Philos Stud (2021) 178:3421–3441
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01607-2
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
Samuel Kimpton-Nye1
Accepted: 19 January 2021 / Published online: 3 February 2021
The Author(s) 2021, corrected publication 2021
Abstract Dispositional Essentialism is a unified anti-Humean account of the
metaphysics of low-level physical properties and laws of nature. In this paper, I
articulate the view that I label Canonical Dispositional Essentialism (CDE), which
comprises a structuralist metaphysics of properties and an account of laws as
relations in the property structure. I then present an alternative anti-Humean account
of properties and laws (still somewhat in the dispositional essentialist spirit). This
account rejects CDE’s structuralist metaphysics of properties in favour of a view of
properties as qualitative grounds of dispositions and it rejects CDE’s view of laws as
relations in favour of a view of laws as features of an efficient description of
possible property distributions. I then defend this view over CDE on the grounds
that it can overcome an explanatory shortcoming of CDE and that it achieves a level
of continuity with science that CDE fails to achieve. The upshot of this paper is a
significant narrowing of the range of possibilities in which the absolutely best
unified account of laws and properties resides.
1 Introduction
Scientific theorizing and the discovery of fundamental properties have gone
hand in hand. For instance the discovery of the phenomena of electromagnetism and the laws governing them was inseparable from the discovery of the
previously unknown, and very likely fundamental, properties of positive and
negative charge (Lewis 2009, 205).
& Samuel Kimpton-Nye
[email protected];
[email protected]
1
University of Bristol, Cotham House, Bristol BS6 6JL, UK
123
3422
S. Kimpton-Nye
There are (at least) three important questions for the metaphysician of science
concerning properties and laws of nature:
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
How should we understand the metaphysics of properties?
How should we understand the metaphysics of laws of nature?
How should we understand the relationship between properties and laws?
Since, as Lewis suggests, the formulation of laws has gone hand in hand with the
discovery of properties, we might expect an answer to any one of these questions to
inform, and be informed by, answers to the others; one might expect to be able to
provide a unified account in response the three questions above.
Lewis’s Humean Supervenience (HS) is perhaps the most influential such account.
According to HS, the world consists of a vast array of properties of, or instantiated at,
point-sized regions of space–time (Lewis 1986, ix). Re question (i), properties,
according to HS, are quiddities; they have no essential features other than primitive selfidentity and distinctness from other properties. Crucially, this means that properties do
not stand in or induce any necessary connections between distinct existences. Perhaps
ours is a world in which everything that instantiates the property F also instantiates the
property G. But this does not entail, according to HS, that there is any necessary
connection between the properties F and G or between their instances. Re question (ii),
laws are features of a particularly efficient description of the spatiotemporal distribution
of fundamental properties. Laws neither pick out nor induce any necessary connections.
And re question (iii), the relationship between laws and properties is that of
supervenience—there can be no change in the laws without a change in the
spatiotemporal arrangement of quiddistic properties, and (significant) difference in
the distribution of properties would be accompanied by a difference in the laws.
Critics have found dissatisfaction with all aspects of HS. First consider
quidditism, on this view, it is no part of the essence of charge, for example, that
like charges repel. Like charges repel in this world, but in other worlds charged
objects may behave very differently because the true nature of charge has nothing to
do with the behaviours/dispositions of charged objects that physics discovers. This
has led some to object that HS makes properties unknowable in principle and that it
is guilty of violating its own naturalistic motivations by positing more structure to
the world than physics has use for (see, e.g., Blackburn 1990, 63; Molnar 1999; Bird
2007; Vetter 2015, 8).1 On the laws side, it might be objected that laws, according to
HS, are not sufficiently modally robust. Since HS laws depend on the thoroughly
contingent arrangement of matters of particular fact, there will be cases in which
altering matters of fact will alter the laws. As Bird discusses (Bird 2007, 81–86),
this leads to some very counterintuitive results because there are situations in which
‘‘a law can be removed just by preventing certain interactions’’ (2007, 84).
Relatedly, it has been objected that HS gets the order of explanation between laws
and property distributions the wrong way around. One might think that laws should
explain the spatiotemporal distribution of properties. However, according to HS, the
1
Lewis’s stated motivation for Humean Supervenience was to ‘‘resist philosophical arguments that there
are more things in heaven and earth than physics has dreamt of’’ (Lewis 1994, 474).
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3423
distribution of properties explains the laws (see, e.g., Armstrong 1983; Bird 2007,
86; Maudlin 2007, 172; Lange 2013).
These problems for HS form a large part of the motivation for Dispositional
Essentialism (DE). Dispositional essentialists typically provide very different
answers to questions (i)–(iii). Roughly speaking, the dispositional essentialist denies
quidditism and maintains that the dispositions associated with properties and
discovered by physics are essential to those properties. Laws of nature are then
understood as flowing from the essences of properties and hence as being necessary
(conditional on the existence of the relevant properties). And laws can be
understood as apt to play a governing role; according to Bird: ‘‘Laws […] supervene
on potencies […]. Indeed, it is not obvious that this supervenience relation prevents
laws from having at least an explanatory function, and, depending on what you think
‘governing’ amounts to, perhaps a governing role also.’’ Bird argues in some detail
(2007, 195–98) against Mumford’s claim that dispositional essentialism precludes
laws from playing a governing role. But the main point is that laws, according to
DE, are thought to be capable of properly explaining property distributions.
DE is thus advertised as avoiding the epistemological and methodological
problems induced by quidditism, as rendering the laws sufficiently modal robust and
able to explain property distributions, all in an attractively reductive package: at the
fundamental level we have just essentially dispositional properties, in terms of
which the laws are explained.
More needs to be said, however, about the details of DE. In particular, more
needs to be said about what, exactly, it might mean for properties to be essentially
dispositional and about what it means for laws to flow from the essences of
properties. In the next section, I’ll outline a particularly influential way of fleshing
out these basic ideas behind DE, the view that I call Canonical Dispositional
Essentialism (CDE). In Sect. 3 I will present an alternative to CDE, which provides
its own distinctive set of answers to questions (i)–(iii). In Sects. 4 and 5, I will
defend this alternative by arguing, respectively, that it is explanatorily superior to
CDE and that it achieves a greater degree of continuity with science than CDE does.
What also comes out in Sects. 4 and 5 is an argument that the particular unified
account of laws and properties that I defend is not merely superior to CDE, but is
superior to any other combination of the accounts of properties and laws discussed
in this paper. There are other accounts of the metaphysics of laws and properties
available in the literature that are not explicitly discussed here. So, I cannot claim on
the basis of the arguments in this paper to have discerned the absolutely best unified
account of laws and properties. Nevertheless, what this paper does show is the broad
outline of what an absolutely best unified account will look like. While some of the
finer details may be open to tweaking, I hope to have significantly narrowed the
range of possibilities in which the absolutely best account resides and I hope to
focus future attention on developing not just an account of laws or properties in
isolation, but the optimal laws-properties unification.
