making enemies
Isak Hammar
making enemies
The Logic of Immorality
in Ciceronian Oratory
LUND UNIVERSITY 2013
Printed with the inancial support of
the National Graduate School of History
ISBN 978-91-7473-614-4 (pdf)
isbn 978-91-7473-613-7
© Isak Hammar
Lund University 2013
Cover Image: Cicero in the Senate Accusing Catiline
of Conspiracy. Fresco by Cesare Maccari, 1889
© IBL Bildbyrå / Bridgeman Art Library
/ Ancient Art and Architecture Collection Ltd.
Book design: John Hagström
Printed in Stockholm, Sweden 2013
to my mother, the historian
Table of Contents
Acknowledgments
Introduction
10
15
Making Sense of Immorality 17
Approaches to Roman Immorality 22
The Study of Roman Immorality 25
Tracing Roman Immorality 27
A Moral Paradox? 29
Outline 30
Chapter I: Methodology, Sources, and Scope
Searching for Immorality: Purpose 33
Finding Immorality: Method 34
Understanding Immorality: Theory 36
Reading Cicero: Sources 41
Deining Immorality: Concepts 44
Speech as Text: Delivery, Audience, and Publication
Deining a Political Culture 50
Previous Scholarship 52
Approaching Rhetoric 53
Invective 57
Immorality 65
Character, Ethos, and Self-fashioning
67
Immorality in Roman Political Culture
70
Chapter II: Roman Political Culture
Political Power in the Late Republic
The Roman Republic
75
74
73
32
48
The Political System 77
Power in Practice 82
Aristocratic Competition 87
Roman Oratory 92
Rhetoric at Rome 96
The Development of Roman Rhetoric 97
Rhetorical Divisions 99
Vituperatio 102
Character in Roman Rhetorical Theory 104
Roman Morality
Ethos
106
112
Summary: Power, Oratory, and Morality
in the Late Republic 114
Chapter III: Defense and Prosecution
—The Early Years (80–69 BCE) 116
The Case of Sextus Roscius from Ameria
117
On the Importance of Character 119
The Immoral Chrysogonus 127
The Portrayal of Gaius Verres
131
The Prosecution 134
The Immoral Charge 135
No Ordinary Criminal 142
A Portrait in Greed 145
The Depravity of Desire 153
The Immoral Arena 163
Gaius Verres the Tyrant 165
Conclusions: Defense and Prosecution
Chapter IV: Republican Politics
—The Consular Years (66–59 BCE)
Forensic Negotiations 171
Conspiracy and Immorality 177
The Mind of a Conspirator
182
167
169
The Life of a Conspirator 187
The Company of a Conspirator 207
The Question of Stuprum 218
Conclusion: Republican Politics
223
Chapter V: Political Conflicts
—After the Exile (57–52 BCE) 227
Exile and Return 228
The Appearance of Immorality 230
The Web of Sexual Immorality 252
The Excessive and The Immoral 274
Conclusion: Political Conlicts 280
Chapter VI: End Game
—The Final Years (44–43 BCE)
286
The Battle for the Republic 287
Immorality Revisited 291
Immorality Portrayed 293
Immorality Displayed 302
The Logic of Immoral Life 306
Immorality as Political Argument 312
The Threat of Immorality 317
Conclusions: Making Enemies 323
The Meaning of Immorality 324
The Immorality Argument—Improbitatem coarguo
A Web of Immorality—Praeterea vitiis 332
The Logic of Immorality 335
Bibliography 339
Index of Subjects 360
Index of Names 365
Index Locorum 370
329
Acknowledgments
Although this is a book about making enemies, the years I
have spent writing it have only been about making friends. It is
a peculiar thing, working on a thesis and it is, in my experience
a peculiar and enormously rewarding world that opens up as a
result of the opportunity to do so. From day one, I have loved
this singular world and the main reason is because of its inhabitants. Without many of the individuals mentioned here and the
help of colleagues and friends this task would have been impossible. My irst heartfelt thanks goes out to the people who make
sure that the ordinary day is never dull, never predictable—to
everyone at the Department of History at Lund University. Tack
samtliga!
Second, I wish to thank my two supervisors in this endeavor,
Professor of History Dick Harrison and Professor emeritus of
Classical Archaeology and Ancient History Örjan Wikander. I
am extremely grateful to you both. When I irst entertained the
thought of changing direction for my inal paper as a student
and explore the really, really old kind of history, Dick was not
only very encouraging but also taught me in a lot about the craft
as he guided my somewhat naïve ideas into clarity. Without him,
there probably would not have been any book about ancient
Rome. He has been a loyal supporter ever since and has provided helpful comments while letting me make and correct my
own mistakes before running interference. He has also proven
10
acknowledgments
11
himself a master of cutting red tape and keeping the pace. Tack
för allt, Dick!
With extreme generosity, Örjan has allowed me the beneit of
his enormous expertise on everything regarding ancient Rome.
Without this support who knows quite frankly how a historian
writing about ancient history—an audacious attempt to be
sure—would have managed. With incredible precision Örjan has
tirelessly helped me sharpen my texts and ideas. I am particularly
grateful for your advice regarding my translations and for your
amazing and generous efforts with the indices! But the most
important thing has been our meetings—complete with coffee,
Danish, and cigars—talking about good old Marcus Tullius and
his world. These sessions have been deinite highpoints these
years and I have always left them smiling and feeling invigorated.
Ett stort tack vill jag rikta till dig, Örjan!
I have been blessed with additional mentors. As a result of
a generous scholarship by STINT, I was in 2011/12 given the
opportunity to spend part of my training at the Classical Department at Boston University working together with Professor Ann
Vasaly, who not only kindly invited me to visit but generously offered her time and remarkable expertise. Thank you Ann for our
stimulating talks, your invaluable comments, and much needed
notes. I will always be grateful!
The months in Boston were among the best of my life. I wish
to thank everyone at the department for making this possible
(especially Stacy Fox for all her amazing work with facilitating
my stay). A special appreciation is reserved for all the PhDs, most
of who I now consider myself lucky to call friends, and everyone
else who made this not only an academically rewarding, but also
socially fantastic experience. Particularly, I wish to thank Dustin
W. Dixon for hours of conversation, helpful comments, and true
friendship.
12
acknowledgments
Being a historian writing about ancient Rome has presented
certain challenges but also many opportunities. Swedish and
international scholars from the areas of Classics, Latin, and
most of all Ancient History (AKS) have been instrumental in alleviating the irst and supplying the second. Thank you everyone
at AKS at Lund University for welcoming me to your seminars
and lectures (för detta ett särskilt tack till Professor Eva Rystedt
och Professor Anne-Marie Leander Touati) and for giving valuable comments and criticism. I am also especially grateful for
the support of Lovisa Brännstedt and Johan Vekselius as fellow
“Roman” PhDs.
Another ancient historian serving as mentor for me has been
Ida Östenberg, an avid supporter and vital commentator and critic along the way, who also generously invited me to the Moving
City conferences in Rome. Stort tack, Ida! As one of the organizers behind the excellent FokusRom network she has together
with others also greatly facilitated the interaction with AKS in
Sweden. A collective thanks to all the participants of the Moving
City project (and especially Anthony Corbeill for taking an interest in my topic and for offering helpful advice) and to everyone
involved with FokusRom! I also want to mention particularly
ancient historian Dominic Ingemark for accepting (at the last
minute) the role of “opponent” at my inal seminar and for his
subsequent thorough reading of my irst draft and his priceless
comments and advice. Tack, Dominic!
I feel a special gratitude toward the PhDs at the Department of
History at Lund in general and to my own generation (“Lekstugan”) in particular. Tack för alla kommentarer, råd och inte minst
skratt under åren! Special recognitions are due David LarssonHeidenblad and Christopher Collstedt for their dedication
beyond the call of duty as regard my own project. I also want
to express my gratitude to Professor Eva Österberg, Professor
acknowledgments
13
Kim Salomon, and Professor Harald Gustafsson for having taken
a special interest in my texts and in my thesis. Additionally,
Professor Ulf Zander has acted as an enormously valuable “third
reader” and offered supportive and helpful comments and insights on structure and academic writing. Tack, Ulf!
Kenneth Johansson, Evelin Stetter, Ingegerd Christiansson,
Barbro Bergner, Charlotte Tornbjer, and Leopoldo Iorizzo all deserve to be mentioned for their kind administrative assistance as
do collectively all those who work with the National Graduate
School of History. I also wish to thank Alan Crozier, who provided a skilled and eficient proof reading of my book.
In one area my gratitude is solely directed at one person. Without the skill and dedication of my great friend and editor John
Hagström this book would be nowhere near as strikingly elegant!
Tack John för din fantastiska insats!
Friends and family have provided support over the years. Tack
till er alla, syskon och vänner! I wish to thank my father, most
importantly for his devout support even before I was accepted
into the National Graduate School of History. Tack, far! At one
point he offered to put our summerhouse up as collateral if I did
not get in! My brothers and sisters probably do not know this…
In one aspect, I am more grateful than anything for the opportunity given to me by academia. During my irst year as PhDstudent I met the love of my life, Anna. Simultaneously my best
friend and my most important colleague, your comments and
advice have been imperative for this book and your loving support has been a constant source of energy and joy. Mitt största
tack och all min kärlek till dig, inaste! Du gör mig lycklig, skrt! I
should also thank my daughter Vilhelmina for bringing so much
happiness to us (not to mention much needed diversion from the
task of inishing a thesis) and for supporting your dad by letting
him get more hours of sleep than he could have hoped for!
14
acknowledgments
This book is dedicated to my mother who passed away before
I gained entrance into the mysterious and fascinating world of
academia which she loved. Among my most cherished memories
are the times when we discussed, debated, and argued history.
She remains my biggest role model as a historian. Jag saknar dig,
mamma! Denna bok är tillägnad dig.
Till min mor, historikern.
Baskemölla, augusti 2013
Introduction
In 43 BCE Marcus Tullius Cicero, the man considered Rome’s
greatest orator and one of the leading statesmen of his time, was
killed on the orders of his political enemy Marcus Antonius. He
was killed as a consequence of his oratory. In the year leading up
to his demise, Cicero had attempted to convince the Senate and
people of Rome that Marcus Antonius was not only his personal
enemy but the enemy of Rome and as such had to be met with
military force. The chief instrument of his political endeavor was
public speeches. On the speaker’s platform however, Cicero not
only debated a particular course of action or political point of
view but also discussed at great length what kind of man Antonius was. Over the course of his attempt to bring down his
adversary he presented his audience with a portrait.
Marcus Antonius was a dangerous man and a man, Cicero
argued, marked both by his stupidity and by his violent nature.
He was a gladiator and a bandit, a tyrant and a foul beast. But
Cicero also depicted his enemy as a man distinguished by his
immorality; his lust and sexual corruption, his debauchery and
drunkenness, his effeminacy and un-Roman ways. The list of
vices was long. Among his friends were the worst of society. His
house was full of gamblers and prostitutes. He was a glutton and
always drunk. He had no shame and no modesty. The personal
immorality of Marcus Antonius was thus made relevant to the
political issue at hand as his opponent argued that a life of vice
15
16
making enemies
was an argument for political action. In trying to achieve his own
political ends—and perhaps even in attempting to save the failing
Republic—Cicero chose to relentlessly and furiously attack the
moral character of his enemy. And he was killed for it.
This episode in Roman history might serve to illustrate several
aspects of the Roman political culture of the late Republic. The
political climate at this point in history was ierce and fundamentally based on conlict between individuals. Whether in
the politically charged courts, at the Rostra of the Forum or in
the Senate, Roman politicians opposed each other with great
intensity, competing for inluence at the expense of each other.
The stakes were high, the outcome uncertain. The bout between
Antonius and Cicero furthermore illustrates the centrality of
oratory in this political culture. Oratory was the tool to win in
court, gain favor with the populace in elections, and persuade
your peers of the right political action. Moreover, oratory was
the main weapon in the political rivalries of Republican Rome.
But the duel between Cicero and Antonius might also leave
us with several questions about how we are to understand these
attacks on Antonius’ morality and character. Emphasizing moral
faults could, from a modern standpoint, be seen as politically irrelevant and inappropriate, petty even; certainly unworthy of a
man of eloquence and philosophy such as Cicero. We might wonder, then, why Rome’s greatest orator chose character abuse as a
rhetorical strategy. What part did such a “portrait of immorality”
play for the decision of the Senate? Furthermore, in what way did
moral corruption relate to the political question? What place did
immorality have in Roman political culture? Questions such as
these are the focus of the following study.
Introduction
17
Making Sense of Immorality
This is a book about Roman immorality and its place in political oratory in ancient Rome during the late Republic. It traces
the portraits of immorality that Cicero made of his political and
forensic enemies throughout his career. It aims to analyze how
and why immorality could be summoned as an argument in oratory. The representation of Marcus Antonius was but the last in a
long line of portrayals of individuals in the orator’s path; some of
these belonged to notorious villains like Gaius Verres and Lucius
Sergius Catilina, others were painted of little-known Romans
caught in his cross hairs. They are found in speeches not only
before senators but also before voters and juries. During his long
and illustrious career, Cicero constantly found new targets in his
oratory. As prosecutor, defense attorney, and magistrate—always
as politician—he engaged in verbal battle with fellow members
of the elite. They were, in his depictions, thieves, murderers, conspirators, and, like Antonius, enemies of the state. They were
dangerous and deviant. They also had one thing in common—
they were all accused of immorality.
Because this is a book about immorality and not about political events or the art of rhetoric, it ascribes no small amount of
relevance to these depictions and discussions of immorality. Yet,
Cicero’s focus on the moral shortcomings of Marcus Antonius
might strike us as misplaced and in fact irrelevant. For a long
time this was the prevailing view of classical scholarship. The
topic of immorality was an unfortunate byproduct of Roman
politics and nothing to be taken seriously.1 As a consequence, it
1
See Pocock 1926, p. 88; Syme 1939, p. 104. For discussions on the views of
previous scholarship, see Edwards 1993, pp. 2, 6–11; Vasaly 1993, p. 246;
Corbeill 1996, pp. 22–24; Powell 2006, pp. 18–20. See also Stroh 1975, p. 26.
18
making enemies
has been either ignored or brushed aside.
The irst problem with immorality was the apparent lack of veracity in Cicero’s claims. Although some scholars deemed certain
of his enemies as simply deserving of the harsh treatment, others
were aware that the orator did not let himself be constrained to
any, in their opinion, justiiable category of moral delinquents.2
More damning was the fact that he himself was accused along the
same lines. At the same time, this pointed to a second problem:
the recurrence of character charges. Cicero’s attacks on the immorality of his adversaries have been read as part of a genre with
similar attacks to be found in poems, comedy, and grafiti—not
to mention the entire corpus of Ciceronian oratory—alongside
charges of tyranny, taunts of cowardice or embarrassing family
history, and even derision of someone’s lack of skill in public
speaking.3 Such invective, scholars began to argue, was unable
to tell the scholar anything about the man behind the portrait.4
Cicero’s exaggerated allegations, like those he made on the character of Antonius, were commonplace and topical, expected as
part of the game.5 The audience could supposedly identify them
as beside the point.6 This led some to question its sincerity and
2
3
4
5
6
See Long 1858, p. 1; Greenwood 1928, p. xiv. For Cicero’s attacks on immorality as justiied, see also e.g. Hardy 1917, pp. 173, 183, 218; Crownover
1934, pp. 137–138; Wilkins 1950, p. ix; Wirszubski 1961, p. 14; Pritchard
1971; Lewis 2001, p. 145.
For abuse in other literary genres, see e.g. Lilja 1965; Richlin 1978; Thome
1993. For character abuse as a literary genre, see Koster 1980, p. 39; Kubiak
1989. For a catalogue of invective, see Craig 2004, pp. 190–191.
DeLacy 1941, p. 58. Cf. Sanford 1939, p. 65. See also Yavetz 1963, p. 498.
See e.g. Gardner 1958, p. 334; Nisbet 1961, p. 193; Crook 1967, p. 255; Earl
1967, pp. 19, 90; Geffcken 1973, p. 67; Gruen 1974, pp. 137, 275; Koster
1980, p. 129; Crawford 1994, pp. 160, 233. They were also seen as inherited
from Greek practice. On this see Corbeill 1996, p. 129.
Austin 1952, p. 52; Lenaghan 1969, p. 162; Gruen 1974, p. 137; Craig 2007,
p. 336. See also Craig 2004.
Introduction
19
inluence, others to call it misdirection and manipulation.7 A likely reason Western scholarship has tended to lay these kinds of ad
hominem attacks by the wayside is therefore that they have been
seen as provokingly irrational in relation to a political issue or
the question of guilt.8
In hindsight, it is furhermore probably not a stretch to imagine
that certain indecent aspects of Cicero’s pejorative portraits have
traditionally been found to be an unsuitable topic of study. It has
certainly been deemed inappropriate, perhaps even embarrassing
behavior on the part of the great orator himself, the man Quintilianus called the name of eloquence.9 While Cicero has throughout the centuries been lauded for the beauty of his rhetorical eloquence, he has also been chided for his ugly and brutal verbal
assaults.10 In sum, since the Romans in all these aspects betray a
disregard for the truth, logical reasoning, and decorum, modern
scholars have tended to ignore this embarrassing quirk of theirs
as irrelevant.
Along the same lines, another possible interpretation has been
to explain Cicero’s portrayals of his enemies as a form of entertainment.11 Certain moral allegations on the orator’s stage were,
according to such a view, pro forma in Roman political culture;
7
8
9
10
11
See Syme 1939, pp. 148, 151; Nisbet 1961, p. xvi; Novokhatko 2009, pp.
14–15. See also Berry 1996, p. 275.
Watts 1931, p. 307; Nisbet 1964, pp. 62–63; Kurke 1989, p. 175. Cf. Kennedy 1972, p. 203. For Cicero’s view on the demands of truth in oratory, see
Off. 2.51.
Quint. Inst. 10.112. See for instance Butler & Cary 1924, p. 89; Ker 1926,
p. 63, n. 1; Lenaghan 1969, pp. 103–104.
For reprimands of Cicero, see e.g. Long 1858, p. vi; Watts 1923, p. 47;
Waters 1970. Also Gruen 1974, p. 270. See also Syme 1939, p. 149: “In the
allegation of disgusting immorality, degrading pursuits and ignoble origin
the Roman politician knew no compunction or limit.” Cf. Nisbet 1939, preface; and p. x.
Merrill 1975, p. 41. See also Geffcken 1973.
20
making enemies
the orator simply went through the motions.12 This would, scholars argue, explain the perceived exaggeration. The crowd expected to be amused by the orations in the same way they might have
found delight in a suggestive poem, a scandalous play or a vulgar
line of grafiti. Classical scholarship has furthermore been satisied with acknowledging that attacks on the orator’s stage was a
part of the conlict of Roman politics; in such a harsh political
culture people made enemies, and the speaker’s platform was an
opportunity to get back at them.13 Cicero attacked Marcus Antonius simply because he carried a grudge.
It should be stated that all of these previous interpretations
have their merits. It is true that moral accusations are found
with perhaps surprising regularity in Roman texts and that to a
Roman orator a range of suitable tropes were available through
rhetorical texts and training. It is also true that some of these
attacks have deinite entertainment value and seem designed
to undermine through ridicule or wit. Lastly, that the speaker’s
platform was a place for retaliation against rivals seems obvious.
Cicero’s own demise bears testament to this.
Despite their respective relevance however, these perspectives
fail to give any satisfactory answers to the questions I posed at
the outset. First and foremost, classifying immoral discourse as a
genre has tended to devoid it of any meaning, not least for ancient
historians in search of origin, originality, and truth. In the end, it
does more to identify than explain. Moreover, such a perspective
dictates that statements about an adversary’s immoral character
should not be distinguished from other types of standard or even
formulaic abuse. Charges of cruelty, hypocrisy, and immorality
were all genre and were all equally irrelevant.
12
13
See Syme 1939, pp. 151–152.
In general see Epstein 1987. See also Powell 2006, p. 3.
Introduction
21
Secondly, taken as a whole, all three perspectives suggest that
verbal attacks on immorality were unrelated and unimportant to
any political outcome.14 Immorality might have been intended
to provoke laughter or hurt, but not to persuade. The main tendency in Western scholarship, if at all recognizing its presence,
has been to question the place of character and immorality in
political and judicial debates.
Viewing the topic of immorality as separated from “real”
political discourse soon, however, proves to be problematic. The
modern distinction certainly collapses when looking at the oratory of Cicero, who, throughout his career, devoted time and
energy to argue the immorality of his opponents. As a case in
point, he chose moral character as a target in a situation where
he perceived the Republic to be at war. Amidst his fatal last political battle, is it reasonable to think that he included arguments
everyone identiied as beside the point and amusing caricatures
of his opponent while at the same time trying to convince his
peers to meet him on the battleield? Clearly, not every mention
of immorality was supposed to be met with laughter. Nor are attacks on the immoral character of a fellow member of the elite
reserved for individuals with whom, as far as we know, Cicero
had vendettas. Survining rhetorical treatises include discussions
of character as a means to persuade and inluence. Granted, revenge might at times have been a motive, but seems unable to
explain immorality’s place in Roman oratory.15
Thus the questions posed remain unanswered. If irrelevant,
why did Cicero focus his efforts on the topic of immorality? If
there was no link between immorality and politics, why go after
the moral character of Antonius in the Senate? Regardless of
14
15
See Pocock 1926, p. 5; Gardner 1958, p. 34; Mouritsen 2001, p. 53.
Cf. Dominik & Smith 2011, p. 2.
22
making enemies
whether scholars have viewed attacks on immorality as genre,
entertainment, or personal hostility, they have tended to offer the
same answer to the question of what place immorality had in
Roman politics: none. It was a law in Roman oratory.
There is however another possibility: that it was not a law.
Rather, immorality was part of Roman oratory because it made
sense to both speaker and audience. It was not beside the point
but rather precisely the point.
Pursuing this possibility, the irst thing then to ask ourselves is
what happens if we take this embarrassing quirk seriously. Not
in the sense that Antonius was really as sordid as Cicero claimed,
but in the sense that the Romans saw immorality as a legitimate
concern and that attacks on immorality therefore were a rational part of Roman oratory. What if a discourse of immorality is
not viewed as a byproduct of Roman politics, but as something
worthy of study in its own right? In other words, what if we
sought to understand this immorality and its place in Roman
culture, political as well as general?
Approaches to Roman Immorality
The category of “traditional scholarship” above has been sharply
drawn in order to illustrate a point and in doing so has been
treated somewhat unkindly. The fact that scholars in previous
decades searched for the answers to the questions they identiied
as pertinent is of course only natural—and, as it happens, also
necessary. It has opened up for the opportunity to ind new ones.
In other words, for a new perspective to be fruitful there have to
be traditional ones, even if sharply drawn.
Seeking new answers to old problems could entail looking for
the meaning of attacks on immorality. In the ield of history this
Introduction
23
task has been advocated by proponents of a direction known as
New Cultural History in which the deciphering of meaning have
taken precedence over causality and explanation.16 The loose
term does not describe a coherent school of thought but rather
new perspectives, as historians have shown a growing interest in
ideas, mentalities, gender, norms, fears, values, and the uses of
history. It is a history about how people in the past understood
their world, rather than a history deined by events.
In more recent times, modern classical scholarship has moved
in precisely this direction. Historians have shown that morality
was a major concern of the elite and of the political culture.17
Additionally, a rise in interest in Roman culture itself has been
noticeable and a range of studies have speciically taken an interest in previously marginalized topics such as immorality.18 These
trends in classical scholarship have all converged to open up for
the perspective argued in the present study.
In light of this, the search for Roman immorality is not merely
a question of explanation but a matter of perspective. The truth is
that Roman orators could have had any number of reasons for attacking their peers, unconscious, emotional, or strategic. The point
here is that in doing so, they communicated the portraits they constructed of their opponents to a larger community. The perspective advocated in this study is irst and foremost that attacks on
immorality were meaningful. This means that they made sense to
speaker and audience. This in turn, means that immorality also had
the capacity of being relevant to both cultural and political issues.
16
17
18
Hunt 1989, p. 12. For Roman cultural history, see e.g. Habinek & Schiesaro
(eds.) 1997; Kaster 2005; Wallace-Hadrill 2008.
Including Hölkeskamp 1987, 2010; Rosenstein 1990, 2006; Steel 2001;
Flaig 2003; Connolly 2007a.
See especially Richlin 1992; Edwards 1993; and Corbeill 1996. Further
references in chapter 1.
24
making enemies
Accordingly, it hardly matters if we ultimately champion genre,
entertainment, or inimical political culture as explanations. These
aspects are, in my view, not mutually exclusive. We are, however,
approaching the problem from another angle. That attacks on
Antonius’ moral character were not unique and can be compared
to those aimed at other politicians does not render such attacks
meaningless. Rather, the opposite is true. Themes of immorality
were a persisting feature of oratory because they resonated with
an audience. Humor and entertainment, moreover, would only
be successful if the audience recognized what was funny. And
hurting someone would only be effective if the attacks carried
meaning. These portraits of immorality had to be culturally coherent whether believed or not, whether commonplace or unusual,
whether funny or dead serious. They had to make sense.
From this perspective, attacks on immorality found in Roman
oratory, were, I argue, both meaningful and illed with meaning.
They lacked neither relevance nor substance. When seen in this
way, immorality is neither about accurately and truthfully portraying the character of an opponent nor merely a way to entertain an audience or settle a score. Instead, immorality is summoned in Roman oratory because there was a cultural connection
to be made between politics and vice. Cicero attacked Marcus
Antonius, not because he held a grudge or was trying to throw
dust in the eyes of his audience for lack of a better argument, but
because character and politics were linked in the Roman mind.
In turn, this perspective means that, if you wanted to ridicule
or retaliate, immorality—precisely because it was culturally and
politically relevant—was a suitable approach. The question then
becomes: what was the nature of this link between immorality
and politics? And furthermore: how can we study it?
Introduction
25
The Study of Roman Immorality
In 1967 Donald Earl noted in his book The Moral and Political
Tradition of Rome that the Romans “were much obsessed with
morality.”19 Despite his claim, the same cannot be said of classical scholarship. Even Earl’s own laudable effort seemingly treats
the Roman preoccupation with morality as misguided. Thus,
similar modern views have often dictated that whether or not
the Romans believed that immorality was of great importance
is by and large irrelevant because they were inherently wrong in
this belief. Although, the topic of immorality is in no way undetectable in ancient history, it has nevertheless been treated along
the same lines as I have suggested above. Immorality at Rome, to
be sure, has captivated the imagination of specialists and readers
alike, just as it has served as a cautionary tale of the dangers of
immorality in every period since the fall of Western Rome, but
only rarely has it been the speciic focus of any scholarly effort
willing to take it seriously.
In more recent years however, scholars have found the subject
more fulilling, and previously disregarded adjacent topics have
been revisited. This goes not least for the area of sexual morality
and masculinity, the study of exempla and the role played by the
morality of the forefathers (mos maiorum), and topics such as
popular morality.20 Some of these developments will be detailed
later in the study. At this point it will sufice to introduce three
directions in classical scholarship in particular that have paved
19
20
Earl 1967, p. 11.
For sexual morality, see e.g. Langlands 2006; and Williams 2010 with bibliography. For masculinity, see e.g. Gleason 1995; Gundersson 2000; Dugan
2005; and Connolly 2007b. For the role of the moral tradition, see especially
Linke & Stemmler 2000; and van der Blom 2010. For popular morality, see
Dover 1974 for the Greek example; Morgan 2007; and Knapp 2011.
26
making enemies
the way for the present study. First, a handful of scholars have
stressed the importance of character in Cicero’s speeches, in the
courts, and in Roman political culture in general.21 Ethos, the
moral character of the speaker, was an important part of political persuasion. The claim is important as it places morality, and
therefore immorality, front and center on the Roman political
scene. Secondly, immorality has been convincingly dealt with as
a rewarding area for the study of Roman culture and politics.
There was, as Catharine Edwards has rightly observed, no separation between morality and politics in ancient Rome; instead these
modern categories overlapped.22 The view identiies the Roman
discourse on immorality not as inherently misguided, but as vital for understanding politics at Rome. Thirdly, after long being
overlooked as apt source material for the analysis of culture and
meaning, scholars have in recent years turned to Roman invective
in order to harvest the “values and presuppositions” articulated
by oratorical texts and present in the Roman audiences who were
exposed to them.23 This has entailed posing questions about the
meaning of attacks on immorality and its interaction with Roman
culture.
In view of this, then, a platform can be created where the importance of character, immorality, and verbal attacks in Roman
politics is recognized and from where it is possible to proceed in
an attempt to chart the Roman moral concerns that are exposed
in our sources and follow, inally, the interaction of this morality
with the political culture. This is the task before us.
21
22
23
See especially May 1988; Riggsby 1999, 2004. Also Santoro L’Hoir 1992;
and Vasaly 1993.
Edwards 1993, p. 8. See also Earl 1967, p. 17. Cf. Barton 2001, p. 2.
Corbeill 1996, p. 8. Further references in chapter 1.
Introduction
27
Tracing Roman Immorality
Two premises of this study have so far been reached. First that
immorality can be understood as meaningful and inluential in
Roman politics. If this is true, as I will argue in upcoming chapters, we no longer have any reason to explain its presence in the
speeches Cicero delivered against Marcus Antonius. The inclusion of attacks on immorality was rational in Rome’s political
culture. Second, these attacks themselves carry meaning that can
be pursued. This means that they also had an inherent cultural
logic or they would not have made sense to an audience. I believe
that tracing this logic will help us unlock the link not only between immorality and culture but also between immorality and
politics at Rome.
This is a study into the logic behind accusations on immoral
character made by Cicero throughout his career. Through a wide
variety of character attacks and arguments—forensic and political—I aim to investigate how a shared understanding of what
was moral and immoral could be summoned in Roman political
oratory. The purpose of this is irst to gain insight into a Roman
mind world or set of values. But I will also argue that the significance of this goes further than understanding Roman values
and norms. I believe a case can be made for the link between
immorality and Roman political culture.
The basis for such a study can be illustrated by the following
line of reasoning. Let us say that Roman orators attempted to
identify opponents as un-Roman in order to politically undermine them. If deviance in a culture is grounds for exclusion,
attributing deviant qualities to an enemy would only be logical.
It could however be argued that while the task of pointing out
difference and deviant qualities in external enemies is relatively
easy—certain outward signs such as appearance, custom, and
28
making enemies
language being at your disposal—identifying a fellow member
of your own social group as deviant requires something more.
When attempting to convince an audience that someone who
looks, walks, and talks like you is actually different, the proof
has to come from somewhere else: it has to be constructed, in a
sense, by the orator.24 One possible approach for the orator is to
construct a portrait that aims to be effective from what he perceives to be a shared cultural foundation. Morality can be said to
be such a shared foundation. The more successful such a portrait
is, the more in line with the audience’s preconceptions and prejudices it supposedly is. In this study I wish to argue that Cicero
not only made enemies in the traditional sense, but that he also
made—or, constructed—enemies with his words.
We cannot, unfortunately, evaluate the success of most isolated
cases in Cicero’s career with any degree of certainty, but, more
fundamentally, Cicero was believed to be the most successful
orator in his day. Therefore, from such an approach, the portraits that Cicero painted of people he wanted to undermine say
nothing of the persons behind the portraits, but speak volumes
about what Cicero perceived to be a common set of values and
a shared understanding of immorality. However, it is possible to
argue that when depicting his adversaries, Cicero did not merely
relect what he thought his audience wanted to hear, but that
he argued immorality, and in the process inluenced, negotiated,
and reafirmed a discourse of immorality present in Rome. A
ixed culture cannot simply be laid bare by the historian, but it is
possible to follow the immorality argument. And by tracing the
logic of immorality that gave these arguments weight, an understanding of the framework of a speciic part of said culture can,
24
Cf. Ruffell 2003, p. 52.
Introduction
29
I believe, be gained. The possibilities and challenges of such an
approach will be discussed in detail in the upcoming chapters of
this book.
A Moral Paradox?
One aspect of studying Roman immorality remains to be addressed at the outset. Only a quick glance is required to realize
that questions of immorality hold a prominent place in Latin
literature as it has been passed down to us. Immorality is everywhere to be found. It was evidently a grave concern to the elite.
Roman historians clearly saw immorality as the cause of political
change. Immorality doomed the kings, the Republic, and in the
end the Empire. Poems, plays, and epigraphic material all bear
witness to this obsession with immorality. Is Roman immorality
hiding in plain sight? The paradox is only strengthened if we
look at early Western scholarship in agreement on Roman moral
laxity as a reason for decline. How then is it that there are still
questions unanswered? How can we gain more insight into this
obvious subject?
The topic is not novel. The sources are among the best known
in all of Western tradition. The number of books about Cicero
is beyond counting. We cannot hope to ind concepts or themes
in Cicero’s speeches uncommented. Still, I believe this study deserves to be undertaken. The reason for this is that I read Cicero
and I see these patterns of culture that I have not found discussed
to my satisfaction by previous scholarship. Often immorality is
everywhere in Cicero and nowhere in books about Cicero. Immorality is either conveniently explained away or ignored altogether. I believe this is a matter of perspective. Immorality’s place
in Roman politics might strike us as strange. But I argue that
we should approach it as logical and that this serves a purpose.
30
making enemies
For while cultural history has often been interested in that which
stands out as strange in the past, the realm of politics, in classical
scholarship at least, has frequently been treated as if outside the
reach of the cultural historian. Politics and culture have been separated and the political arena seen as a place of logic, intentionality, and events. Immorality in Roman politics, however, need
not be explained away. It needs to be understood.
But this is not a book about Cicero or even about his speeches.
It is a book about the mentalities, values, anxieties, and fears that
his speeches still bear witness to. It is a book about the cultural
framework within which politics at Rome took place. Finally, it
is a book about how immorality could be made relevant to the
political culture. From this perspective there still remains something to be done.
Outline
In the next two chapters I will address the prerequisites of a study
into Roman political immorality. First, I will adress the methodological as well as theoretical considerations for the study as well
as sketch the relevant previous scholarship. A background chapter will then outline the framework of the political culture during
Cicero’s long career as well as the conditions for public speaking
at Rome.
The study itself is structured chronologically and thematically.
The irst empirical chapter deals with Cicero’s early career and
introduces immorality in forensic oratory between 81 and 69
BCE. The following chapter frames Cicero’s time at the top of
Roman political life and focuses on Cicero’s use of immorality in
the Catilinarian affair while also developing the discussions on
immorality in the Roman courts. The third empirical chapter instead centers on the political conlicts that distinguished Cicero’s
Introduction
31
return to politics after his ignominious exile and thematically
looks at how immorality could be negotiated through certain
dominant themes during the time 57–52. The fourth and inal
empirical chapter returns to Cicero’s battle with Marcus Antonius and compares his portrait with those previously analyzed.
The last part of the book sums up the study’s indings.
Chapter I
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
In the introduction I sketched the outline of the study of
Roman immorality and proposed the value of a change in perspective from explaining political causality to understanding political immorality. At the heart of the endeavor lies the interaction
between Roman morality and Roman political culture. The intentions and political maneuvering of Cicero thereby take a step
back in favor of a cultural framework within which he acted and
that has left traces in his oratory. It is not a study of the truth behind these allegations, nor is it a literary inquiry into the genre of
character abuse. Instead of rational intention, I look for cultural
coherence. How then can we proceed to study Roman immorality in order to understand it on a cultural level?
When searching for the immorality argument in Roman political oratory, we need a place to start. In this chapter I will suggest
initially that one fruitful approach is looking at the way Cicero
represents the moral character of his opponents. I furthermore
argue that attacking one’s adversaries was a culturally signiicant
act that created meaning and that the logic of this meaning can
be traced. Finally, theoretically this can be seen as linked to the
political culture.
32
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
33
Searching for Immorality: Purpose
The purpose of this thesis is to trace the cultural logic behind
political accusations of immoral character found in Cicero’s
speeches. The preliminary inquiry centers on how the immoral
Roman politician is created by Cicero. The main question is
therefore: How does Cicero represent immorality in character in
his political and forensic oratory? From this we will be able to
broaden the search for the link between immorality and Roman
politics with the question of how immorality could be made relevant to the political and forensic issues at hand.
The chain of reasoning that culminates in the upcoming study
can be described as follows. Classical scholarship has acknowledged that the competition of the elite was an important political force in the late Republic. This in turn meant that individual members of the elite naturally engaged in conlict with each
other in the public arenas of the political culture; in trials, in the
Senate, and on the speaker’s platform in the Forum before public
assemblies. As one of the prime political acts was speeches, the
rivalry of the elite resulted in antagonistic public discourse. In
the chapters that follow I will show that a prime target of attack
in such speeches was morality. From the perspective adopted in
this study, these attacks sought to undermine the position of the
adversary by depicting him as antithetical to a Roman morality
perceived of as shared within the community. In order to be effective, these attacks had to make sense. I propose, that by tracing
the cultural logic of these attacks we have an opportunity to gain
further insight into a Roman mind world; into values, ideals, and
fears, into norms and deviation, and into the negotiation of what
it meant to be Roman. This inally would place Roman politics
within a larger cultural framework than has previously been the
case.
34
making enemies
Finding Immorality: Method
There are two distinct aspects of Cicero’s representation of immorality on which I have focused in my study. The irst is the portraits of immorality Cicero painted of his adversaries. The second
is the oratorical reasoning and arguments regarding immorality
found within the speeches themselves. The basic methodology
for arriving at these two aspects is close reading of Cicero’s extant speeches in stages. This has led to a process of distillation
whereby each reading the subject matter is narrowed. I started by
looking broadly at anything that could be perceived as negative
in Cicero’s depictions of his main adversaries. This resulted in
several wide-ranging portraits of political enemies. Within these
I concentrated on issues of morality which in turn gave a set of
recurring themes and motifs as well as words and concepts that
denoted immorality in a variety of ways. By then following the
usage of these themes, words, and concepts, new ones have been
added to the “immoral catalogue.” It is clear that the study of
these words, and their interrelated links, can offer, to paraphrase
Earl, a whole complex of immoral ideas.25
Important in this regard has been words that in Latin denoted
a general immorality and depravity and suggested shame and
disgrace in the eyes of the community. Chief among these words
are lagitium and improbitas, but they also include turpitudo,
dedecus and others. From these, other words, as well as thematic aspects of immorality, come into focus. They reveal links with
other words and ideas and tell us, for instance: the scene where
depravity took place, the motives and catalysts for immoral behavior; and, also, the consequences of immoral acts and character.
A host of words also signal sexual immorality and are of course
25
Earl 1967, p. 20.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
35
pertinent as well. Reading Cicero’s speeches for traces of immorality also revealed certain signs or marks of immorality that presumably identiied and illustrated for an audience the character
of the adversary.26 I have intentionally left the question of what
these signs were to be answered by the upcoming study. From
this point, the task has been to pursue the identiied notions of
immorality as logical by searching for references in the corpus
of Ciceronian oratory as well as in external evidence. The latter
material is chiely made up of a general moral discourse found in
Latin literature. Furthermore, when possible, this has been discussed in dialogue with the scholarship on the subject. Cultural logic
has furthermore been analyzed through the more explicit chain of
reasoning that is sometimes found in Cicero’s depiction of immorality. In certain instances, Cicero urged his audience to follow his
interpretation of immorality. This might for example include his
advice to a jury on how to weigh the defendant’s character.
Another important aspect has been to look closely at cultural
links forged in these depictions. This includes which concepts are
repeatedly connected in Cicero’s depictions, but also how concepts and themes trigger wider contexts and patterns of cultural
relevance. The last stage is comparison between the representations of immorality identiied throughout Cicero’s career. This
will hopefully present us with a framework on which to base the
discussion of immorality’s place in Roman political culture.
In sum, the method for discussing Roman immorality is looking at polemical discourse and the portraits of political adversaries painted in oratory. By looking at the most extreme examples
of enmity we are able to identify our principal source material
from which we can broaden the ield of study.
26
For the ability of the orator to point to signs of immorality, see also Corbeill
1996, p. 159.
36
making enemies
Understanding Immorality: Theory
In terms of interest, perspective and, following that, expected
results, this study is rooted in the direction of history known
as New Cultural History.27 The name signals neither a coherent
theoretical approach nor a school, and although generally accepted, the epithet is somewhat misleading, as there are few similarities between “old” and “new” cultural history, mainly because
what unites New Cultural Historians, if anything, are perspectives rather than the topic of “culture.”28 While cultural historians in the past had sought to uncover a Zeitgeist or describe a
culture as uniform, the “new” cultural historians posed different
questions regarding gender, sexuality, identity, and power and
often pointed at the problematic categories of older scholarship.
The two can be said to be separated by the so-called linguistic
turn which moved historical scholarship into adapting new perspectives. Chief among these was arguably to see language as no
longer merely relecting, but inluencing and even constructing
the reality around us. As pointed out by Lynn Hunt, one of the
ield’s most inluential scholars, words do not simply “relect social and political reality,” rather they can be seen as “instruments
for transforming reality” and therefore linguistic practice can
actively be “an instrument of (or constitute) power.”29 This is a
primary premise for the study at hand.
27
28
29
For New Cultural History, see Hunt (ed.) 1989; Iggers 1997; and in Swedish,
Ekström 2009.
The name was introduced through the publication of the anthology The
New Cultural History, edited by Lynn Hunt in 1989. For the name as misleading, see Ekström 2009.
Hunt 1989, p. 17. See also Chartier 1982, p. 30. For an example of a similar
theoretical approach within the ield of classics, see Gildenhard 2011.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
37
Hence, central to the historians writing in this ield were meaning and language while subject matter has traditionally provided
less guidance. Cultural history was no longer concerned with an
isolated part of social life, separated from politics or economy. Culture, in this sense of the word, did not refer to “high” or “low”
culture at a given time or cultural expressions such as dance, theater, or literature. Instead the term culture in New Cultural History,
or what has later been dubbed “the cultural turn,” aimed at the
experience and understanding people in the past had of their life
world. Historians inluenced by anthropology and speciically Clifford Geertz saw culture as a system of meaning, or to use Geertz’s
own phrase, “web of signiicance.”30 Language, as noted by George
Iggers, became a “semiotic tool” in the search for this meaning.31
Placing a study within the wide frame of New Cultural History,
however, fails to be very speciic. The range of studies conducted
under this heading is vast. A way to narrow the study’s theoretical position is through the ield known as New Historicism. Culture and language were also vital to this perspective, which grew
out of literary theory and which can be said to have developed
parallel to and as part of New Cultural History. Its most famous
practitioner is Stephen Greenblatt, whose early efforts can be
described as a reaction against the decontextualized readings
dominant in his ield.32 Greenblatt instead argued for the dialectic nature of literary works and their culture. Taking inspiration
from the anthropologist Clifford Geertz, New Historicism treats
culture as a semiotic system. The perspective has been described
in terms of a “shift from materialist explanations of historical
30
31
32
Geertz 1973, p. 5.
Iggers 1997, p. 126. For an example of analysis of Cicero’s speeches with a
similar approach, see Vasaly 1993, pp. 11–12.
See in particular Greenblatt 1980, 1988, 1990a; and Greenblatt & Gallagher 2000.
38
making enemies
phenomena to investigations of the history of the human body
and the human subject” in which discourse analysis has been an
important tool.33 Greenblatt also proposed that there are constant renegotiations of competing representational discourses in
a culture.34 Again, the critique was aimed at the idea of history in
terms of grand systems or narratives.
Culture has been described by Greenblatt as an “ensemble of
beliefs and practices” to which “individuals must conform.”35
The boundaries of a culture are enforced, both positively and
negatively, Greenblatt argues, upon which he elaborates an important point:
Western literature over a long period of time has been one of
the great institutions for the enforcement of cultural boundaries
through praise and blame. This is most obvious in the kinds of
literature that are explicitly engaged in attack and celebration:
satire and panegyric.36
Greenblatts’ line of reasoning touches on the subject matter
of the present study. Attack on character can, in this view, be
seen as the enforcement and negotiation of a culture’s boundaries, the “set of limits within which social behavior must be
contained.”37 They implicitly in turn hold the beliefs and practices that are enforced. Cicero, when attacking the morality of
Marcus Antonius, enforces the limits of his own culture, a point
also argued by ancient historians, albeit in different fashion. In
other words, Cicero’s intention and conscious strategy is one
33
34
35
36
37
Gallagher & Greenblatt 2000, p. 17.
Greenblatt 1988, p. 8.
Greenblatt 1990b, p. 225.
Greenblatt 1990b, p. 226.
Greenblatt 1990b, p. 225.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
39
thing, the moral boundaries he relects and creates in his attack
are another.
Moving on to methodology, Greenblatt holds that:
Eventually, a full cultural analysis will need to push beyond the
boundaries of the text, to establish links between the text and
values, institutions, and practices elsewhere in the culture. But these
links cannot be a substitute for close reading. Cultural analysis has
much to learn from scrupulous formal analysis of literary texts because those texts are not merely cultural by virtue of reference to the
world beyond themselves; they are cultural by virtue of social values
and contexts that they have themselves successfully absorbed.38
Greenblatt’s method echoes the method described in the previous
section of this chapter. By establishing links between Cicero’s
portraits of immorality and other representations found in
Roman culture we can arrive at cultural analysis. However, as
stressed in the passage above, it all starts with close reading to
reveal the beliefs, practices and values of a culture seen as permeating the texts. This relationship between a culture and its text is
sometimes referred to with the term “embeddedness.”39 Another
way of putting it, relating to the passage quoted above, is that
the historical texts, whether they are literary works or political
treatises, necessarily have absorbed these belief-systems.
New Cultural History and New Historicism, although they
share many deining traits, have so far seen little in way of interdisciplinarity.40 The main advantage to both perspectives is an
38
39
40
Greenblatt 1990b, p. 226.
Greenblatt 1990a, p. 164 professes his interest in “the embeddedness of cultural objects in the contingencies of history.” See also Gallagher & Greenblatt 2000, p. 25. Cf. Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 15.
See Maza 2004.
40
making enemies
approach to historical texts as not a mere relection of historical
reality, but as actively shaping it. That gives texts signiicance as
a force in the world. Additionally, historians have pointed to the
impact of language and speech and that we are right to view this
as historical acts comparable to traditional actions. Perhaps most
famously, Quentin Skinner has described words and language in
terms of speech acts. He has furthermore stated:
One of the most salutary achievements of post-modern cultural
criticism has been to improve our awareness of the purely rhetorical aspects of writing and speech, thereby heightening our sensitivity to the relations between language and power. As we have
increasingly been made to see, we employ our language not merely
to communicate information but at the same time to claim authority for our utterances, to arouse the emotions of our interlocutors,
to create boundaries of inclusion and exclusion and to engage in
many other exercises of social control.41
Skinner’s claim has validity for my study since it establishes a link
between language and political power. Like Greenblatt, Skinner
maintains that speech acts can be a force to create a culture’s
boundaries for inclusion and exclusion. Arguably, this is nowhere
more apparent than in cultural acts of attack.
Critique has been raised regarding the nature of cultural meaning. Roger Chartier, for instance, has questioned whether or not
a coherent underlying cultural meaning exists which the historian
can simply uncover.42 Therefore the historical effort does not end
with uncovering meaning. Signiicant, in my view, to both New
Cultural History and New Historicism is the perspective that this
41
42
Skinner 2002, p. 5.
Chartier 1985, pp. 689–690.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
41
meaning is not merely fascinating in itself, but crucial to understanding historical development. Lynn Hunt has maintained that
the aim should not be to reduce discourse to one “stable system
of meaning,” but can instead be to demonstrate how political
language can be rhetorically used “to build a sense of community” and “establish new ields of social, political and cultural
struggle.”43 In view of this, the question of the relationship and
interaction between a cultural and a political sphere is brought
to the fore in the current study.44 A character attack in oratory is
therefore not viewed as merely “rhetoric” or conversely accurate
in its depiction, but as an enforcement of a perceived Roman cultural norm. In this, it not only relects reality, or even values and
beliefs, but negotiates and creates them.45 Oratory and the representations therein exhort to action against the deviant; to pass a
verdict, to exclude, to execute.
The perspective I have so far advocated allows for a better understanding of the interaction between ields that have in the past
been routinely separated: culture and morality on the one hand
and politics on the other. It offers a way to gauge the relevance of
immorality for politics in ancient Rome and a possibility to bring
new light to the “web of immorality” that is in fact a conspicuous
aspect of ancient Rome.
Reading Cicero: Sources
The writings left to us by Marcus Tullius Cicero include not only
the 58 surviving speeches under primary scrutiny in this study,
but over 900 letters and two dozen political and philosophical
43
44
45
Hunt 1989, p. 17. Cf. especially Morstein-Marx 2004, pp. 14–15. See also
Richlin 1992, p. xx.
For this, see Salomon 2000, pp. 138–139.
See Greenblatt 1988, p. 8. Cf. Williams 2010, p. 9.
42
making enemies
works.46 He thereby dominates the source material during the
late Republic, and arguably any time in Roman history. With
Cicero we are able to follow both major events and day-to-day
politics, and gain access to religion, philosophy, and the private
world of the Roman family. The circumstances have not always
been to Cicero’s favor, as scholars have no doubt felt frustration
to be left at the mercy of Cicero at every turn. Additionally, he
has been possible to evaluate at his own game to a degree unlike
any one source probably up to modern times.47 Cicero’s speeches
can be compared to his private letters, personal emotions to
philosophical reasoning. His curse has been to alternately and
simultaneously be an advocate, a philosopher, and a politician
which puts him, from a source-critical standpoint, in a vulnerable position. His agenda and bias have left historians wary of his
statements at every stage. His skill as a speaker has cautioned
scholars not to take him at his word. His involvement in Roman
politics has impaired his objectivity.
For the present question however, Cicero’s bias is exactly why
he is a valuable source.48 His lack of objectivity and premier place
in Roman political culture is favorable. His skill as a speaker
and agenda in the courts, the Senate, and before the people are
the basis for the study. The reason is simple: Cicero wanted to
be inluential in Roman politics and persuasive in his oratory. In
order to reach this level of effectiveness, which his success and
fame alludes to, his words ought to have resonated with his different audiences.
46
47
48
Standard works on Cicero’s speeches include Leeman 1963; Stroh 1975;
Classen 1985; Craig 1993. For later studies, see also Craig 2002 with bibliography. All references to Cicero are to the editions of the Loeb Classical
Library.
See for instance Long 1858, p. vi.
See Santoro L´Hoir, 1992, p. 3.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
43
This speaks also to another traditional problem with Cicero as
source: his representativeness. Cicero is just one man.49 His voice
can therefore be viewed as just one opinion and an elite opinion
at that. The problem is resolved by the same line of reasoning. In
order to persuade, Cicero needed to heed the values and beliefs
of his audience. His attacks on the immorality of his enemies
therefore can be read not only, or even likely, as his own personal
view on right and wrong, but what he perceived to be a shared
understanding of morality.
Next comes the question of selection of sources. Why speeches
and why both forensic and political speeches? Again, the answer
relates to the above line of reasoning. In speeches Cicero openly
engaged in a public discourse of morality. His aim was to inluence and persuade, not merely project his own world view
or private thoughts. In this his is a strong voice. That does not
mean that the values expressed therein were shared by all, but
rather that he was a part of shaping and supporting a shared
understanding of immorality through public speech acts, to follow Skinner. It is an unfortunate circumstance that we have access only to fragments of other speakers, as we cannot exclude
the possibility that other competing discourses were part of this
public process.50 From Cicero’s success, however, it is reasonable
to infer that his audience accepted the world view embedded to a
certain degree. As to why both political and forensic speeches, the
answer will hopefully become apparent by the upcoming chapter.
Roman political culture incorporated both.
Although every extant speech of Cicero has been read, the
criterion for inclusion in the main discussion of immorality is
49
50
For a collection of the examples of oratorical attacks preceding Cicero, see
Koster 1980, pp. 97–112. Also Merrill 1975.
For fragments of other orators, see Malcovati 1976.
44
making enemies
simple: it either contains a portrait of immorality or a rhetorical
discussion on immorality. As stated earlier, I have started with the
most obvious examples of antagonisms in Cicero’s career, but to
a large extent incorporated material from the entire Ciceronian
corpus of oratory, including some available only in fragments.
The study is not quantitative and the reason is partly due to
the nature of the speeches. Some are short while others span several hundred pages in any modern edition. Some deal mainly with
the question of immorality while others mention it in passing.
Any attempt to quantify the indings would hence be problematic
and moreover fail to address the main question of the cultural
logic of the attack on immoral character.
Finally, we have the question of external comparative evidence.
The purpose of these sources is to help clarify immorality’s place
in Roman culture. This part of the study does not pretend to
be exhaustive, but rather helpful in the upcoming discussions.
I have focused my efforts on the “Roman moralists” where we
might expect to ind a Roman moral discourse: Sallustius, Valerius Maximus, and Seneca. This at times includes legal evidence
although scarce in the Ciceronian era.51
Defining Immorality: Concepts
The conventional way of studying concepts such as immorality
is by tracing the Latin usage of the corresponding word. In this
instance, the method is inadequate. First and foremost this is the
case because we are not looking for what the Romans “meant”
by immorality, but instead the research question includes a range
51
Although the focus of this study is cultural and not legal, I would claim that
these were often conlated categories in ancient Rome. For this, see McGinn
1998, p. 345; Harries 2007, p. 86. Cf. Barton 2001, p. 19.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
45
of alternative aspects of culture that conforms to a modern category of immorality, i.e. behavior and character traits that somehow are perceived as opposing proper and expected standards of
an ethical nature. Secondly, there exists no corresponding word
for our “immorality.”
The Latin for morality is mores. Mos or mores often designates
both customs and morality in Roman texts.52 As no Latin word
corresponds to our “culture,” it has therefore been suggested that
we can instead speak of mores when we look for certain cultural elements in Roman society.53 The complicated interaction
between morality and culture is thereby underlined, but mores
is nevertheless ill suited to yield the answers we are looking for.
What then of immorality? In Cicero’s texts there is, as mentioned, no word that directly conforms to our modern notion
of this all-encompassing word. From the circumstances I would
argue that there are two important distinctions to be made initially. On the one hand, that the present use of the English word
immorality is as a concept intended to corral cultural notions
in the past that we understand as contrary to good and proper
behavior in that speciic cultural context; on the other, that we
are not speaking of immorality in general—certainly a much to
broad category—but a speciic type of immorality. I would suggest that this subcategory of “everything that is not moral” can
be narrowed to mean Roman views of depravity. What I intend
to study in the upcoming chapters are those moral faults that
suggest scandalous, outrageous and shameful behavior and character. While this is also a modern English word that has several
52
53
Edwards 1993, p. 4. Edwards (p. 29) utilizes the deinition suggested by
Michel Foucault in History of Sexuality where Foucault sees morality as referring to both a set of values and rules of action, as well as the real behavior
of individuals in relation to these same sets of values and rules.
Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 8.
46
making enemies
possible corresponding words in Latin, it illustrates fairly well
the main focus of the study. This means that murder and political
malpractice, while they can be considered immoral acts, are not
the focus of the study but rather the morally corrupt character
that performs them.
Looking for depravity includes a range of Latin words.54 As
already mentioned, lagitium and improbitas denote debauchery
and shameful and disgraceful behavior. Turpitudo similarly indicates baseness and disgrace. Vitium means vice or fault. Other
words have similar or closely related meaning. Impuritas (impurity), sordes (the state of being ilthy or unclean) can together
with nefarium signal immoral behavior in conlict with religion,
while a word like immodestia means excessiveness. In this study,
however, I am looking for how language is put to use in practice. How Cicero constructed his portraits is a question of the
power of language, but this adheres not to a philological preunderstanding of these words but to their meaning in context.
The Latin words are put in play only insofar as they exist in a
portrait; that is, in a meaningful context. To be clear, the question
is not “what was immoral in ancient Rome,” but how notions of
immorality and depravity interacted with cultural, and political,
considerations.
As an example, to beat your father is beyond question a moral
question in ancient Rome and in modern society, while beating
your wife or owning slaves is a moral question today but not
necessarily in ancient Rome. Yet it is not of necessity perceived as
a vice, as lewd and foul behavior. If, however, we were to equate
domestic violence with depravity—with a person’s level of moral
corruption—a link could be established and would thereby be
54
For a helpful list of pejorative words used by Cicero, see Santoro L’Hoir
1992, p. 10.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
47
of relevance. There is however no need for sharply accentuated
limits to the following discussions on immorality, but rather a
guiding light.
Narrowing immorality to correspond to notions of depravity
has the beneit of aiming this guiding light at the clear-cut examples of moral trespass from which it is then possible to expand,
but it also has another justiication: the prominence of certain
types of moral trespass in Latin literature. Greed, luxury, and
sexuality and other types of behavior that signaled lack of selfcontrol and moral failure are found everywhere in Latin literature. In my opinion, their place in a cultural system of thought
has yet to be fully explained, as has their impact on the political
culture under scrutiny.
Lastly we arrive at character. By now, we are not surprised
to ind that the modern concept of character has no single corresponding Latin equivalent. When we speak of character we are
therefore searching for subject matter that fall into the modern
heading of character.55 In Latin, words like natura, habitus, animus, and persona capture both nature and attributes of a speciic
individual. Cicero deines natura as those character traits which
are bestowed by nature, while habitus is qualities acquired.56
In the rhetorical treatise Ad Herennium, written in the late Republic, the common Latin word is animus, which encompasses
both intellect and senses. Persona, inally, is to be understood as
the projected character of the speaker, much like the theatrical
mask from whence the term stems. Lastly, mores could also signal
moral character. Ethos, Aristoteles’ “moral character,” similarly
55
56
Although it should be noted that “character” in English by no means has a
singular meaning and, as in Latin, corresponds to concepts such as nature,
morality, authority, and persona.
Inv. rhet. 1.35.
48
making enemies
lacks a Latin equivalent.57 Cicero in his later treatise Orator uses
mores and natura as substitutes.58
The usage and meaning of the words enumerated above are
not the focus of the present enterprise. Instead, the modern notion
of character has the possibility of encompassing more than just
those explicit references to any of the existing words. Finally,
we should not assume that the existence of a philosophical or
theoretical understanding between said words did not mean they
could display overlapping connotations.
Speech as Text: Delivery, Audience,
and Publication
The echoes of Roman orators are faint. Over two millennia stand
between us and a performance of oratory in front of a Roman
audience. What we have today are not transcripts, but the later
copies (and copies of copies) of the texts that were published
and circulated in Cicero’s day. Some are preserved only in fragments while others have several different and comparable manuscripts.59 Roman oratorical performance, to be sure, entailed
more than just speaking words from a manuscript. The art of
rhetoric demanded that the orator considered tone of voice, style
and gestures, and memorization. These aspects of a speech are of
course all lost and cannot be recreated.
Classical scholarship has always debated the status of the texts
we have today; in particular the question of delivered vs. published speeches.60 Moreover, we know that Cicero revised his
57
58
59
60
See May 1988, p. 5. Also Quint. Inst. 6.2.8.
Orat. 128. Not, in other words, persona.
For Cicero’s fragmentary speeches, see Crawford 1994.
For this debate see e.g. Humbert 1925; Settle 1962; Stroh 1975; Riggsby
1999; Ledentu 2000; Craig 2007. Cf. Gildenhard 2011, p. 14.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
49
speeches before publication.61 This has understandably led to the
speeches being treated with certain suspicion. But in fact, Cicero
also claims that most speeches were written after and not for
delivery.62
The societies of the ancient Mediterranean world were oral
cultures. Public speaking was central. Texts were often meant to
be read aloud in front of an audience. Ideas, as well as political
decisions and results, were spread orally. The audience would
have been roughly the same as for the performance itself.63 Cato
the Elder, according to Cicero, was the irst to systematically
publish his speeches.64 This ensured that a Roman tradition of
speaking was passed on through the generations.65 Cicero himself
claims to have had access to as many as 150 of Cato’s speeches.
By the late Republic, another innovative way was to publish a
treatise containing the formal framework of being a good Roman
orator.66
Publication was tied to politics. Circulating your achievements
offered a way to project your own oratorical gloria and bestowed
honor on the orator.67 Some speeches were sent to a close circle
of friends, others to broader circulation. Cicero also mentions the
publication of the Catilinarian speeches in a letter as intended for
the rhetorical schools, but we also know that in the heated con-
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
To what extent is debatable. The most conspicuous example is Pro Milone,
see Asc. Mil. 41.9–42.4. See also Fam. 9.12.2; Att. 1.13.5. See also letter
1.20.6–8 of Pliny the Younger and Riggsby 1995.
Brut. 91. That Cicero to some extent equated speeches that existed in his day
with the delivered oration is clear from Font. 38.
Craig 2007, p. 265.
Brut. 60.
See Brut. 129.
For Cicero’s rhetorical works as part of the construction of his identity, see
Dugan 2005. Cf. Craig 2007, pp. 265–266.
For circulation, see Starr 1987.
50
making enemies
licts of the late Republic, political opponents quickly published
speeches directed against each other.68 This happened during the
conlict between Antonius and Cicero in 44 and 43.
When looking for what really happened, the sources can be
perceived as frail, even though it should be noted that most modern scholars tend to see the relationship between published and
delivered speeches as being a close one.69 More importantly, if
we are looking for their embedded cultural values, they are as
strong as ever. This is true because even if revised, they would
not be changed in order to be less cultural coherent. On the contrary, they would be revised to make even more sense. This means
that we need not establish a theory of how well the written text
corresponds to the spoken words. They were published as “documents of persuasion” and in that they still carry the will to correspond to audience expectations of moral standards.70
Defining a Political Culture
Although often not deined with any speciicity within the area of
classics, political culture is a recurring concept in modern scholarship on ancient Rome.71 So far, I have used political culture in
this more general or self-explanatory sense. There are nonetheless
68
69
70
71
Cic. Att. 2.1.3, 4.2.2; Q Fr. 2.1.11.
For arguments, see Riggsby 1999, pp. 178–184. Cf. Morstein-Marx 2004,
pp. 26–30.
For documents of persuasion see Vasaly 1993, p. 9. Cf. Ramsey 2007, p. 130:
“Of course, the written versions of Cicero’s senatorial speeches do reveal, at
the very least, what Cicero wanted to take credit for having said at a given
meeting, even if we cannot vouch for their strict accuracy as a record of what
was actually spoken.” Cf. Zetzel 1993, p. 450.
Notable contributions as to the general political culture of Republican Rome
include e.g. Nicolet 1980; Wiseman 1985 (ed.); Beard & Crawford 1985;
David 1992; Vasaly 1993; Corbeill 1996; Yakobson 1999; Steel 2001; Flaig
2003; Fantham 2004; Hölkeskamp 2004; Morstein-Marx 2004; Rosenstein
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
51
certain advantages to venturing into a detailed discussion of the
concept, as some of these theoretical aspects serve to highlight
aspects that are important in this study.
Originating from the ield of sociology, the concept itself has
received somewhat more detailed interest from historians of later
periods.72 In short, the political culture is the framework within
which a political agent acts. Another basic deinition is that the
political culture is the, often invisible, set of rules that guide or
direct those engaging in political activity with or without their
conscious or explicit understanding. The concept of political culture encapsulates the political mentality, rules, and attitudes that
characterize a speciic historical period.
Sydney Verba, one of the earliest to develop this concept, offers
the following useful deinition: “The political culture of a society
consists of the system of empirical beliefs, expressive symbols,
and values which deines the situation in which political action
takes place.”73 Another inluential scholar, Lucian W. Pye, has
stressed that the ideas and attitudes that guide political behavior
should not be considered random.74 Thus, a political culture is
not to be understood merely by outward traits such as voting
procedures and election processes, but also a political and cultural mentality. The political culture is not just the ixated political
practices but also the belief in them. Given the aim of the present
study, it is worth emphasizing the centrality of values in the concept of political culture.
Of relevance is the reciprocal relationship between the agent
72
73
74
& Morstein-Marx (eds.) 2006; and Connolly 2007a, all with further references. Cf. Hölkeskamp 2010, pp. 53–54.
At least in Sweden. See Demertzis 1985; Aronsson 1992; Österberg 1993;
Harrison 1998. See also Fuchs 2007; and, again in Swedish, Denk 2009.
Verba 1965, p. 513.
Pye 1965, p. 7.
52
making enemies
and the political culture. On this Nicholas Demertzis has suggested that political culture be viewed as something active, encompassing both the stage and the drama at the same time.75 This
means that the agent, in our case Cicero, is both shaped by the
structure of Roman political culture and simultaneously shapes
it. From this approach, the political culture is luid rather than
rigid and the political practice that takes place within the political culture, along with the ideas and norms that are articulated in
this practice are what deine it.
There is thus a basic idea behind the concept that mentality
and cultural values have an impact on political life. Aside from
the political values of a society as a trait for deining political
culture, shared understanding of what arenas are considered
political in nature, how political legitimacy is achieved, and what
patterns of political action are deemed traditional are also part of
any given political culture.76
Previous Scholarship
The link between oratory and politics argued in this study means
that relevant scholarship is found in different directions within
ancient history. Developments in the study of Roman political
culture are detailed in the next chapter as part of the background
canvas for Cicero’s attacks on immorality. The study itself, however, instead inds its natural locus within an emerging ield of
the study of Roman rhetoric. After a brief outline of some vital
developments in this area, I will proceed to the scholarship of
more immediate concern for the speciic study of Roman character attacks. Three different directions are identiied as conver75
76
Demertzis 1985, p. 159.
Österberg 1993, p. 127.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
53
ging in this regard: the study of invective, Roman immorality,
and character.
In the introduction I argued that immorality in Roman oratory
has been neglected. One thing should be made clear: neglect is relative. To be sure, immorality in politics has been put aside of the
mainstream, but the vast amount of scholarly work done in classics guarantees that several of the topics, themes, and concepts under scrutiny have been dealt with at some point. It is important to
note, however, the fact that scholars have frequently approached
these subjects as separate areas of inquiry, while the present study
instead focuses on their cultural links.77 These works, which include studies of such wide-ranging areas as law, religion, sexuality,
humor, and political philosophy, will be referenced when suitable
in the empirical chapters. As stated previously, the speeches of
Cicero belong to the most examined source material in Western
tradition. That said, no study, to my knowledge, has consistently
dealt with Cicero’s portrayal of immorality in his political and
judicial opponents or studied his political use of the immorality
argument over the course of his career in order to trace the cultural logic behind this aspect of his oratory. Furthermore, careful
consideration of the political use of immorality in Cicero’s oratory
is much needed. With that in mind, the following rundown of
previous scholarship focuses mainly on the body of work that in
some shape or form shares, or has allowed for, this perspective.
Approaching Rhetoric
Rhetoric has been both embraced and loathed by the heirs of the
classical world, and Cicero as its main representative has often
gone along with history’s shifts in attitude, either praised for his
77
See also Edwards 1993, p. 6.
54
making enemies
eloquence or despised for his rhetorical tricks.78 For a long time,
rhetoric as an art was suspect in a Western intellectual climate
that above all else cherished sincerity and sought to uncover the
truth. Rhetoric carries with it negative connotations and today,
claiming that a statement is “just rhetoric” indicates that it is
not truthful or should be discarded as an attempt to sway listeners and manipulate the truth. This dichotomy between truth and
rhetoric is misleading. In the present study, it is argued that a
more fruitful approach to look at rhetoric is as the attempt to
persuade through that which listeners ind relevant and coherent.79 It is nevertheless worth keeping in mind, that rhetoric in
modern perceptions still lies dangerously close to deceit by way
of speaking. Moreover, the ancient art of rhetoric, expressed in
surviving treatises, does nothing to alleviate such fears.
The surviving systems of rhetoric have been inluential
throughout the centuries in an almost immeasurable way. But
they have also characterized much of the scholarly body of
work on rhetoric. An ideal form of speech has often been at the
heart of scholarly endeavor. It is therefore worth noting that the
theoretical framework of classical rhetoric, as pointed out by
Ann Vasaly, still determines to a large degree what scholars see
when they look at a Roman speech.80 In other words: the theory
of rhetoric has conventionally been very good at explaining its
historical practice in a more or less uncomplicated manner.81
Rhetoric has been seen as the mold—the rule book—that oratory imperfectly tries to follow. This resilient perspective can
78
79
80
81
To be sure, authorities in antiquity were mindful of the potential to persuade
that lies in rhetoric. See for instance Platon’s Phaedrus.
See also discussion in Vasaly 1993, pp. 246–252.
Vasaly 1993, p. 3.
Poulakis 1993a, p. 1; Connelly 2007, p. 5.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
55
however be challenged and has so been.82
New perspectives on both rhetorical theory and practice have
emerged and as a result rhetoric has experienced a recovery as an
academic subject.83 The scope of rhetoric has been widened from
entailing merely eloquence in speech, to encompass the persuasive aspects of all texts. In traditional scholarship, John Dugan
identiies three genres of rhetorical study as the commentary, the
history of oratory, and the cataloguing of tropes.84 The critical
commentary, Dugan argues, has undergone very little change
across the centuries and he sees the canonical works of Kennedy
and Lausberg as examples of “traditional works of scholarship
that resemble their predecessors in antiquity” and “extensions
of the classical tradition of rhetorical scholarship.”85 In regard
to this pursuit of identiication or assessment, Thomas Habinek
laments that classical texts all too frequently are regarded “in
purely formalistic and aesthetic terms.”86 By way of example,
Habinek instead focuses his approach on “cultural production of
meaning and values” in the texts.87 Such an approach, or rather,
shift in perspective, owes something to developments in literary
criticism that have allowed for a broader understanding of rhe82
83
84
85
86
87
See Gunderson 2000, p. 2; and Gunderson 2003, p. 14: “An uncritical acceptance of ancient rhetorical criticism can lead to the reproduction of their
speciic biases as truths.” See also Connolly 2007a, pp. 1–2.
Poulakos 1993a, p. 2.
Dugan 2007, p. 10. For a different approach to the rhetorical tradition, see
Vitanza 1993.
Dugan 2007, pp. 11, 12. The former is a diachronic history of rhetoric and
the latter a synchronic attempt to organize ancient rhetoric in its entirety.
Cf. Gunderson 2009a, p. 9. As a more explicitly conservative or even antimodern example, Dugan offers Vickers’ In Defense of Rhetoric from 1988,
a work that he describes as trying to “police the disciplinary boundaries” of
the study of rhetoric as he believes in a pure rhetorical tradition, threatened
by interdisciplinary attempts. Dugan 2007, p. 12.
Habinek 1998, pp. 4–5.
Habinek 1998, p. 5.
56
making enemies
toric.88 In later decades, studies inspired by New Historicism and
linguistics, and in particular by Michel Foucault, have surfaced
in an otherwise conservative ield. This has also led to the extant
speeches from antiquity being viewed as texts comparable to other
types of ancient literature.89 Rather than merely imperfect records of an oration, speeches as texts can be analyzed in the same
manner as plays, poetry, or inscriptions.90 The ield has lourished
with these new ideas, even though one should not press an overall
transformation of the study of rhetoric.91 In many aspects, Classics
has stayed a conservative discipline and studies with explicit use of
modern critical theory or methodology remain scarce.92
None the less, the attitude of scholars has changed and therefore also the approach to rhetoric. The explanatory value of rhetorical theory has accordingly been challenged.93 The belief that
persuasion can be bottled, labeled, and sold has diminished. To
be sure, the relation between theory and practice can furthermore
be doubted. Jon Hesk observes that there is much in the real
examples of Greek and Roman oratory that deies explanation
and that cannot be predicted on the basis of any rhetorical classiication.94 Instead of an ideal system of eloquence, rhetorical
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
Dugan 2007, p. 13. Note that Dugan’s identiies this broader view of rhetoric also in antiquity. See also Richlin 1992, p. xiv; Connolly 2007a, p. 15.
Gunderson 2009a, p. 8.
See Gunderson 2009a, p. 8 who argues that it is inadequate to separate
speeches from other types of ancient texts.
For new approaches to the rhetorical tradition, see Poulakos (ed.) 1993;
Habinek 1998; and Gunderson (ed.) 2009.
Dugan 2007, p. 15.
The rhetorical handbooks, from which so much of our knowledge of the
ancient art of speaking stems, were pragmatic in nature. They promised a
system for successful persuasion. Catherine Steel has maintained that this
pragmatic concern with the end results “is the main reason for its limited
use as a critical tool for understanding surviving examples of oratory.” Steel
2009, p. 90.
Hesk 2009, p. 161. Cf. Steel 2009, p. 84. See also Kirby 1997, p. 18.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
57
theory can be seen as “lexible, alive, and disputed throughout
antiquity.”95 Moreover, rhetoric is increasingly seen as a cultural construct that dynamically interacts with society as a whole
and therefore provides a “cultural/linguistic map of the Roman
world.”96 Moreover, Joy Connolly has argued that rhetoric is “a
useful lens through which to observe and understand the workings of republican politics.”97 The present study its neatly into
this evolving part of the ield of rhetoric. Rhetoric is not the object of study per se but “a launching point” into other aspects of
the Roman culture.98
In the present study, rhetoric is a launching point into Roman
immorality and the object of study is the attacks that Cicero
made on the character of his opponents. Interest in these attacks
themselves can be located mainly within the study of invective.
Invective
Traditionally, classical scholarship has identiied attacks on immorality as belonging to the literary genre of invective. Severin
Koster, author of Die Invektive in der griechischen und römischen Literatur, offers the following deinition of this genre:
Die Invektive ist eine strukturierte literarische Form, deren Ziel es
ist, mit allen geeigneten Mitteln eine namentlich gennante Person
öffentlich vor dem Hintergrund der jeweils geltenden Werte und
Normen als Persönlichkeit herabzusetzen.99
95
96
97
98
99
Gunderson 2009a, p. 14.
