Scottish Journal of Theology (2021), 74, 147–157
doi:10.1017/S0036930621000326
RESEARCH ARTICLE
‘Synergy’, ‘energy’ and ‘symbol’ in Pavel
Florensky and Palamism
Dmitry Biryukov*
National Research University Higher School of Economics, Russian Federation
*Corresponding author. Email:
[email protected]
Abstract
This article is a study of Pavel Florensky’s philosophy of symbol in the context of his discovery of Palamism in the 1910s, when Florensky started to speak of symbol using Palamite language. It proposes a fundamental difference between Florensky’s and Palamas’ teachings on
symbol: Palamas views a natural symbol as the energy of an essence, while for Florensky symbol is the essence itself, the energy of which synergises with the energies of other essence. In
this context the prehistory of the concept of synergy in Florensky is studied, leading to the
identification of a further difference in the ontologies of Florensky and Palamas: while
Florensky’s ‘essence-energy’ has the property of necessary correlation with the ‘other’,
following the tendencies of the philosophy of that epoch, in Palamas ‘energy’ does not
presuppose any necessary correlation with the ‘other’. The author connects this difference
in ontologies between the two thinkers with their respective teachings on symbol.
Keywords: correlativity; energy; Pavel Florensky; Gregory Palamas; symbol; synergy
In this article I will consider Pavel Florensky’s philosophy of symbol in the Palamite
context and draw conclusions about the specifics of the ontological ideas of
Florensky against the Palamite background. I propose that one can distinguish two
stages in Pavel Florensky’s teaching on symbol: they may be termed pre-Palamite and
Palamite. This distinction is connected with the fact that at a certain moment of his creative activity, Florensky started to formulate the notion of symbol in the language of
Gregory Palamas.
At the heart of Palamism as a theological system, formulated in fourteenth-century
Byzantium, is the distinction in the divinity between an unknowable and imparticipable
essence on the one hand, and the knowable and participable energies of this essence on
the other. According to Gregory Palamas, the Tabor Light that was revealed to the
Apostles during the Transfiguration of Christ (Matt 17:2) is such an uncreated energy.
The first, pre-Palamite stage in Florensky’s teaching on symbol is reflected in his correspondence with Andrei Bely (Bugaev) from 1904 and in the work The Empyrean and
the Empirical from the same year.1 There Florensky speaks of symbol in order to point
1
Letter from Pavel Florensky to Boris Bugaev, 1904.VII.18; in P. V. Florensky (ed.), Obretaja put’: Pavel
Florenskij v universitetskie gody [Getting the Way: Pavel Florensky in his University Years], 2 vols (Moscow:
Progress-Tradicija, 2015), vol. 2, p. 651.
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press
/148/ out the moment of unity of the empirical world and ‘another world’ (with all their
differences): a human mind can grasp the empirical world as a symbol of the other world,
which shines through it. The empirical world
becomes the bearer of another world, its body, it embodies in itself this other
world or is spiritualized and transformed into a symbol, that is, into an organically
living unity of that which represents and that which is represented, of that which
symbolizes and that which is symbolized.2
The thinker here is far from understanding the nature of symbol simply as a sign; instead,
for Florensky, symbol acquires here connotations referring to the living, animated reality
of that which it symbolises.
The second stage belongs to the time after Russian religious thinkers discovered for
themselves Palamism during the Name-glorifying dispute of 1910s.3 In the wake of these
debates, Florensky began to formulate ‘symbol’ in terms of the essence-energy distinction
– that is, in the language of Gregory Palamas and Palamite doctrine. The terms ‘essence’
and ‘energy’ go back at least to the theology of the Cappadocian fathers of the fourth
century. There they referred to the conceptual pair unknowable-knowable, such that the
(divine) essence is unknowable, while energies of this essence are knowable. In Palamite
theology, which was influenced by Maximus the Confessor (seventh century), essenceenergy came to be connected with another conceptual pair, imparticipable-participable:
again, the (divine) essence is imparticipable, while (divine) energies are participable.4 In
Florensky’s texts the pairing essence-energy correlates with the pair unknowableknowable. Yet when we take into account the historical context of Florensky’s
philosophical activity and deliberations in the 1910s, we can confidently speak about
Palamite connotations in his use of the terms essence and energy.