123
3424
S. Kimpton-Nye
2 Canonical Dispositional Essentialism
According to the canonical version of DE (CDE), the essences of fundamental
physical properties (properties from now on) are exhausted by the modal relations
in which they stand to other properties and hence have their identities metaphysically determined by their position in a structure of such relations among properties.
Call this property structuralism. The canonical view then identifies laws of nature
with arcs in the property structure. This version of DE is explicitly endorsed by
Chakravartty (2003a; 2007) and is the view towards which Bird (2007) is most
inclined. I’ll use this section to articulate these ideas in more detail.
2.1 Property structuralism
The basic dispositional essentialist idea regarding the metaphysics of properties is
that properties are essentially dispositional. This is often contrasted with quidditism
according to which any given property, P, is just essentially self-identical and
distinct from other properties and, hence, any connection between properties and
dispositions is thoroughly contingent. But what, exactly, does it mean to say that
properties are essentially dispositional?
Take the property fragility as an example (it doesn’t matter for present purposes
that fragility is not fundamental, it’s just an easy example to work with). Fragility
disposes its bearers to shatter. The property shattering is the manifestation of
fragility. So, let’s say that the two properties, fragility and shattering stand in the
manifestation relation (M-relation), which is a modal relation because a fragile
object is disposed to shatter even if in fact it never does shatter. Now, to say that the
property fragility is essentially dispositional is to say that the M-relation between
fragility and shattering is part of the essence of fragility, and, hence, that in any
possible world, for any individual x, if x is fragile x will be disposed to manifest
shattering. Bird also talks about the stimulus conditions of essentially dispositional
properties; fragility disposes its bearers to shatter when stressed. So, the property of
being stressed is the stimulus of fragility and shattering its manifestation, on Bird’s
view. In which case we might say that the properties stressed, fragility and
shattering stand in the stimulus-response (SR) relation. For simplicity in what
follows, however, I’ll just talk about the manifestations of dispositional properties,
and hence about M-relations instead of SR-relations. But nothing of importance here
hinges on this decision and the argument would be unchanged by substituting ‘‘Mrelations’’ for ‘‘SR-relations’’ throughout.2
Now, according to property structuralism (endorsed by, e.g., Bird (2007),
Chakravartty (2003a; 2007) and Mumford (2004)) the essences of all properties (all
2
It is worth noting, however, that Vetter (2015, chap. 2) has argued forcefully against understanding
dispositional properties in terms of their stimulus and manifestation conditions, suggesting instead that
dispositional properties be understood in terms of manifestations alone. Relatedly, Vetter defends the idea
that the modality with which dispositions are most fundamentally associated is metaphysical possibility. I
follow Vetter in this respect.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3425
fundamental properties, for Bird) are exhausted by the M-relations in which they
stand to other properties:
[T]he [structuralist] 3 wants the essences and hence identities of her entities to
be determined relationally rather than purely intrinsically. (Bird 2007, 139).
A causal property may be identified as the property that it is in virtue of its
relations to other properties. (Chakravartty 2003a, 394).
[A property is] nothing more than a set of connections to, and causal powers
for, other properties. (Mumford 2004 , 185).
So, fragility and shattering stand in the M-relation. But these properties will also
stand in other M-relations to other properties, which, in turn, stand in further
M-relations to further properties and so on and so forth. Properties and the
M-relations that they enter into, make up a vast network, or structure and a
property’s essence, and hence identity, is exhausted by the M-relations in which it
stands to other properties, according to the property structuralist. In other words, any
given property P has its identity fixed by its place in the structure. Properties are
metaphysically (as opposed to cognitively or epistemically) individuated by their
position in the structure of modal relations among properties.
2.2 Laws in CDE
A key motivation for positing essentially dispositional properties is the desire to use
those properties to provide a metaphysical explanation of the laws of nature (‘‘One
of the nicest features of DIT [the dispositional identity thesis of properties] (and an
ulterior motive for recommending it) is that it yields an intuitive account of laws’’
(Chakravartty 2007, 141)).4 Dispositional essentialism has been offered in response
to the problems faced by best systems analyses of laws (e.g., Lewis 1994, 2001) and
nomic necessitation accounts (e.g., Dretske 1977; Tooley 1977; Armstrong 1999).
The former, it has been argued, do not endow the laws with the necessity and
metaphysical ‘‘oomph’’ and hence explanatory power that we take them to have, and
the latter render the laws mysterious external governing forces.
So, what, exactly, are the laws of nature, according to the structuralist? Both
Chakravartty and Bird have expressed the view that laws are relations between
properties. The following remarks are representative of Chakravartty’s view:
[N]ot only are laws composed of relations between causal properties; they
distinguish and identify properties as well. (2003a, 394).
In a world inhabited by different causal properties, the relations we would
there describe as causal laws would be, ipso facto, different as well. (2003a,
402).
Causal laws are never vacuous in principle, given that they are relations
between causal properties. (2003a, 405).
3
Bird calls his structuralist view of properties dispositional monism.
4
This does not apply to Mumford, who argues that essentially dispositional properties obviate the need
for laws.
123
3426
S. Kimpton-Nye
Causal laws are nothing more than relations between casual properties. (2007,
150).
In each of these quotes, Chakravartty clearly endorses a view of laws as relations
between properties.
Now consider the following remarks from Bird, also concerning the nature of
laws:
If properties have a dispositional essence then certain relations will hold of
necessity between the relevant universals; these relations we may identify with
the laws of nature. (Bird 2007, 43).
[L]aws are general relations among properties. (Bird 2007, 200).
[L]aws are general relationships. (Bird 2007, 202).
[L]aws reflect the essential rather than accidental features of potencies and
kinds. (Bird 2007, 202).
Since laws flow from the essences of potencies, they must hold in every
possible world. (Bird 2007, 5) (where by ‘‘potencies’’ Bird means fundamental, essentially dispositional, properties).
In the first three quotes above, Bird explicitly states that laws are relationships
between properties. In the last two quotes, Bird says that the laws flow from the
essences of properties. Since, according to Bird’s property structuralism, property
essences are exhausted by relations to other properties, we can reasonably interpret
the last two quotes as also claiming that laws are relationships between properties.
To be precise, if laws are to be understood as relations, they should be understood
as modal relations; they have implications for what would or could be the case under
certain circumstances. There is no law requiring that a fragile object actually
manifests shattering—an object can be fragile and never shatter—but it is plausibly
a nomological fact that a fragile object, x, would shatter under the right
circumstances. So, a law can relate properties even if one of the properties related
is not actually instantiated. (See Chakravartty (2007, chap. 5) for more on this in
connection with the dispositional essentialist treatment of vacuous laws).