Dugan 2007, p. 16. See also Ruffell 2003, p. 52.
Connolly 2007a, p. 4.
See Dugan 2007, p. 16.
Koster 1980, p. 39; see also p. 354. Koster’s deinition holds merit because it
underlines the dependency of oratory in general, and invective in particular,
58
making enemies
Invective is a structured literary genre, in which the goal is,
through all appropriate means, to publically and personally
degrade a person mentioned by name, on the basis of contemporary values and norms.
Although the formalistic nature of invective is often emphasized,
as in Koster’s deinition, other scholars have focused on the intensity of attack as the deining feature of invective.100 Kathryn
Geffcken opts to characterize invective as oratory which “has as
its ultimate purpose the destruction of the enemy” and furthermore as “sustained aggression” that uses every type of verbal
weapon available to “smash the enemy and emerge victorious
over the fallen opposition.”101 Often invective furthermore suggests that the attacks are “for their own sake” and have a crude
or hyperbolic character.102
The study of invective has in recent years moved in the same direction as rhetoric in general, but was for a long time stagnant.103
100
101
102
103
on society, and its values, at large. Cf. Novokhatko 2009, p. 13: “Invective
is a literary form that aims to humiliate its object in public by any possible
means and which addresses the object by name.”
There is a conceptual ambiguity to the term itself. When speaking of invective, scholars can denote a type of speech, a particular speech, a vituperative
statement or a broad genre transgressing several literary forms. It is routinely
equated with vituperatio and thus conined within the epedeictic genre. See
Richlin 1978, p. 80 for different types of invective.
Geffcken 1973, p. 66. Cf. Richlin 1978, p. 79: “[The most straightforward
invective is] that which has the primary and practical purpose of disgracing
a certain person.”
Cf. Powell 2006, p. 16. See also Ruffell 2003, p. 57.
Merrill 1975, p. i. Early standard works include Süss 1910; Nisbet 1961;
Opelt 1965; Geffcken 1973; Merrill 1975; and Koster 1980. Richlin 1992;
and Corbeill 1996 further developed a cultural perspective on invective. Lately see chapters on invective by Corbeill 2002b; Craig 2004; and Arena
2007. See also the recent work by Novokhatko 2009; and the edited volumes Booth 2006; and Smith & Covino 2011. For a summary of the scholarly
tradition, see Powell 2006.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
59
One reason perhaps can be attributed to the view, advocated by
Ronald Syme that political speech was viewed as “screen and
sham” concealing oligarchic maneuverings. Invective, the “grosser forms of abuse and misrepresentation,” thus, are of little concern to real politics and scholars have accordingly ignored it.104
The lack of interest in these statements can also be explained by
the fact that they were identiied as part of a literary genre. The
same topoi could be found not only in speeches but also in satire, grafiti, and epigrams. Since all politicians, including Cicero
himself, were subjected to similar attacks it could of course not
be trusted to accurately portray his opponents. One of the most
inluential scholars on the subject, R. G. M. Nisbet, famously described invective as showing “more regard for literary convention
than historical truth.”105 It should not be taken seriously. Scholars
for a long time heeded his words.106 Similarly, Crook maintained
that invective was part of a political and judicial “game” that had
its own rules and did not directly relate to other contexts.107 All
this ensured that invective was not seen as playing any part in
Roman politics. On top of that, Erich Gruen not only agreed that
“invective was commonplace” but added that “hyperbole would
be recognized for what it was.”108 According to such a view, the
Romans did not take invective seriously either.
There are other possible reasons for the neglect of invective. In
describing past scholarship on political abuse, Anthony Corbeill
identiies two sets of attitudes—those who have chosen to judge
Cicero, inding invective unreined and unworthy of the political
104 Syme 1939, p. 151. Cf. Pocock 1926, p. 80.
105 Nisbet 1961, p. 193. Cf. Earl 1967, p. 19. On genre, see however Powell
2006, pp. 17–18.
106 Corbeill 2002b, p. 198, n. 7.
107 Crook 1967, p. 255.
108 Gruen 1974, p. 137. See also Austin 1952, p. 52.
60
making enemies
system of the Roman Republic, and those who have tried to make
apologies for him.109 Invective was, at best, an embarrassing trait
of Roman oratory. The importance and meaning of invective was
thus effectively undermined. A main objective for the scholarly
works on invective instead became to catalogue its contents. In
1910, Süss adopted ten categories of invective from the Greek
rhetorical tradition.110 These were later made to correspond better with the Roman tradition by Nisbet.111 Lastly, Christopher
Craig has formulated, based on Süss and Nisbet, a list containing
seventeen categories of types (or loci) of invective. This list includes: embarrassing family origin; unworthiness of one’s family;
physical appearance; eccentricity of dress; gluttony and drunkenness; hypocrisy for appearing virtuous; avarice; taking bribes;
pretentiousness; sexual misconduct; hostility to family; cowardice in war; squandering one’s patrimony; aspiring to tyranny;
cruelty to citizens and allies; plunder; and inally, to be noted,
oratorical ineptitude.112 These, then, are the stock-themes of invective.113 Instead of context and meaning, identifying and categorizing invective emerges as the central task, something which
has prompted criticism.114 More recently, Jeffrey Tatum has also
stressed this dualism in the scholarship: “Modern approaches to
Roman invective either stress its conventionality by making typo109
110
111
112
Corbeill 1996, pp. 22–23. See also Steel 2006, p. 106.
Süss 1910, pp. 245–62.
Nisbet 1961.
Craig 2004, pp. 190–191. Cf. Geffcken’s list consisting of family, appearance, character, vices and evil deeds. Geffcken 1973, p. 70. See also Game
1909.
113 Craig 2007, pp. 335–336 argues that the audience expected these themes
whereby they identiied the speech as an invective. This however, he states
(p. 337), does not reduce invective to a “mechanical counting process.”
114 See Steel 2006, p. 124 on the “inherent limitations of any approach to Ciceronian invective which attempts simply to catalogue themes and techniques.”
See also Corbeill 2002b, p. 201. Cf. May 1996, p. 143.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
61
logies of it or attempt to explore its sociological premises and
implications.”115 As regards immorality, the typologies are vague.
From the above, it should be clear that previous scholarship on
invective was for a long time content with identifying its content
while leaving its cultural implications uncommented. There have
however been, of late, some different approaches to the study
of invective after the more philological studies in the tradition
of Opelt and Koster.116 Some of these studies have been inspired by New Historicism.117 The genre perspective has also been
questioned. Invective, according to Robin Seager, should not be
understood as a “sharply delimited genre,” but as “a mode of
discourse” the orator could employ according to the demands of
the situation.118 Rather than just an end in itself, it was a natural
part of forensic and deliberative oratory.119
The scholar who broke new ground in the ield was Amy
Richlin. Although her primary focus was Roman satire, she treated invective as a related genre in her dissertation.120 In The Garden
of Priapus, irst published in 1983 she proceeded to investigate
the connection between sexuality and humor and in doing so,
took a novel perspective on invective as an area for scholarly
115 Tatum 2011, p. 167. As examples of typological works, Tatum offers Süss
1910; Nisbet 1961; and Craig 2004. Sociological approaches include Richlin
1992; and Corbeill 1996.
116 See for instance several of the articles in Booth 2006 and in particular the
contribution by Javier Uría. See furthermore Dugan 2005; and Gildenhard
2011.
117 Booth 2006, p. xxi.
118 Seager 2006, p. 25. Craig 2007, p. 338 in comparison sees the genre as a part
of a “zero-sum game of prestige.” Note that Craig allows for the extended
value of ad hominem attacks in forensic and deliberative oratory. Contra:
Ruffell 2003 who argues for the broader cultural implications of invective.
119 Arena 2007, p. 149.
120 See Richlin 1978.
62
making enemies
study.121 Instead of ignoring invective, she held that the Romans
considered verbal abuse a valid means of political expression and
one which they took seriously.122 She also stated that the “frame
of thought” that informs satire and invective “bears on Roman
institutions that are not primarily sexual, like political systems,
the military and religion.”123 Thereby, she included attacks on
immorality in the political culture. In her wake, scholars have
pursued and studied invective with renewed interest, using it to
analyze gender, identity, and elite anxieties.
The perspective advocated by Richlin was developed further
by Anthony Corbeill. In his prominent work on humor, Corbeill refuted that Roman audiences did not believe the attacks of
Roman orators.124 Instead he opted for another interpretation:
that humorous invective should be read as a rhetorical utility
aimed at making a social outcast of its victim. By demonstrating
in oratory that the target of invective behaved contrary to expectations and the well-being of the Republic, the orator could
isolate his opponent and place him outside the boundaries of society.125 The audience, Corbeill claims, is made part of this process
121 Later revised in 1992. References are to this edition. See also Richlin 1984.
122 Richlin 1992, p. 103. See also Gildenhard 2006, p. 174: “Invective seems to
have been an accepted mode of discourse in Republican Rome.”; and Steel
2011, p. 35: “The systematic denigration of political enemies and rivals was
an accepted part of Roman political culture.”
123 Richlin 1992, p. 210; see also p. 104.
124 Corbeill 1996, p. 5; with further arguments on p. 24. Also Corbeill 2002b,
pp. 198–199. On the persistent question of the veracity of invective, see
Craig 2007, p. 336 who argues that to the audience truth was of secondary
importance, if in fact not irrelevant. Ruffell 2003, p. 48 suggests that whether
or not the “audience ‘really’ believed or disbelieved” these attacks was not
the point, but what mattered was whether someone was outmaneuvered by
an opponent.
125 Corbeill 1996, pp. 4, 9. See also Corbeill 2002b, p. 198: “Through the extra
legal means of invective, the public speaker employs language to exclude the
potential law-breaker from the community of the elite.” Cf. Powell 2006, p.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
63
by the orator and the representations of immoral politicians must
have had support, in terms of beliefs and values, what the author
calls biases, in the audience in order to be effective.126 Such a
perspective seems a far cry from viewing invective as merely a
convention or an isolated genre to be ignored. Instead, it includes
invective in communal processes of both identity and politics.
To Corbeill, these expressions had no less impact than “serious
political discussion” in the creating and enforcing of the norms
of the Roman community and he holds that they had “tangible
effects in the political sphere.”127 His work is distinguished by his
ability to convincingly analyze Roman elite morality—a result
of Corbeill’s view that oratory can be seen as a cultural product.
Scholars have now revisited invective with a renewed sense
of urgency. Several books that deal with Roman, or ancient,
sexuality and gender have taken an interest in invective because
of the frequent sexual themes and vocabulary.128 These studies
have analyzed invective as a means to study sexual morality and
identity. Simultaneously, an interest in invective as a phenomenon
and genre of rhetoric has also resurfaced.129 Where scholars in the
past shunned invective—whether because of its insincere, hyperbolic, topical, or ungentlemanly quality—modern approaches
have recognized harsh personal attacks as crucial in understanding Roman culture and politics.
It is easy to get a sense in the scholarly tradition that invective
126
127
128
129
20, who argues, in response to Corbeill, that: “invectives brand their victims
not as excluded, but as deviant members of the in-group.” Further remarks
by Ruffell 2003, pp. 47–48; and Arena 2007, p. 157.
Corbeill 1996, p. 5.
Corbeill 1996, pp. 9, 24.
See e.g. Santoro L’Hoir 1992, pp. 9–46; Langlands 2006, pp. 281–318;
Williams 2010.
See the edited volumes by Booth (ed.) 2006; and Smith and Covino (eds.)
2011.
64
making enemies
explains what has been perceived as an idiosyncrasy. Invective as
a modern category is in its traditional function a literary understanding of the nature of certain statements that otherwise seem
confusing or out of place. Its value has been in acknowledging the
existence of a (lamentable) cultural tendency of severe and intense
personal assailment apparent in several genres of public discourse
in ancient Rome—which can then be brushed aside. This in turn
means that when looking for invective the scholar has a preconceived notion of what to look for and what to ind. Furthermore,
invective once found in the material is explained beforehand; as
a genre, as convention, as something expected, and as something,
subsequently, to be ignored.130 For these reasons I will not in the
upcoming study routinely identify statements in oratory as invective, but as statements about immorality. In this way, there is
no initial assumption about the difference between hyperbolical
and “subtle” claims about character, but that these interacted in
Roman moral discourse. While invective implies the exaggerated
and extreme, Powell has rightly noted that there are types of attacks in the speeches of Cicero for which the term invective is
simply not appropriate.131 So, there appears to be an advantage to
maintaining a difference between character portrayal and character abuse. Finally, this means that rather than starting the study
with the loci suggested by Craig, these are instead available for
comparison after the speeches themselves have been analyzed.
The object of study is not invective, but immorality. While it
is important not to conlate these two, this also means that the
modern categories of invective will at times overlap with “noninvective” in the upcoming study. For this purpose, invective is
130 In my view, invective also signals a conscious oratorical strategy being
employed, whereas the object of this study is the meaning embedded in these
statements, not the meaning necessarily intended.
131 Powell 2006, p. 2.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
65
understood here as particularly intense character claims and holds
no given explanatory value for the study at hand. Moreover, the
question of the status of these attacks can be approached from a
different perspective: as claims about immorality.
Immorality
As previously argued, immorality has not been a frequent object
for scholarly endeavor; the relationship between immorality and
politics even less so. An early study on the topic was Donald
Earl’s The Moral and Political Tradition in Rome (1967) in which
the author emphasized precisely that to the Romans there was no
sharp distinction between morality and politics or economics.132
In particular Earl studied the relevance of virtus for the nobility.
To Earl, however, or what he referred to as the “modern enquirer” attempting to “distinguish [...] the political particular from
the moral general,” the “apparent moral platitudes mask a political reality.”133 Attacks on immorality were seen by Earl as a
convention.134 Nevertheless, in his inal paragraph, Earl defends
the study of the Roman tradition of blurring morality and politics, “[b]anal and cliché-ridden though it may appear to us” and
argues that studying this tradition “can teach us much about the
way in which the Roman mind worked and explain much about
Roman actions and reactions.”135
132 Earl 1967, p. 17. See also Earl 1961; Walbank 1965; Lind 1989, 1992;
and Astin 1988. For morality and emotions in the Roman aristocracy, see
Kaster 2005. For morality in imperial ideology, see Charlesworth 1937; and
Fears 1981. For Cicero’s rhetorical construction of morality and immorality,
consult also Gildenhard 2011.
133 Earl 1967, pp. 20, 56; see also pp. 77 and 118–119. Earl saw Roman politics
as fundamentally dictated by the oligarchy (pp. 14–15).
134 Earl 1967, p. 90; also p. 19.
135 Earl 1967, p. 132. Note the book’s inal sentence: “Not infrequently the
66
making enemies
In The Politics of Immorality (1993), Catharine Edwards proceeded on the same supposition—that understanding morality
was critical to understanding politics, but instead focused on the
inversion of the virtutes that had occupied Earl. Hers was thereby
arguably the irst book to take immorality as a serious scholarly
endeavor in its own right; that is, as rewarding the discourse of
immorality interest in and of itself and not something obstructing
the scholar’s view.136 Edwards traced the Roman obsession with
morality that Donald Earl had noted and that I cited in the introduction, but without regarding it as inherently erroneous.137 Her
perspective advocated that although certain claims about immorality, for instance in oratorical duels, were not necessarily taken
to be the “literal truth” this is not the same as holding them to be
“empty or meaningless.”138 Edwards, like Richlin, clearly linked
claims of immorality with Roman political life and with power.139
The study of Roman immorality has in particular one area
thrived in recent decades: sexuality. The topic has been made the
focus of numerous monographs, articles and edited volumes.140
nature of a society is most clearly revealed in its most cherished clichés.”
136 Edwards 1993, p. 12. For earlier works on immorality, see Friedländer 1862;
Litchield 1914.
137 Cf. Lintott 1972.
138 Edwards 1993, pp. 10–11. Just as important to note is Edward’s deiance
against using ancient sources to reconstruct a person’s behavior which
she rightfully saw as a law in previous scholarship (p. 11). See also her
comments on “colorful characters” as metaphors rather than real people (p.
36).
139 Edwards 1993, p. 27; see also p. 28: “Morality was still one of the most
important spheres for the representation and negotiation of power relations.”
Cf. Connolly 2007a, p. 4.
140 See e.g. Ariès & Béjin (eds.) 1985; Cantarella 1992; Richlin 1992; Hallett
& Skinner 1997; Dupont & Éloi 2001; Skinner 2005; Langlands 2006;
Williams 2010. See also Kiefer 1934. For Greek sexuality, see the standard
works of Dover 1978; and Halperin, Winkler & Zeitlin (eds.) 1990. Articles
on the subject are too numerous to include here.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
67
Much of the classical debate was stimulated by the work of
Michel Foucault.141 As previously discussed, Richlin argued for the
relevance of sexuality for the broader cultural milieu, and for politics in particular. In her work on pudicitia (“chastity” or “sexual
virtue”) Rebecca Langlands similarly observes that the study of
sexual morality, because it is embedded in power structures and relations of power, provides insight into Roman culture in general.142
Character, Ethos, and Self-fashioning
The third direction within the study of rhetoric with particular
bearing for the present study is the importance attached to rhetorical character.143 In his landmark study on the subject, James
May equated ethos broadly with our modern “character” and
argued that it was an “abiding and essential element in the art
of verbal persuasion.”144 May furthermore held that character, or
ethos, was an overlooked aspect of considerable importance in
Cicero’s oratory.145 He went on to show how Cicero’s rhetorical
arguments centered on the ethos of himself, his clients, and his
opponents.
From the study of the Roman judicial system, May’s arguments
were conirmed and further developed by Andrew Riggsby. He
agreed that scholars in fact “must reconsider the status of the distinction between argument about the charge and argument about
character.”146 Attempting to separate the two is anachronistic:
141 For critique of Foucault’s treatment of ancient Rome, see Richlin 1992 and
1998.
142 Langlands 2006, p. 5; see also p. 318.
143 Generally see Süss 1910; Solmsen 1941; Kennedy 1972; McClintock 1975;
Wisse 1989; Leeman et al. 1981–1996.
144 May 1988, p. 1. See Langlands 2006, p. 282.
145 See also Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 259; and Connolly 2007a, pp. 58–59.
146 Riggsby 2004, p. 176. Also Kennedy 1972, p. 41.
68
making enemies
It has long been observed that Roman courts allowed and seem
even to have demanded discussion of matters that would be
excluded as irrelevant and/or prejudicial in an Anglo-American
court. High on the list are the character, reputation, and past life
of the defendant. A century ago this could be adduced as proof of
the corruption or primitiveness of the Roman courts.147
Riggsby has convincingly shown that what he calls the ethical
argument was instrumental in Cicero’s oratory.148 That there
exists a discrepancy between on the one hand the emphasis on
character in Roman rhetoric and surviving examples of oratory,
and on the other the scholarly disregard for character as argument has been attested by other studies as well. Kathryn Tempest
has shown how character appeal was not only effective in Ciceronian oratory, but that it was rooted within Greek practice.149
Nancy Worman has argued that “contrary to received wisdom
on the topic, the language of abuse has a more fundamental role
to play in the forging of oratorical techniques than do elevated
or laudatory modes.”150 Furthermore, she claims that rhetorical
tactics of pillory and exclusion “form the core of classical oratory
in practice,” regardless of the attempts of both Aristoteles and
later theorists to emphasize the importance of “projecting beneicence” and “employing pleasant vocabulary and cadences.”151 In
147 Riggsby 2004, p. 176; May 1988, p. 10: “By Cicero’s day, the speaker’s ethos
had become an important source of proof in the courtroom.” Also McClintock 1975, p. 40.
148 Riggsby 1999, pp. 37–38, 169.
149 Tempest 2007. See also Worman 2009, p. 40: “Athenian orators made frequent use of ictionalizing and abusive tactics that denigrated their opponents’ status and stature, both in forensic cases and in the Assembly.” Cf.
Santoro L’Hoir 1992, p. 27.
150 Worman 2009, pp. 30–31.
151 Worman 2009, p. 41.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
69
other words, strategies suggested in theory as well as the practice
of orators should not be disregarded as “rhetorical tricks” that
merely throw dust in the eyes of the audience, but as evidence
of the weight ascribed to character in Roman political culture
and society at large. It is not a “simple genre feature” and it was
certainly not irrelevant.152
The understanding that public character was a crucial aspect
of Roman oratory and politics has led scholars to pursue the
question of how an orator such as Cicero presented and in essence fashioned himself to the Roman audience.153 Through
this type of oratorical self-fashioning, or self-presentation, the
aristocratic orator constructed his identity within his public discourse. There was, as John Dugan has argued, a cultural understanding of the speech as a relection of the speaker.154 Roman
rhetoric, according to Patrick Sinclair, was not only about persuasion, but also self-invention.155 The self-image projected by
the orator functioned as an aristocratic marker. A digniied and
morally proper impression was in itself a means of persuasion.
In his work on Cicero’s self-fashioning as a new man, a novus
homo, in Rome, Dugan sees these rhetorical strategies, found in
Cicero’s rhetorical treatises and speeches, that is, both in theory
and practice, as deliberate. The orator fashions himself both to
shape Roman culture and to position himself within the same
discourse.156
152 Riggsby 2004, p. 167.
153 See Sinclair 1993; Gleason 1995; Riggsby 1995; Gunderson 2000; Krostenko 2001; Dugan 2005; Kurczyk 2006; Also Hölkeskamp 1987. Cf.
Leach 1990.
154 Dugan 2005, p. 3. See De or. 2.184.
155 Sinclair 1993, p. 561.
156 Dugan 2005, pp. 3, 13; see also p. 18: “Roman rhetoric itself is a discourse
consumed with questions of the projection of identity, the formation of the
self, and the proper use of speech for social acculturation and advancement.”
70
making enemies
The concept, pioneered by Stephen Greenblatt, has found
traction within classics.157 Maud Gleason has stressed the complexity and interconnected whole as regards self-presentation,
“in which conscious choices interact with instinctive responses
to traditional paradigms to produce a carefully modulated public identity.”158 In a more novel philological approach, Brian A.
Krostenko has emphasized the extraordinary importance of what
he calls the “social performance of identity” to the culture of the
Roman elite and to the Latin rhetorical tradition.159 Bottom line,
rhetoric and identity are seen from this perspective as fused, and
by studying the irst, scholars have sought the latter. The morality
or immorality of the speaker in ancient Rome, from such a view,
interacted with and shaped the culture at large.
Immorality in Roman Political Culture
How then do we place the present study in relation to previous
scholarship? What do we know and what knowledge can we
hope to gain?
To be sure, we have, not least through the efforts of the above
mentioned scholars, a good knowledge of Roman anxieties
about their morality. To this discussion, the present study will
hope to add and conceivably accentuate certain themes, but also
in several ways build upon them. More important is the attempt
to connect the dots through the link of what I refer to as cultural
logic; a link I believe can be shown to explain not only the prominence of immorality in Roman oratory, but also show the implementation of immorality as persuasive argument in Cicero’s
157 See Greenblatt 1984.
158 Gleason 1995, p. xxvi.
159 Krostenko 2001, pp. 1, 5.
Methodology, Sources, and Scope
71
speeches and thereby in the political culture where he acted.
The tripartite approach to previous scholarship signals the
natural locus of the impending work. Verbal abuse, immorality,
and character together form the platform from which to take the
next step. Three remarks are initially worth making in relation
to the works I have cited above. First, it should be clear by now
that I wish to take a broader approach to character attack than
merely as verbal abuse. In this I want to include several speeches
outside the canon of invective and moreover, a host of statements
and claims on immoral character not identiied as invective or
as abuse. There is, from my perspective, no obvious reason that
aggressive and non-aggressive arguments in oratory, however deined, reveal different moral standards, and with this approach I
want to reduce the rift between relevant and irrelevant statements
of character and corral a larger body of source material that in
different manner debates and communicates Roman views on
immorality.160 The focus on immorality also means that certain
types of invective are of little importance. Character and morality, rather than genre and convention, take center stage.
Secondly, the task at hand moves from the general discourse of
immorality detailed by Edwards to political practice by looking
at Cicero’s implementation of this moral discourse in Realpolitik. This is not a study of rhetorical theory, but oratory; that is,
practice. In turn this will deepen the understanding of this moral
discourse but also bridge moral and political culture. The question is how immorality could serve political goals and attempt to
produce political outcomes.
160 The same goes for the tendency to equate invective with aggressive humor,
as Richlin 1992 and Corbeill 1996 does (although neither treats it as merely
laughworthy), a perspective I believe has merits but in this study creates
limitations. See also Hickson-Hahn 1998.
72
making enemies
Thirdly, I aim to build on the understanding of character as
fundamental in rhetoric and focus on the immoral aspects of negative ethos with a complete study of Cicero’s speeches. A question in this study becomes how character can be undermined
through the use of immorality and how the immoral politician
can be portrayed; a portrayal that closely interacts with a moral
culture but has consequences for the political culture.
As a inal point, there is reason to stress the important efforts
already made by several scholars on the subject of this thesis. Several perspectives and conclusions argued by the aforementioned
authors have provided vital inspiration for how to view Cicero’s
speeches. At the same time these studies have all made one thing
clear—the conversation on Roman immorality has in fact just
begun.
Chapter II
Roman Political Culture
Marcus Tullius Cicero was born in 106 BCE in the town of
Arpinum, located roughly 100 kilometers southeast of Rome.161
As a novus homo, a new man without the dignity of prominent
ancestors, the climb on the political ladder was particularly arduous. Cicero would eventually do better than most of his peers.
But his success would come at a price. He would master the game
but also fall mercilessly from its highest point.
In this chapter the political culture in which Cicero acted
throughout his career will be outlined. The main question is
in what way immorality was a part of the struggle for power
in ancient Rome. The task is not linear as there are contested
aspects of how politics at Rome actually worked. Three aspects
of Roman political culture are of primary concern: power, oratory, and morality. How did politics work in ancient Rome?
What function did oratory have in regard to politics? And inally:
what role did morality play on the political stage?
Understanding Roman character defamation in public
speeches begins here, with the realization that it was an accepted
part of Roman politics, irmly ixed in its individualistic, competitive, and moral political culture.
161 For the life of Cicero, see Plut. Cic. For modern biographies, see e.g. Gelzer
1969; Stockton 1971; Rawson 1975; Mitchell 1979 and 1991; Habicht
1990; Everitt 2002; and now Tempest 2011.
73
74
making enemies
Political Power in the Late Republic
Rome by the time of the late Republic had grown from a small
village into a vast empire. Although we can roughly reconstruct
parts of this historical narrative, the details of the drastic transformation are by and large lost. Nevertheless, in many ways it
seems the political culture had retained several of its deining
traits and was, more importantly, characterized by its ideological
roots in a Roman past. History, tradition, and politics were intimately linked in Republican Rome.
The past was important because it served as a moral guide to
the Romans.162 The early history of Rome, albeit legendary, was
valuable to the Roman historian Livius because of the lessons
of morality contained therein.163 To the Roman aristocracy and
their system of values, the actions of their forefathers, described
in Rome’s history, were an important source in determining proper political behavior. The elite measured themselves against the
past. Therefore, morality and politics were also fused together in
a fundamental way through the link of history.
Before we can argue that portrayals of immoral character in oratory were important in Roman politics we must locate the place of
both oratory and morality within the political culture. To do this,
we must irst establish the basic rules of the political game. Who
could play? What arenas of politics existed? What acts on the political stage were possible? In order to understand Cicero’s portrayal
of Marcus Antonius as well as those he constructed earlier in his
career, we need to understand the nature of the political culture
that pitted individuals against each other and compelled them to
moral attack.
162 Raalaub 2006, p. 128. See also Dugan 2005, p. 11.
163 Liv. Praef. 6–13. For the early history of Rome, see e.g. Cornell 1995; Oakley
2004; Forsythe 2005; Raalaub 2006.
Roman Political Culture
75
The Roman Republic
By the time Cicero entered Roman politics the Republic had
started to show signs of weakness. The Romans collectively held
that after being ruled by kings for almost 250 years they had
in the year 509 BCE cast out the last of the Etruscan kings and
replaced monarchy with a republic. The idea of a res publica,
a “common thing,” proved a powerful one. The Roman people
were ideologically joined as a community in the serving of the
state. Equally powerful was the fear of a return to monarchy
and tyranny. The Romans set out to create a political system that
guaranteed this would not happen.
The early Republic was characterized by the aristocratic rule
of the patricians over the plebeians.164 The patricians monopolized the political and religious ofices that had supplanted the
authority of the king. The plebeians, who made up the bulk of the
Roman army, rallied together in what is known as the Struggle
of the Orders and had, by the middle of the fourth century BCE,
balanced the scales and gained entrance to the world of politics.
The new political class during the middle Republic was a fusion
between the patrician gentes and wealthy plebeians. This class,
known as the nobility, distinguished themselves by service to
the res publica and leadership in the many wars that both fueled
and were fueled by the political competition among the elite. The
political system of Republican Rome which we ind in the Ciceronian era had by this time in fundamental aspects been set.165
The last era of the Republic felt the strain of being a world
power, but Rome had nevertheless been unwilling to change
164 For a recent challenge to the traditional division of the Republic, see Flower
2010.
165 North 2006, p. 259. Due to our lack of contemporary evidence, the details
of the political system before the third century are obscured.
76
making enemies
its political culture at the core. The Roman historian Sallustius
pointed to the lapse in morality which followed from being the
world’s mistress, a causal explanation that, while its merits can
certainly be argued, serves to illustrate morality’s place in Roman
history.166 For the present purpose it will sufice to consent that several factors connected to imperial expansion—social, economic, political, and military—together formed a background that
coalesced to create instability.167
In 133 BCE, the year traditionally signaling the start of the late
Republic, Tiberius Gracchus was slain by members of the elite
after opposing the Senate. The breach of tradition was believed
to have been cataclysmic by contemporary spectators and later
students of the fall of the Roman Republic alike. A new precedent
had been set. The political consensus that had characterized the
earlier centuries was replaced by political violence.
The late Republic was torn by inner conlict on both a military and a political scale, all the while Rome continued to war
both abroad and against its former allies on the Italian peninsula. In the 80’s BCE, just when the young Marcus Tullius Cicero
was coming of political age, the military dynasts Gaius Marius
and Lucius Cornelius Sulla were waging war with armies no
longer loyal to the Senate, and in the aftermath political violence
reigned, violence that was repeated years later in Cicero’s death.
When Gaius Julius Caesar followed Sulla’s example and made
himself dictator after vanquishing his enemies in the Civil War
of the 40’s, he was slain by members of the aristocracy. In the
eyes of history, if not to the Romans themselves, the res publica
died with him.
166 Sall. Iug. 41; Cat. 10. Cf. Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 9.
167 For modern interpretations, of which there are many, see e.g. Meier 1966;
Gruen 1974; Beard & Crawford 1985; Brunt 1988; Flower 2010.
Roman Political Culture
77
Although the breakdown of the Roman political culture can
too easily be ascribed to a teleological chain of reasoning where
the Republic is doomed the minute political decorum is breached,
we need not doubt that the intensity of the political struggle
during the late Republic escalated.168 Even if, on the surface, the
political system was the same, friction within it contributed to a
more antagonistic political reality. The stakes were higher. During
Cicero’s career violence became part of the political game. One of
his political enemies took to the battleield against his patria and
another employed street gangs as a political tool. The growing
inlux of wealth became even more intertwined with the struggle for ofice.169 Other means of gaining inluence were pursued,
some which resulted in armies on a battleield, some with clashes
in the Forum.
By the time Marcus Tullius Cicero entered the political stage, the
political culture under scrutiny was at any rate harsh and relentless. And during his long career, which we will in a sense follow
from the most antagonistic and polemical aspects, time and again,
the new man from Arpinum experienced this more than most.
The Political System
Now in all political situations we must understand that the
principal factor which makes for success or failure is the form of
a state’s constitution: it is from this source, as if from a fountainhead, that all designs and plans of action not only originate but
reach their fulillment.170
Polybios, second century BCE.
168 For the teleology of violent narratives in Roman history, see Hammar 2014
forthcoming.
169 Rosenstein 1990, p. 2.
170 Polyb. 6.2. Translation by Scott-Kilvert (1979).
78
making enemies
To the Romans, there was an imperative continuity from the past
to the present, guided by the ways of the forefathers, the mos
maiorum.171 The political system that the young Marcus had to
learn to navigate was seen as naturally evolved through the wisdom of the ancestors. This meant that the Roman Republic had
no written constitution. Instead it had, according to Christian
Meier, a “growing constitution” (gewachsene Verfassung).172
There were theoretically three nodes of power in the political
system of ancient Rome: the Senate, the voting public, and the
magistrates. The ancient commentator Polybios saw it as a system which incorporated aristocratic, democratic, and monarchic
aspects.173 This to him was the reason Rome was so successful.
In modern scholarship it has been a long-standing issue which of
these to emphasize.174
Executive power lay with the magistracies while the Senate’s
role was primarily advisory. Basically, the voters of Rome elected magistrates who interacted with the Senate to decide state
business. It was a system of checks and balances designed not to
allow a concentration of power in a single individual. Needless
to say, the system had failed by the time of Cicero’s demise.
Elections to magistracies followed the cursus honorum, the
common career path for politicians. For a young aspiring politi171 North 2006, p. 257. For mos maiorum, see Linke & Stemmler 2000.
172 Meier 1966, p. 56. Cf. Hölkeskamp 2010, pp. 15–16. See also Bleicken
1995.
173 Consult in general book 6 of the Histories and in particular chapters 6.9.
and 6.10. For a thorough discussion of the value and risks regarding Polybios, see Lintott 1993, chapter 3. For critique of Polybios’ account, see
Nippel 1980.
174 Theodor Mommsen, in particular, stressed the role of the magistrate, while
scholars such as Gelzer and Bleicken instead regarded the Senate as the most
politically potent of the three. Millar is the singularly most persistent champion of the People’s power. As noted by Lintott 1993, p. 66, however, the
Roman’s themselves were hardly in agreement on this issue.
Roman Political Culture
79
cian like Cicero, this meant that there was a ixed political ladder
to climb. For every step on this ladder the number of individuals
elected for each year was reduced, increasing competition. Together the magistrates performed the tasks of everyday politics,
public religious acts, and maintenance of the city itself. The inal
step on the cursus, that of censor, is of particular interest as this
ofice entailed the “moral review” of the members of the Senate.175 Immorality could literally be cause for political exclusion
in the upper echelons of power in ancient Rome.
In Roman political culture, religion and politics were intertwined and there existed, parallel to a politician’s ascent on the
path of honors, a religious career.176 Ritual communication was
a vital part of Roman public life, and priests and augurs played
the role of arbiters as regard the legitimacy of different forms of
political action.177 This also meant that the same members of the
elite were simultaneously magistrates and priests.
Most magistrates and priests in Cicero’s day were also senators.
In theory, this kept the magistrates from disobeying the body and
thus constituted a conservative factor in the political culture.
After a one-year term, consuls and praetors were given oficials
175 See Cic. Leg. 3.7; Liv. 4.8.2. For the ofice of censor, see Astin 1988. Cf.
McGinn 1998, pp. 27–28.
176 For religion in Rome, see e.g. Beard, North, & Price 1998; Ando (ed.) 2003;
Rüpke 2004 and 2006. Rüpke 2004, p. 194 suggests that to “talk about
‘Roman religion’ is to talk about cultural practices that it our notion of
religion.” Scholarship of the Roman Republic has often held an apprehensive view of Roman religion and particularly those areas that concern state
business. The possibility of manipulating the will of the gods, of which the
Romans were well aware, has been seen as proof of the impiousness of the
Romans. Consequently, its importance has been downplayed. Brunt, for instance, holds that Cicero was “devoid of personal piety” and that religion
was a matter of paying “lip-service.” See Brunt 1988, pp. 58, 60. For an
example, see also Scullard 1959, p. 212.
177 Rüpke 2006, p. 233; Flower 2004a, p. 10; North 2006, p. 267. For religion
and oratory, see in particular Gildenhard 2011, p. 246.
80
making enemies
duties by the Senate as pro-consuls and pro-praetors. For a consul or praetor this typically meant the governing of a province,
something which in turn presented the opportunity to recover
some of the cost of running for ofice.
For Cicero to begin his climb on the political ladder he irst
had to be elected. There were several voting assemblies, each
with its different conditions.178 It was the assemblies alone, so
Polybios tells us, that could pass legislation and annually elect
the oficials that held the executive power of magistracies.179 The
voting system was skewed towards the elite of the city and the
political weight of an individual vote depended highly on the
social status of the Roman who cast it.180 Furthermore, the assemblies could only accept or reject the propositions put forward by the presiding magistrate.
Beside the voting assemblies there also existed a “public meeting” called contio.181 The contio had no formal legal role and
functioned as a mode of communication between the political
group and the people at large. These meetings were summoned
by the magistrates (who were the only ones allowed to speak
without a formal invitation), and included public announcements, speeches, and arguments for or against issues at hand.
The third node of power was the Roman Senate. It was made
up of ex-magistrates and therefore contained the collected political experience of the res publica. Habitually this body, consisting
178
179
180
181
See Taylor 1966; Lintott 1993. For voting practices, see also Yakobson 1999.
Polyb. 6.14.10.
Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 19.
The ancient commentator Aulus Gellius claims that the difference between
comitia and contio was that in the former you ask the people something
which they then order or forbid, while at the latter you speak to the people
without asking them anything. Gell. NA.13.16.1. See Taylor 1966, pp. 2–3.
For the role played by the contio, see Pina Polo 1989; Mouritsen 2001; and
Morstein-Marx 2004.
Roman Political Culture
81
of 300 members (600 after Sulla’s reforms), was convened by a
consul or praetor who consulted it on political issues. The power
of the Senate was based on mos maiorum, not any formal framework. This, however, was hardly an impediment but instead
meant that their inluence was “practically unlimited.”182 They
ruled, in the words of Ronald Syme, “not in virtue of written law,
but through auctoritas.”183
One more political arena was of major importance in the Republic: the law courts. Roman trials were infused by politics.184 The
Roman courts were also exclusive to matters concerning elite behavior and all crimes were in this sense political by default.185 For
a young ambitious Roman, the irst step on a political career was
typically the arena of the courts. A standing criminal court, called
quaestio perpetua, was not introduced in the Roman Republic
until 149 BCE, but soon became the most frequent institution for
criminal justice.186 Criminal prosecution could also be put before
an assembly of the people by a magistrate. The original purpose
of the quaestiones perpetuae was to deal with the increase in provincial misconduct by governors through repetundae—extortion.
The most notorious example of this is Gaius Verres whom Cicero
prosecuted early in his career. By 80 BCE the crimes dealt with
by this court also included treason (maiestas), embezzlement (peculatus), and electoral transgressions (ambitus). The number of
jurors, made up from the higher segments of society, varied but
could range up to over a hundred. Each side was represented by
182
183
184
185
186
Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 18; also p. 26. See also van der Blom 2011, p. 49.
Syme 1939, p. 10.
On this, see in particular Alexander 2006, pp. 101–102.
See Riggsby 1999, p. 14.
The standard account is Riggsby 1999. For a general overview of the Roman
judicial system, consult e.g. Lintott 2004; Alexander 2006. A notable attempt to reconstruct the trial from the perspective of the prosecutor through
the defense speeches was made by Alexander 2002. See also Powell 2010.
82
making enemies
one or more orators who held at least one speech each. By its very
nature, the system was “strongly adversarial.”187
In sum, the setup was simple. Win elections, perform your
duties as magistrate and join the Senate. In reality, of course, this
was easier said than done. But questions remain: How did one
get elected in the irst place? Who rose on the political ladder?
What drove the individual politician? And which node of power
was in control?
Power in Practice
The brief outline of Roman politics sketched above illustrates
how it was supposed to work. But scholars have not taken the
system at face value. In order to discuss the political culture of
the late Republic we must also retrace previous and current debates in classical scholarship. The question of how this system in
actuality worked has loomed large.
With his Nobel Prize-winning effort Römische Geschichte as
well as his Römische Staatsrecht, Theodor Mommsen laid the
groundwork for much of the last century’s classical studies of
Rome.188 In particular, Mommsen had emphasized how ofice
holding among the elite and the Roman legal structure were
crucial elements in shaping Roman politics. The idea of two opposing parties struggling for supremacy—the optimates and the
populares—also lingered in the work of later scholars.189
In 1912 Matthias Gelzer put forward another theory that
was to become pervasive. Two concepts, amicitia (“friendship”
187 Riggsby 1999, p. 15.
188 See Mommsen 1881–1886, and 1887–1888.
189 Today scholars tend to deine these concepts not as ideology, but as political
behavior, or rather strategies. See for instance; Morstein-Marx 2004; and
before him Yavetz 1969. Now, however, see Wiseman 2009.
Roman Political Culture
83
or allegiances) and clientela (the patronship of the elite toward
their clients), were seen as imperative factors in the political realm.190 The notion was that through complicated networks of
dependencies, the Roman aristocracy decided the outcome of any
election without having to rely on the populace.191 It proved a
persuasive theory and was of course dificult to falsify because
such networks would never have reached the sources. Scholars
nevertheless deemed it possible to lay bare these invisible webs of
ides through the prosopographical method pioneered to a large
degree by Friedrich Münzer192 and a few decades later by Ronald
Syme.193 This meant the meticulous research of biographical details that revealed such connections and exposed, if not parties
in any by default anachronistic meaning, but political factions
or factiones. The prosopographical school produced innumerable
impressive studies that, on the level of rigorous detail at least,
scarcely seem possible to match today.194 Yet, one of its most
inluential practitioners, Erich Gruen, cautioned that classical
studies were perhaps becoming too schematic.195
190 Gelzer 1912.
191 See e.g. Earl 1967, p. 17: “It was through this complex nexus of personal
and extra-constitutional relationships that the nobility controlled not only
the people of Rome but the whole of Italy.”
192 Münzer 1920. A criticism directed against Münzer, as stressed by Hölkeskamp 1987, p. 13 is that he simply assumed the existence of aristocratic
parties. Millar in turn, albeit calling Hölkeskamp’s effort “indispensable,”
criticized the same work for assuming instead assertions that were set out
by Gelzer in 1912. Cf. Millar 1989, pp. 141–143. For Millar’s speciic comments on Gelzer see, Millar 1986, p. 2. On this debate, now see Hölkeskamp
2010.
193 Syme 1939.
194 See e.g. Scullard 1935, 1951; Badian 1958; Gruen 1968, 1974; Broughton
1972.
195 See Gruen 1971. In particular, Gruen criticized the otherwise inluential
Scullard. See Gruen 1968, p. 2, n. 3, however see also Gruen 1968, p. 279.
Further arguments contra by Lintott 1993, p. 167. See also Nicolet 1980,
84
making enemies
Needless to say, if the oligarchy can manipulate their outcome
as it pleases, elections become virtually meaningless. If a political
culture is “ixed,” dominated by acts behind the scenes, public
oratory becomes “a screen and a sham” in the words of Ronald
Syme.196 For a long time this was the view of ancient historians.
Roman politicians duped the populace with words while quietly
deciding the fate of politics among themselves.
A challenge to the stability of factiones had been formulated
by Christian Meier in 1966 but Gelzer’s theory only unraveled
after what can be described as a one-two punch.197 Peter Brunt
in his work The Fall of the Roman Republic published in 1982,
rejected the idea that at the center of Roman political culture
lay the ever powerful patron-client dichotomy, deciding its fate.
This, it has been conceded, can be seen as a paradigm shift.198
The question of course was what to put in its place. A provocative answer came from Fergus Millar, who by this time had
already stated his criticism of the closed-circuit politics of Republican Rome in a series of articles.199 Following Polybios, he
argued that there were obvious democratic elements in ancient
Rome, thereby reintroducing the populus Romanus in discussions of power, deining it as the sovereign body of the Roman
political system.200 He too argued that scholars had put too much
emphasis on amicitia and clientela, the inluence of which could
196
197
198
199
200
pp. 6–7 for the risks of a “cynical” view inherent in prosopography. Cf.
Alexander 2007, p. 102.
See Syme 1939, pp. 7–8; for “a screen and a sham,” see p. 15.
Meier 1966. See also Bleicken 1981.
See for instance Craig 2002; and Alexander 2007, p. 103.
See Millar 1984, 1986, 1989, and 1995. See also Millar 1998.
Millar 1998, p. 4. On democracy in Rome, besides Millar, see in particular
Lintott 1987; North 1990a, 1990b; Jehne (ed.) 1995; and in that volume,
Flaig 1995; and Hölkeskamp 1995; Mouritsen 2001; Morstein-Marx 2004;
and for the most fervent critique of Millar’s view, now Hölkeskamp 2010.
Roman Political Culture
85
not, at the very least he held, be proven. Both these shifts were
followed by intense debate.201 The traditional way of seeing politics was dubbed a “frozen waste theory” by John North.202 KarlJoachim Hölkeskamp, however, maintained that much of this
was in reality ground that had already been covered.203 Millar’s
claims risked putting a new scholarly “orthodoxy” in the place
of the one he criticized, argued Hölkeskamp.204 While it is true
that Millar might have gone too far, the prevailing perspective he
sought to undo could likewise be accused of being extreme in its
rigidity.205 More importantly, he helped invigorate classical scholarship. For the present study the question of whether Rome was
democratic or not is beside the point, but Millar and Brunt both
challenged the view that politics was determined independently
of the voting public. This in itself is of signiicance.
Voices called for a middle ground. Alexander Yakobson held
that surely it was meaningful to venture further than a simple
dichotomy between oligarchy and democracy.206 Michael Alexander also pointed out the needless extremes and hoped that a
consensus would emerge that acknowledged the importance of
oratory in shaping public opinion, while still recognizing that
“public opinion was decisive, and could be shaped only within
limits set by the people.”207
201 For an overview, see Jehne 2006, pp. 14–23.
202 North 1990b, p. 278: “Its implication was that voting behavior in the assemblies could be regarded as completely divorced from the opinions, interests, and prejudices of the voters themselves.” Contra: Harris 1990, p. 291;
Hölkeskamp 1993, p.17, n. 12; 2004, p. 16, n. 21. Morstein-Marx, however,
is more positive to North’s view. See Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 6; and furthermore, p. 32, n. 115.
203 Most signiicantly by Meier 1966. See Hölkeskamp 1993, p. 15.
204 Hölkeskamp 2004, p. 16.
205 For this, see Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 6.
206 Yakobson 1999, p. 231.
207 Alexander 2007, p. 101.
86
making enemies
Several scholars also argued for such an interpretation.
Hölkeskamp maintained that there existed a political hierarchy
in Rome that was based on a meritocratic consensus.208 But this
competitive elite, albeit one still relying on factions, also depended on culturally symbolic “capital” to maintain their social
supremacy.209 Egon Flaig argued for a ritualistic culture in which
the assemblies produced consensus rather than decisions.210 In
his study of mass oratory, Robert Morstein-Marx arrived at a
similar conclusion. There existed an elite hegemony over Roman
politics and the public discourse was paternalistic and unequal.
But he also stresses the competitive aspect of public speech, as
all politicians were forced to try and win the favor of the voters.
Even though others contested this, such a perspective effectively
put oratory back in the game.211
The discussion about where power was situated in Republican
Rome begs the question of how to deine both elite and people. To
be sure, Rome was timocratic and divided its citizens into property
classes.212 For anyone lacking inancial status, the stage of public
affairs was eficiently closed off. Likewise, the voting public was
208 Hölkeskamp 2004, p. 113: “Ihre Identität als ‘Meritokratie’ wurde durch
ein reiches Repertoire von Ritualen und sonstigen symbolischen Formen
der (Selbst-)Repräsentation reproduziert und geradezu immer neu konstruirt, die der Sichtbarmachung und damit dem Einsatz des kulturspeziischen
‘symbolischen Kapitals’ als ‘Kredit’ dienten.” (“Their identity as ‘meritocracy’ was, through a series of rituals and speciic symbolic forms of (self-)
representation, reproduced and therefore always constructed anew, where
the visualization and input of culturally-speciic ‘symbolic capital’ served as
‘credit’.”)
209 Hölkeskamp argues for the formation of this competitive elite in Hölkeskamp
1993, p. 37. See also Hölkeskamp 2004, p. 74.
210 Flaig 1995, 2003.
211 For an opposing view, see Mouritsen 2002 who argues for limited political
participation. See for instance Mouritsen 2002, p. 128; for the political role
of oratory, see for instance pp. 54–55.
212 For this, see for instance Nicolet 1980.
Roman Political Culture
87
always a minority in Rome.213 In that sense, the elite constituted a
small segment of a minority of the people living under their rule.
Christian Meier has offered an enduring deinition of the elite by
proposing that “Wer Politik trieb, gehörte zum Adel, und wer zum
Adel gehörte, trieb Politik.”214 Politics, meaning the management
of the res publica by individuals through magistracies or the Senate, was the exclusive, and excluding, venue of the elite. This
political elite also sat in juries, held religious ofice, and acted as
patrons to those further down in the system. Clearly, democratic
tendencies were few at best. But there is another way of interpreting the relationship between elite and people, one in which the
Roman people were in fact given an important political role. For
this perspective, the key was political competition.
Aristocratic Competition
In the aftermath of scholarly battles over democracy and oligarchy a new perspective gained traction where Roman political
culture was seen as characterized by aristocratic competition.215
To be sure, the competitive nature of Roman politics had long been
acknowledged in classical studies of the Republic.216 The intense
rivalry was described by Polybios as a special characteristic of
213 Nicolet 1980, p. 3.
214 Meier 1966, p. 47. (“Whoever dealt with politics was part of the aristocracy,
and whoever was part of the aristocracy dealt in politics.”) Though criticized
by Millar 1998, p. 4 as circular.
215 For valuable general discussions on aristocratic competition, see Wiseman
(ed.) 1985; Beard and Crawford 1985; Hölkeskamp 1987, 1993, 2004; Harris 1990; North 1990b; Rosenstein 1990a, 1990b, 1993, 2006; Williamson
1990; Flaig 2003. See also Yakobson 1999.
216 Rosenstein 1990, p. 255 gives credit to Syme and The Roman Revolution.
See Syme 1939, p. 12: “The competition was ierce and incessant.”
88
making enemies
Rome and thus had a long tradition.217 Nevertheless, the idea of
aristocratic competition as an explanatory principle for Roman
political culture has during the last decades nevertheless replaced
the predominance of cooperation between blocks, parties, families, or factions and in its stead put an individualistic approach to
the nature of Roman politics.218 As a consequence, more power
has been awarded to the people as it was to them the ambitious
politician had to turn in order to be elected.219
Aristocratic competition meant that the individual member
of the elite was engaged in constant rivalry with his peers over
the ofices of the cursus honorum. The magistracies were coveted
because they allowed a politician to carry out public acts that
bestowed glory on the Republic and therefore on him. The conditions were naturally adversarial and the competition continuously grew as the stakes rose with election to each ofice. Every
step on the magisterial ladder allowed fewer winners each year.
For instance, from a body of eight praetors there could only be
two consuls elected annually and the inal step, the censorship,
was only available every ive years.
The motivation for the individual politician was esteem and
subsequently inclusion into the highest ranks of society. The signif217 Polyb. 6.52.
218 The main doubt that can be formulated about the inluence of aristocratic
competition is arguably based on the fasti, the nominal lines of consulship,
which, it has been argued, at least in the middle Republic, contained only a
small number of families, thereby strengthening the view of a closed oligarchial political culture. Study of the fasti, however, also indicates that there
was no guarantee for an aristocrat to gain the highest ofice and that a considerable portion of members of consular families failed to do so. For this,
see particularly Hopkins and Burton 1983. The authors also argue that the
competition was probably iercer on the lower levels of the cursus honorum.
Cf. Lintott 1993, p. 167. See also Badian 1990.
219 Beard & Crawford, p. 5. For the reciprocal relationship of the elite and
populus, see also Gleason 1995, p. xxi.
Roman Political Culture
89
icance placed on personal achievement by the members of the upper strata in Roman society can be attested by inscriptions as early
as the third century onwards.220 Another impetus was to sustain
the status of the individual’s family, which depended on the ability
of the younger males to gain access to the higher magistracies and
thereby live up to their successful forefathers.221 The following
chain of reasoning illustrates how competition and rivalry worked
during the Republic. The elite’s aspiration for personal glory and
distinction in the public eye (gloria), a good name and reputation
(fama) in turn rewarding social worth (dignitas) and political authority (auctoritas), forced them to persuade the voting public to
trust them with oficial duties within the state that could offer the
opportunity to help the res publica. Cicero was also aware of this.
There is no one, he declared in his rhetorical treatise De oratore, in
such a famous state as Rome, that does not believe the pursuit of
moral worth (dignitas) to be a fundamental ambition.222 This dignitas, this societal distinction, was conferred by holding ofice, and
by merits and achievements acknowledged by the community.223
The people in turn voted for whoever they thought could be most
useful to Rome, thereby giving populi beneicium or “the people’s
support.”224 The aristocracy competed with a speciic set of aristocratic values of which virtus, courage and manliness, was the most
prominent.225 For Hölkeskamp this is how the political function
of the populus should be understood, as bestowing the honors
220 For examples of early evidence of these values, see Wiseman 1985a, pp.
3–10.
221 Rosenstein 1990, p. 176.
222 De or. 2.334.
223 See De or. 2.347.
224 See De or. 1.194.
225 For virtus, see McDonnell 2006 with bibliography. Also Earl 1961, 1967;
Lind 1992; and Alston 1998. For the concept of vir in Cicero’s speeches, see
especially Santoro L’Hoir 1992, pp. 12–15.
90
making enemies
of high ofice (honores) on the elite for which they raced, thus
legitimizing them as a “political class.”226 The hierarchic system of
prestige embraced by the aristocratic segment of society allotted
real political functions to the Roman people.227 Service to the state
alone, chiely on the battleield, but through inner political actions
as well, rendered esteem (dignitas) in Rome.228 Ancestry, for instance, could be a reason for regard, but only, it seems, insofar as
the forefathers had been of service to Rome.
There is an example, persistent in modern scholarship, of the
values with which the elite competed in an anecdote in Plinius’
Historia Naturalis.229 During the funeral oration for his father in
221 BCE, Quintus Metellus enumerated irst the political ofices
his father had held and then his accomplishments. He had been
an excellent warrior, the best orator, and the bravest general. He
carried out the greatest affairs under his own authority (auspicio
suo) and reached the highest honor and wisdom. He had been
considered the foremost senator of the state. He acquired great
wealth in an honorable way and had been survived by many
children. Last, he had been the most renowned (clarissimum)
citizen of the state.230 Notable is the place given to oratory,
second only to being a irst-rate warrior.
226 Hölkeskamp 2004, p. 82; 2011, p. 30. Cf. Connolly 2007b, p. 96. See also
Yakobson 1992, p. 50.
227 Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 92.
228 See Cic. Rep. 1.2. This point stressed for instance by Meier 1966, p. 46:
“Der Anspruch auf dignitas, das heiβt auf Ehre und gesellschaftliche Geltung
war tief und gründlich auf den Staat bezogen, war nur durch Bewährung
als Staatsmann, Feldherr und Diplomat—und eventuell als Jurist und Priester—zu begründen.” (“The demand for dignitas, that is to say, for honor and
societal worth was deep and fundamentally related to the state, and was
grounded solely on the qualiication of being a politician, commander and
diplomat—and possibly an advocate or priest.”)
229 See for instance Wiseman (ed.) 1985a, pp. 3–4.
230 Plin. HN. 7.139–140.
Roman Political Culture
91
This perspective allows a more reciprocal low of power and
inluence without denying that Roman society was unequal and
controlled to a large extent by the political aristocracy. The elite
were forced to present themselves time and again to the scrutiny
and judgment of the people whose opinion in this sense really
mattered.231 This arguably meant that they subscribed to the deinitions of the aristocracy as regards who was worthy to lead,
but failure to live up to public expectations, not only in terms of
skill or formal qualiications, but also perhaps more importantly,
moral character, spelled failure at the polls and failure to achieve
the esteem needed to be part of the upper echelon of power and
prestige.232 From this perspective, public inluence was fueled by
the competitiveness of the elite.
The stakes of this game added to the competitiveness. The
opportunities for advancement were few and the costs of failure
could be devastating. Financial considerations therefore played
an important part in this, as political campaigning was expensive.
Reaching the top echelon of the political pyramid, on the other
hand, promised ample opportunity for enriching oneself.
The Roman funeral amply illustrates the way in which the elite
strove to manifest their superiority. Political action and its actors
could be experienced by not only members of the elite but also by
ordinary citizens.233 Status in this visual culture relied heavily on
the perception of fellow citizens.234 Spectacle, oratory, and visual
reinforcement became important in projecting status in Republican Rome and an essential factor of the political system.235
231 Yakobson 2006, pp. 386–387.
232 Rosenstein 2006, p. 372.
233 Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 72. Cf. Flaig 2003, p. 146: “Die gerichtlichen Duelle
waren begehrte Spektakel.”
234 Flower 2004, p. 322; Bartsch 2006, p. 117.
235 Flower 2004b, pp. 322–323.
92
making enemies
Through the spectacle, in the form of games, processions, and
rituals, the elite not only reinforced aristocratic values, but also
the shared values of the community. The triumph was no doubt
the most extravagant and therefore powerful example of this.236
The rivalry of the Roman elite was the inherent force that
compelled Rome, lacking government, written constitution, or
salaried ofice-holding, to build roads, markets and temples, acts
which bestowed gloria on the benefactor. But also trivial administrative tasks of everyday public affairs were carried out by the
aspiring aristocrat. In the end, as Nathan Rosenstein compellingly puts it, “the city harnessed individual ambition to meet its
essential needs.”237
Roman Oratory
For the more powerful a man was as a speaker, the more easily
did he obtain ofice, the more decisively superior was he to his colleagues in ofice, the more inluence did he acquire with the leaders
of the state, the more weight in the Senate, the more notoriety and
fame with the people. […] The praetorship and the consulship
seemed to offer themselves to them, and even when they were out
of ofice, they were not out of power, for they swayed both people
and Senate with their counsels and inluence.238
Tacitus, Dialogus de Oratoribus
236 For the Roman triumph, see Beard 2007; Östenberg 2009.
237 Rosenstein 1993, p. 313.
238 Tac. Dial. 36: quia quanto quisque plus dicendo poterat, tanto facilius honores adsequebatur, tanto magis in ipsis honoribus collegas suos anteibat,
tanto plus apud principes gratiae, plus auctoritatis apud patres, plus notitiae
ac nominis apud plebem parabat. [...] hos et praeturae et consulatus vocare
ultro videbantur, hi ne privati quidem sine potestate erant, cum et populum
et senatum consilio et auctoritate regerent.
Roman Political Culture
93
In Republican Rome of the irst century BCE a politician was by
deinition an orator.239 Oratory in turn deined the aristocracy.240
For the study of Cicero’s political use of immorality in his speeches, it is important to emphasize that the nature of the political
culture was inevitably integrated with oratorical performance
and, consequently, so was the competition of the aristocracy.
Whereas traditional scholarship for a long time viewed oratory
as having little bearing on Roman politics, modern scholarship
now recognizes it as perhaps the main political act in Roman
political culture.241 The career of an individual was tied to his
success as an orator. Political power, to a large extent, came from
oratory.
The orator was a deep-rooted powerful igure in Roman cultural consciousness, a bulwark against tyranny and a protector of
the Republic.242 Cicero identiied Brutus, the man who according
to legend had put Rome on its Republican path by throwing out
the last king in the sixth century, as the irst Roman orator, an
honor which tells us something about how politics and oratory
were viewed in ancient Rome.243
Oratory at Rome was also, in the fullest sense of the word,
political action. The chief arena for this political action was the
Forum.244 But the central stages acknowledged by the political
239 On Roman oratory in general, see e.g. Leeman 1963; Steel 2001, 2006; May
(ed.) 2002 with Craig 2002; Habinek 2005; Connolly 2007a. For different
aspects of oratory and politics in the Roman late Republic, see also the edited volumes of May (ed.) 2002; Powell & Paterson (eds.) 2004; Dominik
& Hall (eds.) 2007; Berry & Erskine (eds.) 2010; and now Steel & van der
Blom (eds.) 2013.
240 David 2006, pp. 421–422.
241 See e.g. Millar 1998; Jehne 2000; Fantham 2004; Morstein-Marx 2004;
Dugan 2005; Steel 2006; Alexander 2007.
242 Dugan 2009, p. 179.
243 Brut. 53.
244 May 2002b, p. 53.
94
making enemies
culture were all invariably oratorical in nature. Whether in front
of a jury at a trial, the people at a contio, or on the Senate loor,
the premier platform for politics in the Roman Republic was the
speaker’s platform. Decisions were taken, verdicts were given,
and laws were passed as result of individual efforts of oratory.245
As there were no dogmatic religious texts, no comprehensive
book of law, and no written constitution, decisive action was to
a large degree dependent on choosing the way suggested or the
interpretation argued in public speeches. Public discourse hence
carried tremendous force.
Public discourse in Rome was controlled by the elite. The opportunity to speak in front of the populus was be deinition an
elite prerogative. But the aristocratic code of behavior—the basis
for their supremacy and the yardstick of excellence—projected
by oratory, was only powerful insofar as the larger community
shared those values and accepted the merits.246 This meant that
certain boundaries were ixed for the orator. He had to appeal
to common cultural values. “Political life,” Harriet Flower has
noted, “consisted of involvement with this community of shared
concerns and values.”247 The power of a speech depended on its
ability to resonate with the beliefs and values of its audience.248
The success and failure of an orator was related to his ability to
tap into the convictions and prejudices of his audience, the voters,
jury members, and senators.
245 Dugan 2009, p. 178.
246 Cf. Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 70.
247 Flower 2004, p. 2. Also Dugan 2009, p. 180: “The identity of the orator is
part of a larger imagined community that he constructs in his speech, a res
publica […], to whose nature and values Roman oratory repeatedly returns.”
Cf. Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 14.
248 See Vasaly 1993, pp. 245–246; Corbeill 1996, p. 5; Riggsby 1999, p. 19; and
Williams 2010, p. 20. Also Koster 1980, p. 39; and Uría 2006, p. 60. Cf.
Jackob 2007, p. 297. Cf. however Morstein-Marx 2004, pp. 17–18.
Roman Political Culture
95
Oratory and rivalry also went hand in hand. The competitive
culture of Rome routinely pitted individuals against each other
in the various arenas that existed.249 Conlict was an inherent
part of Roman oratory in the race for prestige. This polemical
quality could take different forms. As part of the prosecution at
a trial you were expected to attack the defendant but you were
also in natural oppositions to the side of the defense. When defending a client, a strong offense could often be a good defense.
On the Senate loor, opposing views could easily come to verbal
blows, and a way to make a name for yourself before the Roman
people was by verbally attacking another member of the aristocracy. Success as an orator was for these reasons tied to verbal
attack.250 Direct personal verbal aggression thus seems built into
the Roman political culture of the late Republic.251
We know very little of Roman oratory in the early and middle
Republic.252 David argues that the earliest orators were characterized by brevity and gravitas, i.e. a serious and stern quality.253
Their power of oratory was founded in ethos, in ancestry, ofices
held, and military achievements, and while such aspects continued to be crucial to Roman political culture, in the middle of
the second century BCE a simple stating of merits was confronted
by a more elaborate type of oratory infused by Greek discipline.
David argues that in order to be successful, the orator could no
249 Rosenstein 1990, p. 49; Gleason 1995, p. 159.
250 Arena 2007, p. 150.
251 May 1988, p. 13: “Cicero seems at times to have made it his primary concern
and chief rhetorical aim to disarm his adversary’s authoritative character.”
See also Richlin 1992, p. 13: “character assassination was one of the primary
goals of any orator on the offensive.”; and Edwards 1993, p. 11: “This kind
of abuse was a major element in the arsenal employed in the agonistic rituals
of Roman political life.”
252 For early Roman oratory, see Sciarrino 2007.
253 David 2006, p. 428.
96
making enemies
longer simply rely on a good record of accomplishments or the
name of his family, but had to “prevail in rhetorical duels.”254 For
the young Cicero to be able to compete in the arenas of Roman
political culture, he had to learn the rules of rhetoric.
Rhetoric at Rome
In the ancient world, rhetoric, the art of persuasion, was believed
to be of fundamental importance.255 It played a vital role in shaping the societies of the Mediterranean world, inluencing culture
and knowledge.256 Rhetoric was seen as a prerequisite skill of
every Greek and Roman politician, but also something that could
be approached from a philosophical standpoint.257 It had two
sides, one practical, and the other intellectual, and meant more
than just speaking well; it was part of the moral upbringing and
identity of the governing classes.258
Rhetoric could be classiied and systematized.259 General argu254 David 2006, p. 422.
255 The term rhetoric is routinely used to denote both the theory behind oratory,
persuasion, or eloquence, and the rhetorical action itself and its content. In
this study I will refer to the abstract theoretical perspective on oratory as
rhetoric and the practice as oratory. For deinitions of rhetoric and oratory,
see Connolly 2007a, p. 2: “Rhetoric arises from the practice of oratory”; and
Habinek 2005, p. vi; Gunderson 2009, p. 3. This approach deines rhetoric
primarily as a system for classifying and organizing persuasive discourse. Cf.
Steel 2009, p. 77.
256 For the various roles played by rhetoric and oratory in Rome, see Habinek
1998; Poulakos (ed.) 1993; May 2002b; Gunderson 2009.
257 De or. 1.128.
258 David 2002, p. 422: “Rhetoric was as much an art of aristocratic behavior
and of the ethos of leadership as it was an art of speaking.” See also Gunderson 2003, p. 5; and 2009, p. 110. For the education of the Roman elite,
see Corbeill 2001, 2002; Connolly 2009. For intellectual life during the late
Republic in general, consult Rawson 1985.
259 Such an approach in itself was a way of claiming authority and receiving
credibility. See Steel 2009, p. 78.
Roman Political Culture
97
ments and topics were readily available.260 Competing classiications asserted their superior way to the same fundamental goal
based on the idea that following the rules guaranteed oratorical,
and therefore political, success. Recognizing a formal rhetorical
framework, as argued by Ann Vasaly, is however “not an end but
a beginning.”261 With that in mind, we shall address the question
of how oratory in Cicero’s day was supposed to work. This section will conclude with a particularly neglected area within the
study of rhetoric—the emphasis placed by the ancient rhetorical
handbooks on character and morality in oratory.
The Development of Roman Rhetoric
When Cicero received his education, Roman rhetoric had evolved
through a deep-rooted interaction with a larger intellectual milieu.262 Oratory, even though a distinctive trait of Roman society,
was heavily inluenced by Greek practice and theory.263 Rhetoric
was a contested ield. The Greeks, as one scholar has suggested,
were almost obsessed, with “the phenomenon of persuasive
language.”264 In the early development of rhetoric, the Peripatetic
and Stoic schools alongside the Attic orator Isocrates were inluential. Both Platon and Aristoteles became, alongside their followers, important authorities on the art of persuasion. They differed
260 For topoi, consult Cicero’s Topica.
261 Vasaly 1993, p. 5.
262 This means that examples of Roman behavior, attitudes, and aspects of political culture can often be found and analyzed within a Greek context. For a
particularly illustrative example of the link as regard character, see Tempest
2007; and now Tempest 2011. See also Worman 2008.
263 For detailed accounts of the development of Greek and Roman rhetoric,
see Corbeill 2002a, pp. 23–48; Culpepper Stroup 2007. Also see De oratore
(book 3) and Brutus.
264 Kirby 1997, p. 13.
98
making enemies
however on how to view it. Platon even denied that rhetoric was
an art at all and questioned the moral aspects of persuasion in his
work Gorgias.265 Aristoteles, inluenced but not deterred by his
master’s misgivings, devised, in his more logical manner, a classiication of rhetoric with a tripartite system of ethos, pathos, and
logos, the three pisteis, or sources of persuasion.266
By the last century BCE, Latin manuals were also being written and published on the subject of rhetoric. Two of them survive.267 The irst is De inventione, written by the young Cicero.
The second is the anonymous treatise Rhetorica ad Herennium,
written in the early irst century BCE. Both authors drew heavily
on the Greek tradition in general.268
As shown, the nature of rhetoric could itself be deined in various ways during antiquity. In Ad Herennium, the art (ars) of rhetoric is described as that which provides a ixed and systematic
approach to speaking.269 Cicero, in the opening of his De inventione, allows that “this thing we call eloquence” can be seen as an
art, but also a skill and a gift of nature.270 More importantly, he
sees oratorical ability as part of political knowledge.271
265 He later revised some of his critique in the Phaedrus.
266 On the inluence of the Aristotelian tradition, see Solmsen 1941.
267 The others we know of are De ratione dicendi, probably by M. Antonius and
De gestu by L. Plotius Gallus.
268 And the systemization of Hermagoras of Temnos in particular. Most important in this regard was the division of rhetoric into ive parts, where
inventio, or the “inventing” of the arguments for the speech, was particularly
emphasized. The theory of stasis found in the work of Hermagoras also
had profound inluence. From Theophrastus, Cicero and the author of Ad
Herennium also adopted the four virtues of style: correctness in the language (Hellenismus, latinitas) clarity (perspicitias), ornament (ornatus), and
appropriateness (aptum). See Kirby 1997, p. 14; Corbeill 2002a, pp. 29–31.
269 Rhet. Her. 1.3: Ars est praeceptio, quae dat certam viam rationemque
dicendi. Cf. De or. 2.32.
270 Inv. rhet. 1.2.
271 Inv. rhet. 1.6.
Roman Political Culture
99
Rhetorical Divisions
There is unfortunately no way to summarize any complete “ancient rhetorical theory,” although one might sometimes be led to
believe this is the case.272 There were competing views on how
the art of rhetoric could be structured. The following remains, of
necessity, a basic outline.273
Greeks and Romans seemed to agree that there were basically
three types, or genres, of speeches.274 The three genres were concerned respectively with legal matters, with (political) deliberation, and with demonstration and were known as genus iudiciale,
genus deliberativum, and the genus demonstrativum (more often
referred to as epideictic oratory).275
Judicial, or, forensic, oratory, typically took place in the agora
or Forum (hence the modern name) and meant speaking either
as a prosecutor or as a part of the defense. Rhetoric in ancient
society was much concerned with this arena and consequently
the handbooks are unevenly tilted toward this genre. The treatises guided the pupil in preparing for the various situations of
the judicial courts.
The second type of speech was the deliberative speech. Of the
three genres, this was the most obviously political in nature, the
272 A modern attempt is Lausberg 1998. Standard accounts of the system of
ancient rhetoric include Kennedy 1972 and 1994; Clarke 1996; and May &
Wisse 2001, pp. 26–38. See also Vickers 1998.
273 This summary primarily follows the handbooks that have survived from the
late Republic, De inventione and Ad Herennium.
274 The basic classiication of rhetorical material fell into general (theses) and
speciic (hypotheses) questions. The three genres existed under the latter. The
irst surviving work to utilize such a division was Aristoteles’ Rhetoric. For
types of oratory, see Hesk 2009.
275 See Dugan 2005, p. 25 who calls this triad “inherently unstable.”
100
making enemies
main purpose of which was to recommend a course of action.276
Its natural locus was the Senate loor, the public assembly, or any
such similar deliberative body. But the orator was also recommended to build up his speech as if it was a forensic speech, and
the two genres accordingly blended together.
The third genre, epideictic oratory, was considered a type of
ceremonial or show speech where the skill of the speaker could be
evaluated.277 It included a subdivision of praise (laus) and blame
or censure (vituperatio). The elusive category receives very little
attention in the handbooks and has been seen as having almost
no existence independent of the other genres.278 Instead it was
mostly recommended as a type of exercise or training, as there
were very few applications for it in political life.279 The Roman
handbooks allowed for praise or censure to be inserted when useful into deliberative or forensic speeches, thus blurring the lines
between the genres even further.280
While the genre of speech was often decided by external
276 It was subdivided depending on the possible outcome of the deliberations
and its aim was utility, as well as justice, honor and their opposites.
277 Hesk 2009, p. 145
278 In Cicero’s De oratore, his interlocutor Antonius dismisses it as a third category of speech, next to forensic and deliberative. De or. 2.43–51. See also
Clarke, p. 24; and Kennedy 1972, p. 21: “Greek epideictic or demonstrative
oratory was largely nonexistent in the Roman republic, and the only native
Roman form of signiicance was the funeral eulogy, laudatio funebris.”
279 Rhet. Her. 3.15. Furthermore, in Cicero’s last rhetorical work, Orator, he
opts not to include epideictic oratory in his treatment of the several kinds
of speeches, because they do not concern the political contest of the Forum.
Orat. 37. The foremost example of the genres practical use was the laudatio
funebris, or funeral oration, a privilege of the elite to honor the life of their
deceased members. Cf. the Greek epitaphios logos. See also Hesk 2009, p.
158: “We should not view these funeral speeches as artless or formulaic propaganda.” Now see Covino 2011.
280 Dugan 2005, p. 29:“Although epideictic can afford the young orator valuable preparation for real oratorical combat, its goal is delight and not
conlict.”
Roman Political Culture
101
circumstances, the construction or rather conceiving of the
speech was up to the orator. Both Cicero and his contemporary,
the author of the Ad Herennium, favored the division of rhetoric into ive elements. These included: inventio, meaning the
invention of that which would make up the speech; dispositio,
the arranging of said subject matter in the speech; elocutio, the
style to use; memoria, memorizing the speech, and inally actio
(or pronuntiatio), the oratorical performance itself. These ive
elements constituted the orator’s duties or oficia oratoris.281 He
should irst ind what should be said, in what order it should be
said, and in what style.