Symbol in Florensky and the Palamite language of essence and energies
Although Florensky and his companions borrowed the language of essence and
energies from the Palamite doctrine, where the terms referred first of all to the
(imparticipable and unknowable) divine essence and the (participable and knowable) divine
energy, Florensky infused this language with universal meaning. He uses these terms for
describing the ontological structure of any being and any act of cognition. A good
illustration of this is a passage from Florensky’s Auto-Abstract (1925–6), where, in setting
out his own intellectual biography and worldview, he says about himself:
He sets realism as a conviction in the transsubjective reality of being against illusionism,
subjectivism and psychologism: being opens to knowledge directly. Perceptions are not
subjective, but belong to the subject, although they lie outside of him. In other words, in
knowledge the genuine expansion of the subject is
2
Pavel Florensky, Early Religious Writings, 1903–1909, trans. Boris Jakim (Grand Rapids, MI: William
B. Eerdmans, 2017), p. 55.
3
See Tatiana Senina, ‘The Status of Divine Revelation in the Works of Hieromonk Anthony Bulatovich’,
Scottish Journal of Theology 64/4 (2011), pp. 381–2.
4
See Dmitry Biriukov, ‘Hierarchies of Beings in the Patristic Thought: Maximus the Confessor, John of
Damascus and the Palamite literature’, Scrinium: Journal of Patrology and Critical Hagiography 10 (2014),
p. 300.
/149/ manifested, as well as the genuine uniting of his energy (in the sense of the
terminology of the 14th century) with the energy of the knowable reality.5
Further on Florensky continues his self-description:
F[lorensky] … considers any system to be coherent not logically, but only teleologically,
and in this logical fragmentation and inconsistency he sees an inevitable consequence of
the very process of cognition, as creating on the lower planes patterns
and schemes, and on the higher symbols.6
Here, following the natural course of the account of his own worldview, Florensky passes
from the exposition of his understanding of cognition in terms of Palamite ‘energy’ to the
idea of antinomy (namely, presence of ‘logical fragmentation and inconsistency’ in ‘the
very process of cognition’) as the basic constituent of his philosophical method. Then he
concludes his thought by approaching the subject of symbol. As we will see, in Florensky
these problematics of symbol are closely connected with the Palamite language of essenceenergies.
Thus, in his works of the Name-glorifying cycle (Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical
Premise and On the Name of God, 1919–21) Florensky, in the vein of his ‘symbolic worldunderstanding’,7 defines symbol in the following ways:
such an οὐσία [essence], the energy of which, merging with the energy of some other,
more valuable in a given aspect, oysia [essence], carries in this way that later οὐσία;8
such an essence, the energy of which, intertwined, or rather, merged with the energy of
some other essence, more valuable in this respect, carries in this way this latter in itself;9
essence, carrying, intertwined with its own energy, the energy of some other essence, by
which energy that very second essence is given.10
He also discusses the topic in the work Symbolism of Dreams (1917), where, according
to Florensky, something is recognised as a symbol ‘by indwelling in some reality of the
5
Pavel Florensky, Avtoreferat [Auto-Abstract], in Sochinenija v chetyreh tomah [Works in Four Volumes]
(Moscow: Mysl’, 1994), vol. 1, pp. 39–40. Cf. Florensky, Imeslavie kak filosofskaja predposylka
[Onomatodoxy as a Philosophical Premise], in Sochinenija v chetyreh tomah (Moscow, 2000), vol. 3/1, pp.
254–5; Florensky, On the Cultural-Historical Place and Premises of the Christian World-Understanding.
Lecture Eighteen: The Relation between Philosophy and Science [11.XI.1921], in Pavel Florensky, At the
Crossroads of Science and Mysticism: On the Cultural-Historical Place and Premises of the Christian
World-Understanding, ed. and trans. Boris Jakim (Brooklyn, NY: Angelico Press, 2014), p. 134.
6
Florensky, Avtoreferat, p. 40.
7
This worldview is generally based on the thesis that ‘a thing can bear the energy of another thing’. See
Florensky, At the Crossroads of Science and Mysticism, p. 126.
8
Pavel Florensky, Imeslavie kak filosofskaja predposylka, vol. 3/1, p. 359.
9
Ibid., p. 257.
10
Ibid., p. 263.
/150/ energy of some other reality, and therefore, by the synergism of the two – at least two
– realities’.11
In short, Florensky describes the structure of symbol in the Palamite terms of
essence and energies: symbol is an essence, the energy of which is intertwined with the
energy of some other, higher essence, thus manifesting through itself the energy of this
higher essence, and through it – that very essence itself. As we see, the teaching on symbol,
understood in this way, presupposes the concept of ‘synergy’ (or ‘synergism’). I will
address this issue further below, but first I will consider the question of the relation between
the philosophy of symbol in Pavel Florensky and Gregory Palamas.
‘Symbol’ in Gregory Palamas and Pavel Florensky
Palamas himself had a quite developed teaching on symbol. This allows us to ask
whether Gregory Palamas and Pavel Florensky understood symbol in the same way. For,
as we have seen, Florensky’s teaching on symbol is based on general foundations and
terminology of the Palamite doctrine.
