project. The intuition for this result is quite simple: when
total bank capital is sufficiently high the planner can achieve the first best avoiding
the moral hazard problem and satisfying shareholders participation constraint. On
the other extreme case, when E < E, the total bank capital is not enough to avoid
the risky project even in one single bank. The planner therefore cannot induce any
bank to invest in the safe project. In this case, either it is optimal to connect all the
gambling banks (when the counterparty risk is sufficiently low, i.e., when η ≥ 1/ρ)
or disconnect all the banks getting the empty interbank network.
The following proposition establishes the shape of the CFB network when total
bank capital E is such that E ≤ E < E . It turns out that the CFB network is
characterized by a core-periphery structure. The core is made of banks that invest in
the safe project and are all connected to each other. The periphery banks choose the
gambling project and they can eventually be connected to some core banks and/or
some periphery.
PROPOSITION 2. Assume min ei < E ≤ E < E. Let (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) be a CFB for a given
economy (N , e). Then, for every pair of banks i and j such that si∗ = s ∗j = r f we
have that i ∈ K ∗j and j ∈ K i∗ .
The proof is in the Appendix. The intuition behind the optimality of the coreperiphery structure is as follows. When two banks are investing in the risk-free
project, it is always better to have them connected than not connected. This is true
because one more neighbor increases the possibility of liquidity coinsurance and
therefore the expected payoff. Such additional link does not induce any bank to
switch investment decision from the risk-free to the gambling project. Indeed, if a
bank has enough bank capital to choose the safe project in a given interbank network
and it prefers this allocation to autarky, then the same bank capital will be sufficient
to avoid the gambling behavior if the bank has one more neighbor that invests in the
risk-free project.
The next proposition determines the size of the core in a CFB network. Given an
allocation (K , x, s), we denote by C(K , x, s) the set of banks that choose the risk-free
project. Note that if (K , x) is equal to (∅, e), then all the banks are in autarky. It is
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
377
easy to verify that there is a unique INE in autarky, denoted (∅, e, s A ), such that for
any bank i
B
− 1,
r f if ei ≥ (1−ξ
)R
(9)
siA =
r
otherwise.
PROPOSITION 3. Assume min ei < E ≤ E < E. Let (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) be a CFB for a given
economy (N , e). Then, C(∅, e, s A ) ⊆ C(K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ). That is, the size of the core in a
CFB network can only increase as compared to the number of safe banks in autarky.
Moreover, the core in a CFB network includes the banks that invest in the risk-free
project in autarky.
The proof is in the Appendix. The intuition is as follows. A bank that invests
in the safe project in autarky is a bank with a relatively high initial endowment of
bank capital. But the higher the initial endowment of bank capital, the higher the
capital the planner has to allocate to satisfy the shareholders’ participation constraint
of that bank. Precisely, the minimum bank capital the planner has to offer to make
shareholders participate in the optimal network is sufficiently high to induce them to
choose the safe project in an INE for that network. Because the optimal allocation
must be an INE, Proposition 3 follows.
We determine now the number of optimal links that each bank should have in the
core-periphery CFB network. This number will depend on the relationship between
the benefit, captured by the function f (k), and the cost, represented by the counterparty risk η, of participating in the interbank network. The following assumption
guarantees that the function f (k) satisfies the increasing power ratios (IPR) property.
ASSUMPTION (IPR property). The function f (k) satisfies the IPR property if the
i)
expression ( f (kf (ki +1)
)ki +1 is increasing in ki .
Under the assumption of the IPR property,8 the relationship between f (k) and η
can be parameterized in terms of a number k(η) that is defined as follows
⎧
0
if η < f 1(1) ,
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
k∗
k ∗ +1
∗
∗
⎪
)
⎨ k∗
if f (kf (k−1)
≤ η < f (kf (k∗ +1)
∗)
k(η) =
(10)
⎪
for some k ∗ ∈ (0, n − 1),
⎪
⎪
n−1
⎪
⎪
⎩n − 1 if η ≥ f (n−2)
.
f (n−1)
To understand the meaning of the number k(η), suppose that shareholders in bank
i know that there are k − 1 safe banks. Establishing links to those safe banks is
beneficial because there is no counterparty risk. However, when is it beneficial to
connect to a kth risky bank? The answer is positive, all else equal, if and only if the
expected payoff obtained from connecting to ki = k banks (with gi = 1) is greater
8. An increasing function like f (k) satisfies the IPR property whenever it is also concave (i.e.,
f ′′ (k) < 0), f ′′′ (k) > 0, and f ′ (0) is sufficiently high (result upon request). It is interesting to note that
simple concave functions, like f (k) = 1 + ln(k + 1) or f (k) = 1 + exp{A − k1 } with A > 0, satisfy the
IPR property.
378
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
than (or equal to) the expected payoff of connecting to ki = k − 1 safe banks (i.e.,
gi = 0). This is equivalent to
1
0
η k f (k)R ≥ η k−1 f (k − 1)R,
which implies
η≥
f (k − 1)
f (k)
k
.
i)
)k , then η ≥ ( f (kf (ki +1)
)ki +1 for
When f (k) satisfies the IPR property and η ≥ ( f (k−1)
f (k)
any ki ≤ k − 1. That is, the shareholders are willing to connect to an additional kth
risky bank if they are connected to at most k(η) − 1 safe banks. Instead, when f (k)
f (k) k+1
i)
) , then η < ( f (kf (ki +1)
)ki +1 for any ki ≥ k .
satisfies the IPR property and η < ( f (k+1)
That is, shareholders are not willing to connect to an additional kth risky bank if they
are connected to at least k(η) safe banks.9
The next proposition characterizes the number of optimal links in the CFB network.
PROPOSITION 4. Assume that min ei < E ≤ E < E and that f (k) satisfies the IPR
property. Let (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) be a CFB allocation for a given economy (N , e), and k(η)
be as defined in (10). Then
(i) If k(η) = n − 1, then K i∗ = N \{i} for all i ∈ N .
(ii) If k(η) = 0, then gi∗ = 0 for all i such that si∗ = r .
In the Appendix, we provide the proof of a longer version of Proposition 4 where
results regarding the intermediate values of k(η) are also included. Statement 1
establishes that the CFB network is the complete network structure in which all
banks are connected if η ≥ ( ff (n−2)
)n−1 . The intuition is that when counterparty risk
(n−1)
is small with respect to the benefits provided by the interbank network, connecting
until the last gambling bank in the network increases the total expected payoff.
Statement 2 determines that when η < f 1(1) the CFB network is characterized by
a sparse periphery in which the gambling banks are disconnected among them. In
this case, counterparty risk is sufficiently high that it is not optimal to link two
gambling banks.
For intermediate values of k(η), we show, among other results, that at most one
bank can hold less than k(η) connections in a CFB network. Indeed, if there were at
least two banks holding less than k(η) links, the total expected payoff is increased by
connecting two such banks. Moreover, periphery banks that hold more than k(η) links
cannot be directly connected. That is, holding more than k(η) connections reduces
the expected payoff if the banks who hold more than k(η) connections are investing
in the risky project. Severing their connections then increases the expected payoff.
9. The threshold k(η) captures the nonmonotonic relationship between interconnectedness and individual and systemic risk found in recent theoretical literature. Establishing new connections is beneficial at
the individual and global level when the number of connections in the network is low, while it is harming
otherwise (Wagner 2011, Acemoglu, Ozdaglar, and Tahbaz-Salehi 2015).
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
379
Note that according to Statement 2 of Proposition 4 the planner may still find it
optimal to link a gambling bank to a safe bank. The following Proposition establishes
a sufficient condition under which the CFB network has an empty periphery, that is
gambling banks are disconnected also from safe banks.
PROPOSITION 5. Assume that min ei < E ≤ E < E and that f (k) satisfies the
IPR property. Let (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) be a CFB for a given economy (N , e). Then, if
1−ξ
)n−1 , then K i∗ = ∅ for all i with si∗ = r .
η < ( ρ[1+nρ]
The proof is in the Appendix. The intuition is as follows. The planner finds it
optimal to connect a gambling bank with a safe bank if the expected benefit for the
former are high enough to outweigh the counterparty risk faced by the latter. At some
point, counterparty risk becomes so high that the expected benefit for the gambling
bank does not outweigh the risk taken by the safe bank.10
3. DECENTRALIZED INTERBANK NETWORK
In this section, we study the decentralized interbank network formation. We assume first that bank capital transfers are not allowed at t = 1. Characterizing the
efficiency properties without transfers makes it easier to analyze the effects of bank
capital transfers.
3.1 Decentralized Interbank Networks without Transfers
We define an economy without transfers (N , e) in which the sequence of events in
Table 1 does not include bank capital transfers across banks in t = 1. We solve the
model backward. Banks choose the network structure given their initial endowment
of bank capital, anticipating the INE played in that network. For a given economy
(N , e), an allocation without transfers (K , e, s) is an INE if there are no unilateral
profitable deviations in the type of project in which the shareholders invest.
Without bank capital transfers the network formation game is basically a static one,
that is banks choose simultaneously to whom they want to connect. Accordingly, we
adopt the equilibrium notion of pairwise stability introduced by Jackson and Wolinsky
(1996).11 Given a network K , let K ∪ i j denote the network resulting from adding
a link joining banks i and j to the existing network K . On the contrary, for any two
10. The condition in Proposition 5 is more stringent than the condition η <
(statement 2). We have:
1−ξ
ρ[1 + nρ]
n−1
<
1−ξ
ρ[1 + nρ]
<
1
f (1)
in Proposition 4
1
1
< 1,
<
ρ[1 + nρ]
f (1)
given that 1 > ξ > 0, n > 2 and 1 < f (1) < ρ.
11. Using the stronger equilibrium notion of pairwise-Nash stability (Block and Jackson 2006, Calvo
and Ilkilic 2009), the results, available upon request, remain qualitatively the same.
380
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
banks i and j connected in K , let K \i j denote the resulting network from severing
the link joining banks i and j from K .
DEFINITION 2. An allocation without transfers (K , e, s) is pairwise stable (PSWT) if
the following holds:
(i) For all i and j directly connected in K , m i (K , e, s) ≥ m i (K \i j, e, s̃) and
m j (K , e, s) ≥ m j (K \i j, e, s̃) for all allocations (K \i j, e, s̃) that are INE.
(ii) For all i and j not directly connected in K , if there is an INE (K ∪ i j, e, s̃) such
that m i (K , e, s) < m i (K ∪ i j, e, s̃) , then m j (K , e, s) > m j (K ∪ i j, e, s̃).
The definition of PSWT captures two ideas. The first refers to the network’s
internal stability: no pair of banks directly connected in the current interbank network
individually gain from severing their link. This implies that any of the two banks could
sever the link unilaterally. The second establishes the network external stability: if
one bank could gain from creating a link with another bank, it has to be that the other
bank cannot gain from that link. This implies that both banks have to agree in order
to create a link. Note that if one bank strictly gains with the creation of one link and
the other bank is indifferent, it is assumed that the link is formed.