As for the division of the inished speech, there were ideally six
parts.282 The opening was called the exordium and was followed
by the narratio where the speaker stated the facts of the issue at
hand. The divisio (or partitio) revolved around what the issue
was and what was meant to be argued for. The fourth and ifth
parts together constituted the argumentation and were known
as conirmatio and confutatio. They dealt with arguing for the
orator’s own case and refuting the arguments of the other side.
The conclusio, or peroration, summed up and strove to appeal to
the indignation and pity of the listeners.
This then was the structure of an ideal speech. But as Vasaly
has noted: the surviving handbooks of rhetoric “seem far removed from the stimulating world of ancient praxis.”283 Success
depended on more than knowing the topoi.284 Gunderson argues
281 Not all authorities agreed on this quinquepartite division and some did not
include the more practical aspects of memory and delivery. See Clarke, p. 24.
In the two surviving handbooks, inventio and elucutio make up the lion’s
share of the text.
282 In De inventione and Ad Herennium.
283 Vasaly 1993, p. 3. Cf. Riggsby 2004, p. 172.
284 Vasaly 1993, pp. 252–253.
102
making enemies
in the same vein that the rhetorical handbooks should be seen not
as umpires but as players on the ield.285 The ancient rhetorical
framework can thus be reduced to a system irst proven to be
effective by oratory.286
The rhetorical handbooks, however, did not only debate structure but also subject matter. Next, therefore, we will look for
the place immorality and character attack had within these ideal
systems.
Vituperatio
Within the three genres of speech, the kind of attacks that Cicero
made on Antonius in the Senate in 43 BCE were at irst glance
located in the epideictic, or demonstrative genre concerned with
praise or blame. Attack on a person is there known as vituperatio.287 The handbook Ad Herennium treats praise, laus, and censure, vituperatio, as natural opposites. Everything used in praise
of a person, his virtues, actions, and background, could also, if
required, be turned on its head.288
Praise and censure can be adduced from three areas according to
the anonymous author: external aspects, physical attributes, and
“character” (animus). Examples of external aspects are descent,
education, wealth, political power, fame, citizenship, and bonds
of friendship, while under physical attributes the orator can attack defects in strength or beauty. Animus is divided into pruden285 Gunderson 2009, pp. 8, 11.
286 See Heath 2009, p. 72.
287 Often this has been translated as invective or abuse. However, Quintilianus
claims that only three of Cicero’s senatorial speeches contained vituperatio.
Quint. Inst. 3.7.2. For vituperatio and the epideictic genre, see also Part. or.
69–97. For the topoi of panegyric, see Arist. Rhet. 1.9.
288 Rhet. Her. 3.11. Also De or. 2.46. See Dugan 2005, p. 30: “invective may be
seen as a carnivalesque, parodic, inversion of praise.”
Roman Political Culture
103
tia, iustitia, fortitudo, and modestia, i.e. wisdom, justice, courage,
and temperance. Hence if the speech is vituperative, the character
should be deined as unjust, cowardly, immodest, or stupid.289
It is noteworthy that the speaker should explain why he is
using vituperatio. Three reasons are given: the attack is justiied
because of the way the orator himself has been treated; because
of the common good of censuring bad behavior; or, inally, because it is pleasing to show that which is considered desirable
behavior through the censure of others.290
To ixate vituperatio solely within the epideictic genre, however, soon turns out to be problematic.291 Cicero’s attack on
Antonius was not a “show speech.”292 It was political in nature.
Vituperatio was, in other words, not just an exercise. Both handbooks stress that attack, or censure, can have a wide range of
uses in oratory. In the Ad Herennium, the author cautions the
student of rhetoric not to neglect the subject since large parts of
judicial and deliberative circumstances are often concerned with
both laus and vituperatio.293 Instead of dealing with the details of
attack under the epideictic genre, Cicero refers to his discussion
under legal speeches. Discussion of vituperatio, it turns out, is not
the only aspect of character in Roman rhetoric. A wider search
arc is gained by looking at the importance of character in the
289 Rhet. Her. 3.15.
290 Rhet. Her. 3.11: Si vituperabimus: aut merito facere, quod ita tractate simus;
aut studio, quod utile putemus esse ab omnibus unicam malitiam atque nequitiam cognosci; aut quod placeat ostendi quod nobis placeat ex aliorum
vituperatione.
291 See also Novokhatko 2009, p. 13.
292 Cicero discusses the genre also in Partitiones oratoriae, where it is clear that
the idea of the epideictic speech is to give audience pleasure and enjoyment
and therefore carries with it particular considerations of style etc. See Part.
or. 71–73. Cf. also Batstone 1994, pp. 218–221.
293 Rhet. Her. 3.15. See also De or. 2.349.
104
making enemies
rhetorical handbooks. In fact, it has been suggested that the importance of character in Roman oratory bridges the gap between
formal divisions of rhetoric.294
Character in Roman Rhetorical Theory
The topic of character attack can be found in the Ad Herennium
as a vital part of the opening, or exordium of a speech. Attack,
the author states, can create goodwill for the speaker:
Ab adversariorum persona benivolentia captabitur si eos in odium,
in invidiam, in contemptionem adducemus.295
We will capture goodwill from the character of our adversaries by
bringing them into hate, ill-will, or contempt.
To adduce hatred (odium), the author states, impure, arrogant,
treacherous, cruel, impudent, malicious, or shameful acts should
be used.296 Ill-will (invidia) is produced by describing unjust political behavior and corruption, such as violence and misuse of
power, political alliances and foul play, use of wealth or social
standing above truth. Contempt (contemptio) inally is achieved
by showing the inertia, ignavia, desidia, and luxuria of the targets—their laziness, idleness, sloth, and excessive living.
More references to character are found scattered across the
294 Riggsby 2004, p. 182.
295 Rhet. Her. 1.8. Cf. Inv. rhet. 1.22: ab adversariorum autem, si eos aut in
odium aut in invidiam aut in contemptionem adducemus. The similarity is
often explained by the fact that both authors drew heavily on Hermagoras
of Temnos.
296 Rhet. Her. 1.8: Spurce, superbe, peridiose, crudeliter, conidenter, malitiose,
lagitiose. Cf. Inv. rhet. 1.22.
Roman Political Culture
105
handbooks and in regard to other aspects of rhetoric. The narratio can also be dealt with from the position of character.297 As
part of the narration the orator can go outside the relevance of
a legal case in order to accuse a person. Another aspect is that,
if the defendant pleas for pardon, it is important that his wrongdoing does not appear to stem from fault of character.298 If the
plea is for mercy, past good deeds should be weighed against bad
ones, and virtue and good birth should be brought up.299
The subject of character is discussed at greater length in De
inventione as regard conirmatio, i.e. arguments for the case of
the orator. All arguments of proof, Cicero holds, are supported
by the attributes of either persons or actions. The attributes for
persons are nomen (name), natura (nature), victus (life), fortuna
(fortune), habitus (moral quality or character), affectio (disposition), studia (interests or pursuits), consilia (purpose), facta (acts),
casus (errors, accidents), and orationes.300 Nature, for instance, is
then divided by male and female and by race, origin, family, and
age.301 Life concerns upbringing and education, friends, occupation, and domestic circumstances. Fortune deals with whether a
person is rich or poor and also success, fame, and the like. Habitus is a quality of mind or body that is acquired not by nature,
while affectio is a temporary change in mind or body.302 Acts,
accidents, and orations Cicero explains by posing the questions:
what did someone do, what happened to someone, and what did
someone say?
In legal cases then, these attributes should be pursued in order
297
298
299
300
301
302
Rhet. Her. 1.13; Inv. rhet. 1.27.
Rhet. Her. 2.24.
Rhet. Her. 2.25.
Inv. rhet. 1.34.
Inv. rhet. 1.35.
Inv. rhet. 1.36.
106
making enemies
to make a compelling case.303 Personal qualities and the behavior
of the individual become vital parts of the orator’s arguments.
Suspicion can be raised from the nature of the defendant or by
his way of life, and a person’s fortune can hint at his guilt or innocence. It is the task of the prosecutor to select arguments from
these attributes and use them to discredit the defendant.304
Conversely, Cicero maintains that if the orator cannot show
evidence in the past life of the defendant, he will instead argue
that the accused had now been exposed and the act should therefore not be judged in view of his past, but his past should be
disgraced by the act.305 The duty of the defense is the opposite,
to show that the accused has led an honorable life. This included general aspects such as how he has treated his parents or his
friends or if he has performed some service to the state. He should
also show that he has never committed any wrong or been guided
by his passions.306
The use of character argument—to create goodwill or to adduce
evidence—was approached systematically in the extant handbooks. The list of possibilities was exhaustive. The effectiveness of
character as argument was however not only up to the orator; the
value of such an approach depended on the importance ascribed
to morality in Roman society in general.
Roman Morality
Tied to both the competition among the elite and the prominence
of oratory was the place of morality at the very center of public
life in Roman society. The Romans considered themselves moral303
304
305
306
Inv. rhet. 2.28, 42.
Inv. rhet. 2.32.
Inv. rhet. 2.34.
Inv. rhet. 2.35–36.
Roman Political Culture
107
ly superior to other people and their morality was the basis for
their relationship with the gods and therefore their military success.307 Of all the peoples in the world, Plinius wrote, the Romans
were indubitably the most outstanding in terms of virtus.308 This
entailed not only courage or bravery but also moral excellence.
Morality, as Catherine Steel has observed, rather than administration, was seen as the key to ruling an empire.309
Politics at Rome was not viewed as a separate autonomous
sphere but rather as part of a larger fabric.310 The Romans’ obsession with morality therefore had far reaching implications for the
political culture. Moral authority was political authority.311 The
Senate owed much of its power to its role as a moral guardian of
“the Roman system of values and norms.”312 As discussed earlier,
aristocratic values formed the basis for a public igure’s chances
of success at the polls and subsequently his rise within the social
hierarchy. When Cicero began his climb within its ranks, the elite
had over the course of generations developed and upheld a system
of values that was “ideologically coherent,” but of course also
excluding.313 The status of the elite was dependent on a number
of things: origin and family, political and military careers, and
oratorical skill. But it was also connected to morality.
The status or auctoritas of an individual orator counted for
much in this political culture.314 In the courts, authority could
count for more than formal points at issue.315 In the Senate, the
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
Edwards 1993, p. 21.
Plin. NH. 7.130. See also Cic. Rep. 5.1.
Steel 2001, p. 4.
Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 9; Barton 2001, p. 3.
Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 12.
Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 29.
Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 89.
Dugan 2005, p. 3. See Cic. Top. 73.
Dugan 2009, p. 179; Connelly 2007, p. 64.
108
making enemies
auctoritas of the speaker could decide the value and inluence of
his words. In his study of why defeated generals did not suffer at
the polls as a result of their defeat, Nathan Rosenstein stresses
the moral worth of a politician as the key aspect of their electability in the eyes of the public.316 An aristocratic ethos deined
the elite and legitimized their societal position. To Rosenstein
the needs of the political system “demanded a myth of universal
aristocratic competence.”317 But this myth depended on the moral
superiority of the elite. Displaying a moral character to the voters
was something that could be evaluated far more easily than speciic competence in regard to the varying tasks of the Roman magistrate and became crucial in order to win and to get the coveted
chance to serve the state.318 Other scholars have argued that in
the visual political culture of Rome, morality was something that
could be read by an audience.319 A politician’s morality, in other
words, was on display at the Forum, the curia, and at the trials.
Decorum, as a moral concept, meant not only to be it, but to be
seen as it in the public eye.320 In order to succeed in public life
a man needed to project a moral character.321 It was therefore a
source of comparison between Roman members of the elite.322
Moral worth determined who was most suitable.323
Even if these ideals were in some sense favored by the aristocracy and at the very least allowed them to legitimize their posi-
316
317
318
319
320
Rosenstein 1990, p. 114. Cf. Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 265.
Rosenstein 1990, p. 172.
Rosenstein 1990, p. 175.
Corbeill 2004, p. 109; 2006, p. 439; Langlands 2006, p. 285.
Cic. Top. 78. See also Grifin & Atkins 1991, p. xlvi. Cf. Williams 2010, p.
18.
321 May 2002a, p. 7.
322 The Roman writers are uninterested in the moral behavior of the lower classes. See Edwards 1993, p. 24.
323 Rosenstein 1990, p. 7.
Roman Political Culture
109
tion in society, they were nevertheless accepted by the extended
community. This “moral economy” depended on the elite’s ability,
on the surface at least, to live up to the standards they themselves
had set and therefore also on their ability to police its boundaries.324 Deviation from norms of the elite thus becomes a threat
to the group and one way of understanding the harsh personal
attacks directed at fellow members of the political aristocracy
is to see them as a way of self-policing. On this, Rosenstein has
argued that “charges of degeneracy and corruption also need to
be understood as important tools for enforcing a code of social
norms that empowered those who controlled them.”325 If the elite
ruled by merit of their moral superiority, that supremacy had to
be guarded within the elite.326 One way of doing this was attacks
on immorality.327
Additional testimony to this Roman emphasis on moral
character can be adduced from Cicero’s later work on rhetoric,
De oratore. The same eloquence, Cicero’s spokesperson Antonius
holds, is used to destroy the wrongful and save the righteous.
He asks his ictional audience:
Quis cohortari ad virtutem ardentius, quis a vitiis acrius revocare?
Quis vituperare improbos asperius, quis laudare bonos ornatius?
Quis cupiditatem vehementius frangere accusando potest?328
324 For this view, see for instance Corbeill 2002b, p. 199; Ruffell 2003, p. 47.
Also Connolly 2007a, p. 3. For moral economy, see Rosenstein 2006, p. 373.
325 Rosenstein 2006, p. 374. Cf. Walters 1998, p. 358.
326 For an example of this view in Cicero, see Mil. 42.
327 Edwards 1993, p. 4. See also Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 11; and Habinek
1998, p. 54: “[T]he praise or blame of a Roman aristocrat has ramiications
chiely for his status within the larger community and with respect to potential rivals for the approval of that community.”
328 De or. 2.35. Cf. Part. or. 69–70.
110
making enemies
Who can more passionately incite to virtue, who more ardently
recall from vice? Who can reproach the immoral more severely,
who can praise the good more lavishly? Who can more vehemently
subdue lustful behavior with his accusations?
The relevance of character is thus not only in abuse nor even
as proof in criminal cases. The orator becomes a guardian of
the community with eloquence as his weapon.329 Deviance must
be identiied and punished, good behavior ornamentally commended. The upper order, from this perspective, constrains its
members through moral censure, thereby ensuring a common
morality which in turn justiies their privileged place as the
governors of society.
This attitude can furthermore be found in a couple of Cicero’s
philosophical works. In De re publica there is an arresting passage which seems to deal with a political function of public defamation (vituperatio) and as a deterrent from unjust behavior.330
The passage states that the politician should use his oratorical
skills as well as public opinion in order to repel criminal and evil
actions through the use of shame and dishonor.331 When Cicero
draws up his ideal state in the treatise De legibus, he holds that
the Senate should be a model for the rest of Rome’s citizen and
also goes on to say that if this is accomplished the State is more
or less secured.332 It seems to be Cicero’s view that, since the
329 De or. 1.202, 2.237.
330 It is, like De re publica in general, a fragmented passage, so caution is of
course needed in analyzing it.
331 Rep. 3.4. See also Habinek 2005, p. 6: “In effect, both Greece and Rome are
societies constructed around honor and shame, with public speaking constituting a key means through which the former is accumulated and the latter
(hopefully) avoided.” For shame in Rome, see in particular Barton 2001;
Kaster 2005.
332 Leg. 3.30–32. Cf. Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 9.
Roman Political Culture
111
people imitate the leaders of society, there is an obvious risk that
if the elite fall into bad habits and display a faulty morality, the
rest of society will soon be corrupted along with it. The power of
the good, or in this case bad, example is here amply illustrated.
It shows a top-down perspective that has grave consequences in
the normative view of the orator. Attack on character was a substantial but ideally also a necessary part of the weaponry of the
good Roman orator.
The view that character attacks should be understood as selfpolicing, while appealing, seems to suggest a rational strategy
on the part of the elite and a unity directed toward the lower
segments of society which can, I think, be misleading. Furthermore, it would most likely be dificult to it all of the attacks on
immorality discussed in this book under this heading. Cicero’s attacks on Antonius before the Senate seem to hold other political
motives than a legitimizing of the elite. That said, the perspective
nevertheless has merit as regards the place of morality in the late
Republic.
Because the political culture of Rome was characterized by the
prominent position of oratory, morality and character also took
on great importance in public oratory.333 And because oratory
and power were linked, “discourses of morality in Rome were
profoundly implicated in structures of power.”334 The question of
who had access to power at Rome was also a question of ethos.
333 May 1988, p. 6: “Character was an extraordinarily important element in the
social and political milieu of Republican Rome and exerted a considerable
amount of inluence on native Roman oratory.” Cf. Corbeill 1996, p. 13: “It
was through oratory that the Roman moral codes found constant conirmation.”
334 Edwards, 1993, p. 4. Not only oratory but Latin literature in general participated in these discourses of morality. See Habinek 1998, p. 45: “At Rome literature participates in the ‘formation’ of the aristocracy in both senses of that
word, that is, by deining, preserving, and transmitting the standards of beha-
112
making enemies
Ethos
As previously mentioned, Aristoteles devised a system of three
pisteis or sources of persuasion in his treatise Rhetoric (ca 340
BCE): ethos, the moral character of the speaker; pathos, the emotions of the audience; and logos, the speech itself. Of these, Aristoteles considered ethos to be the most effective pistis.335 Character,
in other words, was the most powerful mode of persuasion.336
Whereas the sophistic tradition sought to devise a rhetoric
that only aimed at convincing the audience, Platon believed that
morality and public speaking were inseparable. In a Roman setting, Cato the Elder famously deined an orator as a vir bonus
dicendi peritus, a good man experienced at speaking. To Cicero,
the orator was the ideal statesman, embodying philosophy and
leadership as well as rhetorical skill.337 Conversely, lessons on
how to appeal to the values of the elite, empowering the speaker,
could be found in rhetorical theory.338 Oratory, in a very fundamental sense, was display of superiority and subsequently superior moral behavior.
The race for public ofice and the auctoritas and gloria
this pursuit promised the successful politician meant that the
individual member of the elite had to prove that his ethos was
worthy of respect.339 The heavy emphasis on portrayal of char-
335
336
337
338
339
vior to which the individual aristocrat must aspire and by valorizing aristocratic ideals and aristocratic authority within the broader cultural context.”
Arist. Rhet. 1.2.4. See in general Kennedy 1991. For ethos, see also Süss
1910; Wisse 1989.
See Kennedy 1972, p. 41: “Ethos, vigorously expressed, produces pathos,
and both of these elements came more easily to the Roman character than
did extensive or intricate logical argument.” Also De or. 2.184.
Brut. 23. Cf. Gunderson 2000, p. 87.
Sinclair 1993, p. 578. Sinclair’s arguments concern the Ad Herennium.
May 1988, p. 7; Morstein-Marx 2004, pp. 276–277.
Roman Political Culture
113
acter in Roman oratory can thus be linked with the importance
that character had in Roman society in general.340 Both the politician striving for ofice and the advocate in the Roman courts
had to rely heavily on arguments drawn from his own and his
adversary’s character. The particular goal of the legal case aside,
the orator’s social and political place depended on him making
an impression in accordance with elite norms and values.341
Roman morality, elite norms, and cultural values all converged
in the ethos of the orator and statesman. Ethos was persuasive
as it identiied the speaker as part of the elite. In turn, arguments provided by an orator with ethos carried more weight,
which allowed him to rise within the elite by winning cases and
elections.342 It follows, by the same rationale, that in a competitive culture, undermining an opponent’s ethos became a crucial
part of the agenda. The positive ethos of the orator could of
course be turned on its head and made to function as a weapon.
In other words, validation of the self can be done by coniguring
the adversary as Other.343
Even though character was of fundamental importance in
oratory, in Roman rhetorical theory, the Aristotelian division into
ethos, pathos, and logos was diminished and was not explicitly
used in the late Republic. Aristoteles’ version of ethos as conined
solely to the speech, as James May notes, could not be accepted
in Rome with its emphasis on past life, social rank, and moral
traditions.344 This view is corroborated in De oratore, where we
ind that what stirred the feelings of the Roman audience, winning them over, was the social worth (dignitas), achievements (res
340
341
342
343
344
May 1988, p. 8.
Sinclair 1993, p. 567.
De or. 2.182.
Dugan 2005, p. 57.
May 1988, p. 9.
114
making enemies
gestae), and conduct in life (existimatio vitae) of the person in
question.345 Andrew Riggsby has therefore suggested that character should be seen as logos rather than ethos, as proof, rather
than just “trustworthiness” or “authority” in the Aristotelian
sense.346 Kennedy also articulates this blend of ethos and pathos,
of character and emotion:
The emotion arises from the character of the speaker or his
opponent, and though it may reach its greatest intensity at the
beginning or the end of a speech, it is often woven into the whole
fabric, or more properly speaking, the speech is an expression of
that character and never departs from it.347
The moral character of the speaker could not be simply isolated
within the speech itself. Character could not be isolated from
politics—and therefore, neither could immorality.
Summary: Power, Oratory, and Morality
in the Late Republic
By the time of the late Republic, Roman political culture had
developed a division of power, each of which placed the individual politician center stage. These individuals were part of an
elite deined by their access to the political arenas and by their
pursuit of gloria. The premier political act in all of these arenas
was oratory. The politician was an orator by trade, as the chief
345 De or. 2.182.
346 Riggsby 2004, p. 182. See also May 1988, pp. 4–5, 167; Wisse 1989,
pp. 240–241. Cf. May 1979. In part, the Roman example might be explained
by the tradition of advocacy. See Kennedy 1968.
347 Kennedy 1972, pp. 101–102. Also May 2001a. Cf. De or. 2.178, 2.209; as
well as Part. or. 71.
Roman Political Culture
115
form of political communication and hence the basis for political
advancement was oratory.
Gloria was attained by service to the res publica, either military or civil. The pursuit of gloria thus led members of the elite
to seek election to the magistracies of state in ierce competition
with each other. In order to get elected, you had to make a name
for yourself, and the foremost way of acquiring fame was getting
up on the political stage and addressing an audience. This in turn
put the elite in conlict with each other. Orators routinely faced
their political rivals in a harsh political climate characterized by
verbal assault.
In this political culture morality was of great concern to the
political hierarchy, and character thus became a crucial target
between opponents. On every stage of politics oratorical combat
focused on the moral inferiority of adversaries. In this, Rome displays a political culture where those values and ideals were the
source of direct personal attack between oratorical combatants,
and where these types of attacks were considered a legitimate and
a traditional form of political discourse. The young novus homo
from Arpinum had better prepare.
Chapter III
Defense and Prosecution
—The Early Years (80–69 BCE)
The young Marcus Tullius Cicero had political ambitions.
He intended to rise within the political hierarchy at Rome in
pursuit of gloria for him and his family. In this endeavor, rhetorical
training could only get him so far. Real experience, needed to start
the climb on the cursus honorum, typically came from the arena
of the courts.
Two trials in the early career of Cicero have traditionally been
seen as decisive for the young orator: his irst causa publica as a
defense lawyer and his irst, and only extant, prosecution. The
trial against Sextus Roscius from Ameria will serve to introduce
the importance of character in Roman trials, while Cicero’s prosecution of Gaius Verres ten years later produced one of the most
notorious portraits of immorality in the Ciceronian corpus. Together with the other, less illustrious, but from our perspective
no less signiicant speeches from Cicero’s early years, they form
a irst step into the study of the connection between Roman immorality and forensic oratory.
Cicero’s career as a defense lawyer, and therefore also as a
player in the political culture, had begun a few years previously
after he had served under Gnaeus Pompeius Strabo and Lucius
Cornelius Sulla in the Social War (91–88). He was neither famous
nor came from a position of strength and he had yet to hold
116
Defense and Prosecution
117
any oficial position in the state. As far as we know, Cicero had
no personal stake in either trial, other than the most important
motive: the advancement of his own career. Rather, both trials
were part of his schooling as a Roman advocate and milestones
in his burgeoning career.
This chapter will not only illustrate how both defense and
attack were crucial elements in his self-fashioning as an orator,
statesman, and member of the Roman elite, but also that both
defensive and aggressive arguments were constructed from moral
concerns. It will moreover demonstrate the orator’s own use of
immoral portrayal in order to argue his case and initiate our
search for the cultural logic behind immorality in Roman political culture.
The Case of Sextus Roscius from Ameria
In 80 BCE, the unknown Marcus Cicero, born not in Rome, but
in Arpinum, undertook a monumental and dangerous task. He
decided, at the age of 26, to defend Sextus Roscius on a charge
of parricide.348
Being born outside of Rome made the young Marcus a novus
homo, a new man in politics, a man without ancestors who had
held magistracies in the cursus honorum, the career path of honors
that meant membership in the elite at Rome. Lacking a name, he
needed to make one for himself. Young men with political aspirations had to enter the political stage of the Roman Forum and
speak in front of people and build a public persona, present a
proper ethos. The Roman courts offered a suitable stage for such
348 Gell. NA. 15.28; Quint. Inst. 12.6.4. Pro Roscio Amerino has received a
lot of scholarly interest over the years. For the function of character, see
Vasaly 1985, and 1993, pp. 157–172; May 1988, pp. 21–31; Riggsby 1999,
pp. 55–66. See Dyck 2010 for further references.
118
making enemies
a pursuit; an arena for self-presentation. The sphere of the courts
was tied to the world of politics. Forensic activity meant oratory
and oratory meant politics. In order to thrive, young politicians
also had to cultivate networks vertically and horizontally, speaking for people in order to secure their support.349 Both oratory
and dependence were marks of the elite at Rome, and the role
of advocate offered opportunities for both to the ambitious who
wanted to join the club.
What made this particular case striking, and most likely risky,
however, was not the fact that Cicero was young and “new.” Nor
was it the fact that the crime was spectacular in its outrageousness. Killing your father was a Roman anathema, an abomination
deserving both cruel and unusual punishment; the guilty being
sewn into a sack with a monkey, a dog, a cock, and a snake, then
thrown into the Tiber.350 No, it was politics that made Cicero’s
decision so precarious. Over the course of his long and illustrious
career, this would turn out to be a recurring theme.
The young orator had to navigate the political waters still
treacherous in the aftermath of the Civil War. The blood had
literally lowed in the Forum, the hub of intellectual, forensic,
and political activity in Roman political culture. The dictator
Sulla had initiated proscriptions of his enemies, decades later to
ominously mirror Cicero’s own fate, and had reformed both the
Senate and the courts. Moreover, Sulla was lurking behind the
stage in the drama of the trial.
The criminal trial against Sextus Roscius was a public affair,
and although this was not Cicero’s irst time as a defense lawyer,
349 For this see Comment. pet. 16.
350 See Rosc. Am. 70–71. For the curious aspect of sewing animals into the
sack, see Justinianus Inst. 4.18.6, and Dig. 48.9.9. It is uncertain if this was
practiced in Cicero’s time.
Defense and Prosecution
119
it was in a sense his baptism of ire.351 It may therefore serve as
a suitable launching point for the pursuit of the orator’s use of
Roman morality as argument and into oratorical construction of
immoral character.
The case of Sextus Roscius gives us not only an example from
Cicero’s early career, but from the arena of the courts. Successfully constructing his public persona as a defense lawyer was an
important part of Cicero’s fame as an orator and a statesman. I
will show how Cicero depended on morality and the character
portraits he constructed in relation to this morality right from
the start. Yet, our main interest in the Pro Roscio Amerino is
not primarily the portraits of immorality painted therein, but his
“advice” to the prosecutor and jury and his rhetorical commentary as regards the importance and place of character in Roman
forensic oratory. The immoral character of a man on trial had to
be shown to a Roman audience.
On the Importance of Character
Part of what made the trial of Sextus Roscius a cause célèbre in
Rome was the enormity of the crime. The patriarchal structure
was the cornerstone of Roman society and the pater familias was
the arbiter of life and death over his adult male children as long
as he lived. Parricide was an affront not only to human laws, but
to divine ones as well.
This circumstance gave Cicero an opportunity to question his
counterpart in the legal drama, the prosecutor Erucius, as to his
general approach to the case. With this he gives us an insight into
a form of legal logic prevalent in Roman forensic oratory. Cicero
contended that so grave, atrocious, and indeed rare a crime, regard351 Cf. Plut. Cic. 3. See also Rosc. Am. 11.
120
making enemies
ed as an ill omen and a monstrosity, demanded certain arguments
from the prosecution. He therefore inquired of Erucius:
nonne et audaciam eius, qui in crimen vocetur, singularem
ostendere et mores feros immanemque naturam et vitam vitiis
lagitiisque omnibus deditam, et denique omnia ad perniciem
proligata atque perdita?352
Should you not show the unparalleled audacity of him that is
accused of the crime, his savage morals and inhuman nature and
his life given to every kind of vice and immorality, in short, as
ruined, corrupted, and lost?
Cicero, in his derisive advice, here places immorality irmly at
the center of the judicial issue. The prosecutor was, in the eyes of
Cicero, beholden to provide arguments of a moral nature which
were apparently needed to lay the foundation for a persuasive
accusation. A charge of this magnitude could not just be applied
to anyone. It would only make sense if it was consistent with
the accused’s moral integrity, or rather lack thereof. Otherwise,
the accusation could never hope to stick. Since, according to the
defense, the prosecutor had not accused Sextus Roscius of any of
these things, consequently he must surely be considered innocent.
Cicero’s reasoning, although obviously biased, speaks to a cultural tradition where morality was expected to matter. Revealing,
or displaying (ostendo) a life of vice and portraying the morals
and nature of the defendant was, it seems, not only relevant, but
required.
352 Rosc. Am. 38. All references to Cicero’s speeches are to the editions of the
Loeb Classical Library unless noted. All translations are my own unless
noted.
Defense and Prosecution
121
In De inventione, Cicero’s early treatise on rhetoric, the young
orator addresses the same point. It is the task of the prosecutor
to select arguments from certain attributes of character and use
them to discredit the defendant:
Nam causa facti parum irmitudinis habet, nisi animus eius qui
insimulatur in eam suspicionem adducitur uti a tali culpa non
videatur abhorruisse.353
For the motive of a crime has little irmness, if the animus of the
accused is not brought into suspicion in such a way that it does
not look inconsistent with such an offense.
The prosecutor should thus discredit the accused by attacking
his past life. Cicero’s claim suggests that guilt cannot be accepted
as credible if the character is not consistent with the crime. Bad
deeds, in other words, necessitate bad character. Or in the case of
Sextus Roscius, a horrible crime like murdering your father must
have been committed by someone with the lowest form of immoral character. Cicero in his book on rhetoric elaborates: “For
all that detracts from the honor and authority of the one accused, diminishes as much his chance for a complete defense.”354
But why then, would Cicero lecture his opponent in a judicial
contest for not doing his job? One reason he did so was to turn
the same line of reasoning into a defense. Erucius’ lack of moral
attack allowed Cicero to beneit from the same logic. If there are
no character laws, then the crime is unimaginable. This might
seem like mere rhetorical trickery, but we should not dismiss it so
353 Inv. rhet. 2.32. See also Quint. Inst. 5.10.28.
354 Inv. rhet. 2.33: Quantum enim de honestate et auctoritate eius qui arguitur
detractum est, tantundem de facultate eius totius est defensionis deminutum.
122
making enemies
easily. After all, a rhetorical strategy only works if certain basic
premises are agreed upon by the audience. For Cicero to be able
to argue the connection between guilt and immorality, the link
must have been possible to make in the cultural context of his
day. Moreover, there is no overt reason to assume that a Roman
audience did not see an essential connection between immorality
and crime.
We ind the same notion in the rhetorical treatise Ad Herennium. The speaker is encouraged to make every effort to relate
the personal history to the issue at hand.355 Fault in character
(animi vitium) should be linked with motive for crime, for instance inancial crime should be explained by avarice. More importantly, if the proper moral fault could not be evinced from
the past life of the target, “in fact, he should brand the defendant with some other or as many faults as he possibly can.”356
Then, the author maintains, the listener will ind it natural that
someone who in a previous case acted so shamefully, did so also
under the present circumstances. This rhetorical advice only
works if such a line of reasoning was culturally coherent. Because Romans tended to believe that character was habitually
rigid and not prone to change, actions were also thought to be
consistent with character and morality.357 In the Roman mind,
the link was logical. Thus, it could effectively be made use of in
the arena of the courts.
Let us return to Cicero’s instructions for his opponent Erucius.
His statement points toward a moral pattern which should be
initially highlighted here. First he maintains that the prosecutor
355 Rhet. Her. 2.5.
356 Rhet. Her. 2.5: si quo modo poterit denique aliquo aut quam plurimis vitiis
contaminare personam. See also Inv. rhet. 2.33.
357 May 1988, p. 26.
Defense and Prosecution
123
should show the unparalleled audacity of the defendant.358 Of
course, audacity or boldness could simply be thought to be required for such a horrendous crime. While this is true, audacia
has deeper connotations of immorality to which we will have
reason to return. The concept igures frequently in the corpus
of Ciceronian character attack as telling of a person’s character. Generally, it was a mark of behavior at odds or in outright
conlict with Roman elite expectations of proper conduct. In
this sense, audaces, the reckless or irresponsible, stood in direct
opposition to the boni, the good men of society.359 The singularity or uniqueness of this character trait that Cicero pretends to
look for similarly enforces the person’s deviating and frustrating
position. This too, is recurrent.360 Furthermore, in Cicero’s faux
inquiry, morality and nature take part in explaining criminal behavior and probabile ex vita arguments, centering on the target’s
life, were vital, he asserts. The life a Roman lives showed the
community who he was. We may inally note the logical conclusion of the passage to a life lived this way: vice and immorality
(lagitium) lead to ruin. The passage, in all its rhetorical mischief,
illustrates the mental link that existed between a person’s life
and his nature and moral character and furthermore how this
was related to the question of guilt. Moreover, it presents us with
a preliminary blueprint for how a member of the Roman elite
could be undermined and portrayed as immoral and deviant.
Cicero feigned surprise that his counterpart was not following it.
The speech continues with Cicero persisting that the approach
of his adversary was faulty. What kind of man is capable of killing
his own father, he hypothetically asks, upon which he proceeds
358 For audacia in the Pro Roscio Amerino, see also e.g. Rosc. Am. 7, 12, 17, 28,
88, 95–96, 104.
359 Wirszubski 1961, pp. 13–14. See also Lacey 1970. Cf. Sest. 100.
360 See Seager 2006.
124
making enemies
to offer his audience, and the inept prosecutor, a few alternatives.
There are, Cicero professes, certain character types that might be
believed ruined enough to have committed this crime. It is clear
that none of these its Sextus Roscius. For is his client a corrupted
youth led astray by vile or worthless men? Is he perhaps a sicarius, an assassin; a homo audax experienced in murder? Or is he
a man deined by luxurious living, debt, and by his unbridled and
lustful mind which compels him to crime?361
We can infer from this argument that, on a cultural level, from
Cicero’s perspective, and according to the logic he wants to present as typically Roman, these types of characters, the corrupted youth, the audacious assassin, or the lustful man of luxury,
would indicate guilt or at least establish the foundation of guilt
to a Roman audience.362 These stereotypical characters, ostensibly, would cast the suspicion he professed as necessary in De
inventione. They are presented in the speech as a form of immoral archetypes. It was apparently plausible that a man of similar
character would act criminally. Cicero presents the case in this
manner because it suited his line of reasoning and therefore his
overall goal of getting his client acquitted, something that would
earn him fame as well as idelity. The argument is obviously
biased and partial. Nevertheless, his assertions had to be conceivable and preferably even convincing to his listeners. If these
character types were counter-intuitive we should not believe that
they would be employed with so much at stake. Therefore, we
can infer that they held cultural potency, or at the very least that
the young Cicero was convinced that they did. The bias veriies
the link. Why then did such an argument, and these character
portraits, make sense to a Roman? And how could they be estab361 Rosc. Am. 39.
362 Cf. Vasaly 1985, p. 13.
Defense and Prosecution
125
lished through oratory? How could they be shown?
Later in the speech Cicero further develops the train of
thought of guilt vis-à-vis immoral character. The terrible nature
of the crime for which Sextus Roscius was accused makes it seem
incredible. Only if a man’s youth had been corrupted or if his
life was stained by every kind of shame and vice; if his lavish
expenses had been followed by disgrace; or if his audacity had
appeared as unbridled, his rashness as bordering on insanity,
could it be accepted or credible.363 A line of reasoning based on
moral concerns is again insisted upon. The individual steps in this
chain of immoral life are worth highlighting: a corrupted youth,
a past full of vice, luxurious living, audacity, and insanity form a
backdrop to guilt. The value for the defense strategy is apparent.
Contrary to the immoral man sketched by Cicero above, his own
client could be shown to be rustic and frugal, living a simple
life, aspects which conversely did not signal criminal behavior.364
Cicero clearly believed such a dichotomy to be meaningful, not
merely on an emotional, but also on a rational level.
Content with schooling his legal competitor, Cicero next turned
his defense into an attack. If his client could not be shown to have
either the character or the motive to indicate crime, conversely
Cicero could show that others in this affair had plenty of both.
His plan was to convince the jury that his client was innocent
of the horrendous crime and had in fact been framed by a conspiracy formed by Lucius Cornelius Chrysogonus, Titus Roscius
Capito, and Titus Roscius Magnus, the latter two, introduced in
the beginning of the speech as gladiatores, also brought into suspicion for the actual murder of the father.365 In order to secure
363 Rosc. Am. 68.
364 Rosc. Am. 75.
365 Rosc. Am. 8, 17. For gladiator as a shameful epithet, see Barton 1993; and
Edwards 1997.
126
making enemies
the wealth that the father of Cicero’s client had left behind, the
three culprits had added him to Sulla’s list of proscribed, thereby
having his means coniscated and auctioned off by the state. They
had then bought several estates that rightly belonged to Sextus
Roscius at bargain prices. Such a claim, however, did not have to
be merely suggested. It could be backed up.
Cicero’s attack relied on the belief that deeds were dictated by
character.366 After accusing both Titi Roscii of shameful living and
criminal acts, he turned instead to instruct the jury in how to
interpret the situation. He implored them to adhere to the principle that wherever such lagitium, greed, audacity, depravity, and
treachery are found, crime also lies hidden.367 In doing so he advocated a culturally logical link between character and acts. Equal
in avarice, depravity, impudence, and audacity, they, in contrast
to Sextus Roscius, were likely to have committed murder. Again,
we might be tempted to interpret this as mere delection from the
issue at hand. It is true, Cicero attempts to divert the scrutiny of
his client to other individuals, but the delection is not random.
Morality is the issue at hand.
The two immoral Roscii are not the main antagonists in
Cicero’s narrative however. That honor he awarded to Chrysogonus, a freedman and favorite of Sulla. The attack on him was
part of why Cicero’s endeavor was so precarious. Attacks on him
might be perceived as attacks on Sulla the dictator. The attack is
all but lost in a lacuna in the text. According to the scholiast it
concerned the luxurious life of Chrysogonus.368 It seems Cicero
employed one of his previously presented character types for the
366 May 1988, p. 17.
367 Rosc. Am. 118. See also Rosc. Am. 122.
368 Schol. Gron. p. 436.14. For the argument that the link between avaritia and
luxury intensiied because of the Sullan proscriptions, see Leach 2003, pp.
149–150.
Defense and Prosecution
127
man he wanted to paint as the real culprit. The cost of luxury and
extravagance gave him his motive. Yet, some of the depiction of
Chrysogonus has survived and serves as an apt appendix to the
case of Sextus Roscius.
The Immoral Chrysogonus
Cicero begins his attack on Sulla’s freedman by assailing the state
of his house. Chrysogonus’ many estates were illed with splendid
vases, statues, and silverware stolen from families in the chaos
following the Civil War. He had a large number of slaves, not
only cooks, bakers, and litter-bearers, but also artists and musicians. The whole neighborhood could hear the instruments by
day and the banquets by night. “Can you imagine,” Cicero asks
the jury, “what daily expenses come from such a life, what excessiveness, what banquets?”369 If it indeed can be called a house
at all, and not an oficina nequitiae et deversorium lagitiorum
omnium—a “workshop of wickedness and a lodging house for
every kind of immorality.”370 Life, lavish expense, excess, and vice
are all morally entangled.
Cicero had employed the same tactics the previous year in his
defense of Publius Quinctius.371 Sextus Naevius, a man portrayed
by Cicero in the Pro Quinctio as a scurra (buffoon) and praeco
(auctioneer),372 as a gladiator, and as audacious, cruel, and greedy,
was contrasted at the end of the speech to Cicero’s client. The question to be decided, Cicero held, was whether the simple, rustic life
369 Rosc. Am. 134: In hac vita, iudices, quos sumptus cotidianos, quas effusiones
ieri putatis, quae vero convivia?
370 Rosc. Am. 134.
371 For character in the Pro Quinctio, see also May 1988; and now Harries
2011.
372 Quinct. 11. For the shame attached to auctioneers, cf. Catul. 106.
128
making enemies
of Quinctius could be defended against luxuria and licentiousness
(licentia), or if his possessions had to be surrendered to covetousness (cupiditas) and impudence (petulantia).373 Luxurious and excessive living was the opposite of a frugal and unassuming life, a
life that had the power of tradition behind it. A scurra was similarly a pathetic city dweller, a man about town. And the auctioneer
was someone who “prostitutes his voice” in the sordid business of
trade.374 Hence, Cicero’s dichotomies worked on many levels. But
they were clearly moral dichotomies.
The city, then, becomes an arena of immorality in direct opposition to the countryside. In the Pro Roscio Amerino, Cicero evinces
an important chain of reasoning when contrasting the two:
In urbe luxuries creatur, ex luxurie existat avaritia necesse est, ex
avaritia erumpat audacia, inde omnia scelera ac maleicia gignuntur.375
The city creates luxury, from luxury inevitably comes greed, from
greed springs audacity, which brings forth all crimes and evil deeds.
The status of the city as a scene of immorality is here made clear.
Furthermore, the steps from this alarming setting to the committing of criminal acts are given in detail. The city breeds luxury
which provokes greed. Men’s greed makes them audacious and
audacia is presented as the root of all evil, a catalyst of crime and
misdeeds. Luxury is thought of as corrupting basically because
of its consequences. Sextus Naevius is a man of the city and this
could be made to imply, or show, immoral traits.
373 Quinct. 92. See Vasaly 2002, p. 77.
374 Quinct. 95.
375 Rosc. Am. 75.
Defense and Prosecution
129
In the Pro Roscio Amerino and in the Pro Quinctio, the household is a mark of character. The good Roman Quinctius does
not live in extravagance; he does not host splendid banquets.
“He does not have a house closed to modesty and sanctity, open
and freely accessible to passion and pleasure.”376 Naevius on the
other hand does. Pudor, meaning modesty, and sacredness, here
signaled important Roman qualities that should distinguish a
respectable home.377 Banquets and luxury, in both speeches, signaled deplorable acts and deplorable character.
After depicting Chrysogonus’ household as sordid, Cicero
turns to another sign of his deviance: his appearance. Look at
him, he urges the jury. See how he contemptuously struts (volito) around, his hair combed and reeking of perfume with his
followers wearing togas.378 The contrast to the boni that Cicero
represents is striking. But what was the signiicance of the outward appearance, walking a certain way, of perfume and hair?
The answer is immorality.
In Cicero’s defense of the comic actor Quintus Roscius Gallus
in 77 BCE, we also ind immorality and appearance brought to
the fore. The dispute was between Cicero’s client and a man called
Gaius Fannius Chaerea and the question was who had cheated
whom. Cicero presented a simple way to decide. He pleaded that
those who knew them should contrast their lives, something we
have already seen, while those who did not should compare their
faces. “Does not the head itself and those shaved-off eyebrows
seem to reek of malice and cry shrewdness?”379 Fannius seems
376 Quinct. 93: non habere domum clausam pudori et sanctimoniae, patentem
atque adeo expositam cupiditati et voluptatibus.
377 For pudor, see Barton 2001.
378 Rosc. Am. 135. As noted by May 1988, p. 29 a depiction of the homo audax.
Cf. Vasaly 1985, pp. 14–15.
379 Q Rosc. 20: Nonne ipsum caput et supercilia illa penitus abrasa olere mali-
130
making enemies
to project fraud and deceit from his bodily frame. This projection is immediately heightened by the professional trade of Roscius. When his client on the stage plays the famous Plautine pimp
Ballio—ilthy, impure and detested—he really portrays Chaerea.
The character in the play, Cicero asserts, echoes the character in
real life as regards mores, natura, and life. Portrayal of character
hence takes a quite literal turn in this speech. By pointing out
how Chaerea presented himself, Cicero attempted to show his
audience the immorality manifest in his appearance; an immorality that in turn could project guilt in a question of fraud.
The passages in the Pro Roscio Amerino that deal with the
relationship between guilt and moral character, alongside the depiction of Chrysogonus, point ahead to our investigation into the
construction of immoral portraits and the Roman logic of morality that imbues them. Some initial observations have been made.
Cicero sought the moral argument in the defense of his client.
He advised his audience that immoral character was closely connected to the question of guilt. Immorality should be shown to
exist in the players of the trial, as offence or as defense. If a type
of behavior was inconsistent with the character of the accused,
guilt was inconceivable. The speeches Pro Quinctio and Pro
Quinto Roscio Comoedo further exemplify the approach. Immorality could be illustrated and consequently evaluated in order
to reach a verdict. Both cases can be characterized as inancial
disputes. The outlook thereby helps to illustrate the importance
of morality in the early years of the orator, even in less dramatic
circumstances as well as in the context of minor charges. Cicero’s
early defense speeches also highlighted certain initial features of
Roman immorality: the corrupting city, sordid household, and
tiam et clamitare calliditatem videntur? For Chaerea’s appearance, see also
Corbeill 1996, pp. 43–45.
Defense and Prosecution
131
the deviant appearance. To these we will return in the upcoming
chapters.
But the initial indings also leave us with new questions. How
could immorality be shown, argued as part of defense or prosecution? Why did the correlation between certain character types
and guilt make sense? What other marks of vice and debauchery
were readily available to the orator?
As a defense lawyer Cicero “demanded” of his opponent the
prosecutor to adhere to a strict logic of crime and character. It
is likely that the strategy to focus the issue on immorality was
effective. Sextus Roscius from Ameria was acquitted.380 Ten years
later, he would have a chance to return to the correlation between
immorality and guilt in the prosecution of Gaius Verres. Now he
was on the other side of the legal battle.
The Portrayal of Gaius Verres
In 70 BCE, Cicero returned to the arena of forensic oratory, this
time as prosecutor.381 After gaining fame for his successful defense of Sextus Roscius he had spent part of the decade studying
oratory in Athens and Rhodes. More important was the fact that
in 75 BCE he had served as quaestor, the irst step on the cursus
honorum, in the Roman province of Sicily. As a result, he was
able to resume his political career in Rome with another trial very
much in the public limelight.
The prosecuted governor Gaius Verres is one of the most
380 Plut. Cic. 3.6. See also Cic. Brut. 312.
381 Although the Verrines have been described as “remarkably understudied”
(Prag 2007a, p. 1) it has received notable attention in recent years. See Vasaly
2009, pp. 102–104 for a survey. See particularly Vasaly 1993, pp. 205–217;
and Tempest 2007 for character in the Verrines. Both Prag (ed.) 2007; and
Frazel 2009 cover numerous aspects of the trial.
132
making enemies
notorious villains in history, forever an example of Roman corruption and greed. The young Cicero’s attack on him, spanning
seven individual speeches (including the contest to “win” the prosecution known as Divinatio in Caecilium) and likely around 500
pages in any modern edition (464 pages in the Oxford edition in
Latin), is relentless and impressive both in length and in intensity.
It has ever since his own day dictated the interpretation of the
character of Verres. Posterity’s condemnation of the man targeted
in the Verrines has been assured. Cicero’s portrait, a prototype of
a provincial oppressor, has in other words reigned supreme.
Traditionally, only the irst speech is thought to have been held
as part of the trial.382 This has contributed to the allure of the
case—the defendant realizing that the game was lost and leeing
Rome into voluntary exile. But it has also raised questions as to
why Cicero had written and published several others and consequently how to value these texts in relation to the actual trial.383
To the present endeavor, however, the problem is of little concern.
The portraits and the moral reasoning in all the extant speeches
are grounded on values Cicero believed existed in the cultural
milieu of Republican Rome and the texts can therefore be used
to search for the logic of Roman immorality.384
In Verrem, in its entirety, represents the high point of character attack in Cicero’s early career. The sheer force with which
he oratorically confronted Gaius Verres was arguably not to be
matched until the last oratorical duel of his life. He would pull no
382 This has rarely been questioned. See Gelzer 1962–64, II, p. 168, n. 124. For
the evidence, see Ps. Asc. 205, 223 St. There is also some confusion as to
when he led.
383 For the publication of the Verrines, see Frazel 2004.
384 This also means that the speeches thought to have been held do not hold
more value as persuasive documents than the ones not believed to have been
heard by an audience.
Defense and Prosecution
133
punches in his portrait of the former governor of Sicily. The result
is a varied and fascinating portrait of immorality. It also means
that to modern eyes, the portrayal found in the Verrines is likely
found to be extreme. It has sometimes been assumed that Verres’
conduct as governor was hardly unique, merely extraordinary.385
By taking Cicero with a grain of salt we can, according to such
a view, supposedly gauge the character and behavior of Verres—
and of Roman governors in general—hidden behind hyperbole.
Such a line of reasoning is precarious. Maybe there were foundations to the charges, but which parts are fabricated, exaggerated,
and accurately depicted and which are not, are at any rate impossible to separate. It is vital that we sort out speculations as to
how well Cicero’s portraits relect the actual individuals portrayed
from the outset, as Verres’ real actions are of no consequence to
a study following arguments based on moral logic. Morality is
not a matter of facts, but interpretations made based on societal
values and concerns. The point is that Cicero presents narratives
and accounts, whether these were truthful or not, as immoral because morality was a powerful argument. As an example taken
from the previous discussion, it is inconsequential whether or
not Chrysogonus’ house was illed with luxurious vases but of
vital importance that Cicero chose to interpret the existence of
luxurious items as immoral. It may also be argued that the, to us,
extreme portrayal of Verres was brought on not because similar
elite practices were common, but because there was no such thing
in the Roman mind as “moderate” immorality. Either way, Verres
was differentiated and cut off by Cicero from the body of the elite.
In order to do so convincingly, the prosecution had to present the
385 See Greenwood 1928, pp. xiv–xv. This then presumably meant that Cicero
had to be careful not to chastise those in his audience guilty of the same
behavior.
134
making enemies
court with a probable character worthy of such suspicion. How
then was this immoral aspect of the prosecution achieved?
The Prosecution
Gaius Verres was a governor of Sicily charged with extortion, i.e.
general misgovernment and corruption. The province of Sicily,
which Verres had administered for three years (73–71) demanded restitution for his crimes. Because of Cicero’s existing ties to
the province as quaestor, he was asked to speak for it. The trial
took place at a time when the judicial system was in disarray and
subject to revision after Sulla’s reforms. It promised great renown
and the possibility to enhance the auctoritas of the prosecutor.
Prosecuting was a young man’s game in Republican Rome, a
way to procure political capital. Veteran politicians often seem to
have avoided the animosity it could bring, as prosecuting one’s peers could appear cruel.386 At the time, Cicero stood for the aedileship and thus had also political stake in the trial. It was an important opportunity for fashioning a public persona. A prosecutor
must possess a particularly upright and faultless character, according to Cicero himself.387 In order to criticize, one must show one’s
own proper conduct. Nothing was more intolerable than attacking
someone for faults that could be illustrated in the attacker himself.
We would expect the prosecution, at least on a general level,
to show that political corruption and economic fraud had taken
place during the defendant’s time as praetor in Sicily. The province
had initiated the trial and demanded inancial compensation. Yet,
we will immediately see how the trial focused on another issue:
the immorality of Verres. In this, Cicero attempted to prove the
386 Off. 2.49–51.
387 Div. Caec. 27. Also Verr. 2.3.1–4.
Defense and Prosecution
135
corruption charges by portraying Verres as morally corrupt, putting his behavior and character on trial. There is no reason to
believe this was an attempt to merely throw dust in the eyes of the
jury.388 Instead, I argue that character was essential to substantiate
corruption and political malpractice. This in turn raises the question of how corruption and morality were linked in the Roman
mind. Who was capable of extortion, bribery, and the plunder of a
province? And how was it veriied by immoral argument?
The list of Verres’ alleged crimes far outstretches the boundaries of this chapter. Many episodes, anecdotes, and crimes are
narrated by Cicero at considerable length and in great detail.
Here, our concern is the portrayed immorality and not the catalogue of criminal charges themselves, and—just like Cicero at
one point remarks—the list of charges must be cut short or I
shall never be done.389 We will not focus on the crimes, but on the
depiction of character capable of them. In this chapter, a number
of key aspects, chief among which is greed, will be considered.
“You know,” Cicero addressed his audience, “the wicked and
impure morality of Verres.”390 More importantly, he assumed
they knew what a wicked and impure morality entailed. Otherwise they would not have been able to follow the orator’s reasoning to which we now turn.
The Immoral Charge
Life and the deeds one had committed in life were intimately
linked with morality and character in the Roman mind. In the
388 Cf. Riggsby 1999, p. 139: “The jurors are expected to use character as a
guide to whether the defendant would have committed speciic acts.” See
also Tempest 2007, p. 27.
389 Verr. 2.2.119.
390 Verr. 2.3.23: Verris mores improbos impurosque nostis.
136
making enemies
Roman court, character was linked to guilt. In the Pro Roscio
Amerino, Cicero had instructed the jury:
In eius modi vita, iudices, in his tot tantisque lagitiis hoc quoque
maleicium, de quo iudicium est, reperietis.391
In a life such as this, among such and so much immorality, you
will also ind the wickedness that is on trial.
The notion was crucial to Cicero’s prosecution of Gaius Verres.
In the opening of his irst speech against the corrupted praetor,
Verres is portrayed as a man already condemned by everyone because of his life and deeds.392 He was already convicted by his vitia and lagitia, his vices and shameful, immoral acts.393 His moral
condemnation should subsequently assure his criminal conviction. Verres is only distinguished, Cicero claims, by two things;
his extraordinary offences and his wealth.394 Therefore, everyone
would think an acquittal to be the result of the latter, since no one
would believe good deeds or even moderation in vice could have
been illustrated. The point that it was only to be expected that a
man of Verres’ moral nature had committed crimes was clear.395
Immorality in the past made present guilt a foregone conclusion.
As observed by Catharine Edwards, the Roman discourse of
morality was to a great extent articulated in terms of past and
present, but previous actions in life also functioned as a blue
391 Rosc. Am. 117.
392 Verr. 1.2: homo vita atque factis omnium iam opinione damnatus. Cf. Verr.
2.3.146. See also Div. Caec. 42.
393 Verr. 1.10. See Verr. 1.35; 2.2.174.
394 Verr. 1.47. A play on words: peccatum and pecuniam.
395 Cf. Verr. 2.5.13 where Cicero states that one particular crime is easier to
believe from the character of the criminal than from the facts of the case.
Also Verr. 2.5.65.
Defense and Prosecution
137
print for future behavior.396 The past had a predictive quality.
In the second speech, Cicero reiies this belief by asking who—
after contemplating Verres’ thievery as quaestor; his plundering
of temples as legatus; and his open robbery as praetor—could
question how the fourth depraved act (improbitas) in the drama
would be played out in the future.397 The assertion is simple, but
important. We may note that improbitas is an immoral quality.398
The future of Verres, were he to be acquitted, would assuredly be
immoral. The past was a crucial factor in establishing character,
but to Cicero this character should furthermore illustrate what
was coming.399
In this way, immorality in general was presented by the prosecutor as crucial to the trial. Immoral behavior in the past functioned as an argument for the prosecution. Less important to Cicero
were the formal criminal charges.400 In fact, these are rarely dwelled upon in the Verrines. A prosecutor, clearly, was not obliged
to. Instead, over the course of his orations Cicero refers to many
incidents that serve to illustrate Verres’ immoral character and
depraved behavior when serving as praetor. Rather than just proving a particular accusation of extortion, Cicero took a broader
approach. Crime and immorality became overlapping categories.
Toward the end of the irst actio, a brief summary is given:
Dicimus C. Verrem, cum multa libidinose, multa crudeliter in
cives Romanos atque in socios, multa in deos hominesque nefarie
396 Edwards 1993, p. 19.
397 Verr. 2.2.18: Etenim quis dubitare posset, [...], qualis iste in quarto actu
improbitatis futurus esset?
398 For improbitas, see also e.g. Verr. 1.36, 50; 2.1.72, 74, 111, 153; 2.2.42, 50,
68; 2.3.97, 122, 195; 2.4.49, 139; 2.5.115.
399 Cf. Verr. 2.5.116 where each crime is worse than the last.
400 See also Steel 2007, p. 45.
138
making enemies
fecerit, tum praeterea quadringentiens sestertium ex Sicilia contra
leges abstulisse.401
We claim that Gaius Verres has repeatedly acted with severe lust
and cruelty toward Roman citizens and the allies, and offensively
toward gods and men, and moreover that he against the laws took
forty million sesterces from Sicily.
The charge against Verres was that of extortion within the lex
Cornelia de repetundis, but the passage above is as close as we
get to any kind of proper charge in the speeches themselves.402 It
moreover stands out in the Verrines because it mentions that the
defendant’s behavior was contrary to the law. Most accusations
against Verres are instead either more general in nature or concern speciic episodes. But is even in this passage, unlawfulness
is not of sole concern. As we can see, lust was not only part of
this accusation but actually comes irst. It is vital that he acted
lustfully and with cruelty. But the acts or crimes that this speciied
immoral behavior led to or originated from are not detailed to
the effect that Verres in this passage is charged with his general
behavior, not the crimes the behavior caused. This is signiicant.
He has also acted offensively or impiously (nefarie) against gods
and men. Again, the general quality of his behavior is of particular concern. It was to be clearly linked to morals and character.
The prosecutor hence seemed to ascribe a lot of weight to this
type of behavior. To act with lust, cruelty, and general nefariousness was worthy of prosecution and punishment. Furthermore,
perhaps such behavior denoted a character whose actions the
401 Verr. 1.56.
402 For a discussion of the charge, see Riggsby 1999, pp. 125–126; and p. 169.
There is a more formal charge also in the Div. Caec. 11.
Defense and Prosecution
139
Roman audience could easily predict. Rather than proving the
facts of the case, Cicero constructs a “biographical narrative”
that serves to illustrate and prove that Verres is immoral.403 It is
not a trial of one particular crime, but a lifetime of wrongdoing.
Cicero explains that he will hold Verres responsible for all of
the fourteen years since he was quaestor. Not even one hour, he
held, of these years has been free from crime, or from cruelty and
immorality (lagitium).404 This is a good example of crime and
immorality coinciding in Cicero’s legal approach. Flagitium, like
improbitas, is unmistakably an immoral quality, denoting shamefulness, depravity and dishonor.405 We might view this as the mere
hyperbolic statement it of course is. But maybe we should read it
as a consistent Roman notion: if you are immoral, then all your
acts follow a pattern of immorality. At one point, in the third
speech, Cicero puts particularly manifest emphasis on the immoral charge: improbitatem coarguo—I convict you as guilty of
immorality.406
In sum, crimes and acts are not presented in a vacuum in Roman
forensic oratory. There is no sharp distinction between, for modern eyes, a “real” or tangible accusation, and a “libelous” or
irrelevant one.407 If such considerations were an essential part of
Roman forensic practice, Cicero gives us no hint that this was the
case or that he believed a jury, or an audience at another arena of
the political culture, thought “formal” arguments more important
and his immoral arguments empty. Their legal importance not-
403 May 1988, p. 39.
404 Verr. 2.1.34.
405 For lagitium, see also e.g. Verr. 2.1.22, 41, 62–63, 82, 101; 2.2.2, 78, 134,
192; 2.3.23, 30, 84, 161, 187, 207; 2.4.139, 151; 2.5.86, 94, 160.
406 Verr. 2.3.217. It is furthermore worth noting that coarguo can mean to
demonstrate or reason, essentially prove that someone is guilty of a crime.
407 Cf. Edwards 1993, p. 26.
140
making enemies
withstanding, criminal behavior and deeds are followed by a
thick layer of character. To illustrate this, the following passage
is apt:
Ego in uno homine omnia vitia quae possunt in homine perdito
nefarioque esse reprehendo; nullum esse dico indicium libidinis,
sceleris, audaciae, quod non istius unius vita perspicere possitis408
I am blaming one man of every vice that a forsaken and impious
man can be guilty of; there is no sign of lust, crime, and audacity,
I say, which you cannot perceive in this one man’s life.
As in the “formal charge” cited above, crime and immorality
here overlap, but in this case immorality clearly takes precedence. Though easily classiied as exaggerated, this statement is
nevertheless decisive. First, I want to emphasize that immorality
or shameful behavior is not coincidental, hidden in legal reasoning to fool an audience. Cicero openly states that his focus is on
vice. Verres can and should in reality be judged on the merits of
his past immorality. Second, instead of questioning the extreme
quality of the statement, we might venture to interpret it as consistent with Roman moral reasoning where immorality is seen
as total, encompassing all aspects of a person’s life. Everything
about Verres is immoral and every aspect of immorality is evident
in his life. A third point concerns Cicero’s legal approach. An accusation that targets omnia vitia, every possible vice that a man
can commit, is pointedly different from a speciic charge of extortion, plunder, or general corruption. Lustfulness and audacia are,
strictly speaking, not necessary for stating and proving criminal
behavior. Still, they are very much present in the Verrines.
408 Verr. 2.3.5.
Defense and Prosecution
141
There is however another aspect of this accusation that deserves
further discussion. Cicero here speaks of signs, indicium—a telltale of a person’s character—which presumably can be exposed in
a life; a life that in this case very clearly stood on trial. Moreover,
no man, Cicero remarks, can be a good judge if he is not affected by convincing “suspicion.”409 A good Roman could read these
signs and was obliged to act on them, to base his understanding of
a man on them. What role then did these signs of immorality play
in Cicero’s oratory? What did such a suspicion entail?
The following year, in 69 BCE, when defending a man accused of similar “malpractice” while governor of Gaul, Cicero
returned to these signs and suspicions. Just as the case with Sextus Roscius from Ameria, the orator pointed to the fact that no
attacks on the character of his client had followed the criminal
charges. “No shameful act (probrum), no misdeed (facinus), no
immorality born of lust, impudence (petulantia) or audacia, if
not truthful, then at least with some credibility or suspicion in
their iction.”410 The statement indicates that any “literal truth”
was not necessarily required and maybe not expected, but more
importantly that these signs were felt to be of the utmost importance. Immorality should naturally follow any criminal accusation. Even great men of old, although of the most upright
character, were forced to endure attacks on their personal character, Cicero holds. His client, Marcus Fonteius, had endured
two trials without any allegations that carried the trace of lustfulness, insolence, cruelty or audacity.411 It follows then, in the
orator’s logic, that Fonteius’ character must be spotless, since the
prosecution did not even bother to try to depict him as immoral.
409 Verr. 2.5.65: iudex esse bonus nemo potest qui suspicione certa non movetur. Cf. Verr. 2.3.6.
410 Font. 37.
411 Font. 40.
142
making enemies
But had he shown these signs, Cicero says, it would also have
been the duty of the jury to convict him.412 Cicero himself however, when prosecuting Verres had not made the same “mistake.”
On the contrary, he had made these “suspicions” the very focus
of his endeavors. These signs of immorality apparently carried
meaning in Roman oratory.
No Ordinary Criminal
It is clear that the prosecutor sought to make the target of his
oratorical attack stand out among his peers. Gaius Verres was
not just another criminal and this was no ordinary trial. The following passage gives a vivid example:
Non enim furem sed ereptorem, non adulterum sed hostem
expugnatorem pudicitiae, non sacrilegum sed hostem sacrorum
religionumque, non sicarium sed crudelissimum carniicem civium
sociorumque in vestrum iudicium adduximus; ut ego hunc unum
eius modi reum post hominum memoriam fuisse arbitrer cui
damnari expediret.413
It is no thief, but one who takes everything away; no adulterer,
but the ravaging enemy of chastity; no common profaner, but the
enemy of all that is sacred and holy; no assassin, but the cruelest
butcher of our citizens and our allies, that we have dragged before
your judgment: so much that to me he would be, as he is, the one
man in history who would beneit from a verdict of condemnation.
412 Font. 34–35.
413 Verr. 2.1.9.
Defense and Prosecution
143
This passage illustrates several of the major points in Cicero’s
attack on Gaius Verres. The escalation and hyperbole are common Ciceronian traits. He was the most outrageous thief and
most cruel murderer and an enemy of Roman religion.414 Time
and again over the course of the speeches he would return to
these points. Morevoer, he is not corrupt in an ordinary sense but
rather uniquely wicked. But once more, Cicero also takes care to
reiterate his moral transgressions and seamlessly include them in
his charge. Moreover, his vices are not only his own but endanger
the community; his immorality threatens Rome.415 Verres is not
only adulter, unchaste, but a hostis pudicitiae, an enemy of chastity. Cicero points out elsewhere in the Verrines that, yes he is a
thief (fur), yes he is a sacrilegious thief (sacrilegus), but he is also
the princeps of every vice (vitium) and immorality (lagitium).416
The logical link is not broken by the inal assertion. Thievery
and crime are blatantly associated with immoral acts. Crimes,
although important, are, it seems, not enough but instead they
are to be backed up by accusations of immorality.
We may wonder why these things are connected at all. What
do they have to do with a charge of provincial corruption? Even
though it is true that Roman forensic tradition did not demand
“formal charges” in the modern sense, the range of the charge is
striking.417 If Verres was a murderer, why was he not charged with
murder?418 How are thievery and chastity, sacrilege, and murder
linked together? And, as we go further into the study Cicero’s
speeches, what other themes are they connected to? Should we
simply attribute this to a Roman tradition of slander, to Cicero’s
414
415
416
417
418
For the sacrilegious aspect of Verres’ behavior, see Frazel 2009, chapter 2.
Cf. Gildenhard 2011, p. 81.
Verr. 2.5.4. Also Verr. 2.4.60.
See Riggsby 2004, pp. 172–173.
For the murder charge, see Riggsby 1999, pp. 51–78.
144
making enemies
attempt to entertain his audience or meet generic expectations?
Or should we ascribe the link between crime and immorality relevance in the Roman mind and legal system?
That the link between moral life and behavior was connected
to crime and furthermore to punishment is made clear toward the
very end of the Verrines. In the inal passage, Cicero returned to
the uniqueness of the defendant as he addressed the jury:
deinde uti C. Verrem, si eius omnia sunt inaudita et singularia
facinora sceleris, audaciae, peridiae, libidinis, avaritiae, crudelitatis,
dignus exitus eius modi vita atque factis vestro iudicio
consequatur.419
So, if Gaius Verres’ deeds all are unheard of and unparalleled in
their criminality, audacity, treachery, lust, greed, and cruelty, then
let your verdict give him such an end that beits such a life and
such actions.
Not only does the passage contain most of the key character
traits of Gaius Verres, his audacity, lust, greed, and cruelty, but it
also emphasizes the importance of the past life of the defendant
and the importance of his immorality in determining his guilt and
rightful punishment. And just like the previous quotation, it accentuates the unparalleled and unique quality of the man on trial.
The way this uniqueness was detailed was through his overall
depravity. In this way, it appears that charges of immorality could
function to substantiate criminal charges—to serve as argument,
but also that immorality was an effective way to brand someone
as deviant.
419 Verr. 2.5.189.
Defense and Prosecution
145
A Portrait in Greed
O di immortales, incredibilem avaritiam singularemque audaciam! 420
Immortal gods, what incredible greed and unparalleled audacity!
One of the most conspicuous aspects of Verres’ singular immorality as presented by his accuser, was his greed. This is arguably
the most dominant theme of immorality in the Verrines. Verres’
enormous avarice made him a deviant. But, although greed is a
predictable trait to ind in an attack on a provincial governor
accused of corruption, greed in Roman culture was also closely
associated with a larger set of vices and patterns of depravity.
The two Titi Roscii whom Cicero blamed for the murder of Sextus’ father had been equal in greed (avaritia) and immorality (improbitas). When prosecuting the former Sicilian governor, Cicero
took care to make these links visible to his audience. What part
then did greed play in Cicero’s portrait?
The wealth of Gaius Verres was irst and foremost in itself
immoral. In Cicero’s interpretation, it was both a motive for and
a cause of improbitas.421 His immorality made him rich. But his
lust for wealth was also the reason for his immorality. Greed
could thus not only explain immorality, but furthermore led to
it. Immorality had both explanatory and predictive value for the
prosecutor’s argument. Avaritia was easily connected to a chain
of accusations:
Tenetur igitur iam, iudices, et manifesto tenetur avaritia, cupiditas
hominis, scelus, improbitas, audacia.422
420 Verr. 2.1.87.
421 Verr. 2.3.111. For greed and improbitas, see also Verr. 2.2.17.
422 Verr. 2.3.152.
146
making enemies
It is therefore already proven, members of the jury, and proven
unmistakably—the greed, desire, crime, immorality and audacity
of this man.
Greed was, Cicero at one point remarks, Verres’ only quality,
only drive and one for which he was known by everyone.423 Not
least the jury, he holds, knows the defendant would never lift a
inger if there were no proit or plunder in it.424 The lion’s share
of accusations in the Verrines deals with deeds that can be traced
back to the theme of greed: thievery, plunder, or extortion. His
thefts were also connected to his immoral acts.425 Precious artifacts have been removed from their proper sanctuaries (greed and
sacrilege), farmers have been robbed or tricked (greed and injustice), corn has been embezzled rather than sent to Rome (greed
and fraud), and bribery has led to corruption of the legal system. Cicero employs different strategies to highlight the aspect of
greed. Verres acts like a pirate, according to the orator, echoing
the deep-rooted problem of piracy at the time, a pirate that has
plundered Sicily and committed foul deeds of piracy even in the
Roman Forum.426 His “love of art,” suspiciously Greek in nature,
is likewise a perverted result of his longing for precious things.427
All these deeds stem from his avarice which in turn helps predict
and explain them.
Of course, Cicero did not decide himself that greed was immoral. It was a prevalent theme in a Roman cultural tradition
of morality. Cato the Elder, the moral authority in Cicero’s day,
wrote that the forefathers had considered avaritia to encompass
423
424
425
426
427
Verr. 2.2.134, 2.2.84. Also Verr. 2.3.40.
Verr. 2.5.11.
For furtum—lagitium, see e.g. Verr. 2.2.2, 114; 2.3.84, 151; 2.4.83.
Verr. 2.5.122. Also Verr. 2.1.154.
For this, see Vasaly 1993, chapter 3.
Defense and Prosecution
147
every vice.428 To the historian Sallustius similarly, it was the root
of all evil.429 He held that it ruined noble qualities like honor
and uprightness. Moreover, Sallustius saw avarice as corrupting
of masculinity and leading to effeminacy.430 It was also believed
that avarice was a vice that had been introduced relatively late
and gradually into Roman culture, thereby slowly but surely corrupting it. This meant that Romans were not greedy to begin
with, but rather sullied by outside inluence. Cicero himself argues in the speech Pro Tullio, held the previous year, that during
the times of the ancestors, both the estates and the cupiditas of
men were smaller, whereas his own time was a time of excessive
licentiousness (nimiam licentiam).431 As always, the ways of the
forefathers, the mos maiorum, was the model for proper Roman
conduct and morality. More wealth had brought more avarice
and following that luxury and lust in the words of Livius.432 Although, in the Pro Roscio, Cicero claimed reversely that avaritia
was born of luxury the link was logical. Lust, luxury, and greed
were all part of the same pattern of immorality.433
The Latin for greed is commonly avaritia. But avaritia also
lies close to cupiditas, cupidity or passion.434 Greed and desire
can in this be said to at times overlap. In De inventione, Cicero
even speculated as to whether avaritia was a part of the genus
of cupiditas.435 Both avaritia and cupiditas were also possible to
428 Gell. NA. 11.2. Cf. Krostenko 2001, p. 36, n. 51. See also Gell. NA. 18.9.1
for Cato’s use of avaritia in a speech.
429 Sall. Cat. 10.4. Cf. Sall. Iug. 41.9.
430 Sall. Cat. 11.3.
431 Tull. 8–9. See also Tull. 46.
432 Liv. 1.pr.2. Cf. Liv. 34.4.1–2.
433 Cf. Sall. Cat. 5.8.
434 See e.g. Quinct. 9, 53, 83; Rosc. Am. 101; Verr. 2.3.152; 2.4.60, 68.
435 Inv. rhet. 1.32.
148
making enemies
associate with libido, lust, and libidinosus, lustful.436 A lust for
money and precious things is a lust for whatever one desires.
These concepts were highly pejorative and are found throughout
all of Latin literature. Seneca the Younger, for instance, designates
both greed and lust as “evils” that God, Jupiter, relieves good men
of.437 To the elite, they had become deining traits of the wicked.