Gregory Palamas’ teaching on symbol (τό σύμβολον) is expressed first of all in his
Triads, especially in the first part of the third Triad. Here Palamas polemicises against the
thesis that the Tabor Light is merely a symbol of the divinity and therefore is not uncreated;
obviously, this thesis presupposes the understanding of symbol as a conventional sign. In
his response, Palamas maintained that symbol is that which, in a natural way, manifests the
symbolised, which is manifested itself in this symbol.
Specifically, in Triads, III.1.14, 19–20, 36, Palamas distinguishes between natural
and non-natural symbols. A natural symbol is of the same nature as the symbolised. Such
a symbol always accompanies the symbolised: it naturally proceeds from the symbolized
and manifests it. By contrast, a non-natural symbol is of another nature than the
symbolised; it appears and disappears in time, not accompanying the nature of the
symbolised. As examples of natural symbols Palamas cites the light of the sun, the warmth
of a fire, and the Tabor Light, understood as one of countless uncreated energies, always
accompanying the essence of the divinity, each of which is a natural symbol of the divine
essence. A non-natural symbol is, for instance, fire which is kindled in the case of the
invasion of an enemy to notify one’s own army; signs that appeared to the Old Testament
prophets. We can say that the examples of non-natural symbols, cited by Palamas,
correspond to the communicative type of symbol.12
11
Pavel Florensky, Simvolika snovidenij [Symbolism of Dreams], in Sochinenija v chetyreh tomah, vol.
3/1, p. 424.
12
‘Every symbol either derives from the nature of the object of which it is a symbol, or belongs to an
entirely different nature. Thus, when the sun is about to rise, the dawn is a natural symbol of its light, and
similarly heat is a natural symbol of the burning power of fire. As to signs which are not connatural in this
way, and which have their own independent existence, they are sometimes considered symbols. Thus, a
burning torch might be taken as a symbol of attacking enemies. If they do not possess their own natural
existence, they can serve as a kind of phantom to foretell the future, and then the symbol consists only in
that. … So a natural symbol always accompanies the nature which gives them being, for the symbol is
natural to that nature; as for the symbol which derives from another nature, having its own existence, it is
quite impossible for it constantly to be associated with the object it symbolises, for nothing prevents it from
existing before and after this object, like any reality having its own existence. Finally, the symbol lacking
an independent existence exists neither before nor after its object, for that is impossible; as soon as it has
appeared, it at once is dissolved into nonbeing and disappears completely.’ Gregory Palamas, The Triads,
III.1.14, ed. John Meyendorff, trans. Nicholas Gendle, (New York: Paulist Press, 1983), p. 74; see also
Triads, III.1.19–20, 36. On the natural symbol in Palamas see Dmitry Biriukov,
/151/ My analysis of Pavel Florensky’s works has shown that, when he referred to patristic
authors in his philosophical and theological works, he commonly relied on the existing
Russian translations and did not turn to the untranslated patristic texts. I have, moreover,
found out which texts of Palamas and the Palamites were available to Florensky in Russian,
what his possible circle of reading in the Palamite literature was and whether he was
acquainted with Gregory Palamas’ teaching on symbol. One can maintain that the texts
containing Palamas’ teaching on symbol (as well as his theological-philosophical texts in
general) had not been translated into Russian in Florensky’s time. Small fragments of
Palamas’ Triads had been translated by Theophanes the Recluse as a part of the Russian
Philokalia, but the passages where Palamas develops his teaching on symbol (as well as
all the theological-philosophical content of the Palamite doctrine as such) were not
included there. Of all Palamite literature containing the teaching about symbol, only the
Russian translation of the exegesis for Parables 9:1 (‘Wisdom hath builded her house’) by
the Palamite Philotheus Kokkinos existed then.13 Florensky was familiar with this edition.14
But it contains only the teaching on symbol that corresponds to Palamas’ concept of nonnatural symbol. So, in my mind, Florensky was not acquainted with theologicalphilosophical works of Gregory Palamas – and with his teaching on natural symbol in
particular – at all.15 One cannot trace any connection between Florensky’s teaching on
symbol and Palamas’ doctrine of natural symbol on either the textual or the conceptual
level.