DEFINITION 3. An allocation without transfers (K , e, s) is a decentralized equilibrium
(DEWT) if it is INE and PSWT.
We assess now the relationship between the CFB and the DEWT. We first establish
the conditions for a DEWT to be shaped as the complete network both when banks
choose the risk-free project (i.e., the first best) and when they choose the risky project.
PROPOSITION 6. Assume that (N , e) define an economy without transfers and f (k)
satisfies the IPR property. Then: (i) the allocation (K e , e, s e ) with K ie = N \{i} and
sie = r f for all i is a DEWT if and only if mini∈N ei ≥ E; (ii) if maxi∈N ei < E,
then (K e , e, s e ) with K ie = N \{i} and sie = r for all i is a DEWT. Furthermore, if
η > f 1(1) , then (K e , e, s e ) with K ie = N \{i} and sie = r for all i is the unique DEWT,
whereas if η ≤ f 1(1) , then (K e , e, s e ) with K ie = ∅ and sie = r for all i is also a DEWT
(and there are no other DEWT).
The proof is in the Appendix. Let us compare the conditions in Proposition 6 with
those in Proposition 1. The condition in Proposition 1 that guarantees the first best
is not enough to achieve it as a DEWT. The planner can sustain the first best as far
as the total capital is high enough (E ≥ E), because she can transfer capital among
banks. In the DEWT, no transfers are possible and hence the first best is a DEWT if
and only if each individual bank capital is high enough (min ei ≥ E). Because the
latter condition is more stringent than the former condition, whenever the first best is
a DEWT, it is also achieved by the planner, whereas the opposite is not always true.
On the opposite case, all banks are connected and choose the risky project in the
DEWT if each individual bank capital is low enough (max ei < E). According to
Proposition 1, the fully connected network with gambling banks is a CFB only if
total capital is low enough (E < E). Because the latter condition is more stringent
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
381
than the former condition, whenever the complete network with gambling banks is a
CFB, it is also DEWT, whereas the opposite is not always true. Again, the planner
can pool the capital of several banks to induce at least one bank to choose the safe
project that is not possible in a DEWT. Finally, note that in the DEWT the complete
network with gambling banks is unique if η > 1/ f (1). According to Proposition 1,
the condition η ≥ 1/ρ guarantees that the CFB complete network with gambling
banks is unique. Because 1/ f (1) > 1/ρ, whenever η > 1/ f (1), gambling banks are
all connected both in the CFB and in the DEWT.12
The remaining propositions characterizes the decentralized network for the remaining possible values of bank capital ei . That is, whenever min ei < E < max ei
(note this condition, as before, implies B > (1 − ξ )ρ R). The following proposition
states that any DEWT is also characterized by a core-periphery structure.
PROPOSITION 7. Assume that min ei < E < max ei and (N , e) define an economy
without transfers. Then, a DEWT is a core-periphery structure, that is, if (K e , e, s e )
is a DEWT, then, for every pair of banks i and j such that sie = s ej = r f , we have
that i ∈ K ej and j ∈ K ie .
The proof is in the Appendix, whereas the intuition is as follows. On the one
hand, a bank agrees to be connected to any neighbor that is choosing the risk-free
project because this decision entails no counterparty risk. On the other hand, if a
bank invests in the risk-free project, any other bank would like to be connected to
it for the same reason. Because a link in this case is beneficial, two banks choosing
the safe project have the right incentive to be connected. A core-periphery structure
emerges in which the safe banks are connected among themselves. Similar to the
analysis of the CFB network, the connectivity in the decentralized network of the
banks choosing the gambling project depends on the relationship between f (k) and
η. We have the following.
PROPOSITION 8. Assume that min ei < E < max ei and f (k) satisfies the IPR property.
Let k(η) be as defined in (10). Then
(i) If k(η) = n − 1, then K ie = N \{i} for all i ∈ N .
(ii) If k(η) = 0, then gie = 0 for all i.
Similarly to Proposition 4, in the Appendix, we provide the proof of a more
general version of Proposition 8 that takes into account also intermediary values of
k(η). Statement 1 shows that the decentralized interbank network is characterized by
)n−1 . This is the same condition of the CFB
the complete structure when η ≥ ( ff (n−2)
(n−1)
network (recall Statement 1 in Proposition 4). When counterparty risk is very low,
the incentives in the formation of the decentralized network are aligned with those of
the planner. It is important to note that Proposition 8 does not imply that investment
decisions are also the same in both networks. In the DEWT, the investment decisions
12. The discrepancy between these two conditions is due to the equilibrium notion of pairwise stability.
With the stronger notion of pairwise-Nash stability, the condition on uniqueness for the DEWT coincides
with the one for the CFB (i.e., η ≥ 1/ρ).
382
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
might be suboptimal (i.e., too many banks investing in the risky project). However,
when η tends to 1, the risk-free and the risky projects yield (almost) the same expected
payoff. As counterparty risk vanishes, the only factor that determines the expected
payoff in the economy is the network structure.
Statement 2 in Proposition 8 establishes that the condition η < 1/ f (1) is sufficient
to observe an empty periphery in the decentralized network. That is, banks that
invest in the risky project are not linked with any other bank including the safe ones.
However, statement 2 in Proposition 4 shows that the same condition is not sufficient
for the empty periphery to be optimal. In this case, the planner allows safe banks to
have more risky links compared to the decentralized network. The condition to have
an empty periphery in the CFB network is given in Proposition 5. As a consequence,
banks that invest in the risky project can be inefficiently underconnected in the
decentralized interbank network whenever13
n−1
1−ξ
1
η∈
,
.
ρ[1 + nρ]
f (1)
For intermediary values of k(η), like in the CFB network (recall the long version
of Proposition 4), also the general version of Proposition 8 establishes that in the
decentralized network there is at most one bank holding less than k(η) connections.
The reason is the same as in the CFB. More importantly, in the decentralized network,
a bank with more than k(η) links will be connected only to banks that invest in the
risk-free project. This does not coincide with the condition of the CFB network,
where k(η) is the highest number of links that two connected periphery risky banks
can have. Although it is not individually optimal to hold more than k(η) links when
there is at least one risky neighbor, the planner could find it optimal to have a bank
holding more than k(η) links if the expected benefits of the risky banks compensate
for the expected loss of the safe banks.
The decentralized interbank network may show fewer connections than the CFB
network when banks that invest in the risk-free project consider engaging in bilateral
insurance too risky. The benefit provided by the interbank network is neglected when
counterparty risk is particularly high.14 The emergence of inefficient networks may
be due to the absence of a mechanism that allows banks to internalize the network
externalities. We are going to analyze this possibility in the next section.
3.2 Allowing for Transfers
In our model, the inefficiency is rooted in two sources of externalities: those related
to the decision of establishing the connections in the network (i.e., due to the network
formation process) and those related to the investment decision (i.e., risk-free versus
13. The interval is nonempty (see footnote 10).
14. Clearly, because counterparty risk η is not the only parameter in determining the shape of a CFB
network (bank capital endowments are important as well), the decentralized network is “underconnected”
whenever the more connected network is feasible given the initial capital endowments.
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
383
risky project). The two sources of externalities are intertwined in our model and they
cannot be separated. Let us explain why this is the case. When bank i invests in the
risky project, then it reduces also the probability of success of its directly connected
neighbors (respect to the case in which bank i invests in the risk-free project). This is
the externality that concerns the type of project chosen: the expected payoff of bank
i’s neighbors depends on the investment decision of bank i. Furthermore, whether
bank i decides to invest in the risk-free or the risky project depends on its network
position (i.e., whether other banks want to be connected to it). In turn, bank i’s
network position depends on bank i’s investment decision. Note that when bank i
invests in the risk-free project any bank would like to connect to it, otherwise, when
bank i invests in the risky project, other banks may connect depending on the severity
of counterparty risk.
Externalities due to the network formation process have been analyzed by Bloch
and Jackson (2007), whereas externalities due to the investment decision are peculiar
to our model. Bloch and Jackson (2007) show that efficient networks are supported,
although not uniquely, by pairwise stable equilibria when agents can make transfers
contingent on the network formation process. As it will become clearer later on in
this Section, allowing only for transfers contingent on the network formation process
is not enough to obtain the CFB network (because, as said, the two sources of
inefficiency cannot be separated in our model). Therefore, the interesting question
is whether allowing only for transfers affecting the investment decisions in general
suffice to sustain the CFB network.
We consider then a sequential-move game in which banks can transfer bank capital
to their neighboring banks. Following the sequence of events in Table 1, we consider
transfers that are made before the investment decisions take place.15 The goal of a
bank making such transfer is to induce the desired choice of the investment project
of its neighbors in the attempt to reduce the exposure to counterparty risk and to
increase the expected payoff.16
We again solve the model backward. We analyze the INE given the transfers
and the network. Then, given the network, we solve for the transfers anticipating
the INE played in the last stage. Finally, we characterize the decentralized network
anticipating the transfers and the INE played in the following stages. Recall that our
INE is determined by a simultaneous-move game in which it might not be unique.17
This can be problematic in a decentralized context where there is no coordination
device. Therefore, to avoid inefficiencies due to coordination failure in the INE,
we consider a sequential-move game with perfect information in the transfer stage
assuming a well-defined rule of order.
15. Although transfers conditional on network formation necessarily have to occur in t = 0, transfers conditional on the investment decision can also occur in t = 1 but before the investment decisions
take place.
16. We can interpret such capital transfers as capital-rich banks acquiring shares in capital-poor banks.
17. Note that the definition of PSWT does not preclude the possibility of coordination failure, that is
the possibility of encountering more than one INE given network K and the initial endowment e.
384
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
We rank banks according to their bank capital endowment, and we start the order
of transfers from the highest to the lowest capital endowed bank. Once the bank
endowed with the lowest capital has taken his transfer decision, we move on to the
investment stage. In this stage, the bank with the highest capital (which now might be
different from the bank with the highest capital endowment because of the transfers)
decides the type of investment, and the other banks follow according to their level
of bank capital. The backward solution allows us to select one INE and one profile
of transfers for a given network, that will be a Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in
the transfer and investment game. Once the transfer and the investment profile are
uniquely determined in equilibrium, we can apply pairwise stability to the network
formation process.
We have the following.
PROPOSITION 9. Let K be a given network and x be a vector of bank capital reallocation
such that there are multiple INE following (K , x). Let Q(s, s ′ ) ⊆ N be the group of
banks for which investment decisions change from the risky to the risk-free project
in two INE s, s ′ following (K , x). Then the backward induction argument in the
sequential-move investment game does not select the INE where agents in Q choose
the risky project, independently of the rule of order.