Verres’ greed, his desire, Cicero declares, was of the iercest
type as he needed only to hear of precious things to passionately
covet them.438 In the contest for the opportunity to prosecute
Verres, the divinatio, Cicero explicitly linked Verres’ unparalleled cupiditas not only with crime and audacia but also with
lagitia, which we can translate as immoral acts.439 In one passage, Cicero refers to the accused as an unequaled homo lagitiosissimus, a most shameful, immoral man, spurred on by his
cupiditas improbissimus, his most depraved desire.440 He was an
immoral man led by his immoral greed. From cupiditas the step
could also be made to amentia, insanity.441 I will not speak only
of Verres’ greed but his singular madness, Cicero at one point
states.442 In the following passage, Cicero offered an interpretation of the unrestrained mind of his adversary:
Furor enim quidam, sceleris et audaciae comes, istius effrenatum
animum importunamque naturam tanta oppresit amentia ut num-
436
437
438
439
440
See e.g. Verr. 1.13; 2.1.58,86; 2.2.97. See also Merrill 1975, p. 18.
Sen. Dial. 1.6.1.
Verr. 2.4.39.
Div. Caec. 6.
Verr. 2.1.76. Cf. Verr. 2.2.136; 2.3.187. For cupiditas—improbitas, see also
Verr. 2.2.42. See also avaritia—spurce in Verr. 2.1.94; and avaritia—nequitia in Verr. 2.5.91.
441 Verr. 2.4.75. Also Verr. 2.4.34. For cupiditas—audacia—amentia, see Verr.
2.4.99. See also Verr. 2.2.36 for cupiditas—insania.
442 Verr. 2.4.38.
Defense and Prosecution
149
quam dubitaret in conventu palam supplicia, quae in convictos
maleicii servos constituta sunt, ea in cives Romanos expromere.443
Because a certain insanity that accompanies crime and audacity
thrust this man’s unrestrained spirit and ruthless nature into such
a madness, that never did he hesitate before the eyes of those
gathered to bring forth such punishments that are common for
convicted atrocious slaves, on Roman citizens.
Insanity followed crime and audacity and in turn led to offensive
behavior as it was unmistakably madness to treat Romans like
slaves. It demonstrated a corrupt, deviant mind. Insanity could
however also more explicitly be connected to immorality. Valerius
Maximus, writing in the early decades of the irst century, made
this association. Lust and greed led to furor, a concept frequently
found in Cicero’s immoral portraits.444 Like amentia, furor can be
translated as madness or insanity, but should perhaps better be
understood as signaling frenzy and agitation. To Valerius Maximus, the most admirable part of the soul was moderation, as it
did not let the mind be carried away by sudden impulse.445 Verres,
in contrast, is depicted as unrestrained in the passage above. Sudden impulses, usually stemming from passion and desire, were
clearly at odds with Roman proper behavior. In his defense of
Sextus Roscius ten years before, Cicero had demanded that the
crime necessitated summus furor atque amentia, an insanity and
frenzy of the worst kind.446 Similarly, Verres’ acts of thievery had
443 Verr. 2.5.139.
444 Val. Max. 4.3. pr.
445 Val. Max. 4.1: quae mentes nostras inpotentiae <et> temeritatis incursu
transversas ferri non patitur.
446 Rosc. Am. 62, 67.
150
making enemies
left his mind haunted by furor and amentia.447 Acting insane and
acting criminally or immorally intersected in portraying the ethos
of an oratorical target.
Greed and insanity were behavior also associated with cruelty,
crudelitas.448 Chrysogonus for instance, in Cicero’s severe portrayal in the Pro Roscio Amerino, was not content to satisfy his
greed with money, but sought blood to satiate his cruelty.449 In
the divinatio, Cicero posited that the Sicilians who had contracted him to prosecute Verres had endured the praetor’s lagrant
immorality, cruel punishments, greedy plunder, and arrogant
insults.450 Cicero could also enumerate Verres’ faults as being
greed, insanity, lust and cruelty.451At one point Cicero rhetorically addresses Verres:
Errabas, Verres, et vehementer errabas cum te maculas furtorum
et lagitiorum tuorum sociorum innocentium sanguine eluere
arbitrabare; praeceps amentia ferebare, qui te existimares avaritiae
vulnera crudelitatis remediis posse sanare.452
You were wrong, Verres, so very wrong, in thinking that the stains
of your thievery and immorality would wash away with the blood
of innocent allies; you must have been insane, to think that the
wounds of your greed can be cured with the remedy of cruelty.
447
448
449
450
Verr. 2.1.7. See also Verr. 2.4.38.
See the cupidity and cruelty of Sextus Naevius in Quinct. 59.
Rosc. Am. 150.
Div. Caec. 3: luxuries in lagitiis, crudelitas in suppliciis, avaritia in rapinis,
superbia in contumeliis. See also Verr. 2.2.9; and cf. Verr. 2.3.126.
451 Verr. 2.5.42. Cf. Verr. 2.5.189.
452 Verr. 2.5.121.
Defense and Prosecution
151
Thus, greed could easily lead to cruel behavior and signal insanity. Together they pointed toward a larger pattern of depravity.
This allowed Cicero to connect greed, foul lust (stuprum), and
cruelty in a depiction of an episode where the crime was born of
cupiditas, enlarged by stuprum, and completed by crudelitas.453
In this way, again, greed functioned as a catalyst for immorality.
In the passage that began this part of the chapter, we saw that
the orator could combine avaritia with audacia, a concept we
discussed in the previous part of this chapter as having connections to immoral character.454 One link between the two which
made the oratorical connection effortless was that audacity, or
effrontery, could often be established by lavish display, luxury, or
greed. In fact, we saw that, in Cicero’s train of thought in the Pro
Roscio Amerino, luxury bred greed and greed in turn bred audacia, the cause of omnia maleicia. Audacia was needed, according
to Cicero in his defense of Sextus Roscius, to establish guilt in a
court of law. It had accordingly been prominent in his attack on
Sextus Naevius in Pro Quinctio, where he also presented the case
to the jury as a struggle between greed and audacity on the one
hand and truth and modesty on the other.455 Greed and audacity
were clearly on the side of evil.
In sum, the closely related concepts of avaritia and cupiditas
are not only in Cicero’s portrayal without apparent strain associated with lust but with audacity, cruelty and insanity. It could
furthermore be easily hinged on to criminal behavior (scelus) and
453 Verr. 2.2.82.
454 See also Verr. 2.1.154; 2.5.113, 189; and Rosc. Am. 75. For the link between
cupiditas—crime—audacia, see Rosc. Am. 12; and Div. Caec. 6. For cupiditas and audacia, see Verr. 2.4.78. For luxuria and audacia, Verr. 2.3.22. Cf.
Plaut. Capt. 2.2.287; and Inv. Rhet. 1.32.
455 Quinct. 79. See also Quinct. 56, 88, 94.
152
making enemies
immorality in general (improbitas, lagitium).456 All of these aspects of his depravity were connected like nodes in a web of immorality.
The importance of greed in the immoral portrait of Gaius Verres, and consequently in Roman moral reasoning, can be deduced
not only from its prominence but from its consequences. It had
caused Verres to neglect tradition and duty as well as his honor
and even his human nature, his humanitas.457 A barren Sicily, the
result of Verres’ plunder, threatened the corn supply of Rome.
Greed likewise affected the balance of affairs between gods and
men, and Cicero asks if there was ever before such greed that
could devastate holy things?458 Another accusation contends that
because of his luxuria and avaritia a Roman leet was captured
by pirates.459 The immoral character of Verres threatens even
Rome’s military strength. In particular one passage sums up the
danger of acquitting Verres:
Videtis iam profecto, iudices, hac aestimatione a vobis comprobata neque modum posthac avaritiae cuiusquam neque poenam
improbitatis futuram.460
You see now truly, members of the jury, that if you give your
sanction to this behavior, neither will there be moderation in any
form of greed after this nor will immorality be punished.
In Roman cultural tradition, greed was dangerous. It threatened
society because in the Roman mind it signaled a bad moral cha456
457
458
459
460
For scelus and avaritia, see Verr. 1.42; 2.3.152; 2.5.32. Cf. Div. Caec. 6.
Verr. 2.2.97.
Verr. 2.1.48: Fuit ulla cupiditas tanta quae tantam exstingueret religionem?
Verr. 2.5.137.
Verr. 2.3.221.
Defense and Prosecution
153
racter. There existed in Cicero’s Rome a deep-rooted anxiety over
avaritia and cupiditas, over a lack of control in its elite that they
believed it indicated. Cicero without hesitation used this aversion
to greed to paint his portrait of a corrupt governor. Greed could
be oratorically latched on to other pejorative and damning concepts which in turn empowered the prosecutor’s argument. But
the links were logical: immorality and greed were closely merged
in Roman consciousness.
The Depravity of Desire
As shown, the three concepts of avaritia, cupiditas, and libido
were possible to place in close context with each other in Roman
oratory. Greed, desire, and lust all carried a similar pejorative
meaning. Lust and desire, however, could not only be directed
at beautiful things or wealth. They also signaled sexual desire.
Someone who lusted for money could easily be suspected of sexual wantonness, as Roman culture did not ostensibly distinguish
between sexual immorality and excesses of other kinds.461 Lust
was lust. And it was immoral; Verres was a homo lagitiosissimus, libidinosissimus nequissimusque—the most immoral, the
most lustful and the most wicked of men.462 In other words, being depraved and being lustful could be portrayed as naturally
blending together. To the elite, this lust, whether for material or
sexual gratiication, signaled a degrading lack of control.463 It is
therefore not surprising that Cicero portrayed Gaius Verres as a
slave to his lust.464 This was degrading in itself, but the immoral
logic of lust also centered on the belief that it triggered further
461
462
463
464
Edwards 1993, p. 5.
Verr. 2.2.192. See also Verr. 2.1.86; 2.3.60. Cf. Richlin 1992, p. 30.
See Verr. 2.1.62. Cf. Verr. 2.1.65; 2.4.115. Cf. Edwards 1997, p. 68.
Verr. 2.4.112.
154
making enemies
immoral behavior. Its meaning and relevance lay in the broader
context of immorality.
Lust was an important part of Cicero’s approach, as we saw in
the “formal charge” cited above. In trying to win the opportunity
to prosecute, he inquired of his opponent in the divinatio, much
in the same manner as he had interrogated Erucius, if he thought
himself up to the task of making Verres’ acts of lust cause as
much pain and indignation to the jury as it had to the victims of
the former governor.465 Then, in the irst speech, Cicero professed
that his own sense of decency kept him from repeating the sexual
offences and impious immorality of Verres’ lustful behavior.466
This, according to the prosecutor, included many episodes of
sexual assault on free-born individuals and married women and
even children whom he submitted to his sexual immorality.467 In
this, Cicero maintained that Verres’ morality (mos) was in accordance with his depraved acts of lust (libidines lagitiosae).468
There were other concepts an orator could use to portray his
adversary that more clearly denoted the sexual corruption of his
target. To this effect, Cicero depicted Verres as a man without
decency (pudor) or modesty (pudicitia).469 These were extremely
important moral notions in Roman culture. Hence, we ind that
another incriminatory concept in sharp contrast with pudor and
pudicitia was adulterium, adultery or the violation of an honorable or married woman:
465 Div. Caec. 38.
466 Verr. 1.14: In stupris vero et lagitiis nefarias eius libidines commemorare
pudore deterreor.
467 Verr. 2.1.62. See also Verr. 2.1.68, 76, 78; 2.2.134; and in particular 2.5.80–
83.
468 Verr. 2.1.63. Also Verr. 2.2.135; 2.3.60.
469 Verr. 2.3.8; 2.4.18, 41. See also Verr. 2.2.40. For pudicitia, see Langlands
2006.
Defense and Prosecution
155
Pudorem ac pudicitiam qui colit, potest animo aequo istius
cotidiana adulteria, meretriciam disciplinam, domesticum
lenocinium videre?
Can one who honors modesty and chastity, with indifference
look upon this one’s daily adulteries, school of whores, and
house of pimps?470
The answer to Cicero’s question was of course no—immorality
demanded action of the good men of the community. Associating with the lowest of society, meretrices (whores) and lenones
(pimps), not only reinforced this dichotomy between honorable
and dishonorable segments of society, but was of course in itself a clear sign of what kind of depravity was taking place.471
Another closely related concept denoting sexual immorality was
stuprum.472 Everyone knew, Cicero explained, that Verres spent
his nights in stupris and adulteriis—that is, in sexual debauchery.473 Craig Williams has observed that whenever Cicero enumerates immorality in his philosophical treatises, he lists adultery.474
It had a natural place in his list of vices. Portraying the defendant
as immoral through these concepts was clearly vital. An immoral
man stood in opposition to pudor and pudicitia. Roman mothers
and children are on one side. Meretrices, whores, and lenones,
470 Verr. 2.3.6. For adultery in Rome, see Richlin 1981; Treggiari 1991, pp.
262–319; Edwards 1993, chapter 1; Harries 2007, pp. 96–101. For adulterium, see also Verr. 2.1.9; 2.3.6.
471 For the use of meretrix in Ciceronian oratory, see McCoy 2006. See also
Adams 1983, pp. 321–327.
472 For stuprum, see e.g. Verr. 1.14; 2.1.62; 2.4.20; 2.5.34. See discussion in
next chapter.
473 Verr. 2.4.144.
474 Williams 2010, p. 123. See Cic. Fin. 2.27; Leg. 1.43; Off. 1.128. Williams
also notes that stuprum is not listed in the same catalogues of immorality.
156
making enemies
pimps, are on the other.475 The bad qualities that Verres had, his
audacia and cupiditas, corrupted the pudicitia of others and he
was, as we saw in an earlier quote, an enemy of modesty.476 In this
way, the immorality of someone, in this case his lust, could be put
forward in Roman oratory as a credible threat to the community.
Verres’ libidines would only grow until neither the Roman provinces nor the foreign peoples could take or bear it anymore.477
This possible line of reasoning before an audience can be
further exempliied by how the consequences of sexual desire
could be oratorically argued. To be sure, views on immorality
and attitudes toward sexual trespass were very closely associated
in the Roman moral tradition. In Roman immoral logic, licentious behavior in general pointed, as shown, to sexual desire
which in turn were associated with sexual corruption of others;
particularly of those of a young age. The correlation is clearly
illustrated in the following passage where Cicero portrays the
most shameful (turpissimus) and immoral (lagitiosissimus) aspects of Verres’ life:
Nihil a me de pueritiae suae lagitiis audiet, nihil ex illa impura
adulescentia sua. […]. Sileantur de nocturnis eius bacchationibus
ac vigiliis; lenonum, aleatorum, perductorum nulla mentio iat;
damna, dedecora, quae res patris eius, aetas ipsius pertulit,
praetereantur.478
Nothing will be heard from me regarding his immoral boyhood,
nothing of his unclean youth. […]. Let there be silence about the
475 For meretrices and lenones, see Verr. 2.1.101; 2.4.83.
476 Verr. 2.5.39. Cf. Verr. 2.1.9; 2.5.39, 85.
477 Verr. 2.1.78: Tantaene tuae, Verres, libidines erunt ut eas capere ac sustinere
non provinciae populi Romani, non nationes exterae possint?
478 Verr. 2.1.32–33; 2.2.16.
Defense and Prosecution
157
orgies and sleeplessness; let there be no mention of the pimps and
gamblers and seducers; let the deilements and debaucheries that
ravaged his youth and his father’s riches be passed by.
This passage collects several important signs of someone’s immorality; feasting, the type of company one kept, over-spending,
and, most importantly, the corruption of youth. In the Pro Roscio
Amerino we saw how Cicero pressured his legal adversary to
prove his client had the character of one capable of murdering
his own father.479 One of the types he himself offered was the
corrupted youth. In his defense of Fonteius the following year,
he would similarly mention an unclean youth (adulescens turpis)
as something that would have hypothetically been incriminating
to his client.480 Verres’ corruption, his immorality, began already
when he was a puer, a boy. Once started on that road, the result,
in oratorical logic, was ixed. The next step was an unclean adolescence.481 Then there were feasts with disreputable characters
followed by inancial destitution. In an enigmatic passage that
details his earlier days, Verres was in the prosecutor’s words “pulled out of the Forum, rather than pulled in it” (e foro abduci, non
[…] perduci), meaning, as one scholar has argued, that he was
prostituted.482 Less obscured is the statement that he furthermore
paid off his debts with “the fruits of his youth” (aetatis fructu).
479 Rosc. Am. 38.
480 Font. 34.
481 Cf. Verr. 2.3.60 where Cicero portrays Verres’ henchman Apronius as having
been born to dedecus, schooled in turpitudo and shaped to accommodate
Verres’ desires.
482 Verr. 2.5.33. To a male customer by a pimp, and therefore not, by own volition and without payment. This is the interpretation held by D. H. Berry,
who maintains that this passage has either been misunderstood or obfuscated by earlier translations, but that it is clear from the whole passage that
Verres was prostituted as a young man. Berry 2006, p. 281.
158
making enemies
Eventually, Cicero explained, Verres grew accustomed, hardened
to this foul submission of others, but as they inally grew tired
of it, he himself never did.483 Instead he “stormed” the “strongholds” of decency (pudor) and modesty (pudicitia) of others as a
grown man.484 This, then, should come as no surprise to Cicero’s
audience. They were expected to identify the dangers of that type
of depravity.
At the center of this logic of immorality lies a cultural expectation of different sexual roles.485 The passive sexual behavior that
becomes the object of the orator’s narrative is of key importance
to many of the portraits that Cicero painted of his adversaries
in public oratory. In The History of Sexuality, Michel Foucault
noted that passivity in ancient sexuality was linked with immorality.486 Passive behavior in general was abhorred in a Roman
man, passive sexual conduct was devastating to his status as a
vir. Being a Roman man, a vir, was not so much a category of
gender, as of class and social status, or rather, to the Romans they
blended together.487 Sex, as concluded by Paul Veyne in regard to
the Roman example, had nothing to do with it. “What mattered
was being free and not a passive agent.”488 This also meant that
483 Verr. 2.5.34: Iam vero, cum in eius modi patientia turpitudinis aliena, non
sua, satietate obduruisset.
484 For Verres violating Roman women and children during his career, see Verr.
2.1.62. See also Verr. 2.1.68; 2.5.28.
485 For passive sexual behavior as “Greek,” see MacMullen 1982; and Williams
1995.
486 Foucault 1985, p. 47.
487 See Skinner 2005, pp. 195–196. Richlin 1993, p. 532 holds that as regards
Roman social hierarchy and sexuality “the two systems can hardly be understood independently.” For gender roles, see also Gardner 1998.
488 Veyne 1985, p. 29. For Roman references, see Williams 1995, p. 519, n.n.
13, 18. See also Habinek 1997, p. 23: “In the classical world, in particular,
[…], sex remained imbedded in other social relations and other categories of
discourse and was not capable of producing meaning in and of itself. As a
result, many of the categories through which sexuality (that is, the distincti-
Defense and Prosecution
159
Roman views on sexuality made no moral distinction between
homosexual or heterosexual activity.489 A free-born male member
of the elite was expected to be the penetrator, whether of women
or slave-boys, and whichever way suited him.490 Verres, by contrast is portrayed by his accuser as transgressing the boundaries
between men and women in the following claim by the orator:
At homo inertior, ignavior, magis vir inter mulieres, impura inter
viros muliercula, proferri non potest.491
You cannot ind a lazier, more slothful man, one who to a greater
extent plays the man among women and the impure and weak
woman among men.
The attack has strong sexual implications. To be the woman
among men suggests that Verres is sexually penetrated by men.
He is thereby depicted as passive and unable to defend his societal status. Representing his youth as immoral likewise meant he
was still sexually corrupted. The only question is, then, what all
this had to do with a trial of provincial corruption. Why did such
a reproach make sense to Cicero’s audience?
A similar attack on an adversary’s status as a vir can be found
in another speech in the early career of Cicero, but under diffe-
vely modern discourse of sexuality), produces meaning, especially those of
sexual orientation, are quite simply irrelevant to the interpretation of ancient
culture and literature.”
489 For this view, see especially Williams 2010, pp. 4–9. See also Taylor 1997, p.
322. Cf. however Butrica 2005. For the question of homosexuality in Rome,
see also Lilja 1983; Richlin 1993. Cf. Gonfroy 1978 for Cicero’s oratory.
490 Dixon 2001, p. 36. Cf. Cantarella 1992, p. 217. See also Richlin 1993, p.
535: “Roman class-consciousness equated sexual submission with loss of
honor, admission of inferiority, and lack of virility.”
491 Verr. 2.2.192.
160
making enemies
rent circumstances. In 69 BCE, Cicero led the defense in a land
dispute. It was a case preoccupied with the legitimacy of private
violence that had on the surface very little to do with the infamous case against the former governor of Sicily. Nonetheless, in
such a “trivial” case, arguing over the interpretation of the law,
the young Cicero still found use of the argument of character. In
a swift passage, Cicero deals with a person in opposition to his
own client, a man called Aebutius:
Quam personam iam ex quotidiana cognoscitis vita, recuperatores,
mulierum assentatoris, cognitoris viduarum, defensoris nimium
litigiosi, [...], inepti ac stulti inter viros, inter mulieres periti iuris et
callidi, hanc personam imponite Aebutio492
Whose character you know from your daily life, gentlemen, a
latterer of women, a widow’s advocate, an all too quarrelsome
attorney, [...], useless and stupid among men, among women an
experienced and shrewd lawyer, such a character should you
ascribe to Aebutius.
This, admittedly lighter, attack, nevertheless makes use of the
same apparent cultural logic. Sextus Aebutius is repeatedly referred to by Cicero as depraved (improbitas).493 The logical connection between manliness and character (persona) is explicitly
stated. Aebutius’ character is known because everyone can see it
displayed around the Forum. In Cicero’s portrayal he loses his
place among the men and is only as a man when among women.
He is as a woman, because he interacts with them and specializes
in female cases—work that signal a breach from norm, a parody
492 Caecin. 14.
493 Caecin. 4, 23, 30.
Defense and Prosecution
161
or distortion of the lawyer’s profession. Such work is clearly
undigniied, but the consequences are not intended as merely
humorous, but as an argument. Cicero aims for it to make sense.
This speaks to the heart of the matter, in this case a land dispute.
It makes sense, because character was an argument.
Let us again return to the life cycle of Verres that Cicero pretended to pass over to see how this could be achieved. We may
note that the passage starts with immorality in the form of sexual
corruption and ends with Verres having depleted his inheritance
in search of gratiication of his lusts. The importance of arguing
Verres’ sexual immorality can thus be understood as arriving at
both his greedy and lustful nature and his inancial state; aspects
which in turn give Cicero both the character argument and a
motive for provincial corruption to present to the jury. In the
Pro Roscio Amerino, Cicero had put forward a similar train of
thought. Lavish expenses from unchecked desire (cupiditas) lead
to enormous debts, which in turn lead to crime.494
Other aspects of Cicero’s portrayal home in on the passivity
and corrupted masculinity of his target.495 In the passage above
he is described as lazy and slothful. Verres lacks virtus and diligence (industria) and instead he displays inertia.496 This also puts
him in sharp contrast to the ideal of the Roman vir whose deining trait was virtus. Nor does he have the reinement (humanitas) indicative of the elite: “He has none of that, on the contrary,
his whole conduct is tainted by disgrace and shamefulness, as
well as exceptional stupidity and crudeness.”497
Furthermore, Verres not only surrounds himself with women
494
495
496
497
Rosc. Am. 39.
On this, see also Gonfroy 1978.
Verr. 2.4.90; 2.5.40.
Verr. 2.3.8: nihil eorum est, contraque sunt omnia cum summo dedecore ac
turpitudine tum singulari stultitia atque inhumanitate oblita.
162
making enemies
of low moral iber, he allows himself, and thus, in essence, the
Roman province of Sicilia, to be run by a woman.498 When
he was city praetor in 74, even people living in the countryside knew that all his decisions were controlled by his mistress
Chelidon; a woman married to one, but available to all (nuptam
uni, propositam omnibus).499 Just as Aebutius deviates from the
role of the lawyer, Verres deviates from the proper conduct of a
praetor, but also from the proper behavior of a man. By using
motifs of erotic distraction and by illustrating his dependence
on a woman, aspects which “were felt to divert a man from his
public responsibilities,” Cicero paints a portrait of Verres that
draws on Roman expectations not only of civic duty but also
of male behavior.500 Instead of battle scars he had the scars of
women’s teeth, evidence of his immoral lust.501 Cicero mocks
his relationship with one of his commanders as effeminate and
delicate, alluding to their sexual liaison.502 At the center of their
intimate relationship were immorality and depravity (lagitium,
turpitudo).503 Even worse was his right-hand man, Apronius, a
man who could match all his immoral and vile desires. Verres,
Cicero told his audience, could not live without this Apronius
and shared his private chamber with him.504 These relationships,
it is important to stress, were not only shameful or embarrassing, but centered also on immorality.
Appearance and manner could also signal effeminacy and cor498 Verr. 2.1.140. Cf. Verr. 2.3.31.
499 Verr. 2.5.34. By allowing himself to be carried back into the city to her after
taking his vows as military commander he also violated religious laws.
500 Edwards 1993, p. 85.
501 Verr. 2.5.32.
502 Verr. 2.5.104.
503 Verr. 2.5.107.
504 Verr. 2.3.23. See also Verr. 2.3.65: blanditia lagitiosa, immoral caresses or
lattery.
Defense and Prosecution
163
rupted manhood.505 Verres is depicted as traveling in the tradition of foreign kings, in luxurious litters, smelling of and snifing
lowers. The litter bearers, as soon as the retinue arrived in a
town, would carry him to his bed chamber.506 Moreover, the governor did not dress in traditional Roman garb but in colorful
Greek clothes.507 Deviant and immoral behavior went hand in
hand.
The depiction of Verres as effeminate and sexually submissive
makes sense as a character argument because it signals immorality. The sexual deilement of the governor’s youth is meant to
corroborate his present crimes. This is logical because in Roman
moral discourse, immorality breeds immorality. And once someone is immoral, only immorality can be expected of them. The
trick, then, was to argue this immorality.
The Immoral Arena
There were a number of ways in which an orator could allude
to immoral behavior in an adversary. Depravity took place in
certain arenas and involved certain types of people. In Cicero’s
speeches the feast or convivium were often evinced as a setting
of immorality.508
As advocate for both Quinctius and Sextus Roscius, Cicero
stressed that his clients did not attend the type of banquet that
would have signaled immoral behavior.509 They lived traditional,
frugal lives. The villain in the trial against Roscius, Chrysogonus,
505 For signs of effeminacy, see Edwards 1993, pp. 68–70.
506 Verr. 2.5.27.
507 Verr. 2.5.31, 40, 86, 137. For Verres’ Greek clothing, see Heskel 1994, pp.
133–135.
508 For the immoral convivium, see especially Corbeill 1996 and 1997.
509 Quinct. 59, 93; Rosc. Am. 39, 52.
164
making enemies
on the other hand, hosted lavish feasts that pointed toward iniquity.510
In Cicero’s portrayal of Verres, the convivium is the setting for
sexual immorality, marked by stuprum and lagitium.511 During
Verres’ time as military commander, Cicero remarks, he was rarely seen out of bed: ita diei brevitas conviviis, noctis longitudo
stupris et lagitiis continebatur—“so were the short days with
banquets, and the long nights with debaucheries and depravity
passed.”512 The banquets were also the scene of Verres’ sexual
aggression. The prosecutor narrates the episode of how Verres’
house in a town called Lampsacum was set on ire by an incensed
mob after he attempted the violation of a young girl during his
party.513 His own son was brought up feasting among unchaste
women and unrestrained men at his father’s luxurious dinnerparties, thereby schooling him, not in the ways of the forefathers,
but in his own immorality.514 As a Roman magistrate he devoted
his days to Venus and Bacchus and his convivia were not the
digniied affairs suitable for a Roman praetor and imperator, but
signiied by clamor and loud noises and even ist ights. He who
never cared about the laws of the Roman people was adamant
about the laws prescribed about drinking and feasting.515
We may wonder why the convivium was such a sign of immorality. Could not feasts be a sign of hospitality and wealth? We
are offered a clue as Cicero contrasts the proper and improper
conduct of a Roman magistrate. By using the theme of the ban-
510 Rosc. Am. 134.
511 Verr. 2.4.71. Also Verr. 2.5.86 and cf. Verr. 2.5.137. Cf. Fantham 1991, pp.
287–288; and Corbeill 1996, p. 135.
512 Verr. 2.5.26.
513 Verr. 2.1.66–70. See also Verr. 2.5.28.
514 Verr. 2.3.160–161. See also Verr. 2.5.30, 137
515 Verr. 2.5.27–28. Cf. Verr. 2.5.92.
Defense and Prosecution
165
quet, Cicero portrays Verres as the antithetical Roman statesman
where the feast symbolizes the ultimate breach of decorum and
duty. Throughout the ifth speech of the Verrines, Cicero exempliies how Verres’ behavior and drunkenness causes him to neglect his duties.516 A Roman magistrate was of course supposed to
admit people into his house, but Verres only admitted those who
could share or minister his vices. And while the feasting went on,
no legal activity was pursued in the Forum and instead of the
voices of litigants and judges, music and women’s voices were
heard.517 In this depiction, and by being contrasted with the normal activities of a statesman, the nocturnal banquet effectively
becomes the perversion of the political arena of the Forum.518 The
proper and normal daily activities are contrasted with the deeds
that can take place during a feast. Hence, immorality, symbolized
by the convivium where noises, clothes, guests, and luxury could
all signal the debaucheries that took place, argued that military
considerations had not been met and duties not honored.
Gaius Verres the Tyrant
Many of the pejorative claims made about the character of Verres in Cicero’s portrayal of the corrupt governor can be summed
up in the igure of the Hellenistic tyrant. No doubt this was the
prosecutor’s intention; there are recurring explicit accusations
of tyrannical behavior throughout the Verrines.519 The former
governor had been a king of Sicily (rex Siculorum) and Syra-
516 Verr. 2.5.63, 83, 87, 94.
517 Verr. 2.5.30–31. Cf. Rosc. Am. 134.
518 In Verr. 2.4.83 also contrast Verres’ sordid house with the paragon of Roman manhood, Scipio Africanus.
519 For the tyrant in political invective, see Dunkle 1967; Erskine 1991. See also
Thome 1993; and Tempest 2007, pp. 30–36.
166
making enemies
cuse (tyrannus Syracusanis).520 The tyrant, a powerful igure in
the Greek and Roman mind, was above all violent, lustful and
greedy, arrogant and cruel.521
The tyrant and the tyrannical king was the quintessential
un-Roman motif. The tyrant stood in direct opposition to the
very idea of the Roman Republic, loaded not only with oppressive connotations but with foreign ones. The tyrant, as observed
by Ingo Gildenhard, is in fact the “paradigmatic other” to the
Roman community, a Greek threat which provided a resource for
attacking others in Roman oratory.522 But what made the image,
or theme, of the tyrant powerful?
Indeed, we soon come to realize that the tyrant is a host of several, if not all, of the marks of immorality we have just discussed.
The people of Sicily decided to prosecute their tormentor because
of his luxuria, crudelitas, avaritia, and superbia (arrogance).523
His tyranny is likewise marked by amentia.524 While it is true that
these are the marks of a tyrant, they are, as shown, also character
traits of an immoral character in general. Verres is a tyrannum
libidinosum crudelemque—a lustful and cruel tyrant who committed acts of lagitium.525 His acts are marked by audacia and
superbia—the latter no doubt evoking the last of Rome’s kings,
Tarquinius Superbus. His behavior is also foreign and feminine.
All these aspects of a portrait could be comfortably linked to
notions of immorality prevalent in Roman culture.526
We might therefore argue that the image of the tyrant is the im520
521
522
523
524
525
526
Verr. 2.3.76–77; 2.4.123. See also Verr. 2.4.51.
See Dunkle 1967, p. 151; Gildenhard 2011, p. 88.
Gildenhard 2011, p. 89. Cf. Steel 2001, p. 31.
Verr. 2.2.9. For cruelty and superbia, see also Verr. 2.1.122.
Verr. 2.5.103: importuni atque amentis tyranni. See also Verr. 2.3.24–25.
Verr. 2.1.82.
Note too, the image of the immoral Apronius, (Verrem alterum), as a tyrant
in Verr. 2.3.31. Cf. Verr. 2.3.115.
Defense and Prosecution
167
moral portrait taken to the extreme and that the logic that makes
this image powerful and effective is the same. Certain traits, such
as crudelitas and superbia, have traditionally, and rightly, been
associated with the tyrant. But the image is not merely based on
people’s fear of tyranny or historical connotations. It is based on
moral logic. It follows the same pattern of immorality.
Conclusions: Defense and Prosecution
Non est querendum in hac civitate, quae propter virtutem omnibus
nationibus imperat, virtutem plurimum posse.527
No one should complain that in this city, which because of virtus
rules all other nations, virtus is everything.
Virtus is a dificult word to translate. It denotes manliness but
also excellence and bravery.528 But in the sentence above we are
not wrong to translate it with high or even moral character. It illustrates that in Rome, character and morality was of the utmost
importance. The Romans themselves believed it crucial to their
success. This morality, this virtus could be attacked in oratory.
Certain themes could be utilized; certain traits illustrated that
chipped away at the moral integrity of a target. By drawing on the
shared area of knowledge, prejudice, and fears known from other
parts of Latin literature, the orator could empower his arguments.
These attacks lead us back to their source, Roman morality and
values. In this chapter we have discussed different logics underlying the attacks that made them appear rational to an audience.
527 Verr. 2.4.81.
528 For the different connotations of virtus in Cicero’s speeches, see McDonnell
2006, pp. 340–355.
168
making enemies
As we continue, several of these questions will linger as we further
attempt to disentangle the moral logic of Cicero’s oratory.
Who was capable of misgoverning a province and what did
morality have to do with it? It is clear that greed could be presented as both the crucial explanation and the raison d’être for
the complex portrait of immorality that Cicero painted of his
adversary. Gaius Verres, in Cicero’s portrait of immorality, is deined by his greed, but the portrait far from ends here. Rather,
it expands through immoral links and associations. Greed clasped together with desire and lust, audacity, cruelty, insanity, and
sexual corruption in a chain of interrelated immorality. These
aspects of Roman moral logic were powerful themes shared by
the community. It was in all likelihood a persuasive and eficient
portrait.529 Instead of ignoring the emphasis he put on morality,
we can see it as part of his success. Immorality was a way to
argue guilt in ancient Rome. Signs of depravity and suspicion of
immoral behavior could be presented to an audience in various
ways. Crime and immorality were not sharply separated, rather
they merged in the portrait of Verres and the forensic arguments
that Cicero chose.
The early career of Marcus Tullius Cicero from Arpinum was
marked by success. The two most important trials were great
accomplishments. Roscius was acquitted, Verres led Rome. As
I have shown, he used moral arguments and a moral chain of
reasoning right from the start and as part of both the defense
and the prosecution, in famous and “minor” trials, and as part of
inancial disputes as well as capital offences. In fact, none of the
extant speeches from this period lacks character arguments. He
was subsequently rewarded within the political culture. Cicero
had started his climb on the cursus honorum.
529 Cf. Frazel 2009, p. 223.
Chapter IV
Republican Politics
—The Consular Years (66–59 BCE)
In the years following his early forensic triumphs, Marcus
Tullius Cicero reaped the beneits of his success. After the trial
against Verres the road to higher political ofice lay open. The
new man from Arpinum became the most celebrated politician
in Rome by seizing the opportunities of the political culture. As a
result of winning in both the courts and the polls, his auctoritas
grew. The pinnacle of his career was the consulship of 63 BCE.
It was the top spot of the cursus honorum and it afforded him
the opportunity to essentially become the res publica. Cicero, in
service of the Republic against the perceived threat of conspiracy,
was awarded the honorary title pater patriae, father of the fatherland. This was truly Cicero’s decade.
Much of this happened as a result of oratory. Cicero continued
to persuade juries of the innocence of his clients. He swayed the
populus to vote him into ofice. On the Senate loor, he convinced
his peers of the danger posed by a fellow member of the elite.
Lucius Sergius Catilina, a man of noble birth, was so forcefully
portrayed as the enemy of the state that he led the city. Cicero
was hailed as the savior of his country.
Representations and evocations of immorality played a part in
these developments. The present chapter deals with the relationship between Roman moral culture and political oratory during
169
170
making enemies
the 60’s BCE, between Cicero’s rise to the consulship and his
subsequent fall from grace and exile. Between the years 66 and
59, the orator gave a number of speeches in which he regularly
attempted to undermine his opponents. He did this by immoral
portrayal and by arguing the relevance of immorality for political
and forensic decisions. As we saw in the previous chapter, speciic
suspicious signs could be summoned to signal immorality. This
chapter will seek to further address these signs of immorality—
compromising marks of immoral character and life—by examining how Cicero utilized them in his depictions of character and
oratorical reasoning.
We have seen how a Roman orator could argue that immorality was relevant to guilt on the forensic stage. Now, new arenas
of the political culture will come into focus. Cicero’s portrayal of
Catilina took place on the Senate loor as well as in the contio,
in front of peers as well as populus. The line between forensic
and political speeches was at the same time effectively blurred as
Cicero could make use of the courts to debate political matters.
Cicero fought his battle with Catilina at every stage of the political culture.
The depiction of Catilina is an inescapable point of reference
when dealing with this era of the late Republic. The notorious
speeches against Lucius Sergius Catilina are textbook examples
of political exclusion. The looming threat of Catilina was an important part of Cicero’s political career, a phantom he returned to
again and again. The consul’s portrayal of this supposed menace
is without doubt central to understanding Roman views on immorality. The Catilinarian affair was however not the only opportunity for Cicero to depict and discuss immorality in oratory
during the decade in question. Before addressing the immoral
portrayal of the man who posed a threat to the republic, we will
return to the Roman arena of forensic duels.
Republican Politics
171
Forensic Negotiations
Immorality as an argument continued to be a prominent feature
in Cicero’s forensic oratory during the 60’s BCE. Character was
a source of persuasion; depravity and vice a foundation for a
guilty verdict. A case in point is the trial of Cluentius in 66, where
Cicero acted as defense lawyer.
The case revolved around several different issues of character.
From the outset, the defense had to deal with the problem that
Cluentius was tarnished by his reputation. This, it seems, risked
being a decisive factor for the outcome. Thus, even the fact that
Cicero felt obliged to address the sullied reputation of his client
(devoting the majority of his speech to this issue) suggests the signiicance of moral character. His strategy to deal with the problem further corroborates this importance. To defend his client’s
reputation, the orator went back eight years in time and his present client’s prosecution of the father of the man now prosecuting
him. Because Cicero’s client, Cluentius, seems to have been generally suspected of bribing the court at that time, thereby unjustly
condemning the father of the prosecutor, the point was to show
that the father was, in fact, worthy of the guilty verdict. In a sense,
he sought not only to change people’s opinion, but also the historical narrative. If confusing, Cicero still deemed it the best line
of defense, and more importantly, the issue obviously had to be
addressed.530 It is however important to note that this was not a
covert strategy. On the contrary, it was explicitly stated to the au-
530 Famously, Quintilianus records that Cicero later claimed to have thrown
dust in the eyes of the jury. Quint. Inst. 2.17.21. This has been taken as proof
that Cluentius was guilty, but the meaning is uncertain. If the issue of immorality was “the dust,” this does not diminish its importance as argument
and only means that Cicero trusted it to be effective. For the Pro Cluentio,
see Classen 1965; Kirby 1990.
172
making enemies
dience.531 But to convince his audience that the correct verdict had
been reached, Cicero did not dig up any formal evidence of the
case. To prove guilt, he instead turned to the topic of immorality.
The father of the prosecutor was a man by the name of Oppianicus, a man Cicero claimed guilty of numerous murders and
crimes. The point was to illustrate that no one could believe this
man to be anything but guilty.532 One character trait above all
dominated his portrait of this man: an unparalleled audacity.
This audacia, Cicero asserted, demanded universal hatred and
the severest of penalties and it could be observed. “Behold irst
the man’s audacity,” Cicero instructed his audience.533 Cicero,
as he had done regarding Gaius Fannius Chaerea in 77, insisted
that the wickedness (nefarium) and guilt of Oppianicus could be
clearly seen in his face.534 Moreover, all parts of his life had been
like this. He was shunned by society, hated and seen as a savage
and as a beast. His nature was monstrous and violent.535
Cicero’s portrait of immorality does more than just undermine
the memory of the target. His depiction of Oppianicus can be
read as serving to substantiate his claims. The shocking crimes
that this man had committed could be related, as Cicero explicitly said, in order to convince his audience of the truth of his
allegations.536 I imagine, he said when he had done so, that I have
now proved the charges against Oppianicus to be such that an
acquittal was impossible.537 What more, he asked, can I say about
531 Clu. 11, 30.
532 Clu. 30.
533 Clu. 23: Primum videte hominis audaciam. For audacia, see also Clu. 26–27,
29, 42, 48, 64.
534 Clu. 29.
535 Clu. 41–42, 44. Also: Clu. 170. For Cicero’s portrayal of his enemies as beasts and monsters, see May 1996.
536 Clu. 43.
537 Clu. 49.
Republican Politics
173
the character (persona) and trial of Oppianicus?538
Cicero’s approach to this case warrants further discussion.539
Without presenting any formal evidence, he proves his case by
relating the crimes and character of Oppianicus. He does not
hide this approach behind a strategy of pathos by trying to imply immorality to arouse contempt or ridicule. Oppianicus was
dead; there was no need for any derision of him. Instead, he conidently acts as though his audience will agree that immoral character could “prove” or bear witness to guilt. The crimes Cicero
recounts are all stained with immorality. Oppianicus’ audacious
crimes were driven by greed and licentiousness.540 He partook in
the immorality and extravagance of the city.541 His friends and
accomplices were depraved, known for their vices.542 The lack of
evidence might seem reprehensible or a law, but as observed by
Ann Vasaly, “ancient rhetoricians often maintained the superiority of argument over evidence.”543 According to Andrew Riggsby, character arguments clearly counted as evidence in Roman
trials.544 Because of the effectiveness of character as proof, biographical information naturally became the “facts” of the case,
rather than arguments stemming from external circumstances.545
Cicero, in representing his target as depraved and immoral, asserted his portrayal over any formal proof.
The same logic of immorality is employed by the orator later
in the speech about another man, Staienus. In the following pro538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
Clu. 59.
See also Stroh 1975, pp. 212–213.
Clu. 26–27, 28, 35.
Clu. 36.
Clu. 36, 46.
Vasaly 1993, p. 210. Cf. Arena 2007, p. 158. See also Kennedy 1972, p. 41.
Riggsby 2004, p. 177. Cf. Dixon 2001, p. 34.
May 1988, pp. 9, 16; Corbeill 2002b, p. 199; Langlands 2006, p. 315; Arena
2007, p. 150.
174
making enemies
clamation by the orator, we are reminded of the “advice” to the
jury at the trial of Sextus Roscius from Ameria:
Atque haec, iudices, quae vera dicuntur a nobis, facilius credetis,
si cum animis vestris longo intervallo recordari C. Staieni vitam et
naturam volueritis.546
And this, members of the jury, which I am truthfully relating to
you, you will more easily believe, if you agree to recollect after so
long a time the life and nature of Gaius Staienus.
For we can best, the orator continues, judge what a man will
or will not do, if we evaluate his morality (mores).547 Immorality was in other words not only a valid argument, but a crucial one. Cicero exempliied the character of Staienus as egens
(needy), sumptuous (extravagant), audax (audacious), callidus
(shrewd), and peridiosus (treacherous). He also offered his audience further signs of immorality. His house was miserable. He
had squandered his money to satisfy his lust, which led him to
embezzlement. His face, just like Oppianicus’ face, betrayed his
character.548 His persona, so notorious and transparent, led to
every suspicion of disgrace.549 In the Pro Cluentio, the connection between guilt and immorality is manifest, further illustrated
by Cicero’s simple explanation as to why a man named Bulbus
had been convicted of treason. He was a homo nequam, turpis,
improbus—a vile, shameful, and immoral man who was stained
546
547
548
549
Clu. 70.
Cf. Flac. 12. See also Clu. 159.
Clu. 68–72.
Clu. 78: Huius Staieni persona populo iam nota atque perspecta ab nulla
turpi suspicione abhorrebat.
Republican Politics
175
by depravity before ever setting foot in the court.550 The condemnation had accordingly been easy.
Another way to persuasively argue the relevance of immorality
is apparent from a speech known as Pro Flacco held several years
later. In 59, Cicero undertook the defense of Lucius Valerius Flaccus, on trial for provincial malpractice in Asia. Cicero explained
to his audience that the usual course of action when dealing with
witnesses against one’s client was either to disprove the evidence
they gave or attack their life in order to undermine their credibility.551 Since, he said, in this case the evidence did not permit
argumentation, he ought to concentrate his efforts on the latter
approach. The only problem was that the witnesses were Greek
and therefore unknown in Rome. How then could you attack a
man of whom you knew nothing? The witnesses could however
be undermined by relating their “common character” to the audience. And because the Greeks were generally characterized by a
lack of respect for witness testimony, Greek witnesses should be
regarded as unreliable.552 These particular Greek witnesses were
furthermore motivated by their cupiditas and could of course not
to be trusted with testimony against a Roman noble.553
Two aspects of the line of thought that Cicero presents here
are worthy of note. First the prominence and forthright nature
of character attack as a strategy. It was only natural to attack the
life of the witness. Without pause, Cicero admits as much. But we
may also note the sentiment that what is known about a man is
of relevance in Roman law. A man’s reputation was his cultural
550 Clu. 97.
551 Flac. 23: Nam aut oratio testium refelli solet aut vita laedi.
552 Flac. 9–12. Consult in general chapter 6 in Vasaly 1993. For Roman attitudes toward Greeks and foreigners, see e.g. Sherwin-White 1967; Petrochilos
1974; Balsdon 1979; Gruen 2006.
553 Flac. 24–27, 64. Cf. Font. 27.
176
making enemies
capital.554 This is also why it was crucial to save the tarnished
name of Cluentius.
Cicero later in the Pro Flacco used the general tactic of undermining a witness based on past life on a man by the name of
Asclepiades. This man’s shameful life (vita turpis) was enough
to justify disregarding his statements.555 He was without means,
condemned by public opinion and, like Oppianicus, distinguished
by audacia and impudentia. His inancial situation, social standing, and certain character traits were all expected to matter in a
court of law.
In sum, in the Roman courts, and in the two forensic speeches
chronologically framing the present chapter, Cicero continued to
argue his case from immoral life and immoral character. He considered it evidence of guilt and he wanted his audience to treat
it as such. Addressing his audience during his speech in defense
of Flaccus, Cicero reminded them that what separated Greeks
from Romans was that a Roman jury always found it prudent to
scrutinize mores.556 Moreover, once again we ind that Cicero’s
reasoning supports the idea that suspicion in itself carried weight
and could function as forensic argument. This shows us the importance Rome’s most successful orator attached to character,
whether as mores, natura, or persona in his defense. Character
could be shielded or sullied, depending on the situation, by signs
of immorality. The father of the prosecutor whom Cicero wanted to mark with guilt was evaluated on the basis of his life, his
nature, and his appearance. Likewise, there was a logical train of
thought to the depiction of Staienus that rendered it meaningful,
or so Cicero hoped, to his audience. The poor state of his house
554 Cultural capital is a reference to Pierre Bourdieu. See for instance Bourdieu
1983. Cf. Edwards 1993, p. 24.
555 Flac. 35.
556 Flac. 12: mores tamen exquirendos putatis.
Republican Politics
177
was a sign while his lust was a catalyst for crime. This could all be
read in his face. Thereby, certain triggers were evoked to illustrate
a morally problematic character.
From a legal standpoint, then, Cicero frequently favored a moral approach. Character, life, and inappropriate behavior igured
heavily in his court cases. The relevance was not only in clearing
his clients on the basis of the lack of immoral charges, as when
Cicero defended Sextus Roscius, or in immoral portrayal as when
he prosecuted Gaius Verres. The Pro Cluentio and Pro Flacco illustrate further uses of the immorality argument. Immorality
could be an effective argument, and argument in Roman courts
could outweigh formal proof. But what place did immorality have
in political oratory, in front of different audiences and on other
stages in the political culture?
Conspiracy and Immorality
Cicero’s career during the 60’s BCE is deined by his role in the
Catilinarian affair of 63, a notorious drama played out against
a backdrop of ierce rivalry and aristocratic competition. Cicero,
by defeating a man with a better name and nobler ancestry primarily with speeches, irst in the polls, and later in the Senate and
contio, demonstrated the power of oratory in ancient Rome.557
As a testament to the lasting power of Cicero’s words, the igure
of Catilina has captured the imagination of playwrights, artists,
557 Scholarship on the Catilinarians and the conspiracy is extensive. Standard
works include Hardy 1917; Yavetz 1963; Gruen 1969; Seager 1973; Phillips
1976; and Price 1998. Of particular relevance are Konstan 1993 for Cicero’s
rhetorical representations and strategies; Batstone 1994 for how Cicero constructs his consular ethos; and Habinek 1998 for the study of how Cicero
represents Catilina as a bandit. For the irst Catilinarian as invective, see
Craig 2007. Consult generally Drexler 1976.
178
making enemies
authors, and political commentators across the centuries.558 Catilina, more than a man of lesh and blood, has stood as a symbol
of the archetypical conspirator, or when it itted better, the revolutionary.559 The reason is Cicero’s portrayal of him.
In a series of speeches, Cicero cast Catilina as the enemy of the
state, as a man aiming to overthrow its constitution.560 Catilina
was accused of conspiring to commit massacre on Roman citizens and of having designs to burn down the city.561 The consul
strove to paint Catilina as a hostis, an enemy “whose plans and
actions had thrust him outside the pale of citizenship and the legal protection that accompanied that status.”562 Cicero, in other
words, tried not only to undermine, but also to exclude in order
that decisive action could be taken against his adversary. When
action was taken, it was fatal; after leeing Rome, Catilina was
ultimately killed in battle against his fatherland.
But conspiracy, perhaps the ultimate political transgression,
was not merely argued from a strict political or judicial perspective. The accusations against the man Cicero wanted to portray
as a threat were not just centered on his criminal acts. This is
illustrated by the following dual allegation from the irst speech
in the Senate:
Nullum iam aliquot annis facinus exstitit nisi per te, nullum
lagitium sine te.563
For years now, no crime has been committed that wasn’t
committed by you, no immoral act without you.
558
559
560
561
562
563
See Dyck 2008, pp. 13–16.
See for instance Allen Jr. 1938.
Flower 2006, p. 99.
See e.g. Cat. 1.2–3, 5, 7, 12. Also Cat. 2.6; and 3.1.
Vasaly 1993, pp. 51–52.
Cat. 1.18
Republican Politics
179
The consul’s hyperbolic statement placed immorality front and
center on the political stage. It demonstrates how it was possible
for a Roman orator to connect crime (facinus) with immoral acts
(lagitium) formed into a single attack. Hence, clearly conspiracy
and crime could be logically linked to the issue of depravity.564
Murder and destruction was then, like in the Roman courts, not
necessarily an isolated issue, but could be followed without overt
strain by the accusation of immorality. A conspirator, on the other
hand, was perhaps also of necessity immoral as surely no good
man would ever betray the res publica. The question then is who,
in the Roman mind, would? We might remind ourselves that just
as Verres’ corruption, in modern eyes, did not in any strict legal
sense require adultery, trespass against political institutions does
not beforehand demand moral transgressions. It is however possible for a cultural moral logic to encompass such a demand.
To the historian Sallustius at least, writing his Bellum Catilinae
a few decades later, beginning his narrative with details of the
conspirator’s character, his mores, was, it seems, only rational.565
Immorality could explain the course of historical events. Could it
also argue the charge of conspiracy?
As shown by the orator’s statement above, this appears to
be the case. The act of conspiracy should be seen as a political
claim, rather than an unbiased statement of fact; as an accusation presented by an antagonist. And as a political accusation it
can be backed up. Allegations charged with depravity and vice
are of course not the only possibility to corroborate such a claim,
but one, I argue, necessitated by the prominent place of morality in the common identity of the Roman elite. This analysis of
the Catilinarians therefore foregoes the charges of murder, arson,
564 See Earl 1967, p. 17.
565 Sall. Cat. 4.
180
making enemies
and destruction as well as the mention of evidence and witnesses during the course of the speeches, but looks instead at how
immorality could be summoned in order to substantiate a hard
political claim.
A part of the argument was the portrait. Cicero represented
Catilina as a villain while presenting himself as the hero. Both
these rhetorical constructions made use of Roman morality. A
moral system of which both orator and audience had knowledge gave weight to Cicero’s representations of Catilina. The
speeches against Catilina, as argued by Thomas Habinek, exempliied the willingness of the orator “to tap into the deepest
passions and fears” of what he refers to as “the Roman collective unconscious.”566 How then, using a shared understanding of
morality, could an enemy of the state be constructed in Roman
oratory through the use of immorality?
The perspective ascribes considerable inluence to oratory. An
immoral portrait does not necessarily relect reality, but it can most
deinitely inluence it. At no point in Cicero’s career is this clearer
than when he portrayed Catilina. This in turn speaks to the power
of oratory and its very real consequences. “Politics,” as David Konstan writes in reference to the Catilinarian speeches, “is control
of discourse.”567 In 63 BCE, Cicero wielded the power of consul,
enjoyed considerable auctoritas and had the command over the
arenas of political culture. In some respects, the case of Catilina is
the best argument for the power that the orator and his words had
in Roman political culture.568 A political adversary could be undermined to the extent that he had to lee the political scene.
566 Habinek 2005, p. 28.
567 Konstan 1993, p. 29.
568 Cf. Konstan 1993, p. 13: “In other words, he must decide the outcome by
his rhetoric.” Cf. Habinek 1998, p. 70: “Cicero in the Catilinarians is the existimator of his own performance, the arbiter of political, social, and ethical
Republican Politics
181
The approach to the Catilinarian affair in classical scholarship
has moved from a condemnation of the conspiracy to the opinion
that Cicero could very well have constructed much of the political
situation, emphasizing the danger and inventing parts of the enemy.569 Scholars have shown how Cicero represented his adversary
as standing outside both the political and the religious community.570 David Konstan and Ann Vasaly have furthermore both
argued that Cicero separated those inside and outside the walls
of Rome and that this “moral geography” or “moral boundary”
was crucial in determining good and evil.571 The premise of this
chapter is that, rather than playing a minor, or irrelevant, role in
the attack on Catilina, representations of immorality were part
of the puzzle of constructing him as the enemy and that part of
the success of the depiction was due to its moral aspects.572 This
oratorical weapon needed only itself and its own logic.573
One of the most famous quotations from antiquity, found in
the opening of the irst Catilinarian, furthermore suggests the importance of morality in Rome and for the orator’s task at hand.
O tempora, o mores! The times are wicked, morality corrupted.
We need not think of this as merely a turn of phrase. Cicero in the
569
570
571
572
573
divisions, and the hero of a founding myth of his own creation.” See also
Morstein-Marx 2004, pp. 14–15.
Zetzel 2009, p. 107 suggests for instance that the whole irst Catilinarian
conspiracy as well as the charges that Catilina was a brutal torturer, a sexual
deviant, and that he had murdered his relatives was fabricated by Cicero to
win him the consular election. See also Seager 1973, p. 244.
Konstan 1993, p. 13; Habinek 2005, p. 29. See also Achard 1981, pp. 117–
119.
Konstan 1993, p. 15; Vasaly 1993, pp. 52–53. See also Habinek 1998, p. 86.
For the speeches as shaped ex post facto, revised after the events had taken
place, see for instance Habinek 1998, p. 70; Zetzel 2009, p. 105. Cicero himself comments on the publication to his friend Atticus (Att. 2.1), seemingly
because there was a demand in rhetorical schools.
For this, see also Batstone 1994, p. 215: “Cicero does not prove that Catiline
is a public enemy, he assumes that fact.”
182
making enemies
Catilinarians evoked Roman morality as support of his claims.
In portraying Catilina as a conspirator, the question of morality
was inescapable.
The Mind of a Conspirator
In the year 63 BCE, Marcus Tullius Cicero the consul, standing
on the Senate loor, began his oration known as In Catilinam. The
man he charged with conspiracy against Rome was in attendance.
The result of this speech seems dificult to overestimate. It would
in the end mean exile for one of them, and death for the other.
Over the course of the speech, Cicero would describe in detail
for his audience how Catilina had plans to gather men with the
intention of attacking the city with ire and sword. Before charging Catilina with any acts of conspiracy, however, the consul
attacked his mind—a mind that could signal immorality.
In the irst few lines of the irst speech, Cicero referred to his
opponent’s furor, or madness, rage, or passion, and his audacia
effrenata, or unbridled audacity or effrontery.574 Both character
traits were portrayed as the opposite of the character of the senators for whom Cicero claimed to speak.575 The message was clear.
Catilina was a man who lacked control of his senses. The theme
was to prove prevalent. The second speech against Catilina, now
in front of the audience of a contio, similarly began by pointing
out his furor and audacia. He was labeled a homo audacissimus,
a most audacious man.576 Cicero thus presented both his audiences
with an insight into the mind of his opponent.577
574 Cat. 1.1. Furor also 1.2, 15, 22, 31; and Sull. 56. Audacia also Cat. 1.4; and
Mur. 17. For audacia and coniuratio, see also Sull. 30.
575 For the opposition between boni and furor and audacia, see Rab. perd. 4;
and Leg. agr. 2.92.
576 Cat. 2.1, 13.
577 Cf. Morstein-Marx 2004, p. 252; Gildenhard 2011, pp. 102–103.
Republican Politics
183
Why these concepts? Both audacia and furor, bold and mad
behavior were signs that the person in question was not only irrational, but also immoral. The homo audax was one of Cicero’s
character types in the Pro Roscio Amerino, a man easily conceived
of as a culprit, but he also advocated deinite links between immorality and audacity. Audaciousness was associated with un-Roman
traits such as luxury and greed and could, as in the Pro Cluentio
above, be used to argue guilt and demand the animosity and punishment of the community.578 Verres was in this way unparalleled
in his audacia—a man marked not only by his greed, desire, crime,
and immorality but also by his audacity.579 Furor was closely linked
to this type of behavior. In order for someone to be plausibly guilty
of the crime of parricide of which his client was accused, Cicero
in the Pro Roscio had expected the prosecution to show, not only
audacity but the worst kind of furor and amentia.580
Both concepts are common in Cicero as well as in Latin literature in general. In that sense, audacia and furor were standard
accusations that Cicero often found use for. As we continue our
study of Cicero’s conlicts, this will become apparent. Publius
Clodius and Marcus Antonius were both audacious and characterized by their frenzy. Their prevalence does not however explain
their prominence. In this study at least, their frequency cannot
simply be attributed to convention. I assume they had relevance
and meaning in the moral discourse at Rome.
Part of this meaning came from their associations with other
character traits. Furor and audacia were concepts that lay close
to and were often used in relation to amentia, a word Cicero also
used to describe Catilina’s mind.581 Amentia, too, could signal
578
579
580
581
Clu. 29.
Verr. 2.3.152.
Rosc. Am. 62.
Cat. 1.8.
184
making enemies
immorality and was a crucial part of Cicero’s portrait of Verres. But what form of immorality? Whereas Verres’ audacity and
insanity pointed toward his greed his extravagant behavior and
his cruelty, Catilina was not accused of avaritia or crudelitas.582
Nor is luxury, crucial in Cicero’s portraits of Chrysogonus and
Verres, emphasized in his portrait of Catilina.583 Those immoral
links are therefore disentangled in reference to him. Still the same
concepts were deemed it by the orator to explain a conspirator’s
mind. But if they were not marks of greed and luxury, what did
they signal?
One passage in the irst speech does however connect madness,
both furor and amentia, with cupiditas, which we saw was closely
tied to avaritia in the speeches against Verres:
Ibis tandem aliquando quo te iam pridem tua ista cupiditas
effrenata ac furiosa rapiebat; neque enim tibi haec res adfert
dolorem, sed quandam incredibilem voluptatem. Ad hanc te
amentiam natura peperit, voluntas exercuit, fortuna servavit.584
Finally, then, you will go where, for a long time, your uncontrolled
and insane passion has impelled you; no pain will it cause you
either, but rather a kind of unbelievable pleasure. To this madness
nature has given birth to you, your will trained you and fortune
preserved you.
582 Sallustius however makes the connection with avaritia. See Sall. Cat. 6.
Cicero describes the ensuing conlict with crudelitas in Cat. 2.28; and 3.23,
25. See also the portrait in Cael. 12–14.
583 Catilina’s associates are described with luxuria in Cat. 2.5, 11, 25. For
luxury as immoral, see also Leg. agr. 2.97.
584 Cat. 1. 25. For the link between audacia and cupiditas, see also Leg. agr.
2.37. For avaritia and cupiditas, see also Leg. agr. 1.9.
Republican Politics
185
Insane passion is here offered as a clue to the behavior of the
conspirator who has been seized and impelled (rapio) by it.585 His
mind, marked by irrationality, fury, and insanity, is furthermore a
result of his nature.586 This cupiditas, which here relates to pleasure (voluptas), rather than wealth or luxury, is the raison d’être,
the logic of Catilina’s behavior in this passage.
An interesting point of comparison that links cupiditas and
amentia exists in the Pro Cluentio. The portrait of Cluentius’
mother, Sassia is a relentless representation of female immorality.587 Sassia, who lusted for her son-in-law, tried at one point to
control her passion, her cupiditas.
deinde ita lagrare coepit amentia, sic inlammata ferri libidine, ut
eam non pudor, non pudicitia, non pietas, non macula familiae,
non hominum fama, non ilii dolor, non iliae maeror a cupiditate
revocaret.588
Soon, such madness began to blaze, carrying such inlamed lust,
that neither decency, nor modesty, nor sense of duty, nor family
disgrace, nor the reputations of a man, the pain of a son, nor the
grief of a daughter could cause her to withdraw from her passion.
Amentia and cupiditas, again clearly linked, lead to immorality.
The signiicance echoes in the irst Catilinarian as Cicero at one
point addresses his opponent:
585 See Riggsby 2004, p. 170.
586 Cf. here especially Cael. 15.
587 For invective against women, see Richlin 1984; and Santoro L’Hoir 1992,
chapter 2. See also Richlin 1992, p. 97.
588 Clu. 12.
186
making enemies
Neque enim is es, Catilina, ut te aut pudor a turpitudine aut metus
a periculo aut ratio a furore revocarit.589
You are indeed not the sort of man, Catilina, to withdraw from
disgrace because of decency, from danger because of fear, or from
madness because of reason.
There is a logic to be uncovered here. In both passages, the mental
state of the portrayed has led them into depravity. The unsound
mind is in direct conlict with virtues such as pudor (decency) or
pudicitia (modesty). Like Catilina, Sassia is impelled by her mind.
Her cupiditas and furor overcame everything: vicit pudorem libido, timorem audacia, rationem amentia—lust triumphed over
decency, audacity over timidity, and madness over rational thinking.590 The mind characterized by amentia, furor, and audacia
was, we can surmise, deemed uncontrollable. The uncontrolled
mind in turn gave way to immorality. It caused neglect of the virtues and responsibilities exempliied in the catalogue of Sassia’s
faults.
The unsound and immoral mind was easily conceived of as
guilty. In the irst and second Catilinarian, furor, amentia, and
audacia are several times associated with scelus, translatable as
wicked deeds or crime.591 Cicero moreover referred to Catilina’s
conscientia scelerum, or criminal mind or conscience.592 Cicero
gave considerable attention to these aspects of the mind. He
589 Cat. 1.22. Cf. Sull. 17.
590 Clu. 15.
591 For furor linked with scelus, see Cat. 1.15; and also Cat. 3.4; and Mur. 28;
and with scelus and audacia, Cat. 1.31. Cf. Rosc. Am. 33. For amentia and
scelus, see Cat. 1.8. Also Cat. 3.27. In the third Catilinarian (Cat. 3.16.)
Cicero holds that he had a resolution or intention (consilium) apt for crime
that his hand and tongue never wavered from. Cf. Clu. 23.
592 Cat. 1.17.
Republican Politics
187
could have just called Sassia a lustful person and claimed that
lust drove her. He could have settled with calling Catilina a criminal. But in Roman moral discourse, the state of the person’s
mind evidently mattered. Audacia, furor, and amentia signaled
immorality because they signaled lack of control.
Sallustius follows Cicero in the belief that Catilina’s mind was
an important explanation for his behavior, having, as he wrote,
an animus audax.593 He also put audacia in opposition to virtue,
and stated: Vastus animus immoderata, incredibilia, nimis alta
semper cupiebat.594 “His harsh mind always longed for the excessive, the incredible and the enormous.” The mind of Catilina,
both Cicero and Sallustius seem to argue, was crucial to understanding his behavior. To establish that, certain concepts could
be put forward in oratory as well as in the writing of history. Put
together, audacia, furor, amentia, and cupiditas gave the audience
clues to who this man was and what he was capable of. The mind
was a crucial part of the immoral pattern.
The Life of a Conspirator
Nunc vero quae tua est ista vita?595
What kind of a life is yours?
According to his chastiser, Catilina lived in a way that conirmed
his audacity.596 An immoral mind could therefore be substantiated
by an immoral life. As already shown, a common way to taint
a defendant in court with immorality was by reproaching his
life. By recollecting the life of the immoral Staienus, his trespass
593
594
595
596
Sall. Cat. 5.
Sall. Cat. 3.
Cat. 1.16.
Cat. 1.4.
188
making enemies
would be, Cicero had claimed, easier to believe. As it turns out,
so would the charge of conspiracy.
In his later work on oratory, Partitiones oratoriae, Cicero discusses vituperatio—the censure, or attack of a person in oratory.
He holds that the most important aspects of such a speech should
be to illustrate in what manner the person was born, brought up,
educated and instructed and how he is morally constituted.597
Vita, life, was of crucial concern. The logic of the inal aspect
in Cicero’s list is in itself apparent; how someone had lived his
or her life was deining of his or her morals. In Roman moral
discourse, therefore, life and moral character frequently blended
together.598 And, conversely, to illustrate immorality, the life of an
opponent was a prime target. How, then, did Cicero portray the
immoral life of Catilina, and how could this life be linked to his
conspiracy?
Politics and private life were not separated by any sharp distinction in Republican Rome. This was especially true when it
came to matters of immorality. The fragmentary speech In toga
candida, delivered as a part of the political competition in the
election to consul which Cicero subsequently won, contains a
passage which illustrates how easy it was for an orator to blend
political and private.599 Cicero addressed Catilina, at the time his
rival for the consulship, in one of the extant fragments:
Hanc tu habes dignitatem qua fretus me contemnis et despicis,
an eam quam reliqua in vita es consecutus? cum ita vixisti ut non
597 Part. or. 82: sed in toto quasi contextu orationis haec erunt illustranda maxime, quemadmodum quisque generatus, quemadmodum educatus, quemadmodum institutus moratusque fuerit.
598 See also Leg. agr. 2.95.
599 For In toga candida, see Crawford 1994, pp. 163–203. References to fragments follow her numbering. See also Steel 2011, pp. 38–42.
Republican Politics
189
esset locus tam sanctus quo non adventus tuus, etiam cum culpa
nulla subesset, crimen afferret.600
Do you possess the dignity it takes to despise and insult me, or do
you rather possess that which follows from the rest of your life?
For you have lived in such a way that there has been no place so
holy that, even if no guilt existed, your arrival there did not bring
criminal suspicion.
Domestic or private life was not only fair game in a political
contest for ofice, “the rest of your life” could be represented as
a sign of immorality and hence be invoked as grounds for exclusion from the political arena. Attacking someone took a measure
of dignity, and from the life Catilina had lived Cicero argued that
he had none. The immorality of individuals was in this way seen
as crucial to the nature of politics. And immorality was thought
to show itself in the way you lived. In his rejection of Catilina’s
life, Cicero even separates suspicion from guilt. In doing so, he
submitted that an immoral life warranted suspicion, whether or
not the person was guilty of a particular offence.601 It was not
only in the Roman courts that instances of bad behavior constituted evidence of further wrongdoing. It was true in political
logic as well.602
The parts that remain of the In toga candida are often identiied as invective, i.e. malicious personal abuse to be expected
600 Tog. cand. F18.
601 The fragment, Asconius tells us, refers to an accusation of sexual relations
with a Vestal Virgin named Fabia. According to the commentator, he added
the statement of guilt because Fabia was the sister of Cicero’s wife Terentia.
Asc. 91.19–23C.
602 Riggsby 1999, p. 169. See also May 1988, p. 52.
190
making enemies
as part of political rivalry.603 But as we have seen, exposing the
immoral life of an adversary was not just a matter of slander.
It could be made into an argument for action. The following
passage from the irst Catilinarian illustrates further the prominent place life held in political issues, also as part of deliberative
speeches.604 Cicero urged Catilina to leave the city since he was
now isolated:
in qua nemo est extra istam coniurationem perditorum hominum
qui non metuat, nemo qui non oderit. Quae nota domesticae
turpitudinis non inusta vitae tuae est? quod privatarum rerum
dedecus non haeret in fama?605
In this [city], there is no one outside that conspiracy of ruined men
who does not fear you, no one who does not hate you. What mark
of domestic debauchery is not branded on your life? What disgrace
from your private affairs does not cling to your reputation?
Moving from a general claim that Catilina had formed a conspiracy against the state, to stating that his past and present life was
characterized by depravity and disgrace, seems to have caused
the orator no dificulty. His reasoning remained sound. The isolation was a moral one. Catilina’s life—branded (inusta) by immoral signs (nota)—bore witness to his character and thus to
the allegation of conspiracy. His tarnished reputation was made
relevant to his attacker’s argument.
The signs of immorality of which the consul spoke were then
603 Crawford 1994, pp. 159–160.
604 Traditionally, the Catilinarian corpus is not identiied as invective, but as
deliberative speeches. See the discussion in Batstone 1994, pp. 218–221. Cf.
Craig 2007.
605 Cat. 1.13.
Republican Politics
191
given in detail. Catilina was marked by eyes full of lust, hands
stained with crime, and a body given over to immorality.606 Lust
(libido), crime, (facinus), and immorality (lagitium) were hence
possible to group together as illustrative of Catilina’s character.
These marks were clearly meant to show the audience of senators that Catilina was capable of this deplorable act. Not only criminal deeds, but lustful and shameful corporeal acts had bearing
on the issue. Without hesitation, Cicero then tied this immorality
back to the charge of conspiracy: “What young man that you have
ensnared with the enticement of corruption did you not provide
with a sword for his audacity or a torch for his lust?”607 By traversing the supericial line between immorality and conspiracy,
the consul effectively erased it. Lust and violence were connected.
Conspiracy and immoral life merged in the reasoning of the orator.
Another passage from the irst speech emphasized the cultural
logic of the connection between immoral signs of character and
politics:
Praetermitto ruinas fortunarum tuarum quas omnis proximis
Idibus tibi impendere senties: ad illa venio quae non ad privatam
ignominiam vitiorum tuorum, non ad domesticam tuam dificultatem ac turpitudinem, sed ad summam rem publicam atque ad
omnium nostrum vitam salutemque pertinent.608
I will pass over your inancial ruin that you will feel hanging over
you on the upcoming Ides: I come to that which does not concern
the private dishonor brought on by your vices, not the poverty and
606 Cat. 1.13: quae libido ab oculis, quod facinus a manibus umquam tuis, quod
lagitium a toto corpore afuit?
607 Cat. 1.13: cui tu adulescentulo quem corruptelarum inlecebris inretisses non
aut ad audaciam ferrum aut ad libidinem facem praetulisti?
608 Cat. 1.14.
192
making enemies
shame of your household, but to that which concerns the supreme
interest of the State and the life and safety of us all.
Here again, Cicero moved effortlessly from private marks of
shame and immorality (ignominia, turpitudo) to the threat to the
state. A sign of this domestic immorality was bankruptcy. Catilina had squandered his money. What then was the link between
inancial ruin and immorality? Why did the connection make
sense? A passage from the second Catilinarian classifying the
members of the conspiracy sheds some light on the orator’s logic.
Debt was a recurring mark not only of Catilina himself but of
the company he kept.609 The following claim fused this debt with
both immorality and murder.
Non enim iam sunt mediocres hominum libidines, non humanae et
tolerandae audaciae; nihil cogitant nisi caedem, nisi incendia, nisi
rapinas. Patrimonia sua profuderunt, fortunas suas obligaverunt;
res eos iam pridem, ides nuper deicere coepit: eadem tamen illa
quae erat in abundantia libido permanet.610
The lusts of these men are certainly no longer normal. Their audacity is no longer civilized or tolerable; they think of nothing except
murder, arson, pillage. They have spent their patrimony, their
estates are mortgaged. Money is long since gone and their credit
has lately run out; yet the lusts from when they lived in abundance
remain the same.
Cicero connects the dots for his audience; lust leads to poverty
which leads to murder, destruction, and plunder. Squandering
609 Cat. 2.8.
610 Cat. 2.10.
Republican Politics
193
your estate and patrimony therefore becomes a sign that you have
lived immorally and can, following that reasoning, be used as a
warning of future immoral and dangerous behavior including
conspiracy.611 Desire, because it was thought of as uncontrollable and insatiable, could serve as a motive for crime, just as it
did in Cicero’s attack on Chrysogonus.612 The same logic worked
on the political arena. Cicero, in his reproach on Catilina’s poor
inancial state, meant to suggest immorality. Moreover, this immorality prompted action.
In a forensic interlude between the second and third Catilinarian speech, the portrayal of immoral life was brought to the fore
in a particularly notable manner. In the midst of his endeavors to
persuade Rome of the eminent threat, Cicero opted to defend the
consul elect Lucius Murena on a charge of bribery.613 The defense
speech was however without question political in nature and was
connected to Cicero’s conlict with Catilina.614 Had Murena been
convicted, Catilina, so Cicero contended, would be next in line for
the job. The Catilinarian affair thus spilled over into the courts.