M-relations, that is, arcs in the property structuralist’s structure,5 are modal
relations among properties, which (exhaustively) constitute the essences of those
properties. Hence, it seems fair to attribute to Chakravartty and to Bird, both of
whom explicitly endorse a structuralist metaphysics of properties and the idea that
laws flow from the essences of properties, the view that M-relations just are laws.
Chakravartty adds further plausibility to this interpretation of CDE when he says:
‘‘If the identity of a property is determined by the relations of which it is capable, as
described by law statements, then citing these law statements is a necessary
precondition for picking out or identifying properties.’’ (2007, 134).
Earlier I said that there is work to be done in order to precisify the core
dispositional essentialist tenets that properties are essentially dispositional and that
laws flow from the essences of properties. The canonical precisification of these
5
M-relations will likely be directed; shattering is the manifestation of fragility, and not vice versa.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3427
ideas results from combining a structuralist metaphysics of properties, in the sense
discussed in Sect. 2.1., with a view of laws as identical with the M-relations that
make up the property structure, in the sense discussed here in Sect. 2.2. Canonical
Dispositional Essentialism (CDE) earns its canonical status, I suggest, because of
the prominence of its main proponents (Bird and Chakravartty) in the development
of DE in general and because it seems to be the most thorough fleshing out of the
dispositional essentialist ideas about the metaphysics of laws and properties and the
relation in which properties and laws stand to each other.
3 Reconsidering the Canon
I will now present an alternative set of answers, still somewhat in the dispositional
essentialist spirit, to questions (i)–(iii) about the metaphysics of properties, laws of
nature and the relationship between the two. I’ll call this alternative unified answer
to (i)–(iii) qualitative dispositional essentialism (QDE).6 Then, in Sect. 4, I’ll
motivate QDE by showing that it can overcome an explanatory deficiency for CDE
before, in Sect. 5, arguing that QDE is continuous with science in a way that CDE is
not.
3.1 QDE properties—the grounding view
In answer to question (i), ‘‘how should we understand the metaphysics of
properties?’’ QDE pursues a middle ground between the quidditism of HS and the
structuralism of CDE. With CDE and against HS, QDE posits necessary connections
between properties and dispositions, so, for example, according to QDE, there is no
possible world in which like charges are not disposed to repel each other. But with
HS and against CDE, QDE denies that the essences of properties are constituted by
the dispositional relations in which they stand. QDE denies property structuralism
and maintains that properties are self-individuating qualities, where qualities are not
metaphysically dependent upon a structure or upon any relations in which they may
stand.
In order to account for the different behaviours/dispositions associated with
different properties, QDE properties ought not be understood as ‘bare quiddities’
where there is nothing more to say about what distinguishes different bare quiddities
than that they are numerically distinct. Rather, properties should be understood as
‘thick’ or ‘qualitative’ quiddities (see Hildebrand (2016)), where different
qualitative quiddities are distinguished by their different qualitative natures, and
the fact that different properties are associated with different dispositions is thus
accounted for in terms of their different qualitative natures (see Tugby (2020),
6
The name is borrowed from Tugby (2012). Tugby uses ‘‘QDE’’ to refer just to an account of the
metaphysics of properties that he argues is able to overcome a problem raised by Barker and Smart (2012)
against property structuralism. I also endorse this account of properties and for similar reasons to those
discussed by Tugby. But in this paper, I will use ‘‘QDE’’ more broadly to refer to the combination of the
aforementioned account of properties and a BSA-type account of laws.
123
3428
S. Kimpton-Nye
Hildebrand (2016), Smith (2016)). In practice, it may be difficult to say anything
more about the qualitative differences between low-level properties, such as charge
and mass, than that they are there and account for the different dispositions
conferred by the different properties. But this view of properties is nonetheless
justified on the basis of the explanatory work it is capable of (more on this in
Sect. 4).
In order to secure the necessary connections between properties and dispositions,
e.g., between charge and the disposition to exert a repulsive force on like charges,
QDE maintains that properties fully ground dispositions, so, following Tugby
(2020), I will call this view of properties the grounding view. Coupled with the
plausible idea that grounding is necessitating in the sense that if X fully grounds Y,
then it is metaphysically necessary that Y exists if X exists (prominent defenders of
grounding necessitarianism include Fine (2015), Dasgupta (2014) and Trogdon
(2013)), this yields necessary connections between properties and the dispositions
that they fully ground. We may still envisage the very same structure of
manifestation relations as that envisaged in CDE. But whereas, in CDE, the
structure metaphysically individuates and hence grounds properties, in QDE,
properties are self-individuating grounds of the structure.7
Smith (2016) identifies two kinds of quidditism: I-quidditism and R-quidditism.
This distinction helps to shed further light on the grounding view of QDE and its
standing in relation to the quidditism of HS and the structuralism of CDE.
According to I-quidditism, properties are individuated independently of their
theoretical roles or any dispositions/causal powers with which they may be
associated (see Smith 2016, 239). And according to R-quidditism, ‘‘there are no
restrictions on the recombination of properties in metaphysically possible worlds’’
(Smith 2016, 240). The present suggestion, that properties are qualities that fully
ground and hence are necessarily connected with dispositions, is inconsistent with
R-quidditism but is consistent with I-quidditism. HS is consistent with both
I-quidditism and R-quidditism and CDE is inconsistent with both I-quidditism and
R-quidditism.
3.2 QDE Laws—the BSA
In answer to question (ii) about the metaphysics of laws, one could combine the
QDE account of properties with a view of laws as arcs in the structure of relations
that those properties ground. To take this route would be to stick as close as possible
to the CDE conception of laws. However, for reasons that I shall discuss in Sect. 5,
QDE, as I define it, includes something far closer to the HS account of laws.
Roughly speaking, then, QDE results from combining a view of properties as
qualitative grounds of dispositions with a view of laws as features of a description of
possible spatiotemporal distributions of property instances. I’ll elaborate briefly.
7
This account of properties is just the view of properties that Tugby (2012) defends in response to an
explanatory problem for property structuralism (see Barker and Smart 2012; Barker 2013) – more on this
later.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3429
HS, as defended by Lewis, comprises the best systems analysis of the laws of
nature (BSA). According to the BSA, laws are the axioms of a deductive
systematization of all information about the spatiotemporal locations of properties.
Strength and simplicity of such a systematization trade off: a very strong system
could just list the spatiotemporal location of every property instance. But this would
be incredibly complicated and unwieldy. A simpler system might provide fewer,
more general statements about the spatiotemporal distribution of properties, from
which we could deduce additional information not explicitly given. The optimal
system is one that maximises the virtues of strength and simplicity.8 The laws,
according to the BSA, are the axioms of this optimal system (see, e.g., Lewis (1973;
1983)).
QDE includes an account of laws very much like the BSA of HS. However,
instead of just systematizing the spatiotemporal distributions of properties at the
actual world, laws, according to the QDE-BSA, are axioms of the strongest,
simplest systematization of actual and metaphysically possible property distributions (see, Demarest (2017) and Kimpton-Nye (2017) for more detailed articulations
of this idea).
