Med Health Care and Philos (2013) 16:663–670
DOI 10.1007/s11019-013-9500-6
SCIENTIFIC CONTRIBUTION
Vulnerability, diversity and scarcity: on universal rights
Bryan Stanley Turner • Alex Dumas
Published online: 12 July 2013
Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013
Abstract This article makes a contribution to the on-going
debates about universalism and cultural relativism from the
perspective of sociology. We argue that bioethics has a
universal range because it relates to three shared human
characteristics,—human vulnerability, institutional precariousness and scarcity of resources. These three components
of our argument provide support for a related notion of
‘weak foundationalism’ that emphasizes the universality
and interrelatedness of human experience, rather than their
cultural differences. After presenting a theoretical position
on vulnerability and human rights, we draw on recent
criticism of this approach in order to paint a more nuanced
picture. We conclude that the dichotomy between universalism and cultural relativism has some conceptual merit,
but it also has obvious limitations when we consider the
political economy of health and its impact on social
inequality.
Keywords Ethics Vulnerability Scarcity
Precariousness Human rights Universalism
Relativism Diversity Inequality
B. S. Turner
Department of Sociology, The Graduate Center,
The City University of New York, 365 Fifth Ave, New York,
NY 10016-4309, USA
e-mail:
[email protected]
B. S. Turner
School of Social Sciences, University of Western Sydney,
Campbelltown, Australia
A. Dumas (&)
School of Human Kinetics, University of Ottawa,
125 University, Ottawa, ON K1N 6N5, Canada
e-mail:
[email protected]
Introduction
The generic concepts of ‘ethics of rights’ and ‘ethics of
duties’ (Patrão Neves 2009)—found implicitly in most
official bioethics documents—can be viewed as two relevant ideas for a sociological study of human rights and
global health policy. They identify basic human needs and
socio-cultural conditions that should be safeguarded by
political institutions. The fact that health is now considered
a basic good within international conventions is an
important point of departure for universal rights to health
(UNESCO 2011). The duties that are associated with these
rights are also expressed by the moral obligation to develop
a social contract that would achieve a modicum of social
justice by for example reducing social inequalities.
Both dimensions of the ethics debate (rights and duties)
converge on the notion of ‘institution’. In sociology, the
problems of developing universal institutions to achieve a
civilized level of social protection, while respecting personal autonomy, lie at its core. In an effort to promote
‘multidisciplinary and pluralistic dialogue’ (UNESCO
2005) in bioethics, this article makes a contribution to ongoing debates about universalism and cultural relativism
from the perspective of sociology. We argue that bioethics
has a universal range because it relates to three shared
human characteristics,—human vulnerability, institutional
precariousness and scarcity of resources. These three
components of our argument provide support for a related
notion of ‘weak foundationalism’ that emphasizes the
universality and interrelatedness of human experience,
rather than their cultural differences. After presenting a
theoretical position on vulnerability and human rights, we
draw on recent criticism of this approach in order to paint a
more nuanced picture. We conclude that the dichotomy
between universalism and cultural relativism has some
123
664
conceptual merit, but it also has obvious limitations when
we consider the political economy of health and its impact
on social inequality.
Cultural relativism, globalization and human rights
The idea that different cultures produce not only different
ethics and values but also vastly different ways of experiencing the world has become the dominant assumption of
both anthropology and sociology. In terms of philosophical
anthropology, our social being-in-the-world is deeply rooted in distinctive and separate sets of cultural practices,
often referred to simply as ‘habitus’ (Bourdieu 2000). The
implication is that we cannot assume that the experiences
of sickness and disease, and experiences of the body are
universal and it follows that some assumptions of western
bioethics cannot be generalized.
In sociology the problem of relativism occurs under the
general discussion of ‘social constructionism’, namely that
the phenomena of the social world have no consistent or
permanent essence; they are always and already produced
by social conditions. Perhaps the classic illustration of the
argument was the work of Margaret Lock (1993) on the
cross-cultural experience of menopause in American and
Japanese women. She found that, while the discomforts of
menopause in the United States were widely prevalent,
Japanese women did not experience negative symptoms to
the same extent. Medical sociologists therefore concluded
that the social construction of menopause was at the source
of its medicalization in some areas of the word.