For the beneit of his audience, Cicero recapitulated in his
speech the arguments presented by the prosecution, led by the
stern moralist Cato the Younger.615 He divided it into three parts.
According to Cicero, the irst part was an attack on the life of his
client Murena, the second concerned with comparing the merits
611 See Skinner 2005, p. 211.
612 See also Clu. 68.
613 The Pro Murena is probably one of Cicero’s most studied speeches. See Kennedy 1972 for a good recapitulation of the circumstances; and Leeman 1982
for analysis of the rhetorical technique. See also Leff 1983; and Stem 2006.
614 Habinek 2005, p. 29.
615 See Ayers 1954 for an attempt to recreate Cato’s speech against Murena.
Craig 1986 examines Cicero’s use of humor and mos maiorum to undermine
the stoical authority of Cato. For Cicero’s treatment of the ethos of Cato, see
also Van der Wal 2006.
194
making enemies
of the candidates (for the consulship), while the third part dealt
with the charges of corruption. Cicero maintained that of these
three, the irst should have been most telling.616 Hence, he submitted that the life of the defendant was more important than
the actual charges against him. Cicero’s subsequent reasoning offers a valuable insight into Roman moral reasoning and demonstrates both the importance of character and the Roman regard
for proof based on it.617
We have previously encountered the orator’s professed logic
that if no charges of immoral life had been brought against his
client and no suspicions had been raised he was to be considered
innocent. Lack of suspicion of immorality could be put forward
as an argument in court. When defending Flaccus later in his career, Cicero would once again ind use for the defense tactic that
lack of suspicion and slander should infer innocence. No avaritia
in Flaccus’ private affairs could be detected, no inancial disputes
and no scandal in his private life.618 In other words, there were no
signs of immorality branding Flaccus. But what if such signs were
presented? How did Cicero approach a case where he defended a
client accused of immorality? In the Pro Murena, he was forced
to deal with the problem as it was clear from his recapitulation
that Murena had not, like Flaccus been fortunate enough to escape
moral censure.
Cicero proceeded to deliberate over the charges of immorality
brought against his client.619 Straightaway he accused the attack
616 Mur. 11: quae gravissima debeat esse.
617 For a valuable discussion of the importance of character in Pro Murena, see
May 1988, pp. 58–69.
618 Flac. 7.
619 See Ayers 1954 for a discussion of the charges Cicero responded to. Cf. the
Milan fragment of Flac.
Republican Politics
195
of being weak (inirma) and trivial (levis).620 More importantly,
it was, he said, prompted by a kind of convention (lex) among
prosecutors rather than any genuine grounds for criticism of
Murena’s life.621 It seems that character attack could indeed be
viewed as conventional (a view shared by traditional scholarship
on invective); as statements that were commonplace and did not
relate to the speciic person on trial. Yet, Cicero also makes it
clear that there was a form of moral charge that was not only
appropriate but vital.
Cicero moves to discuss the accusations themselves. The irst
point of attack seems to have been that Murena while governing
the province of Asia had lived in luxury. Cicero refuted this while
admitting that Asia carried such a stigma. But, he dictated, in order to have been effective, his client should have been reprimanded for speciic points of lagitium and dedecus, both while in Asia
or as vices that he brought back from the province. Merely proclaiming luxury in general was not, Cicero argued, enough to
convict his client of inappropriate behavior.
Secondly, Cato hade called Murena a dancer. This in itself was
not an uncommon allegation.622 It was a reproach that, if true,
Cicero admitted, was proof of a stern prosecutor but if false instead indicated an abusive slanderer.623 Here, Cicero rebuked
Cato for it. It appears moral reproach could be separated into
620 Mur. 11.
621 Mur. 11: ita fuit inirma et levis ut illos lex magis quaedam accusatoria quam
vera male dicendi facultas de vita L. Murenae dicere aliquid coegerit. See also
Rab. perd. 7–9 for accusations of immorality as unsubstantiated and weak.
622 For dancing as immoral, see Corbeill 1996, pp. 135–139. Cf. Geffcken 1973
p. 86. Cicero himself had use for this charge on a number of occasions. See
Pis. 22. He also had to defend another client against it. See Deiot. 26–28.
623 Mur. 13: Maledictum est, si vere obicitur, vehementis accusatoris, sin falso,
maledici conviciatoris.
196
making enemies
two groups.624 There was, Cicero seems to assert in the following
passage, slander or abuse and then there was the issue of morality
as central to establishing guilt:
Qua re cum ista sis auctoritate, non debes, M. Cato, adripere
maledictum ex trivio aut ex scurrarum aliquo convicio neque
temere consulem populi Romani saltatorem vocare, sed
circumspicere quibus praeterea vitiis adfectum esse necesse sit
eum cui vere istud obici possit.625
Therefore, this is beneath your dignity and you should not,
Marcus Cato, pick up slander from street corners or any of the
abuse from city-buffoons, nor at random call a consul of the
Roman people a dancer, rather you should look around for those
other vices that need to distinguish someone before he can be
truthfully presented so.
Derogatory terms, Cicero lectured his opponent, were not enough.
That was mere slander, something you ind on the street. What he
did not say, however, was that immorality was irrelevant. In fact,
Cicero never, in any of his works, states that immorality or character attack is irrelevant in oratory.626 Rather, the portrayal of
Murena as immoral needed to be substantiated by “other vices”
in order to be meaningful; vices, he furthermore maintained, that
were distinguishing traits. Immorality, in other words, corroborated immorality.
Cicero then elaborated on what it meant to be a dancer. Almost no one, he held, dances sober unless they are out of their
624 See also Cael. 6. For a discussion of the distinction, see also Merrill 1975, pp.
33–35; Corbeill 1996, pp. 17–18. Cf. Langlands 2006, p. 312.
625 Mur. 13.
626 Cf. Corbeill 1996, p. 17.
Republican Politics
197
minds. There has to be, he continued, a setup in the form of partying, dining, and certain surroundings for dancing to occur since
dancing is the last and inal thing you do at that type of event.
Thereby, he also seemed to say, it is not the dancing that is the
problem, but what it is the culmination of, what it in fact signals.
In this way, dancing presupposed, just as Corbeill has observed,
“a broader context of corruption.”627 What then are these other
vices? Cicero turned to Cato again.
Tu mihi adripis hoc quod necesse est omnium vitiorum esse
postremum, relinquis illa quibus remotis hoc vitium omnino esse
non potest? Nullum turpe convivium, non amor, non comissatio,
non libido, non sumptus ostenditur, et, cum ea non reperiantur
quae voluptatis nomen habent quamquam vitiosa sunt, in quo
ipsam luxuriam reperire non potes, in eo te umbram luxuriae
reperturum putas?628
You are seizing upon what is necessarily the last of all vices, but
leave out those without which this vice cannot exist? You have
given evidence of no disgraceful banquets, no love-making, no
revelry, no lust, no extravagance, and since that cannot be found
which goes by the name of pleasure but is really vice, do you really
think you can ind the shadow of luxury, where you cannot ind
the substance of luxury?
Returning to the banquet as the scene of immorality, Cicero exempliies how the presence of one vice pointed toward others.
This, then, is the importance of displaying for the audience signs
of immorality in an adversary. The banquet is a place of immoral
627 Corbeill 1996, p. 138. Also Corbeill 2002b, p. 203. Cf. Earl 1967, p. 20.
628 Mur. 13.
198
making enemies
love affairs, excessive drunkenness, and provocative luxury. Here
Cicero rhetorically sets up an internal correlation between vices,
thereby revealing what I have referred to as a web of immorality. Drunkenness, sex, and extravagance were cognate signs of
depravity, one meaningful in relation to the other. Settings and
scenery were thereby thought to brand a person’s character with
immorality. Lastly, the correlation between suspicion and reality
must here be emphasized. If there was no substance of immorality, there was no shadow of it. This however, also meant that the
opposite was true. Signs of immorality were crucial to establish
its existence.
The passages directed at the prosecutor could be read as demonstrating that Cato’s attacks were not grounded enough, that
his accusations, in the view of his opponent, lacked the substance
to make them persuasive. The reasoning, Cicero objected, was
not sound. It did not follow the cultural logic of immorality—
that vices and depravity were interconnected. To dance was not
necessarily a cause for moral judgment on its own. Unless backed
up, it was just slander. An orator could in this way maintain that
there existed a causality of immorality. Dancing was deplorable
and telling of character only insofar that it was linked to other
vices and character laws. Suggesting these links of meaning then
was of tremendous importance and the task of the orator. Argumentation, whereby the orator suggested and illustrated these
links, in turn counted as evidence.
Cicero undeniably used this reasoning as a way of delecting
the attacks on his client’s life and therefore the interpretation suited him. It is most certainly a rhetorical strategy. We cannot know
whether the audience had already been swayed by the mere statement of dancing, nor indeed if Cato’s accusation was as “unsubstantiated” as Cicero alleged. Nonetheless, the fact that Cicero
could employ similar reasoning as though everybody agreed with
Republican Politics
199
its rationality is signiicant. The fact that he could separate slander
from signs of immorality is telling. And furthermore, as Corbeill
has pointed out, both orators presumed that the motif of dancing
implicated Murena in the other vices that followed and that this
would in turn show that Murena, guilty of immorality, was also
guilty of electoral corruption.629 The passages consequently indicate that arguments drawn from morality were not only signiicant but negotiable within Roman culture; they also show that
these negotiations rested on certain dominant themes agreed upon
by the community. It was not only a rhetorical strategy, but a form
of oratorical argumentation.
Since Cato has failed to set his image of the dancer up by producing signs of immorality, nothing then could be said about
Murena’s private life. Content with this, Cicero presented his line
of defense to his audience. “My defense of the consul-designate
is that there is no deceit, no greed, no treachery, no cruelty and
no offensive language that can be found in his life.”630 The list of
positive character traits might seem surprising. The moral laws
referenced by Cicero are not obviously correlated to the previous
line of reasoning. The immoral traits of the banquet connected to
the accusation of being a dancer were luxury, immoderate consumption, and illicit love-making. We may take note, however,
that the honorable traits enumerated by the defense councilor are
those that would logically be under scrutiny for someone accused
of bribery. They are traits valued in a political culture. The logic
of this “irrational” step is striking. Cicero wanted his audience to
relect on the lack of immoral suspicion and delect those signs
of immorality that the prosecution had in fact attempted. And
629 Corbeill 1996, p. 138.
630 Mur. 14: Sic a me consul designatus defenditur ut eius nulla fraus, nulla
avaritia, nulla peridia, nulla crudelitas, nullum petulans dictum in vita proferatur.
200
making enemies
after doing so he could securely arrive at the political character
traits that he wanted to emphasize, whether or not they mirrored
the immoral traits signaled by Cato’s prosecution. A vir bonus
was deined by the absence of immorality just as much as speciic
traits of morality, good only insofar as immorality did not cling
to his reputation.631
The following year, Murena was consul. Catilina had been killed on the battleield. But the ripples of the Catilinarian affair had
just begun. Several of the accused conspirators were rounded up
and charged with political violence under the lex Plautia de vi.
Despite his role in the affair, Cicero defended one of the accused
conspirators, Publius Cornelius Sulla. As always, his strategy was
multifaceted, but this time he saved the best for last. The last
line of defense was simple enough: Sulla’s character (persona) did
not admit accusations of such serious and atrocious crimes.632
He thereby effectively made reverse use of the logic. Through
immorality and vice Catilina could be shown to be a conspirator.
Sulla, because he lacked such signs, could be proven innocent of
the same charge. To his audience, he then presented a chain of
reasoning that conirms the place of morality, character, and life
in Roman courts and society at large:
Omnibus in rebus, iudices, quae graviores maioresque sunt, quid
quisque voluerit, cogitarit, admiserit, non ex crimine, sed ex
moribus eius qui arguitur est ponderandum. Neque enim potest
quisquam nostrum subito ingi neque cuiusquam repente vita
mutari aut natura converti.633
631 See also Gildenhard 2011, p. 80.
632 Sull. 69.
633 Sull. 69.
Republican Politics
201
In any matter, gentlemen, that is more serious and important, what
someone has wanted, thought or committed, should be judged, not
by the charges, but by the morality of the accused. Because none
of us are shaped in an instant, nor can anyone’s life suddenly be
changed or nature altered.
With the irst part of this statement, Cicero proclaims that mores—
morality or moral character—is to be the most important aspect
when evaluating a person on trial.634 We are again reminded of
Staienus in the trial against Cluentius in 66. Morality exposes not
only the deeds committed, but the mind of the accused, his intentions and wishes. It is for that reason proper to gauge someone’s
moral character in order to get at the truth. The second part of the
statement is crucial to understanding the reason for this contention. Morality, as we have seen, was demonstrated and proven by
actions taken in life. The logic behind this is here given by Cicero;
past life cannot be changed on a whim; nature cannot be altered
when convenient. The notion, although circular—morality and
nature give actions in life and actions in life give morality and
nature—nevertheless strongly suggests that the Romans believed
that past actions could determine character and that character
determined guilt. In particular this was true in matters of immorality. This is a cultural idea with its own cultural logic. This logic
stated that because morality and immorality were decisive factors
in a person’s life and actions, they could be predicted.635 A moral
man is bound to perform moral acts while an immoral man can
only be expected to act immorally.
Whether or not the Romans thought of character as being ixed,
at least in a person’s adult life, has been a question in recent
634 For this passage, see Riggsby 2004. See also Sull. 79.
635 Cf. Riggsby 2004, p. 177.
202
making enemies
scholarship, and several scholars have argued for the view that
morality and ways of life were seen by the Romans as internal
and natural parts of character that could, almost genetically, be
passed on through generations.636 Therefore, an individual’s actions in the past could be seen as “manifestations of a ixed and
determining character” and could be presented as predicting his
present and future character.637 Admittedly, the issue was up for
contestation. The defense could and should always argue contrary to the prosecution, for instance that the past was irrelevant or
that committing another crime did not prove the present one.638
As we have seen, character and past life could be argued and
debated as part of a political or forensic contest, but they were
nevertheless intimately linked in the Roman mind.
In his defense of Sulla, Cicero presumed with this statement
that his audience shared a belief in the rigidity of character.639
This furthermore allowed him to proceed in analyzing the character of the conspirators among whom his client should not be
counted. The main villain himself was irst:
Catilina contra rem publicam coniuravit. Cuius aures umquam
haec respuerunt, conatum esse audacter hominem a pueritia non
solum intemperantia et scelere sed etiam consuetudine et studio in
omni lagitio, stupro, caede versatum?640
636 Wallace-Hadrill 1997, p. 8. Further arguments by May 1988, pp. 6–7. See
also Corbeill 1996, pp. 76–77; Gildenhard 2011, pp. 62–63; van der Blom
2011, pp. 57–58.
637 Riggsby 2004, p. 177; and see also p. 179: “there appears to have been
widespread belief in the predicative power of character as revealed in past
actions.” See also May 1988, pp. 78–79, 163.
638 Inv. rhet. 2.50.
639 May 1988, p. 75; Riggsby 2004.
640 Sull. 70.
Republican Politics
203
Catilina conspired against the state. Whose ears have ever
rejected that an audacious attempt was made by a man who from
boyhood was not only unrestrained and criminal, but from habits
and schooling involved in every sort of immorality, foul sexual
deeds, and murder.
We can without dificulty follow the moral-cultural logic of the
reproach on Catilina’s past. Who would disbelieve that Catilina
had conspired against the state when his immoral boyhood so
clearly pointed in that direction? He was born for conspiracy,
or as Cicero referred to it: banditry (latrocinium).641 Flagitium
and sexual immorality, stuprum, were here in an unproblematic
fashion linked with murder and helped corroborate the act of political trespass. They are all immoral deeds in Catilina’s past that
explained his actions. His sexual corruption was by no means
irrelevant, but rather only a logical step away. Cicero presented
the reasoning in such a way as to suggest that he was destined to
revolt against his fatherland.
In the previous chapter we encountered the cultural belief that
immorality often started in the youth of a Roman.642 Verres had
been corrupted at an early age, which in turn explained his deviant behavior and pointed toward his guilt. In Pro Sulla, Cicero
paints the following vivid picture of the conspirators:
Nova quaedam illa immanitas exorta est, incredibilis fuit ac
singularis furor, ex multis ab adulescentia conlectis perditorum
hominum vitiis repente ista tanta importunitas inauditi sceleris
exarsit.643
641 For Cicero’s use of latrocinium to deine the conspiracy, see Habinek 1998,
pp. 69–87.
642 See also the depiction of Manlius in Clu. 39.
643 Sull. 75.
204
making enemies
It was a new kind of monstrosity that sprang forth; it was an
extraordinary and unparalleled madness that out of a large
collection of vices from the youth of abandoned men that this
crime, so insolent and unheard of, swiftly blazed.
The origin of the conspiracy could be found in the immoral
youth of abandoned men. As in Cicero’s defense of Murena, he
held that this youth had been distinguished by not just one inappropriate aspect but “a large collection of vices” and again it was
naturally linked to a quality of the mind, furor. A corrupted life
pointed toward guilt. Immorality pointed toward crime.
About another conspirator, Lentulus, the orator presented another logical pattern based on past life:
Quis Lentuli societates cum indicibus, quis insaniam libidinum,
quis perversam atque impiam religionem recordatur qui illum aut
nefarie cogitasse aut stulte sperasse miretur?644
Who, that remembers Lentulus’ relationship with informers, his
insane lust, his perverted and impious beliefs, is surprised at the
wickedness of his plots or the stupidity of his desires?
The past was proof for the orator in Republican Rome. The
wrong type of relations, “insane lust,” and deviant beliefs could
be made into signs that someone might conspire. All the conspirators, Cicero pointedly observes, were convicted by their own
lives before the community’s suspicions passed its verdict.645
Like Verres, the conspirators were condemned beforehand by
their immorality. The orator exempliies with a conspirator
644 Sull. 71.
645 Sull. 71.
Republican Politics
205
named Autronius. Was he not, he asks, convicted by his life and
natura?
Semper audax, petulans, libidinosus; quem in stuprorum
defensionibus non solum verbis uti improbissimis solitum esse
scimus verum etiam pugnis et calcibus, quem exturbare homines
ex possessionibus, caedem facere vicinorum, spoliare fana
sociorum, comitatu et armis distubare iudicia, in bonis rebus
omnis contemnere, in malis pugnare contra bonos, non rei
publicae cedere, non fortunae ipsi succumbere.646
Always audacious, impudent, lustful; who in his defense of foul
sexual deeds not only used foul language, but we know used ists
and feet, who drove men from their properties, murdered his
neighbors, ravaged the altars of the allies, threw justice into
disorder with gangs and weapons, in good times despised
everyone, in bad times fought against good men, never to bow
to the public good or yield to Fortune herself.
This man would be convicted by his life and mores whether or
not the most obvious facts could prove his case.647 Autronius was,
just like Catilina, audacious and lustful and sexually corrupted,
marked by stuprum. He stood clearly in opposition to the good
of society, posing a serious threat to it. “Facts” are dismissed here
by the orator as being less important than the tarnished reputation and sullied life of Autronius. Morality was more important.
Cicero then compared this life with the life of his client and
enumerated his qualities. In a man deined by such modesty (pudor)
646 Sull. 71.
647 Sull. 71: Huius si causa non manifestissimis rebus teneretur, tamen eum mores ipsius ac vita convinceret.
206
making enemies
and such a life, there could be no place for such an enormous crime
as conspiracy.648 Cicero pleaded for the jury to examine his client’s
appearance and compare the charge with the life led from beginning to the present. Just as with Sextus Roscius, the deed and the
character simply did not match.
Non, inquam, cadit in hos mores, non in hunc pudorem, non in
hanc vitam, non in hunc hominem ista suspicio.649
Such suspicion, I say, does not correspond to his morality, not with
such modesty, not with his life, not with a man like him.
The life of Sulla freed him according to the oratorical reasoning
of his advocate. This was clearly as it should be, as Cicero ends
his line of reasoning by asking: if your life does not help you in
times like these, when will it? What is the use of a good life, if it
does not serve you when under moral attack?650 One could also
argue, Cicero says in his rhetorical treatise De inventione, that it
is an offense to every good man that a life of honor should not be
the greatest possible help to him when faced with an accusation,
since the accusation could be made up, while the past cannot be
made up or changed when suited.651 In this view, moral character
is manifest. Sulla, in Cicero’s portrayal, had no signs of immorality that could substantiate the judicial charge. The conspirators
did. If you look into the minds of the conspirators, Cicero again
making the connection, you will ind this immorality: lust (lididines), depravity (lagitium), foulness (turpitudines), audacity
648 Sull. 74: In hoc vos pudore, iudices, et in hac vita tanto sceleri locum fuisse
credatis?
649 Sull. 75.
650 Sull. 77.
651 Inv. rhet. 2.36.
Republican Politics
207
(audacia), and madness (furor). But, importantly, you would also
ind, the orator claimed, evidence of wrongdoing: stains of wickedness, (notas facinorum), proof of parricide (indicia parricidiorum), and heaps of crime (acervos scelerum).652 These aspects of
their morality were what led them to violence. Their immoral
lives led them to conspiracy.
The Company of a Conspirator
An accusation of conspiracy by necessity demands more than one
culprit. As we saw above, Catilina was not alone. In fact, as the
drama unfolded, Cicero focused his efforts more and more on the
accomplices left behind by the leeing patrician. Several of these
conspirators were in turn named, portrayed as immoral, and executed by the consul.653
But the key igures of the conspiracy were not the only villains
in Cicero’s narrative. In fact, the consul reported to his audiences
in great detail the nature of Catilina’s followers and supporters,
the portrayal of whom in effect tainted Catilina himself. Following mind and past life, we will therefore now turn to a third
way to argue immorality in Roman oratory; immoral company.
A man’s friends and associations could in ancient Rome reveal
to the community who he was.654 What, then, were the moral
stigmas that were branded on the people surrounding Catilina
and what logic was used to paint them, and through guilt by association Catilina, as morally corrupt?
In the irst Catilinarian, Cicero famously describes how the
seats next to Catilina were vacated by his peers upon his arrival
652 Sull. 76.
653 See e.g. Cat. 3.16, 25; and Cat. 4. 11–12. For their immorality (improbitas),
see Cat. 3.7, 11, 28.
654 For company as “sign,” see also Rosc. Am. 68; Leg. agr. 1.22.
208
making enemies
in the Senate chamber.655 The trick of course, was to show that,
rather than the member of the elite his lineage advocated, Catilina was an isolated deviant.656 Cicero represented him as the
leader of the desperate, those who have lost all hope.657 But separating Catilina from the body of good men was also achieved
by moral argument. Among the feasting and revelry of Catilina’s
friends, no vir bonus will be either seen or heard.658 In the second
speech against Catilina, the immoral segments of society supporting conspiracy take center stage as the consul painstakingly
catalogues those who are intimate with the supposed enemy of
the state:
Quis tota Italia veneicus, quis gladiator, quis latro, quis sicarius,
quis parricida, quis testamentorum subiector, quis circumscriptor,
quis ganeo, quis nepos, quis adulter, quae mulier infamis, quis
corruptor iuventutis, quis curruptus, quis perditus inveniri potest
qui cum Catlilina non familiarissime vixisse fateatur?659
In the whole of Italy, what poisoner, what gladiator, what bandit,
what assassin, what parricide, what forger of wills, what swindler,
what glutton, what spendthrift, what adulterer, what dishonorable
woman, what corruptor of youth, what corrupted and what ruined
man can be found, who cannot be shown to have lived intimately
with Catilina?
655
656
657
658
Cat. 1.16. Also Cat. 2.12; and Cat. 3.17.
For moral isolation, see also Clu. 170.
Cat. 1.23, 25.
Cat. 1.26: Hic tu qua laetitia perfruere, quibus gaudiis exsultabis, quanta
in voluptare bacchabere, cum in tanto numero tuorum neque audies virum
bonum quemquam neque videbis!
659 Cat. 2.7.
Republican Politics
209
Not unlike Cicero’s archetypes in the Pro Roscio Amerino, in
this inventory we are offered several immoral stereotypes. These
were the supporters of conspiracy and followers of Catilina. It
is important to note that many of these stereotypes were irst
and foremost immoral in nature and that what a modern reader
would likely see as “actual” criminals are rounded up alongside
these moral transgressors. Murderers, bandits, and swindlers are
placed right next to gluttons, adulterers, and dishonorable men
and women, indicating that no sharp distinction was felt to be
needed. The logic of such an apparent variety and range in the
catalogue of conspirators seems to be that immoral people committed crime and, conversely, that criminals are also guilty of depravity. One pointed toward the other. Moral transgressors either
already were “actual” criminals, to allow the modern distinction,
or would soon enough be corrupted enough to become criminals.
In this, forensic rhetoric and political oratory evidently blended
together.
What, then, is the nature of the immorality portrayed in these
depraved characters? We ind, beside the criminals who no doubt
are meant to signal the physical danger of the conspiracy, disreputable characters of the city. The ganeo for instance was a person
known for revelry and pleasure. There are also the inancially destitute, the forgers and spendthrifts.660 Perhaps most noteworthy,
however, is the inclusion of the sexually dishonored. In Catilina’s
midst, Cicero’s audience should expect to ind the adulterer, the
corrupter of youths, the corruptus and the disreputable woman
(mulier infamis). Sexually disgraceful characters hence could be
used to taint Catilina and his conspiracy with sexual immorality
and in this manner, Cicero evoked, through the use of company,
different dimensions of the depravity on display. Furthermore,
660 For spendthrifts, see also Leg. agr. 1.2, 7. Cf. Flac. 90.
210
making enemies
through his followers, links between immorality and Catilina’s
conspiracy were effectively created.
Another passage further blends immorality and criminal intent
while depicting the segments that rallied to Catilina’s cause as
Cicero returns to the scene of the banquet:
Quod si in vino et alea comissationes solum et scorta quaererent,
essent illi quidem desperandi, sed tamen essent ferendi: hoc vero
quis ferre possit, inertis homines fortissimis viris insidiari,
stultissimos prudentissimis, ebrios sobriis, dormientis vigilantibus?
qui mihi accubantes in conviviis, complexi mulieres impudicas,
vino languidi, conferti cibo, sertis redimiti, unguentis obliti,
debilitati stupris eructant sermonibus suis caedem bonorum
atque urbis incendia.661
If they in their drunkenness and gambling only sought revelry and
whores, they would indeed be beyond hope, but still tolerable:
but who can tolerate when lazy weaklings plot against honorable
men, fools against wise men, drunkards against the sober, or the
lethargic against the watchful? They who, say I, recline at their
banquets, embracing their impure women, dull from wine, stuffed
with food, garlands bound on their head, reeking of perfume,
weak from debauchery they vomit forth in their conversation the
murder of the highest of state and the burning of the city.
The line drawn between the good and bad of society in this passage is above all else a moral line.662 The immorality of the conspirators is here by Cicero adamantly demonstrated before the
661 Cat. 2.10.
662 For these categories in Cicero’s oratory, see in particular Gildenhard 2011,
chapter 3.
Republican Politics
211
audience of the contio; signaled by motifs such as drunkenness,
gambling and prostitution. The immoral are distinguished by
inertia, laziness and lethargy, antithetical to the honorable and
wise.663 They consort with mulieres impudicas, impure women
and eat and drink in abundance. They are recognized by the use
of perfume and the wearing of garlands.
We should not too eagerly dismiss this moral contrast as caricature. The scene presented by the consul does not aim at mere ridicule or conservative scorn but moves resolutely from immorality
to murder and arson. The danger and the immorality are clearly
connected. The depravity of the conspirators is a threat. The difference between moral and immoral, between good and bad is forcefully underlined in the following enumeration of vice and virtue:
Ex hac enim parte pudor pugnat, illinc petulantia; hinc pudicitia,
illinc stuprum; hinc ides, illinc fraudatio; hinc pietas, illinc scelus;
hinc constantia, illinc furor; hinc honestas, illinc turpitudo; hinc
continentia, illinc libido; hinc denique aequitas, temperantia,
fortitudo, prudentia, virtutes omnes certant cum iniquitate,
luxuria, ignavia, temeritate, cum vitiis omnibus, […], conligit.664
On this side ights modesty, on their side impudence; on this side
pudicitia, on theirs stuprum; on this side faithfulness, on theirs
fraud; on this side sense of duty, on theirs crime; on this side
irmness, on theirs furor; on this side honor, on their side dishonor;
on our side restraint, on theirs lust; and on this side inally
consistency, temperance, fortitude, prudence, certainly all of
the virtues, are with inequity, luxury, idleness, rashness, with all
vices, […], at war.
663 For inertia, see also Leg. agr. 2.103.
664 Cat. 2.25.
212
making enemies
There is a war with immorality, and virtue and vice are on opposite sides. The consul here reiterates his distinction between
good and bad using moral dichotomies. Constantia or irmness
is placed opposite furor, madness or fury. Restraint is the virtue
contrasted with libido or lust. Luxury and idleness go hand in
hand. Cicero had at one point referred to Verres precisely as a
homo singulari luxuria atque inertia.665 Cicero is again adamant
that the conspirators were not only criminals, but immoral men.
There is no reason he would do this unless it made sense. The
entertaining of a crude audience does not sufice to explain his
emphasis on these marks of immorality. But, the depravity of the
conspirators that Cicero portrays would have made perfect sense
if a conspirator against Rome by deinition was seen immoral.
That this is not just deplorable behavior is also shown by the
consul’s statement that these men have rightful punishment waiting
for them for their improbitas, their nequitia, their scelus, and their
libido.666 Just like Catilina, they have lived a life that has avoided
rightful retribution.667 A life of vice demanded punishment.
Immoral company remains a persistent topic in the second Catilinarian, as Cicero continues to describe the different groups that
for various reasons rallied to Catilina’s lag. Some are heavily in
debt or seek the power of ofice guided by their furor.668 Other
groups are comprised of those who have gotten used to luxury
and lavishness. Another collection of men that cannot be separated
from Catilina are the criminals and the assassins. Those closest to
Catilina reside in the last group. They are the ones Cicero is most
concerned about and describes in greatest detail. This group is last
not only in number but also in character (genus) and life:
665
666
667
668
Verr. 2.1.34.
Cat. 1.11.
Cat. 1.20.
Cat. 2.19.
Republican Politics
213
Quos pexo capillo, nitidos, aut imberbis aut bene barbatos
videtis, manicatis et talaribus tunicis, velis amictos, non togis:
quorum omnis industria vitae et vigilandi labor in antelucanis
cenis expromitur. In his gregibus omnes aleatores, omnes adulteri,
omnes impuri impudicique versantur. Hi pueri tam lepidi ac
delicati non solum amare et amari neque saltare et cantare sed
etiam sicas vibrare et spargere venena didicerunt.669
They are the ones you see with combed hair, groomed, either
beardless or with a full beard, with tunics down to their wrists
and ankles, wrapped up in dresses, not togas; whose energy in
life and labors while awake are all devoted to banquets that last
until dawn. In this lock all the gamblers, all the adulterers, all the
impure and sexually deiled men are to be found. These boys, so
charming and effeminate, have learnt not only to love or be
loved, nor only to dance and sing, but also to brandish daggers
and distribute poison.
The most important of Catilina’s followers are also the most morally corrupted. This portrayal is closely related to their manliness
and their sexuality. First and foremost it is their appearance, represented as delicate and feminine, that betrays their depravity and
demonstrates their deviant position. The second aspect that shows
immorality is the feast that lasts all night and that depletes the
energy of these men. The comment about beards also signals that
some are younger while others are old men. This alludes to improper sexual liaisons and the corruption of youth. This is further
strengthened by the inclusion of the impudicus in the list of the
depraved. The word denoted a man who had lost his sexual integ-
669 Cat. 2.22.
214
making enemies
rity, who had lost his pudicitia—his chastity.670 These young boys
have been schooled in servicing the pleasures of others and here
the link between sexual acts and singing and dancing becomes crucial. Dancing, which Cato had cast in the teeth of Cicero’s client
Murena, not only established the association with the sexual debauchery that the feast represented, but meant that someone was
delightful and amusing to others. This was degrading and directly
related to immorality. This portrayal of Catilina’s intimate friends
might at irst seem like mere mockery attempting to humiliate. But
the orator in the last part of the passage returns to the danger
that this immorality poses. We might instead see this as the main
point of the portrayal. Their depravity is not meant as an amusing distraction, nor as mere slander, but as conirmation to the
audience that this conspiracy was a real threat. Cicero evoked the
scene of the banquet frequented by these effeminate youths only to
end up back in conspiracy and murder. Hence, in oratory, political
accusations could be corroborated by sexual immorality. This was
possible because the logic of immorality on which Cicero’s oratory
relied stated that moral and amoral offences overlapped or even
that there was no such thing as an amoral offence. In any case
the distinction could be comfortably ignored. This allowed him to
present Catilina’s corrupting of Roman youth as at the same time
proof of sexual immorality and criminal behavior:
Iam vero quae tanta umquam in ullo iuventutus inlecebra fuit
quanta in illo? Qui alios ipse amabat turpissime, aliorum amori
lagitiosissime serviebat, aliis fructum libidinum, aliis mortem parentum, non modo impellendo verum etiam adiuvando pollicebatur.671
670 For impudicus, see also Sall. Cat. 14.2. For aleo and impudicus, cf. Catull.
29.2.
671 Cat. 2.8. Cf. the portrait of Avillius in Clu. 36.
Republican Politics
215
Who indeed at any time gave so many temptations to young men
as he did? Some of them he himself loved most disgracefully,
others’ love he serviced most shamefully. To some he promised the
satisfaction of their lust, to others the death of their parents, not
only impelling them, but indeed by assisting.
The portrayal forcefully argued that Catilina was a sexual deviant who corrupted some while taking on a sexually passive role
with others. This is explicitly referred to as lagitiosissime, most
immoral and shameful, while his love of others likewise is dubbed turpissime, most foul and disgraceful. Both roles—the corrupter and the corrupted—were in other words clearly identiied
as immoral. But, again, Cicero does not stop with portraying this
sexual immorality. He connects it to a heinous criminal act: the
murder of one’s parents. Immorality once again functions to substantiate criminal behavior.
The sexual corruption of Roman youths was a powerful cultural anxiety in ancient Rome. The freeborn male youth, as pointed out by Jonathan Walters, occupied an ambivalent position in
Roman public discourse.672 He was not yet a vir because conceptions of maleness did not just revolve around gender.673 The
concept denoted “those adult males who are freeborn citizens in
good standing.”674 If subjected to sexual submission, which meant
taking the female role, a young man would risk not developing
into a proper man.675 Cicero pointedly refers to one of the alleged conspirators, Tongilius, who he claimed had been Catilina’s
lover ever since Tongilius was a boy, a praetextatus.676 This claim
672
673
674
675
676
Walters 1997, p. 33.
Gleason 1995, p. 162.
Walters 1997, p. 32.
See also Cantarella 1992, pp. 116, 218; and Sissa 2008, p. 162.
Cat. 2.4. Not more than sixteen.
216
making enemies
struck at the immorality of both men; Tongilius for losing his
sexual integrity and Catilina for corrupting it. One of the aspects
of being a Roman vir, was, Walters argues, his impenetrability,
a corporeal inviolability that separated him from lower classes
and slaves.677 Part of it was respectability and this respectability
then could be tainted. This in turn could be suggested by political
opponents in order to undermine their status as vir.
That this was not only rhetorical trickery or crude oratorical
entertainment is clear from the work of Sallustius. He also saw
this motif of unmanliness as an important factor in the Catilinarian conspiracy of which he wrote. To him it was all linked to
wealth, to avaritia and luxuria. As soon as these immoral things
were regarded as honorable, young men disregarded modesty
(pudor) and their chastity or sexual integrity (pudicitia); virtues
which we saw above were characteristic of the moral man.678
Luxury anticipated this because of the self-indulgence that followed it.
Sed lubido stupri, ganeae ceterique cultus non minor incesserat;
viri muliebria pati, mulieres pudicitiam in propatulo habere.679
But the desire for stuprum, gluttony and other such manners of
life had been advanced to no smaller degree; men endured the
woman’s role, women made their chastity available in public.
677 Walters 1997, p. 30. See also Corbeill 1996, p. 147; Fredrick 2002a, p. 237;
and Skinner 2005, p. 195: “The body of the Roman vir, the adult citizen
male, was regarded as inviolable, legally protected from sexual penetration,
beating, and torture.”
678 Sall. Cat. 12.2.
679 Sall. Cat. 13.3.
Republican Politics
217
In Sallustius’ narrative, where “moral depravity manifests itself through a perversion of natural appetites,” a moral logic is
visible.680 Immorality had causality. Un-Roman vices such as
luxury led to a decline in morality, betrayed by the loss of male
and female sexual integrity. Men’s sexual appetites became effectively perverted.681 They accepted a passive role akin to that of the
woman. Women on the other hand gave up their perhaps most
valued possession in a patriarchic society, their pudicitia.
The logic of attacking someone’s sexual integrity, tied as it
was to notions of masculinity, is made abundantly clear. Catilina
is here accused of servicing these young men, casting him in a
sexually passive role and as effeminate. This was not just ridicule.682 This was a serious blow to his status as a vir. But it was
not merely shameful. It made sense. Cicero’s careful depiction of
the company of Catilina illustrates that the “facts” of conspiracy
were not relevant without moral condemnation. A conspirator
was immoral by default and the way Cicero chose to forcefully demonstrate this immorality in his oratory was through the
theme of corrupted sexuality. This was easily conceived of as a
threat, because this logic furthermore stated that the corrupted
also corrupts others. It was in other words crucial that Catilina
himself was also sexually depraved—a passive, corrupt and immoral man—as this “proved” that he would in turn corrupt the
group in society most valuable and most vulnerable: the male
youths. Both sexual corruption of youths and submitting to the
receptive role in intercourse was referred to as stuprum, a powerful signal of immorality in Rome.
680 Skinner 2005, p. 198.
681 See Parker 1998, p. 56.
682 For the dangers of effeminacy, see also Corbeill 1996, pp. 143–146.
218
making enemies
The Question of Stuprum
In ancient Rome, certain sexual acts were deemed disgraceful and
contrary to Roman tradition and morality. These acts fell under
the concept of stuprum.683 We have already encountered stuprum
as a powerful signal of immorality. But what did it entail?
The word itself is nearly impossible to translate with precision. Originally it referred to any disgrace committed in public,
but in Cicero’s time stuprum denoted speciically a shameful and
reprehensible sexual activity or intercourse.684 It was, as noted by
Williams, in characteristic Roman fashion, open both to moral
and legal condemnation, any distinction thereby effectively blurred.685 From a Roman perspective, stuprum was illicit in the sense
of not being approved by the community and accompanied by
social stigma, but it was also prohibited, subject to criminal prosecution.686
As previously discussed, sexual immorality in ancient Rome
was not a question of homosexuality vs. heterosexuality, but
of the dichotomy between active and passive.687 In regard to
stuprum then, victim and perpetrator could be of either sex,
meaning that gender was not the issue of concern. Instead, what
decided whether a sexual act was considered stuprum or not was
683 For scholarship on stuprum, see Gardner 1986; Fantham 1991; Langlands
2006; and Williams 2010, in particular pp. 103–126. Consult also Adams
1982, pp. 200–201.
684 Festus 418.8–18.
685 Williams 2010, p. 104. Cf. McGinn 1998, p. 345.
686 Probably under the Lex Scatinia (or Scantinia). See Lilja 1983, pp. 112–121;
Cantarella 1992, pp. 106–114 and 2005; Ryan 1994; Williams 2010. See
also Quint. Inst. 4.2.69. Legal repression of stuprum came through the Lex
Iulia de adulteriis during the principate.
687 Nor was sexual preference—as long as the male was active—necessarily
an issue. See Skinner 2005, p. 213. See also Cantarella 2005, p. 9. Contra:
Butrica 2005, p. 221.
Republican Politics
219
the status of the penetrated, i.e. passive party. The often quoted
Curculio by Plautus illustrates the premise: “as long as you keep
away from the bride, the widow, the virgin, the young man, and
freeborn boys, love whatever you please.”688 Stuprum indicated
a sexual violation of a freeborn person and the corruption of
that person’s pudicitia, or sexual integrity. It can therefore be
deined also as a social transgression that “violated traditional
standards of propriety.”689 Stuprum also marked “the spoiling of
a young woman for marriage and motherhood, or the corruption
of the young man, by preventing the proper development of his
virility.”690 To this effect, Valerius Maximus claimed that it was in
reverence of pudicitia that “the lower of youth is preserved.”691
In his portrayal of Gaius Verres, Cicero made repeated accusations that the former governor had committed acts of stuprum.
He connected it to his greed, his lust, his cruelty and his crimes,
frequently in close relation with lagitium.692 His home and his
banquets were both characterized by stuprum and lagitium.693
And with both stuprum and lagitium he violated and corrupted
others.694
In the Catilinarians, Cicero makes use of the immoral stigma
attached to stuprum. Often he did so without there being any
distinction from crimes of a seemingly different caliber:
688 Plaut. Curc. 35–38 [my italics]: dum ted abstineas nupta, vidua, virgine,
iuventute et pueris liberis, ama quid lubet.
689 Williams 2010, p. 105.
690 Fantham 1991, p 271. Cf. Langlands 2006, p. 284.
691 Val. Max. 6.1.
692 See e.g. Verr. 1.14; 2.1.62; 2.2.82, 110.
693 See e.g. Verr. 2.4.72, 83; 2.5.26.
694 See e.g. Verr. 2.1.64; 2.4.20, 102.
220
making enemies
quae caedes per hosce annos sine illo facta est, quod nefarium
stuprum non per illum?695
What murder has been committed in all those years without his
involvement, what foul stuprum for which he is not responsible?
Murder is here, without any overt strain, associated with stuprum.
Cicero apparently does not need to excuse or comment upon the
connection. The accusation of murder, the sentence leads us to
believe, was instead backed up by the motif of stuprum. Another
example from the fragmentary speech In toga candida, delivered
during the consular election, illustrates the possibility for an orator to make the connection:
Stupris se omnibus ac lagitiis contaminavit; caede nefaria
cruentavit; diripuit socios; leges quaestiones iudicia violavit.696
He deiled himself with every kind of sexual disgrace and outrage;
he stained himself with nefarious murder; he ravaged the allies,
violated the laws, the courts, the legal process.
While the concept of stuprum in a portrayal of character identiies someone as immoral, it could also be linked with a range of
other offences. Clearly, there was no breach in the orator’s logic
when he put sexual immorality on the same list as murder, plunder and legal infraction. Cicero’s reasoning was sound: a man that
had sexually deiled himself could be expected to commit violent
crimes and vice versa.
That an accusation of sexual immorality made sense did of
695 Cat. 2.7.
696 Tog. cand. F10.
Republican Politics
221
course not mean it could not have the purpose of scorn or ridicule. In the In toga candida, Cicero also alludes to a speciic
situation that he referred to as stuprum. Its clever turn of phrase
suggests the type of oratorical aggression that is often categorized
as invective:
Cum deprehendere in adulteriis, cum deprehendebas adulteros
ipse, cum ex eodem stupro tibi et uxorem et iliam invenisti.697
When you were caught in adultery, when you caught adulterers
yourself, when you found yourself through the same sexual
disgrace both a wife and a daughter.
Certainly, this type of mockery and derision was part of the political competition at Rome. The fragment leaves no clue as to
whether or not Cicero made any effort to connect this immoral
affair to another argument. But the attack was nevertheless harsh.
Adultery was a form of stuprum where a free married woman engaged in sexual intercourse with another man. It was considered a
severe offense in Republican Rome, later to be the object of regulation under the lex Iulia de adulteris.698 In oratory, it did not require a formal condemnation but could be used to taint a political
adversary with depravity. Catilina’s honor was here attacked both
by saying that he was an adulterer, but furthermore that he himself
was the victim of adultery; the charge deepened by the concept of
stuprum, here as a suggestion of incest. If people laughed or were
delighted by Cicero’s abuse, it was because he referenced a real
moral concern.699 Adultery was serious and so was stuprum.
697 Tog. cand. F19.
698 For the legal sources regarding adultery, see Richlin 1981, pp. 380–383.
699 See Hickson-Hahn 1998, p. 36.
222
making enemies
The logic of immorality connected to stuprum had another
component. In the second speech, Cicero returns to the topic in
relation to Catilina’s followers:
Atque idem tamen stuprorum et scelerum exercitatione
adsuefactus frigore et fame et siti et vigiliis perferendis fortis ab
istis praedicabatur, cum industriae subsidia atque instrumenta
virtutis in libidine audaciaque consumeret.700
Moreover, [Catilina], on the other hand, accustomed after
practicing stuprum and crime to endure cold and hunger and
thirst and sleep deprivation, became famous by these sorts of men,
yet his physical strength dissipated and his manly powers were
devoured by sexual lust and audacity.
The conclusion to this passage is important. This type of immoral
behavior had speciic consequences. The wrong type of sexual
activity led to a loss of masculinity. We saw example of this cultural belief in the consequence of immorality in Cat. 2.10 above
where the conspirators were portrayed as weak from committing foul sexual acts (stuprum). Valerius Maximus, writing about
the military dangers of luxury, asked what could be fouler and
more ruinous than those vices that wore down the virtus of men:
that destroyed the strength of both mind and body.701 Again, the
sexual immorality which stuprum signaled was a threat to the
ideal of a Roman man. It was a real cultural anxiety. Not only
could it corrupt young Roman males of the elite before they had
a chance to become viri, but it could corrupt daughters, wives as
700 Cat. 2.9.
701 Val. Max. 9.1.ext: quid iis ergo vitiis foedius, quid etiam damnosius, quibus
virtus atteritur, victoriae relanguescunt, sopita gloria in infamiam convertitur, animique pariter et corporis vires expugnantur.
Republican Politics
223
well as religion. Furthermore, the manly strength of the elite was
in danger of dissipating through this immorality, thereby threatening the military ability for which Rome prided itself.702
Sexual depravity in different forms was in forceful opposition
to traditional Roman ideas of morality and in direct conlict with
virtues like pudor and pudicitia. The logic worked in the race for
ofice, in court, and in convincing both senate and people of conspiracy. It rendered men weak and “as women.” Certain signs of
immorality could be invoked to tarnish a politician’s masculinity
and thereby his standing as a member of the governing elite. A
man’s sexual integrity could easily be made a political concern.
Conclusion: Republican Politics
In his oratorical campaign against Lucius Sergius Catilina, the
consul alluded to a range of abilities for which his rival seems
to have been known; endurance against cold, hunger, and sleep
deprivation. To be sure, impressive qualities like these—the mark
of a Roman soldier—could not be allowed to impair Cicero’s
portrayal, and through the prism of immorality they were consequently perverted into negative ones.703 These abilities, the consul argued, had prepared Catilina well for such a life as he was
leading. Lying on the bare ground was helpful for committing
sexual violations (stuprum) or crime; wakefulness was useful for
cheating husbands in their sleep as well as robbing citizens. These
abilities will also, Cicero warned his nemesis, be the end of him.704
702 For conceptions of masculinity and soldiers, see Alston 1998.
703 May, 1988, p. 53. See also Clu. 72.
704 Cat. 1.26: Ad huius vitae studium meditati illi sunt qui feruntur labores
tui, iacere humi non solum ad obsidendum stuprum verum etiam ad facinus
obeundum, vigilare non solum insidiantem somno maritorum verum etiam
bonis otiosorum. Habes ubi ostentes tuam illam praeclaram patientiam
224
making enemies
While it is noteworthy that Cicero’s attempted to discredit what
was presumably part of the fama of Catilina by placing sexual
immoral acts (stuprum and adultery) next to “amoral” trespass
(crime and robbery), it is also apparent that immorality dominates Cicero’s representation. By summoning central concepts of
Roman morality, the undermining of masculine qualities could be
achieved. It offered a new interpretation to his audience, one that
was in line with Cicero’s overall effort to persuade the people of
Rome that he was right: that Catilina was in fact a conspirator
and a traitor to Rome.
To do so Cicero turned to a shared Roman view on immorality
and its own cultural logic. He used signs to taint his adversary
with depravity and vice. By depicting him as uncontrolled, he
showed that his mind gave evidence of immoral behavior. He
portrayed his life as immoral and thus gave an explanation for
his plotting against the patria. He offered up his friends and allies
as proof of his immorality. All these signs led logically to crime
and to conspiracy.
Certain aspects of Roman immorality gave these representations a logic and a power to persuade. Because arguments in
Roman oratory could hold superiority over formal proof, immorality could, with the help of this logic, be argued. In the Pro
Murena, Cicero demanded that the links of immorality were crucial to establish a reproachable life. A single vice was questionable. Depravity included a set of vices all in relation to each other.
Thus he could argue that dancing was unlikely to have occurred
without the vice of shameful love and disgraceful lust; that type
of immoral acts that took place during extravagant feasting. The
immoral banquet was a sign of immorality and, Cicero claimfamis, frigoris, inopiae rerum omnium quibus te brevi tempore confectum
esse senties. See also Cat. 2.9 above. Cf. Sall. Cat. 5.3.
Republican Politics
225
ed, would have been an argument for Murena’s guilt. Without
these links—without a web of immorality—the accusation was
just slander.
Another piece of cultural logic that empowered the orator was
presented in the Pro Sulla. A life could not be altered, changed
to suit any situation and therefore, past immorality proved present guilt and future danger. As in the Pro Cluentio, looking at a
person’s past life, which of course meant accepting the orator’s
portrayal of that life, meant inding out the truth. Because morality was a determinant factor in people’s behavior, an immoral
man would only commit immoral acts. Conversely, a moral man,
proved so by the lack of immorality in his past, could be expected
to act justly.705
A third cultural logic of immorality was the fact that the
immoral man in turn corrupts others. The most powerful way
to demonstrate this was through the components of sexual
immorality and Roman youth. Causality was clearly visible in
this. Once corrupted by vice, a complex of depravity followed,
leading in the end to crime or even conspiracy. Attacking the state
and murdering its citizens could in this way be traced to the loss
of sexual integrity in the formative years. Stuprum was therefore a central part of Cicero’s portrayal but could also, without
breach in cultural logic, be positioned adjacent to conspiracy and
murder in Cicero’s list of accusations. Cicero portrayed Catilina
as sexually corrupted, but this also proved that he was capable of
corrupting others sexually. From this sexual immorality, conspiracy was only a short step away. A similar line of reasoning can
be inferred from Cicero’s depictions of Catilina’s company. Crime
and immorality went hand in hand, because crime was immoral.
Trespass against the community, against the established order, in
705 Cf. Corbeill 2004, p. 153.
226
making enemies
any shape or form, could be understood as depraved, contrary to
proper behavior. One proved the other.
At the height of his public career Cicero regularly found the
need for immoral representations. In the courts he continued to
connect guilt with mores. The moral character of individuals
could both free them and convict them according to the orator’s
logic. This moral character was also the focus of Cicero’s attention when facing Catilina, both in the race for consul and while
trying to persuade his different audiences of the danger that he
embodied. Hence, Cicero used moral arguments in all three of the
arenas of Roman political culture; the courts, the Senate, and the
contio. Immorality was pertinent in the question of electoral malpractice as well as who would conspire against the patria. Guilt
and immorality were also linked in the political sphere.
When looking at the period 66–59 BCE, we ind that the pattern of Roman immorality is both expanded and complicated.
Greed, so central in the portrayal of Verres, as it was in Roman
moral discourse in general, is conspicuously absent in the arguably
most important immoral portrait of Cicero’s political career. The
consul moreover showed little concern for tyrannical depravity
and its links. Greed is not the motive for the conspiracy, nor is
cruelty a dominant trait in the conspirator. Instead, immorality, disgrace and shameful behavior could be demonstrated in a
number of ways. But in order to argue a charge of conspiracy,
immorality also had to be argued. And in order for it to be a
persuasive argument, it had to make sense.
Chapter V
Political Conflicts
—After the Exile (57–52 BCE)
The Catilinarian affair was Marcus Tullius Cicero’s greatest hour but it led to his darkest moment. Achievement turned
into humiliation as the crowned father of the fatherland was
forced into exile as a result of his execution of the conspirators.
His control of the political discourse, so prevalent the previous
decade, now faltered. The man who had prosecuted Verres and
driven out Catilina stood himself accused of tyranny and cruelty.
Roman political culture was ickle; the fall from the top of the
magisterial ladder was long. The new man from Arpinum now
had to face banishment from Rome. The former consul had to
start again.
His way back into the political elite had to be accomplished
with the aid of oratory. Although his political networks were fundamental in revoking his conviction, it was left to Cicero and
his skill as a speaker to try to reclaim his former position in the
state—with the people and with his peers. His position was no
longer one of strength, and for every supporter it seemed he now
had an enemy.
Oratory was also a weapon that he could turn on those he felt
responsible for his disgrace.706 Vice was ammunition for his at706 For oratory as a weapon, see Red. pop. 20.
227
228
making enemies
tacks. Over the course of the decade, Cicero fought many battles
with his political rivals. Before senators, priests, jurors, and the
Roman public, he assailed his opponents in speech after speech,
arduously arguing their immorality and attempting to brand
them with the stigma of depravity.
In extant speeches from 57–52 Cicero fought a war on many
fronts. Four political enemies dominate Cicero’s agonistic representations during the decade. Certain signs of depravity betrayed
their character. One was a feasting glutton and another a slave to
carnal pleasures; a third was in love with his sister and the last
one distinguished by his hideous appearance. They were all deviant and dangerous. They were all depicted as deeply immoral.
What part did immorality play in Cicero’s feuds on the orator’s
stage during the 50’s? How was immorality represented and how
could it be persuasively argued? In this chapter I will attempt to
map how Cicero’s attacks on his political opponents could draw
on Roman expectations of appearance, sexual morality, and
norms of masculinity to rhetorically place his opponents outside
the moral boundary of the political elite.
Exile and Return
During the 50’s BCE, the deterioration of the unity of the elite
continued and an escalation of political violence is evident.707
One man in particular altered the rules of the game and came to
dominate the face of Roman politics: Publius Clodius Pulcher. He
embodied the popularis—the popular politician who relied on
the support of the populace rather than the Senate.
In 58 BCE, Clodius proposed a law which stipulated that any
707 For violence in the late Republic, see Lintott 1968; Brunt 1971; Vanderbroek
1987; Nippel 1995; and Riggsby 1999, pp. 79–119.
Political Conflicts
229
man who had executed a Roman citizen without trial was to be
denied “ire and water.” The meaning of the phrase was exile,
and before the bill was even voted, Cicero, who although not
mentioned by name was the intended target, left Rome. Attempts
to revoke Cicero’s exile were repelled by Clodius with the help of
his operae—street gangs.
Cicero and Clodius are arguably one of history’s most famous
antagonists.708 Their inimicitia spanned almost a decade and resulted not only in altercations on the speaker’s platform, but also
in violent clashes on the streets of Rome.709 Clodius’ law was an
act of revenge for Cicero’s testimony at a trial in 62 where he
stood accused of violating the religious rites of the female deity
Bona Dea.710 When Cicero’s family and political allies after a
year and a half had successfully managed to revoke his exile, he
devoted his energies—and his oratory—to the condemnation of
this man and those he felt had aided him, mainly the two consuls for the year 57, Aulus Gabinius and Lucius Calpurnius Piso.
Cicero took the role of defender of the mos maiorum and of the
optimates in direct opposition to the men he claimed threatened
the Republic.711
In his conlicts with these men, fought on the orator’s stage
and through published speeches, Cicero returned to themes in
his portraits of immorality which we now recognize. They were
distinguished by their immoral mind; their audacia, furor, and
708 See for instance Vell. 2.45. In general, see Plut. Cic. 29–34.
709 Q Fr. 2.1, 2.3; Att. 4.3, 4.7.
710 For the scandal, see e.g. Moreau 1982; Mulroy 1988. Consult in general
Tatum 1999. See also Att. 1.18.3.
711 For the dichotomy between populares and optimates, see the Pro Sestio, in
particular Sest. 96. Cf. Hölkeskamp 2010, p. 42 with n. 43 for overview of
scholarship.
230
making enemies
amentia.712 They kept immoral company.713 They were repeatedly
depicted as greedy, desirous, and lustful.714 They were associated
with lagitium and improbitas.715 And they were enemies of the
Republic.716
The Appearance of Immorality
In their attempts to portray immorality in their adversaries,
Roman orators did not just rely on their audience listening.
Throughout his career, Cicero appealed to his audience to look
for themselves. Just as immorality could be shown, it could, he
frequently argued, also be seen. Bodies could be read and the
internal and the external were thought of as correlating.717 In
his attempts to distinguish individuals as morally deviant, their
external appearance could therefore be presented by the orator
as proof of their moral faults.718
712 For audacia, see e.g. Red. pop. 1; Red. sen. 19; Dom. 80, 115, 130, 133; Har.
resp. 4; Sest. 36, 112; Pis. 39; Mil. 30. For furor, see e.g. Dom. 25, 91; Har.
resp. 10, 39; Prov. cons. 16; Sest. 20; Pis. 50; Mil. 3. For amentia, see e.g.
Dom. 2; Har. resp. 48; Pis. 21; Mil. 12.
713 See for instance, Har. resp. 5, 11, 42; Pis. 22, 70–71, 89.
714 For cupiditas, see e.g. Dom. 47, 107, 115–116; Prov. cons. 43; Sest. 138;
Pis. 57, 59. For libido, see e.g. Red. sen. 14–15; Dom. 23, 106; Har. resp.
38; Prov. cons. 8, 16; Sest. 93; Pis. 86; Mil. 73, 76. For avaritia, see e.g. Red.
pop. 13; Dom. 60; Prov. cons. 11; Pis. 86.
715 For lagitium, see e.g. Red. sen. 15, 25; Dom. 3, 72, 126; Har. resp. 8, 27;
Prov. cons. 14; Sest. 16, 22; Pis. 12, 42. For improbitas, see e.g. Red. sen. 11;
Har. resp. 37; Prov. cons. 8; Sest. 38; Pis. 27. See also general references to
depravity in e.g. Dom. 23, 40, 125, 137; Har. resp 30, 53, 57; Pis. 33, 45, 49,
53, 62, 72.
716 See e.g. Dom. 5, 12; Har. resp. 4, 45; Pis. 78; Mil. 24, 78.
717 Gunderson 2000, p. 70. See also Corbeill 1996, p. 99; Corbeill 1997, p. 119;
2002, p. 207; Dyck 2001, p. 121. Cf. Walters 1998, p. 357.
718 For the link between status, morality, and external appearance, see McGinn
1998, p. 342; Walters 1998, p. 363; Gleason 1999, p. 73; Olson 2006, p.
189.
Political Conflicts
231
Cicero entered the political and oratorical stage immediately
following his return to Rome.719 In a speech known as Post reditum in senatu, he gave his thanks to the senators for overturning the verdict of exile. He also took the opportunity to attack
the two consuls he felt had been agents in his misery: Lucius
Calpurnius Piso and Aulus Gabinius. He maintained that they
were dangerous to the res publica and that they were corrupt and
criminal. He also claimed that they were immoral. The orator
however did not just rely on his audience taking his word for it.
He pointed toward certain visual clues that betrayed their moral
character.
Cicero’s portraits pointed to several ways to visually conirm
immorality. In the Pro Roscio Comoedo and the Pro Cluentio he
had claimed that the true nature of the depraved characters he
portrayed could simply be read in their faces. Similarly, Cicero
held that it was easy to determine what kind of a man Aulus Gabinius was when he appeared in front of the people: vini, somni,
stupri plenus, madenti coma, composito capillo, gravibus oculis,
luentibus buccis, pressa voce et temulenta—“full of wine, sleep,
and sexual debauchery, with dripping and neatly groomed hair,
heavy eyes, labby cheeks, with drunken and subdued speech.”720
Gabinius was the opposite of a vir as easily deduced by this
“Lasterkatalog des effeminierten Lebesmannes.”721 In fact, his
portrayal comprised the three aspects of immorality in Roman
oratory that form the basis for this chapter: appearance, sexuality, and excessive behavior.
In Cicero’s visualization, essential and meaningful links of immorality converged. First of all, drunkenness and lack of sleep
719 For the Post reditum speeches, see Riggsby 2002.
720 Red. sen. 13. For buccis luentibus, see also De. or. 2.266; and Pis. 25.
721 Koster 1980, p. 121.
232
making enemies
were accompanied by a charge of stuprum. Cicero had offered
the same triad of depravity in his portrait of Verres.722 The connection pointed clearly toward the feast and showed how sexual
depravity and feasting could easily be presented in oratory as
coinciding. But these irst three aspects of Gabinius’ immorality
also became mutually complementary and strengthened Cicero’s
depiction because of a general context of immorality. Drunkenness suggested immoderation and lack of control, while sleeplessness could be interpreted as a sign of the inappropriate sexual
activities that this lack of control led to. The logic was clear;
someone who was up all night drinking was also easily suspected
of sexual debauchery. Cicero hence established for his audience
the appropriate links of vice, the lack of which he had reproached
Cato for in the Pro Murena. Moreover, the visual portrayal
further conirmed his claim. The heavy eyes and drunken speech
of Gabinius were proof of his overindulging in wine, his lack of
sleep, and therefore of his sexual immorality.
An even more conspicuous feature of Gabinius’ appearance
mentioned by Cicero was his hairstyle. This could also be made
to be a sign of his immorality. In describing the most morally depraved of Catilina’s followers, Cicero had pointed to their hairstyles as clearly distinguishable marks. Continuing his derision
of Gabinius, Cicero ironically wondered why this curly-haired
dancer had for so long allowed his distinguished virtues to lie
dormant in favor of debauchery and gluttony.723 With the use of a
calamister, a form of curling-iron, Gabinius had groomed himself
in a way that Cicero presented for his audience as a sign of his de722 See especially Verr. 2.5.94 for the use of vini, somni, stupri plenus. See also
Liv. 39.8.6–7.
723 Red. sen. 13: cur in lustris et helluationibus huius calamistrati saltatoris tam
eximia virtus tam diu cessavit? See also Red. sen. 12 for cincinnatus ganeo,
curly-haired glutton.
Political Conflicts
233
praved morality.724 The links were again put forward by the orator. Gabinius, the calamistratus saltator, ignored virtue in favor
of gluttony (helluatio) and debauchery (lustrum). Feasting was
hereby established and Gabinius’ dancing was hence to be understood as a result of his immoral character; the hairstyle serving as
an important visual clue for the audience that proposed to them
an interpretation of the nature of Gabinius that backed up the
general representation as immoral.
In a defense speech for a man named Sestius a few years later,
Cicero made even more adamant connections between Gabinius’
appearance and his immorality. He was portrayed as “dripping
with perfume, with curled hair, looking down upon his companions in stuprum and the gray-haired abusers of his youth.”725
Much like the followers of Catilina, Gabinius was a man sexually corrupted by older men in his youth and who continued
to engage in sexual immorality. In both cases, deviant hairstyles
igured prominently in Cicero’s depictions as proof of this depravity. And because they were linked with sexual passiveness,
perfume and hair were also interpreted as effeminate. Effeminacy,
in turn, was presented as immoral.
The portrayal of Gabinius’ immorality was conspicuous. His
immorality was supposed to be easily read by an audience. But
Cicero also took the opportunity to turn to his colleague Piso and
chastise him for not being able to identify the signs of depravity
in Gabinius:
Non te illius unguentorum odor, non vini anhelitus, non frons
calamistri notata vestigiis, in eam cogitationem adducebat, ut, cum
724 For hairstyle and grooming as an alarming sign, see also Ov. Ars am. 3.433–
434.
725 Sest. 18: Alter unguentis afluens, calamistrata coma, despiciens conscios stuprorum ac veteres vexatores aetatulae suae.
234
making enemies
illius re similis fuisses, frontis tibi integimento ad occultanda tanta
lagitia diutius uti non liceret?726
Did not the smell of his perfume, not the wine on his breath, not
the mark of the curling iron on his forehead, suggest to you that
since you were just like him, you would not be able any longer to
use your appearance to hide your depravity?
The marks of the curling iron, manifest marks of immorality,
should reveal Gabinius’ character. Piso’s external façade however
did not immediately expose his lagitium even though, in Cicero’s
view, he was just as immoral as Gabinius. This presented the orator with a problem. But it was a problem he was determined to
overcome.727
Cicero approached Piso’s appearance in two ways. Both were
meant to argue his immoral character. First in the passage above,
he insisted that the external signs of Gabinius also exposed Piso’s
concealed vice. When associating with the obviously deviant
Gabinius, on whom immorality could even be smelled, Piso’s
moral integrity was undermined, regardless of his own appearance. As shown in the previous chapter, the company you kept
was a possible sign of your own moral shortcomings. More telling was however that, secondly, Cicero adamantly argued that
Piso’s appearance was just a front hiding his immorality. He
thereby asserted that external features could both advertise and
conceal vice.
According to Cicero, even if anyone had happened to see Piso’s
uncultivated (incultus), unpolished (horridus), and gloomy (maestus) appearance, they would not have thought him lustful and
726 Red. sen. 16.
727 For Piso’s appearance, see also Corbeill 1996, pp. 169–173.
Political Conflicts
235
corrupt.728 If you met him in the Forum you would see a man,
sine sensu, sine sapore, elinguem, tardum, inhumanum, without
sense, without elegance, speechless, dull, and brutish—more like
a slave than a man. But, Cicero remarked, if you met him at
home, you would see him full of desire (libidinosus), ilthy (impurus), and without self-control (intemperans) receiving his lusting companions through the secret door.729 We may infer that accusing Piso of being uncultivated and an incompetent politician
was not enough for Cicero. Instead his point is only made when
he arrives at Piso’s immorality.730 Piso’s front does not hide crime
or stupidity, it hides his depravity. Before, however, this point
could convincingly be made to his audience, Cicero, it seems, felt
compelled to reinterpret Piso’s appearance.
The strategy was in all likelihood necessary. Piso was a formidable member of the elite. He had a suitable background and a
successful career. We might surmise that he exhibited the usual
signs of a member of the elite to his surroundings. Cicero’s tactics
therefore demonstrate that immorality was an important conclusion to arrive at through oratorical argument. But it also reveals
Cicero’s belief that, for his audience, the appearance and moral
integrity of someone was connected. Cicero, therefore, because
the manifest signs were supericially lacking in Piso, had to explain the fact that Piso did not look immoral.
In the In Pisonem, where Cicero inveighed against Piso, he
again elaborates on the relation between Piso’s façade and his
immorality:
728 Red. sen. 13: Quem praeteriens cum incultum, horridum maestumque vidisses, etiam si agrestem et inhumanum existimares, tamen libidinosum et perditum non putares. Cf. Pis. 67.
729 Red. sen. 13–14. Also Sest. 19, 21–22; and Pis. 1. For impurus as having
sexual connotations, see Richlin 1992, pp. 28–29.
730 See also Steel 2001, p. 52.
236
making enemies
non enim nos color iste servilis, non pilosae genae, non dentes
putridi deceperunt: oculi, supercilia, frons, voltus denique totus,
qui sermo quidam tacitus mentis est, hic in fraudem homines
impulit, […]. Pauci ista tua lutulenta vitia noramus.731
It was not your slave complexion, your hairy cheeks or your
rotten teeth that deceived us: it was the eyes, brows, forehead,
and in fact entire countenance, which is a silent declaration of the
mind, that pushed men into delusion, […]. Few of us knew of
your ilthy vices.
The countenance (voltus) of someone could in oratory speak to
their character. But even though Cicero claims that Piso’s face displayed less lattering signs, he was clearly not satisied to simply
ridicule Piso. He wanted to taint him with vice and depravity.
In one of his forensic speeches, the logic of his attempts can be
found. In the Pro Sestio, Cicero urged his audience to consider the
appearance of Piso and Gabinius. As in his attacks on Chaerea in
Pro Roscio comoedo and Staienus in the Pro Cluentio, he stipulated that their deeds, their crimes against the state, would in
this way more easily appear in their minds.732 Their immorality—
which was possible to perceive by looking at them—bore witness
to their criminal deeds (one of which, in his mind, had been to
his own exile). In this, Gabinius deceived no one. His smell and
hairstyle were logically linked to sexual disgrace. Piso’s animus,
however, was hidden behind his face, his disgracefulness concealed behind the walls of his home. But his lusts were visible to those
731 Pis. 1. For the In Pisonem, see e.g. Nisbet 1961; Grimal 1966; Kubiak 1989;
Gozzoli 1990; van der Blom 2013. See also Dugan 2005, pp. 55–74. Grifin
2001, p. 85 calls it the only extant “pure invective.” Cf. Koster 1980, p. 129.
732 Sest. 17: vultum atque incessum animis intuemini; facilius eorum facta occurent mentibus vestris, si ora ipsa oculis proposueritis.
Political Conflicts
237
who came closer. The façade was not so thick that “inquiring
eyes” could not see through it.733 The immorality was there.
Without having the obvious telltale signs of vice and depravity
at his disposal, Cicero still attempts to associate Piso’s exterior
with his immorality and persuade his audience to visually read
Piso according to his interpretation: Piso was immoral but had
managed to deceive the Roman people with his voltus. His lack
of immoral appearance, through nothing more than oratorical
argument, is effectively turned on its head to signal his hidden
depravity. Although we have no way of knowing the audience’s
reaction to what modern observers might deem a disingenuous
trick, the fact that Cicero devoted so much energy to negotiating
Piso’s appearance strongly suggests that a Roman audience expected a correlation between appearance and morals and, moreover, that they anticipated the question of immorality in itself
would be addressed—not as ridicule but as argument. It should
furthermore be underlined that Cicero was committed to precisely this oratorical approach for several years while he attempted to combat the two consuls.
Gabinius, all the while, was more easily recognized by his
braided hair with curled and well-oiled locks, as well as buccae luentes purpurissataeque—cheeks dripping and colored with
purple.734 It might seem a simple caricature. May has argued that
“Gabinius’ portrait is marked by its afinity to the stock traits of
a comic character.”735 While this is true—in Plautus’ comedies
the humor connected to gender transgression is particularly evident—the notion can be misleading and it is therefore important
to emphasize that this afinity did not make them harmless.736
733
734
735
736
Sest. 22.
Pis. 25.
May 1988, p. 92. For this, see also Corbeill 1996, p. 130.
See for instance Plaut. Truc. 2.2.35.
238
making enemies
While there was clearly ridicule in Cicero’s portrait of Gabinius,
this ridicule was based on certain Roman anxieties connected to
the proper behavior of the elite. Moreover, what might be funny on stage, even on the orator’s stage, was no light matter to
Roman moral logic.737 Gabinius devoted himself to his appearance in a disturbing way and, more importantly, in an unnatural
way, hiding himself behind perfume and color.738 This in turn was
something that presented a real problem to many Roman commentators. Effeminate behavior in the men that were supposed to
defend Rome was a cause for concern.
Cicero’s portraits of the two consuls were not show speeches
illed with amusing parody. They were portraits of immorality.
Effeminate behavior and appearance were immoral. The fervor
with which Cicero set about showing speciically this immorality
tells us that he took the task seriously. Gabinius was pathetic
and laughworthy because, in Cicero’s portrait, he displayed signs
of effeminacy. This also made him corrupt and dangerous. As
we saw above, Cicero consciously contrasted his looks with the
auctoritas of the vir. He also clearly displayed the logic of depicting Gabinius this way: Who could believe that so great an
empire could be guided by a man who “suddenly emerged from
a long-lived obscurity of debauchery and stuprum, worn out by
wine, eating, prostitution, and adultery?”739 Verres had been undermined in much the same way; in Cicero’s portrait he failed to
honor his military duties after emerging in daylight vini, somni,
stupri plenus.740 Immorality was of grave concern. It stood in opposition to political ability.
737 See Hickson-Hahn 1998, p. 2.
738 For this see Barton 2002, p. 222.
739 Sest. 20: hominem emersum subito ex diuturnis tenebris lustrorum ac stuprorum, vino, ganeis, lenociniis adulteriisque confectum.
740 Verr. 2.5.94.
Political Conflicts
239
Signs of effeminacy were prominent features also in Cicero’s
recurring portrayal of his archenemy Publius Clodius Pulcher, at
one point labeled a homo effeminatus.741 Another aspect of appearance was however dominant in these portraits: clothing.742
Cicero had presented speciic details of the clothing of his opponents earlier in his career. The Greek garb of Verres signaled his
tyrannical immorality and Catilina’s companions were recognized as wearing tunics and dresses instead of togas. Cicero
evoked Clodius’ immorality by highlighting his female dress. The
motif went back to 62 BCE and the event known as the Bona Dea
scandal. At the house of the pontifex maximus, the rites of the
sacred deity, where only women were allowed, were supposedly
violated by Clodius. To gain entrance he had been dressed as a
woman. He was brought to trial by his political rivals for the
crime of incestum.743 Cicero gave evidence at this trial in favor
of the prosecution, refuting Clodius’ professed alibi. Although
Clodius was in the end acquitted, this, it seems, was the seed of
their enmity.744
741 Mil. 89.
742 For the dress and appearance of Clodius, see especially Geffcken 1973;
Skinner 1982; Leach 2001. For clothing as a sign of immorality, see Richlin
1992, pp. 92–93. See furthermore Tracy 1976; Heskel 1994; Dyck 2001; and
Olsen 2006 for the interpretation of dress in Ciceronian oratory.
743 Cicero discusses this incident in a number of letters: See Att. 1.12, 1.13, 1.14.
For the charge of incest, see Val. Max. 4.2.5, 8.5.5, 9.1.7. For incestum, see
Harries 2007, pp. 90–95. Cf. Lenaghan 1969, p. 61. Incestum is an elusive
term but most likely to be considered an impious act, nefas, as well as a
sexual act with blood relatives, because the later in itself was nefas.