The proof is in the Appendix. Proposition 9 states that with sequential investment
decisions there is no coordination problem among banks. This means that if banks
arrive at the investment stage after choosing the optimal network and having done
the optimal transfers, the decentralized interbank network would coincide with the
CFB network. We can then explore whether bank capital transfers in a sequential
move game lead to a CFB allocation, assuming that INE decisions in the last stage
are optimal.
We first provide a condition under which bank capital transfers are never initiated
by the banks.
PROPOSITION 10. There exists a ξ ∈ [0, 1] such that if ξ > ξ , then there are no bank
capital transfers in the sequential-move transfer game.
The proof is in the Appendix. The intuition is the following. When the probability
of success of the gambling project is sufficiently high, then no bank capital transfers
occur. The high probability of success of the gambling project implies that counterparty risk is relatively low. Therefore, the amount of bank capital that has to be
transferred becomes too costly. Whenever ξ is sufficiently high, safe banks prefer to
face the (low) counterparty risk. It follows that if the decentralized network is not a
CFB it remains an inefficient network even when transfers affecting the investment
decisions are allowed.
We now analyze whether allowing for transfers when the probability of success of
the gambling project becomes lower (and counterparty risk becomes higher) is enough
to sustain the CFB network. It turns out that, even when transfers are correct (i.e.,
they give the right investment incentives to the neighboring banks), the decentralized
allocation with bank capital transfers is not able to mimic the CFB network. We
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
385
illustrate this result with a couple of examples.18 In particular, we show that allowing
for transfers affecting the investment decisions, not only does not avoid the formation
of underconnected decentralized network (like it was the case without such transfers),
but it may actually induce the formation of overconnected decentralized networks.
Overconnected decentralized network. Consider four banks. Bank 1 has a large
amount of capital e1 , whereas the other three banks have an amount of capital close to zero: e2 = e3 = e4 = ε ≈ 0. Assume the total capital E is such that
2I ∗ (1, 0, ξ, η) ≤ E < 3I ∗ (2, 0, ξ, η), and couterparty risk is such that η < 1/ f (1).
Under these assumptions, the CFB interbank network is made of Bank 1 connected
to one of the three banks. Let us indicate as Bank 2 the bank connected to Bank 1.
The two connected banks invest in the risk-free project after a capital transfer is made
from Bank 1 to Bank 2. In the decentralized network, Bank 1 would transfer to Bank
2 exactly the amount of capital necessary to switch from the risky to the risk-free
project. Such transfer t is equal to
x2 = e2 + t =
B
− 1,
(1 − ξ ) f (1)R
B
and Bank 2’s expected payoff is equal to (1−ξ
− 1.
)
What happens if Bank 2 connects to one of the two risky banks that are disconnected
in the CFB? For some values of the parameters, Bank 1 still transfers to Bank 2 the
amount of capital necessary to switch investment decision (so that transfers are
correct). However, the transfer now needs to make Bank 2 change its investment
decision when Bank 2 has two connections (one of them risky). The transfer t˜ is now
equal to
x2 = e2 + t˜ =
B
− 1,
(1 − ξ )η1/2 f (2)R
B
and Bank 2’s expected payoff is as before equal to (1−ξ
− 1. Given that η < f 1(1)
)
implies that η < ( ff (1)
)2 we have t˜ > t. Therefore Bank 1’s expected payoff is equal
(2)
to f (1)R(e1 + 1 − t) − 1 when it is linked only to Bank 2, and equal to f (1)R(e1 +
1 − t˜) − 1 when it is linked to Bank 2, which is linked to another bank. Clearly,
Bank 1 strictly prefers the first network over the second network. The latter network
therefore is overconnected, in the sense that the link between Banks 2 and another
risky bank imposes a negative externality on Bank 1. In other terms, the transfer made
by Bank 1 to Bank 2 represents a positive externality for the gambling banks because
it induces a positive switch, from the risky to the safe project, in the investment
decision of Bank 2. The other banks have an incentive to over connect.
Finally, note that both the disconnected risky banks strictly gain from connecting
to Bank 2. The disconnected banks have an expected payoff equal to ξ R f (1)(ε +
1) + B − 1 if they connect to Bank 2 as opposed to the lower expected payoff ξ R(ε +
18. More elaborated numerical examples are available upon request.
386
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
1) + B − 1 if disconnected. Overall, the CFB cannot be an equilibrium because two
banks that should not be connected would gain from linking by free-riding on Bank
1’s transfer.
Let us illustrate with this example why transfers only contingent on the network
formation process (a lá Bloch and Jackson 2007) are not enough to restore the CFB
network. Assume risky banks can propose a transfer to the safe Bank 1 conditional
on being connected to Bank 1. This transfer can be interpreted as a repayment with
high interest in case the risky project succeed. Likely the safe bank may find it
convenient to link to only one of the risky banks but the investment behavior of the
linked risky bank will not change, because its bank capital does not increase. The
CFB (including the proper investment decision) cannot be reached. It is true that the
CFB network structure, that is, two banks linked, can be obtained but the two banks
will not invest both in the risk-free project. It could be tempting to conclude that at
least the externality due to the network formation process is solved, as the network
structure coincides with the CFB one, although not the investment decision. However,
this is not true in general.
Let us slightly modify the example by assuming that the total capital E is such
that 3I ∗ (2, 0, ξ, η) ≤ E < 4I ∗ (3, 0, ξ, η). In this case, the CFB consists of three
safe banks in the core and one risky bank in the periphery disconnected from the
core. Assume again only transfers conditional on the network formation process are
possible. The three risky banks can then propose a transfer to the safe bank conditional
on being connected to Bank 1. Again Bank 1 will accept to connect to the risky banks
but the risky banks will not change investment behavior. Because η is small enough
that it is not convenient to connect a risky bank to a safe bank, a fortiori a risky
bank is not willing to connect to another risky bank and their connection will not
be created. In this case, the equilibrium network is a star where the safe Bank 1
is the center and the three gambling banks are connected to it. However, the CFB
network is made of a core with three safe banks and a disconnected risky periphery
bank. Hence, in general, the CFB is not supported when only transfers conditional
on the network formation are possible. In our model, transfers that are conditional
on the investment decision are necessarily needed to have hope to restore efficiency.
However, this example has shown that also such transfers alone cannot guarantee the
CFB network.
Underconnected decentralized network. Consider the same four banks, and assume
that 3I ∗ (2, 0, ξ, η) ≤ E < 4I ∗ (3, 0, ξ, η) so that the CFB interbank network has
three banks in the core. In the CFB, Bank 1 makes a transfer to two neighbors that is
sufficient to make them switch the investment decision from the risky to the risk-free
project. What happens if Bank 1 deletes one of his connections in the CFB? For
some values of the parameters, Bank 1 still transfers the exact amount of capital
that induces to switch the investment decision of the remaining connected bank (so
transfers are correct) but it severs the connection and the relative transfer with the
other bank. The reason is that in the CFB the planner guarantees that the expected
gains of the two core banks receiving the transfers compensate for the expected loss
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
387
that Bank 1 suffers, such that the three banks are better off than in autarky. This is
not incompatible with the fact that Bank 1 individually prefers being connected to
one bank (making only one transfer) than being linked to two banks (making two
transfers), even though the latter situation is better than autarky. The CFB cannot be
an equilibrium, as Bank 1 has an incentive to delete one of its links.
Overall assessment. Our examples show that, even allowing for transfers conditional
on the investment decisions, the equilibrium networks feature either too many or too
few connections with respect to the CFB network. Therefore, such transfers do not
guarantee in general that the CFB network is sustained in equilibrium. We also show
that transfers conditional only on the network formation are not effective in our
model. The overall conclusion is that we need transfers that affect both the network
formation process and the investment decision in order to sustain CFB network
structures in equilibrium. How realistic is such possibility? Bloch and Jackson (2007)
must consider a wide array of transfers contingent on the network formation process
(transfers can be proposed to all the agents in order to subsidize the formation of a link
and to incentivate the severance of a link). We consider such transfers contingent on
the network formation coupled with the capital transfers affecting investment decision
to be too demanding from a practical point of view. It clearly requires a high level of
coordination among all the banks in the system even before the network is formed
and investment decisions are taken. If however such coordination is considered to
be feasible, then inefficiencies both in the investment decision and in the network
formation process are less of a concern.
4. CONCLUSIONS
We present a model of interbank network formation and characterize the set of optimal networks as core-periphery structures. The decentralized interbank networks also
show a core-periphery structure. However, when the counterparty risk is sufficiently
high the decentralized core-periphery interbank network may be underconnected with
respect to the optimal one. The root of the inefficiency is that a bank’s investment
choice has a direct effect on the expected payoff of its neighbors in the interbank
network. This network externality in general is not internalized even if bank capital
transfers conditional on the investment decision are allowed. A more comprehensive
set of transfers, including those conditional on the network formation process, should
be feasible for banks to avoid inefficiency.
Some of our modeling choices need some qualification. First, our exogenous
assumptions on the benefits and costs of connecting to the interbank network allow
us to sharp our analysis on the optimal network structure and the decentralized
network formation. Even if we provide, in our opinion, a reasonable justification for
these assumptions, a better understanding of the microfoundations that are able to
rationalize such benefits and costs is clearly needed.
388
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
Second, we assume that all banks have access to the same coinsurance independently of the connections of their counterparts. Consider, for example, a network in
which bank 1 and bank 2 are disconnected but both connected to bank 3, and another
network in which the three banks are directly connected. In our setting, bank 3 has
the same access to coinsurance in both networks. However, there could be reasons
to believe that bank 3 coinsurance becomes weaker when also bank 1 and bank 2 are
directly connected.19 Including this possibility in our model represents a challenge
for future research on interbank network formation.
Finally, it is consistently observed across countries that large banks are in the core
of interbank networks. Our model, like many in this literature, features homogeneous
bank size so it cannot be directly related to this evidence. However, as long as size can
be considered a proxy for safety our model seems to be supported by this evidence.
Indeed, a larger size is related to better diversification and therefore lower risk.
Also bigger banks exploit the implicit guarantee due to the too-big-to-fail policy.
Clearly, both more sophisticated models and, because of the evident endogeneity
issues between size and risk, more detailed evidence are needed to shed light on this
challenging research agenda.
APPENDIX: PROOFS
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 1. The existence of a CFB can be proven in two steps. First,
for given network K and vector of investments s, we maximize the objective function
with respect to the vector of capital x subject to
xi ≥ 0
for all i ∈ N ,
(A1)
(A2)
i∈N
xi =
ei ≡ E,
i∈N
xi ≥ I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η),
xi < I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η)
if si = r f,
if si = r.
(A3)
(A4)
Second, once the maximum total expected payoff is obtained given K and s , it
suffices to choose the combination of K and s that delivers the highest expected total
payoff. Note that the second step does not create problems of existence as we are
choosing the highest number on a discrete set of numbers. However, to guarantee
that the set of constraints define a closed set in ℜn in the first step, the problematic
restriction is (A4). Let us modify the planner problem by rewriting such constraint
19. Castiglionesi and Wagner (2013) provide a three-bank model where this issue is analyzed.
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
389
as
xi ≤ I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η)
if si = r.