While social constructionism is a basic premise of
modern anthropology and sociology, it has certain limitations in the context of rights. We defend the idea some
conditions such as human vulnerability, precariousness
institutions and scarcity of resources, are common to
human societies and can serve as a grounding for future
research in bioethics. In short we defend a position that we
call ‘weak foundationalism’. Without rejecting cultural
relativism, we argue that humans share a physical
embodiment, which has significant consequences regardless of cultural variations. For example, the prospect of
post-humanism is threatening to alter what it is to be
human and is generating many ethical questions that appear
to go beyond cultures or religious denomination; it is in this
perspective that the study of embodiment in social sciences
is central to ethical life (Frank 2012: 395). We also elaborate the notion of institutional precariousness that occurs
in context of scarcity. The result is that over many issues
we have to co-operate through mutual recognition just in
order to survive.
We start with the observation that cultural relativism
runs up against at least two obvious counter arguments.
123
B. S. Turner, A. Dumas
The first is that the notion of cultural specificity is contradicted by the widespread assumption in the social sciences that globalization is the dominant form of social
change in the modern world. Globalism is especially evident in the fact that the world is shaped by a common
technology and production system. For example, access to
medical technology, international vaccination co-ordination efforts, and sharing of information through the World
Health Organisation can be viewed as proof that most
countries are to some degree part of globalized networks.
While the interaction between global and local cultures
often results in hybrid cultures that sociologists describe as
a process of ‘glocalization’, there are important common
processes that result in shared problems and experiences.
Medical anthropologists, by grasping the relativist implications of her work, can too easily ignore one of the conclusions of Margaret Lock’s research, which was that
Japanese women would come to acquire menopausal difficulties as a result of globalization.
This first point is supported primarily by the nature of
human ageing, demographic data and considerations on the
specificity of the social classification of disease. Let us take
two examples of the emergence of a common ‘health
world’ with respect to globalization and health. Perhaps the
most important demographic revolution of the late twentieth century was the decline in female total fertility rates
and the greying of human populations. This demographic
change is more or less uniform regardless of cultural differences and especially religious differences. By the
beginning of this century, only four countries in the world
have a fertility rate above five, and half the world’s population now live in societies that have fertility rates that are
near or below the replacement level (MacInnes and Pérez
Diaz 2009: 150). Obviously there are important differences. China’s one-child policy is very different from the
demographic situation of the United States, but there are
common global processes: the improvement in female
education, the availability of contraceptives, rising prosperity of the middle classes and changing attitudes towards
children. In association with changing fertility, there is the
longer life expectancy and lower death rates that translate
into a strong trend of ageing of the world’s population. For
most societies demography is central to various health,
labour and economic policies.
It would also be possible to construct a list of such
shared health circumstances related to ageing—cancer,
Alzheimer’s disease, strokes, and so forth. With globalization, there is the rapid transmission of conditions such as
HIV/AIDS, SARS, and the annual influenza outbreak.
There are also more ‘exotic’ problems such as the arrival
and spread of West Nile virus to Texas where 118 people
died and 3,000 were infected in the summer of 2012. We
can therefore legitimately argue that in the past humans
Vulnerability, diversity and scarcity
lived in communities that were more or less isolated and
hence diseases with geographically and culturally specific.
This communal autonomy and isolation was relative. In the
medieval world, the bubonic plague devastated human
communities across much of Europe. The modern world is
very different. An outbreak of SARS in East Asia can reach
Ottawa in a matter of days if not hours. Another example
would be diabetes. There is a worldwide epidemic of diabetes. It is clearly widespread among urban, sedentarized
and developed societies from Australia to the United
States, where lack of exercise, fast food and urbanization
contribute to its rising incidence among young people.
Obviously more efficient detection and monitoring contribute to the growth of the disease, but it is also widespread among indigenous peoples from Australian
aboriginals to Native Americans.
The second counter argument is the widespread, if not
universal, acceptance of human rights. Sociologists have
suggested that the cultural contexts of moral debate are not
as radically incommensurable as many philosophers suggest, and thus the process of globalization has provided a
counter-balance to national and cultural diversity (Mouzelis 2011). The contemporary almost universal acceptance
of human rights suggests that the globalization of the
principles of the Declaration of 1948 can mitigate if not
overcome the fragmentation and diversity of human cultures. There are of course many well-known problems with
human rights, such as the difference between the acceptance and enforcement of rights (Woodiwiss 2009).