744 The acquittal seems to have been considered a scandal. See Att. 1.18.3.
Cicero’s reasons for giving evidence at the trial, thus also the reasons for the
enmity between the men, has been debated by modern scholarship. Plutarchos maintained that Cicero’s wife Terentia, out of hatred of Clodius, forced
her husband to testify. de Benedetti 1929; and Epstein 1986 have tried to
support this account. This has been in turn refuted by Tatum 1999, p. 208
who maintains that Cicero’s public concern should be interpreted as sincere.
240
making enemies
We ind evidence of the hostility that followed in a letter
Cicero wrote to his friend Atticus wherein he references a particular altercation that took place in the Senate in 61. It serves as
a good example of the antagonistic political culture of the late
Republic and its reliance on combative oratory:
Clodium praesentem fregi in senatu cum oratione perpetua
plenissima gravitatis tum altercatione huius modi; ex qua licet
pauca degustes.745
I crushed Clodius in person in the Senate both with an
uninterrupted and stern speech and by way of altercatio;
of which I let you taste a little.
Scholars have traditionally identiied the speech that Cicero mentions here as the fragmentary In Clodium et Curionem.746 In this
speech, whether or not it was the one Cicero told Atticus about,
Cicero makes allusions to the female garb that Clodius had worn
in order to sneak in and violate the rite:
Nam rusticos ei nos videri minus est mirandum, qui manicatam
tunicam et mitram et purpureas fascias habere non possumus. Tu
vero festivus, tu elegans, tu solus urbanus, quem decet mulieris
ornatus, quem incessus psaltriae, qui effeminare vultum, attenuare
vocem, levare corpus potes. O singulare prodigium! O monstrum!
Nonne te huius templi, non urbis, non vitae, non lucis pudet?747
745 Att. 1.16.8.
746 It has however been suggested that the speech to which Cicero refers is a
completely different speech. See McDermott 1972, p. 410. For the In Clodium et Curionem, see the invaluable treatment in Crawford 1994, pp. 227–
263. References are to this work. See also Geffcken 1973, pp. 59–89.
747 In Clod. F.21. Also F.23.
Political Conflicts
241
It is no surprise that we look like rustics to him, since we cannot
wear the long-sleeved tunic or turban or purple headbands. You,
who certainly are cheerful, delicate, you alone who are in city
style, with your female dress, your stride like a female lute player,
who can produce an effeminate look, a thin voice and a weak
body can. Oh, unparalleled portent! You monster! Does not this
temple, the city, lives or light, give you shame?
The appearance of Clodius is contrasted with the norm of the
elite. The depiction of his clothes, his walk and his voice and
body all portray him as effeminate.748 His manner is light and elegant. With the image of the psaltria, a female lute player found in
Roman comedy, the orator constructed “a scandalously suggestive character.”749 The psaltria was associated with festivities but
could also be recognized as a prostitute. The tone was no doubt
mocking, laughter likely the sought-after response. But it is important to note that Clodius’ transgression in the passage above
was not only the target of ridicule. It is connected in this passage
directly to sacrilege and shame (pudor). The fragment that follows further illustrates the seriousness in Clodius’ deviating appearance. He was dressed as a woman in order to commit acts of
lust and stuprum.750 Comedy, surely, could be effective, but found
its relevance in serious apprehensions in the community.751
The In Clodium et Curionem was according to Quintilianus
one of the few speeches held in the Senate where Cicero incor-
748 Cf. Gleason 1995, p. 64. See also Taylor 1997, p. 339.
749 Geffcken 1973, p. 86. See also Merrill 1975, p. 4.
750 In Clod. F.22. For effeminacy, see also F.5: Sin esset iudicatum non videri
virum venisse quo iste venisset.
751 For the contrast between comedy and gravity, see also Geffcken 1973, pp.
76, 78, 86–87. See also Leigh 2004. Cf. Tatum 2011, p. 176.
242
making enemies
porated vituperatio.752 Cicero, however, found use for the motif
upon his return from the exile he blamed Clodius for. In the
speech known as De haruspicum responsis (On the answer of the
soothsayers), held in 56, Cicero continued to malign his adversary. Again the Bona Dea scandal was called to mind and again
the effeminate dress was connected to religious trespass:
In Clodium vero non est hodie meum maius odium quam illo
die fuit, cum illum ambustum religiosissimis ignibus cognovi
muliebri ornatu ex incesto stupro atque ex domo pontiicis
maximi emissum.753
As for Clodius, I certainly hate him no more today than I did that
day when I learned that he had burnt himself on the sacred ires as
he dashed out of the supreme pontiff’s house from his incestuous
stuprum in female clothing.
Cicero also alluded to Clodius’ appearance outside this particular
incident albeit no doubt with it in mind. In another passage he similarly to the In Clodium et Curionem details his enemy’s dress:
P. Clodius a crocota, a mitra, a muliebribus soleis purpureisque
fasceolis, a strophio, a psalterio, a lagitio, a stupro est factus
repente popularis.754
Publius Clodius suddenly appeared as a popularis from his saffroncolored dress, his headband, his womanly shoes and purple garters,
his breast-band, his psaltery, his immorality, and his stuprum.
752 Quint. Inst. 3.7.2. Cf. Geffcken 1973, p. 62.
753 Har. resp. 4. See also Har. resp. 8.
754 Har. resp. 44.
Political Conflicts
243
In this passage, certain colors, speciic clothing and shoes all point
out the trespass of gender divisions. Female shoes, not to mention a strophium or breast-band, for instance function as pars
pro toto; effeminate garb mean an effeminate man.755 Though
the articles of clothing enumerated once again are remarkably
detailed, the sentence leads to and sets up Clodius’ acts of immorality. There is reason to believe that the depravity that concepts
like lagitium and stuprum denoted was central to Cicero’s portrayal but furthermore that this made sense to his audience. Gender trespass was equated with immorality. Stuprum signals that
Clodius was like a woman sexually as well, and the important
logic for the attack to reference thus is that his appearance mirrors his moral character. The effeminate dress is a result of and a
clue to Clodius’ sexual immorality. In view of the fact that Cicero
repeatedly arrives at immorality in his mocking portrayal of his
rival, it is reasonable to argue that immorality is what truly empowered his representations. We should furthermore note that
feminine clothing functions to undermine the victim politically,
as the sentence not only links effeminate clothing to lagitium and
stuprum but also identiies Clodius as a popularis. This connection must have made sense too. Deviant appearance is telling of
deviant sexuality and results in political exclusion.
The scene as well as the circumstances made the representation
of Clodius well suited. The issue concerned the religious interpretation of a strange sound that had been reported in a Roman
suburb. The violation of the rites through sexual acts therefore
most likely struck a powerful note. Cicero, however, presented
the same motif in court years later. In the Pro Plancio he spoke
of the effeminacy of Clodius and his violation of religion through
755 For strophium, see Olson 2003.
244
making enemies
stuprum.756 The connection, it seems, did not need a scandal
fresh in the audience’s mind or an appropriate religious setting.
It was not just the isolated incident itself that supplied cultural
substance to the accusation. Effeminate behavior could in itself
be considered nefas, in conlict with proper religious behavior
(fas). The following attack on Clodius from De domo sua in 57,
held before the college of pontiffs and again regarding a religious
dispute, illustrates how the connection could be made:
[I]ste impurus atque impius hostis omnium religionum, qui contra
fas et inter viros saepe mulier et inter mulieres vir fuisset.757
That impure and impious enemy of all religion, who against
proper religious behavior (fas), often had been as a woman among
men, and as a man among women.
Clodius in his disguise had been a man among women.758 Therefore, he was now a woman among men. Clodius’ passive sexual
role and therefore his immorality are here spelled out by his nemesis. Cicero used this motif in his portraits of both Verres and
Aebutius. In this passage, another dimension is added in the link
that could be established between unmanly behavior and sacrilege. Immoral sexual behavior could also be construed as in conlict with the gods. We saw in the In Clodium et Curionem that
Cicero went from details of Clodius’ dress to calling him a prodigium. The word, which means bad omen or sign, was, according
to Anthony Corbeill, not just name calling. Its religious connotation labels the adversary “a disruption of nature, a disturbance in
756 Planc. 87. See also Langlands 2006, pp. 299–305.
757 Dom. 139.
758 See also Mil. 55: mulier inciderat in viros.
Political Conflicts
245
the web of divine order.”759 The prodigium, by its very nature, is
related to societal fear; it tells the community that something is
wrong. It also signals that exclusion is the proper response to this
occurrence.760 Furthermore, prodigium linked religious trespass
with deviant appearance and with immorality.
The mocking portrayal of Clodius had wider relevance than
just laughter.761 In representing Clodius as immoral, Cicero made
use of a previous scandal which had even reached the courts. But
what made the representations work was not just the fact “that it
had happened,” but that effeminate appearance, dress, and manner all were logical signs of immorality.762 It pointed toward the
corrupted sexuality of Clodius, because morality could be read
and an effeminate man was so deined by his sexual passivity.
The important conclusion to Cicero’s portraits over the course of
several years was not that Clodius was pathetic or weak, but that
he was in fact immoral. This immorality was also presented as a
religious transgression and as something dangerous. Individual
articles of clothing hence served to prove something of wider signiicance.
Besides female garb, Cicero calls attention to other feminine
qualities detectable in his opponents. The voice, particularly a
weak voice, as we saw in the In Clodium et Curionem could
also signal unmanliness, and Clodius is described both as sine
voce and stuttering in De haruspicum responsis.763 Smell simi759 Corbeill 2008, p. 243. For prodigia, see also Rasmussen 2003. See also Garland 1995, pp. 67–72; and May 1996. For belua, see also Mil. 40, 85. Cf.
Cantarella 2005.
760 Corbeill 2008, p. 244. See also Garland 1995, p. 178. For religion in Cicero’s
attacks, see Gildenhard 2011.
761 Cf. Heskel 1994, p. 140.
762 See also Vatinius’ improper black dress as sign of deviance in Vat. 30; and
Piso dressing as a slave in Pis. 93. Cf. McDonnell 2006, p. 143.
763 Har. resp. 2.
246
making enemies
larly could indicate depravity as previously noted. Gabinius is
repeatedly represented as wearing perfumes, and the stench from
the drinking den where Piso at one point emerges or from his
house also paints a vivid picture of what goes on inside.764 A
single piece of deviant clothing could also link the person to immorality, as when Cicero relates to his audience that he met Piso
coming out of a drinking den wearing a type of sandal (solae).765
The way someone walked could also be used as evidence. In his
defense of Sextus Roscius, when Cicero wanted to persuade his
audience that the real culprit was Chrysogonus, he had implored
them to consider—besides his hair and his perfume—also his
walk.766
An altogether different external sign of immorality was bodily
deformity. In Cicero’s speech against Publius Vatinius this was
brought to the fore. Vatinius was a witness in the trial against
Sestius discussed above. Cicero here took his own advice from
the Pro Flacco and attacked the character of the witness.767 The
result was, in the eyes of one scholar, “einer Invective gröbster
Art.”768 More importantly for present concerns however was
764 Pis. 13; Sest. 24. For perfume, see also Cael. 27.
765 Pis. 13. For solae, see also Har. resp. 44.
766 Rosc. Am. 135. See also Sest. 17. For walking as an indication of character,
see Corbeill 2004, pp. 107–139.
767 For Vatinius’ career as well as the speech itself, see Gardner 1958; and Albini
1959. The standard commentary has been Pocock 1926; however see also
Shackleton Bailey 1991; and Maslowski 1995. Corbeill 1996, pp. 46–56
discusses Vatinius at some length.
768 Koster 1980, p. 127. See Pocock 1926, p. 5 for a defense of Cicero’s abuse as
a consequence of the taunts made by Vatinius, “perhaps a factor which led
him say things which in calmer moments he might have itched but would yet
have prudently suppressed.” Gardner 1958, p. 34, holds that the ostensible
purpose of the cross-examination was to undermine the value of any evidence given by Vatinius at the trial, but that “the real aim of the speech was
to abuse a political enemy.” Cf. Pocock 1926, p. 5: “Cicero frankly seizes the
opportunity of abusing an enemy.”
Political Conflicts
247
that Vatinius’ bodily features could be linked to his immorality.
Cicero immediately set about establishing this immorality in the
opening of his speech:
Si tua tantummodo, Vatini, quid indignitas postularet, spectare
voluissem, fecissem id, quod his vehementer placebat, ut te, cuius
testimonium propter turpitudinem vitae sordesque domesticas nullius momenti putaretur, tacitus dimitterem.769
If I had merely wanted to consider you, Vatinius, in the way your
unworthiness required, I would have done what these men eagerly
wished, and dismissed you, whose testimony because of your
shameful life and sordid household should be awarded no weight,
in silence.
A shameful life and sordid household—signs of immorality—are
presented by the orator as aspects that undermine the credibility
of a witness. Consequently, proving immorality becomes central to the orator’s task. Giving someone the silent treatment, as
Cicero pretended to consider, was not an option. As he had done
in the past, Cicero alluded to the immoral youth of Vatinius and
declared his audacia and furor.770 Simply stating immorality was
not ideal, however. Instead, oratory in Republican Rome offered
the chance to argue and negotiate immorality. In Cicero’s attempt
to depict Vatinius as immoral, and to prove his unreliability as a
witness, appearance and external signs of immorality could serve
that purpose.
Vatinius seems to have been generally considered ugly in his
day. Seneca called him a “man born for both laughter and hatred,”
769 Vat. 1.
770 Vat. 11. For audacia, see e.g. Vat. 2, 17. For furor, see e.g. Vat. 7.
248
making enemies
in itself a notable pairing.771 Velleius writes of the hatred the army
felt toward him and his deformities.772 In the Pro Sestio, Cicero
ironically refers to Vatinius as the pretty one (pulcherrimus).773
When undermining his witness, Cicero found use for this visual
circumstance. The orator offered his audience the interpretation
that physical ugliness bore witness to immorality. Throughout
the course of his speech, Cicero paid considerable attention to his
target’s appearance. Vatinius, Cicero told the audience, appeared
at the trial, like a serpent from his hiding, eyes protruding, with
bulging and swollen neck (te tamquam serpens e latibulis oculis
eminentibus, inlato collo, tumidis cervicibus intulisti).774 Furthermore he commented on the risk of his swellings bursting.775 In
another passage, the foulness of Vatinius is positioned against the
interests of the state:
sic ego te, quamquam es omni diritate atque immanitate taeterrimus, tamen dico esse odio civitati non tam tuo quam rei publicae
nomine.776
So to you, although you are, in your calamity and monstrosity, the
foulest of men, still I say you are hated by the community, not for
your own sake, but in the name of the Republic.
771 Sen. Dial. 2.17.3: hominem natum et ad risum et ad odium. For the derision
of deformities and disabilities, see Garland 1995, chapter 5.
772 Vell. 2.69.3.
773 Sest. 134. Cf. Vat. 5.
774 Vat. 4. Pocock 1926, p. 79 speculates as to what kind of disease this could
suggest. “Probably he suffered from tuberculous glands and perhaps ordinary goitre as well.” The protruding eyes though, “might be merely temporary
and due to excitement.”
775 Vat. 10: aut ita impudenter, ut manus a te homines vix abstinere possint, aut
ita dolenter, ut aliquando ista, quae sunt inlata, rumpantur.
776 Vat. 9.
Political Conflicts
249
Cicero’s attacks might strike us as particularly slanderous and malicious. Cicero, writing to his brother Quintus, tells him that he
cut up Vatinius “to the applause of gods and men” and that this
was what his client Sestius most of all wanted.777 Nevertheless,
Vatinius is not simply loathed or ridiculed, but, as in the accounts
of Seneca and Velleius, hated because of the danger he poses to the
Republic.778 One reason might be that the ugly exterior in fact had
other connotations. It could be connected to immorality:
si cognati respuunt, tribules exsecrantur, vicini metuunt, adines
erubescunt, strumae denique ab ore improbo demigrarunt et aliis
iam se locis conlocarunt, si es odium publicum populi, senatus,
universorum hominum rusticanorum,—quid est quam ob rem
praeturam potius exoptes quam mortem, praesertim cum popularem te velis esse neque ulla re populo gratius facere possis?779
If your kinsmen reject you, your tribesmen utter curses at you,
your neighbors fear you and your relatives blush with shame
for you, and lastly if your boils migrate from your vile mouth to
relocate on other parts of your body, if you are hated publicly by
people, Senate and all the men of the countrysid—what is the
reason you desire the praetorship more than death, especially
when you want to be a popularis and nothing would satisfy the
people more than that?
Corbeill has discussed this particular passage in relation to the os
improbum—the “immoral” or “unclean” mouth.780 The mouth,
777 Q Fr. 2.4.1.
778 For bodily deformity interpreted as religious warning, see Garland 1995, pp.
178–179.
779 Vat. 39. See also Att. 2.9.2. For Vatinius’ immorality, see also Vat. 13.
780 See generally chapter 3 in Corbeill 1996; for Vatinius see pp. 53–54, 100–
250
making enemies
because it represents so many of the actions connected to Roman
immorality—both feasting and passive sexuality—is stained and
thus serves as an outward proof of inner immorality and becomes, Corbeill argues, twice as incriminating, as the mouth both
symbolizes immorality and has itself created the immorality in
question.781 To Cicero, then, and thus supposedly to his audience,
the appearance of Vatinius is clearly indicative of his corrupted
character and, by drawing attention to the mouth, the source of
this immorality is emphasized. More than just important in itself, Vatinius’ deformities could be argued to mirror his past acts
of depravity. His ugly exterior therefore was not only possible
to ridicule but provided opportunity to taint him with immorality. Thus, his appearance could speak to graver concerns of the
Roman community.782 Immorality demanded hatred.783
Dress, hairstyle, smell, and walk, as well as bodily deformity
could all be adduced as proof in oratory of the immorality of
an individual member of the elite. If the proofs were not visibly
there, appearance could still be argued to hide the true depravity of the opponent. We should note that through these different visible features of a Roman, Cicero concentrated his efforts on linking appearance to immorality. This link made sense,
because the correlation was supposed to exist. Seneca argues
that the character of someone can be established by observing
their appearance: omnia rerum omnium, si observentur, indicia
sunt et argumentum morum ex minimis quoque licet capere—
“everything is always, if you observe them carefully, telling and
it is possible to judge their morals from the most trivial sign.”784
781
782
783
784
101. For the os impurum, see also Richlin 1992, pp. 26–27, 99.
Corbeill 1996, p. 100.
Corbeill 1996, p. 53.
For this see Mil. 35, 42. Cf. Clu. 29, 41.
Sen. Ep. 52.12. Cf. Cic. Off. 1.129.
Political Conflicts
251
An effeminate man, he continues, walks a certain way or has a
particular body language. Furthermore, to Seneca, a man dressing like a woman lived contrary to nature.785 His father, Seneca
the Elder, noted that sleep and laziness, which were prominent
features in Cicero’s portrait of Gabinius were an indication of
singing and dancing and therefore of effeminacy.786 In the same
manner, bodily shortcomings could be seen as signaling moral
faults. The link between immorality and appearance was therefore proposed through the theme of effeminacy and deviance.
To the Roman audience, a cultural moral logic must have
stated that the exterior could betray immoral character. It is
reasonable to infer the afinity of this logic with the one Cicero
had professed in Pro Sulla; just as you cannot change your nature
or character, your face and body cannot hide your depravity. But
immorality, it is important to stress, even though it could be seen,
also had to be shown. The orator could depict certain features
that supported his portrayal. They were, however, not just there.
Instead, immoral appearance was made meaningful through the
orator’s argument. Portraying one’s adversary in particular clothing or hairstyle supported the charge of immorality. Although
several of these depictions might appear comical to the modern
reader—and I do not mean to claim that they could not at times
have been perceived as such—it is striking how regularly they are
grounded in a context of depravity that was a real concern to the
Roman community.
785 Sen. Ep. 122.7. For the connection between character and dress, see also Sen.
Ep. 5.1–2.
786 Sen. Controv. 1, praef. 8–9.
252
making enemies
The Web of Sexual Immorality
Tainting an opponent with sexual immorality was an important
weapon in a Roman orator’s arsenal.787 As a prosecutor, Cicero
had focused his efforts on the lust and stuprum of Verres to prove
his corruption, and as consul he had used the motif of sexual
corruption to persuade his listeners that Catilina was a traitor
to Rome. During the 50’s BCE, Cicero regularly came back to
the sexual depravity of his political rivals. How then could such
debauchery be argued?
Preceding chapters have indicated that sexual immorality and
non-sexual immorality were not distinctly separated in the representations found in Roman oratory, or in the Roman mind
world. Instead lack of moral integrity in general could be suggested to point to lack of sexual integrity. As previously discussed, the youth of a Roman man was a particularly suitable target.
The early years were regarded as passive and therefore vulnerable.788 Because of the weakness of youth, young men of the elite
had to be sheltered.789 In 70 BCE, Cicero made pointed reference
to the son of Gaius Verres, who he claimed had been sullied by
his father’s immorality at his most vulnerable period in life.790
The son would grow up in the depraved image of his father. The
fear of this manly passiveness in Rome thus informs Cicero’s attacks.791 But in this fear we can also discern the belief in past im-
787
788
789
790
791
Langlands 2006, p. 286.
Fantham 1991, p. 274; Edwards 1993, p. 69; Williams 2010, p. 80.
See for instance Cael. 10–11; Pis. 68.
Verr. 2.5.137. See also Verr. 2.3.23; 2.5.30.
For an illustrative example, see Tac. Ann. 11.2 where Valerius Asiaticus in
response to a charge of immorality and mollitia (softness) urged the prosecutor to ask his own sons to attest to Valerius’ manhood: interroga […],
Suilli, ilios tuos: virum esse me fatebuntur.
Political Conflicts
253
morality as indicative of present character.792 This in turn ensured
that such accusations were not beside the political point. In his
irst speech upon his return, Cicero attacked Gabinius:
Quis enim ullam ullius boni spem haberet in eo, cuius primum
tempus aetatis palam fuisset ad omnes libidines divulgatum, qui ne
a sanctissima quidem parte corporis potuisset hominum impuram
intemperantiam propulsare, qui cum suam rem non minus strenue
quam postea publicam confecisset, egestatem et luxuriem
domestico lenocinio sustentavit.793
For, who could hope for anything good from one whose youth
was made open to everyone’s passions, who could not defend even
the holiest part of his body from impure and unrestrained men,
who after he had ruined with no less effort his own estate as later
the state, in order to support his destitution and luxury, turned to
prostitution.
We can follow Cicero’s reasoning in this passage from youthful
transgression to political corruption. Gabinius was available to
all who lusted. He was not a vir because he could not defend his
pudor as a young man. He was a penetrable object of vile men’s
pleasure and therefore nothing good could be expected from him.
That he lost his wealth and also hurt the state was only natural,
because his perverted tastes, a consequence of his sexual corruption, demanded satisfaction. Luxury and sexual corruption was
here a natural connection to make, both as cause and effect, because luxury could be argued to be a sign of lost sexual integrity
792 Reversely, if someone had protected their youth, their morals should not be
subject to similar accusations. See Cael. 11.
793 Red. sen. 11. For Gabinius’ immoral youth, see also Sest. 18 (above).
254
making enemies
that in turn led to further sexual debauchery. Because he was
a destitute, Gabinius turned to prostitution to sustain his pleasures.794 This suggested that he was still passive as an adult.795
In an attack previously discussed in the Pro Sestio, Cicero had
argued along the same lines, that because of Gabinius’ sexual
depravity he was unit for government.796 In De domo sua, an
attack on Gabinius emphasizes the political consequences of an
immoral life cycle; his immoral boyhood (impudicitia pueritiae),
followed by his licentious youth (libidines adolescentiae) and his
subsequent years of disgrace (dedecus) and destitution, all the
way to his latrocinium consulatus—his consulship of banditry.797
Behind the chain of reasoning lies the idea that a man who was
capable of one sin was capable of any sin.798 It also shows that
the logic of immorality dictated that once sexually and morally
corrupted you were no longer a vir, no longer capable of good
and hence no longer it to rule. Rather you were ruled by your
immorality. Passiveness meant exclusion from the political sphere
and therefore also became a real political weapon.
We should not be surprised that all of Cicero’s political enemies during the 50’s BCE were so portrayed. Piso, in Cicero’s
oratorical representations, had been intimate with an Epicurean
philosopher as a young man and, like Gabinius had as a result developed a perverted view of pleasures.799 In his attack on Vatinius,
Cicero alluded to a “shameful youth hidden by his obscurity and
depravity.”800 A similar attack was made on a man named Gellius
794 For an Imperial example of the notion of sustaining a life of debauchery with
prostitution, see Apul. Apol. 74–75.
795 Richlin 1992, p. 98; Edwards 1993, p. 71.
796 Sest. 20.
797 Dom. 126. Cf. Langlands 2006, p. 288.
798 Richlin 1992, p. 98; Langlands 2006, p. 287.
799 Pis. 68–69.
800 Vat. 11. For allusion to youthful transgressions in In Vatinium, see also Vat. 32:
Political Conflicts
255
Poplicola in the Pro Sestio. Gellius was a man, Cicero argued,
who could have beneited from the dignity of his family, but who
after a youth of impurity (impuro adulescente) had squandered
his patrimony and now had an insatiable belly. Insatiable desires
therefore, whether for sex or food, were a direct consequence
of sexual corruption at a young age. That such reasoning had
consequences for someone’s status as a politician was clear. The
rhetorical question that follows the orator’s representation of the
life of Gellius is hereby telling: “Was there ever a riot where he
was not the leader?”801 Sexual morality was not an isolated concern; Gellius’ sexual corruption as a young man and the passions
that they created gave him his motive for sedition. His cognomen,
poplicola or “friend of the people,” could be construed as negative and seditious because of his background.
Clodius was of course not spared this treatment. In the speech
De haruspicum responis, Cicero presented his audience with a
detailed description of his enemy’s life that made sure that he
could not be considered a man at all:
Qui post patris mortem primam illam aetatulam suam ad scurrarum locupletium libidines detulit, quorum intemperantia expleta in
domesticis est germanitatis stupris volutatis: deinde iam robustus
provinciae se ac rei militari dedit atque ibi piratarum contumelias
perpessus, etiam Cilicum libidines barbarorumque satiavit.802
He who after his father’s death gave his early years to the lusts
to wealthy depraved men, whose passions he satisied before
wallowing in domestic sexual debauchery with blood relatives:
numquam puer aut adulescens inter cocos fueras? See also Sest. 133.
801 Sest. 110: Ecquae seditio umquam fuit, in qua non ille princeps?
802 Har. resp. 42.
256
making enemies
following that, as he became strong he entered the military in the
provinces and endured the insults of pirates and satisied the lusts
of Cilicians and barbarians.
Having endured other men’s lusts as a young man, it was only
logical that Clodius as a grown man submitted his own body to
pirates and barbarians. By prostituting himself to wealthy men—
by satisfying others—he had lost his sexual integrity which also
led him to depraved sexual acts such as incest. The logic of immorality hence argued that corruption of manhood impelled further
sexual debauchery, but this also likely meant that it was only men
spoiled in this fashion that could be readily believed to have committed such depraved acts. Moreover, the sexually tarnished man
was not only expected to commit sexual trespass. Further details
of Clodius’ life in Cicero’s narration naturally involved criminal
acts, murder, and fraud. He was also a danger to the Republic.
His lost status as a vir logically meant he could no longer be of
service to the res publica. Rather, he could only harm it. Tainting
someone with sexual immorality hence activated a wider framework of meaning. By undermining the corporeal integrity, moral
integrity was effectively sullied. In the following passage, Cicero
stated that although the list of crimes that Clodius had committed against his patria was long and dire, the worst crimes he had
committed against himself:
Quis minus umquam pepercit hostium castris quam ille omnibus
corporis sui partibus. Quae navis umquam in lumine publico tam
vulgata omnibus quam istius aetas fuit? Quis umquam nepos tam
libere est cum scortis quam hic cum sororibus volutatus?803
803 Har. resp. 59. Cf. Langlands 2006, p. 302.
Political Conflicts
257
Who has ever been less sparing toward enemy camps than he to
the parts of his own body? What ship in a public river was ever so
open to everybody as he in his youth? What wastrel ever wallowed
so freely with prostitutes as he with his own sisters?
Despite Cicero’s professed ranking of faults, the overlap in the
political sphere between trespass against the Roman state and
against Roman morality was only natural. Giving the audience
the details of a depraved youth therefore made sense from a cultural standpoint. It was not merely about humiliating an opponent. Rather than mere slander, Cicero’s line of reasoning was a
political argument.804
We recognize the accusation of being open to all who lusted
from the biographical details Cicero offered about Gabinius. The
same logic could, however, also be turned against Cicero. When
he defended Marcus Caelius in 56 BCE, his client, just as with
Lucius Murena in 63, had been accused of immorality by the prosecution. Topics such as luxury, lust, the vices of youth, and morals had, according to Cicero, been thoroughly discussed.805 One
of the reproaches was however particularly serious, as it pertained to the question of the youth and pudicitia of the defendant.806
From Cicero’s defense speech we gather that Caelius had been
accused of being an impudicus.807 This meant that he had failed
to protect his sexual integrity. As shown, Caelius, and therefore
Cicero could not risk such an epithet to go unchallenged. Above
we saw how Cicero referred to Gabinius’ immoral youth with the
term impudicitia. Such a man could not be numbered among the
804
805
806
807
Cf. Skinner 1982, p. 208.
Cael. 25. Cf. Scaur. 6.
Cael. 6.
Cael. 30.
258
making enemies
elite.808 Nor was the impudicus necessarily only a pathetic outcast, he was easily understood of as an enemy of Rome. One of
the dire results of the biographical narrative presented by Cicero
in the above passage was that Clodius had violated not only the
gods and the laws of men, but had attacked the pudor and pudicitia of the entire state.809 In this manner, the immorality of
one person could be positioned against the morality of the entire
community. Similarly, in the Pro Sestio, the orator accuses Clodius of being not only an impudicus but also a demented and
proligate hostis pudoris et pudicitiae—an enemy of modesty and
chastity.810 The logic of immorality, as in the case of Catilina and
his conspiracy, made it possible to point toward the threatening
aspects of moral transgressions. Hence, an impudicus threatened
the pudicitia of others. How then did Cicero approach the accusation against his client in the Pro Caelio? We shall, he said,
proceed with arguments.811
In recognizable fashion, Cicero argued that those who accuse
his client of being an impudicus have no foundation for this
charge.812 But he also, like in the case of Murena, separated accusation (accusare) from slander (male dicere):
Accusatio crimen desiderat, rem ut deiniat, hominem ut notet,
argumento probet, teste conirmet; maledictio autem nihil habet
808 Cf. Langlands 2006, pp. 289–292.
809 Har. resp. 43. See also Mil. 77. For the political exclusion of the impudicus,
see also Gunderson 2003, pp. 38–39 on Seneca’s declamatory scenario impudicus contione prohibeatur.
810 Sest. 73. Cf. Prov. cons. 24. For impudicus see Har. resp. 1.
811 Cael. 22: Argumentis agemus. Cf. Cael. 54 where Cicero discusses “artiicial
proofs” in oratory. See Austin 1952, p. 115. For the distinction between artiicial and non-artiicial proof in oratory, see Aristoteles’ treatment in Rhet.
1.2 and 1.15; and Cicero’s in De. or. 2.116. Cf. Part. or. 48–49.
812 Cael. 30.
Political Conflicts
259
propositi praeter contumeliam quae si petulantius iactatur,
convicium, si facetius urbanitas nominatur.813
Accusation requires an offense, to deine the issue, to mark a man,
to prove by argument, conirm by testimony. Slander, meanwhile,
has no intention other than insult, which if thrown by impudence
is called abuse, if reined called elegant.
Here Cicero again alludes to the fact that accusations of immorality had to be properly argued to distinguish them from insult
and abuse. Which accusations constituted one or the other of
these was clearly a matter of contestation between prosecution
and defense. But importantly, the distinction could still be offered. If the attacks had no other purpose than insult, they could
be dismissed. But these accusations could also have a larger purpose—to prove an offence. It is hard to believe this did not constitute a recognizable distinction for a Roman jury. Nor is it likely
that they did not ind the distinction acceptable. Cicero’s entire
prosecution against Verres would in fact be pointless if the jury
had taken every charge of immorality as beside the forensic question.
The accusations against Caelius were of course, in the eyes of
his defense attorney, part of the category of mere insult. Calling
him an adulterer and an impudicus was mere slander (contumelia), a charge that lacked foundation and was hurled angrily and
without authority.814 This sort of misbehavior typically linked
to young men, were used, according to Cicero, to rouse invidia
813 Cael. 6. Cf. Cael. 8 and 29–30. For a discussion of this passage, see Corbeill
1996, pp. 17–18.
814 Cael. 30: “Adulter, impudicus, sequester” convicium est, non accusatio;
nullum est enim fundamentum horum criminum, nulla sedes; voces sunt
contumeliosae temere ab irato accusatore nullo auctore emissae.
260
making enemies
against his client.815 Just as in the Pro Sulla, he declared that the
mores of his client was incompatible with the crime.816 Marcus
Caelius, who stood on trial for political violence, could thus be
accused of immorality to establish guilt, but the charges had to
be argued properly and could also be refuted by argument. But
the link between immorality and violence was in itself not questioned. That Caelius had lost his sexual integrity was in other
words, if persuasively put forward by the prosecution, not by any
means irrelevant to a political crime. The reason was that losing
your sexual—and moral—integrity ensured that you were unit
for the political scene if not the community all together. The logic
of immorality in ancient Rome denied that a passive man could
be an active leader.
Another way to paint your adversary as sexually corrupt was
through the theme of prostitution.817 This could be suggested
to an audience in a number of ways. Of course, it could also
be stated outright. In the Pro Sestio, Cicero accuses Clodius of
being a scurrarum locupletium scortum, or a prostitute for the
wealthy and depraved of the city,818 an accusation also found in
the passage from De haruspicum responsis that detailed his early
years. In De domo sua, Cicero labeled him a scortum populare—
a whore to the masses.819 Prostitutes were infames or “untouchable” and unclean.820 Often they were slaves. Since they were
physically available to others, they were thought of as lacking
the integrity of a free individual. Their lawful rights were also
815
816
817
818
819
Cael. 29.
Cael. 53. Also Cael. 16.
For prostitution, see McGinn 1998; and Faraone & McClure 2006.
Sest. 39.
Dom. 49. Cf. Opelt 1965, p. 155. For scortum, see Adams 1983, pp. 321–
327.
820 Richlin 1992, pp. 99–100. See also Edwards 1997; Duncan 2006.
Political Conflicts
261
circumscribed as a result of their being thought of as without
honor.821 The point of portraying someone as a prostitute is hereby clear; it was antithetical to being a Roman vir.822 An orator in
Rome could reference this logic of immorality without risking the
accusation that his attacks were just slanderous.
Using the services of prostitutes was not automatically cause
for moral censure.823 But associating with them as equals was
shameful and could easily be made to function as a sign of sexual
immorality. In the Verrines, for instance, Cicero frequently mentioned the fact that Verres had lenones and meretrices—pimps
and whores—as his guests.824 That in turn of course triggered the
idea of the immoral banquet of feast and subsequently what type
of sexual activities went on there. A wider context of immorality
was hereby activated. The real threat of the taint of being associated with prostitutes was thus that the target had in fact prostituted himself. It was therefore fundamentally based on the logic
of immorality that sexually submitting to the lust of others—with
or without payment—was immoral and led to immorality.
Another epithet illustrates this logic. Gabinius is referred to by
Cicero a leno impudicissimus—a sexually corrupted pimp, another time for as a leno impurissimus—foul or impure pimp.825
That his opponent was not only a pimp, but also sullied by sexual
passivity by the words impudicus and impurus in fact made perfect sense since it was grounded in a cultural creed which stated
821 For the legal rights of infames in general and pimps and prostitutes in particular, see McGinn 1998. See also Gardner 1993, chapter 5.
822 Edwards 1997, p. 81.
823 McGinn 1998, p. 344; McClure 2006, p. 11.
824 See Verr. 2.1.101, 2.3.6.
825 Red. sen. 12; Sest. 26. For Verres as a leno turpissimus, see Verr. 2.4.71. Cf.
Verr. 2.4.6. For the cultural and legal status of pimps, see McGinn, pp. 23–
69. Under the Lex Iulia municipalis, pimps were for instance barred from
public ofice.
262
making enemies
that in order to deal in acts of sexual depravity you were also
expected to have been sexually corrupted at one point. This was
not random insults strung together. For Cicero’s audience the reproach did not just say that you are a purveyor of disreputable
merchandise, but that this is a result of your own moral depravity. This same idea tied into the accusation that he had turned
to prostitution in order to sustain his depraved passions.826 Destitution backs up the allusion to prostitution and references an
idea that was culturally coherent—that the reason the elite lost
their wealth was a result of their immorality. For the same reason—immorality—you then risked becoming dangerous to the
community.
Other poignant themes were incest and stuprum. Cicero used
two motifs to brand Clodius as a sexual deviant in this regard;
the Bona Dea scandal and his immoral relationship with his sister
Clodia from whose bedroom, Cicero sarcastically had claimed,
he emerged as a defender of good Roman morality, of pudor and
pudicita.827 Although it was considered unnatural to engage in
sexual activity with kin, the term incestum also referred to violation of religious pudicitia.828 Therefore both the violation of the
female rites and the suggested incest between brother and sister
could be considered incestum. They blended together as immoral in Cicero’s oratory. Clodius, as we have previously seen, was
a man characterized by stuprum.829 Cicero also frequently emphasized the sacrilegious nature of these sexual acts. His sexual
826 Sest. 26. Cf. Red. sen. 11 (above). See also Corbeill 1996, p. 133.
827 Dom. 9. For Clodius’ incest, see also e.g. Sest. 116; Pis. 28; Cael. 32; Mil. 73.
See also the attack on Clodia in Cael. 32, 34–36, 38, 47, 49.
828 Fantham 1991, p. 289. Cf. Harries 2007, pp. 90–91. For incest, see also
Hickson-Hahn 1998.
829 Dom. 50: hominem omnium facinorum et stuprorum. For other accusations
of impiousness, see Har. resp. 26, 28–30.
Political Conflicts
263
trespass was interpreted by Cicero as an affront to the gods and
they consequently punished his behavior with madness.830 Verres’
stuprum had also been presented by Cicero as contra fas—against
sacred laws.831 Similarly, Clodius had polluted the sacred rites not
only by looking at them, but also incesto lagitio et stupro—“by
incestuous depravity and sexuality.”832 Sexual immorality could
clearly be associated with the religious concerns of the community. In this respect, immorality was also argued to be dangerous.
Other remarks that linked religion and incest were more mocking in tone. At one point Cicero responds to what seems to have
been an accusation from Clodius that Cicero had called himself
Jupiter and stated that Minerva was his sister. Cicero, who had a
particular devotion to the goddess, was thereby implicated as aspiring to tyranny. He replies to Clodius in the following manner:
Sed tamen ego mihi sororem virginem ascisco: tu sororem tuam
virginem esse non sisti. Sed vide ne tu te soleas Iovem dicere, quod
tu iure eamdem sororem et uxorem appellare possis.833
But at least I claim my sister a virgin: you have not allowed your
sister to be a virgin. But you should be careful getting used to
calling yourself Jupiter, since you rightfully can call the same
woman both sister and wife.
Just like the god, who could call Juno both wife and sister, Clodius could, mocks his opponent, refer to Clodia, whose virginity
he himself had violated, by both terms. The clever turn of phrase
830 Lenaghan 1969, p. 154. Cf. Har. resp. 48: Caecus amentia.
831 Verr. 2.5.34. For incest as threatening to the community, see Harries 2007,
p. 91.
832 Dom. 105. Also Har. resp. 4, 8, 38; Pis. 95; Mil. 13, 85, 87.
833 Dom. 92.
264
making enemies
was certainly meant to generate laughter and humiliation, thereby obfuscating the serious charge of tyranny.834 But the fact
that an orator could utilize serious cultural apprehensions for
comedic effect did not mean that the topic of sexual immorality
vis-à-vis religious trespass was treated in a light-hearted manner.
Instead it was included in Cicero’s catalogue of the offenses of
his adversaries:
Tu, cum furiales in contionibus voces mittis, cum domos civium
evertis, cum lapidibus optimos viros foro pellis, cum ardentes faces
in vicinorum tecta iactas, cum aedes sacras inlammas, cum servos
concitas, cum sacra ludosque conturbas, cum uxorem sororemque
non discernis, cum quod ineas cubile non sentis, tum baccharis,
tum furis, tum das eas poenas, quae solae sunt hominum sceleri a
dis immortalibus constitutae.835
You, when you hurl your frenzied utterances at the contio, when
you overturn citizens’ houses, when you drive the best men from
the forum with rocks, when you throw burning torches onto the
roofs of your neighbors, when you set sacred buildings ablaze,
when you stir up slaves, when you disturb that which is sacred and
the games, when you do not distinguish between wife and sister,
when you do not know whose bedchamber you enter, then you are
in delirium, then you are in frenzy, then you receive the only punishment that the Immortal Gods have ordained for human crime.
The long list of crimes, which include the political offenses of
rioting and violence, also makes pointed references to religious
trespass. This could be seen as expected considering the religious
834 See Hickson-Hahn 1998, p. 22.
835 Har. resp. 39.
Political Conflicts
265
occasion for this speech. Yet, we should note that accusations of
incest and adultery follow naturally in the catalogue of Clodius’
wrongdoing and logically set up the punishment of the gods that
Cicero asserts. In no way do charges of immorality seem misplaced in this passage. Instead, I would argue, they help form the
raison d’être of the passage. The inclusion of depravity among
other forms of trespass can be attributed to a cultural logic that
equated immoral character with the expectation of any type of
crime. In Pro Milone, Cicero makes this point: A good man cannot be induced to crime, but an improbus or immoral man will
easily be compelled to do so.836 In the same speech, this time
without the religious setting, Cicero in a long harangue conlated “impious adultery on holy couches,” which required punishment to cleanse the state from pollution and sacrilegious incest
with his sister, with accusations of political violence, corruption,
plundering, and destruction.837 Similarly, irst stating that Clodius
was a whore to the wealthy, who committed adultery with his
sister and was a priest of stuprum,838 not only actively argued
that since he was sexually passive he could be expected to sexually corrupt others as well as Roman religion, but also allowed
the orator to continue branding him a poisoner, a forger of wills,
an assassin, and a bandit. Once portrayed as immoral, the other
offences could follow without effort or distinction.
As a result of Roman anxieties over passiveness, certain types
of sex were also especially degrading precisely because they turned the man into the submissive party. In particular accusations of
performing oral sex tainted the victim.839 Speaking about orato836 Mil. 32. For ethos in the Pro Milone, see May 1979.
837 Mil. 72–73. See also Mil. 87.
838 Sest. 39: cum scurrarum locupletium scorto, cum sororis adultero, cum stuprorum sacerdote, cum veneico, cum testamentario, cum sicario, cum latrone.
839 Richlin, 1992, p. 99. Cf. Skinner 1982, p. 204.
266
making enemies
rical strategies, Quintilianus mentions in passing that acts which
violate the mouth will stir great embarrassment in an audience.840
As we saw in the previous section of this chapter, Vatinius’ mouth
signaled sexual immorality. His boils around the mouth were
a sign to be read and interpreted. In his prosecution of Verres,
Cicero made several references to the mouth of his most immoral
companion Apronius. In fact, like Vatinius, Apronius advertised
his vile depravity not only with his life, but also with his body
and mouth. 841 One remark stated that while not even wild beasts
could endure the vile smell that came from his mouth, Verres
alone had found it pleasant, thus implicating him in the sexual
immorality that it symbolized. Similarly, one of Clodius’ familiars Sextus Cloelius had an extremely ilthy mouth, os impurissimum.842 He stole away Clodius’ sister, Clodia with his tongue
and could be found with her capite demisso—“head down.”843
In the Pro Caelio, Cicero describes him as a man without estate
or credit, without hope, home or fortune, whose mouth, tongue,
hand, and entire life are stained.844 These statements certainly implicated Clodius in similar acts.845 Gabinius was likewise accused
of having tainted breath (contaminatus spiritus),846 and when
Cicero encountered Piso coming out of a drinking den, he complained that his enemy reeked from the mouth (os foetidus).847 By
840 Quint. Inst. 11.1.84.
841 Verr. 2.3.23.
842 Dom. 26. Also Har. resp. 11; Dom. 47; for which cf. Adams 1982, pp. 140–
141. For Cicero’s attacks on Sextus Cloelius, see Uría 2006. For the identity
of this man, see Damon 1992.
843 Dom. 25, 83. Cf. Adams 1982, p. 192.
844 Cael. 78: hominem sine re, sine ide, sine spe, sine sede, sine fortunis, ore,
lingua, manu, vita omni inquinatum.
845 See also Dom. 104.
846 Pis. 20.
847 Pis. 13.
Political Conflicts
267
this particular motif of passivity, Cicero suggested that his main
rivals were immoral.
There is an ostensible paradox in the sexual morality of ancient Rome. As shown, playing the passive role in sexual activities was considered unmanly and degrading for a member of
the elite. To be subjected was a sign of weakness and low status.
Slaves, women, and freedmen were submissive by nature, and
passiveness in a man suggested that he should be counted among
these instead of among the viri. Therefore, a modern observer
would perhaps expect an aggressive sex drive, as long as the male
stayed the active one, to be considered unproblematic or even
appropriate.848 It was not. That is, at least not according to the
notion of immorality that Cicero fell back on in his political representations. Active “womanizing” could also be construed as
depraved. Lust was a matter of reproach. To explain this, we can
turn to a cultural understanding of immorality that ensured that
this apparent paradox made perfect sense.
During the 50’s BCE, Piso was most haunted by Cicero’s accusations in this regard. In the speech Post reditum in senatu,
Cicero presented the character of Piso as a man who kept his
pleasures hidden from the public eye. But if you saw him at home
you would see him for what he was, a ilthy and intemperate libidinosus.849 To emphasize this Cicero labels him a perverted Epicurean, his sole focus on indulgence and pleasure.850 This lust led
him to “drown in immoral acts” (lagitium) and he listened only
to “his Greeks” in taverns, and when indulging in stuprum, food,
and wine.851 Hence, his immoral lust clearly pertained to both
sexual and non-sexual desires. Herein, then, lies part of the logic
848
849
850
851
See Gleason 1999, p. 76; Langlands 2006, pp. 292–293.
Red. sen. 14.
For Piso as an Epicurean, see Red. sen. 15; Sest. 23; Pis. 37, 42, 59.
Pis. 42: te in tot lagitia ingurgitasses.
268
making enemies
behind the ostensible paradox. Immoderation in food, drink, and
sex was without hesitation linked in the immoral chain. Therefore Cicero’s comment that his enemy attached the highest value to the pleasures of the belly pointed in the same direction
as sexual gratiication and in fact strengthened his portrayal.852
Immorality was a critique of self-control.
But there is one more piece to this puzzle. Part of Cicero’s derision of his philosophy was that Piso had met an Epicurean at an
early age who, because of Piso’s immaturity at the time, instead
of a magister virtutis became to Piso an auctor libidinis or “authority on lust.”853 The taunt should not only be interpreted as a
bit of scandalous invective, but as itting the logic of immorality
that explained why lust was not manly. Lust was construed in
Cicero’s portraits as a result of immorality, often at a young age,
which had branded the target as passive. That Verres for instance
continued to violate women should be understood as a consequence of his own submissive sexual history. In the speech De
provinciis consularibus Cicero discusses Piso’s rule of his province and the crimes he committed there:
caedes relinquo, libidines praetereo, quarum acerbissimum exstat
indicium et ad insignem memoriam turpitudinis et paene ad
iustum odium imperii nostri, quod constat nobilissimas virgines se
in puteos abiecisse et morte voluntaria necessariam turpitudinem
depulisse.854
I pass over murders; I leave out lustful deeds, of which we have the
sharpest proof, serving as a record of his disgrace and almost as
852 Pis. 66.
853 Pis. 69.
854 Prov. cons. 6. For such dangers of immorality, see also Dom. 144; Mil. 76.
For character in the de provinciis consularibus, see Steel 2001, pp. 47–52.
Political Conflicts
269
justiication of the hatred of our rule, in the fact that noble virgins
have thrown themselves into wells and by voluntary death avoided
inevitable shame.
The portrait of Piso here closely echoes the one Cicero had constructed of Verres 14 years before. Like Verres, Piso continued to
display excessive lust because of his perverted sexuality; in his
case a result of his dealings with the Epicurean. Clodius’ lust had
the same consequences.855 Whether or not this was true is beside
the point here. What matters is that it itted the logic of immorality. Once Cicero had made the connection for his audience,
it ought to have made sense. As a result, so should Piso’s other
crimes.
The passage above links both murder and political malpractice
to lustful character, but is furthermore interesting because Cicero,
after this passage, holds that he omits these charges because at
present he has no witnesses. The proof, in other words, rests solely with the argument.856 To argue lust, then, the orator could offer
the audience certain signs. In the Pro Sestio, Piso’s philosophy of
pleasure was mocked by Cicero in the following manner:
Ex his assiduis eius cotidianisque sermonibus, et quod videbam,
quibuscum hominibus in interiore parte aedium viveret, et quod
ita domus ipsa fumabat, ut multa eius sordium indicia redolerent,
statuebam sic, boni nihil ab illis nugis esse exspectandum, mali
quidem certe nihil pertimescendum.857
855 Mil. 76.
856 Cf. Cael. 22; Scaur. 15, 19.
857 Sest. 24.
270
making enemies
From his constant everyday talk of this sort, and because I saw
what kind of men he lived with in the inner parts of his house, and
because the house itself reeked with the stinking signs of many
sordid acts, I decided that one would expect nothing good from his
idle talk, and that one certainly did not need to fear no any harm.
Here we see the connection pointed to earlier in the case of Gabinius, that the result of immoral character was that no good
could be expected. Because, as previously discussed, Piso hid his
depravity Cicero reproached his house in reference to company and smell, which in turn serve as indicia of immorality. Like
Sextus Naevius in Cicero’s irst extant speech the Pro Quinctio,
Piso’s immorality was illustrated by his sordid household which
pointed to his perverted views of Epicurean pleasures. As we saw
in the portrait of Chrysogonus, another way to cast suspicion on
someone’s house was by the theme of luxury. Excess in things
meant excess in matters of morality, and lust and luxuria as a
consequence were associated in the Roman mind. When portraying Piso, Cicero stresses that no one is more excessive (luxuriosus) and more licentious (libidinosus) before adding, just to
be sure, that nor is anyone as low (posterus) or vile (nequior)
as he.858 And while Cicero reluctantly admits there is a type of
luxury that could pass for digniied, he also directly asserts that
the only thing grand about the uncouth Piso is his lust.859 When
defending a man named Balbus who stood accused of luxuria,
Cicero, similar to his line of defense in the Pro Murena, pointed
to the fact that his luxury was not substantiated by accusations
858 Pis. 67.
859 Pis. 67: Luxuriem autem nolite in isto hanc cogitare: est enim quaedam,
quamquam omnis est vitiosa atque turpis, tamen ingenuo ac libero dignior:
nihil apud hunc lautum, nihil elegans, nihil exquisitum—laudabo inimicum—
quin ne magno opere quidem quicquam praeter libidines sumptuosum.
Political Conflicts
271
of lust.860 As we saw in Cicero’s portrayal of Verres, lust was always accompanied by other faults of character and could, by way
of supplying character and motivation, point toward guilt. In De
domo sua, Piso is in this manner described as most offensive (taeterrimus), cruel (crudelissimus), and false (fallacissimus), branded with the stains of both lust and crime.861 Plunder, greed, lust,
and luxury were also linked in Gabinius who had plundered his
province, squandered the wealth through his lust and unheard-of
luxuries.862 Another consequence of lust was religious trespass;
Clodius’ foul lust had caused him to violate two of Rome’s most
sacred possessions: religion and pudicitia.863 In turn, his punishment was blind lust.864
Male lust was not the only topic of concern for the orator.
Cicero also discusses at great length the lust of Clodius’ sister,
Clodia, “a woman not only of nobility, but also of notoriety.”865
In doing so, he supplies us with further clues as to the relationship between lust and immorality. Cicero’s client Marcus Caelius
had been accused by the prosecution of intimacy with Clodia.
Her lust was portrayed as a danger to young men. She was, according to Cicero, surrounded by rumors of lust, lovers, adultery, feast, and parties, music and revelry.866 In the fashionable
vacation spot Baiae there was talk of her lust which she paraded
openly.867 She too, could be judged by her appearance and Cicero
could use it to excuse his client’s involvement with her:
860
861
862
863
864
865
Balb. 56.
Dom. 23. For Piso’s lust, see also Red. sen. 13–14.
Pis. 48. Also: Dom. 60; Red. pop. 13.
Prov. cons. 24.
Har. resp. 38.
Cael. 31: muliere non solum nobili, sed etiam nota. For Cicero’s attack on
Clodia, see e.g. Dixon 2001; McCoy 2006; Tatum 2011.
866 Cael. 35.
867 Cael. 47. See Grifin 1985, p. 90. For Baiae, see also Sen. Ep. 51.
272
making enemies
Si quae non nupta mulier domum suam patefecerit omnium
cupiditati palamque sese in meretricia vita collocarit, virorum
alienissimorum conviviis uti instituerit, si hoc in urbe, si in hortis,
si in Baiarum illa celebritate faciat, si denique ita sese gerat nonincessu solum, sed ornatu atque comitatu, non lagrantia oculorum,
non libertate sermonum, sed etiam complexu, osculatione, actis,
navigatione, conviviis, ut non solum meretrix, sed etiam proterva
meretrix procaxque videatur; cum hac si qui adulescens forte
fuerit, utrum hic tibi, L. Herenni, adulter an amator, expugnare
pudicitiam an explere libidinem voluisse videatur?868
If an unmarried woman opened her house to the passions of all
and publicly led the life of a whore, attending banquets with totally unknown men, if she does this in the city, in the gardens, among
the crowds of Baiae, if additionally she carries herself so that not
only her bearing, but also her dress and escort, not only the glow
of her eyes, her lustful talk, but also her embraces and kisses, her
parties on the beach and at sea and banquets, betray her to be not
only a whore, but a shameless and wanton whore and if a young
man happened to be with her, would that look to you, Lucius
Herennius, like an adulterer or a lover, like someone who wanted
to ravage her chastity or satisfy his own lust?
The passage illustrates that, unsurprisingly, all types of lust were
not necessarily equally reproachable.869 If the woman’s lust was
like that of a whore, the man only satisied his own needs, which
could be considered proper, without committing an offense. The
868 Cael. 49. See also Cael. 50. Cf. Cael. 38.
869 Jonathan Walters reminds us that: “The ‘woman’ constructed by men, particularly perhaps when that construction is embedded in a discourse addressed
primarily to other men, is a male igment, used to say something about men,
not about women.” Walters 1997, p. 32. Cf. Gleason 1995, pp. 160–161.
Political Conflicts
273
offense was to another man, the husband or father. Moreover,
that the woman in question was a meretrix and not a woman of
standing could be established by Cicero’s oratorical representation which focused on her house and her looks.870 Through his
oratory, Cicero negotiated, with the help of signs of immorality,
the term adulter, which he reasoned was inappropriate for his
client. The marks of lust were attached to another person to identify her as immoral. This was not the irst time Cicero had argued
that his client had been a victim to a woman’s lust. The immorality and lust of Sassia, the mother of Cicero’s client, had played a
prominent part in 66 BCE in his defense of Cluentius.871
The consequence of a deviant and depraved sexuality—and
also a reason for the fear of it—is apparent from several passages in the speeches under present scrutiny. When assailing Piso,
Cicero linked lust with idleness and inactivity, desidia and inertia.872 These traits were enumerated by the anonymous author
of the rhetorical treatise Ad Herrenium as adducing contempt
in an audience, and hence goodwill for the speaker.873 More
importantly, it signaled lack of virtus. Clodius tried to hide his
lust supericially, instead of with pudor and self-control (temperantia), character traits of the vir.874 Likewise, Gabinius was a
man exhausted (confectus) by wine, gluttony, prostitution, and
adultery.875 They were both enervati and exsangues, meaning effeminate and without energy and strength.876 Sexual debauchery,
870 For the idea that as long as a man did not commit an offense against another
man his behavior could be deemed unproblematic, see also Cael. 42. For the
comparison between houses, see Cael. 55, 57.
871 See also Scaur. 8. Cf. Gildenhard 2011, p. 62.
872 Sest. 22. For Verres’ lack of manly strength, see also Verr. 2.5.39.
873 Rhet. Her. 1.8.
874 Prov. cons. 8.
875 Sest. 20.
876 Sest. 24. See also Edwards 1993, p. 86.
274
making enemies
and its accompanying vices, depleted the strength of men. That in
turn made them unit for public life. Sexual passivity also led to,
and could hence be illustrated with, passivity and lack of manly
vigor in general. As proof that Caelius did not have the immoral
character his chastisers had claimed, Cicero argued that it is impossible for a mind marked by lust and related vices to be able
to cope with the demands of public speaking.877 Caelius was a
renowned orator and could thus not be suspected of immorality.
Seneca the Elder had the same notion and challenged anyone to
ind orators among the lustful.878 The strain of political life was
incompatible with the corruption that followed from vice. When
attacking Clodius, the orator summoned this logic when he asked his audience, “what energy could a man who had led such a
life have; a man exhausted by disgrace with brothers, stuprum
with sisters and every unheard of act of lust?”879 Lust, incest, and
stuprum all led to a diminished masculinity. Summoning these
moral concepts in oratory therefore had meaning beyong trying
to get a routine audience reaction or simply acquire goodwill.
Cicero’s point was culturally coherent, as was his line of reasoning. Immoral men were incapable of guiding the res publica.
The Excessive and The Immoral
In his speech against Piso, Cicero at one point refers to his colleague Gabinius as saltatrix tonsa or shaved dancing girl.880 This
877 Cael. 45–47. Cf. Cic. Orat. 59.
878 Sen. Controv. 1, praef. 10.
879 Sest. 16: qui enim in eius modi vita nervi esse potuerunt hominis fraternis
lagitiis, sororiis stupris, omni inaudita libidine exsanguis? Cf. Corbeill 1996,
p. 115. For enervatus, see Pis. 82. For exsanguis, see also Har. resp. 2; Pis.
88.
880 Pis. 18.
Political Conflicts
275
humiliating epithet triggered a wide array of immoral associations existing in Roman society. By following the threads that
made saltatrix tonsa a meaningful taunt in Roman political culture, we shall attempt to disentangle as far as possible the web
of immorality evoked in the portraits Cicero painted of his rivals
of the 50’s BCE. The insult, I argue, rather than beside the point,
was consistent with Roman notions of political immorality.
First and foremost, Cicero called him not a dancer, but a dance
girl—saltatrix. We might safely surmise by this that his main
point was that Gabinius was effeminate. By further referencing
the appearance of Gabinius, Cicero continued to establish an
immoral connection between deviant appearance and inherent
immorality. As we saw in the beginning of this chapter, Roman
audiences could expect a correlation between the two. In this
case, the appearance of Gabinius signaled, through an immoral
train of thought, sexual depravity. Shaving the body hair was for
a man associated with an unnatural desire to appear young.881
This in turn meant that he wanted to appear desirable to others,
which was seen as a female and passive quality. In sum, both
saltatrix and tonsa were reproaches to Gabinius’ manhood and
suggested that he was sexually submissive. There were however
further associations to be made from the epithet that strengthened this suspicion.
With its reference to dancing, labeling Gabinius a saltatrix tonsa pointed clearly toward revelry and feasting, evidenced further
by the two consuls in Cicero’s vivid scene being dragged from a
dark popina or cook-shop into the Senate.882 The convivium, as
we have repeatedly seen, was a culturally recognized immoral
881 See Sen. Controv. 1, praef. 8–9.
882 Pis. 13. For Gabinius as a dancer, see Red. sen. 13; Dom. 60.
276
making enemies
arena, the scene of drunkenness, indulgence, excess, and sex.883
There were numerous ways of referencing the feast, and thereby
triggering its connotations, several of which have been previously
touched upon. That Gabinius appeared drunk and sleepy at a
contio should be read by Cicero’s audience as a consequence of
his dedication to the pleasures of the feast.884 Smelling of wine, as
Piso had done, was likewise a sure sign. The followers of Catilina
could be identiied by perfume and garlands. Excess and spending could furthermore signal the immorality of feasting, illustrated by Cicero’s question to the jury regarding Chrysogonus in
the Pro Roscio Amerino: “Can you imagine what daily expenses
come from such a life, what excessiveness, what banquets?”885
Cicero defended Marcus Caelius, who had been attacked by the
prosecution as an immoral man, by saying that in his client you
would ind no luxuries, no extravagance (sumptus), no debts and
no lust for banquets and feasts.886 We have also seen how closely
Cicero linked Clodia’s lust with parties of extravagant kind.
Gluttony logically became an important vice in this web of immorality. Drunkenness was a sure sign of excess.887 In the speech
before the senate upon his return, Cicero labels him a curly-haired ganeo, in several other speeches he is referred to as a helluo.888
At other times he is called a gurges, a whirlpool that glutted the
883 Gabinius’ scene of depravity was chiely the convivium, whereas Piso’s was
the shabby drinking den or cook-shop. See Pis. 13, 22.
884 Ovid also comments on the risks of falling asleep at a banquet when immoral acts could be done to you. Ars am. 3.767–768.
885 Rosc. Am. 134: In hac vita, iudices, quos sumptus cotidianos, quas effusiones ieri putatis, quae vero convivia?
886 Cael. 44.
887 For conceptions of drinking, see Grifin 1985, pp. 65–87.
888 Red. sen. 12. For Gabinius as a glutton, see also Red. sen. 13; Prov. cons. 11,
14. Sextus Cloelius was referred to as a helluo in Dom. 25; while Gellius was
also referred to as a ganeo and gurges in Sest. 111.
Political Conflicts
277
blood of the Republic.889 Overindulgence in food could in turn
be associated with luxury and as a result to squandering of money.890 Catilina’s boon companions were destitute because of their
revelry and so inancial ruin was a symptom of immoral character. This in turn represented a danger to the community.891 Gabinius, therefore, was a helluo patriae, a glutton devouring his
own country and just as he had depleted his patrimony, he would
deplete his patria.892 Gluttony, feasting, and greed, as discussed by
Anthony Corbeill, were linked, both morally and semantically.893
A major point was also that the glutton was sexually corrupted.
Lack of control as regards intake of food and wine suggested lack
of sexual control. Marilyn B. Skinner points out that charges of
squandering money were followed, logically to the Romans, by
accusations of singing, dancing, feasting, adultery, and sexual passivity—“vices linked together in a metonymic chain” connected
to the excess of wealth.894 Sallustius also emphasized this. Avaritia
makes the body and mind of a man effeminate.895
There was a certain type of company one could expect to
ind at an immoral feast; in particular actors and prostitutes. In
the same manner, the banquet could be likened to a brothel, the
participants to prostitutes and pimps.896 Typically, these shady
characters both signaled the immorality that took place and explained why the feast was thought of as immoral. In the guide to
political campaigning attributed to Quintus Cicero, the link was
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
Dom. 124. Cf. Sest. 93.
Edwards 1993, p. 186.
Edwards 1993, p. 176.
Sest. 26.
See Corbeill 1996, p. 131.
Skinner 2005, p. 211. Cf. Edwards 1993, p. 5.
Sall. Cat. 11.3: corpus animumque virilem effeminat. See also Gell. NA. 3.1.
Red. sen. 11; Sest. 20, 26. Cf. Pis. 42. See also Val. Max. 7.7.7. Cf. James
2006. See also McGinn 1998, p. 348.
278
making enemies
explicitly made in connection with Catilina and offered as a way
of undermining him: He was friends with actors (histriones) and
lived lustfully with them.897 The feast was a place where stuprum
and adultery took place.898 Branding the former consul a saltatrix
tonsa furthermore portrayed Gabinius himself as an entertainer.
As discussed in relation to Pro Murena, dancing at parties was
highly suspect since it, to Cicero at least, should suggest a host of
closely related vices. But it also suggested that in entertaining, you
were the agent of the pleasures of others and not vice versa.899 By
the same rationale as sexual immorality, and most deinitely referencing it, this of course made a Roman man seem passive and
effeminate. One passage in the speech against Piso depicts him
as dancing nude at a banquet with song and cymbals.900 In Pro
Sestio, Cicero harangues Clodius with a similar motif.
Ipse ille maxime ludius, non solum spectator, sed actor et acroama,
qui omnia sororis embolia novit, qui in coetum mulierum pro
psaltria adducitur.901
That great stage performer himself, not solely a spectator, but an
actor and entertainer, who knows all the “interludes” of his sister,
who is admitted into a company of women dressed like a harp-girl.
The cultural link between actors and sexual immorality is manifest in the depiction of the incest between Clodius and Clodia. The
897 Comment. pet. 10. For Roman disdain of the theatre, see also Wistrand
1992, pp. 30–40; Edwards 1993, chapter 3.
898 Pis. 71.
899 For entertainment as subjection, see Bartsch, 2006, p. 139.
900 Pis. 22: Cum conlegae tui domus cantu et cymbalis personaret cumque ipse
nudus in convivio saltaret. Cf. Apronius in Verr. 2.3.24.
901 Sest. 116.
Political Conflicts
279
mention of Clodius’ feminine attire and the company of women links it with his sexual corruption. The passage was entirely
coherent with Roman views on sexual morality. Both actors and
prostitutes were “symbols of the shameful” in ancient Rome.902
Their legal status was that of infames.903 They were both available
to provide pleasure.904 Being called and actor and a harp-girl—
and a saltatrix tonsa—hence referenced the same logic of immorality. Those who are sexually available to others are to be treated
as having no honor—as infames.
Finally, since feasting was immoral it could logically be presented in Roman oratory as detrimental to political ability:
Quid ego illorum dierum epulas, quid laetitam et gratulationem
tuam, quid cum tuis sordidissimis gregibus intemperantissimas perpotationes praedicem? Quis te illis diebus sobrium, quis agentem
aliquid quod esset libero dignum, quis denique in publico vidit?905
Why should I relate the banquets of your days, your exultation
and rejoicing, your unrestrained drinking bout with your crew of
most sordid men? Who in those days ever saw you sober, who saw
you doing anything that beits a free man, who even saw you in
public?
The passage echoes the concerns of the political commentator
Polybios writing the history of Rome in the second century BCE.
902 Edwards 1997, p. 66. Also Richlin 1992, p. 10; and McGinn 1998, p. 68. See
also Duncan 2006.
903 For this, see also Cic. Rep. 4.10.
904 Edwards 1997, p. 85: “Subordinated to the desires of others, these infamous
persons are assimilated to the feminine and the servile, unworthy to be fully
Roman citizens.” See also Cic. Off. 1.150.
905 Pis. 22.
280
making enemies
Young men had been made weak from their love affairs with
boys and prostitutes and from luxurious banquets adopted from
Greece.906 This was not only deplorable, but also dangerous. In
Cicero’s attack on Piso above, the same concern is invoked. We
should particularly take note of the word libero—free. Libertas
was a deining characteristic of the elite and their concept of status and manhood.907 Immorality was diametrically opposed to
the expected behavior of the elite, distinguished by their status
as free.
Conclusion: Political Conflicts
In a fragment from 142 BCE, preserved in Gellius, Scipio Aemilianus attacked Publius Sulpicius Galus. His reproach connects
several of the thematic points covered in this chapter:
nam qui cotidie unguentatus adversus speculum ornetur, cuius supercilia radantur, qui barba vulsa feminibusque subvulsis ambulet,
qui in conviviis adulescentulus cum amatore cum chiridota tunica
inferior accubuerit, qui non modo vinosus, sed virosus quoque sit,
eumne quisquam dubitet, quin idem fecerit, quid cinaedi facere
solent?908
For he who daily perfumed adorns himself before the mirror,
whose eyebrows are shaved, who with his beard and thigh hair
plucked out walks around, who in the banquet as a young man
with his lover, dressed in long-sleeved tunica, lies at a low spot,
906 Polyb. 31.25.
907 Nicolet 1980, p. 320; and Alston 1998, pp. 208–209. For libertas, see also
Wirszurbinski 1950; Brunt 1988, pp. 281–350. See also Williams 2010, pp.
124–125.
908 Gell. NA. 6.12.5= ORF 21.17.
Political Conflicts
281
who not only likes wine, but also men; who could doubt that he
has done what the cinaedi do?
The man who pays too much attention to his appearance and
tries to look young and smooth, hiding his natural manly features, is the same man who reclines at banquets like Catilina’s
followers with older men. Their dress and drunkenness reveal
their position in lustful relationships and their passive role, the
role of the cinaedus or pathic.909 The cultural power of the banquet, we are therefore informed, is the arena of illicit, immoral
sexual activity which made men into women.
In the 50’s BCE, Cicero vehemently portrayed the politicians
he felt had been the cause of his ruin as immoral. To a large
extent, in Cicero depictions of Clodius, Gabinius, Piso, and Vatinius, this immorality converged in the effeminate Roman male
to which a considerable cultural anxiety was tied. Above all their
immorality was linked to their lack of manliness. They were not
viri, that is, they were not part of the elite as free men of power.
Instead they were like women, weak and passive, unable to take
part in the governing of state.910 They looked like women, had
sex like women, and participated in the arena where this intersected.
The relevance of reproaching an adversary’s appearance had
wider ramiications than mere mockery. The external betrayed
the internal.911 It was not that his enemies looked funny that
made Cicero’s representations powerful. Instead, his visual portraits proclaimed that they were immoral. This immorality was
constructed from several overlapping aspects into a coherent
909 For the cinaedus, see Richlin 1993; Gleason 1995, pp. 62–67; Taylor 1997,
pp. 349–357.
910 Cf. Gildenhard 2011, pp. 9–10.
911 Corbeill 1996, p. 162; Dyck 2001, p. 121. Cf. Walters 1998, p. 357.
282
making enemies
whole the orator assumed his audience could relate to. External
signs made it possible for the Roman orator to persuasively argue
that his opponents were unit to lead.
It was not just there to behold, unless the speaker acted as
his community’s interpreter. Signs played a large role in arguing
immorality. Clodius’ female dress and his entire appearance,
his walk, his voice, and his clothes were offered as visual evidence. Gabinius’ hair betrayed his desire to appear less manly.
This in turn was considered unnatural by the Roman moralists.
His perfume also was in the same manner unnatural. Certain
clothes, cosmetics, perfume, or other altercations to appearance
could be attempts to liken someone to a prostitute or an actor—
both infames, both thought of as sexually immoral.912 Vatinius’
bodily deformity, while more striking to the spectator, likewise
had to be presented and argued as mirroring his internal immorality.
Effeminacy deduced from external signs in turn revealed sexual bias. If you took on the passive role in sexual intercourse you
lost your status as a vir and your membership in the governing
elite. This was in fact dangerous to all of society. The passiveness
of men made them unit for politics and military duty. Moreover,
sexual immorality led to further acts of depravity and always
risked corrupting others. Once moral integrity had collapsed the
individual was only capable of deplorable acts.
Being available to the lusts of others and not being the one
whose pleasures were of primary concern was tied to societal
status. At the top of society’s pyramid were the men who were
free and active. Part of being a vir was independence from the
control of others.913 All below them on that pyramid were subject
912 See also Sen. Q Nat. 7.31.
913 Alston 1998, p. 206; Frederick 2002, p. 258.
Political Conflicts
283
to their whims and pleasures, to corporeal violation and subjugation. They were passive and unfree.
Several other marks of sexuality could be evoked by the Roman
orator to signal sexual immorality. Incest and stuprum, for instance made the sexual violation a religious crime. Lust likewise,
even if active and, in modern views, “manly” could be understood by Cicero’s audience to be immoral and a sign of unmanly
character. Also, lust could be logically construed as naturally following upon sexual submission. Once corrupted, the young male
grew into a depraved individual and forfeited his chance of being
accepted in the upper stratum of society’s hierarchy. The violated
Roman man displayed uncontrollable and depraved desires. In
other words, he let his passions rule him. This of course made
him unit for public life, the domain of the uncorrupted elite
male.914 The homo effeminatus could in Cicero’s oratory quite
literally be positioned against the vir fortis.915
Certain venues where immorality could be easily imagined
to take place were also important for the orator. The feast or
convivium remained a powerful setting and motif where effeminate, passive acts took place. Beside the immoral feast, the dark
tavern, the brothel, or the luxurious vacation spot could all function as probable scenes for excess and vice. Gluttony and luxury
connected to destitution and inancial debt were in themselves
marks of lack of self-control but thereby also alluded to sexual
immorality because it was at such places that these activities took
place.916 This also functioned as a potent contrast to the political
arena. Seneca remarked that while virtue was found in Rome’s
public spaces, “you will more often ind pleasure lurking around
914 Cf. Gleason 1999, p. 72; Skinner 2005, p. 212.
915 Mil. 89.
916 See also Sall. Cat. 1.1, 2.8. Cf. Sen. Ep. 60.4.
284
making enemies
searching for the darkness around public baths, sweating rooms,
and those places that dread the aedile; soft and effeminate, reeking of unmixed wine and perfume, pale or perhaps painted and
made up with cosmetics.”917
Political reasons for portraying your adversary as sexually passive, as an actor or as a pimp can also be found in Roman law.