Indeed, Florensky’s philosophy of symbol, expressed in essence-energy terms, is
completely different from that of Palamas, and in some sense opposed to it. Namely,
Palamas understands energy as natural symbol of essence, while Florensky does not
consider energy as symbol, but rather considers symbol as an essence, the energy of which
synergises with the energy of another essence. Although dressed in Palamite terminological
clothing, Florensky’s symbolology conceptually follows the idea of symbol developed by
him in his pre-Palamite period, where, as we have seen, ‘symbol’ had connotations
referring to the animated reality. The same philosophy of symbol is met in those texts of
Florensky’s where he speaks about symbol in Palamite terms: symbol, understood as
essence having its own energy and capable of synergy, carries connotations of animated
being. Indeed, in his lectures on the analysis of spatiality and time in his works on fine arts
(1921), Florensky, reflecting on symbol in the Palamite terms of
‘Neilos Kabasilas’s Rule of Theology and the Distinction between the Light and Warmth of Fire in Neilos
Kabasilas and Gregory Palamas’, Scrinium: Journal of Patrology and Critical Hagiography 14 (2018), p.
390.
13
Bishop Arsenius, Filofeja, patriarha Konstantinopol’skogo XIV veka tri rechi k episkopu Ignatiju, s
ob’jasneniem izrechenija pritchej: Premudrost’ sozda sebe dom i proch [Three Discourses of Philotheus,
Patriarch of Constantinople, Addressed to Bishop Ignatius with an Explanation of the Expression of the
Proverb: ‘Wisdom hath builded her house’, etc.], Greek text and Russian translation (Novgorod, 1898).
14
Pavel Florensky, The Pillar and Ground of the Truth: An Essay in Orthodox Theodicy in Twelve Letters
[1914], trans. Boris Jakim (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997), p. 557, n. 693.
15
My research has shown that the only sources about the philosophical content of the Palamite doctrine
available in Florensky’s circle were the anathemas against Barlaam and Akindinos in the conciliar decision
of 1351, quoted in the Synodikon of Orthodoxy, which had been published by that time by Fyodor Uspensky
as Sinodik v nedelju pravoslavija. Svodnyj tekst s prilozhenijami [The Synodikon of the Sunday of
Orthodoxy: Summary with Appendices] (Odessa, 1893).
/152/ essence and energy, says that this essence-symbol is an artist himself, whose energy
unites with the energy of ‘another reality’.16
I will touch upon the basic philosophical premises of this divergence between
Florensky and Palamas later. First, I will consider the terms ‘synergy’ and ‘synergism’,
which, as we have seen, play an important role in Florensky’s philosophy of symbol.
From ‘synergism’ to ‘synergy’
When Florensky uses the term synergy or synergism, he sometimes uses the Greek
form συνεργεία,17 which obviously refers to the Byzantine-patristic background of its
theological use. This concept appears in Florensky’s works after he discovered Palamism
for himself.18
The notion ‘synergy’ is morphologically closely connected to the notion ‘energy’
(ἐνέργεια), one of the key terms in Palamite doctrine. It can seem that the notion of
synergism in Florensky is conditioned by his reception of the Palamite doctrine.19
However, I would contend that it is not so. On the one hand, the term ‘synergy’ is not more
characteristic of the theological lexicon of Gregory Palamas than of other Byzantine
authors; indeed, one can even say that Palamas utilises this term and its derivatives quite
rarely. On the other hand, as I have said, there is no evidence that Florensky had read
Palamas’ theological-philosophical texts. At the same time, as I will show, the notion of
‘synergy’ appeared in Russian religious and theological literature at the end of the
nineteenth century and gradually manifested itself at the very beginning of the twentieth
century, until it gained stability in Florensky’s lexicon.
I suggest the following reconstruction of the emergence of the term in Florensky.
The term ‘synergism’ appeared in Russian scholarly literature as a calque from the German
Synergismus, which, in its turn, is derived from Greek συνεργία/συνέργεια (‘cooperation,
‘co-participation’). The original form in which this term was used in Russian theological
literature (i.e. the form ‘synergism’) is explained by its borrowing from German
Synergismus, which corresponds less well than ‘synergy’ to the original Greek word
συνεργία, but which, in the end, has remained in Russian language. The notion of
Synergismus was utilised in German church history scholarship to denote the position of
Erasmus of Rotterdam, Philipp Melanchthon and others regarding a correlation between
the human will and the divine grace. This position upheld the necessity of the human
cooperation with divine grace for human salvation.20 It was defined in opposition to the
Lutheran and Calvinist ‘monoenergism’, derived from Augustine and presupposing that
the salvation is effected by divine grace alone.
16
Pavel Florensky, Analiz prostranstvennosti i vremeni v hudozhestvenno-izobrazitel’nyh proizvedenijah
[Spatial and Time Analysis in the Art and Graphic Works] (Moscow: Progress, 1993), p. 302.
17
Pavel Florensky, Ob Imeni Bozhnem [On the Name of God], in Sochinenija v chetyreh tomah, vol. 3/1,
p. 358.