Human rights began to emerge on the global political
agenda in the 1970 s when growing dissatisfaction with the
historic the role of states in the international order and
widespread recognition of the failures of communism
opened up opportunities for rethinking the role of rights in
international affairs. Human rights emerged as a serviceable ideology for a variety of social movements such as
women’s internationalism, political dissidents in Poland
and Hungary, and as the basis of global NGO activity. The
presidency of Jimmy Carter, who in his inauguration in
1977 declared an absolute commitment to human rights as
the basis of American foreign policy, was also an important
development. However, the critical turning-point occurred
when academic lawyers came to embrace human rights as
the normative framework of international law. These lawyers, who began to question the prevailing realist doctrines
of international relations theory, embraced human rights as
part of their core business (Moyn 2010).
One standard argument against human rights has been
that they are western and individualistic. But even this
argument has lost a lot of traction. The so-called ‘Asian
values debate’ has more or less disappeared. At one stage
both Mahatir in Malaysia and Lee Kwan Yew in Singapore
sought to ground a view of human rights in Confucianism
665
with its emphasis on the family, order and respect, but for
critics of these societies such values were thought to be a
screen to hide the authoritarianism of their respective
regimes (Kamaludeen and Turner 2012). Although the
spread of human rights is far from complete, there is a
growing network of international law that is binding on
nations. The United Nations Convention on the Law of the
Sea (1982) is a significant illustration of this development
(Charney and Smith 2002). The growth of legally binding
relations within the European community has also been
seen by legal scholars as an important example of legal
internationalism. For example in 1951 the Treaty Establishing the European Coal and Steel Community made
provision for an independent court, the Court of Justice, to
interpret and enforce of the treaty’s provisions. Another
example is the creation of the European Court of Human
Rights in 1959. These international legal relations have
multiplied with juridical globalization in clear recognition
of the need to develop a set of universal norms to address
global concerns relating to major issues, especially the
environment (Charney 1993).
In addition, important normative instruments developed
in bioethics and human rights over the last decades (e.g.,
Declaration of Helsinki, Belmont Report, European Convention on Bioethics, Universal Declaration of Bioethics
and Human Rights) have identified a number of shared
human conditions that should be preserved through political
means. The notion of shared vulnerability—that is commonly used in bioethics as an answer to relativistic claims in
health policy—is a good example in this regard. Generally
speaking, the notion of vulnerability holds two meanings.
First, the word refers to a universal and persistent character
of human beings (e.g., Kottow 2004; Luna 2009; Patrão
Neves 2009; Ruof 2004). In some respect, it holds an
ontological priority over other bioethical principles
(Solbakk 2011). Second, it holds a more variable status,
which is dependent on a sociocultural context. Socioeconomic inequalities increase vulnerability, and humans thus
become vulnerated and, as a consequence, more susceptible
to disease and shorter lives (Kottow 2004). Essentially,
global rights institutions and conventions protect humans
because they are vulnerable. The arguments invoking a
‘bioethics of protection’ or a ‘duty to aid’ often put forward
the significance of international solidarity as an answer to
health inequalities (e.g., Schramm and Braz 2008; London
2005). As stated in a recent report of the International
Bioethics Committee: ‘‘vulnerability might provide a bridge
between the moral ‘strangers’ of a pluralistic society,
thereby enhancing the value of solidarity rather than mere
individual interest’’ (UNESCO 2013: 2). Economic development does not automatically reduce the vulnerability of
every sector of society, and hence there is a continuing need
for basic forms of protection.
123
666
With respect to recent biotechnological developments,
various treaties and conventions on the integrity of the
human species testify to the existence of a global risk
society. In ‘Protecting the endangered Human’ Annas,
Andrews and Isasi (2002) suggest an international treaty
prohibiting cloning and inheritable alterations in response
to species altering technology: ‘prevention … must be
based on the recognition that all human are the same, rather
than on an emphasis on our difference’ (2002: 136).
Vulnerability, precariousness and scarcity
We believe that sociological arguments about globalization
and human rights can contribute to philosophical debates in
bioethics since the empirical findings of sociological
research have an obvious bearing on bioethics and health
policy. However we do not want to present a counter
argument in terms of various empirical examples. We need
to develop our position at a much more fundamental and
conceptual level.