The motivation for systematizing metaphysically possible property distributions
as well as the actual distribution of properties is roughly as follows. QDE shares
with CDE the desire to imbue the laws of nature with necessity so that it may
overcome the problems for HS that arise given a view of the laws as thoroughly
contingent. By systematizing all metaphysically possible distributions of properties,
the laws are rendered metaphysically necessary. There are some options regarding
alien properties9: (i) laws may be indexed to sets of world that share properties
(Kimpton-Nye (2017) defends this on epistemological grounds), (ii) alien properties
may be deemed metaphysically impossible (there may be good naturalistic
motivations for this), or (iii) laws may concern worlds that include alien properties,
but these would be laws we cannot know about. On any of these options, laws come
out necessary because they concern the space of possible property distributions,
which is itself necessary assuming that what is possible is necessarily possibly as
per S5 modal logic. But I would be inclined to recommend option (i) or (ii) to ensure
the epistemic accessibility of laws.
QDE also shares with CDE the desire to provide a reductive account of natural
laws in terms of modally ‘‘oomphy’’ physical properties. Properties, according to
QDE, are metaphysically necessarily connected with certain dispositions because
they fully ground those dispositions (given the plausible assumption that grounds
necessitate what they fully ground). On the plausible assumption that the modality
with which dispositions are associated is metaphysical possibility (see, e.g., Vetter
(2015) for an extensive and compelling defence of this idea), QDE properties can
thus be understood as metaphysically determining various possibilities and, in
particular, as determining the full range of metaphysically possible property
distributions. It follows that the best systematization of all possible property
8
For simplicity, I omit discussion of fit.
9
Thanks to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to mention this issue.
123
3430
S. Kimpton-Nye
distributions is, in turn, metaphysically determined by the properties. So, given the
QDE-BSA, the laws of nature are necessary and are metaphysically explained by
the modally oomphy properties, in keeping with the spirit of dispositional
essentialism. In the remainder of this paper I will defend the QDE laws-properties
package just articulated.
4 In Defence of QDE—explanation
In response to a question about why opium puts patients to sleep, Bachelerius, a
prospective doctor of medicine in Molière’s Le Malade Imaginaire, says that ‘‘there
is a dormitive virtue in it, whose nature it is to make the senses drowsy.’’ This
answer, given by Bachelerius in his viva voce examination, is received enthusiastically by his examiners, much to the amusement of the audience.
Bachelerius’ humorously bad explanation seems to turn on paraphrasing the
explanandum—opium’s ability to put patients to sleep—as dormitive virtue, which
is then said to be part of the nature of opium. But it does not suffice as an
explanation of why opium puts people to sleep to be told that it is in the nature of
opium to put people to sleep. The purported explanation appears to just tell us what
we already know, albeit phrased slightly differently.
CDE succumbs to a similar explanatory pitfall—laws/M-relations are said to
constitute the essences of properties, and properties are said to explain the laws of
nature. So, for example, in response to the question ‘‘why do charged objects
interact in accordance with Coulomb’s law?’’, the CDE answer would be (roughly)
‘‘because Coulomb’s law is part of the essence of the property charge’’. But an
explanation of laws in terms of properties according to which it is part of the
essence of properties that those laws hold seems as dissatisfying as Bachelerius’
‘‘explanation’’ of opium’s ability to make a patient sleep in terms of its dormitive
virtue.
In this section, I’ll precisify this worry with an argument to the conclusion that
CDE laws and properties symmetrically ground each other, which makes the
explanation of laws in terms of properties circular. I’ll explain how QDE does better
by breaking this symmetry and providing a properly reductive picture. I’ll also
argue (in 4.2) that DE’s explanatory aspirations cannot be satisfied just by
identifying laws with regularities (the point holds whether regularities are
understood as things in the world or descriptions) as opposed to M-relations, i.e.,
problems remain for the combination of a structuralist view of properties and a BSA
account of laws.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3431
4.1 Symmetrically grounded laws and properties in CDE
As discussed in Sect. 2.1, CDE posits a structure of M-relations. One question that
we may ask is what (if anything) grounds this structure? Yates (2018) talks about
properties, on the structuralist conception, as composing a structure:
[Structuralism]10 require[s] that entities can be individuated by their places in
a structure composed by the entities themselves. (Yates 2018, 4543).
In [structuralism], powers are fully individuated by their places in a typecasual structure fully composed of powers. (Yates 2018, 4544).
Granting that properties compose the structure, and that composition is a grounding
relation, it follows that properties ground the structure.
However, one might object to the idea that properties ground structure given that
the option remains to posit the structure as an ungrounded primitive entity. The
main precedent for this idea is ontic structural realism (OSR). According to OSR,
individuals are eliminated from the ontology in favour of an ontologically primitive
relational structure (e.g., French and Ladyman 2003; Ladyman et al. 2007). Prima
facie talk about individuals is then understood as merely abstracting from the
fundamental relational structure. Since, on this view, structure is all there is, it
certainly is not the case that the structure ontologically depends on anything else.
Perhaps, then, the structuralist about properties could say something similar,
namely, that a relational structure is all there is to properties, in which case it would
be false to say that this structure ontologically depends on properties, or anything
else. However, this interpretation of structuralism about properties shares with OSR
a commitment to relations without relata, which is something that many have found
objectionable (e.g., Chakravartty 1998, 2003b; Psillos 2006a); according to
Chakravartty ‘‘one cannot intelligibly subscribe to the reality of relations unless
one is also committed to the fact that some things are related’’ (1998, 399). In the
interest of avoiding such controversies, it would seem reasonable to follow Yates’
understanding of structure as ontologically dependent upon the properties that
‘‘compose’’ it—CDE properties ground the structure.
Recall that, according to property structuralism, the structure, S, at a world, w,
grounds the properties at w because it metaphysically individuates them. Hence,
properties and structure symmetrically ground each other.11 Odd as this may sound,
things get worse for CDE because, as I shall now show, it follows that properties
and laws symmetrically ground each other, which directly threatens CDE’s
aspirations to (asymmetrically) explain laws in terms of properties.
In Sect. 2.2, it was argued that CDE laws are identified with M-relations. Now, if
you fix the M-relations (that is the laws, according to CDE) at a world, w, you fix the
10
Yates actually uses the term ‘‘PPO’’ here, for ‘‘pure powers ontology’’, but the idea is the same – that
all fundamental properties are essentially and exhaustively dispositional and so have their identities fixed
by the relations in which they stand to other properties, viz. place in a structure.
11
This is consonant with more moderate versions of OSR. Esfeld and Lam (2008), for example, maintain
that objects and relations are on an ontological par ‘‘with objects being characterized only by the relations
in which they stand’’ (Esfeld and Lam 2008, 27).