The Lex Iulia municipalis stated that a man qui corpore suo mulebria passus est—that had been “bodily treated as a woman,”
should be excluded from political ofice holding alongside actors and brothel owners.918 Albeit from a later date than Cicero’s
portrayals, the cultural values underlying this law were likely
found in the preceding decades. Whether a legal question or not
in the 50’s BCE, sexual immorality was no doubt cause for political exclusion.
Cultural logic gave the portrait of the effeminate Roman politician its meaning and relevance in political discourse. It was not
misrepresentation or humiliating jabs taken in stride. The logic
of immorality dictated that the feminine man was immoral because the effeminacy in itself was a consequence of immorality.
Immorality was corrupting. Being immoral also meant he was
dangerous to the Republic since in the Roman mind world there
existed a relevant dichotomy between good men and bad men
which to a large extent was deined as categories by a shared
understanding of immoral and improper behavior.
The elite ruled by merit of the moral superiority. They ruled
by governing and defending the res publica. An effeminate man
could not do this. But not only because he was viewed as lack-
917 Sen. Dial. 7.7: voluptatem latitantem saepius ac tenebras captantem circa
balinea ac sudatoria ac loca aedilem metuentia, mollem eneruem, mero atque unguento madentem, pallidam aut fucatam et medicamentis pollinctam.
918 Dig. 3.1.1.
Political Conflicts
285
ing the necessary strength, but because nothing good could be
expected of an immoral man. This made immorality a political
question.
Chapter VI
End Game
—The Final Years (44–43 BCE)
In the years following a turbulent decade of oratorical battles, Marcus Tullius Cicero withdrew from the public arenas of
politics. After serving as proconsul in Cilicia between 51 and 50,
the orator turned to philosophy in the 40’s only to resurface on
the speaker’s platform for a handful of court cases in 46 and 45
BCE.919 By then, however, Rome had changed.
In the irst month of the year 49, Gaius Julius Caesar had crossed the river Rubicon and a line in Roman political culture. After
the Civil War that ensued between him and Gnaeus Pompeius
Magnus, power now rested with one man. The senatorial elite
had inally lost its grip on Roman politics. Cicero had stood on
the side of the optimates, the Senate, and on the side of Pompeius.
Political life changed with one-man rule, and as a result, so
ostensibly did the dynamic of the traditional rivalry of the elite.
One can argue that the use of oratory diminished during the next
phase of Roman history and the importance of arguing and portraying immorality along with it.920 Reaching the top of the cursus
honorum in the rule of emperors was simply not a matter of
aristocratic competition anymore.
919 For these, so called Caesarian speeches, see Gotoff 1993, and 2002.
920 For the changing role of oratory during the principate, see Rutledge 2007.
286
End Game
287
There was to be one more opportunity for the man from Arpinum to return to the scene of oratory and the topic of immorality.
He had one more political battle to ight and one more enemy to
construct—Marcus Antonius. In doing so he would indeed both
fail and succeed. He did not save the Roman Republic with his
oratory, but the portrait of immorality lingered for two millennia; and it was powerful enough to claim his life.
For the last time, Cicero argued his representation of an adversary; his portrait of immorality. Once again he interpreted the
signs for his audience and merged morality and politics into a
coherent whole. The task was to cast Antonius as the enemy of
Rome and to convince his senatorial audience to oficially declare him a hostis. Oratorical reasoning naturally took center
stage. Before legally becoming the enemy, Antonius had to be
convincingly depicted and constructed as one. The immorality
argument was again brought to the fore.
The conlict with Marcus Antonius, interpreted by Cicero as
the battle for the Republic, was the culmination of Cicero’s antagonistic oratory and his inal rivalry. He had made use of the
immorality argument since the early years of his legal career. He
had vanquished Catilina by arguing the existence of an immoral
threat against the state. His vengeance on the men he blamed
for his exile was exerted by portraying them as depraved and
disgraceful. The last question remaining, then, is what part immorality played in making Marcus Antonius an enemy of Rome.
The Battle for the Republic
In December of 44, Cicero wrote the following line in a letter to
Quintus Corniicius:
288
making enemies
Nos hic cum homine gladiatore omnium nequissimo, collega
nostro, Antonio, bellum gerimus, sed non pari condicione, contra
arma verbis.921
We are here waging war with the most worthless gladiator of
all, our colleague Antonius, but not on equal terms, words stand
against arms.
The sentence poignantly encapsulates the overall premise of the
present study: politics at Rome was inherently about conlict between individuals fought on the orator’s stage. Cicero here refers
to this aristocratic combat as bellum, as a war where speeches
could be understood as weapons, albeit as Cicero admits, sometimes inferior to the force of arms. But Cicero’s letter also demonstrates the perspective advocated in this study that this was
conlict between equals, collegae, which had to be—with the aid
of oratory—constructed as inferior, as gladiatores nequissimi.
Oratory is hereby recognized as political action, not as empty
words disguising the true nature of politics. Words were Cicero’s
weapon and it was a weapon that he mastered.
The importance of oratory also factored in the aftermath of
Caesar’s murder. Approximately six months before the clash between Cicero and Antonius, Gaius Julius Caesar had been assassinated by members of the elite discontent with his authority. This
act, preceded by the Civil war between Caesar and Pompeius as
well as Caesar’s inluence on the affairs of the res publica, had left
the political culture in disarray and uncertainty. The ight over
the prerogative to interpret the event started almost immediately.
Words became critical. The death of Caesar could be understood
as an unlawful murder or as a justiied tyrannicide. Antonius as
921 Fam. 12.22.
End Game
289
consul for the year conducted business in Rome after the assassination on the Ides of March. But the uneasy truce with the men
who had plotted against Caesar was shattered almost instantaneously if not openly. In the eyes of history, Antonius’ most central act has been seen as the speech where he roused the audience
at Caesar’s funeral to such frenzy that they burned the body of
the dictator on the Forum. Words led to action. A speech decided
the outcome of politics. Marcus Junius Brutus and Gaius Cassius
Longinus, as leaders of the uprising against Caesar, now found
the situation in Rome all too perilous. They could have been perceived as saviors of the Republic against the perennial Roman
fear of one-man rule, but failed in fashioning their own narrative.
They left it to Cicero to try to do it for them.
Soon enough, after what at least Cicero would deem mismanagement of his magistracy, Antonius took to the ield. The
military phase of the conlict began. An intricate series of events,
political appointments and alliances, recruitment and troop
maneuverings made Rome an uneasy place for any politician.922
Circumstances were rapidly changing as the tides of battle shifted back and forth. A third player had unexpectedly joined the
theatre of war: Gaius Julius Caesar Octavianus, Caesar’s heir. He
would ultimately lead Rome into a new era. The clashes on the
battleield will not be our focus here, but serve only to illustrate
the insecurity of the day where nothing was certain. In Rome the
battles were fought in a different manner.
Between September of 44 and until the death of Cicero at the
hands of men sent by Antonius on 7 December 43 BCE, the two
men battled intensely and insistently with each other. They had
no known history of inimicitia and cooperated in the aftermath
of Caesar’s death. Their antagonism seems sudden and unexpec922 For historical background, consult in general Frisch 1946.
290
making enemies
ted, but escalated almost instantaneously. They became bitter
political rivals in the death throes of the Roman Republic. The
primary weapon in this was speeches, often quickly published in
order that their content could be widely spread.923 Neither of the
combatants was present for any of the other’s attacks, yet Cicero
had to face the allies of Antonius in Rome. Crucial political decisions were taken continuously and in Roman political culture
had to be argued on basis of interpretation of history, events, and
character. It was Cicero’s main objective to portray his adversary
as an enemy, not primarily of himself, but of Rome.924 He arduously and unwaveringly endeavored to have Antonius publicly
condemned a hostis and therefore a uniied target of Roman society. Although the Senate did not declare Antonius an enemy of
Rome as a direct result of any of Cicero’s speeches, his incessant
oratorical representation did win out. According to Plutarchos,
he inally persuaded them.925 To a large extent this was the purpose of the diverse corpus of speeches known as the Philippics to
which we now turn.926
As a result of these speeches, Antonius is one of antiquity’s
923 See Shackleton Bailey 1986, p. xi. For the publication of the Philippics, see
also Ramsey 2003; Kelly 2008.
924 May 1988, p. 149.
925 Plut. Ant. 17.
926 For the Philippics, consult in general Stevenson & Wilson (eds.) 2008. See
also Wooten 1983; and Lacey 1986 for aspects of rhetoric in the speeches.
Hall 2002 offers a helpful overview and bibliography. For character in the
Second Philippic, see Pitcher 2008; in the Third, see May 1988, pp. 148–
155; and in the Sixth, see Steel 2008. For the function of praise and blame
in the Philippics, see Manuwald 2011. The irst speech was not hostile. The
Second Philippic, regarded as a “monumental” (Ramsey 2003, p. ix) and
“classic” (Berry 2006, p. 222) invective, was never delivered, but published
as part of the conlict between the two men. The remaining twelve speeches
differ as regards, for instance, length, main topic, and content. In the present
chapter I will not distinguish between immoral arguments and statements
made in different speeches within the corpus.
End Game
291
most infamous characters. Velleius writes that Cicero branded
the memory of Antonius for all time with his speeches.927 Juvenalis was an admirer of his attacks against Antonius.928 But for once
the great orator’s prerogative faltered. Others disagreed with
him—on the Senate loor and in the annals of history. Cicero did
not save the Republic and on the order of Marcus Antonius, he
was killed in December of 43 BCE. The story goes, that Antonius
ordered the hands of his nemesis, the hands that had written the
Philippics, to be cut off and together with his head placed on the
Rostra—the speaker’s platform.929
We return now to the depiction of Marcus Antonius with which
we began. Throughout the chapters of this book I have argued
that immorality was an important argument for political action.
I have also proposed that this immorality had to be argued and
that Cicero not merely stated that his opponents were depraved
but attempted to persuade his audiences through reasoning and
through logic; with the help of signs and meaningful connections.
In the inal chapter of the study I will start by comparing Cicero’s
inal portrait of immorality with his former foes before turning
to the speciic question of how immorality could be construed
as a political argument for action against the threat of Antonius.
Immorality Revisited
Arguing immorality in Republican Rome often entailed presenting one’s audience with a portrait corresponding to their expectations of depravity and vice. The portrait of immorality of Marcus
Antonius delivered by Cicero during 44 and 43 and over the
927 Vell. 2.64: Haec sunt tempora, quibus M. Tullius continuis actionibus aeternas Antonii memoriae inussit notas.
928 See Juv. 10.125.
929 For Cicero’s death, cf. Plut. Cic. 48; App. B Civ. 4.19–20.
292
making enemies
course of several speeches displays themes and motifs of immorality and vice found also in the portrayal of enemies earlier in his
career. This is one of the reasons earlier scholarship has tended to
emphasize the generic nature of Roman oratorical abuse. As one
of these topoi of invective, immorality has often been found irrelevant. Handbooks of rhetoric pragmatically enumerate certain
aspects for the orator to attack whether or not the corresponding
fault of character in the person attacked could be readily found.
Scholars have pointed to the fact that Cicero’s political rivals
hardly were guilty of his, sometimes exaggerated, accusations;
that he himself was also accused of the same faults; that he at
times reconciled with them; and that he always had a “political”
motive for his attacks. This search for the social reality behind
invective has been a hard perspective for classical scholarship to
shake off. Invective or immorality arguments in such interpretations veil the scholar’s eyes and cloud the issue. It has also led to
problems to tackle. Rational Romans could not very well believe
these hyperbolic allegations, could they? Surely they did not put
that much stock in something as irrelevant as character? Hence,
they must have been comical, entertaining, expected but discarded. The Romans, scholars have argued, enjoyed these stinging
pieces of invective, but they could of course see it for what it
was: misdirection. The task of the historian is to sift through
the empty rhetoric to arrive at what had really happened. Was
Verres guilty of misgoverning his province and stealing statues?
Was Catilina conspiring against the state? Was Gabinius perhaps
something of a drunken buffoon? Was Marcus Antonius really an
enemy of the state?
This study has taken a different approach, bracketing the question of whether or not immorality attacks were part of a genre,
while consciously ignoring the question of their relation to truth,
instead pursuing the immoral argument in oratory as something
End Game
293
relevant for the understanding of Roman political culture. This
entails the view that moral accusations not only had to resonate
with the audience’s values and norms, but they also had to make
sense. If moral character mattered in Roman society then attacks
on morals had to be meaningful to an audience in order to be
accepted at a primary level. That meaning in turn can be studied
in its own right and we can search for its inner—cultural—logic.
In this study this has also meant looking at surviving oratory
irst, not the categories of invective or rhetorical handbooks, to
analyze what moral frameworks Cicero attempted to base his
reasoning and his portrayals on.
From this perspective, then, it also makes sense that the portrayal of Marcus Antonius echoes some of Cicero’s earlier inimical depictions. His portrait had to resonate with the same,
more or less stable, moral culture. This furthermore gives us the
opportunity to compare the portrait of Marcus Antonius with
previously discussed depictions of immorality and thereby sum
up some of the study’s indings.
Immorality Portrayed
Truth is, however, that the portraits Cicero painted of his enemies
during his political career were far from identical carbon copies
based on rhetorical guidelines. There were of course similarities,
but there were also notable differences. Chrysogonus was a man
of the city whose luxury gave away his immorality. Gaius Verres
was above all a greedy, lustful, and cruel tyrant, while Catilina
was a frenzied and sexually corrupting conspirator and a morally
inverted soldier. Clodius was distinguished by sacrilege and incest
and by effeminate clothes. The appearance of Gabinius was similar, but his true mark of immoral egregiousness was his gluttony
and feasting. Piso did not appear immoral or effeminate, but he
294
making enemies
was nonetheless a perverted Epicurean. They were all immoral,
but this immorality could be portrayed in different ways. The
portraits were wide-ranging but emphasized different aspects in
the immoral pattern.
Hence, the most important similarity was the fact that they
were all portrayed as immoral. But certain aspects of this immorality were also shared by this gallery of improbi. Their acts were
often referred to with concepts such as lagitium or improbitas,
often too with turpitudo and dedecus. In this, the shame and
disgrace of their lives and character were communicated. They
were most of them tainted with stuprum, which meant sexual
depravity and trespass, and with some form of lustful behavior.
They were all described as audaces and frequently as frenzied, erratic, and insane. Upon scrutiny their lives showed deinite signs
of sexual and moral corruption. As a result they were passive and
effeminate. Many of them were found in the immoral arena of
the feast where gluttony and sexual excess coincided.
In this they were joined by Marcus Antonius—a man whose
lagitium, impudentia, nequitia, and libido were impossible to
bear;930 a man who should have been brought to ruin as a consequence of his immorality and infamia;931 a man who had committed acts of lagitium and stuprum in his past and as a boy;932
a man whose vices offered many opportunities for oratorical
censure;933 a man whose lagitium, turpitudo, and dedecus were
unparalleled in the world.934
930 Phil. 2.15. For lagitium, see also e.g. Phil. 3.34; 7.15; 13.17; 14.9. For improbitas, see e.g. Phil. 2.63, 99; 7.3–5; 11.2.
931 Phil. 2.24.
932 Phil. 2.44–45, 47, 50.
933 Phil. 2.43.
934 Phil. 2.57–58, 76. For turpitudo and dedecus, see also Phil. 5.16; 7.15–16;
14.9.
End Game
295
Cicero was no stranger to using history. In his attacks on Antonius he conjured up both Catilina and Clodius.935 His old foes
mirrored his current one. Antonius had, he claimed, surpassed
Clodius in every vice.936 He was equal to Catilina in wickedness
(scelus) but inferior in industria, meaning energy or diligence.937
Another area where the orator found the comparison fruitful was
in the representation of the immoral mind. Antonius had more
audacia than Catilina, more furor than Clodius.938 The mind was
in Cicero’s oratory a signiicant part of the pattern of immorality.
Audacia was a trait that Cicero attributed to all of his enemies
and often used in a court of law to argue guilt. In order to be
immoral, it seems, you had irst to be at odds with traditional society and in conlict with the boni, the good who were distinguished by their moral character. But audacity was not only immoral
in itself. It was a concept that Cicero often latched on to other
aspects of the mind—most prominently furor, frenzy and amentia, insanity.939 In the irst big trial of Cicero’s career not only
was one of the immoral archetypes he offered the homo audax,
but he demanded of the prosecutor that he showed unmatched
audacia but also furor and amentia before anyone would believe
that his client was guilty of killing his father. The audacious man
was unbridled and uncontrolled. Audacia was furthermore often
coupled in Cicero’s oratory with other immoral traits.940 It could,
935
936
937
938
For this, see Evans 2008.
Phil. 2.18. See also Phil. 8.16.
Phil. 4.15.
Phil. 2.1. Note that he again starts his most furious invective with attacking
the mind. For audacia, see furthermore e.g. Phil. 2.9, 19, 44, 90; 3.13, 25;
5.42; 9.15; 12.15; 13.29; 14.7.
939 For audacia and furor, see Phil. 3.31; 6.18; 10.11. Furor also e.g. Phil. 3.3;
4.3; 11.37. For audacia and amentia, see Phil. 3.2; 5.10. Amentia also e.g.
Phil. 2.42; 5.37; and for Dolabella, Phil. 11.6, 9.
940 See for instance Phil. 3.25, 28; 8.21; 13.10. Cf. in particular Sest. 112.
296
making enemies
as several times in the Pro Quinctio, be linked with cupiditas, or
as often in the portrait of Verres with avaritia. In the Pro Cluentio, audacia was one of the strongest signs of Oppianicus’ guilt.
It demanded hatred and action from the community.941 Hence
it was readily believed that a person distinguished by audacia
also had other moral laws. An explanation for the close afinity
between the audacious and the immoral man could be argued to
lie in the role of tradition as a bearer of proper conduct and morality. In Cicero’s portrayal of Antonius it is several times coupled
with impudentia—shamelessness.942 This too, was recurrent. The
Titi Roscii whom Cicero identiied as the culprits in the trial of
Sextus Roscius were equals not only in immorality (improbitas)
but also in audacity and impudentia.943 The homo audax was,
by deinition, a person in conlict with propriety and virtuous
behavior; unprincipled, unscrupulous, and without shame.944
Antonius’ audacity is described as inhuman.945 In his portrait it
was enumerated together with lust, cruelty, and impudentia as his
only qualities, in conlict with shame, modesty, and chastity.946
In fact, it was his audacity that made him an improbus or an
immoral man.947 The prominence of audacia in Cicero’s depiction of his enemies and its connection to both shameless behavior overall and other central immoral traits, strongly suggests
941 For this, see also in particular Mil. 42.
942 See e.g. Phil. 2.4, 19; 3.18; 6.6–7. This overlap is particularly evident in the
portrayal of Sextus Aebutius in Pro Caecina, see Caecin. 1–2. For impudentia, see also e.g. Phil. 2.15, 81–82, 99; 3.10; 8.25; and for Lucius Antonius,
Phil. 6.13; 11.10.
943 Rosc. Am. 118.
944 Santoro L’Hoir 1992, p. 22.
945 Phil. 2.68: O audaciam immanem! Also Phil. 2.4; 13.10.
946 Phil. 3.28.
947 Phil. 2.90. See also Phil. 14.7, for this overlap and for audacious as synonymous with bad (malus).
End Game
297
that the concept in Cicero’s oratory might actually be seen as
denoting immorality itself.948 The homo audax was the immoral
man. Audacia was the origin of all evil and criminal deeds, Cicero
maintained in the Pro Roscio Amerino.949 An observable cultural
logic supports this—in Rome, immorality was the opposite of
the character traits on which the elite prided themselves. And the
homo audax was in fact the perverted and corrupted member of
the elite.
In the Second Philippic, another aspect of the mind is added in
the portrayal of Antonius: stupidity (stultitia). Cicero repeatedly
mocks his opponent for his weak mind.950 This could in turn be
linked closely in his oratory with audacia, the two qualities even
said to be overlapping in Antonius.951 Similarly, it could be linked
with furor.952 Piso was also accused of stupidity, but this does
not seem to have been the orator’s chief purpose.953 Cicero was
content irst when he had made the point that Piso was depraved.
Stupidity could, however, serve as link to other concepts inherent
in an enemy. Stupidity could be argued to point ahead to more
crucial aspects of depravity.
Antonius’ mind and nature were also repeatedly described as
uncontrolled and ungoverned. He is portrayed as having an effrenatio impotentis animi and is described as iracundus (irritable)
contumeliosus (insulting), and superbus (arrogant) and as always
drunk.954 In particular his overindulging in wine is frequently
commented upon. Antonius was a man who acted correctly with-
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
See also Merrill 1975, p. 13.
Rosc. Am. 75.
See for instance Phil. 2.8, 19, 29-30, 81.
Phil. 2.19.
Phil. 2.65. Also impudentia, Phil. 2.81–82.
For the association between stultitia and improbitas, see Caecin. 23, 30.
Phil. 5.22 and 5.24.
298
making enemies
out cause or for no reason, but acted offensively as a result of his
nequitia or wickedness.955 This lack of control also tied into other
aspects of the immoral man.
Greed for instance spoke to the same poor self-control. Antonius, Cicero claimed, had been overtaken by the wealth of Caesar.
He had become egens, needy as a result. It is incredible and almost portentous, he said, how much he squandered in so little
time.956 The immorality of greed was axiomatic in ancient Rome
and of great concern to the elite. Greed, avaritia, and desire, cupiditas, could therefore logically and with ease be connected to
other traits of immorality.957 At no time in Cicero’s career were
these concepts more prominent in his oratory than when he prosecuted Verres. Although avaritia loses its place of prominence in
the pantheon of Ciceronian immorality after that, cupiditas remains one of the more frequent character traits in Cicero’s representations of his enemies.958 The immoral man lacked restraint
and was also driven by his covetous longings. As consul, Cicero
had emphasized the furor and cupiditas of Catilina as his motivation for conspiracy.959 Sassia was impelled by her desire into
depravity and crime. Sexual lust, which always lay close to desire in general, was particularly dangerous in this regard. About
Antonius, Cicero claims:
Semper eo tractus est, quo libido rapuit, quo levitas, quo furor, quo
vinulentia.960
955 Phil. 6.11.
956 Phil. 2.66: Incredible ac simile portenti est, quonam modo illa tam multa
quam paucis non dico mensibus, sed diebus effuderit.
957 For cupiditas, see Phil. 2.117; 3.25. For avaritia, see 2.97, 115; and cf. 13.18.
958 He does however seem to have defended his clients regularly against avaritia.
959 Cat. 1.25. Also Cat. 1.22; and Sull. 17.
960 Phil. 6.4.
End Game
299
He has always been dragged where his lust, levity, frenzy, and
drunkenness have seized him.
Antonius is a man who has never governed himself; a man who is
impelled by his lust, his furor, and his drunkenness. The immoral traits that the Roman elite feared were aspects which drove
their members into doing wrong. Greed made you plunder. Desire
threatened others. Furor led you to conspiracy and crimes against
the state. Lust made you violate the chastity of others. Verres,
Piso, and Gabinius were all accused of sexual assault as a consequence of their lust. The lust of Antonius was likewise intolerable.961 He was driven by his lust.962 Because of his immorality, he
could not be counted on. In Cicero’s portraits, avaritia, cupiditas,
and libido form a triad of uncontrolled wantonness, sexual and
material. The orator did not need to distinguish between them
in his oratory. An interesting aspect to this is offered in the Second Philippic. The immoral, Cicero asserts, have no estimation
of praise and glory which were, as we have seen, key components
to the elite at Rome. Just as people who because of some illness or
numbness of sensation cannot taste the lavor of food, so the lustful, greedy, and the criminal cannot, he claims, savor real praise.963
It therefore does not lead them into making good. Instead they
are compelled to commit wrongs, spurred by their immorality. As
Cicero states in the Pro Roscio, the unbridled and lustful mind is
compelled to crime.964 Verres had acted multa libidinose against
961 Phil. 2.15. For libido, see furthermore, e.g. Phil. 2.45, 71, 105, 115; 3.28, 35;
5.33; 6.4; 13.17.
962 Phil. 2.45: hortante libidine. See also the attack on Dolabella in Phil. 11.9;
and the brothers Antonius in Phil. 13.10.
963 Phil. 2.115: Sed nimirum, ut quidam morbo aliquo et sensus stupore suavitatem cibi non sentiunt, sic libidinosi, avari, facinerosi verae laudis gustatum
non habent.
964 Rosc. Am. 39.
300
making enemies
the Sicilians and was a slave to his lust.965 The Catilinarian conspirators all had cultivated unnatural lusts which drove them irst
to destitution and then into conspiracy. Who, Cicero wondered,
remembering Lentulus’ insane lust was surprised at his plots? Was
not Autronius—always audacious and lustful—convicted by his
life, natura, and mores? In the speeches against Catilina, Cicero
also placed lust in opposition to restraint as two sides of the moral coin. The principle was especially prevalent in the portrayal of
Piso as not only lustful (libidinosus) and ilthy (impurus) but also
intemperans—intemperate or unrestrained.966
Other aspects of sexual immorality besides lust were essential to Cicero’s portraits. He accused his enemies of adulterium,
stuprum, and incestum, concepts that were closely linked and
that were often joined with lagitium. The immoral man engaged
in disgraceful and shameful sexual activity. This was also construed as dangerous for the community. Sexual depravity could
endanger the relationship with the gods or the collective chastity
of free women and young men. The immoral man had himself
been sexually corrupted at a young age. This meant that Roman
views on morality dictated that once sexually corrupted, these
men would cause harm also to others. Immorality bred immorality. Sexual immorality meant that these men were seen as passive.
Verres and Clodius were women among men. But this effeminacy
was not only deriding and humiliating. Among Catilina’s followers, Cicero paid special attention to the young men whose lust he
had serviced before extending to them the torch of conspiracy.
Now they reclined at banquets with older men. An accusation
of passiveness also meant that a man was not a vir and therefore
not it for public duty. In this, Antonius was no exception. His
965 Verr. 1.56; 2.4.112.
966 Red. sen. 13–14.
End Game
301
childhood, too, was marked by stuprum and lagitium.967 He is
described as an impudicus and as someone who has lost his chastity, his pudicitia.968 Like Clodius he is described as effeminatus
and like Piso impurus and similar to his other enemies, Antonius
is tainted by his immoral mouth, to the Romans shamefully denoting his sexual passiveness.969
The immoral portrait of Marcus Antonius comprises many of
the aspects covered in this study. But before attributing this to
simply being pro forma we should consider the possibility that
the similarities stemmed from a cultural belief—that immorality
was a total, all-encompassing quality. Cicero’s lament of the character of his enemy serves as a good example of this view of immorality in Roman culture:
Hanc vero taeterrimam beluam quis ferre potest aut quo modo?
Quid est in Antonio praeter libidinem, crudelitatem, petulantiam,
audaciam? Ex his totus conglutinatus est. Nihil apparet in eo
ingenuum, nihil moderatum, nihil pudens, nihil pudicum.970
But who can bear this most foul beast and how? What is there in
Antonius besides lust, cruelty, impudence, and audacity? From this
he is solely put together. Nothing in him shows any good nature,
no moderation, no modesty, no chastity.
In portraying immorality, Cicero throughout his career chose to describe his enemies as solely immoral. Just as the character of Antonius was comprised of only immoral qualities, and no rewarding
traits could be found, Verres had not spent a single hour in absence
967
968
969
970
For stuprum, see Phil. 2.47, 99; 3.15; 6.4.
Phil. 2.70; 3.12; and 2.3, 15; 3.15. See also Phil. 2.77.
Phil. 3.12; 12.13. For Antonius’ mouth, see Phil. 2.68; 5.20.
Phil. 3.28.
302
making enemies
of immorality and Catilina was behind every lagitium that had
taken place for years. Modern readers will cringe at the hyperbole.
We would probably ind the statement more believable if Cicero
had admitted to certain strengths or redeeming qualities. But while
your typical Western modern politician would likely concede to
his opponent’s good side before attacking his bad ones, this made
no sense to a Roman politician or a Roman audience. The cultural
logic of immorality dictated this; a depraved character meant that
there were no redeeming qualities. Therefore it was also possible to
blame Verres of omnia vitia, every vice.971 In Cicero’s oratory there
was no moderate immorality and no light depravity. He argued
that a man was either good or bad—either moral or immoral. In
this, the totality of immorality made sense in ancient Rome.
Immorality Displayed
How then could you convince your audience that a man lacked
control of himself and that he was immoral? In this study I have
attempted to show that one way to argue depravity in an adversary was that he displayed the signs of immorality.
Cicero himself spoke of signs (indicia) and marks (notae). There was no indicium of lust, crime, and audacity that could not be
found on Verres, and Catilina’s life was branded by every nota
turpitudinis.972 We do not need to know which signs and marks
Cicero would have enumerated—if indeed he thought of it as being certain particular and not just general signs of immorality—
the idea is consistent with his portraits. Immorality showed itself
in your past life, your private affairs, as well as your behavior
and appearance.
971 Verr. 2.3.5.
972 Verr. 2.3.5; Cat. 1.13.
End Game
303
There was an array of such signs that the Roman orator could
summon in order to persuade his audience of immorality. Certain
venues were clearly important. The city itself for instance could
be immoral. It bred luxury, greed, audacity, and crime. The scurra
or ganeo were city types that signaled corruption. If they were
found in your company, you were tainted by them. The disgracefulness of the city could furthermore be differentiated from a
more frugal and traditional life. Within the city, there was another treacherous arena of depravity: the feast or the drinking
den. The banquet in turn could be described as either too luxurious, as Cicero did with Chrysogonus, or as sordid, as he did
with Piso. The feast could be made to signal certain types of depravity: over-eating, drinking, and sexual debauchery. A sign that
a feast was immoral—which was crucial to establish, as Cicero
lectured Cato—could be its guests. The shameful nature of Verres’ banquets, for instance, was signaled by the meretrices and
lenones that took part in them. But sounds and smells were also
giveaways, as were certain activities like love-making or dancing,
or even worse, dancing nude. Throughout the Philippics, the immoral feasting of Antonius is a recurring theme:
Apothecae totae nequissimis hominibus condonabantur. Alia
mimi rapiebant, alia mimae; domus erat aleatoribus referta, plena
ebriorum; totos dies potabantur, atque id locis pluribus.973
Whole wine cellars were made available to the lowest of men.
Some things were looted by mime-actors some by mime-actresses;
the house was stuffed with gamblers, full of drunkards. For entire
days the drinking went on at different places.
973 Phil. 2.67. See also Phil. 3.31.
304
making enemies
As shown here, the house was also a possible sign of immorality.
In the immoral house, feasting went on. This was indicated by
its guests and sometime by the loud noises. In the Pro Quinctio, Sextus Naevius had a house closed to pudor and open to
cupiditas and voluptas. Chrysogonus’ house was described as a
lodging house for every kind of lagitium. Piso’s house even emitted the smell of debauchery. Antonius’ house displays the signs
of feasting, and is also likened to a den and a brothel.974 This of
course meant that sexual debauchery and degrading submissive
acts were taking place.
Chrysogonus’ house was described as luxurious. Luxuria (or
luxuries), from which the Roman authors recoiled and saw as
antithetical to proper morality, was a sure sign of immorality,
linked to greed and desire. Luxury betrayed foreign inluence,
lack of control, and effeminacy. Signs of luxury activated an
array of meaning to an audience and could supply motives for
crime. Those men who had gotten used to luxury would deplete
their patrimonies before they conspired or pillaged. Importantly, luxuria pointed to inertia, idleness—deplorable in a Roman
man. Nevertheless, outright accusations of luxuria are not as
common as one might expect. Verres, of course, is the exception.
His luxurious tastes ran alongside his lust. The same was true of
Piso, and Gabinius even supported this kind of life by turning
his house into a brothel. Others were not described in the same
fashion. Although it gives some of his followers their motivation and Cicero described the conlict as a battle with luxuria,
Catilina himself is not portrayed as a man of luxury.975 Clodius
and Vatinius also escape relatively unscathed in this regard. Nor
974 Phil. 2.69: Huius in sedibus pro cubiculis stabula, pro conclavibus popinae
sunt.
975 Cat. 2.11.
End Game
305
was Marcus Antonius portrayed as a Chrysogonus or Verres who
desperately coveted Greek vases or statues.
Cicero did however frequently evoke the company that Antonius kept. In the passage above, his house is full the lowest of men,
gamblers and drunkards. He travels in a retinue with actors and
pimps.976 Particular for Antonius was his association with mimes,
alluded to as sexual and in conlict with pudor.977 This was a frequent way to taint an opponent with sexual immorality. The list of
Catilina’s followers is a good example of this. Cicero furthermore
consistently displayed signs of sexual immorality through certain
individuals close to his main antagonists. Verres had his Apronius
and Clodius his Sextus Cloelius. Both were arguably more harshly
treated and described as having sexually stained mouths. Marcus
Antonius was tainted by a man called Dollabella. In the Eleventh
Philippic Cicero refers to Antonius and Dolabella as the foulest
and ilthiest creatures ever born, who had immoral natures and
disgraceful lives.978 Dolabella, like Apronius and Sextus Cloelius
had an incestuous mouth and had been corrupted in his youth.979
He served as a warning to watch Antonius carefully, Cicero maintained.980 Women were also used in this regard. Clodia smeared
Clodius with incest while Verres’ mistress Chelidon illustrated his
unmanliness. Antonius had his mime, known as Volumnia whom
he disgracefully kept as his travel companion.981
Appearance, discussed at length in the previous chapter, was a
powerful sign of an immoral character. Chrysogonus was distin976 Phil. 2.58.
977 Phil. 2.61: Venisti Brundisium, in sinum quidem et in complexum tuae mimulae.
978 Phil. 11.1: duo haec capita [...], taeterrima et spurcissima; Phil. 11.2: improbissimae naturae et turpissimae vitae.
979 Phil. 11.5: os incestus. Also Phil. 11.7.
980 Phil. 11.10.
981 Phil. 2.58. See also Att. 10.10, 10.16, 15.22.
306
making enemies
guished by his walk, Gaius Fannius Chaerea by his shaved eyebrows, and Verres by his foreign clothes. Catilina’s eyes shone with
lust and Oppianicus’ audacia could be observed. In his conlicts
during the 50’s BCE, appearance took on a new signiicance; Clodius was dressed, and carried himself, like a woman and a prostitute and Gabinius was a shaved dance-girl and a pimp with curly
hair. Antonius was accused by Cicero of being nude.982 This remark was in reference to a speciic episode when he had, according
to Cicero, harangued naked, smeared with unguents and drunk before the people.983At another point, he ridicules Antonius for wearing foreign slippers and a lacerna, a type of mantle.984 Again, the
orator took an aspect of one of his adversaries, something which
might well have occurred, and offered his audiences the interpretation that this appearance mirrored their true nature.
In sum, recurring signs of immorality were invoked in oratory to illustrate, and argue, their depraved character. Like the
portraits themselves, these signs were not identical. Not every
immoral house was the same, not every type of company was
similar. But Cicero claimed that all his adversaries displayed signs
of their depravity. In this, he argued and negotiated not only their
trustworthiness or authority, but also their place in society.
The Logic of Immoral Life
Visne igitur te inspiciamus a puero? Sic opinor; a principo
ordiamur.985
Would you like us then to examine you as a boy? I think we
should; let us start at the beginning.
982
983
984
985
Phil. 2.86, 111.
Phil. 3.12; 13.31.
Phil. 2.76. For the dress of Antonius, see Heskel 1994, pp. 136–137.
Phil. 2.44.
End Game
307
Heretofore, we have seen in this chapter that Cicero opted to
portray the enemy of Rome as an immoral man and that he used
certain signs of immorality to trigger a wider context of meaning.
In Cicero’s oratory, nothing was arguably a more important sign
of immorality than past life. Frequently, his opponents had a history of sexual depravity. Again, Antonius was no exception. In
describing the immoral youth of Antonius, Cicero also illustrated
vital Roman perceptions of morality that in turn gave these depictions relevance in oratory.
When portraying the depravity of Antonius, Cicero started at
the beginning. The boyhood of a member of the elite made sense
as a starting point when trying to taint him with immorality because it was conceived as a vulnerable part of a Roman man’s life.
Cultural expectations of the protection of the young man’s pudicitia and its subsequent importance ensured this. Cicero narrated
Gabinius’ life as starting with a boyhood marked by impudicitia
which was then followed by a lustful adolescence and years of
disgrace before he turned to corrupting the state. He and Clodius
were described as having been available to the vile lusts of older
men in their youths. Like the seditious Gellius Poplicola, Cicero
explained their offences against the res publica with their past
impurity which had given them insatiable desires. Even the scorned Vatinius had an adulescentiae turpitudo, although like Piso’s
it was hidden by obscurity.986 But Vatinius too was a man whom
Cicero called violent and accused of crimes against the Republic.
Who did not believe that Lucius Catilina—a man from boyhood
schooled in every type of lagitium and stuprum—would grow up
to conspire against the state?987 Sexual corruption was a logical
explanation for crimes against the community.
986 Vat. 11; Pis. 1.
987 Sull. 70.
308
making enemies
It was Cicero’s intention to portray Marcus Antonius as a hostis, as an enemy of Rome. He logically traced this to his early years:
Sumpsisti virilem, quam statim muliebrem togam reddidisti. Primo
vulgare scortum, certa lagitii merces, nec ea parva; sed cito Curio
intervenit, qui te a meretricio quaestu abduxit et, tamquam stolam
dedisset, in matrimonio stabili et certo collocavit. nemo umquam
puer emptus libidinis causa tam fuit in domini potestate quam
tu in Curionis. Quotiens te pater eius domu sua eiecit, quotiens
custodes posuit, ne limen intrares! Cum tu tamen nocte socia,
hortante libidine, cogente mercede per tegulas demitterere. Quae
lagitia domus illa diutius ferre non potuit.988
You assumed the toga of manhood, and immediately turned into
the toga of a prostitute. At irst you were a common whore, with
a ixed price for your disgraceful acts, and not a small price; but
soon Curio intervened and led you from the prostitution business
and as if giving you a matron’s stola, he placed you in a stable and
certain marriage. No boy bought for the sake of lust was ever so
in his master’s power as you were in Curio’s. How often did his
father throw you out of his house, how often did he place guards
so you could not enter! Still, with the aid of night, urged by your
lust, driven by proit, you sneaked in through the roof tiles. Such
shameful acts the house itself could endure no longer.
This passage is notorious.989 It is often identiied as a particularly
harsh piece of invective.990 We might be prone to dismiss it as an
988 Phil. 2.44–45.
989 For discussion of this particular passage, see Richlin 1992, pp. 14–15;
Edwards 1993, pp. 64–65; Corbeill 1996, p. 139; Langlands 2006, pp. 306–
307.
990 Cf. Pitcher 2008, pp. 131, 138. See also Ker 1926, p. 63, n. 1.
End Game
309
exaggerated or even vulgar attempt at humiliating a hated enemy
and, to be sure, this is one of the iercer attacks in the Ciceronian
corpus of oratory on the manhood of one of his opponents. But
in fact, I believe it also made perfect political sense. Cicero’s other
enemies had all been portrayed in this manner. They had all been
seen as threatening to the state. The sexually corrupted man endangered the state, indirectly but also directly. There is however
one more moral-cultural logic that instills this passage: Roman
social hierarchies.
In the orator’s narrative above, Antonius is a man corrupted at
a young age. Rather than becoming a man in taking on the toga
of the vir, he becomes a whore by taking on the toga of the prostitute. We could regard this as mere slander, but the dichotomy itself
is signiicant. It is grounded in a basic understanding of Roman
society. Clothes illustrate morality because they illustrate status.
The vir and the prostitute occupy diametrically opposed positions
in the Roman hierarchy of social status.991 The vir is the leader of
society, while the prostitute is without status or infamis. This is
logical from an immorality perspective. As discussed earlier, the
status of the male member of the Roman elite was not separately
connected to his gender, but to his position in a power structure.
The vir, which in itself is a speciic status within the category of
man, is deined by his freedom and dominance. The status of the
prostitute is linked to the same societal structure and deined by
servitude and submission. In Cicero’s depiction, Antonius becomes
the object of another man’s desires; he is explicitly in the power of
another man. This refutes his status as a vir because of a cultural
understanding of society as divided into those who dominate and
those who are dominated. When portraying Gabinius as an effeminate glutton, he explicitly did this in contrast with the vir.
991 Cf. Richlin 1992, p. 27; Ruffell 2003, p. 59.
310
making enemies
Immorality was part of the grading scale of society’s hierarchy.
The most moral were at the top, the most immoral at the bottom. Exclusion from the elite was logically construed as a moral question. Portraying Antonius as a whore therefore becomes
meaningful to an audience regardless of whether or not he had
prostituted himself.992
In the representation of Antonius as a whore, manhood and
servitude converge. The bias of the audience gives the portrayal
meaning and power. But other key concepts pertaining to Roman
morality are also evoked. Cicero links the portrayal to other aspects of immorality, speciically greed and lust. As a young man,
Antonius’ corruption is caused by lust. This also leads to lust according to the logic that immorality causes immorality. But this is
also presented by Cicero as connected to his lust for money. The
connection does not break the chain of reasoning. Sexual lust and
greed are what motivates Antonius into submitting to the lust of
others and what then motivates him to sneak past the guards. To
Roman moral sensibilities, a lust for money and a lust for sexual
gratiication were conlated. In this way, an immoral character
could be presented as persuasive to an audience. Lust could signal
greed. Greed could signal lust. In sum, it is therefore not merely
stated that Antonius is immoral, but argued through meaningful
signs and relevant links, and with the aid of cultural logic.
Portraying adversaries as slaves, prostitutes, gladiators, or
other infames is a question of portraying and arguing immorality. Dichotomies could be upheld as part of the understanding in
Roman culture of who was capable of having a moral character. The following depiction of what goes on in Antonius’ house
serves to illustrate these hierarchies:
992 Cf. Pitcher 2008, p. 136.
End Game
311
At vero te inquilino (non enim domino) personabant omnia
vocibus ebriorum, natabant pavimenta vino, madebant parietes,
ingenui pueri cum meritoriis, scorta inter matres familias
versabantur.993
While you were staying there (for you were not the master of the
house) drunken voices were heard everywhere, the paved loors
swimming in wine, the walls were wet, freeborn boys consorted
with those that were for hire, whores among mothers of families.
Amidst this vivid scene of depravity, Cicero makes sure that
Antonius is not the master, the dominus of this house. Rather, he
is part of the meltdown of social and moral hierarchies that take
place.994 Freeborn boys and those that prostituted themselves,
whores and mothers were all intermingled. The status of everyone, not least Antonius, is crucial. Immorality is depicted through
these statuses while also pointing toward its dangers. An immoral
society is a society where moral hierarchies have collapsed.
The moral argument was grounded in society’s hierarchy. Immorality was detrimental to the proper behavior of a vir: Virtus signaled the role and responsibility of the elite Roman male:
as a guardian of family and, in the role of politician, of society.
But virtus did not merge with depravity. Character tainted with
disgrace could not be manly in the Roman sense. Virtus was not
just courage or bravery, but a moral quality. Not everybody was
entitled to it, but some of those who were lost this prerogative.
They lost it as a consequence of their immorality:
993 Phil. 2.105.
994 For this, see also Edwards 1993, p. 175.
312
making enemies
ecquo te tua virtus provexisset? ecquo genus? In lustris, popinis,
alea, vino tempus aetatis omne consumpsisses, ut faciebas, cum in
gremiis mimarum mentum mentemque deponeres.995
Would your virtue have elevated you? Your birth? In debauchery,
drinking dens, gambling and wine would you have wasted all the
days of your life, as you did, when you surrendered your chin and
your mind in the laps of mimes.
Immorality as Political Argument
The interaction between immorality and the political culture
was not only dependent on the orator’s attacks on his enemies;
political issues could also be presented in moral terms. The conspiracy led by Catilina was an immoral offense against the state,
construed by the consul as a war between virtue and vice. So
too did he explain the difference between the two sides in the
battle for the Republic. Antonius should be seen as an enemy of
the state and those he fought should be considered its saviors.
While Antonius is a man tainted by his sexual immodesty (impudicitia) and sexual trespass (stuprum), Octavianus is his moral
counterpart:
Quis enim hoc adulescente castior, quis modestior? Quod in
iuventute habemus inlustrius exemplum veteris sanctitatis? Quis
autem illo, qui male dicit, impurior? 996
For who is more morally pure than this young man, who is more
modest? What more illustrious example of traditional purity do
995 Phil. 13.24.
996 Phil. 3.15. Also: Phil. 13.19.
End Game
313
we have among our youths? And who is more impure than he who
abuses him?
In this way, immoral portrayal could be a direct political argument. Traditional moral values were here positioned against moral impurity. The young man who had protected his chastity stood
against the man who had not. The war could thus be understood
as a conlict of morality. “What,” asks Cicero, “can be fouler and
ilthier and less decent than marching against the Senate, against
the citizens and against the fatherland?”997 The man who threatened the res publica was in Cicero’s oratory, by deinition, an
immoral man because the act itself was immoral. This also meant
that immorality and threat were rationally linked.
As I have discussed earlier, acts of depravity and disgrace could
also be included in the list of political offenses made by one of
Cicero’s enemies. Clodius’ incest could be listed next to political
violence or destruction. When attacking Catilina, Cicero made
no distinction between his murders and his stuprum. One argued the other. The man who committed acts of sexual indecency
could not only be a more believable murderer; such a train of
thought followed a cultural logic that dictated that the immoral
man without fail would end up hurting others. It is therefore
not necessarily the case that Cicero wants to verify murder by
immorality, but rather that murder follows from immorality. In
the wake of lagitium you would ind crime. Cicero also chose to
present the political trespass of Antonius as naturally related to
his immoral acts:
997 Phil. 13.14: Quid autem turpius aut foedius aut quod minus deceat quam
contra senatum, contra cives, contra patriam exercitum ducere?
314
making enemies
Quod quidem cuius temperantiae fuit, de M. Antonio querentem
abstinere maledictis! praesertim cum tu reliquias rei publicae
dissipavisses, cum domi tuae turpissimo mercatu omnia essent
venalia, cum leges eas, quae numquam promulgatae essent, et de te
et a te latas coniterere, cum auspicia augur intercessionem consul
sustulisses, cum esses foedissime stipatus armatis, cum omnis
impuritates inpudica in domo cotidie susciperes vino lustrisque
confectus.998
What self-control it was to abstain from abuse when complaining
of Marcus Antonius! Particularly when you dispersed with the
last remnants of the Republic, when at your house with foulest of
trades everything was for sale, when you admitted that those laws
that had never been promulgated had been presented by you for
you, when you as augur abolished the auspices and as consul the
tribune’s veto, when you were most disgracefully surrounded by
armed men, when you daily submitted to all forms of impurity in
your shameless house, exhausted by wine and debauchery.
Speciic political acts are here linked with Antonius’ household
depravity and sexual dishonor. To be sure, this type of passage
is one where the reference to his immorality could very well be
seen as illogical and as political misdirection. The speech itself is
often seen as an exaggerated attempt to humiliate Antonius. But
we cannot fail to realize by now that Cicero offers his audience
the logical connection that a man who is exhausted by immorality and who is the feminine and submissive party in his sexual
depravity also corrupts the state, her laws, and her religion. Antonius’ immorality explained his acts. The reasoning returns in the
Sixth Philippic:
998 Phil. 2.6. For impudica/pudica in this passage, see Langlands 2006, p. 308.
End Game
315
Quid enim ille umquam arbitrio suo fecit? Semper eo tractus est,
quo libido rapuit, quo levitas, quo furor, quo vinulentia; semper
eum duo dissimilia genera tenuerunt, lenonum et latronum; ita
domesticis stupris, forensibus parricidiis delectatur, ut mulieri
citius avarissimae paruerit quam senatui populoque Romano.999
For what has he ever done of his own initiative? He has always
been dragged where his lust, levity, frenzy, and drunkenness have
seized him; two different types of people have always held him in
their grip, pimps and bandits; so much has he enjoyed his stuprum
at home and his parricides in the Forum that he rather obeyed a
greedy woman than the Senate and People of Rome.
In both passages quoted above, Antonius’ desire for sexual immorality was presented by Cicero as in direct conlict with the
political culture.1000 His immoral character was thereby made
a political issue. Let us pass over his stuprum and immorality,
Cicero says at one point, for my mind hastens to the acts he
performs daily.1001 In Cicero’s oratory, these acts did not occupy
diametrically opposed ends of the scale. Immorality was not irrelevant for political issues at hand. The immoral feast too could
be positioned in direct conlict with politics. State business is described by Cicero as being postponed due to his drinking and
feasting or as taking place at birthday parties in his gardens for
the depraved.1002 Breach of the political culture could likewise be
explained by his loss of pudor and pudicitia.1003 In other parts
999 Phil. 6.4.
1000 See also Phil. 2.71; 5.33
1001 Phil. 2.47: Sed iam stupra et lagitia omittamus.
1002 Phil. 3.30. See also Phil. 2.15.
1003 Phil. 2.15: Adeone pudorem cum pudicitia perdidisti, ut hoc in eo templo
dicere ausus sis.
316
making enemies
of the Philippics, Cicero links Antonius’ pillaging with his association with mimes. In one passage, Cicero describes how Antonius had vomited at an assembly of the Roman people from his
drinking. Just like Gabinius, Antonius was a glutton (helluo) his
drinking emphasized to illustrate his excessiveness and lack of
control.1004 This was not just a matter of reproach in itself but
had consequences for his acts as a politician. Repeatedly, Cicero
constructed the immorality of Antonius as a political argument.
He had done so throughout his career. Verres’ immorality was a
military concern. The disgraceful appearance of Piso and Gabinius illustrated their crimes against the state. Clodius was a popularis and Gellius was seditious because they were both depraved
and effeminate. Immorality could be presented as a political matter and urge political action. In 44 and 43 BCE, Cicero perceived
the state to be in danger. He wanted the Senate to act against this
threat. This danger he also argued in moral terms:
Accipite nunc, quaeso, non ea, quae ipse in se atque in domesticum
(de)decus inpure et intemperanter, sed quae in nos fortunasque
nostras, id est in universam rem publicam, impie ac nefarie fecerit;
ab huius enim scelere omnium malorum principium natum reperietis.1005
Hear now, I beg you, not that which concerns the disgrace he
brought upon himself and his house with impurity and immodesty,
but the acts of impiety and sacrilege which he has done against us
and our fortunes, that is, against the entire Republic; for from this
man’s wickedness you will discover was born the beginning all our
ills.
1004 Phil. 2.65.
1005 Phil. 2.50.
End Game
317
The Threat of Immorality
In his battle for the Republic, Cicero chose to portray the enemy
of Rome as not only an enemy, but also an immoral enemy. In order to convince his peers, and the people, he thereby relied to no
small degree on the moral concerns of his audiences. In Roman
society, immorality could be conceived of as a serious threat.1006
A man with corrupted morality was unworthy of being a
member of the elite. He could not be trusted with guarding the
res publica. His immorality made him unit for public life. His
lack of control made him undependable. He would feast and
drink instead of conduct his political duties and, like Verres and
his province, end up controlled by immoral men and women.
The effeminacy that followed from such depravity was likewise
damaging to the military prowess of Rome. In the third speech
against Antonius, Cicero held that as long as there was immorality among the elite, no one was safe:
Qui enim periculo carere possumus in tanta hominum cupiditate
et audacia? 1007
How can we be free from danger when men display such vast
desires and audacity?
Immorality was, Cicero emphasized time and again, dangerous
and not just because it made the elite weak. The immoral man was
likely to commit crimes to sustain his costly depravity and would
eventually threaten the state. Immorality posed a threat also to
Rome’s relationship with her gods. Verres’ greed for instance had
1006 Cf. Barton 2001, p. 27. See also May 1996, pp. 152–153.
1007 Phil. 3.25.
318
making enemies
caused him to steal from sanctuaries. Immorality would lead to
the destruction of temples and altars. Marcus Antonius’ trespass
against the Republic was in the same manner presented by Cicero
as a religious threat:
Serius omnino, patres conscripti, quam tempus rei publicae
postulabat, aliquando tamen convocati sumus, quod lagitabam
equidem cotidie, quippe cum bellum nefarium contra aras et focos,
contra vitam fortunasque nostras ab homine proligato ac perdito
non conpari, sed geri iam viderem.1008
Although, conscript fathers, altogether later than demanded by
this time for the Republic, we are gathered here at length:
something which I have urged daily, witnessing as I have a
sacrilegious war not only being prepared, but already being waged
against our hearths and houses, against our lives and fortunes by a
proligate and corrupt man.
Clodius’ lust was a prime example of this religious threat. Immoral lust was insatiable and only led to further acts of lust until
the entire pudicitia of Rome was in danger. His desire caused him
to violate sacred rites. This act was construed as immoral and
effeminate by Cicero. Marcus Antonius and his brother itted the
description:
Quas enim turpitudines Antonii libenter cum dedecore subierunt,
easdem per vim laetantur aliis se intulisse. Sed vis calamitosa est,
quam illis obtulerunt, libido lagitiosa, qua Antoniorum oblita est
vita.1009
1008 Phil. 3.1.
1009 Phil. 14.9.
End Game
319
For such foulness as the brothers Antonius freely submitted to
their own disgrace, they have with force gladly inlicted upon
others. But the violence is disastrous for those who endured it, the
immoral lust of the brothers a stain on their life.
The passage well illustrates Roman moral-cultural logic. Those
who have been made subject to immorality will inlict it on others.
This imperiled in particular certain groups in society perceived of
as vulnerable. The depraved could even, like Catilina, turn these
groups against the state since once they had lost their moral integrity their path was set for destruction. These arguments all rested
on a particular notion about immorality: that it was corrupting
and would lead a person to corrupt others.1010 In Cicero’s depiction of Marcus Antonius, this cultural logic forms a crescendo.
It explained the most terrible threat of all—the threat of slavery.
In the Third Philippic, held before the Senate, Cicero again
makes use of history. He proceeds from the claim that an immoral
man is threatening Rome by comparing Marcus Antonius with
her quintessential historical antagonist, Tarquinius Superbus, the
king who was overthrown and whose banishment was the start
of the Republic for which Cicero now—rightly as it turned out—
feared.1011 Like the tyrant, Antonius is a homo amens, audacious,
cruel, and distinguished by furor.1012 He is inpudens, shameless,
and greedy, more so even than the historical tyrant.1013 As we have
seen throughout the course of this study, these were all marks of
the immoral man. As we saw in the portrait of Verres, this immorality could be presented in the shape of the foreign tyrant.
1010 For cruelty as connected to sexual submission, see Phil. 11.8–9.
1011 See also Phil. 2.87. Tyrannus also Phil. 2.90, 96, 117; 13.17–18. Cf. Phil.
4.3. For Antonius as tyrant and king, see Stevenson 2008a.
1012 Phil. 3–5.
1013 Phil. 3.10.
320
making enemies
But there was also another link with the old king. The threat
from Antonius, Cicero iercely argued, was in the end the threat
of slavery for the Roman people.1014 Because of the previously
discussed dichotomy between free and unfree, such a threat was
of course appalling. Nothing could be worse than slavery. Cicero
then in no uncertain terms links this threat—and his portrait of
Antonius as hostis—to a familiar form of immorality:
Cum autem omnis servitus est misera, tum vero intolerabilis est
servire inpuro, inpudico, effeminato, numquam ne in metu quidem
sobrio.1015
But even if all slavery is wretched, it is in truth intolerable to be
slaves under an unclean, sexually corrupted, effeminate man, who
never even in fear is sober.
The passage is not comical or mocking. It certainly does not appear out of place in the speech. The conclusion to Cicero’s comparison instead made perfect sense. The connection between sexuality and servitude was not only implicitly understood; it could
be overtly referenced.1016 But what made the link between the
immorality of Antonius and slavery poignant was a cultural logic
which Cicero explicitly referenced. In the Second Philippic, Cicero
makes reference to an episode where he claimed that Antonius
had attempted to place a diadem upon the head of Caesar, thereby announcing him as a king.1017 This, Cicero held, would have
meant placing the Roman people under slavery to a tyrant. But
1014 For the threat of slavery, see also Phil. 5.21; 6.19; 8.12; 10.18, 20; 13.31.
Cf. Phil. 4.11.
1015 Phil. 3.12.
1016 See also Phil. 3.28–29.
1017 Phil. 2.85–87. See also Phil. 5.38; 10.7; 13.17.
End Game
321
he should have asked for it himself alone, the orator professed,
“you who ever since a boy have lived so, as to submitting yourself to anything” (qui ita a puero vixeras, ut omnia paterere).1018
Because he had been sexually submissive, Antonius would himself
endure slavery with ease. In fact, he already was a slave. In the
Thirteenth Philippic the same logic returns. In his youth Antonius
had endured the lusts of his own personal tyrants.1019 Later in the
same speech, Cicero again links immorality with the threat of servitude: drunken, smeared in perfume, and nude Antonius had tried
to place the Roman people in slavery.1020 Antonius was, as Cicero’s
portrait makes clear, tainted by immorality. His moral integrity was
corrupted by sexual disgrace. As a grown man he would therefore
suffer the tyranny of Caesar. Submitting sexually meant submitting
in all areas of life, and the manner in which you had lived your life
was the argument. The political consequence of Antonius’ immorality is made abundantly clear. Slavery is argued from immorality.
It is persuasive because Antonius had lost his sexual and therefore
moral integrity which by cultural logic meant that he himself was
in servitude and because as an immoral man he would eventually
impose this on others.
Antonius has become an enemy of all good men. His actions in
Rome are ruinous and illegal. He attempts to march an army on
Rome, and the nature of this army is immoral. His soldiers feast
and drink in excess and violate mothers, virgins, and freeborn
boys.1021 Cicero then for his audience brings back the important
link between immorality and political threat:
1018 Phil. 2.86.
1019 Phil. 13.17.
1020 Phil. 13.31: Lupercorum mentionem facere audet neque illius diei memoriam perhorrescit, quo ausus est obrutus vino, unguentis oblitus, nudus
gementem populum Romanum ad servitutem cohortari.
1021 Phil. 3.31.
322
making enemies
Nemo est tam stultus, qui non intellegat, si indormierimus huic
tempori, non modo credulem superbamque dominationem nobis,
sed ignominiosam etiam et lagitiosam ferendam esse. Nostis
insolentiam Antoni, nostis amicos, nostis totam domum.
Libidinosis, petulantibus, impuris, impudicis, aleatoribus, ebriis
servire, ea summa miseria est summo dedecore coniuncta.1022
No one is so stupid, that he does not realize that if we remain
sleeping at this time, we shall have to bear despotism that is not
only cruel and arrogant, but also shameful and disgraceful. You
know the insolence of Antonius, you know his friends, his whole
house. To be made slaves to the lustful, to the petulant, to the
impure, to the sexually corrupted, to the gamblers and the
drunken is the worst kind of misery joined with the worst
kind of shame.
Nothing, he says, is more detestable than disgrace (dedecus),
nothing fouler than servitude.1023 The threat of Marcus Antonius
is an immoral threat. He threatens the res publica because of
his depravity in the past. This was culturally sound logic. It is
precisely his immorality that makes him an enemy.
1022 Phil. 3.34–35.
1023 Phil. 3.36. Also: Phil. 12.15–16. Cf. Har. resp. 61.
Conclusions: Making Enemies
Marcus Tullius Cicero had a long career. This study has focused on one aspect of a spectacularly diverse political legacy. By
studying the antagonistic portrayals that the man from Arpinum
communicated to Roman audiences, I have sought to understand
the place of immorality in his oratory and in the political culture
within which he acted. Accusing an opponent of vice and arguing
that politics could be understood in terms of morality were certainly not the only strategies available to an orator in Rome, but
they made sense from a cultural perspective. Morality mattered
in Rome, so immorality mattered in Roman oratory.
In summing up the indings, three aspects will be highlighted
in this last chapter. First, this study has shown that immorality in
Roman political oratory was not primarily understood or identiied as a pointless exercise of skill, amusement, or topical slander,
but could be construed as a meaningful argument and seen and
presented as central for the acts performed within the political
culture. Furthermore, the degree to which Cicero employed the
immorality argument in various situations and stages of his career has been demonstrated.
Second, immorality in Roman political oratory triggered a
context of ideas, attitudes and apprehensions—a shared cultural
belief system—which I have termed a web of immorality. By referencing single strings in this web, the orator could link accusations to a coherent whole. In studying Cicero’s attacks on moral
323
324
making enemies
character, this cultural web has been bared.
Third, I have argued that by looking at immorality in Roman
political oratory, a cultural logic of immorality can be traced and
mapped out which not only made moral character a vital aspect
of politics and trials, but from which immorality could be persuasively argued by orators in order to inluence political and
forensic outcomes. This furthermore ensured that accusations of
immorality made sense to the audience within the context of the
speech and the arena. By following the patterns of this cultural
logic the study has shown that several of Cicero’s moral attacks
on his enemies, instead of being viewed of as slanderous, scandalous, and hyperbolic, can be seen as serving a rational political
argument to which an audience could relate.
These three aspects will now be dealt with in turn. But irst we
will return to the premise of the study itself.
The Meaning of Immorality
In my attempt to show the place of immorality in Roman political culture, however, it has not been my intention to claim that
immorality was everything in ancient Rome. Nor have I wished
to portray the Romans as irrational or fundamentally uninterested in facts or truth. Instead I argue that there was a cultural
link between immoral character and life on the one hand and
facts and truth on the other. While this means that immorality
should not be automatically discarded as irrational or illogical,
it is also true that playing the immorality card did not trounce
all other arguments on the orator’s stage or in the private life of
Romans. Not all issues depended on the immorality argument.
Instead, I have aimed to include immorality in the political culture as a whole: a culture that included just as much praise and
virtue as it did censure and vice; that included strategic military
Conclusions: Making Enemies
325
debates, deals made behind the scenes, bribery and violence, as
well as advice and reasoning based on other concerns than moral
ones. But it also, just like our own society, included a hefty dose
of immorality. What I have tried to show is that immorality was
a possible—and at times logical—argument to choose among
a range of other alternatives. I have tried to give immorality a
patent place at the political table.
For us, an immorality argument is most often a law. Modern
sensibilities, frequently if not always, dictate that by its very nature, immorality clouds the issue. It can and should be rejected
as empty rhetoric seeking to elicit an emotional rather than a
rational response. We feel politicians should be elected on basis of their political skill not their moral character. But to the
Romans, character was only a natural, only a logical merit to
consider and evaluate. When our modern-day politicians try to
portray their opponents as immoral, we call it mudslinging or a
smear campaign. Today, immorality is seldom stated outright. It
is inherently beside the point. Therefore, modern politicians have
to be careful since our societies often, if certainly not always,
display great anxiety over the overlap between morality and politics. Over his long career, Cicero did not display the same anxiety.
In his political culture immorality was politics.
That Cicero frequently in his career explicitly argued the importance of the immorality argument does not mean that immorality did not carry with it certain caveats for the Roman orator
as well.1024 Apparently, a Roman audience could blush. We might
see some of Cicero’s portrayals as extreme, but there was a line.
The author of the Ad Herennium stated that the orator had to
explain why he attacked someone and Cicero himself admits that
1024 See e.g. De or. 2.242. For a discussion of Roman views on obscenity, see
Richlin 1992, pp. 1–31.
326
making enemies
attacks on opponents could be thought of as inappropriate, scandalous and most of all hypocritical. Other genres illustrate clearly
that the Romans had another gear when it came to immorality
that the orator did not explore. Cicero at several instances in
his speeches addressed this question by distinguishing between
abuse and relevant moral scrutiny. But his distinction was not
our distinction. We do not draw the line after but before the issue
of morality.
Immorality in oratory, rather than being a ixed set of topics,
displays great variety. Similarly, what made recurrent attacks on
persons effective was not their inclusion in a rhetorical list of
ideal topoi, but, to a large extent, their link to Roman notions of
immorality. It has been my intention in this regard to be inclusive, and therefore what modern eyes might deem outrageous or
scandalous accusations have been evaluated next to what those
same eyes would deem moderate or even justiiable ones. I have
done so because irst of all, again, I do not believe that line was
drawn similarly by the Romans and secondly because I have tried
to argue that immorality in oratory referenced a cultural logic
which did not necessarily depend on the perceived aggressiveness
of the claims.
We should not, however, assume that immorality when found
relevant by an orator always had the same effect, purpose or
meaning for a Roman audience. In this, the perspective of earlier
scholarship can very well merge with the one I have advocated in
the present study. Cicero’s career was diverse. Different speeches
surely would have been considered more or less signiicant and
different portrayals within them more or less relevant to the issue. It is perfectly conceivable that an audience was outraged by
one portrayal of Cicero’s enemies and amused by another while
ignoring a third. At times they might have expected the immorality argument. At times they might have rejected it. Furthermore,
Conclusions: Making Enemies
327
it is certainly possible that different members of the audience
might react with similar diverse responses. One man’s laughter
is another’s chagrin. Both these scenarios, however, meant that
immorality had an effect. Moreover, immorality was consistently
part of Cicero’s oratorical reasoning, sometimes to the point of
ignoring every other aspect of a case or a political issue. In this,
it is also possible that Cicero was more or less convincing in his
argument as in his overall strategy. But his expectation of his culture was nonetheless that immorality was pertinent to political
and forensic decision-making.
We cannot recreate the responses Cicero provoked. It is entirely possible that immorality at times had little effect on audiences,
on the verdict of a jury or the decision of the Senate. But this
only means that Cicero, whom we trust with great knowledge of
the political culture of his day, miscalculated. More importantly,
this does not devoid portraits of immorality from meaning or
cultural coherence. We do not need to know the responses to evaluate the relevance in this regard. But the circumstances do raise
the question of how important these attacks on character—these
portraits of immorality—were for the political culture in general.
At the outset, I posed several questions regarding the place
of immorality in Roman political culture which have been dealt
with throughout the study. I also declared a speciic interest in the
nature of the link between immorality and politics. Such a question, however, cannot in a strict sense be answered by the study of
Cicero’s speeches, because an epistemological gap exists between
text and historical political action. We cannot prove that cultural
meaning harvested in historical texts had a direct impact on political development. Although, to be sure, this is a problem that
does not escape the traditional political historian as he or she,
too, is faced with the representations of actions, there is nonetheless no secure causality to unveil here. We cannot prove political
328
making enemies
cause and effect by looking at the “absorbed” values and ideas
in extant texts. Still, we can study and show the patterns of immorality in our sources. We can furthermore determine that the
immorality argument was deemed relevant enough to igure prominently in Roman oratory and thereby in the political culture
and that it included more than generic and irrelevant character
assassination or entertaining pastime. But to establish that a set
of cultural beliefs had effect on historical events requires from us
a theoretical assumption like the one I argued in the beginning.
There is also another possibility: that the lack of causality is
not necessarily a weakness. A stable model of cause and effect
would perhaps offer a long line of events following upon each
other, but cultural history is concerned with understanding historical action in a deeper sense. It aims at uncovering the beliefs,
values, and fears and anxieties of people in the past and posits
that unveiling their world view—or differently put, their mind
world—provides an understanding of their actions. Simple cause
and effect is one thing. The complex cultural world that people
live in is quite another. And understanding this world might in
fact be more clarifying than establishing causality. This is what
I believe my perspective—and my interpretation—can offer. By
shifting the angle of the search light in order to shine on a previously neglected aspect of oratory, and by supposing that this
aspect in fact had relevance we can gain knowledge about the
way the mind world exerted inluence on political action.
That there is no absolute truth at the end of the hermeneutical tunnel need not discourage us. We can still attempt to bridge
the gap between text and political culture. The way that I have
proposed is to analyze the argument, to follow the line of reasoning and attempt to uncover the cultural coherence and logic of
statements about immorality in politics. How do we know that
immorality was meaningful in ancient Rome, capable of deciding
Conclusions: Making Enemies
329
legal and political outcomes, capable of shaping the political reality? The irst thing is to recognize that immorality exists as a
pattern in Roman political culture and that Cicero at all times
acted as though he expected it to matter. This immoral reasoning
can also in fact be shown to have made sense from a Roman’s
point of view. Over the course of this study I have attempted to
show two key aspects: that Cicero in a court of law, before the
Senate and before the people, constructed arguments from moral
concerns; and that there was a cultural logic underlying these
arguments. The fact that Cicero argued immorality should lead
us to believe that the immorality argument was capable of great
impact. What, then, did the immorality argument in Ciceronian
oratory entail?
The Immorality Argument— I mprobitatem coarguo
In court, Cicero often favored a moral approach. His strategies
in this regard went beyond simply trying to smear his opponents
and white-wash his clients. In his prosecution of Gaius Verres,
formal charges, reference to laws or external evidence took a
back seat to the moral character of the man on trial, and Cicero
at one point simply stated: improbitatem coarguo. Coarguo in
Latin translates as to expose, convict or overwhelm with proof
or as to prove or demonstrate guilt. This, then, was his frequent
purpose: to expose and prove the improbitas—the immorality
or depravity of his opponents. Cicero claimed that an immoral
character could be shown and exposed (ostendo) by the orator.
Although character or ethos in itself was a source of persuasion
in ancient rhetoric, the orator hereby assumed that he could essentially prove by argument. Cicero furthermore intended this
morality to be a part of the decision-making at a trial. He stated
that immorality was capable of convicting a man before he set
330
making enemies
foot in court. Suspicion carried weight. A good judge should be
affected by immorality. It was, he argued time and again, supposed to matter.
In this, Cicero’s oratory was based on an assumption about
the connection between immorality and guilt. He thus gives us
the key to understanding his political culture and the stock it
placed in issues of depravity and shameful behavior. Character
and morality were necessary to substantiate claims. An upstanding citizen or a frugal man was not easily suspected of wrongdoing. Absence of immorality was for this reason a recurring line
of defense. But a man that could be persuasively portrayed as
depraved would likely have committed the offense in question.
You did not have to prove murder or thievery in the past in order
to convict a murderer or a thief, but you should be able to ind
some signs of immorality. This was vital, because if someone was
immoral then their life was expected to follow an immoral pattern. In his forensic speeches, Cicero habitually assumed this cultural belief; moral men did not commit crime while immoral men
did. That did not mean that a member of the audience could not
fathom crime from someone with an unblemished record, but it
meant that if crime was evident, the clean record was very likely
false. Immorality thus was a self-fulilling prophecy and it was
therefore naturally the task of both the prosecutor and the defense to point to the pattern of immorality. This also meant that
immorality offered both explanation and predictions for the future. This was true not only in court but also in politics. Character dictated acts. Immorality pointed toward crime and toward
political trespass. To prove a threat against the res publica, you
had to argue immorality.
In Ciceronian oratory, we ind the immorality argument not
hidden but explicitly stated. Cicero clearly did not deem it inferior or embarrassing. The orator overtly stated that depraved
Conclusions: Making Enemies
331
and disgraceful behavior should be of the utmost importance
and explained to his audience that immorality ought to be more
meaningful than other aspects of a trial or political issue. Cicero
did not excuse his inclusion of immoral concerns in a trial. He
acknowledged no difference between immoral trespass and
other crimes. Moreover, he did not appear to share with us the
view of crimes as dictated by law and immoral acts as dictated
by culture. In all this, audiences were neither tricked nor duped.
They were given the immorality argument point blank and without pause.
The issues debated on the speaker’s platform—legal, political,
military—could be presented by the orator as issues concerning
morality. How to view current and previous verdicts or decrees,
the interpretation of law or the formal declaration of who were
enemies of the state could be argued from moral perspectives.
Moral dichotomies illustrated guilt and danger to the community. Virtue and vice were at times at war. Threats against the state
were argued based on moral concerns. The study has shown that
Cicero repeatedly made immorality a part of Roman political issues. He thereby made use, often succesfully, of the expectations
and traditions found in his political culture. His portraits of his
enemies were arguments and he clearly believed that immorality
was an effective argument and one that belonged in the political
sphere. Moreover, he stated and proceeded as though arguments
in oratory could outweigh formal proof. Finally, immorality in
Cicero’s oratory was also a call for action. He expected it to matter in verdicts, in voting, and in political decisions. Immorality
demanded action from the community.
But Cicero did not just state that immoral arguments should
be important. He acted as though they were by arduously arguing depravity in his adversaries.
332
making enemies
A Web of Immorality— P raeterea vitiis
Making enemies was about making links. In the Pro Murena,
Cicero refuted his own client’s immorality and reproached one
of the prosecutors, Cato the Younger, for succumbing to slander.
He said that a single charge of dancing made no sense, since it
was not followed by “other vices” (quibus praeterea vitiis adfectus), speciic points of lagitium and dedecus that made this
accusation plausible.1025 His defensive argument reveals reference
to what we might call a cultural logic: that an act of immorality was not isolated—it was preceded and followed by further
shameful behavior. By pointing to these other vices, the argument
could be felt to be more convincing. Cicero furthermore returned
throughout his career to signs and marks of immorality as proof
of someone’s moral deviance. Thus, one way of arguing immorality in Roman oratory seems to have been to establish links between different immoral nodes.
This could be done by semantically connecting concepts that
denoted different aspects of Roman views on depravity and
disgrace. Audacia, furor, amentia could be strung together and
then latched on to avaritia, cupiditas, and libido. To heighten
these concepts they could be presented in tandem with lagitium,
improbitas, turpitudo, or other Roman notions of moral transgressive behavior. By forging these links in his oratory, Cicero
also reveals to us his expectations of these connections in his
own culture. The audacious man was insane. The lustful man was
frenzied. Cultural ideas could also generate these wider patterns
of meaning. Greed signaled lust which in turn could reveal sexual
passivity. All three aspects could be triggered by mentioning that
someone had squandered their inheritance. Lavish expenses also
1025 Mur. 13.
Conclusions: Making Enemies
333
motioned to the immoral feast which in turn had an array of
connotations: drunkenness, gluttony, and sexual and effeminate
behavior. Company indicated not only your own moral integrity,
but could be made to point to activities. If you associated with
drunkards, then you were immoderate yourself. If your quests
included prostitutes then you yourself were likely engaging in
sexual submission. Pointing to merely one aspect of the effeminate man activated the image of his passivity. He would likely
commit other trespasses against the community such as adultery,
incest, or stuprum. He would eventually squander all his money
in trying to satisfy his insatiable lusts and turn to crime.