These examples from our discussion so far indicate that
what human beings share in common, even when they are
profoundly divided by culture and religion, is their ontological vulnerability. This point has been emphasized in
Vulnerability and Human Rights, in which Turner (2006)
argued from a sociological perspective that the concept of
vulnerability, which is derived from the Latin vulnus or
‘wound’, recognises the corporeal dimension of human
existence, namely our embodiment; it describes the condition of sentient, embodied creatures, who are exposed to
the dangers of their natural environment, and who are
conscious of their precarious circumstances. Our vulnerability signifies our capacity to be open to wounding, and
therefore to be open to the world. This theme of human
vulnerability clearly has strong religious connotations. It
can be easily related to the Christian tradition the symbol
of which is the cross of Jesus. But it can also be recognized
in the teachings of the Buddha. In a discussion of the
Buddhist idea of dukkha or suffering, Robert Bellah
(2011:532) notes that it can also be translated as meaning
that life is ‘unsatisfactory’. One reason life is less than
satisfactory is because we experience it as transient and
tragic. He concludes that ‘fundamentally it is the recognition of the vulnerability and fragility of life’ (Bellah 2011:
532). One might also relate this concept of human vulnerability to the Shi’ite tradition of Islam with its profound
sense of martyrdom and suffering. These comparisons
suggest that vulnerability is not cultural specific but speaks
to the human condition as a shared ontology.
Human beings are ontologically vulnerable and insecure, and their natural environment, uncertain. In order to
protect themselves from the uncertainties and challenges of
123
B. S. Turner, A. Dumas
the everyday world, they must build social institutions
(especially political, familial and cultural institutions) that
come to constitute ‘society’. We need a certain level of
trust in order to build companionship and friendship to
provide us with mutual support in times of uncertainty. We
need the creative force of ritual and the emotional ties of
common festivals to renew social life and to build effective
institutions, and we need the comforts of social institutions
as means of fortifying our individual precarious existence.
Because we are vulnerable, it is necessary to build political
institutions to provide for our collective security. These
institutions are, however, themselves precarious and they
cannot begin to function without effective leadership,
political wisdom and good fortune to provide an enduring
and reliable social environment. However rituals typically
go wrong; social norms offer no firm or enduring blue-print
for action in the face of rapid social change; and the
guardians of social values—priests, academics, lawyers
and politicians—turn out to be all too easily open to corruption, mendacity and self interest. Nevertheless the
uncertainties and contingencies of everyday life also generate inter-societal patterns of dependency and connectedness, and in psychological terms this shared world of risk
and uncertainty results in sympathy, empathy and trust
without which society would not be possible. All social life
is characterised by this contradictory, unstable and delicate
balance between scarcity, solidarity and security.
In its report on the Principle of respect for human vulnerability and personal integrity, the International Bioethics Committee notably indicates that the ‘most significant
worldwide barrier to improving the levels of attainment of
health through health care interventions is the scarcity of
resources’ (UNESCO 2011: 29). Drawing on sociology, in
recent publications we have placed greater emphasis on
this problem of scarcity (especially on the political economy of scarcity), because we believe that debates about
human rights have often neglected some of the basic economic problems associated with rights claims.
The idea of scarcity has been a basic assumption of
economics in which, considering its most generic meaning,
it signifies a shortage of means to achieve desirable ends of
action. A shortage of income means that I cannot purchase
basic commodities to satisfy needs such as food and shelter. Adam Smith in The Wealth of Nations recognized the
often negative consequences of swings between years of
plenty and years of scarcity, and in the latter case for
example in 1,740 workers could often be hired for less than
subsistence. Our arguments relating to vulnerability and
precariousness also have an economic dimension by
grasping the relationship between vulnerability and economic analysis of environment. In The Entropy Law and
the Economic Process, Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen
(1971) argued that waste is an unavoidable aspect of the
Vulnerability, diversity and scarcity
development process of modernization, and that human
beings inevitably deplete natural resources and create
environmental pollution. Economic progress merely speeds
up the inevitable exhaustion of the earth’s natural resources. Georgescu-Roegen’s theory showed that classical
economics had neglected the problem of natural scarcity,
thinking that technology and entrepreneurship could eventually
solve the problem described by Thomas Malthus of
population growth in relation to fixed resources. His
economic theory of waste applied the ideas of Alfred Lotka
(1925) on biology to the accumulation of capital. Human
beings have to rely on what Lotka called ‘exosomatic
instruments’ to develop the environment, unlike animals
which depend on ‘endosomatic instruments’. In some
respects this distinction is an old anthropological argument.