In the modified problem, a maximum always exists. Furthermore, the solution of the
modified problem is also a maximum of the social planner’s problem. If this were
not true, then there is an economy for which the solution (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) of the modified
problem is such that xi∗ = I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η) for at least one bank i with si = r . But if
xi∗ = I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η) for at least one bank i, then the triple (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ′ ), where s ′ and
s ∗ differ only on the choice of investment by bank i, is also feasible and yields a
higher expected payoff to at least bank i and its neighbors (and no bank gets lower
expected payoff) than in s ∗ . Therefore, (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) could not have been a maximum
of the modified problem, which is a contradiction.
Let us now consider the second statement of the proposition. We have to check that
both
the participation and incentive constraints have to be satisfied. First, note that if
i∈N ei = E ≥ E there is enough bank capital to satisfy the incentive constraint in
all banks. This is because E ≥ n I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η).
Regarding the participation constraints, note that the higher the initial capital
endowment of a bank, the harder it is for the planner to satisfy the participation
constraint. The most difficult case is when one bank is endowed with all the bank
capital in the economy E and the remaining banks have 0 bank capital. The banks
with 0 bank capital choose the risky project given that B > (1 − ξ )R, or, equivalently,
I ∗ (0, 0, ξ, η) > 0. We separate two cases depending on the type investment project
chosen in autarky by the all-endowed bank.
If the “all-endowed” bank chooses the risk-free project, then the planner needs to
− 1} dollars of bank capital to the all-endowed bank and
give max{ (1−ξB)ρ R − 1, E+1
ρ
B
−
1
to
each
of
the
other
banks. Given that B > (1 − ξ )ρ R > (1 − ξ )R, this
(1−ξ )ρ R
B
− 1 to each gambling
redistribution of capital gives an expected payoff equal to 1−ξ
bank, which is higher than the expected payoff in autarky equal to ξ R + B − 1.
Note that if the all-endowed bank chooses the risk-free project in autarky, we have
E+1
≥ (1−ξB)ρ R . Therefore, the planner needs E to be at least equal to E+1
−1+
ρ
ρ
(n − 1)( (1−ξB)ρ R − 1), or, rearranging
E≥
(n − 1) ρ B
nρ − 1
n−1 ∗
−
=
I (0, 0, ξ, η) − n.
(ρ − 1) (1 − ξ )R
ρ−1
ρ−1
B
− 1, which
If the all-endowed bank chooses the risky project, then E < (1−ξ
)R
B
implies (1−ξ )R (n − ρ) < nρ − ρ. The planner now needs to give max{ (1−ξB)ρ R −
+ ρBR − 1} of bank capital to the all-endowed bank and (1−ξB)ρ R − 1 to each
1, ξ E+1
ρ
of the remaining banks. As before, given that B > (1 − ξ )R, this reallocation of
B
capital guarantees an expected payoff of 1−ξ
− 1 to each gambling bank, which is
higher than the expected payoff in autarky ξ R + B − 1. Note that if the all-endowed
390
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
bank chooses the risky project in autarky, it is ξ E+1
+ ρBR < (1−ξB)ρ R . Therefore, the
ρ
planner needs E to be at least equal to n( (1−ξB)ρ R − 1) = n I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η).
If the banks had the same bank capital endowment, it is easy to check that the
condition for INE is sufficient to induce shareholders of all banks to participate in
the first best network with xi = ei .
Finally, assume E < I ∗ (n − 1, 0, ξ, η) = (1−ξB)ρ R − 1, then E < (1−ξ )ηBg/k f (k) − 1
for any k ∈ [1, n − 1) and g ≤ k. This means that at any INE no bank that is connected
can choose the safe project, even if the planner pools all capital into one bank. Given
that f is increasing, if it is optimal to have some banks connected, then it is optimal
to have all of them connected as η f (k) ≤ ηρ. It is optimal to have all gambling banks
connected (so k = g = n − 1) when ηρ ≥ 1. Nevertheless, it is optimal to keep banks
disconnected if 1 > ηρ because the empty network yields a higher expected payoff
than the complete network.
To prove the following propositions, it is useful to make use of reallocations of bank capital that are payoff equivalent to the shareholders’ expected
payoff in autarky. We indicate the expected payoff in autarky for bank i as
m iA = max{R(ei + 1) − 1, ξ R(ei + 1) + B − 1}. For given K and s, let xiA (K , s)
be such that m i (K , xiA (K , s), s) = m iA . That is, xiA (K , s) is a reallocation of bank
capital that makes bank i indifferent between participating or not in the network K
with strategy profile s. Note that the reallocation of bank capital xiA (K , s) is unique
given (K , s).
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 2. The proof is made by contradiction. Assume that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ )
is a CFB for (N , e) but there are two disconnected banks i and j such that si∗ =
s ∗j = r f . Take a new allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) for the same economy (N , e), where the
allocation of bank capital and strategies are the same but the new network structure
adds the link between banks i and j. Formally, K̂ i = K i∗ ∪ { j}, K̂ j = K ∗j ∪ {i}, and
K̂ b = K b∗ for all banks b = i, j. We show now that the allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an
INE: it satisfies the participation constraints in any bank and it yields a higher expected
total payoff. Therefore, the initial allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) cannot be a solution to the
planner’s problem and Proposition 2 follows.
Note that, by definition of K̂ , pb ( K̂ , s ∗ ) = pb (K ∗ , s ∗ ) for all b ∈ N , and
∗
k +1
k̂b = b∗
kb
if b = i or b = j
otherwise.
Note that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an INE given that it is a CFB. This means, because both i and j are choosing the risk-free project, that xi∗ ≥ I ∗ (ki∗ , gi , ξ, η)
and x ∗j ≥ I ∗ (k ∗j , g j , ξ, η). By definition of the functions I ∗ , it is true then that
xi∗ ≥ I ∗ (ki∗ + 1, gi , ξ, η) and x ∗j ≥ I ∗ (k ∗j + 1, g j , ξ, η). Therefore, the allocation
( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an INE.
Given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraints for any bank, it
is true that xi∗ ≥ xiA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) and x ∗j ≥ x jA (K ∗ , s ∗ ). Recall that: (i) xiA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) =
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
m iA +1
η gi /ki f (ki∗ )R
− 1 and x jA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) =
1 and x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) =
m Aj +1
η g j /k j f (k ∗j )R
m Aj +1
− 1; (ii) xiA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) =
:
m iA +1
η gi /(ki +1) f (ki∗ +1)R
391
−
− 1. Given that f (k) is increasing in k and η is
η g j /(k j +1) f (k ∗j +1)R
a probability, it is true that xiA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) > xiA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) and x jA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) >
Therefore, xi∗ ≥ xiA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) and x ∗j ≥ x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ). This means that the
∗ ∗
x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ).
allocation
( K̂ , x , s ) satisfies the shareholders’ participation constraints in any bank.
Finally,
m b K̂ , xb∗ , s ∗ + Mb K̂ , s ∗ −
m b (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) + Mb K ∗ , s ∗
b∈N
b∈N
gi
gj
gi
∗
∗
∗
= R xi∗ + 1 η (ki +1) f ki∗ + 1 − η ki f ki∗ + R x ∗j + 1 η (k j +1) f (k ∗j + 1)
gj
∗
−η k j f k ∗j > 0
because f (k) is increasing in k and η is a probability. Given the last inequality, the
allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) yields a higher expected payoff and therefore (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) was
not a CFB.
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 3. We prove that if an allocation is an INE and it satisfies the
shareholders’ participation constraints in any bank, then it has to be that any bank
choosing the risk-free project in autarky chooses the same project in the optimal allocation as well. Take any bank i such that max{R(ei + 1) − 1, ξ R(ei + 1) + B − 1} =
R(ei + 1) − 1, that is, it chooses the safe project in autarky. Assume by contradiction
that there exists an allocation (K , x, s) that is an INE, it satisfies the shareholders’
participation constraints for any bank and si = r . This implies
(i) xi < I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η) because (K , x, s) is an INE, and
(ii) ξ η gi /ki f (ki )R(xi + 1) + B − 1 ≥ R(ei + 1) − 1 because (K , x, s) satisfies the
participation constraint.
Given that bank i chooses the risk-free project in autarky, we have R(ei + 1) ≥
The last condition together with the participation constraint for bank i (item 2
above) implies
B
.
(1−ξ )
ξ η gi /ki f (ki )R(xi + 1) + B ≥
B
,
(1 − ξ )
and, after rearranging, we have
xi ≥
B
− 1 = I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η),
(1 − ξ )η gi /ki f (ki )R
392
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
a contradiction with (K , x, s) being an INE (item 1 above). Therefore, any bank i
choosing the risk-free project in autarky chooses the same type of project in any INE
satisfying the shareholders’ participation constraint (for at least that bank i).
PROPOSITION 4 (Long version). Assume that min ei < E ≤ E < E and f (k) satisfies
the IPR property. Let (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) be a CFB allocation for a given economy (N , e).
Let k(η) be as defined in (10). Then:
(1) If k(η) = n − 1, then K i∗ = N \{i} for all i ∈ N .
(2) If k(η) = 0, then gi∗ = 0 for all i such that si∗ = r .
(3) If k(η) ∈ (0, n − 1), then:
/ K i∗ .
(a) ki∗ < k(η) for some i implies that si∗ = r and k ∗j ≥ k(η) for all j ∈
(b) ki∗ > k(η) and si∗ = r implies that for all j ∈ G i :
(bi) k j ≤ k(η);
/ K j;
(bii) there is no other bank b with kb∗ < k(η) and b ∈
(biii) for any other bank b with kb∗ > k(η): sb∗ = r and there is no bank
z ∈ G b such that z ∈
/ K j.
In order to prove Proposition 4 (Long version), it is useful to prove the following
lemma.
)k and
LEMMA A1. Let k(η) be the highest k ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1} such that η ≥ ( f (k−1)
f (k)
f (k) k+1
) . Then:
let k(η) be the lowest k ∈ {0, 1, . . . , n − 2} such that η < ( f (k+1)
(1) If (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is a CFB allocation, then, ki∗ < k(η) for some i implies that
si∗ = r and k ∗j ≥ k(η) for all j ∈
/ K i∗ .
(2) If (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is a CFB allocation, then, ki∗ > k(η) and si∗ = r implies that for
all j ∈ G i :
(a) k j ≤ k(η);
/ K j;
(b) there is no other bank b with kb∗ < k(η) and b ∈
(c) for any other bank b with kb∗ > k(η), sb∗ = g there is no bank z ∈ G b such
that z ∈
/ K j.
PROOF OF LEMMA A1. We prove all statements by contradiction.