123
3432
S. Kimpton-Nye
property structure at w. If we let [M] denote the plurality of M-relations/laws at a
world, w, and let S denote the property structure at w, then we may ask the following
question: what is the relationship between [M] and S? Answer: identity. The
plurality of M-relations at a world, w, just is the structure at w.
Now, if the collection of M-relations, [M], at a world, w, and the property
structure, S, at w are identical, then anything true of S must be true of [M] too.
According to property structuralism, the structure, S, at w grounds the properties at
w because it metaphysically individuates them. But if S grounds the properties at
w then [M] must ground properties at w too, since S and [M] are identical. But
M-relations, I have argued, just are the laws, according to CDE. Thus, the collection
of M-relations at w, [M], just is a collection of laws. To say that [M] grounds
properties, then, is just to say that laws ground properties, given CDE. To be clear,
the argument runs as follows:
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
(iv)
(v)
S = [M].
[M] is a collection of laws (from the CDE account of laws).
S grounds properties(from the CDE account of properties).
[M] grounds properties (from i, iii and Leibniz’s Law).
Laws ground properties (from ii and iv).
The conclusion that laws ground properties is antagonistic to CDE’s aspiration to
explain laws in terms of properties. Grounding is plausibly understood as an
explanatory relation distinct from, but analogous to causation (Fine 2012, Sect. 1),
see also Schaffer (2016); just as one may explain some fact A by saying that some
temporally prior fact B caused it, one may explain A in terms of B by saying that B
grounds A. An explanation of A in terms of B will not do, however, if in order to
explain B, we must appeal to A—this kind of circularity of explanation is vicious.
The type of explanation of the laws that the dispositional essentialist should seek to
provide is a grounding explanation whereby properties ground laws. But if laws
ground properties too, then the explanation is circular and thus fails to satisfy a key
motivation for dispositional essentialism, which was to explain laws in terms of
properties, not vice versa.12
Another way of seeing the problem is as follows: according to CDE, M-relations
constitute the essences of properties, and M-relations are laws. Structuralist DE thus
builds laws into the essences of properties and then seeks to explain the laws of
nature in terms of those very property essences (c.f. Jaag (2014)). But this looks a
lot like explaining the fact that opium induces sleep in terms of opium’s dormitive
nature.
A further problem highlighted by the above argument is that CDE multiplies the
number of fundamental entities. Dispositional essentialism, at least on the face of it,
promised an attractively reductive picture; at the fundamental level we just have
physical properties which ground the laws of nature. What the above argument
shows, however, is that according to CDE, properties cannot be more fundamental
12
Perhaps there are other cases in which symmetrical grounding is kosher. The point here is just that
symmetrically grounded laws and properties would be antagonistic to the motivations for DE.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3433
than laws because each grounds the other. The picture presented, then, is one of
properties and laws as equifundamental, which is a far less parsimonious picture
than one according to which it is just properties at the fundamental level.
QDE breaks the symmetry by denying that properties are in any way
ontologically dependent upon the structure of M-relations. Properties, according
to QDE, are self-individuating qualities that asymmetrically ground a structure of
M-relations. And laws, according to QDE, are axioms of the best deductive
systematization of all actual and possible property distributions. QDE is thus
preferable to CDE in two significant respects: it avoids symmetrically grounded
properties and laws and hence avoids any Molière-type concerns, it also avoids
positing both properties and laws at the fundamental level.
4.2 Laws as regularities?
Perhaps the obvious response to the symmetrical grounding problem for CDE is to
maintain that laws are universal generalizations, or regularities, of the form
Vx(Fx ? Gx), as opposed to M-relations, viz., arcs in the property structure.
Indeed, Bird himself considers this option13:
According to the regularity version of dispositional essentialism about laws,
laws are those regularities whose truth is guaranteed by the essentially
dispositional nature of […] properties. (2007, 46–47, my emphasis).
The idea, then, is that M-relations do the work of guaranteeing the truth of, or
grounding (depending on whether regularities are understood as linguistic entities or
entities in the world) and hence explaining, nomic regularities. But surely no
M-relation is identical with any regularity, in which case premise ii. in the
symmetrical grounding argument of the previous subsection can be rejected and the
circularity concern is blocked. While properties cannot explain laws qua M-relations, properties can explain laws qua regularities, or so one might think.
But how, exactly, are we to understand the claim that properties explain
regularities? According to an argument from Barker and Smart (2012), the property
structuralist component of CDE cannot achieve even this.
According to the property structuralist, there is nothing more to the essence of a
property than the M-relations in which it stands to other properties—all properties
have their essences exhausted by M-relations. Hence, all that the property
structuralist may appeal to in answering the question about how properties, F and
G, say, explain the regularity Vx(Fx ? Gx) are the M-relations in which F and G
stand to other properties (Tugby 2012, 725, highlights this nicely). To clarify the
point, it will help to introduce some abbreviations:
M(F, G) = the fact that the M-relation holds between F and G.
R = the fact that if x is F then x is disposed to manifest G.
13
Though Bird ultimately leans more heavily towards the view of laws as relations as evidenced by the
official definition of laws later in his book: ‘‘The laws of a domain are the fundamental, general
explanatory relationships between kinds, quantities, and qualities of that domain, that supervene upon the
essential natures of those things.’’ (Bird 2007, 201, my emphasis).
123
3434
S. Kimpton-Nye
We can thus understand the property structuralist as positing a necessary
connection between M(F, G) and R to explain the regularity Vx(Fx ? Gx). It is no
accident, according to the property structuralist, that if M(F, G) holds then R holds,
hence it is no accident that if M(F, G) holds then every x that is F will be G too.
Thus, the regularity, Vx(Fx ? Gx), is explained by M(F, G)’s holding.
But now we may ask: what accounts for the necessary connection between M(F,
G) and R? Why is it that in every possible world in which M(F, G) holds, every x
that is F will be G? Perhaps there is some third-order relation, M*, between the
relational facts M(F, G) and R, which ensures that if M(F, G) holds then R holds too.
We can denote the situation like this: M*[M(F, G), R]. But now we may ask what
accounts for the connection between M*[M(F, G), R], M(F, G) and R? What ensures
that if M*[M(F, G), R] holds at a world, w, then if M(F, G) holds R holds too? Is
there some fourth-order relational fact, M**, such that M**[M*[M(F, G), R], M(F,
G), R]? We are clearly off on a regress of higher and higher order M-relations. (This
is the nub of Barker and Smart’s ‘‘ultimate argument against dispositional monist
accounts of laws’’ (2012), see also Barker (2013).14)
Perhaps the regress can be blocked by repudiating the initial explanatory demand.
The property structuralist might say that there is a brute necessary connection
between the fact that the M-relation holds between F and G and the fact that for all
x, if x is F then x is disposed to manifest G. That is to say, there is a brute necessary
connection between M(F, G) and R such that in any world in which M(F, G) holds,
R holds too. By maintaining that the necessary connection between M(F, G) and R
is just brute, the property structuralist needn’t appeal to higher order relations and
the regress is blocked.