Reptiles evolve wings to fly; human beings create aeroplanes. However, wings involve low entropy solutions and
do not deplete natural resources; technological solutions,
such as jet-propelled aeroplanes, are high entropic solutions that use up finite energy. Because humans are ontologically vulnerable, they develop high entropy strategies
that have the unfortunate consequence of creating a precarious environment.
More importantly, the entropy law implies a pessimistic
conclusion that social conflict is inevitable. Because
resources are scarce, humans degrade their environment,
and they must consequently compete within limited space.
These Malthusian conditions of social conflict in modern
times have been further exacerbated by the mechanization
of violence and by the de-stabilising impact of new wars.
We can as a result interpret social citizenship as an institutional attempt to reduce conflict through, typically
modest, income redistribution in the framework of the
nation state, and human rights as conflict-reducing instruments between and within states. As argued by Etzioni
(1993), increased social divisions and power of lobby
groups can be linked to moral relativism. Although this
assertion has been criticized, it shows that systems that
privileges the virtues of the market and individual freedom,
fail to nurture the roots of the community (Turner and
Rojek 2001).
While recognizing the common vulnerability of human
beings, as sociologists we cannot ignore the precariousness
of human institutions and the basic condition of scarcity. In
order to engage with other human beings as moral agents
worthy of our respect, there has to be mutual recognition.
This basic starting point of ethics is referred to as ‘recognition ethics’ (Williams 1997). In a human community, this
basic act of recognition requires some degree of equality.
For example, Hegel’s master-slave analysis takes account
of the fact that neither slave nor master can arrive at mutual
recognition, because the master perceives the slave as his
property, while the slave is too lowly to recognise the
667
master. Hence, without some degree of social equality,
there can be no ethical community, and hence a system of
rights and obligations cannot function. Material scarcity
undercuts the roots of social community without which
conscious, rational agency is always compromised. Taking
their cue from the critique of liberal theories of rights by
Karl Marx (1818–1883), sociologists have remained sceptical about human rights traditions that have no corresponding social policies to secure some minimum level of
equality through strategies of redistribution such as progressive taxation (Waldron 1987). Rights to individual
freedoms without democratic egalitarianism are thought to
be merely symbolic not real claims for recognition. Without some degree of equality, however basic, bioethics can
have no real purchase on the social world. Recognition
requires some basic redistribution.
Weak foundationalism—point and counterpoint
The vulnerability thesis has received some criticism
because it is very relevant to some human rights but not to
others. It is limited by its inability to explain the individual
rights of liberalism. In fact, it is often is used to prevent
excess freedom that may increase inequalities. It can also
be criticised on the grounds that we do not automatically
feel responsible for the suffering of others. Relativism
‘opens the door’ to moral queuing principles in function of
interest groups and political agendas. In Luc Boltanski’s
Distant Suffering (1999), there has been some discussion
about whether we can sympathize with those with whom
we are not connected.
Our argument that embodiment is a valid basis for the
defence the universalism of human rights is partly grounded in the notion of the ubiquity of human misery and
suffering. In 1850 Arthur Schopenhauer opened his essay
‘On the Suffering of the World’ (2004) with the observation that every ‘individual misfortune, to be sure, seems an
exceptional occurrence; but misfortune in general is the
rule’. While the study of misery and misfortune has been
the stuff of philosophy and theology, there is little systematic study of these phenomena by sociologists. One
exception is Barrington Moore (1970:11) who argues in
Reflections on the Causes of Human Misery that ‘suffering
is not a value in its own right. In this sense any form of
suffering becomes a cost, and unnecessary suffering an
odious cost’. In general political opposition to human
misery becomes a stand-point that can transcend and unite
different cultures and values.