18
Pavel Florensky, Simvolika snovidenij, p. 423; Magichnost’ slova [Magic of the Word] [1920], in
Sochinenija v chetyreh tomah, vol. 3/1, p. 240; Imeslavie kak filosofskaja predposylka, pp. 257, 259, 261;
Ob imeni Bozhiem, p. 358.
19
See Clemena Antonova, Visual Thought in Russian Religious Philosophy: Pavel Florensky’s Theory of
the Icon (New York: Routledge, 2020), pp. 30–1.
20
See e.g. G. Frank, ‘Synergismus’, in Realencyclopadie D. A. Hauck (Leipzig, 1884), Heft 141–50, S.
103–13. An example of corresponding Russian usage in this context can be found in Alexander Katansky,
Uchenie o Blagodati Bozhiej v tvorenijah drevnih sv. otcov i uchitelej Cerkvi do bl. Avgustina. Istorikodogmaticheskoe issledovanie [Teaching on the Grace of God in Church Fathers up to Augustine of Hippo.
A Historical and Dogmatic Research] (St Petersburg, 1902), p. 19.
/153/ The ‘synergistic’ positions of Erasmus and Melanchthon are ideologically close to
the so-called semi-Pelagian teachings of the fifth century about the relation between human
freedom and divine grace, which took a polemical stance against Augustinism but were
held by many Byzantine authors. This was the reason why Russian church historian Vassily
Bolotov brought the term back from the Reformation context to the Byzantine one. This
term appeared in his lectures on early church history, where he, in discussing the position
of the Western bishops in the Byzantine East, touched upon the Pelagian controversy. In
this context, Bolotov speaks of ‘synergism’ as a characteristic position of Byzantine
theologians in the Pelagian controversy.21 In a similar context, this notion occurs in the
materials of the Proceedings of St Petersburg’s Religio-Philosophical Meetings. There it
is mentioned that in the 17th meeting (1903) a person called S. Zorin discussed Bolotov’s
understanding of the development of the dogmatic consciousness of the Byzantine church
and spoke about ‘synergism’ of the divine and the human in this process.22
Further on, the notion of synergism appears in the study by S. Zarin (perhaps the
same person as S. Zorin mentioned above), devoted to the patristic foundations of
asceticism. This study was published in 1907 under the title Asceticism according to the
Orthodox Christian Teaching. Zarin insists that the Orthodox view on man’s salvation
presupposes both divine and human constituents. In this connection, he states: ‘The
Orthodox teaching affirms the synergism of divine grace and the human freedom’ and he
gives in a note a short reference about the notion of synergism.23 He mentions there the
passages from the Gospel and early church thinkers (Clement of Alexandria, Origen and
Gregory of Nyssa) and refers to the position of Erasmus and Melanchthon in the
Reformation controversy on freedom and grace.24
At the same time, the concept of synergy – almost framed as a term – also appears
in the work A System of Philosophy: An Attempt at a Scientific Synthesis (1903–4) by a
thinker who had a great influence upon Pavel Florensky: Archimandrite Serapion
Mashkin.25 Mashkin and Florensky knew each other through correspondence and never
met personally. In 1905, after Mashkin’s death, Florensky acquired his archive. After
Florensky had delved deeply into the ideas of the A System of Philosophy, he felt great
closeness between his own worldview and Mashkin’s philosophy. Therefore, during the
writing of The Pillar and Ground of the Truth Florensky made use of ‘very many ideas’ of
Serapion, and said about himself: ‘I do not even know where his [Serapion’s] ideas end
and where mine begin’.26
Archimandrite Serapion systematically uses the term ‘synergy’. In Mashkin’s A
System of Philosophy, this term occurs most often when he speaks about humanity’s
21
Vassily Bolotov, Lekcii po istorii Drevnej Cerkvi. III. Istorija Cerkvi v period Vselenskih
soborov. I. Cerkov’ i gosudarstvo. II. Cerkovnyj stroj [Lectures on the History of the Ancient Church. III]
(St Petersburg, 1913), p. 316.
22
Sergei Polovinkin (ed.), Zapiski peterburgskih Religiozno-filosofskih sobranij [Proceedings of St
Petersburg’s Religio-Philosophical Meetings] (Moscow: Respublika, 2005), p. 368.
23
Sergei Zarin, Asketizm po pravoslavno-hristianskomu ucheniju. Tom pervyj: Osnovopolozhitel’nyj.
Kniga vtoraja: opyt sistematicheskogo raskrytija voprosa (Asceticism according to the Orthodox Christian
Teaching, vol. 1, Fundamental. Book 2: The Experience of Systematic Disclosure) (St Petersburg, 1907),
p. 75, cf. p. 692.
24
Ibid., pp. 75–6, n. 42.