However, appeal to brute necessary connections is antagonistic to the motivation
for property structuralism, and CDE more generally, which was to explain patterns
of property distributions, not in terms of some brute necessary connections, but in
terms of powerful properties. As Tugby puts it, ‘‘One of the main intuitions behind
dispositionalism is that the properties of things are not inert: they pack a powerful
punch; they give a causal ‘biff’ to their possessors.’’ (2012, 726). But if it turns out
that all the work is being done by brute necessary connections between higher-order
relational facts, then this motivation for CDE seems not to have been satisfied.
The point, then, is that it will not help one with anti-Humean/dispositional
essentialist sympathies, who is concerned by the symmetrical grounding problem, to
identify the laws with regularities instead of M-relations. Furthermore, it doesn’t
matter if the regularities in question are more sophisticated, as per the BSA. As
mentioned in Sect. 3.2, the dispositional-BSA account of laws (Demarest 2017;
Kimpton-Nye 2017) still wants the laws/regularities to be metaphysically explained
by properties, which it achieves by maintaining that properties metaphysically
explain their distributions which, in turn, metaphysically explain the BSA-laws. But
what the Barker-Smart problem shows is that structuralism about properties
precludes those properties from explaining regularities in property distributions, and
14
The regress is modified to fit my set up in terms of M-relations. Barker and Smart stick with the
standard conception of dispositions in terms of stimulus and manifestation conditions, which they call
SR-relations. Hence the regress they articulate is of higher and higher order SR-relations.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3435
if properties cannot metaphysically explain their own distributions, they cannot
explain the BSA laws. Whether laws are M-relations, simple regularities or
sophisticated BSA-regularities, a structuralist metaphysics of properties is not cut
out to do the explanatory work that dispositional essentialism requires. We are thus
pushed towards more radically rethinking dispositional essentialism and QDE
constitutes just such a radical rethink.15
4.3 An opacity worry for QDE
The opacity worry for QDE is a challenge to add plausibility to the claim that
qualities ground dispositions. As Tugby puts it ‘‘…opponents […] might object […]
that the alleged internal connection between qualities and dispositions is itself pretty
opaque.’’ (2012, 729).16
Schaffer defines a relevant sense of ‘‘opacity’’ as follows:
Opacity: It is opaque as to why the obtaining of the ground state is linked to
the obtaining of the grounded state if and only if the proposition that the
ground state obtains without the grounded state obtaining is [conceivable/logically possible/a priori open]. (Schaffer 2017, 4).
The worry, then, is that the purported grounding link between quality and
disposition is opaque in the above sense—it is certainly conceivable, logically
possible and a priori open that a quality, positive charge, say, exists in the absence
of a disposition to exert an attractive force on instances of negative charge. So why
think that any such grounding link exists?
Schaffer has argued, however, that a purported grounding link’s being opaque is
not a good reason to reject that link out of hand. This is because Schaffer advocates
an abductive methodology in metaphysics according to which metaphysical posits
are justified to the extent that they are explanatorily fruitful (Schaffer forthcoming,
pp. 8–9) (see also (Lewis and Lewis 1970; Paul 2012 for ideas relating to and in
defence of this abductive methodology in metaphysics)).
It may be explanatorily fruitful, and hence justified, to posit the existence of a
grounding link even if that link is not transparent in the sense that its existence is
evident to pure reason or a priori knowable. For example, and assuming that sets
exist, Schaffer suggests that we are justified in positing a grounding link (namely,
set formation) between Socrates and {Socrates}. This is because, given that Socrates
exists and that the set formation grounding link exists between Socrates and
{Socrates}, it is no accident that {Socrates} exists given the existence of Socrates,
so the link is explanatorily fruitful:
15
One might be concerned that Barker and Smart’s ‘‘Ultimate Problem’’ trumps the symmetrical
grounding problem of Sect. 4.1. However, the Ultimate Problem specifically targets the property
structuralist’s claim to be able to explain regularities in the universe in terms of structuralist properties,
and isn’t directly a problem just for the view according to which laws are identical with arcs in a property
structuralist structure, which is the target of the symmetrical grounding problem. So, the two problems
affect slightly different aspects/variants of CDE.
16
See also Barker (2013) and Sider (2020, chap. 2) for a similar challenge.
123
3436
S. Kimpton-Nye
To buttress this […] claim [that a grounding link obtains between Socrates and
{Socrates}], note that the theoretical role of explanation includes (i) revealing
patterns, (ii) providing recipes, and (iii) allowing understanding [Schaffer
2018 ]. Seeing {Socrates} as the output of Socrates via set formation
(i) reveals a unifying pattern that extends through Plato and {Plato}, Aristotle
and {Aristotle}, etc.; (ii) conveys a recipe to wiggle the existence of
{Socrates} by wiggling the existence of Socrates; and (iii) allows one to
understand why {Socrates} exists, by revealing how sets are collected.
(Schaffer forthcoming, 2).
Schaffer discusses other examples from mereology (2017, forthcoming), metaethics and quantum ontology (forthcoming). In each of these examples, we are
justified in positing a grounding link between two entities because doing so is
explanatorily fruitful in the sense that it reveals patterns, provides a recipe, and
allows understanding. What’s more, the grounding link in each case is opaque in the
above sense that it is conceivable/logically possible/a priori open that the ground
state obtained without the obtaining of the grounded state. For example, it is
conceivable that Socrates existed without the existence of {Socrates} and it is
conceivable that some wood arranged table-wise existed without the existence of a
table (mereological nihilism is conceivable). Nevertheless, we are justified in
positing grounding links in these cases—set formation in the former and a
mereological fusion principle in the latter—because doing so is explanatorily
fruitful.
So, according to Schaffer, the existence of grounding links need not be evident to
pure reason or knowable a priori, i.e., they need not be transparent. Rather, we can
take a more holistic, abductive approach to metaphysics, according to which we are
defeasibly justified in positing grounding links if they are explanatory. In this sense,
Schaffer thinks that there is an important analogy between grounding and causation:
Those who would demand a priori grounding principles strike me as akin to
those in the early days of the sciences who demanded a priori causal principles
(‘‘rational mechanics’’). We have come to recognize the need for substantive
dependence functions in concrete causal cases. I am trying to extend this
insight to concrete metaphysical cases. (Schaffer 2017, 14).
According to this Schafferian line, then, it is no objection to QDE that the grounding
link between quality and disposition is opaque. Indeed, we have defeasible
justification for believing in grounding links between qualities and dispositions
given their explanatory fruitfulness. And the point of the discussion thus far has
been that QDE, ‘‘opaque’’ grounding links and all, is explanatorily fruitful. QDE is
explanatorily superior to Humean accounts of laws and properties because it
guarantees that the laws are sufficiently modally robust (see sect. 1), and it is
explanatorily superior to CDE because it breaks the problematic symmetry and
equifundamentality between laws and properties.