Proof of Statement 1. Assume that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is a CFB allocation where there
are two banks i and j not directly connected and such that ki < k(η) and k j < k(η).
Take a new allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) for the same economy (N , e), where the allocation
of capital and strategies are the same but the network structure adds the link between
banks i and j. Formally, K̂ i = K i∗ ∪ { j}, K̂ j = K ∗j ∪ {i}, and K̂ b = K b∗ for all b =
i, j.
We show first that the participation constraint is satisfied by ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) for all
banks. Later, we show that ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) yields a higher total expected payoff than
(K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ). Therefore, the initial allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) cannot be a solution to the
planner’s problem and Statement 1 follows. We separate cases depending whether
bank i chooses the risk-free or the risky project in the investment profile s ∗ .
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
393
Note that if (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is a CFB, then it has to be an INE and it has to satisfy the
shareholders participation constraints in any bank. If at least one of them, for example
bank i, is choosing the risk-free project, then xi∗ ≥ I ∗ (ki∗ , gi , ξ, η). The other bank,
say j, is choosing the risky project. We know from Proposition 2 that both banks
cannot invest in the risk-free project because in such a case (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) would not
be a CFB allocation.
We note that I ∗ (ki∗ , gi , ξ, η) ≥ I ∗ (ki∗ + 1, gi + 1, ξ, η) if and only if
gi +1
∗
ki∗ −gi
∗ ∗
gi
∗
η ki +1 f (ki∗ + 1) ≥ η ki f (ki∗ ), or, equivalently, η ki (ki +1) ≥
f (ki ) ki +1
)
tio (
is increasing in ki we have that
f (ki + 1)
k(η)
f k(η) − 1
≥
f k(η)
f (ki )
f (ki + 1)
ki +1
f (ki∗ )
.
f (ki∗ +1)
Given that the ra-
for any ki ≤ k(η) − 1,
k ∗ −g
i
η < 1 and k ∗ (ki ∗ +1)
< (k ∗1+1) . Hence, η > ( f (k(η)−1)
)k(η) implies that η >
f (k(η))
i
i
i
∗
f (ki ) k ∗ +1
)i
(
because ki∗ ≤ k(η) − 1. The latter inequality implies in turn that
f (ki∗ + 1)
η
ki∗ −gi
ki∗ (ki∗ +1)
≥
f (ki∗ )
.
f (ki∗ +1)
Therefore, the allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an INE as far as x j <
I ∗ (ki + 1, gi , ξ, η). If it were not, there is an allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , ŝ) in which bank j
chooses the risk-free project instead of the risky one. This would be an INE for bank
i because I ∗ (ki∗ + 1, gi + 1, ξ, η) > I ∗ (ki∗ + 1, gi , ξ, η).
Participation constraints. Assume that bank i chooses the risk-free project in
1
∗
)k(η) , then η ki +1 f (ki∗ + 1) > f (ki∗ ) for ki < k(η). As
(K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ). If η ≥ ( f (k(η)−1)
f (k(η))
gi +1
ki∗ +1
−
gi
ki∗
=
ki∗ −gi
ki∗ (ki∗ +1)
<
1
,
ki∗ +1
the latter inequality implies
gi +1
gi
∗
∗
η ki +1 f ki∗ + 1 R xi∗ + 1 − 1 > η ki f ki∗ R xi∗ + 1 − 1.
Given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraints for any bank, it has to
gi
∗
be that η ki f (ki∗ )R(xi∗ + 1) − 1 ≥ m iA , and therefore, ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraints for bank i.
If bank i chooses the risky project in (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ), the argument is equivalent. Note
1
∗
)k(η) , then η ki +1 f (ki∗ + 1) > f (ki∗ ) for ki < k(η). As
that if η ≥ ( f (k(η)−1)
f (k(η))
ki∗ −gi
ki∗ (ki∗ +1)
<
1
,
ki∗ +1
gi +1
ki∗ +1
−
the latter inequality implies
gi +1
gi
∗
∗
ξ η ki +1 f ki∗ + 1 R xi∗ + 1 + B − 1 ≥ ξ η ki f ki∗ R xi∗ + 1 + B − 1.
gi
ki∗
=
394
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
Given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraints for any bank, it has to
gi
∗
be that ξ η ki f (ki∗ )R(xi∗ + 1) + B − 1 ≥ m iA , and therefore, ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the
participation constraint for bank i.
Checking that the participation constraint for bank j, which chooses the gambling
project in (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ), is satisfied in ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) works the same way as in the previous
case and it is therefore omitted.
Total expected payoff. If bank i chooses the risk-free project in (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) we
have
m b K̂ , xi∗ , s ∗ + Mb K̂ , s ∗ − m b K ∗ , xi∗ , s ∗ − Mb K ∗ , s ∗ =
b∈N
gi
ki∗
=η R
xi∗
∗ i
kki∗−g
∗
∗
+1
i
+1 η
f ki + 1 − f ki
1
1
∗
∗
+ ξ η g j R x ∗j + 1 η k j +1 f k ∗j + 1 − η k j f k ∗j .
(A5)
If banks i and j both choose the risky project in (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ), we have
m b K̂ , xi∗ , s ∗ + Mb K̂ , s ∗ − m b K ∗ , xi∗ , s ∗ + Mb K ∗ , s ∗ =
b∈N
∗
gi
ki∗−gi
∗
= ξ η ki R xi∗ + 1 η ki +1 f ki∗ + 1 − f ki∗
k ∗ −g
j
j
∗
k
+1
+ ξ η R x ∗j + 1 η j f k ∗j + 1 − f k ∗j .
gj
k ∗j
Expressions (A5) and (A6) are greater than 0 because 1 > η ≥ (
f (k ∗j )
∗
(A6)
f (ki∗ ) k ∗ +1
)i
f (ki∗ + 1)
)k j +1 for ki∗ < k(η) and k ∗j < k(η). Therefore, the allocation
f (k ∗j + 1)
( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) yields a higher total expected payoff and therefore (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is not
a CFB.
/ K i∗ would be
Furthermore, equation (A5) implies that if si∗ = r f any bank j ∈
better off connecting to bank i. Hence, there is no bank j such that j ∈
/ K i∗ if si∗ = r f
∗
∗
and ki < k(η). But then ki = n − 1, a contradiction. Therefore, if ki∗ < k(η), then
/ K i∗ . Finally, if ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is not an INE it
si∗ = r and k ∗j > k(η) for any bank j ∈
is because bank j would choose the safe project as well, once K̂ is given, or, when
both banks i and j choose the risky project in (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ), an INE would select at
least one of the two banks to choose the safe project. In all these cases, the new
INE will yield a higher expected payoff for both banks i and j. This implies that
the participation constraint would be satisfied, and therefore a higher total expected
payoff than in ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ).
and 1 > η ≥ (
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
395
Proof of Statements 2(a), 2(b), and 2(c). Assume that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is a CFB allocation where there is at least one bank i with si∗ = r and gi∗ = 0. As before, we show that
for all the three cases there is an allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) that satisfies the participation
constraint for any bank and yields an higher total expected payoff. In particular, the
allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) yields both individual and total expected payoffs higher than
the allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ), which then cannot be a solution to the planner’s problem.
Assume that statement 2(a) is not true and k j > k(η) for some j ∈ G i∗ . Take a
new allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) where the bank capital and strategies are the same but the
network structure removes the link between banks i and j. Formally, K̂ i = K i∗ \{ j},
K̂ j = K ∗j \{i}, and K̂ b = K b∗ for all b = i, j.
Assume that statement 2(b) is not true and there is a bank b = j with kb < k(η) and
b and j are not directly connected. Take a new allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) where the bank
capital and strategies are the same but the network structure removes the link between
banks i and j and creates a link between banks j and b. Formally, K̂ i = K i∗ \{ j},
K̂ j = K ∗j \{i} ∪ {b}, and K̂ b = K b∗ ∪ { j} and K̂ l = K l∗ for all l = i, j, b.
Finally, assume that statement 2(c) is not true and there is a bank b = j with
kb∗ > k(η) and sb∗ = r such that one of its direct gambling neighbors z is not directly
connected to j. Take a new allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) where the bank capital and strategies
are the same but the network structure severs the links between banks i and j, and
between b and z, and it creates a link between banks j and z. Formally, K̂ i = K i∗ \{ j},
K̂ j = K ∗j \{i} ∪ {z}, K̂ b = K b∗ \{z}, and K̂ z = K z∗ \{b} ∪ { j} and K̂ l = K l∗ for all l =
i, j, b, z.
1
f (k(η)) k(η)+1
∗
Participation constraints. If η < (
, then η ki f (ki∗ ) < f (ki∗ − 1)
)
f (k(η) + 1)
because ki∗ > k(η). This implies η
gi −1
ki
1
∗
× η ki f (ki∗ ) < η
gi −1
ki
× f (ki∗ − 1), and hence
gi
gi −1
∗
∗
ξ η ki f ki∗ R xi∗ + 1 + B − 1 < ξ η ki −1 f ki∗ − 1 R xi∗ + 1 + B − 1,
or
gi
gi −1
∗
∗
η ki f ki∗ < η ki −1 f ki∗ − 1 .
(A7)
Given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraints for any bank, it has to
gi
∗
be that ξ η ki f (ki∗ )R(xi∗ + 1) + B − 1 ≥ m iA , and therefore ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the
participation constraints for bank i. The proof is equivalent for bank j if statement
2(a) is considered and for bank b if statement 2(c) is considered. Note that bank j
in statements 2(b) and 2(c) and bank z in statement 2(c) are indifferent between the
allocations (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) and ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ). Consider now the participation constraint
for bank b in statement 2(b). Note that given the definition of k(η), it has to be that
1
∗
η kb +1 f (kb∗ + 1) > f (kb∗ ) for kb∗ < k(η). This implies
gb +1
gb
∗
∗
ξ η kb +1 f kb∗ + 1 R xb∗ + 1 + B − 1 > ξ η kb f kb∗ R xb∗ + 1 + B − 1,
396
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
or
gb +1
gb
∗
∗
η kb +1 f kb∗ + 1 > η kb f kb∗ ,
if b chooses the risky project. If bank b chooses the risk-free project, we have
gb +1
gb
∗
∗
η kb +1 f kb∗ + 1 R xb∗ + 1 − 1 > η kb f kb∗ R xb∗ + 1 − 1,
or
gb +1
gb
∗
∗
η kb +1 f kb∗ + 1 > η kb f kb∗ .
Given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraints for any bank, it has to be
gb
∗
gb
∗
that ξ η kb f (kb∗ )R(xb∗ + 1) + B − 1 ≥ m bA if bank b is gambling, or η kb f (kb∗ )R(xb∗ +
1) ≥ m bA , otherwise. Therefore, the allocation ( K̂ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation
constraints for bank b as well.