25
Pavel Florensky, ‘Otoshedshie. Arhimandrit Serapion (Mashkín) (Zhizn’ myslitelja)’ [Those Who Have
Gone. Archimandrite Serapion (Mashkin) (Life of the Thinker)], Symbol 68–9 (2016), p. 259.
26
Florensky, The Pillar and Ground of the Truth, p. 438.
/154/ agreement with God.27 Mashkin also speaks about the synergy of Christ with God
the Father,28 as well as about the synergy of ‘many’ when they reach unity and harmonious
coordination in the truth.29 As we have seen, before Mashkin the notion of ‘synergism’ had
a narrow, technical meaning conditioned by the way through which it came into Russian
language: the co-direction of human aspiration and the divine will. ‘Synergy’ in Mashkin
includes this meaning, but he has a strong tendency to use the notion of ‘synergy’ in a
universal sense. One can say that in Mashkin ‘synergy’ is a term referring to the idea of
dynamic unity as such. I should also note that Mashkin uses the form ‘synergy’, and not
‘synergism’, which had been used in Russian before. Mashkin’s ‘synergy’ thus appears as
if from nowhere, without any connection with the previous Russian tradition. I conclude
that this notion appears in his work independently, and is not derived from the conception
of ‘synergism’ that had up to that point been employed in Russian theological literature (as
I have outlined above).
To my mind, the notion of synergism/synergy appeared in Florensky’s lexicon under
influence of the two above-mentioned sources: the essay of Mashkin on the one hand, and
the book of Zarin on the other. The influence of Mashkin on Florensky is obvious. As for
Zarin’s Asceticism, we know that Florensky read it from his mention of this book in The
Pillar and Ground of the Truth.30 One of the aspects why Zarin’s book that was appealing
for Florensky was that Zarin was one of the first (if not the first) Russian theologian to
devote a few pages to the philosophically loaded account of the Palamite teaching about
the distinction of essence and energies in the divinity, drawing on Palamas’ own works.31
The influence of both these sources (namely, the works of Mashkin and Zarin) is evident
from the fact that Florensky uses the term in both forms, ‘synergism’ and ‘synergy’,
without making any distinction between them (though ‘synergy’ is used more often): we
can see him following Mashkin’s usage in ‘synergy’, and Zarin’s in ‘synergism’.
27
Archimandrite Serapion (Mashkin), ‘Sistema filosofii: Opyt nauchnogo sinteza. V dvuh chastjah. Chast’
I’ [A System of Philosophy: An Attempt at a Scientific Synthesis. In two parts. Part I], Simvol 67 (2016),
pp. 267, 421, 463. This publication, from only a few years ago, is the first edition of A System of Philosophy.
It represents only the first part of the last revision of A System of Philosophy by Serapion. The second part,
according to Florensky, ‘remains in the form of separate fragments and even in the form of jottings that are
barely legible owing to the indecipherability of the handwriting’ (Florensky, The Pillar and Ground of the
Truth, p. 439).
28
Archimandrite Serapion (Mashkin), Sistema filosofii, pp. 422–3.
29
Ibid., p. 541.
30
Florensky, The Pillar and Ground of the Truth, pp. 533, 570.
31
Zarin, Asketizm, pp. 405–7, see also pp. 93–4, n. 118. It is interesting, that, expounding the Palamite
teaching about the distinction of the unparticipable essence and participable energies in God, Zarin refers
to the dialogue Theophanes and the treatise 150 Chapters by Palamas and quotes them (Asketizm, pp. 403,
406). At the same time, as we can see from the texts, the first Russian religious philosopher who, when he
got interested in Palamism, turned directly to the dogmatic texts of Gregory Palamas, was Sergei Bulgakov,
the closest friend of Florensky. See Sergei Bulgakov, Svet Nevechernij. Sozercanija i umozrenija [Unfading
Light: Contemplations and Speculations] (Moscow: Respublika, 1994), pp. 111–13; cf. Hegumen Andronik
(Trubachev) (ed.), Perepiska svjashhennika Pavla Aleksandrovicha Florenskogo so svjashhennikom
Sergiem Nikolaevichem Bulgakovym [Correspondence between Priest Pavel Florensky and Priest Sergiy
Bulgakov] (Tomsk: Vodolej, 2001), p. 78 (Bulgakov’s letter to Florensky from 15 Feb. 1914). I think it is
very probable that Bulgakov, when he turned to the philosophical-dogmatic content of the Palamite
doctrine, relied on Zarin’s book.
/155/Following Serapion Mashkin, Florensky employs the notion of
synergism/synergy in the universal sense, not limiting it only to the synergy of man with
God.32 And whereas in Mashkin there was merely a tendency towards the universalisation
of this notion, in Florensky it acquires a genuinely universal meaning. Thus, in his
Onomatodoxy Florensky speaks of synergy as a connection and relationship of beings.