Schaffer’s argument for the explanatoriness of the set formation grounding link
(see second Schaffer quote above) can be mirrored for QDE: positing a grounding
link between positive charge and a disposition to exert an attractive force on
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3437
negatively charged individuals (i) reveals a unifying pattern that extends through
mass and a disposition to exert an attractive force on massive individuals, etc.; (ii)
conveys a recipe to wiggle the existence of a disposition by wiggling the existence
of a quality; and (iii) allows one to understand why certain dispositions exist by
revealing how they depend on the existence of certain qualities.
QDE’s ‘‘opaque’’ grounding links are explanatorily fruitful—this has been the
main thrust of the argument of the present section. We are thus justified in believing
in the existence of these grounding links given a holistic, abductive approach to
metaphysics.
Perhaps one could object that the analogy between Socrates grounding
{Socrates} and qualities grounding dispositions breaks down because whereas we
have independent reason to believe in the existence of Socrates, the only reason for
positing qualities is to ground dispositions and laws.17 Admittedly, qualities, in the
present sense, are more ‘‘theoretical’’ than individuals such as Socrates—the main
reason for positing qualities is the theoretical work that they can do and the
theoretical work of concern here is explaining dispositions and laws. But qualities
can also do other theoretical work besides accounting for dispositions and laws,
such as explaining objective similarity and difference. Indeed, accounting for
similarity and difference is generally a role assigned to natural properties, so one
could understand the present discussion as a case in favour of understanding the
metaphysics of natural properties in such a way that they can also explain laws and
dispositions.
5 In Defence of QDE—continuity with science
For all that’s been said, one could opt for an account of properties as selfindividuating, qualitative grounds of dispositions, as per QDE, but instead of
adopting a BSA-type account of laws, one could stick closer to CDE and maintain
that laws are arcs in the dispositional structure that properties asymmetrically
ground. In this section, I defend the BSA-laws component of QDE.
The following is a plausible desideratum on a philosophical theory of laws:
CONTINUITY: an account of laws should be continuous with actual scientific
practice.
Scientists are largely concerned with discovering laws of nature and philosophical
interest in laws is due to their central importance to science. So, a philosophical
account of laws ought to yield something close to the important scientific concept,
and something that scientists could reasonably hope to have epistemic access to. A
philosophical account of laws that is not continuous with science in this way risks
irrelevance.
Lewis derives the idea of balancing the virtues of strength and simplicity, which
is central to the BSA account of laws, from actual scientific practice:
17
Thanks to a reviewer for raising this point.
123
3438
S. Kimpton-Nye
I take a suitable system to be one that has the virtues we aspire to in our own
theory-building, and that has them to the greatest extent possible given the
way the world is… [I]t must be as simple in axiomatisation as it can be
without sacrificing too much information content; and it must have as much
information content as it can have without sacrificing too much simplicity. A
law is any regularity that earns inclusion in the ideal system. (Lewis 1983,
367).
The standards of simplicity, of strength, and of balance between them are to be
those that guide us in assessing the credibility of rival hypotheses as to what
the laws are. (Lewis 1986 , 123).
Scientists use strength and simplicity as epistemic guides in the discovery of laws;
the strongest, simplest statements about how the world is are assumed most likely to
be the laws of nature. The QDE-BSA (like the original BSA) takes the scientists’
epistemic principles and makes them constitutive of laws. In this way, the QDEBSA achieves continuity with actual scientific practice by sticking close to the
scientific understanding of laws and by ensuring the epistemic accessibility of the
laws via scientific methods, which is good at discovering strong, simple statements
about the world. As Dorst puts it: ‘‘it is as if Lewis asked himself: ‘How should one
design a theory of laws to make sense of the ways that scientists investigate them?’.
And his response was this: ‘Figure out what sorts of things scientists’ epistemic
practices would be good at discovering, and make those things the laws’.’’ (Dorst
2017, 880). (See also Hall (2015)).
M-relations, in contrast with QDE-BSA laws, are highly specific—they are
individual arcs in a potentially huge structure. Thus, taken individually, M-relations
would likely not be very informative. Listing all the M-relations would be very
informative, but it would be far from simple; indeed, a list of all the M-relations
would likely be far too complex and unwieldy to be of any use at all to intellectually
limited creatures like us.
Furthermore, epistemic accessibility of specific M-relations is far from guaranteed. As mentioned, science appears to be in the (successful) business of
formulating very general statements about the world. But the contribution made
by any given M-relation to the most general goings on in the world is likely to be
intimately tied up with its interactions with a whole host of other M-relations. It is
not obvious that we should be able to easily isolate and (epistemically) identify
particular M-relations independently of the whole tangled web of M-relations which
as a whole is responsible for the regularities we observe in nature.
Identifying laws with all and only the M-relations thus has the significant
disadvantage of failing to respect CONTINUITY; M-relations don’t look much like
the scientific conception of laws as strong simple statements about the world and
they risk being epistemically inaccessible via scientific methods of inquiry. (See
Kimpton-Nye (2017) for a detailed discussion of how to ensure the epistemic
accessibility of laws if something akin to the BSA is combined with an unHumean
account of properties). To ensure the generality and epistemic accessibility of laws,
we thus seem compelled to zoom out to the larger scale patterns in possible property
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3439
distributions and to identify those patterns with laws; this is exactly what the QDEBSA recommends.
The following is a further plausible desideratum on a theory of laws.
PRAGMATISM: part of what it is to be a law of nature is to afford predictive
utility to creatures like us.
PRAGMATISM is closely related to CONTINUITY; the continuity with science
that the QDE-BSA achieves ensures that the laws have the predictive utility that
PRAGMATISM demands. A strong systematization will carry lots of information,
including information about the future and about other possibilities, which is what
we need to make predictions. And a simple systematization will be easy for
cognitively limited being such as ourselves to wield in order to actually make those
predictions (see Dorst (2017) on this point, though Dorst argues that the ‘‘nomic
formula’’ we will need to include principles in addition to strength and simplicity if
BSA laws are to properly satisfy the pragmatic demand).
Conversely, failure to respect CONTINUITY, as in the case in which laws are
identified with M-relations, compromises PRAGMATISM for three reasons:
particular M-relations are highly specific and so will be of limited predictive
power, the list of all M-relations will likely be very long and complicated and so of
limited use to us in making predictions, there is no guarantee that all or even many
of the M-relations that there are will be epistemically accessible to us, so even if
M-relations were highly predictive in theory, we may not be able to tap into this
predictive power.
To summarize this section: the QDE-BSA is preferable to an account of laws as
identical with M-relations because the former, but not the latter, is continuous with
actual scientific practice, which implies that the former, but not the latter, yields
laws that are useful for creatures like us.