Total expected payoff. Let
∗ ∗ ∗
m l K̂ , xl∗ , s ∗ −
m l K , xl , s ≡ ,
l∈N
l∈N
and, depending on which of the three cases is considered, we have:
Statement 2(a)
gi
g∗i −1
∗
= ξ R xi∗ + 1 η ki −1 f ki∗ − 1 − η ki f ki∗
gj
g∗j −1
∗
+ ξ R x ∗j + 1 η k j −1 f k ∗j − 1 − η k j f k ∗j ,
where both ki∗ > k (η) and k ∗j > k (η);
Statement 2(b)
gi
kg∗i −1
∗
∗
∗
−1
ki∗
i
f ki − 1 − η f ki
= ξ R xi + 1 η
gb
g∗b +1
∗
+ ξ R xb∗ + 1 η kb +1 f kb∗ + 1 − η kb f kb∗ ,
where ki∗ > k (η) and kb∗ < k (η);
Statement 2(c)
gi
∗
kg∗i −1
∗
∗
ki∗
−1
i
f ki − 1 − η f ki
= ξ R xi + 1 η
gb
g∗b −1
∗
+ ξ R xb∗ + 1 η kb −1 f kb∗ − 1 − η kb f kb∗ ,
where both ki∗ > k(η) and kb∗ > k(η).
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
397
Applying the same reasoning used above, namely condition (A7 ) and the IPR
property, it follows that > 0 in each of the three cases.
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 4 (Long version). Assume first that k(η) = n − 1. According
to Statement 1 of Lemma A1, if there is any bank i with ki∗ < n − 1 then, for all bank
j not directly connected to bank i , we have k ∗j = n − 1. But this is a contradiction,
because any bank j with n − 1 connections has to be directly connected to bank i.
Assume now that k(η) = 0. According to Statement 2(a) of Lemma A1, if there is any
bank i that invest in the risky project and it is directly connected to another gambling
bank j, it has to be that k ∗j = 0. But again this is a contradiction with the fact that
bank j is directly connected to bank i. Finally, assume k(η) = n − 1 and k(η) = 0.
1
By definition, k(η) is the minimum number k such that η k+1 f (k + 1) ≤ f (k). Then it
1
has to be that η k+1 f (k + 1) > f (k) for k ≤ k(η) − 1. This follows because f satisfies
the IPR property.
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 5. Assume that bank i is choosing the risk-free project in the
1
, we have g j = 0
CFB allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ), with gi∗ > 0. As shown, if η <
f (1)
∗
for any j ∈ G i . Take a new allocation ( K̂ , x̂, s ) where the investment strategies are
the same but (i) the bank capital given to every j ∈ G i is the autarky-equivalent
payoff x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) , and (ii) the network structure severs all the risky links of bank i.
Formally, (i) x̂ j = x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) for any j ∈ G i , x̂i = xi∗ + j∈G i (x ∗j − x̂ j ), and x̂b =
/ G i , b = i, and (ii) K̂ i = K i∗ \{G i }, K̂ j = K ∗j \{i}, for all j ∈ G i , and
xb∗ for all b ∈
K̂ b = K b∗ for all b ∈
/ G i , b = i. We show that the new allocation ( K̂ , x̂, s ∗ ) satisfies
the participation constraints for any bank, it is an INE, and it yields a higher total
expected payoff. Therefore, the initial allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) cannot be a solution to
the planner’s problem.
Participation constraints. We consider only bank i, because for any bank j ∈ G i
the investor participation constraints are satisfied by definition. For any other bank,
the participation constraints are satisfied because the allocation (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies
the participation constraints. For shareholders in bank i, we need to show that
xi∗
+
j∈G i
x ∗j
− x̂ j ≥
xiA
K̂ , s
∗
for η <
1−ξ
1 + nρ
n−1
.
Recall that, given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) satisfies the participation constraint, it has to be
that xi∗ ≥ xiA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) and x ∗j ≥ x jA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) for any j ∈ G i . Therefore,
xi∗ +
j∈G i
A ∗ ∗
x ∗j − x̂ j ≥ xiA K ∗ , s ∗ +
x j K , s − x̂ j .
j∈G i
Note that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an INE satisfying the participation constraint. By Proposition 3, any j ∈ G i chooses the risky project in autarky. This means that
398
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
x jA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) =
e j +1
f (k ∗j )
− 1 and x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) =
e j +1
f (k ∗j −1)
− 1 for any j ∈ G i . Because bank i
m iA +1
chooses the risk-free project, we have xiA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) =
η
m iA +1
gi
∗
η ki −gi
f (ki∗ −gi )R
gi
ki∗
f (ki∗ )R
− 1 and xiA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) =
− 1, with m iA = max{R (ei + 1) − 1, ξ R (ei + 1) + B − 1}.
Consider first x jA (K ∗ , s ∗ ) for any j ∈ G i . Because (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an optimal allocation it has to be a core-periphery structure. Furthermore, g j = 0 for any j ∈ G i
given that η < f 1(1) . Then, k ∗j ≤ ki∗ for any j ∈ G i . This is so given that (i) bank i
is connected to all other banks choosing the safe project and to all banks in G i , that
is ki∗ = c∗ − 1 + gi (with c∗ being the number of banks in the core); (ii) any bank
j choosing the gambling project can be connected at most to all the banks choosing
the safe project (and no bank choosing the gambling project), that is k ∗j ≤ c∗ . Then,
because gi ≥ 1, we have k ∗j ≤ ki∗ and therefore
ej + 1
ej + 1
−1
x jA K ∗ , s ∗ =
∗ −1≥
f (k j )
f (ki∗ )
for any j ∈ G i .
(A8)
Consider now x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) for any j ∈ G i . Note that
x jA K̂ , s ∗ =
ej + 1
f k ∗j − 1
− 1 ≤ ej
for any j ∈ G i ,
given that f (k ∗j − 1) ≥ 1 for any k ∗j ≥ 1. Then we have
A ∗ ∗
xiA K ∗ , s ∗ +
x j K , s − x̂ j ≥
j∈G i
−1+
j∈G i
Note that
or
ej + 1
− 1 − ej .
f ki∗
m iA + 1
−1+
gi
∗
η ki f ki∗ R
j∈G i
= xiA K̂ , s ∗ ,
m iA + 1
η f ki∗ R
ej + 1
− 1 − ej
f ki∗
gi
ki∗
≥
mA + 1
∗i
−1
f ki − gi R
⎤
⎡
f ki∗ − 1
m iA + 1
1
1
⎦
⎣ gi
(e j + 1),
− f k ∗ − g ≥ f k ∗
∗
R
i
i
i
η ki f ki∗
j∈G i
(A9)
:
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
1
m iA +1
[
R
given that (i)
399
η
gi
ki∗
1
−
f (ki∗ )
1
]
f (ki∗ −gi )
≥
B
R
1−η n−1 ρ
×
1
η n−1
ρ
, because m iA + 1 ≥ B, (ii)
f (k ∗ )−1
B
n−1
1 ≤ f (.) ≤ ρ, (iii) f (ki ∗ )
j∈G i (e j + 1) ≤ R × 1−ξ , given that by Proposition 3 we
i
know that any j ∈ G i chooses the risky project in autarky and f (ki∗ ) − 1 ≤ f (ki∗ ),
1
1
1−ξ
1−ξ
1−ξ
1
and (iv) η n−1 ρ < n−ξ
if η n−1 ρ < (1+nρ)
because (1+nρ)
< n−ξ
.
∗
∗
∗ ∗
The allocation ( K̂ , x̂, s ) is an INE. If (K , x , s ) is a CFB, then it has to be an
INE. Consider any player j ∈ G i . Given that (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) is an INE, it has to be that
x ∗j <
B
− 1,
(1 − ξ ) f (k ∗j )R
for any j ∈ G i , because s ∗j ∈ G i and g j = 0. From equation (A8), x ∗j ≥
The two last inequalities imply
ej <
B
− 1.
(1 − ξ )R
e j +1
f (k ∗j )
− 1.
(A10)
e j +1
f (k ∗j −1)
By definition of x̂, we have x̂ j = x jA ( K̂ , s ∗ ) =
− 1. From (A10),
e j +1
f (k ∗j −1)
−
B
(1−ξ ) f (k ∗j −1)R
− 1, and therefore x̂ j < I ∗ (k ∗j − 1, 0, ξ, η). Consider now bank i
and recall that x̂i = xi∗ + j∈G i (x ∗j − x̂ j ). From equation (A9), we know that
1<
xi∗
+
j∈G i
We prove that
x ∗j
− x̂ j
mA + 1
≥ gi i − 1 +
∗
η ki f ki∗ R
j∈G i
m iA + 1
−1+
gi
∗
η ki f ki∗ R
j∈G i
ej + 1
− 1 − ej
f ki∗
≥
ej + 1
− 1 − ej .
f ki∗
B
−1
(1 − ξ )R
(A11)
B
because (1−ξ
− 1 ≥ (1−ξ ) f (kB ∗ −gi )R − 1 = I ∗ (ki∗ − gi , 0, ξ, η). Rearranging terms,
)R
i
equation (A11) is equivalent to
f ki∗ − 1
m iA + 1
B
(e j + 1).
gi
≥ (1 − ξ )R + f k ∗
∗
i
η ki f k ∗ R
j∈G
i
i
gi
∗
1
Note that m iA + 1 ≥ B and η ki f (ki∗ )R ≤ η n−1 ρ R. Thus,
m iA + 1
B
B
≥n
,
1
∗ ≥ n−1
(1 − ξ )R
η ρR
η f ki R
gi
ki∗
400
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
1
the last inequality being true for η n−1 ρ <
1−ξ
1+nρ
<
1−ξ
.
n
1−ξ
.
n
1
By assumption, η n−1 ρ <
1−ξ
,
1+nρ
with
Finally, we have
f ki∗ − 1
B
B
≥
+
(e j + 1),
n
(1 − ξ )R
(1 − ξ )R
f ki∗
j∈G
i
f (k ∗ )−1
B
given that f (ki ∗ )
j∈G i (e j + 1) < gi (n−1)R , because e j <
i
G i , and that gi ≤ (n − 1).
B
(1−ξ )R
− 1 for any j ∈
Expected total payoff. We need to prove that
m b ( K̂ , x̂, s ∗ ) + Mb ( K̂ , s ∗ ) −
m b (K ∗ , x ∗ , s ∗ ) + Mb (K ∗ , s ∗ ) =
b∈N
b∈N
= R f ki∗ − gi (x̂i + 1) − η f (ki∗ )R xi∗ + 1 +
+ξ
f (k ∗j − 1)R x̂ j + 1 − ξ
f (k ∗j )R x ∗j + 1 > 0,
gi
ki∗
j∈G i
j∈G i
e +1
1−ξ
for η < ( ρ(1+nρ)
)n−1 . Recall that x̂i = xi∗ + j∈G i (x ∗j − x̂ j ), where x̂ j = f (kj ∗ −1) − 1.
j
Rearranging terms, we have to prove that
gi
∗
∗ ∗
∗
ki∗
xi + 1 +
f ki − gi − ξ f k ∗j x ∗j −
f ki − gi − η f ki
j∈G i
f ki∗ − gi − ξ f k ∗j − 1 x̂ j > ξ
f k ∗j − f k ∗j − 1 .