Such synergy is both characteristic of each of these beings and something new, for the
energies of these beings, when uniting, create a reality that is new in respect to each of
them.33 This new synergetic reality, which was created through union of the energies of the
two beings, is more than itself if one of the beings is the cause of the other.34 In this way,
Florensky leads the reader to the subject of symbol, which, according to him, presupposes
the presence of two – more valuable and less valuable – essences: such that the energy of
symbol, as the less valuable essence, carries the energy of the more valuable essence.35
So, Florensky’s attitude was to make ‘synergy’ as universal as possible, taking it in
this way beyond the limits of theology into the field of philosophy. This was reflected also
in how he ‘plays’ with the corresponding term, as evidenced by the fact that a few times in
Onomatodoxy Florensky uses the form ‘synenergy’, a neologism which appears to be
intended to point to a new approach to the old concepts implemented by the thinker.36 The
form ‘synenergy’ is made up by Florensky as a calque of the Greek συνενέργεια, although
such a form never existed in patristic Greek (unlike ἡ συνέργεια, which ‘synergy’
corresponds to).
‘Correlative’ and ‘non-correlative’ ontologies: Consequences for the theory of symbol
Now I will again turn to the problematics of symbol in Florensky. As I have shown,
although Florensky, conceptualising the notion of symbol, actively used the Palamite
essence-energy language, his philosophy of symbol is essentially different from Palamas’.
Gregory Palamas understood energy as natural symbol of essence, while for Florensky
energy as such is not considered as symbol; symbol for him is an essence synergising with
other essences. One can put a question: what are the foundations upon which Florensky’s
philosophy of symbol is built, which make it different from Palamas’ philosophy of
symbol?
I see two lines in this respect. One, more particular line, is connected to the
‘Goetheanism’ of Florensky and the corresponding concept of the ‘sun sight’, understood
as a paradigm for the process of cognition. I will treat this topic in another article.
32
On synergy in this sense in Florensky see e.g. Pavel Florensky, Filosofija kul’ta (Opyt pravoslavnoj
antropodicei) [Philosophy of Cult (Experience of Orthodox Anthropodicea)] (Moscow: Akademicheskij
proekt, 2014), pp. 384–5, 396.
33
Florensky, Imeslavie kak filosofskaja predposylka, p. 256.
34
Ibid., p. 257.
35
Ibid. I want to point out that, after the concept of synergy was entered in Florensky’s lexicon, it appeared
in the works of Sergei Bulgakov as well: this concept was actively used at least in the late work of Bulgakov,
The Bride of the Lamb (written in 1939, the first edition in 1945, in Russian). Bulgakov uses it in the
technical sense (i.e. in the context of speaking of the correlation between God and the created world; see,
first of all, section I, chapter 4, ‘God and Created Freedom’; section II, chapter 7, ‘God and Afterlife
Existence’; and section III, ‘Eschatology’). For this reason, this notion was used in The Bride of the Lamb
in the form ‘synergism’, which in Russian theological literature, as we have seen, traditionally referred to
the aforementioned technical sense.
36
Florensky, Imeslavie kak filosofskaja predposylka, pp. 256, 259.
/156/ Here I will trace the second, fundamental line, connected with the divergence of the
basic ontological intuitions of Florensky and Palamas.
Palamas’ doctrine presupposes two interconnected modes of being: the mode of
being concealed in itself and unmanifested (in Palamism this links up with the notion of
‘essence’) and the mode of manifestation, which discloses what is unmanifested (this is
tied to the notion of ‘energy’). In the Palamite language, this entails a distinction in unity
between the unknowable and imparticipable essence and knowable and participable energy
of this essence. The aspect of distinction of essence and energy consists in the fact that
energy is not essence; the aspect of their unity is that energy manifests essence, being the
energy of this essence. A paradoxical philosophical move of Palamism is that this
distinction between unmanifested and its manifestation becomes substantive, such that it
is held to exist independently from the fact of whether anybody actually perceives the
manifestation (energy). Accordingly, the participable and knowable divine energies, in
distinction from the imparticipable and unknowable divine essence that they manifest, are
considered in the Palamite doctrine as always inherent in the divine essence and therefore
existing without connection with and independently from the created world.37 I suggest
that this fundamental Palamite insight, carrying certain paradoxicality in itself, was not
shared by Florensky. Indeed, he was just not aware of the specifics of the Palamite teaching
in this respect (since, as I have shown, he was not acquainted with philosophically loaded
works of Palamas).