A critic might object that suffering is too variable in its
cultural manifestations and too indefinite in its meanings
and local significance to provide such a common, indeed
universal, standpoint. What actually constitutes human
123
668
suffering might well turn out to be culturally and historically specific. Those who take note of the cultural variability of suffering have made similar arguments against a
common standard of disability. Although one could well
accept this anthropological argument on the grounds that
suffering involves essentially the devaluation of a person as
a consequence of accident, affliction or torture, pain is less
variable. Whereas bankruptcy for example could involve
some degree of variable psychological suffering through a
loss of face, a toothache is a toothache. If we claim that
disability is a social condition (basically the loss of social
rights) and thus relative, we might argue that impairment is
the underlying condition about which there is less political
dispute or philosophical uncertainty. In short, some conditions or states of affairs are less socially constructed than
others. Suffering is often, perhaps always, a threat to our
dignity, which is obviously culturally variable. Pain by
signalling a deeper somatic malfunction is a threat to our
existence.
Yet another criticism is the medical technology paradox.
The more medical science improves our global health
condition, the less vulnerable we are. Therefore technological progress could make this vulnerability thesis historically specific. In principle if we live longer, because we
have become less vulnerable with advances in medical
technology, then the relevance of human rights might well
diminish. This paradox however helps us to sharpen our
argument, which is that we are human, because we are
vulnerable. The irony of medical advances is that we could
only finally escape our vulnerability by ultimately escaping
from our own humanity. Technological change threatens to
create a post-human world in which, with medical progress, we could in principle live forever. This criticism
presents an interesting argument, but there are two potentially important counter-arguments. The first is that, if we
could significantly increase our life expectancy, then we
would live longer but in all probability with higher rates
of discomfort and disability. The quantity of life might
increase in terms of years, but there would be a corresponding decline in its quality. A post-human world is a
medical utopia that has all the negative features of a Brave
New World. Secondly, medical improvements in the
advanced societies are likely to increase the inequality
between societies, creating a more unequal and insecure
international order. In such a risk society, where human
precariousness increases and human vulnerability decreases, the need for human rights protection would continue to
be important. The prospect of living forever might require
us to inhabit, in Max Weber’s pessimistic metaphor, an
‘iron cage’ in which our existence is by courtesy of lifesupport machines. A post-human world would in principle
require a different ethical system namely a post-human
ethics (Fukuyama 2004).
123
B. S. Turner, A. Dumas
Scarcity is nonetheless at the centre of bioethics. For
many scholars, scarcity is regarded as socially constructed
in the sense that it is produced by a consumer culture in
which expectations are elastic and diverse. The theory of
positional goods suggests that demand for status goods can
be controlled only with great difficulty (Hirsch 1977). Our
notion of inescapable vulnerability may be questioned by
the optimism often generated by medical technologies that
promise to provide replacement organs, brain implants, and
a wealth of interventions aims to extend life ‘indefinitely’.
The task of bioethics is to address the problems of scarcity
in societies of abundance and to consider the consequences
of medical technology that will increase social inequality.
With the scarcity of resources, there is always social
competition and conflict– even in the richest societies of
the developed world (Turner and Rojek 2001). The Occupy
Wall Street slogan—we are the 99%—may become a relatively permanent feature of social movements in this
century. There are few discussions on the nature of scarcity
in terms of bioethics. If scarcity itself is not a product of
modernity, globalization, or ageing populations, new
technologies are important factors involved in the politics
of life. Bioethics will need to consider its relations to
humans suffering and protective institutions.
Geriatric technologies are bringing new standards of
longevity and quality of life, and are generating new social
and ethical questions. Characteristics of patients such as
age, capacity to pay, degree of success of medical intervention, and social value of the individual, are all deciding
factors that are used to different degrees that determine
access to health care in the face of scarcity (Moody 2002).
The opportunity costs of massive investments of health
care for older populations are also being evaluated in terms
medical ethics and social justice. Ageing societies are
faced with the difficult questions of ‘choosing who’s to
live’, and under what conditions, by limiting resources for
the very old (Walters 1996).
Researchers in biogerontology have revived the medical
utopia of wanting to significantly extending life well
beyond the current human life span, situated approximately
at 125 years. Whether this life extension is achievable or
not is somewhat irrelevant for our discussion. However, the
justifications for funding such a project have been interpreted as ‘cutting through ethics’ (Dumas and Turner 2007,
2013).
Conclusion
Our criticism of cultural relativism does not endorse a pure
foundationalist approach; we recognize that societies are
different and have different value systems. However, we
cannot minimise the import of universalist claims because
Vulnerability, diversity and scarcity
there are shared similarities between humans and potent
social forces such as globalization that shape and reshape
human experiences. Perhaps bioethics is deemed to follow
a version of the ‘glocalization’ model, where, on the one
hand, it would acknowledge and act upon the fact that
globalized forces are being opposed to the legitimate
resistance of local cultures, and on the other hand, it would
strongly promote universal thresholds when in comes to
health and human rights.