−
j∈G i
j∈G i
First note that ki∗ = c∗ − 1 + gi ≥ c∗ ≥ k ∗j , where c∗ is the number of core banks.
f (k)
Given that ξ < η < f 1(1) , and that the ratio f (k+1)
is increasing in k— f is concave—
we have
f ki∗ − gi − ξ f k ∗j x ∗j ≥
f k ∗j − 1 − ξ f k ∗j x ∗j ≥ 0.
j∈G i
j∈G i
gi
∗
Furthermore, f (ki∗ − gi ) − η ki f (ki∗ ) > ξ
η
1
n−1
<
1−ξ
.
ρ(1+nρ)
So, it suffices to show that
j∈G i [
f (k ∗j ) − f (k ∗j − 1)] because ξ <
gi
∗
∗ ∗ ∗
ki∗
f ki − gi − η f ki xi >
f ki − gi − ξ f k ∗j − 1 x̂ j
to prove our claim.
j∈G i
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
gi
∗
1
B
We have (i) [ f (ki∗ − gi )] − η ki f (ki∗ ) ≥ (1 − η n−1 ρ); (ii) xi∗ ≥
∗
cause x satisfies the incentive constraint; (iii)
e j +1
f (k ∗j −1)
f (ki∗
− gi ) −
:
401
− 1, be-
1
(1−ξ )η n−1 ρ R
ξ f (k ∗j − 1) < ρ
for any
B
(1−ξ )R
j ∈ G i ; (iv) x̂ j =
− 1 ≤ ej <
− 1, given that by Proposition 3, bank
j chooses the risky project in autarky. Then the following inequality holds
gi
∗
1
∗
∗
∗
f ki − gi − η ki f ki xi ≥ 1 − η n−1 ρ
B
−1 >
1
(1 − ξ )η n−1 ρ R
B
> (n − 1)ρ
−1
(1 − ξ )R
f ki∗ − gi − ξ f k ∗j − 1 x̂ j ,
>
j∈G i
1
where the second inequality follows from the assumption η n−1 <
1−ξ
.
ρ(1+nρ)
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 6. Assume that (N , e) and η are given and that f is increasing
in k and satisfies the IPR property.
Assume first that mini∈N ei ≥ (1−ξB)ρ R − 1. We show that (K e , e, s e ) with K ie =
N \{i} and sie = r f for all i is a DEWT. The necessary condition it is straightforward
to check. Note that m i (K e , e, s e ) = ρ R(ei + 1) − 1 if K ie = N \{i} and sie = r f for
all i . First, we check that (K e , e, s e ) with K ie = N \{i} and sie = r f for all i is an
INE. Indeed, note that
ρ R(ei + 1) − 1 ≥ ξρ R(ei + 1) + B − 1
because ei ≥ (1−ξB)ρ R − 1 for all i and hence (K e , e, s e ) is an INE. We prove now
that there is no other INE ( K̂ , e, ŝ) that can yield a higher payoff m i ( K̂ , e, ŝ) to any
i ∈ N . We consider two cases: (i) If bank ŝi = r f , then
ĝi
m i (K e , e, s e ) = ρ R(ei + 1) − 1 ≥ η k̂i f (k̂i )R(ei + 1) − 1 = m i ( K̂ , e, ŝ),
because η < 1 and f (k̂i ) ≤ ρ. (ii) If bank ŝi = r , then
m i (K e , e, s e ) = ρ R(ei + 1) − 1 ≥ ξρ R(ei + 1) + B − 1
ĝi
≥ ξ η k̂i f (k̂i )R(ei + 1) + B − 1 = m i ( K̂ , e, ŝ),
because ei ≥ (1−ξB)ρ R − 1, η < 1, and f (k̂i ) ≤ ρ.
Hence, no bank i can strictly gain from deleting any link, either if the investment
decision is risky or risk-free after the deletion of the link. As K e is already complete,
no new links can be established. Hence, (K e , e, s e ) is pairwise stable without transfers.
Given that (K e , e, s e ) is INE and pairwise stable without transfers, it is a DEWT.
402
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
Assume now that maxi∈N ei <
then si = r for all i because
I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η) =
B
(1−ξ )ρ R
B
(1 − ξ )η
gi
ki
− 1. First note that if (K , e, s) is an INE,
−1≥
f (ki )R
B
−1
(1 − ξ )ρ R
given that η < 1 and f (ki ) ≤ ρ. Hence, (K e , e, s e ) with sie = r for all i is an INE.
We now check that if η f (1) ≥ 1, then (K e , e, s e ) with sie = r and K ie = N \{i} for
all i is the unique pairwise stable network without transfers, and hence the unique
DEWT. We prove that if two banks i and j are disconnected in an INE (K , e, s), they
always benefit from creating their connection. Indeed, given that (K , e, s) is an INE,
it has to be that s = r for all i. Take two banks i and j such that i ∈
/ K j (therefore,
j∈
/ K i ). We have that, if ki > 0, then
m i (K , e, s) = ξ η f (ki )R(ei + 1) + B − 1 < ξ η f (ki + 1)R(ei + 1) + B − 1
= m i (K ∪ {i, j}, e, s),
because in any INE sb = r for all b and f is increasing, and if k j > 0,
m i (K , e, s) = ξ η f (ki )R(ei + 1) + B − 1 < ξ η f (ki + 1)R(ei + 1) + B − 1
= m i (K ∪ {i, j}, e, s),
because in any INE sb = r for all b and f is increasing. This means that when banks
hold n − 2 connections they always benefit from creating the last one, and, turning
the argument around, they never benefit from breaking the last connection (i.e., they
prefer holding n − 1 connections than n − 2 ). In particular, no pair of banks has an
incentive to delete their link, and hence (K e , e, s e ) is pairwise stable without transfers
and therefore a DEWT. If ki = 0, then
m i (K , e, s) = ξ R(ei + 1) + B − 1 ≤ ξ η f (1)R(ei + 1) + B − 1
= m i (K ∪ {i, j}, e, s),
because η f (1) ≥ 1. Hence, bank i always gains from building new links and the same
argument can be applied to bank j. Given that two disconnected banks always benefit
from building their connection, the only pairwise stable allocation without transfers,
and hence the only DEWT, is (K e , e, s e ) with sie = r and K ie = N \{i} for all i.
We finally check that if η f (1) < 1, then there are two DEWT: (i) (K e , e, s e ) with
e
si = r and K ie = ∅ for all i (the empty network), or (ii) (K e , e, s e ) with sie = r
and K ie = N \{i} (the complete network). The complete network is pairwise stable
without transfers because, as argued just above, any bank i gains from creating a new
link as far as ki > 0, in particular whenever ki = n − 2, because f is increasing and
all banks are choosing the risky project in any INE.
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
403
In order to check that the empty network is also DEWT, we check that it is pairwise
stable without transfers if η f (1) ≤ 1. Indeed, if K i = ∅, then
m i (K , e, s) = ξ R(ei + 1) + B − 1 ≥ ξ η f (1)R(ei + 1) + B − 1
= m i (K ∪ {i, j}, e, s),
and no bank has a strict incentive to create the first link. Hence, (K e , e, s e ) with
sie = r and K ie = ∅ for all i is pairwise stable without transfers, and given that it is
also an INE, it is also a DEWT.
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 7. Assume by contradiction that (K e , e, s e ) is a DEWT, but
/ K ej , and therefore
there are two banks i and j such that sie = s ej = r f with i ∈
e
e
e
j∈
/ K i . We prove that (K ∪ i j, e, s ) is an INE and that both m i (K e ∪ i j, e, s e ) >
m i (K e , e, s e ) and m j (K e ∪ i j, e, s e ) > m j (K e , e, s e ), contradicting the fact that
(K e , e, s e ) is a PSWT, and therefore it cannot be a DEWT.
Note that, because (K e , e, s e ) is a DEWT, it has to be an INE. This means that ei ≥
∗
I (ki , gi , ξ, η) and e j ≥ I ∗ (k j , g j , ξ, η). Furthermore, it has to be I ∗ (ki , gi , ξ, η) ≥
I ∗ (ki + 1, gi , ξ, η) and I ∗ (k j , g j , ξ, η) ≥ I ∗ (k j + 1, g j , ξ, η) given that f (k) and
g
η k are increasing in k. This implies ei ≥ I ∗ (ki + 1, gi , ξ, η) and e j ≥ I ∗ (k j +
1, g j , ξ, η). Therefore, (K e ∪ i j, e, s e ) is also an INE. Finally, note that
gi
gi
m i (K e ∪ i j, e, s e ) = η ki +1 f (ki + 1)R(ei + 1) − 1 > η ki f (ki )R(ei + 1) − 1
= m i (K e , e, s e )
and
gj
gj
m j (K e ∪ i j, e, s e ) = η k j +1 f (k j + 1)R(e j + 1) − 1 > η k j f (k j )R(e j + 1) − 1
= m j (K e , e, s e )
g
because the functions f (k) and η k are increasing in k. Therefore, (K e , e, s e ) cannot
be a DEWT.
PROPOSITION 8 (General version). Assume thatmin ei < E < max ei and f (k) satisfies the IPR property. Let k(η) be as defined in (10). Then:
(i) If (K e , e, s e ) is a DEWT allocation, then kie < k(η) for some iimplies that
sie = r and k ej ≥ k(η) for all j ∈
/ K ie .
e
e
(ii) If (K , e, s ) is a DEWT allocation, then kie > k(η) only if G i = ∅.
COROLLARY OF PROPOSITION 8 (General version) (Proposition 8 in the text). Assume
that min ei < E < max ei and f (k) satisfies the IPR property. Let k(η) be as defined
in (10). Then
(i) If k(η) = n − 1, then K ie = N \{i} for all i ∈ N .
(ii) If k(η) = 0, then gie = 0 for all i.
404
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 8 (General version). The proof is based on Lemma A1. Assume
kie < k(η). This means that kie ≤ k(η) − 1, and by definition of k(η) and the fact that
f (kie ) k e +1
f (k) k+1
)
is increasing in k, we have η ≥ ( f (k e +1)
) i . Hence, bank i will
the ratio ( f (k+1)
i
gain if connecting to any other bank j ∈
/ K ie , no matter j’s strategy. Therefore, K e
can be a pairwise stable structure only if there is no other bank j willing to connect to
bank i. If bank i is choosing the risk-free project, any bank not yet connected to bank
i would be better off by connecting to it. Therefore, if sie = r f , then K ie = N \{i}.
This is a contradiction with ki < k(η) ≤ n − 1. If sie = r , it has to be that no other
bank j not connected to bank i could be better off from connecting to bank i. This
/ K ie , given that any bank j would
could only happen if k ej ≥ k(η) for any bank j ∈
e
like to connect with bank i if k j < k(η).