Thus, in his lectures on the premises of the Christian worldview, Florensky,
expounding the position of Palamas in the context of the Palamite controversy, says:
The Orthodox understanding is that one can indeed see God, but what one sees is not His
essence but His energy. The energy seems not to express the essence, but it is God insofar
as He is revealed to people, and the essence is God as He is in Himself. … For every
entity, the essence is the side turned toward itself, whereas the energy is the side turned
outward; in other words, only non-being does not have energies.38
As we see, unlike Palamas, Florensky understands the divine energies as something
directed by God ‘outward’, to people as created beings, and in this respect he distinguishes
energies from the divine essence, which is ‘God as He is in Himself’. However, within the
framework of the Palamite doctrine there is, paradoxically, no
37
Gregory Palamas’ teaching presumes that the energies in the divinity (and, accordingly, the difference
between the divine essence and energies) exists regardless of the created world. In this sense we can say
that relativity is not inherent to the category of energy in historical Palamism. But at the same time Palamas’
doctrine includes the teaching about the kind of divine energies which exist only in their relation to the
created world. These are the ‘creating’ energies, by which various kinds of created beings are produced and
in which they participate (see Gregory Palamas, Triads, I.3.27; III.2.5–7; 150 Chapters, 72–3, 113, 140; on
the structure and hierarchy of these ‘relational’ energies in Palamas see Biriukov, ‘Hierarchies of Beings in
the Patristic Thought’, pp. 294–303). This means that Palamas’ doctrine includes the kind of energies which
are ‘relational’, although this property of ‘correlativity’ within the frames of Palamism does not apply to
the category of divine energy as such.
38
Using the formula ‘only non-being does not have energy’, Florensky refers to the anathemas against
Barlaam and Akindinos from the Synodikon of Orthodoxy: Uspensky, Sinodik v nedelju pravoslavija [The
Synodikon of the Sunday of Orthodoxy], p. 31 (for the modern edition, see Jean Gouillard, ‘Le Synodikon
de l’orthodoxie: Édition et commentaire’, Travaux et mémoires 2 (1967), p. 83.589–90). Pavel Florensky,
‘On the Cultural-Historical Place and Premises, Lecture Seventeen’, in At the Crossroads of Science and
Mysticism, p. 126.
/157/‘outward’ for God, where His energies necessarily would be directed to; rather, the
divine energies are God in Himself in the same way as the divine essence. In Onomatodoxy
Florensky gives a more universal picture and speaks not of the divine essence and energies,
but of essence and energy as such:
Being has an inner side, by which it is turned to itself in its unconfusedness with all that is
not it, and the external side, directed to the other being. These are the two sides; but they
are not attachments to each other and are in the original unity; they are one and the same
being, although in different directions. One side serves self-assertion of being, the other –
its disclosing, manifesting, uncovering or whatever name you can call this life, connecting
one being with the other being. According to the ancient terminology, these two sides of
being are called essence, ουσία, and action, or energy, ενέργεια.39
One can discern in this fragment essential features of Florensky’s ontological ideas,
expressed here in terms of essence and energy. Specifically, Florensky’s ontology
presupposes internal and external sides in any unit of being, and these two sides are in
unity. One is connected with self-assertion of the being in its own existential core, the other
with its disclosing outwards. This disclosing, being directed outwards, interacts and
connects this unit of being with the other. Florensky links the first side with the notion of
essence, the second with the notion of energy. This ontology would seem to be close to the
Palamite one. However, it is not: the Palamite doctrine, as I have said, does not presuppose
that energy (namely, manifestation of essence) is necessarily turned outside, to some other
being; energy in Palamite ontology does not require the presence of another being, with
which it would have to interact. One can affirm here that the correction of the ontological
frame of Palamism made by Florensky (namely, his ascribing to the concept of energy the
property of necessary correlation with the other) is connected with the personalist and
existentialist tendencies relevant for the philosophical field of the beginning of the
twentieth century. By contrast, Palamite ontology proper is not personalist or loaded
existentially.
In this way, Florensky’s philosophy of symbol is linked to the specifics of his
ontology: this is a personalistically loaded ontology, in which energy of essence is
understood as correlational, and which necessarily presupposes synergetic interactions of
essences by means of their energies. Appropriately, this ontology makes the conception of
symbol also loaded personalistically, whereas the Palamite natural symbol proceeds from
a non-personalist and non-correlative ontology, where essence and its energy are not held
to be necessarily correlating with other essences and energies. Such teaching of natural
symbol would be impossible within the frames of the ‘correlational’ or personalist ontology
of Florensky, where energy of essence has to be synergetically correlated with energies of
other essences. As a result of exactly this ontology, inside Florensky’s philosophy a
conception of symbol was matured, which harked back to Florensky’s early insights, and
which was based on the principle of correlation.
39
Florensky, Imeslavie kak filosofskaja predposylka, p. 255.