Our contribution to the understanding of conventional
bioethics is also based in the strong assumption that there is
always a struggle over scarce resources and that scarcity
will continue to dominate the lives of large sections of the
population, even within the wealthiest countries (Bury
2000). Bioethics needs political economy. If we do not
hold any firm foundationalist arguments in contexts of
scarcity, we must recognize the inflation of demand for
health technologies, increased competition for scarce
resources and increased health inequalities. We note that
our argument is somewhat similar to the position taken by
Hervé Juvin (2010) in The Coming of the Body. For Juvin,
globalized societies are market-driven and characterized by
individualism, indeterminacy, increased concerns over
health and body appearance. Without a strong and forceful
legal framework that overrides individual investments in
biomedicine, social inequalities will increase further
eroding social and intergenerational relations. Opposition
to austerity measures in many European societies in 2012
may become a regular feature of street politics with
growing unemployment and increasing inequality. Indignation against visible inequality may evolve into political
rage (Reich 2012).
Furthermore, a strict opposition between universalism
and cultural relativism is problematic because related
forms of ethics are characterized by mutual recognition and
empathy between people of different cultures. These forms
of ethics also recognize cultural identity as a key component of agency, and without sufficient agency it is difficult
to mobilize individuals to preserve their institutions.
Political anthropology has been dealing with these tensions
for some time; however they are mainly framed in efforts
to safeguard cultural diversity, which is quite different
from the problem of sustaining human rights and bioethics.
Sociology has brought more attention towards increasing
social inequalities. Amongst other things, income
inequality underlines new power struggles over life and
health between the rich and the poor areas of the world.
Assuming there is a connection between health and
wealth, relativism can nourish liberalism in biomedicine
to the expense of vulnerable groups. Post-humanists, for
example, are transforming the discursive space in which
bioethical debates are taking pace, and are proposing a detraditionalization of biomedical practices,—a process
669
described as a moving away from nature and tradition that
is essentially market-driven (Giddens 1995). This opposition to ‘tradition’ is radically changing the foundations of a
politics of life.
Contemporary health care systems and research policies
are faced with ethical questions that are derived from the
relationship between the ‘infinite demand’ for health care
services and the ‘finite systems’ of institutions (Foucault
1988). Scarcity is thus creating an ‘ethic of limits’ in which
universal claims for global health are being challenged by
various forms of relativism. In this regard, a sharper focus
on social inequalities in bioethics within the on-going
discussion on cultural diversity will certainly clarify universal thresholds regarding health status and reinforce key
objectives of social justice that are central to all major
conventions in human right and bioethics.
References
Annas, G.J., L.B. Andrews, and R.M. Isasi. 2002. Protecting the
endangered human: Toward an international treaty prohibiting
cloning and inheritable alterations. American Journal of Law
Medicine 28(2–3): 151–178.
Bellah, R.N. 2011. Religion in human evolution. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Boltanski, L. 1999. Distant suffering: Morality, media and politics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bourdieu, P. 2000. Pascalian meditations. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bury, M. 2000. Health, ageing and the lifecourse. In Health, medicine
and society: Key theories, future agendas, ed. S.J. Williams,
J. Gabe, and M. Calnan, 87–105. London: Routledge.
Charney, J. 1993. Universal international law. American Journal of
International Law 87(4): 529–551.
Charney, J., and R.W. Smith. 2002. International maritime boundaries. Dordrecht: Kluwer Law International.
Dumas, A., and B.S. Turner. 2007. The life extension project: A
sociological critique. Health Sociology Review 16(1): 5–17.
Dumas, A. and B.S. Turner. 2013. Statecraft and soulcraft: Foucault
on prolonging life. In Medical sociology on the move: new
directions in theory, ed. W.C. Cockerham. Dordrecht: Springer.
Etzioni, A. 1993. The spirit of community. New York: Touchtone.
Foucault, M. 1988. Social security. In Michel Foucault. Politics,
Philosophy, culture: Interviews and other writings, 1977–1984,
ed. L. Kritzman, 159–177. New York: Routledge.