Assume that kie > k(η) for some bank i. This means that kie ≥ k(η) + 1, and by
f (k) k+1
)
is increasing in k, we know
definition of k(η) and the fact that the ratio ( f (k+1)
f (k e −1)
e
that η < ( f (ki e ) )ki . This means that bank i is better off if it unilaterally disconnects
i
any of its links with banks investing in the risky project. So, the allocation (K e , e, s e )
can only be PSWT if G i = ∅.
PROOF OF COROLLARY OF PROPOSITION 8 (General version). Substituting k(η) by its
extreme values in the general version of Proposition 8, we obtain the statements. The
arguments used are similar to the ones used in the proof of Proposition 4 and can
therefore be omitted.
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 9. Given the definition of Q, we have
Q = i such that I ∗ (ki ,
gi , ξ, η) ≤ xi < I ∗ (ki ,
gi + qi , ξ, η) ,
where
gi is the number of banks in K i \Q that choose the gambling project, and qi
is the minimum number of banks in Q connected to bank i that, by choosing the
gambling project, would make bank i switch from the risk-free project to the gambling
project. Note that 1 ≤ qi ≤ |K i ∩ Q|. Namely, qi has to be at least one, otherwise
bank i will always choose the gambling project and would not belong to Q(s, s ′ ).
Furthermore, qi has to be at most Q ∪ K i , that is, the number of banks in Q that are
connected to bank i. Otherwise, bank i will always choose the risk-free project and
would not belong to Q(s, s ′ ). Assume that the sequential-move investment game calls
bank i to make the investment decision (given the choices of banks Q.) If history in
the game is such that qi banks in Q connected to bank i choose the gambling project,
bank i chooses the gambling project as well. If history in the game is such that there
are less than qi banks in Q connected to bank i choosing the gambling project, bank
i chooses the safe project. But if history is such that if by choosing the safe project
there are less than qi , say, c1 banks choosing the gambling project in Q and if by
choosing the gambling project there are more than qi , say, c2 banks choosing the
gambling project, bank i chooses the gambling asset only if
η
gi +c1
ki
f (ki )R(xi + 1) − 1 < ξ η
gi +c2
ki
f (ki )R(xi + 1) + B − 1,
(A12)
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
405
where c1 < qi ≤ c2 . The previous inequality implies
B
xi <
1 − ξη
c2 −c1
ki
η
gi +c1
ki
− 1,
(A13)
f (ki )R
a contradiction with the fact that
B
xi ≥
(1 − ξ )η
gi +c1
ki
f (ki )R
− 1 = I ∗ (ki ,
gi , ξ, η),
given that c1 banks in |Q ∩ K i | are not enough to make bank i switching from the
safe project to the gambling one.
This implies that every time a bank is critical in the rule of order to decide among
different continuation paths, it will choose the safe path. Then we can conclude that
for any rule of order, the sequential-move investment game selects the INE profiles
where the highest number of banks choose the risk-free project.
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 10. Recall that xi = ei + ti ≥ 0. Assume bank i is considering
to make a transfer ti . Denote by j one bank (there might be many) that receives
a transfer t j to be induced to choose the risk-free project. Therefore, x j = e j +
∗
t j ≥ I ∗ (k j , g j , ξ, η). Given that xi ≥ 0,
it has to be that xi + x j ≥ BI (k j , g j , ξ, η) >
B
− 1. Clearly, xi + x j ≤ E = i∈N ei . Thus, for E < (1−ξ )ρ R − 1, there is
(1−ξ )ρ R
no transfer ti that can induce bank j to invest in the risk-free project, no matter
B
the values of xi or x j . This happens when ξ > 1 − ρ R(E+1)
. We have ξ = max{1 −
B
, 0}.
ρ R(E+1)
LITERATURE CITED
Acemoglu, Daron, Asuman Ozdaglar, and Alireza Tahbaz-Salehi. (2014) “Systemic Risk in
Endogenous Financial Networks.” Columbia Business School Research Paper No. 15–17.
Acemoglu, Daron, Asuman Ozdaglar, and Alireza Tahbaz-Salehi. (2015) “Systemic Risk and
Stability in Financial Networks.” American Economic Review, 105, 564–608.
Afonso, Gara, Anna Kovner, and Antoinette Schoar. (2011) “Stressed, not Frozen: The Federal
Funds Market in the Financial Crisis.” Journal of Finance, 66, 1109–39.
Allen, Franklin, and Ana Babus. (2009) “Networks in Finance.” In The Network Challenge,
edited by Paul R. Kleindorfer, Jerry Wind, and Robert E. Gunther, pp. 367–82. Upper Saddle
River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Allen, Franklin, Ana Babus, and Elena Carletti. (2012) “Asset Commonality, Debt Maturity
and Systemic Risk.” Journal of Financial Economics, 104, 519–34.
Allen, Franklin, and Douglas Gale. (2000) “Financial Contagion.” Journal of Political Economy, 108, 1–33.
Babus, Ana. (2016) “The Formation of Financial Networks.” RAND Journal of Economics,
47, 239–72.
406
:
MONEY, CREDIT AND BANKING
Bech, Morten, and Enghin Atalay. (2010) “The Topology of the Federal Funds Market.”
Physica A, 389, 5223–46.
Bloch, Francis, Garance Genicot, and Debraj Ray. (2008) “Informal Insurance in Social
Networks.” Journal of Economic Theory, 143, 36–58.
Bloch, Francis, and Matthew O. Jackson. (2006) “Definitions of Equilibrium in Network
Formation Games.” International Journal of Game Theory, 34, 305–18.
Bloch, Francis, and Matthew O. Jackson. (2007) “The Formation of Networks with Transfers
among Players.” Journal of Economic Theory, 133, 83–110.
Boss, Michael, Helmut Elsinger, Martin Summer, and Stefan Thurner. (2004) “Network Topology of the Interbank Market.” Quantitative Finance, 4, 1–8.
Bramoullé, Yann, and Rachel Kranton. (2007) “Risk Sharing Networks.” Journal of Economic
Behavior and Organization, 64, 275–94.
Brusco, Sandro, and Fabio Castiglionesi. (2007) “Liquidity Coinsurance, Moral Hazard and
Financial Contagion.” Journal of Finance, 62, 2275–2302.
Caballero, Ricardo J., and Alp Simsek. (2013) “Fire Sales in a Model of Complexity.” Journal
of Finance, 68, 2549–87.
Cabrales, Antonio, Piero Gottardi, and Fernando Vega-Redondo. (2016) “Risk-sharing and
Contagion in Networks.” Review of Financial Studies, 30, 3086–127.
Calvó-Armengol, Antoni, and Rahmi Ilkilic. (2009) “Pairwise-stability and Nash Equilibria in
Network Formation.” International Journal of Game Theory, 38, 51–79.
Castiglionesi, Fabio, and Mario Eboli. (2018) “Liquidity Flows in Interbank Networks.” Review
of Finance, 22, 1291–1334.
Castiglionesi, Fabio, Fabio Feriozzi, and Guido Lorenzoni. (2019) “Financial Integration and
Liquidity Crises.” Management Science, 65, 955–77.
Castiglionesi, Fabio, and Wolf Wagner. (2013) “On the Efficiency of Bilateral Interbank
Insurance.” Journal of Financial Intermediation, 22, 177–200.
Cocco, Joao, Francisco Gomes, and Nuno Martins. (2009) “Lending Relationships in the
Interbank Market.” Journal of Financial Intermediation, 18, 24–48.
Craig, Ben, and Goetz von Peter. (2014) “Interbank Tiering and Money Center Banks.” Journal
of Financial Intermediation, 23, 322–47.
Elliott, Matthew, Benjamin Golub, and Matthew O. Jackson. (2014) “Financial Networks and
Contagion.” American Economic Review, 104, 3115–53.
Embree, Lana, and Tom Roberts. (2009) “Network Analysis and Canada’s Large Value Transfer
System.” Bank of Canada Discussion Paper No. 2009–13.
Farboodi, Miryam. (2017) “Intermediation and Voluntary Exposure to Counterparty Risk.”
Manuscript, Princeton University.
Freixas, Xavier, Bruno M. Parigi and Jean-Charles Rochet. (2000) “Systemic Risk, Interbank
Relations and Liquidity Provision by the Central Bank.” Journal of Money, Credit and
Banking, 32, 611–38.
Furfine, Craig. (2001) “Banks as Monitors of Other Banks: Evidence from the Overnight
Federal Funds Market.” Journal of Business, 74, 33–57.
Furfine, Craig. (2002) “The Interbank Market During a Crisis.” European Economic Review,
46, 809–20.
FABIO CASTIGLIONESI AND NOEMI NAVARRO
:
407
Heider, Florian, Marie Hoerova, and Cornelia Holthausen. (2015) “Liquidity Hoarding and
Interbank Market Spreads: the Role of Counterparty Risk.” Journal of Financial Economics,
118, 336–54.
Holmström, Bengt, and Jean Tirole. (1997) “Financial Intermediation Loanable Funds and the
Real Sector.” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112, 663–91.
Inaoka, Hajime, Takuto Ninomiya, Tokiko Shimizu, Hideki Takayasu, and Ken Taniguchi.
(2004) “Fractal Network Derived from Banking Transaction – An Analysis of Network
Structures Formed by Financial Institutions.” Bank of Japan Working Paper No. 04-E-04.
Jackson, Matthew O., and Asher Wolinsky. (1996) “A Strategic Model of Social and Economic
Networks.” Journal of Economic Theory, 71, 44–74.
King, Thomas. (2008) “Discipline and Liquidity in the Interbank Market.” Journal of Money,
Credit, and Banking, 40, 295–317.
Leitner, Yaron. (2005) “Financial Networks: Contagion, Commitment, and Private Sector
Bailouts.” Journal of Finance, 6, 2925–53.
Langfield, Sam, Zijun Liu, and Tomohiro Ota. (2014) “Mapping the UK Interbank System.”
Journal of Banking and Finance, 45, 288–303.
Malherbe, Frederic. (2014) “Self-Fulfilling Liquidity Dry-Ups.” Journal of Finance, 69, 947–
70.
Morrison, Alan, and Lucy White. (2005) “Crises and Capital Requirements in Banking.”
American Economic Review, 95, 1548–72.
Soramäki, Kimmo, Morten Bech, Jeffrey Arnold, Robert J. Glass, and Walter E. Beyeler.
(2007) “The Topology of Interbank Payment Flows.” Physica A, 379, 317–33.
Wagner, Wolf. (2011) “Systemic Liquidation Risk and the Diversity-Diversification Tradeoff.”
Journal of Finance, 66, 1141–75.
Zawadowski, Adam. (2013) “Entangled Financial Systems.” Review of Financial Studies, 26,
1291–1323.