6 Conclusion
This paper discussed two different anti-Humean accounts of the metaphysics of
properties: structuralism and the grounding view. And it discussed two different
accounts of the metaphysics of laws: laws-as-M-relations and the BSA. CDE
resulted from the combination of structuralism and laws-as-M-relations and QDE
resulted from the combination of the grounding view and the BSA. I argued that
QDE is superior to CDE because it avoids Molière-type explanatory concerns for
CDE and it achieves a greater degree of continuity with actual scientific practice
than CDE does. I also argued that the remaining two ways of packaging together
some combination of the above accounts of properties and laws are inferior to QDE.
Combining structuralism with the BSA does nothing to address Barker and Smart’s
explanatory regress (Sect. 4.2) and combining the grounding view with laws-as-Mrelations does not achieve the same level of continuity with science as is achieved
by the QDE combination of the grounding view with the BSA. The desiderata of
explanatoriness and continuity with science thus give us a good sense of what the
absolutely best laws-properties package deal will look like. While there may be
123
3440
S. Kimpton-Nye
some wiggle room on the precise details of the metaphysics of laws and properties,
properties should not have their essences constituted by anything that they are then
expected to explain, this was the lesson of the symmetrical grounding argument and
of Barker and Smart’s ‘‘ultimate’’ argument. And laws should be the sort of things
that are useful to creatures like us in our practical and scientific endeavours, this was
the lesson of the continuity with science argument.
Acknowledgements This work has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under
the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme as part of the MetaScience
project, grant agreement no. 771509. For feedback on earlier versions of this work I am grateful to:
Barbara Vetter, Francesca Bellazzi, Jessica Leech, Matthew Tugby, Toby Friend, Tuomas Tahko,
Vanessa Seifert and some anonymous referees.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as
you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative
Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this
article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line
to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended
use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain
permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
References
Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Armstrong, D. M. (1999). What Is a Law of Nature? Repr. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Barker, S. (2013). The Emperor’s New Metaphysics of Powers. Mind, 122(487), 605–653. https://doi.org/
10.1093/mind/fzt082.
Barker, S., & Smart, B. (2012). The Ultimate Argument against Dispositional Monist Accounts of Laws.
Analysis, 72(4), 714–722. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans114.
Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford, New York: OUP Oxford.
Blackburn, S. (1990). Filling in Space. Analysis, 50(2), 62–65. https://doi.org/10.2307/3328847.
Chakravartty, A. (1998). Semirealism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 29(3),
391–408. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0039-3681(98)00013-2.
Chakravartty, A. (2003a). The Dispositional Essentialist View of Properties and Laws. International
Journal of Philosophical Studies, 11(4), 393–413.
Chakravartty, A. (2003b). The Structuralist Conception of Objects. Philosophy of Science, 70(5),
867–878. https://doi.org/10.1086/377373.
Chakravartty, A. (2007). A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Dasgupta, Shamik. 2014. On the Plurality of Grounds. Philosophers’ Imprint 14.
Demarest, H. (2017). Powerful Properties Powerless Laws Causal Powers (Vol. 1, pp. 38–53). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Dorst, C. (2017). Towards a Best Predictive System Account of Laws of Nature. British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 70(3), 877–900. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axy016.
Dretske, F. I. (1977). Laws of Nature. Philosophy of Science, 44(2), 248–268.
Esfeld, M., & Lam, V. (2008). Moderate Structural Realism about Space-Time. Synthese, 160(1), 27–46.
Fine, K. (2012). Guide to Ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical Grounding (pp.
37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
123
Reconsidering the Dispositional Essentialist Canon
3441
Fine, K. (2015). Unified Foundations for Essence and Ground. Journal of the American Philosophical
Association, 1(2), 296–311. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2014.26.
French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2003). Remodelling Structural Realism: Quantum Physics and the
Metaphysics of Structure. Synthese, 136(1), 31–56. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1024156116636.
Hall, N. (2015). ‘Humean Reductionism about Laws of Nature. A Companion to David Lewis (pp.
262–277). New York: Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118398593.ch17.
Hildebrand, T. (2016). Two Types of Quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(3), 516–532.
https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2015.1112418.
Jaag, Siegfried. 2014. Dispositional Essentialism and the Grounding of Natural Modality. Philosophers
Imprint 14 (34).
Kimpton-Nye, S. (2017). Humean Laws in an UnHumean World. Journal of the American Philosophical
Association, 3(2), 129–147. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2017.19.
Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. G. (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics
Naturalized. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Lange, M. (2013). Grounding, Scientific Explanation, and Humean Laws. Philosophical Studies: An
International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 164(1), 255–261.
Lewis, D. (1983). New Work for a Theory of Universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4),
343–377. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408312341131.
Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical Papers (Vol. II). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lewis, D. (1994). Humean Supervenience Debugged. Mind, 103(412), 473–490.
Lewis, D. (2001). Counterfactuals (Vol. Rev). Malden, Mass: Blackwell Publishers.
Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan Humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual Analysis
and Philosophical Naturalism (pp. 203–222). Cambridgee: MIT Press.
Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, D. K., & Lewis, S. (1970). Holes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 48(2), 206–212. https://doi.
org/10.1080/00048407012341181.
Maudlin, T. (2007). The Metaphysics Within Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Molnar, G. (1999). Are Dispositions Reducible? The Philosophical Quarterly, 49(194), 1–17.
Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in Nature (Vol. 1). London: Routledge.
Paul, L. A. (2012). Metaphysics as Modeling: The Handmaiden’s Tale. Philosophical Studies, 160(1),
1–29.
Psillos, S. (2006). The Structure, the Whole Structure, and Nothing but the Structure? Philosophy of
Science, 73(5), 560–570. https://doi.org/10.1086/518326.
Schaffer, J. (2016). Grounding in the Image of Causation. Philosophical Studies, 173(1), 49–100.
Schaffer, Jonathan 2017. The Ground Between the Gaps.. Philosopher’s Imprint 17 (11). http://hdl.
handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0017.011.
Schaffer, J. (2018). Laws for Metaphysical Explanation. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 82,
1–22. https://doi.org/10.1017/s1358246118000164.
Schaffer, J. (forthcoming). Ground Functionalism. Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Mind.
Sider, T. (2020). The Tools of Metaphysics and the Metaphysics of Science. New York: OUP Oxford.
Smith, D. C. (2016). Quid Quidditism Est? Erkenntnis, 81(2), 237–257. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670015-9737-y.
Tooley, M. (1977). The Nature of Laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(4), 667–698.
Trogdon, K. (2013). Grounding: Necessary or Contingent? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 94(4),
465–485.
Tugby, M. (2020). Grounding Theories of Powers. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-027812.
Tugby, M. (2012). Rescuing DispositionalismFrom the Ultimate Problem: Reply to Barker and Smart.
Analysis, 72(4), 723–731.
Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality (1st ed.). Oxford Philosophical
Monographs: Oxford University Press, New York.
Yates, D. (2018). Inverse functionalism and the individuation of powers. Synthese, 195(10), 4525–4550.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1417-9.
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published
maps and institutional affiliations.
123