Frank, A.W. 2012. The varieties of my body: Pain, ethics and illusion.
In Routledge handbook of body studies, ed. B.S. Turner,
389–395. New-York: Taylor and Francis.
Fukuyama, F. 2004. Transhumanism. Foreign Policy Sept–Oct 42–44.
Georgescu-Roegen, N. 1971. The entropy law and the economic
process. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Giddens, A. 1995. Affluence, poverty, and the idea of a post-scarcity
society. Geneva: United Nations Research Institute for Social
Development.
Hirsch, Fred. 1977. The social limits to growth. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Juvin, H. 2010. The coming of the body. London: Verso Press.
Kamaludeen, B.M.N., and B.S. Turner. 2012. Governing as gardening: Reflections on soft authoritarianism in Singapore. Citizenship Studies. doi:10.1080/13621025.2012.707005.
123
670
Kottow, M.H. 2004. Vulnerability: What kind of principle is it?
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 7: 281–287.
Lock, M. 1993. Encounters with aging. mythologies of Menopause in
Japan and North America. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
London, A.J. 2005. Justice and the human development approach to
international. Research Hastings Center Report 35(1): 24–37.
Lotka, A.J. 1925. Element of physical biology. Baltimore: William
and Wilkins.
Luna, F. 2009. Elucidating the concept of vulnerability. Layers not
labels. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2(1): 120–138.
MacInnes, J., and J. Pérez Diaz. 2009. Transformations of the world’s
population: The demographic revolution. In The Routledge
international handbook of globalization studies, ed. B.S. Turner,
137–161. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Moody, H. 2002. Aging and controversies, 4th ed. Thousand Oaks:
Pine Forge Press.
Moore Jr, B. 1970. Reflections on the causes of human misery and
upon certain proposals to eliminate them. London: Allen Lane.
Mouzelis, N. 2011. Encyclopedia, genealogy and tradition: A
sociocultural critique of MacIntyre’s three moral discourses.
The Sociological Review 95(1): 1–16.
Moyn, S. 2010. The last utopia. Human rights in history. Cambridge,
Mass: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Patrão Neves, M. 2009. Respect for human vulnerability and personal
integrity. In The UNESCO universal declaration on bioethics
and human rights. Background, principles and application.
Ethics Series, eds. H.A.M. ten Have and M.S. Jean, 155–164.
Paris: UNESCO Publishing,
Reich, R.B. 2012. Beyond outrage. What has gone wrong with our
economy and our democracy, and to fix it. New York: Vintage
Books.
Ruof, M.C. 2004. Vulnerability, vulnerable populations, and policy.
Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 14(4): 411–425.
123
B. S. Turner, A. Dumas
Schopenhauer, A. 2004. On the suffering of the world. London:
Penguin.
Schramm, F.R., and M. Braz. 2008. Bioethics of protection: A
proposal for the moral problems of developing countries?
Journal international de bioéthique/International journal of
bioethics 19: 73–86.
Solbakk, J.H. 2011. The principle of respect for human vulnerability
and global bioethics. In The SAGE handbook of health care
ethics: Core and emerging issues, ed. R. Chadwick, M.A.H. ten
Have, and E. Meslin, 228–238. Washington, DC: Sage.
Turner, B.S. 2006. Vulnerability and human rights. University Park,
PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Turner, B.S., and C. Rojek. 2001. Society and culture. Principles of
Scarcity and Solidarity. London: Sage.
UNESCO. 2005. Universal declaration of bioethics and human
rights. Accessible at: http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0014/
001461/146180E.pdf.
UNESCO. 2011. Report of the international bioethics committee of
UNESCO on social responsibility and health. Paris: UNESCO
Publishing.
UNESCO. 2013. Report of the international bioethics committee of
UNESCO on the principle of respect for human vulnerability and
personal integrity. Paris: UNESCO Publishing.
Waldron, J. 1987. Nonsense on stilts. Bentham, Burke and Marx on
the rights of man. London: Routledge.
Walters, J.W. 1996. Introduction. In Choosing who’s to live: Ethics
and aging, ed. J. Walters. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Williams, R.R. 1997. Hegel’s ethics of recognition. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Woodiwiss, A. 2009. Taking the sociology of rights seriously. In
Interpreting human rights. Social science perspectives, eds.
R. Morgan and B.S. Turner, 104–120. London: Routledge.