Luxury could therefore mean effeminate behavior, and someone who dressed as a passive man could be expected to have
luxurious tastes without stating it outright. A man who had foreign extravagant tastes probably engaged in immoral feasting. A
frenzied man could be suspected of depraved lust—they were two
sides to a coin. The greedy man, similarly, was plausibly sexually
corrupted at a young age, since his self-control was damaged.
Gluttony was the same as sexual indulgence. Drunkenness implied you would likely succumb to immoral activities of others.
The orator could point to one link in a perpetual chain of depravity and a larger context was thereby activated.
Cicero at times also more distinctly gave his audiences the
cause and effect of immorality. From the city came luxury that
bred greed and developed audacity. From a shameful boyhood
came adolescent lust and crimes against the state. From stuprum
came conspiracy, from submission came slavery. But linking together nodes on this heuristic web of immorality was nonetheless
circular; morality and nature gave immoral actions and immoral
actions revealed morality and nature. At times audacia could be
the source of immorality, at times the result. Immorality, although
cultural notions dictated that it probably began at a young age,
334
making enemies
did not originate from one source. At one point Cicero stated
that greed came from the luxury of the city, but greed could also
be argued to result in luxurious tastes. It could be presented as
simultaneously the cause and the motive for the immorality of a
man. Luxury was at once the telltale, the reason, and the result of
moral corruption. The feast was a place where people engaged in
depravity because they were depraved. Hosting feasts thus pointed toward earlier moral corruption, as well as current and future
moral trespass. Effeminate clothes, hairstyle, or body language
was a consequence of a person’s depravity, but an effeminate man
would always continue on his disgraceful path. He would engage
in shameful acts of sex because he was passive, but he was passive
because he had at one point been submitted to the lust of others.
Lust was a consequence of immorality. Being the victim of lust led
to lust. These could all be arguments in oratory about motives,
dereliction of duty, and political ineptitude. Sexual debauchery
likewise was seen as depleting manly strengths. To this effect, effeminacy betrayed immoral acts which made a person unit for
public life, but it simultaneously addressed the community’s concern for military strength. It was not necessarily the case that one
of these conclusions was more important to arrive at. Rather, the
point was the pattern of meaning. Although the circular quality
might seem to breach logic, it did not breach the cultural logic of
immorality. Life showed immorality. But immorality also showed
your life. There was no reason for the orator to be strict. The
notion relied on the complete pattern all at once. Cultural logic
did not demand a direction for immorality. It only dictated that
disgraceful behavior must come from depravity in the past, that
depravity in the past meant lack of moral integrity which in turn
ensured immoral behavior in the future.
Conclusions: Making Enemies
335
The Logic of Immorality
The idea that immorality breeds immorality might seem a
simple one. We might be tempted to compare it to “once a thief
always a thief” or some other intuitive notion. But Roman views
on the rigidity of immorality in fact go deeper than just the likelihood of someone that had committed moral trespass doing so
again, or the creed that vice and immorality led to ruin. The very
ability to make good or bad decisions could be culturally construed as related to the moral character you could be shown to
have. Cicero relied on this notion in his oratory. In the political
culture of his day, legitimacy was linked to moral concerns. Action depends on morality—on moral character and nature. The
moral man acts morally, the immoral can only do wrong.
This is the basic logic, then. Immorality betrayed past immorality and led to future immorality. It allowed the Roman orator
to make peers into adversaries, and adversaries into enemies. The
idea expressed by Cicero that morality and nature could not be
changed instantly or in order to escape a crime, an idea that also
manifests itself in the belief that external appearance bears witness to immoral character, strongly suggests that the connotations of depravity and vice were far-reaching. It threatened the
young. It threatened the collective pudor and pudicitia of the
community. Moreover, this was tied to the culture as a whole,
linked to social hierarchies, elite responsibilities, and anxieties
and fears. Your moral character deined who you were in a social
structure, the most moral at the top, those without morality at
the bottom. Fear of immorality was a fear of the collapse of such
hierarchies, and portraying someone as depraved and shameful
naturally entailed associating him or her with the lower segments
on this moral scale.
336
making enemies
But morality at Rome was not primarily a matter of doing
good and committing moral acts. It was a matter of decorum, the
community’s appraisal of a person’s moral worth. It was a matter
of the traditional values of the elite and concerned moral integrity. This is why morality and sexuality constantly overlapped.
Domination was an elite prerogative. Sexual submission was detrimental to their character. Integrity was thereby lost. This was
understood in terms of immorality—as depraved, disgraceful, and
shameful. Elite views on morality declared that those who could
not defend their corporeal integrity were most immoral. The vir
had to be untainted by acts of submission or his status would be
revoked by his peers. The logic dictated that those who had been
subjected to the will of others could not lead, but also that they
could not lead since their characters were as a result unhinged,
undependable, and prone to trespass against society. They were
not just shameful or ridiculous but also dangerous. This logic of
immorality could be framed in different fashions in oratory. He
who had been corrupted was set to corrupt others; the passive
man would threaten the community with his lust; the man ruined
by desire would commit crimes to sustain his debauchery; sexual
crimes led to murder; submission to the destruction of the state.
Immorality made these men into enemies of Rome.
The choice of “logic of immorality” as the focus of this study
is a slight attempt at provocation. In our society, and thus in the
academic perspectives favored in our society, immorality is not
logic. Political rationality, we would like to believe, has to do
with sound arguments, facts, proof, and truth. But to the elite at
Rome, immorality was logic. Because of cultural notions on the
importance of morality, the argument made sense to audiences.
By treating it so, the perspective argued in this study has offered
a different way to look at Roman political culture and a deeper
understanding of some of its distinct aspects.
Conclusions: Making Enemies
337
In this, the intensity or vulgarity of the claim did not matter.
The fact that someone had become sexually passive was not merely an obscenity or a humiliation. Because there was a powerful
cultural link between statesmanship and personal virtue, between
political ineptitude and immoral traits of character, the attacks
on someone’s youthful depravities or immoral upbringing—malicious and slanderous to us—belonged in political discourse, in
political oratory, and in the political sphere.
“Logic” targets two aspects of rationality: that it made sense
to Romans to argue portraits of immorality, and that the portraits of immorality made sense. The reason, then, that Cicero’s
portraits show many similarities is not merely that the orator
was given the blueprint beforehand, but that they were culturally
coherent; they adhered to the same cultural logic, a logic that
could be referenced, accentuated, and framed in different ways
and with the help of different tools but with a core that was
simple: immorality mattered.
Bibliography
Achard, Guy, Pratique rhétorique et idéologic politique dans les discourse
“optimates” de Cicéron, Leiden, 1981
Achard, Guy & Ledentu, Marie (eds.), Orateur, auditeurs, lecteurs: à
propos de l’eloquence romaine à la in de la République et au début du
Principat, Paris, 2000
Adams, J. N., The Latin Sexual Vocabulary, London, 1982
Adams, J. N., “Words for Prostitute in Latin,” Rheinisches Museum 126,
pp. 321–358, 1983
Albini, Umberto, “L ’orazione contro Vatinio,” Parola del passato 14, pp.
172–184, 1959
Alexander, Michael C., The Case for the Prosecution in the Ciceronian Era,
Ann Arbor, 2002
Alexander, Michael C., “Law in the Roman Republic,” in Rosenstein &
Morstein-Marx (eds.), pp. 236–255, 2006
Alexander, Michael C., “Oratory, Rhetoric, and Politics in the Republic,” in
Domink & Hall (eds.), pp. 98–108, 2007
Allen Jr., Walter, “In Defense of Catiline,” Classical Journal 34, pp. 70–85,
1938
Alston, Richard, “Arms and the Man: Soldiers, Masculinity and Power
in Republican and Imperial Rome,” in Foxhall & Salmon (eds.), pp.
205–223, 1998
Ando, Clifford (ed.), Roman Religion, Edinburgh, 2003
Arena, Valentina, “Roman Oratorical Invective,” in Dominik & Hall (eds.),
pp. 149–160, 2007
Ariès, Phillipe & Béjin, André (eds.), Western Sexuality: Practice and
Precept in Past and Present Times, Oxford, 1985
Aronsson, Peter, Bönder gör politik: det lokala självstyret som social arena i
tre Smålandssocknar, 1680–1850, PhD. diss. Lund University, 1992
Astin, Alan E., “Regimen Morum,” Journal of Roman Studies 78, pp.
14–34, 1988
Austin, R. G., M. Tulli Ciceronis Pro M. Caelio oratio, Oxford, 1952
339
340
bibliography
Auvray-Assayas, Clara & Delattre, Daniel (eds.), Études de littérature ancienne.
12, Cicéron et Philodème: la polémique en philosophie, Paris, 2001
Ayers, D. M., “Cato’s speech against Murena,” Classical Journal 49, pp.
245–253, 1954
Badian, Ernst, Foreign Clientelae, 264–70 BC, Oxford, 1958
Badian, Ernst, “The Consuls, 179–49 BC,” Chiron 20, pp. 371–413, 1990
Balsdon, J. P. V. D., Romans and Aliens, London, 1979
Barton, Carlin A., The Sorrows of the Ancient Romans: The Gladiator and
the Monster, Princeton, 1993
Barton, Carlin A., Roman Honor: The Fire in the Bones, Berkeley, 2001
Barton, Carlin A.,”Being in the Eyes: Shame and Sight in Ancient Rome,” in
Fredrick (ed.), pp. 216–235, 2002
Bartsch, Shadi, The Mirror of the Self: Sexuality, Self-Knowledge, and the
Gaze in the Early Roman Empire, Chicago, 2006
Batstone, William W., “Cicero’s Construction of Consular Ethos in the First
Catilinarian,” Transactions of the American Philological Association
124, pp. 211–266, 1994
Beard, Mary & Crawford, Michael, Rome in the Late Republic: Problems
and Interpretations, London, 1985
Beard, Mary, North, John, & Price, Simon, Religions of Rome, Cambridge,
1998
Beard, Mary, The Roman Triumph, Cambridge, 2007
Berry D. H., Cicero P. Sulla Oratio, Cambridge, 1996
Berry, D. H., Political Speeches, Oxford, 2006
Berry, D. H. & Erskine, Andrew (eds.), Form and Function in Roman
Oratory, Cambridge, 2010
Bjornebye, Jonas, Malmberg, Simon & Östenberg, Ida (eds.), Ancient
Rome: Passages, Processions and Promenades (Moving City Series):,
London, forthcoming 2014
Bleicken, Jochen, “Die Nobilität der römischen Republik,” Gymnasium 88,
pp. 236–253, 1981
Bleicken, Jochen, Die Verfassung der römischen Republik, Paderborn, 1995
Booth, Joan (ed.), Cicero on the Attack: Invective and Subversion in the
Orations and Beyond, Swansea, 2006
Booth, Joan, “Introduction: Man and Matter,” in Booth (ed.), pp. ix–xiv,
2006a
Bourdieu, Pierre, La distinction: critique sociale du jugement, Paris, 1979
Broberg, Gunnar, Wikander, Ulla & Åmark, Klas (eds.), Tänka, tycka, tro:
svensk historia underifrån, Stockholm, 1993
bibliography
341
Broughton, T. Robert S., “Senate and Senators of the Roman Republic: The
Prosopographical Approach,” Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen
Welt 1.1, pp. 250–265, 1972
Brunt, P. A., Social Conlicts in the Roman Republic, London, 1971
Brunt, P. A., The Fall of the Roman Republic, Oxford, 1988
Butler, H. E., & Cary, Max, De provinciis consularibus oratio ad senatum,
Oxford, 1924
Butrica, James L., “Some Myths and Anomalies in the Study of Roman
Sexuality,” Journal of Homosexuality 49, pp. 209–269, 2005
Cantarella, Eva, Bisexuality in the Ancient World, New Haven, 1992
Cantarella, Eva, “Bisexuality in Ancient Legal Codes,” Diogenes 52, pp.
5–14, 2005
Charlesworth, M. P., “The Virtues of a Roman Emperor: Propaganda and
the Creation of Belief,” Proceedings of the British Academy 23, pp.
105–133, 1937
Chartier, Roger, “Intellectual History or Sociocultural History? The French
Trajectories,” in LaCapra & Kaplan (eds.), pp. 13–46, 1982
Chartier, Roger, “Text, Symbols, and Frenchness,” Journal of Modern
History 57, pp. 682–695, 1985
Clarke, Martin, Rhetoric at Rome: A Historical Survey, London, 1996
Classen, Carl Joachim, “Cicero Pro Cluentio 1–11 im Licht der
rhetorischen Theorie und Praxis,” Rheinische Museum 108, pp.
104–142, 1965
Classen, Carl Joachim, Recht, Rhetorik, Politik: Untersuchungen zu Ciceros
rhetorischer Strategie, Darmstadt, 1985
Connolly, Joy, The State of Speech: Rhetoric & Political Thought in Ancient
Rome, Princeton, 2007a
Connolly, Joy, “Virile Tongues: Rhetoric and Masculinity,” in Dominik &
Hall (eds.), pp. 83–97, 2007b
Connolly, Joy, “The Politics of Rhetorical Education,” in Gunderson (ed.),
pp. 126–144, 2009
Corbeill, Anthony, Controlling Laughter: Political Humor in the Late
Roman Republic, Princeton, 1996
Corbeill, Anthony, “Dining Deviants in Roman Political Invective,” in
Hallett & Skinner (eds.), pp. 99–128, 1997
Corbeill, Anthony, “Education in the Roman Republic: Creating
Traditions,” in Too (ed.), pp. 261–288, 2001
Corbeill, Anthony, “Rhetorical Education and Social Reproduction in the
Republic and Early Empire,” in Dominik & Hall (eds.), pp. 69–82, 2007
342
bibliography
Corbeill, Anthony, “Rhetorical Education in Cicero’s Youth,” in May (ed.),
pp. 23–48, 2002a
Corbeill, Anthony, “Ciceronian Invective,” in May (ed.), pp. 197–218,
2002b
Corbeill, Anthony, Nature Embodied: Gesture in Ancient Rome, Princeton,
2004
Corbeill, Anthony, “The Republican Body,” in Rosenstein & MorsteinMarx (eds.), pp. 439–456, 2006
Corbeill, Anthony, “O singulari prodigium: Ciceronian Invective as
Religious Expiation,” in Stevenson & Marcus (eds.), pp. 240–254, 2008
Cornell, T. J., The Beginnings of Rome: Italy and Rome from the Bronze
Age to the Punic Wars (c. 1000–264 BC), London, 1995
Covino, Ralph, “The laudatio funebris as a Vehicle for Praise and
Admonition,” in Smith & Covino (eds.), pp. 69–81, 2011
Craig, Christopher P., “Cicero’s Understanding with the Jury in the Speech
for Murena,” Transactions of the American Philological Association
116, pp. 229–239, 1986
Craig, Christopher P., Form as Argument in Cicero’s Speeches: A Study of
Dilemma, Atlanta, 1993
Craig, Christopher P., “A Survey of Selected Recent Work on Cicero’s
Rhetorica and Speeches,” in May (ed.), pp. 503–532, 2002
Craig, Christopher P., “Audience Expectations, Invective, and Proof,” in
Powell & Paterson (eds.), pp. 187–214, 2004
Craig, Christopher P., “Self-restraint, Invective, and Credibility in Cicero’s
First Catilinarian Oration,” American Journal of Philology 128, pp.
335–340, 2007
Crawford, Jane W., M. Tullius Cicero The Fragmentary Speeches, Atlanta,
1994
Crook, J. A., Law and Life of Rome, London, 1967
Crownover, Emma, “The Clash between Clodia and Cicero,” Classical
Journal 30, pp. 137–147, 1934
Culpepper Stroup, Sarah, “Greek Rhetoric Meets Rome: Expansion,
Resistance, and Acculturation,” in Dominik & Hall (eds.), pp. 23–37,
2007
Dalton, Russel J. & Klingemann, Hans-Dieter (eds.), The Oxford
Handbook of Political Behavior, Oxford, 2007
Damon, Cynthia, “Sex. Cloelius, Scriba,” Harvard Studies in Classical
Philology 94, pp. 227–250, 1992
David, Jean-Michel, Le patronat judiciarie au dernier siècle de la
République romaine, Rome, 1992
bibliography
343
David, Jean-Michel, “Rhetoric and Public Life,” in Rosenstein & MorsteinMarx (eds.), pp. 421–438, 2006
de Benedetti, Gina, “L’esilio di Cicerone e la sua importanza storicopolitica,” Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 3, pp. 331–363, 1929
Demertzis, Nicolas, Cultural Theory and Political Culture: New Directions
and Proposals, PhD. diss. Lund University, 1985
Denk, Thomas, Politisk kultur, Malmö, 2009
DeLacy, Phillip, “Cicero’s Invective against Piso,” Transactions of the
American Philological Association 72, pp. 49–58, 1941
Deroux, Carl (ed.), Studies in Latin Literature and Roman History, vol.
5–6, Brussels, 1989–1992
Dixon, Suzanne, Reading Roman Women, London, 2001
Dominik, William (ed.), Roman Eloquence: Rhetoric in Society and
Literature, London, 1997
Dominik, William & Hall, Jon (eds.), A Companion to Roman Rhetoric,
Oxford, 2007
Dominik, William & Smith, Christopher, “Introduction: Praise and Blame
in Roman Oratory,” in Smith & Covino (eds.), pp. 1–15, 2011
Dorey, T. A. (ed.), Cicero, London, 1964
Dover, Kenneth J., Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and
Aristotle, Oxford, 1974
Dover, Kenneth J., Greek Homosexuality, London, 1978
Drexler, Hans, Die Catilinarische Verschwörung: ein quellenheft,
Darmstadt, 1976
Dugan, John, Making a New Man: Ciceronian Self-fashioning in the
Rhetorical Works, Oxford, 2005
Dugan, John, “Modern Critical Approaches to Roman Rhetoric,” in
Dominik & Hall (eds.), pp. 9–22, 2007
Dugan, John, “Rhetoric and the Roman Republic,” in Gunderson (ed.), pp.
178–193, 2009
Duncan, Anne, “Infamous Performers: Comic Actors and Female Prostitutes
in Rome,” in Faraone & McClure (eds.), pp. 252–273, 2006
Dunkle, Roger, “The Greek Tyrant and Roman Political Invective of the
Late Republic,” Transactions of the American Philological Association
98, pp. 157–171, 1967
Dupont, Florence & Éloi, Thierry, L’érotisme masculin dans la Rome
antique, Paris, 2001
Dyck, Andrew R.,”Dressed to Kill: Attire as Proof and Means of
Characterization in Cicero’s Speeches,” Arethusa 34, pp. 119–130, 2001
Dyck, Andrew R., Catilinarians, Cambridge, 2008
344
bibliography
Dyck, Andrew R., Pro Sexto Roscio, Cambridge, 2010
Earl, Donald, The Political Thought of Sallust, Cambridge, 1961
Earl, Donald, The Moral and Political Tradition of Rome, Ithaca, 1967
Edwards, Catharine, The Politics of Immorality, Cambridge, 1993
Edwards, Catharine, “Unspeakable Professions: Public Performance and
Prostitution in Ancient Rome,” in Hallett & Skinner (eds.), pp. 66–95,
1997
Ekström, Anders, Representation och materialitet: introduktioner till
kulturhistorien, Nora, 2009
Epstein, David F., “Cicero’s Testimony at the Bona dea Trial,” Classical
Philology 81, pp. 229–235, 1986
Epstein, David F., Personal Enmity in Roman Politics 218–43 BC, London,
1987
Erskine, Andrew, “Hellenistic Monarchy and Roman Political Invective,”
Classical Quarterly 41, pp. 106–120, 1991
Evans, Richard, “Phantoms in the Philippics: Catiline, Clodius and
Antonian Parallels,” in Stevenson & Wilson (eds.), pp. 62–81, 2008
Everitt, Anthony, Cicero: The Life and Times of Rome’s Greatest Politician,
New York, 2002
Fantham, Elaine, “Stuprum: Public Attitudes and Penalties for Sexual
Offences in Republican Rome,” Echoes du Monde Classique/Classical
Views 35, pp. 267–291, 1991
Fantham, Elaine, The Roman World of Cicero’s De Oratore, Oxford, 2004
Faraone, Christopher A. & McClure, Laura (eds.), Prostitutes and
Courtesans in the Ancient World, Madison, 2006
Fears, J. Rufus, “The Cult of Virtues and Roman Imperial Ideology,”
Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt 2, pp. 827–948, 1981
Flaig, Egon, “Entscheidung und Konsens: Zu den Feldern der politischen
Kommunikation zwischen Aristokratie und Plebs,” in Jehne (ed.), pp.
77–127, 1995
Flaig, Egon, Ritualisierte Politik: Zeichen, Gesten und Herrschaft im Alten
Rom, Göttingen, 2003
Flower, Harriet I. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Roman
Republic, Cambridge, 2004
Flower, Harriet I., “Spectacle and Political Culture in the Roman Republic,”
in Flower (ed.), pp. 322–343, 2004a
Flower, Harriet I., The Art of Forgetting: Disgrace and Oblivion in Roman
Political Culture, Chapel Hill, 2006
Flower, Harriet I., Roman Republics, Princeton, 2010
Forsythe, Gary, A Critical History of Early Rome: From Prehistory to the
First Punic War, Berkeley, 2005
bibliography
345
Foucault, Michel, The History of Sexuality II: The Use of Pleasure, tr.
Robert Hurley, New York, 1985
Foxhall, Lin & Salmon, John (eds.), When Men Were Men: Masculinity,
Power and Identity in Classical Antiquity, London, 1998
Frazel, Thomas D., “The Composition and Circulation of Cicero’s In
Verrem,” Classical Quarterly 54, pp. 128–142, 2004
Frazel, Thomas D., The Rhetoric of Cicero’s In Verrem, Göttingen, 2009
Fredrick, David (ed.), The Roman Gaze: Vision, Power, and the Body,
Baltimore, 2002
Fredrick, David, “Mapping Penetrability in Late Republican and Early
Imperial Rome,” in Fredrick (ed.), pp. 236–264, 2002a
Frisch, Hartvig, Cicero’s Fight for the Republic: The Historical Background
of Cicero’s Philippics, Copenhagen, 1946
Fuchs, Dieter, “The Political Culture Paradigm,” in Dalton & Klingemann
(eds.), pp. 161–184, 2007
Gallagher, Catherine & Greenblatt, Stephen, Practicing New Historicism,
Chicago, 2000
Game, Josiah, An Introduction to the Philippics of Cicero and to the Study
of his Invective, PhD. diss. Yale University, 1909
Gardner, R., Cicero Pro Sestio, In Vatinium, Loeb Classical Library,
London, 1958
Gardner, Jane F., Women in Roman Law and Society, London, 1986
Gardner, Jane F., Being a Roman Citizen, London, 1993
Gardner, Jane F., “Sexing a Roman: Imperfect Men in Roman Law,” in
Foxhall & Salmon (eds.), pp. 136–152, 1998
Garland, Robert, The Eye of the Beholder: Deformity and Disability in the
Graeco-Roman World, London 1995
Geertz, Clifford, The Interpretation of Cultures, New York, 1973
Geffcken, Katherine, Comedy in the Pro Caelio, with an appendix on the In
Clodium et Curionem, Leiden, 1973
Gelzer, Matthias, Die Nobilität der römischen Republik, Leipzig, 1912
Gelzer, Matthias, Kleine Schriften vols. 1–3, Wiesbaden, 1962–1964
Gelzer, Matthias, Cicero: ein Biographischer Versuch, Wiesbaden, 1969
Gildenhard, Ingo, “Greek Auxiliaries: Tragedy and Philosophy in
Ciceronian Invective,” in Booth (ed.), pp. 149–182, 2006
Gildenhard, Ingo, Creative Eloquence: The Construction of Reality in
Cicero’s Speeches, Oxford, 2011
Gleason, Maud W., Making Men: Sophists and Self-Presentation in Ancient
Rome, Princeton, 1995
Gleason, Maud W., “Elite Male Identity in the Roman Empire,” in Potter &
Mattingly (eds.), pp. 67–84, 1999
346
bibliography
Gonfroy, Francoise, “Homosexualité et l’idéologie esclavagiste chez
Ciceron,” Dialogues d’histoire ancienne 4, pp. 219–265, 1978
Gotoff, Harold C., Cicero’s Caesarian Speeches, Chapel Hill, 1993
Gotoff, Harold C.,“Cicero’s Caesarian Orations,” in May (ed.), pp.
219–271, 2002
Gozzoli, Sandra, “La In Pisonem di Cicerone: Un esempio di polemica
politica,” Athenaeum 78 pp. 451–463, 1990
Greenblatt, Stephen, Renaissance Self-Fashioning: From More to
Shakespeare, Chicago, 1980
Greenblatt, Stephen, Shakespearean Negotiations: The Circulation of Social
Energy in Renaissance England, Berkeley, 1988
Greenblatt, Stephen, Learning to Curse: Essays in Early Modern Culture,
New York, 1990a
Greenblatt, Stephen, “Culture,” in McLaughlin & Lentricchia (eds.), pp.
225–232, 1990b
Greenwood, L. H. G., The Verrine Orations I, Loeb Classical Library,
London, 1928
Grifin, Jasper, Latin Poets and Roman Life, London, 1985
Grifin, Miriam T. & Atkins, E. M. (eds.), Cicero, On Duties, Cambridge,
1991
Grifin, Miriam T., “Piso, Cicero and their Audience,” in Auvray-Assayas &
Delattre (eds.), pp. 85–100, 2001
Grimal, Pierre, Contre L. Pison, Paris, 1966
Gruen, Erich S., Roman Politics and the Criminal Courts, 149-78 B.C.,
Cambridge, 1968
Gruen, Erich S., “Pompey, Metellus Pius, and the Trials of 70–69 B.C. The
Perils of Schematism,” American Journal of Philology 92, pp. 1–16,
1971
Gruen, Erich S., The Last Generation of the Roman Republic, Berkeley,
1974
Gruen, Erich S., “Romans and Others,” in Rosenstein & Morstein-Marx
(eds.), pp. 459–477, 2006
Gunderson, Erik, Staging Masculinity: The Rhetoric of Performance in the
Ancient World, Ann Arbor, 2000
Gunderson, Erik, Declamation, Paternity, and Roman Identity, Cambridge,
2003
Gunderson, Erik, (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Rhetoric,
Cambridge, 2009
Habicht, Christian, Cicero the Politician, Baltimore, 1990
bibliography
347
Habinek, Thomas N., & Schiesaro, Alessandro (eds.), The Roman Cultural
Revolution, Cambridge, 1997
Habinek, Thomas N., The Politics of Latin Literature: Writing, Identity,
and Empire in Ancient Rome, Princeton, 1998
Habinek, Thomas N., Ancient Rhetoric and Oratory, Malden, 2005
Hall, Jon, “The Philippics,” in May (ed.), pp. 273–304, 2002
Hallett, Judith P. & Skinner, Marilyn B., Roman Sexualities, Princeton,
1997
Halperin, David M., Winkler, John J. & Zeitlin, Froma I. (eds.), Before
Sexuality: The Construction of Erotic Experience in the Ancient Greek
World, Princeton, 1990
Hammar, Isak, “Rolling Thunder: Movement, Violence and Narrative in
the Roman Late Republic,” in Bjornebye, Malmberg & Österberg (eds.),
forthcoming 2014
Hardy, E. G., “The Catilinarian Conspiracy in Its Context: a Re-Study of
the Evidence,” Journal of Roman Studies 7, pp. 153–228, 1917
Harries, Jill, Law and Crime in the Roman World, Cambridge, 2007
Harries, Jill, “Violating the Principles of Partnership: Cicero on Quinctius
and Naevius,” in Smith, & Covino (eds.), pp. 127–143, 2011
Harris, W. V., “On Deining the Political Culture of the Roman Republic:
Some Comments on Rosenstein, Williamson, and North,” Classical
Philology 85, pp. 288–294, 1990
Harrison, Dick, The Age of Abbesses and Queens, Lund, 1998
Heath, Malcolm, “Codiications of Rhetoric,” in Gunderson (ed.), pp.
59–73, 2009
Hesk, Jon, “Types of Oratory,” in Gunderson (ed.), pp. 145–161, 2009
Heskel, Julia, “Cicero as Evidence for Attitudes in Dress in the Late
Republic,” in Sebesta & Bonfante (eds.), pp. 133–145, 1994
Hickson-Hahn, Frances, “What’s so Funny? Laughter and Incest in
Invective Humor,” Syllecta Classica 9, pp. 1–36, 1998
Hölkeskamp, Karl-Joachim, Die Entstehung der Nobilität: Studien zur
sozialen und politischen Geschichte der Römischen Republik im 4. Jhdt.
v. Chr, Stuttgart, 1987
Hölkeskamp, Karl-Joachim, “Conquest, Competition and Consensus:
Roman Expansion in Italy and the Rise of the Nobilitas,” Historia:
Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 42, pp. 12–39, 1993
Hölkeskamp, Karl-Joachim, Rekonstruktionen einer Republik: Die
politische Kultur des antiken Rom und die Forschung der letzten
Jahrzehnte, Munich, 2004
348
bibliography
Hölkeskamp, Karl-Joachim, Reconstructing the Roman Republic: An
Ancient Political Culture and Modern Research, Princeton, 2010
Hölkeskamp, Karl-Joachim, “Self-serving Sermons: Oratory and the Selfconstruction of the Republican Aristocrat,” in Smith & Covino (eds.),
pp. 17–34, 2011
Hopkins, Keith, Death and Renewal, Cambridge, 1983
Hopkins, Keith and Burton, Graham, “Political Succession in the Later
Republic (249-50 BC),” in Hopkins, 1983
Humbert, J., Les plaidoyers ecrits et les plaidoires realles de Cicéron, Paris,
1925
Hunt, Lynn (ed.), The New Cultural History, Berkeley, 1989
Iggers, George, Historiography in the Twentieth Century, Hanover, 1997
Jackob, Nikolaus, “Cicero and the Opinion of the People: The Nature, Role
and Power of Public Opinion in the Late Roman Republic,” Journal of
Elections, Public Opinions and Parties 17, pp. 293–311, 2007
James, Sharon L., “A Courtesan’s Coreography: Female Liberty and Male
Anxiety at the Roman Dinner Party,” in Faraone & McClure (eds.), pp.
224–251, 2006
Jehne, Martin (ed.), Demokratie in Rom?: Die Rolle des Volkes in der
Politik der römischen Republik, Stuttgart, 1995
Jehne, Martin, “Rednertätigkeit und Statusdissonanzen in der späten
römischen Republik,” in Neumeister & Raeck (eds.), pp. 167–189, 2000
Jehne, Martin, “Methods, Models, and Historiography,” in Rosenstein &
Morstein-Marx (eds.), pp. 3–28, 2006
Kaster, Robert A., Emotion, Restraint, and Community in Ancient Rome,
Oxford, 2005
Kelly, Douglas, “Publishing the Philippics, 44–43 BC,” in Stevenson &
Wilson (eds.), pp. 22–38, 2008
Kennedy, George, “The Rhetoric of Advocacy in the Roman World,”
American Journal of Philology 89, pp. 419–436, 1968
Kennedy, George, The Art of Rhetoric in the Roman World: 300 BC–AD
300, Princeton, 1972
Kennedy, George, Aristotle. On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse,
New York, 1991
Ker, Walter C. A., Philippics, Loeb Classical Library, 1926
Kiefer, Otto, Sexual Life in Ancient Rome, London, 1934
Kirby, John T., The Rhetoric of Cicero’s Pro Cluentio, Amsterdam, 1990
Kirby, John T., “Ciceronian Rhetoric: Theory and Practice,” in Dominik
(ed.), pp. 13–31, 1997
Knapp, Robert, Invisible Romans, London, 2011
bibliography
349
Konstan, David, “Rhetoric and the Crisis of Legitimacy in Cicero’s
Catilinarian Orations,” in Poulakos (ed.), pp. 11–30, 1993
Koster, Severin, Die Invektive in der griechischen und römischen Literatur,
Meisenheim am Glan, 1980
Krostenko, Brian, A., Cicero, Catullus and the Language of Social
Performance, Chicago, 2001
Kubiak, David, P. “Piso’s Madness (Cic. in Pis. 21 and 47),” American
Journal of Philology 110, pp. 237–245, 1989
Kurczyk, Stephanie, Cicero und die Inszenierung der eigenen
Vergangenheit: Autobiographisches Schreiben in der Späten Römischen
Republik, Köln, 2006
Kurke, Alexander D., Theme and Adversarial Presentation in Cicero’s pro
Flacco, PhD. diss. University of Michigan, 1989
LaCapra, Dominick & Kaplan, Steven L. (eds.), Modern Intellectual
History: Reappraisals and New Perspectives, Ithaca, 1992
Lacey, Walter K., “Boni atque improbi,” Greece & Rome 17, pp. 1–16,
1970
Lacey, Walter K., Cicero’s Second Philippic Oration, Warminster, 1986
Langlands, Rebecca, Sexual Morality in Ancient Rome, Cambridge, 2006
Lausberg, Heinrich, Handbook of Literary Rhetoric: A Foundation for
Literary Study, ed. by David E. Orton & R. Dean Anderson, Leiden,
1998
Leach, Eleanor W., “The Politics of Self-Presentation: Pliny’s Letters and
Roman Portrait Sculpture,” Classical Antiquity 9, pp. 19–39, 1990
Leach, Eleanor W., “Gendering Clodius,” Classical World, pp. 335–359,
2001
Leach, Eleanor W., “Otium as Luxuria in the Status Economy of Pliny’s
Letters,” Arethusa 36, pp. 147–166, 2003
Ledentu, Marie, “L’orateur, la parole et le texte,” in Achard & Ledentu
(eds.), pp. 43–56, 2000
Leeman, Anton D., Orationis Ratio: The Stylistic Theories and Practice
of the Roman Orators, Historians, and Philosophers 1–2, Amsterdam,
1963
Leeman, Anton D. & Pinkster, Harm, M. Tullius Cicero, De Oratore Libri
III, Heidelberg, 1981
Leeman, Anton D., Pinkster, Harm & Nelson, H. L. W, M. Tullius Cicero,
De Oratore Libri III, Heidelberg, 1985
Leeman, Anton D., Pinkster, Harm & Rabbie, Edwin, M. Tullius Cicero, De
Oratore Libri III, Heidelberg, 1989
350
bibliography
Leeman, Anton D., Pinkster, Harm & Wisse, Jacob, M. Tullius Cicero, De
Oratore Libri III, Heidelberg, 1996
Leeman, Anton D., “The Technique of Persuasion in Cicero’s Pro Murena,”
in Ludwig (ed.), pp. 193–228, 1982
Leff, Michael, “The Topics of Argumentative Invention in Latin Rhetorical
Theory from Cicero to Boethius,” Rhetorica, 1983
Leigh, Matthew, “The ‘Pro Caelio’ and Comedy,” Classical Philology 99,
pp. 300–335, 2004
Lenaghan, John O., A Commentary on Cicero’s Oration De haruspicum
responso, The Hague, 1969
Lewis, R.G., “Catilina and the Vestal,” Classical Quarterly 51, pp.
141–149, 2001
Lilja, Saara, Terms of Abuse in Roman Comedy, Helsinki, 1965
Lilja, Saara, Homosexuality in Republican and Augustan Rome, Helsinki,
1983
Lind, L. Robert, “The Idea of the Republic and the Foundations of Roman
Morality I” in Deroux (ed.), pp. 5–34, 1989
Lind, L. Robert, “The Idea of the Republic and the Foundations of Roman
Morality II” in Deroux (ed.), pp. 5–40, 1992
Linke, Bernhard & Stemmler, Michael, Mos Maiorum: Untersuchungen zu
den Formen der Identitätsstiftung und Stabilisierung in der römischen
Republik, Stuttgart, 2000
Lintott, Andrew, Violence in Republican Rome, Oxford,1968
Lintott, Andrew, “Imperial Expansion and Moral Decline in the Roman
Republic,” Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 21, pp. 626–638,
1972
Lintott, Andrew, “Democracy in the Middle Republic,” Zeitschrift der
Savigny-Stiftung 104, pp. 34–52, 1987
Lintott, Andrew, The Constitution of the Roman Republic, Oxford, 1993
Lintott, Andrew, “Legal Procedure in Cicero’s Time,” in Powell & Paterson
(eds.), pp. 61–78, 2004
Litchield, Henry W., “National exempla virtutis in Roman Literature,”
Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 25, pp. 1–71, 1914
Long, George, Orationes, vol. 4, London, 1858
Ludwig, Walther (ed.), Éloquence et rhétorique chez Ciceron, Geneva, 1982
Malcovati, Henrica (ed.), Oratorum Romanorum Fragmenta, Turin, 1976
Malking, Irad & Rubinsohn, Z. W. (eds.), Leaders and Masses in the
Roman World: Studies in Honor of Zvi Yavetz, Leiden, 1995
Manuwald, Gesine, “The Function of Praise and Blame in Cicero’s
Philippics,” in Smith & Covino (eds.), pp. 199–214, 2011
bibliography
351
Maslowski, Tadeusz, M. Tulli Ciceronis scripta quae manserunt omnia.
Fasc. 23, Orationes in P. Vatinium testem pro M. Caelio, Stuttgart, 1995
May, James M., “The Ethica Digressio and Cicero’s Pro Milone: A
Progression of Intensity from Logos to Ethos to Pathos,” Classical
Journal 74, pp. 240–246, 1979
May, James M., Trials of Character: The Eloquence of Ciceronian Ethos,
Chapel Hill, 1988
May, James M., “Cicero and the Beasts,” Syllecta Classica 7, pp. 143–153,
1996
May, James M., “Cicero’s Pro Milone: An Ideal Speech of an Ideal Orator,”
in Wooten (ed.), pp. 123–134, 2001a
May, James M. & Wisse, Jakob (eds.), Cicero: On the Ideal Orator,
Oxford, 2001b
May, James M. (ed.), Brill’s Companion to Cicero: Oratory and Rhetoric,
Leiden, 2002
May, James M., “Cicero: His Life and Career,” in May (ed.), pp. 1–22,
2002a
May, James M., “Ciceronian Oratory in Context,” in May (ed.), pp. 49–70,
2002b
Maza, Sarah, “Stephen Greenblatt, New Historicism, and Cultural History,
or, What We Talk About When We Talk About Interdisciplinarity,”
Modern Intellectual History 1, pp. 249–265, 2004
McClintock, R. C., Cicero’s Narrative Technique in the Judicial Speeches,
PhD. diss. Univeristy of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, 1975
McCoy, Marsha, “The Politics of Prostitution: Clodia, Cicero, and Social
Order in the Late Roman Republic,” in Faraone & McClure (eds.), pp.
177–185, 2006
McDermott, W. C., “Cicero’s Publication of his Consular Orations,”
Philologus 116, pp. 277–284, 1972
McDonnell, Myles, Roman Manliness: Virtus and the Roman Republic,
Cambridge, 2006
McGinn, Thomas A. J., Prostitution, Sexuality, and the Law in Ancient
Rome, Oxford, 1998
McLaughlin, Thomas & Lentricchia, Frank (eds.), Critical Terms for
Literary Study, Chicago, 1990
McMullen, Ramsay, “Roman Attitudes to Greek Love”, Historia:
Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 31, pp. 484–502, 1982
Meier, Christian, Res publica amissa: Eine Studie zur Verfassung und
Geschichte der späten römischen Republik, Wiesbaden, 1966
352
bibliography
Merrill, Norman W., Cicero and Early Roman Invective, PhD. diss.
University of Cincinnati, 1975
Millar, Fergus, “The Political Character of the Classical Roman Republic,
200–151 B.C.,” Journal of Roman Studies 74, pp. 1–19, 1984
Millar, Fergus, “Politics, Persuasion, and the People before the Social War
(150–90 B.C.),” Journal of Roman Studies 76, pp. 1–11, 1986
Millar, Fergus, “Political Power in Mid-Republican Rome: Curia or
Comitium,” Journal of Roman Studies 79, pp. 138–150, 1989
Millar, Fergus, “Popular Politics at Rome in the Late Republic,” in Malkin
& Rubinsohn (eds.), pp. 91–113,1995
Millar, Fergus, The Crowd in Rome in the Late Republic, Ann Arbor, 1998
Mitchell, Thomas N., Cicero: The Ascending Years, New Haven, 1979
Mitchell, Thomas N., Cicero: The Senior Statesman, New Haven, 1991
Mommsen, Theodor, Römische Geschichte, 5 vols., Berlin, 1881–1886
Mommsen, Theodor, Römische Staatsrecht, 3 vols., Leipzig, 1887–1888
Moreau, Philippe, Clodiana Religio: Un procès politique en 61 av. J.-C.,
Paris, 1982
Morgan, Teresa, Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire, Cambridge,
2007
Morstein-Marx, Robert, Mass Oratory and Political Power in the Late
Roman Republic, Cambridge, 2004
Mouritsen, Henrik, Plebs and Politics in the Late Roman Republic,
Cambridge, 2001
Mulroy, David, “The Early Career of P. Clodius Pulcher: A Re-Examination
of the Charges of Mutiny and Sacrilege,”Transactions of the American
Philological Association 118, pp. 155–178, 1988
Münzer, Friedrich, Römische Adelsparteien und Adelsfamilien, Stuttgart,
1920
Neumeister, Christoff & Raeck, Wulf (eds.), Rede und Redner: Bewertung
und Darstellung in den antiken Kulturen, Möhnesee, 2000
Nicolet, Claude, The World of the Citizen in Republican Rome, Berkeley,
1980
Nippel, Wilfried, Mischverfassungstheorie und Verfassungsrealität in Antike
und früher Neuzeit, Stuttgart, 1980
Nippel, Wilfried, Public Order in Ancient Rome, Cambridge, 1995
Nisbet, R. G. M., M. Tulli Ciceronis De Domo Sua ad Pontiices oratio,
Oxford, 1939
Nisbet, R. G. M., M. Tulli Ciceronis In L. Calpurnium Pisonem oratio,
Oxford, 1961
Nisbet, R. G. M., “The Speeches,” in Dorey (ed.), pp. 47–79, 1964
bibliography
353
North, John A., “Democratic Politics in Republican Rome,” Past and
Present 126, pp. 3–21, 1990a
North, John A., “Politics and Aristocracy in the Roman Republic,” Classical
Philology 85, pp. 277–287, 1990b
North, John A., “The Constitution of the Roman Republic,” in Rosenstein
& Morstein-Marx (eds.), pp. 256–277, 2006
Novokhatko, Anna A., The Invectives of Sallust and Cicero: Critical
Edition with Introduction, Translation, and Commentary, Berlin, 2009
Oakley, Stephen, “The Early Republic,” in Flower (ed.), pp. 15–30,
2004
Olson, Kelly, “Roman Underwear Revisited,” Classical World 96, pp.
201–210, 2003
Olson, Kelly, “Matrona and Whore: Clothing and Deinition in Roman
Antiquity,” in Faraone & McClure (eds.), pp. 186–204, 2006
Opelt, Ilona, Die lateinischen Schimpfwörter und verwandte sprachliche
Erscheinungen: Eine Typologie, Heidelberg, 1965
Östenberg, Ida, Staging the World: Spoils, Captives, and Representations in
the Roman Triumphal Procession, Oxford, 2009
Österberg, Eva, “Vardagens sträva samförstånd,” in Broberg, Wikander &
Åmark (eds.), pp. 126–146, 1993
Parker, Holt N., “The Teratogenic Grid,” in Hallett & Skinner (eds.), pp.
47–65, 1997
Petrochilos, Nicholas, Roman Attitudes to the Greeks, Athens, 1974
Philipps, E. J., “Catiline’s Conspiracy,” Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte
Geschichte 25, pp. 441–448, 1976
Pina Polo, Francisco, Las contiones civiles y militares en Roma, Zaragoza,
1989
Pitcher, Roger A., “The Second Philippic as a Source for Aristocratic
Values,” in Stevenson & Wilson (eds.), pp. 131–139, 2008
Pocock, L. G., A Commentary on Cicero In Vatinium, London, 1926
Potter, D. S. & Mattingly, D. J., Life, Death, and Entertainment in the
Roman Empire, Ann Arbor, 1999
Powell, Jonathan G. F. & Paterson, Jeremy (eds.), Cicero the Advocate,
Oxford, 2004
Powell, Jonathan G. F., “Invective and the Orator: Ciceronian Theory and
Practice,” in Booth (ed.), pp. 1–23, 2006
Powell, Jonathan G. F., “Court Procedure and Rhetorical Strategy in
Cicero,” in Berry & Erskine (eds.), pp. 21–36, 2010
Poulakos, Takis (ed.), Rethinking the History of Rhetoric: Multidisciplinary
Essays on the Rhetorical Tradition, Boulder, 1993
354
bibliography
Poulakos, Takis, “Introduction: Alternative Approaches to the Rhetorical
Tradition,” in Poulakos (ed.), pp. 1–10, 1993a
Prag, Jonathan (ed.), Sicilia Nutrix Plebis Romanae: Rhetoric, Law, and
Taxation in Cicero’s Verrines, London, 2007
Prag, Jonathan, “Introduction,” in Prag (ed.), pp. 1–4, 2007a
Price, Jonathon, “The Failure of Cicero’s First Catilinarian,” Studies in
Latin Literature and Roman History 9, pp. 106–128, 1998
Pritchard, R. T., “Gaius Verres and the Sicilian Farmers,” Historia:
Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 20, pp. 224–238, 1971
Pye, Lucien & Verba, Sidney (eds.), Political Culture and Political
Development, Princeton, 1965
Qvarsell, Roger & Sandin, Bengt (eds.), Den mångfaldiga historien: tio
historiker om forskningen inför framtiden, Lund, 2000
Raalaub, Kurt A., “Between Myth and History: Rome’s Rise from Village
to Empire (the Eight century to 264),” in Rosenstein & Morstein-Marx
(eds.), pp. 125–146, 2006
Ramsey, John T., Cicero: Philippics I-II, Cambridge, 2003
Ramsey, John T., “Roman Senatorial Oratory,” in Dominik & Hall (eds.),
pp. 122–135, 2007
Rasmussen, Susanne, Public Portents in Republican Rome, Rome, 2003
Rawson, Elizabeth, Cicero: A Portrait, London, 1975
Rawson, Elizabeth, Intellectual Life in the Late Roman Republic, London,
1985
Richlin, Amy, Sexual Terms and Themes in Roman Satire and Related
Genres, PhD. diss. Yale University, 1978
Richlin, Amy, “Approaches to the Sources on Adultery at Rome,” Women’s
Studies 8, pp. 225–250, 1981
Richlin, Amy, “Invective Against Women in Roman Satire,” Arethusa 17,
pp. 67–80, 1984
Richlin, Amy, The Garden of Priapus: Sexuality and Aggression in Roman
Humor, Oxford, 1992
Richlin, Amy, “Not Before Homosexuality: The Materiality of the Cinaedus
and the Roman Law Against Love Between Men,” Journal of the
History of Sexuality 3, pp. 523–573, 1993
Riggsby, Andrew M., “Pliny on Cicero and Oratory: Self-Fashioning in the
Public Eye,” American Journal of Philology 116, pp. 123–135, 1995
Riggsby, Andrew M., “Did the Romans Believe in Their Verdicts?,”
Rhetorica 15, pp. 235–251, 1997
Riggsby, Andrew M., Crime and Community in Ciceronian Rome, Austin,
1999
bibliography
355
Riggsby, Andrew M., “The Post Reditum Speeches,” in May (ed.), pp.
159–198, 2002
Riggsby, Andrew M., “The Rhetoric of Character in the Roman Courts,” in
Powell & Paterson (eds.), pp. 165–186, 2004
Rosenstein, Nathan, Imperatores Victi: Military Defeat and Aristocratic
Competition in the Middle and Late Republic, Berkeley, 1990a
Rosenstein, Nathan, “War, Failure, and Aristocratic Competition,” Classical
Philology 85, pp. 255–265, 1990b
Rosenstein, Nathan, “Competition and Crisis in Mid-Republican Rome,”
Phoenix 47, pp. 313–338, 1993
Rosenstein, Nathan & Morstein-Marx, Robert (eds.), A Companion to the
Roman Republic, Malden, 2006
Rosenstein Nathan, “Aristocratic Values,” in Rosenstein & Morstein-Marx
(eds.), pp. 365–382, 2006a
Ruffell, Ian A., “Beyond Satire: Horace, Popular Invective and the
Segregation of Literature,” Journal of Roman Studies 93, pp. 35–65,
2003
Rüpke, Jörg, “Roman Religion,” in Flower (ed.), pp. 179–195, 2004
Rüpke, Jörg, “Communicating with the Gods,” in Rosenstein & MorsteinMarx (eds.), pp. 215–235, 2006
Rutledge, Steven H., “Oratory and Politics in the Empire,” in Dominik &
Hall (eds.), pp. 109–121, 2007
Ryan, F. X., “The Lex Scantinia and the Prosecution of Censors and
Aediles,” Classical Philology 89, pp. 159–162, 1994
Salomon, Kim, “Symboler och ritualer i politisk samtidshistoria,” in
Qvarsell & Sandin (eds,), pp. 123–144, 2000
Sanford, Eva Matthews, “The Career of Aulus Gabinius,” Transactions and
Proceedings of the American Philological Association 70, pp. 64–92,
1939
Santoro L’Hoir, Francesca, The Rhetoric of Gender Terms: ’Man’, ’Woman’,
and the Portrayal of Character in Latin Prose, Leiden, 1992
Scullard, Howard H., A History of the Roman World from 753 to 146
B.C., London, 1935
Scullard, Howard H., Roman Politics, 220–150 B.C., Oxford, 1951
Scullard, Howard H., From the Gracchi to Nero: A History of Rome from
133 B.C. to A.D. 68, London, 1959
Seager, Robin, “Iusta Catilinae,” Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte
22, pp. 240–248, 1973
Seager, Robin, “Ciceronian Invective: Themes and Variations,” in Booth
(ed.), pp. 25–46, 2006
356
bibliography
Sebesta, Judith Lynn & Bonfante, Larissa (eds.), The World of Roman
Costume, Madison, 1994
Settle, James N., The Publication of Cicero’s Orations, PhD. diss. University
of North Carolina, 1962
Shackleton Bailey, David R., Philippics, Chapel Hill, 1986
Shackleton Bailey, David R., Back from Exile: Six Speeches Upon his
Return, Atlanta, 1991
Sherwin-White, A. N., Racial Predjudice in Imperial Rome, Cambridge,
1967
Sinclair, Patrick, “The Sententia in Rhetorica ad Herennium: A Study in
the Sociology of Rhetoric,” American Journal of Philology 114, pp.
561–580, 1993
Sissa, Giulia, Sex and Sensuality in the Ancient World, New Haven, 2008
Skinner, Marilyn B., “Pretty Lesbius,” Transactions of the American
Philological Association 112, pp. 197–208, 1982
Skinner, Marilyn B., Sexuality in Greek and Roman Culture, Malden, 2005
Skinner, Quentin, Visions of Politics: Regarding Method, Cambridge, 2002
Smith, Christopher & Covino, Ralph (eds.), Praise and Blame in Roman
Republican Rhetoric, Swansea, 2011
Solmsen, Friedrich, “The Aristotelian Tradition in Ancient Rhetoric,”
American Journal of Philology 62, pp. 35–50, 1941
Starr, Raymond, J. “The Circulation of Literary Texts in the Roman World,”
Classical Quarterly 37, pp. 213–223, 1987
Steel, Catherine E.W., Cicero, Rhetoric, and Empire, Oxford, 2001
Steel, Catherine E.W., Roman Oratory, Cambridge, 2006
Steel, Catherine E.W., “Name and Shame? Invective against Clodius and
others in the Post-exile Speeches,” in Booth (ed.), pp. 105–128, 2006
Steel, Catherine E.W., “The Rhetoric of the De Frumento,” in Prag (ed.), pp.
37–48, 2007
Steel, Catherine E.W., “Finessing Failure: the Sixth Philippic,” in Stevenson
& Wilson (eds.), pp. 255–265, 2008
Steel, Catherine E.W., “Divisions of Speech,” in Gunderson (ed.), pp. 77–91,
2009
Steel, Catherine E.W., “Cicero’s Oratory of Praise and Blame and the
Practice of Elections in the Late Roman Republic,” in Smith & Covino
(eds.), pp. 35–48, 2011
Steel, Catherine E. W. & van der Blom, Henriette (eds.), Community and
Communication: Oratory and Politics in Republican Rome, Oxford, 2013
bibliography
357
Stem, Rex, “Cicero as Orator and Philosopher: The Value of the Pro
Murena for Ciceronian Political Thought,” The Review of Politics 68,
pp. 206–231, 2006
Stevenson, Tom & Wilson, Marcus (eds.), Cicero’s Philippics: History,
Rhetoric, Ideology, Auckland, 2008
Stevenson, Tom, “Tyrants, Kings and Fathers in the Philippics,” in
Stevenson & Wilson (eds.), pp. 95–113, 2008a
Stockton, David, Cicero: A Political Biography, London, 1971
Stroh, Wilfried, Taxis und Taktik: Die advokatische Dispositionskunst in
Ciceros Gerichtreden, Stuttgart, 1975
Süss, Wilhelm, Ethos: Studien zur älteren griechischen Rhetorik, Leipzig,
1910
Syme, Ronald, The Roman Revolution, Oxford, 1939
Tatum, Jeffrey W., The Patrician Tribune, Chapel Hill, 1999
Tatum, Jeffrey W., “Invective Identities in Pro Caelio,” in Smith & Covino
(eds.), pp. 165–180, 2011
Taylor, Lily Ross, Roman Voting Assemblies from the Hannibalic Wars to
the Time of Caesar, Ann Arbor, 1966
Taylor, Rabun, “Two Pathic Subcultures in Ancient Rome,” Journal of the
History of Sexuality 7, pp. 319–371, 1997
Tempest, Kathryn, “Saints and Sinners: Some Thoughts on the Presentation
of Character in Attic Oratory and Cicero’s Verrines,” in Prag (ed.), pp.
19–36, 2007
Tempest, Kathryn, “Combating the Odium of Self-Praise: Cicero’s Divinatio
in Caecilium,” in Smith & Covino (eds.), pp. 145–164, 2011
Tempest, Kathryn, Cicero: Politics and Persuasion in Ancient Rome,
London, 2011
Thome, Gabriele, Vorstellungen vom Bösen in der lateinischen Literatur:
Begriffe, Motive, Gestalten, Stuttgart, 1993
Too, Yun Lee (ed.), Education in Greek and Roman Antiquity, Leiden,
2001
Tracy, Valerie A., “Roman Dandies and Transvestites,” Echoes du Monde
Classique/Classical Views, pp. 60–63, 1976
Treggiari, Susan, Roman Marriage: Iusti Coniuges from the Time of Cicero
to the Time of Ulpian, Oxford, 1991
Uría, Javier, “The Semantics and Pragmatics of Ciceronian Invective,” in
Booth (ed.), pp. 47–70, 2006
van der Blom, Henriette, Cicero’s Role Models: The Political Strategy of a
Newcomer, Oxford, 2010
358
bibliography
van der Blom, Henriette, “Historical Exempla as Tools of Praise and Blame
in Ciceronian Oratory,” in Smith & Covino (eds.), pp. 49–68, 2011
van der Blom, Henriette, “Fragmentary Speeches: the Oratory and Political
Career of Piso Caesoninus,” in Steel & van der Blom (eds.), pp.
297–312, 2013
Vanderbroeck, Paul J. J., Popular Leadership and Collective Behavior in the
Late Roman Republic (ca. 80–50 B.C.), Amsterdam, 1987
van der Wal, Roger L., “’What a funny Consul we have!’ Cicero’s Dealings
with Cato Uticensis and Prominent Friends in Opposition,” in Booth
(ed.), pp. 183–205, 2006
Vasaly, Ann, “The Masks of Rhetoric: Cicero’s Pro Roscio Amerino,”
Rhetorica 3, pp. 1–20, 1985
Vasaly, Ann, Representations: Images of the World in Ciceronian Oratory,
Berkeley, 1993
Vasaly, Ann, “Cicero’s Early Speeches,” in May (ed.), pp. 71–112, 2002
Vasaly, Ann, “Cicero, Domestic Politics, and the First Action of the
Verrines,” Classical Antiquity 28, pp. 101–137, 2009
Verba, Sidney, “Comparative Political Culture,” in Pye & Verba (eds.), pp.
512–560, 1965
Veyne, Paul, “Homosexuality in Ancient Rome,” in Ariès & Béjin (eds.), pp.
26–35, 1985
Vickers, Brian, In Defense of Rhetoric, Oxford, 1988
Vitanza, Victor J., “Some Rudiments of Histories of Rhetorics and
Rhetorics of History,” in Poulakos (ed.), pp. 193–240, 1993
Walbank, Frank William, “Political Morality and the Friends of Scipio,”
Journal of Roman Studies 55, no. 1/2, pp. 1–16, 1965
Wallace-Hadrill, Andrew, “Mutatio Morum: the Idea of a Cultural
Revolution,” in Habinek, & Schiesaro (eds.), pp. 3–22, 1997
Wallace-Hadrill, Andrew, Rome’s Cultural Revolution, Cambridge, 2008
Walters, Jonathan, “Invading the Roman Body: Manliness and
Impenetrability in Roman Thought,” in Hallett & Skinner (eds.), pp.
29–43, 1997
Walters, Jonathan, “Making a Spectacle: Deviant men, Invective, and
Pleasure,” Arethusa 31, pp. 355–367, 1998
Waters, K. H., Cicero, Sallust and Catiline,” Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte
Geschichte 19, pp. 195–215, 1970
Watts, N. H., Orations. Loeb Classical Library, London, 1923
Watts, N. H., Orations. Loeb Classical Library, London, 1931
Wikander, Örjan, Senators and Equites I-VIII, Opuscula Romana, Uppsala,
1991–2001
bibliography
359
Williams, Craig A., “Greek Love at Rome,” Classical Quarterly 45, pp.
517–539, 1995
Williams, Craig A., Roman Homosexuality, Oxford, 2010
Williamson, Callie, “The Roman Aristocracy and Positive Law,” Classical
Philology 85, pp. 266–276, 1990
Wilkins, A. S., The Orations of Cicero Against Catilina, London, 1950
Wirszubski, Chaim, ‘Libertas’ as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late
Republic and Early Principate, Cambridge, 1950
Wirszubski, Chaim, “Audaces: A Study in Political Phraseology,” Journal of
Roman Studies 51, pp. 12–22, 1961
Wiseman, T. P. (ed.), Roman Political Life 90 B.C-AD 69, Exeter, 1985
Wiseman, T. P., “Competition and Co-operation,” in Wiseman (ed.), pp.
3–19, 1985a
Wiseman, T. P., Remembering the Roman People: Essays on LateRepublican Politics and Literature, Oxford, 2009
Wisse, Jakob, Ethos and Pathos from Aristotle to Cicero, Amsterdam, 1989
Wistrand, Magnus, Entertainment and Violence in Ancient Rome: The
Attitudes of Roman Writers in the First Century A.D., Gothenburg,
1992
Wooten, Cecil W., Cicero’s Philippics and their Demosthenic Model: The
Rhetoric of Crisis, Chapel Hill, 1983
Wooten, Cecil W. (ed.), The Orator in Action & Theory in Greece & Rome:
Essays in Honor of George A. Kennedy, Leiden, 2001
Worman, Nancy, Abusive Mouths in Classical Athens, Cambridge, 2008
Worman, Nancy, “Fighting Words: Status, Stature, and Verbal Contest in
Archaic Poetry,” in Gunderson (ed.), pp. 27–42, 2009
Yakobson, Alexander, “Petitio et Largitio: Popular Participation in the
Centuriate Assembly of the Late Republic,” Journal of Roman Studies
82, pp. 32–52, 1992
Yakobson, Alexander, Elections and Electioneering in Rome: A Study of the
Political System of the Late Republic, Stuttgart, 1999
Yakobson, Alexander, “Popular Power in the Roman Republic,” in
Rosenstein & Morstein-Marx (eds.), pp. 383–400, 2006
Yavetz, Zvi, “The Failure of Catiline’s Conspiracy,” Historia: Zeitschrift für
Alte Geschichte 12, pp. 485–499, 1963
Yavetz, Zvi, Plebs and Princeps, London, 1969
Zetzel, James, Ten Speeches, Indianapolis, 2009
Index of Subjects
actors, as immoral, 277, 278, 279,
282, 284, 303, 305
adultery 154, 155, 179, 221, 224,
238, 265, 271, 273, 277, 278,
333, 354
amentia 148–150, 166, 183–187,
230, 263, 295, 332
amicitia 82, 84
animus 47, 102, 121, 122, 148,
187, 236, 277, 297
appearance 27, 60, 129–131, 162,
176, 206, 213, 228, 230–239,
241–243, 245, 247, 248, 250,
251, 271, 275, 281, 282, 293,
302, 305, 306, 316, 335
aristocratic competition 87, 88,
177, 286
auctoritas 81, 89, 107, 108, 112,
134, 169, 180, 238
audacia 120, 123, 128, 140, 141,
144, 145, 148, 151, 156, 166,
172, 176, 182–184, 186, 18,7
191, 192, 207, 222, 229, 230,
247, 295– 297, 301, 306, 317,
332, 333
avaritia 126, 128, 144–148, 150–
153, 166, 184, 194, 199, 216,
230, 277, 296, 298, 299, 332
Baiae 271, 272, 283
banquets, see feasts
beast, as pejorative, 15, 172, 301
Bona Dea 229, 239, 242, 262
boni, see vir bonus
Bourdieu, Pierre 176
brothels 277, 283, 284, 304
censor, censorship 79, 88
cinaedus 281
city, as immoral, 128, 130, 173,
196, 209, 241, 260, 293, 303,
333, 334
clientela 83, 84
clothes, see dress
company, immoral, 157, 192, 207,
209, 212, 217, 225, 230, 234,
270, 277–279, 303, 305, 306,
333
contio 80, 94, 170, 177, 182, 211,
226, 264, 276
convivium, see feasts
cultural logic 27, 33, 35, 44, 53, 70,
117, 160, 191, 198, 201, 203,
224, 225, 265, 284, 293, 297,
302, 309, 310, 313, 319, 320,
321, 324, 326, 329, 332, 334,
337
cultural turn 37
cupiditas 128, 145, 147, 148, 151–
153, 156, 161, 175, 184–187,
230, 296, 298, 299, 304, 332
cursus honorum 78, 79, 88, 116,
117, 131, 168, 169, 286
dancing 195, 197–199, 214, 224,
360
index of subjects
233, 251, 274, 275, 277, 278,
303, 332
danger, of immorality, 25, 158, 225,
228, 249, 256, 262, 268, 277,
280, 284, 311, 316–318, 331,
336, of greed, 152, connected
to conspiracy, 193, 211, 214,
226, of effeminacy, 217, 222,
223, 238, 245, 282, connected
to religion, 263, 300, of Clodia,
271, of lust, 298, 309, 318
debt 124, 157, 161, 192, 212, 276,
283
decorum 19, 77, 108, 165, 336
democracy 78, 84, 85, 87
dignitas 89, 90, 113
dress 60, 163, 213, 239, 241–245,
250, 251, 272, 278, 280, 282,
306, 326, 333, 334
drinking, as immoral, 15, 60, 164,
165, 198, 210, 211, 231, 232,
246, 266, 276, 279, 281, 292,
297, 299, 303, 305, 306, 311,
312, 315, 316, 321, 322, 333
education 96, 97, 102, 105, 188
effeminacy 15, 147, 162, 163, 213,
214, 217, 231, 233, 238–245,
251, 273, 275, 277, 278,
281–284, 293, 294, 300, 301,
304, 316–318, 333, 334
elite, deinition of, 86, 87
embeddedness 39, 43, 50, 64, 67,
272
ethos 26, 47, 67, 68, 72, 95, 96, 98,
108, 111–114, 117, 150, 177,
193, 265, 329
fama 89, 185, 190, 224
fas, see nefas
feasts, feasting 127, 129, 157, 163–
361
165, 197, 199, 208, 210, 213,
214, 219, 224, 228, 232, 233,
250, 261, 271, 272, 275–281,
283, 293, 294, 300, 303, 304,
315, 317, 321, 333, 334
lagitium 34, 46, 104, 120, 123,
126, 127, 136, 139, 143, 146,
148, 150, 152–154, 156, 162,
164, 166, 178, 179, 191, 195,
202, 203, 206, 214, 215, 219,
220, 230, 234, 242, 243, 263,
267, 274, 294, 300, 302, 304,
307, 308, 315, 318, 322, 332
Foucault, Michel 45, 56, 67, 158
frugality 125, 128, 163, 303, 330
furor 148–150, 182–184, 186, 187,
203, 204, 207, 211, 212, 229,
230, 247, 295, 297–299, 315,
319, 332
gambling 15, 157, 210, 211, 213,
303, 305, 312, 322
ganeo 208, 209, 232, 276, 303
Geertz, Clifford 37
gladiator, as pejorative, 15, 125,
127, 208, 288, 310
gloria 49, 89, 92, 112, 114–116,
222
gluttony 15, 60, 208, 209, 216, 228,
232, 233, 273, 276, 277, 283,
293, 316, 333
greed, see avaritia
Greeks, as immoral, 175, 176, 267,
280
Greenblatt, Stephen 37–41, 69
hair, hairstyle, as sign of immorality,
129, 213, 231–233, 236, 237,
246, 250, 251, 276, 280, 282,
306, 334
history, as moral, 74, 76
362
index of subjects
homosexuality 159, 195, 218
hostis 143, 178, 244, 258, 287, 290,
308, 320
house, household, as immoral, 15,
127, 129, 130, 133, 155, 165,
174, 176, 192, 246, 247, 270,
272, 273, 303–306, 308, 310,
311, 314, 316, 318, 322
Hunt, Lynn 23, 36, 41
immorality argument 28, 32, 53,
135, 139, 177, 287, 290, 292,
323–326, 328–331
improbitas 34, 46, 137, 139, 145,
148, 152, 160, 207, 212, 230,
294, 296, 297, 329, 332
impudentia 176, 248, 294, 296, 297
impudicitia, impudicus 210, 211,
213, 214, 254, 257–259, 261,
301, 307, 312, 314, 322
inertia 104, 159, 161, 210–212,
273, 304
incest 221, 239, 242, 256, 262, 263,
265, 274, 278, 283, 293, 300,
305, 313, 333
infamia, infames 208, 209, 222,
260, 261, 279, 282, 294, 309,
310
inimicitia 229, 289
invective 18, 26, 53, 57–64, 71,
102, 165, 177, 189, 190, 195,
221, 236, 246, 268, 290, 292,
293, 295, 308, 315, deinition
of, 57, 58, catalogue of, 60
law 53, 81, 94, 119, 138, 160, 162,
164, 175, 176, 220, 228, 229,
260, 263, 284, 314, 329, 331
leno, see pimps
lex Cornelia de repetundis 138
lex Iulia de adulteriis 218, 221
lex Iulia municipalis 261, 284
lex Plautia de vi 200
lex Scantinia 218
libertas 280
libido 137, 140, 144, 148, 153,
154, 156, 166, 185, 186, 191,
192, 197, 204, 205, 211, 212,
214, 222, 230, 235, 253–255,
267, 268, 270, 272, 274, 294,
298–301, 308, 315, 318, 322,
332
linguistic turn 36
logic of immorality 28, 158, 173,
198, 214, 222, 225, 254, 256,
258, 260, 261, 268, 269, 279,
284, 302, 324, 334–336
lust, see libido
luxuria, luxury 47, 104, 124–129,
133, 147, 150–152, 163–166,
184, 185, 195, 197–199, 211,
212, 216, 217, 222, 253, 257,
270, 271, 276, 277, 280, 283,
293, 303, 304, 333, 334
masculinity 25, 147, 161, 217, 222,
223, 228, 274
meretrices, see also prostitutes 155,
156, 261, 272, 273, 303, 308
mind world 27, 33, 252, 284, 328
Mommsen, Theodor 78, 82
monster, as pejorative, 241
mos/mores 45, 47, 48, 120, 130,
135, 154, 174, 176, 179, 181,
201, 205, 206, 226, 260, 300
mos maiorum 25, 78, 81, 147, 193,
229
natura 47, 48, 105, 120, 130, 148,
174, 176, 184, 200, 205, 300
nefas 239, 244, 263
index of subjects
New Cultural History 23, 36, 37,
39, 40
New Historicism 37, 39, 40, 56, 61
novus homo 69, 73, 115, 117
nudity 278, 303, 306, 321
oficia oratoris 101
oligarchy 59, 65, 84, 85, 87, 88
optimates 82, 229, 286
oral sex 265, 266
os impurum 249, 250, 266, 301,
305
parricide 117–119, 121, 123, 295
passivity 158, 159, 215, 217–219,
233, 244, 250, 252, 254, 260,
265, 267, 268, 275, 278,
281–284, 294, 300, 301, 333,
334, 336, 337
perfume 129, 210, 211, 233, 234,
238, 246, 276, 280, 282, 284,
321
persona 47, 48, 104, 134, 160, 173,
174, 176, 200
pimps 130, 155–157, 261, 277,
284, 305, 306, 315
political culture, deinition of,
50–52
political violence 76, 200, 228, 260,
265, 313
popularis 82, 228, 229, 242, 243,
249, 260, 316
praeco 127
probabile ex vita 123
prodigium 240, 244, 245
prosopography 83, 84
prostitutes, prostitution 15, 128,
155–157, 210, 211, 238, 241,
253, 255–257, 260–262 265,
272, 273, 277, 279, 280, 282,
303, 306, 308–311, 333
363
publication 48–50, 132, 181, 229,
290
pudicitia 67, 142, 143, 154–156,
158, 185, 186, 211, 214, 216,
217, 219, 223, 254, 257, 258,
262, 271, 272, 301, 307, 312,
315, 318, 335
pudor 129, 154, 155, 158, 185,
186, 206, 211, 216, 223, 241,
253, 258, 262, 273, 304, 305,
315, 335
quaestio perpetua 81
religion 42, 46, 53, 62, 79, 142,
143, 152, 204, 223, 243–245,
263, 265, 271, 314
reputation, see also fama 68, 89,
171, 175, 185, 190, 200, 205
rhetoric, disdain for, 19, 53, 54
rhetorical theory 55–57, 71, 99,
104, 112, 113
scurra 127, 128, 196, 255, 260,
265, 303
self-fashioning 67, 69, 117
self-policing, of the elite, 109, 111
sexual immorality 34, 153–155,
161, 164, 203, 209, 214, 215,
218, 220, 222, 225, 232, 233,
243, 252, 256, 261, 263, 264,
266, 278, 282–284, 300, 305,
315
shame 15, 34, 110, 125, 127, 192,
241, 249, 269, 294, 296, 322
signs of immorality 35, 141,
142, 170, 174, 176, 190, 194,
197–199, 206, 223, 245, 247,
273, 302, 306, 307, 330
Skinner, Quentin 40
slander 143, 190, 194–196, 198,
199, 214, 225, 249, 261, 309,
364
index of subjects
323, 324, 332, 337, as separated
from moral argument, 195–199,
224, 225, 258–260
slaves 46, 127, 149, 216, 260, 264,
267, 310, 320, 322
slavery, as threat, 319–321, 333
social hierarchies 107, 158, 309,
335
stuprum 151, 154, 155, 164, 202,
203, 205, 211, 216–225, 232,
233, 238, 241–244, 252, 262,
263, 265, 267, 274, 278, 283,
294, 300, 301, 307, 312, 313,
315, 333, deintion of, 218, 219
topoi 59, 97, 101, 102, 292, 326
tyrant, tyranny 15, 18, 60, 75, 93,
165–167, 226, 227, 239, 263,
264, 288, 293, 319–321
vir 89, 112, 158–161, 200, 208,
215–217, 222, 231, 238, 241,
244, 252–254, 256, 261, 264,
267, 273, 281–283, 300, 309,
311, 336
vir bonus 112, 123, 129, 182, 200,
208, 295
virtus, virtutes 65, 66, 89, 107, 109,
161, 167, 211, 222, 232, 268,
273, 311, 312
vituperatio 58, 100, 102, 103, 110,
122, 188, 242
voice, as sign of immorality, 128,
165, 241, 245, 282, 311
walk, as sign of immorality, 241,
246, 250, 251, 280, 282, 306
web of signiicance 37
web of immorality 41, 152, 198,
225, 252, 275, 276, 323, 332,
333
whores, see prostitutes
women, as immoral, 162, 185–187,
262, 263, 271, 273, 276, 298,
305
youth, immoral, 124, 125, 156,
157, 159, 163, 203, 204, 208,
209, 213–215, 217, 219, 225,
233, 247, 252–255, 257, 305,
307, 321, 337
Index of Names
This index includes the names of all ancient persons mentioned in the
book. For cited authors, see the Index Locorum. Romans are to be found
under their family name (nomen gentile). Persons more often referred
to by their surname (cognomen) are found by cross-reference under
that name. Moreover, the entries include the person’s number in the
Realencyclopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft (RE), their time
of life, highest held magistracy, relationship with other persons in the
index, if accused or defended by Cicero, and occasional other facts of
relevance. All dates are BCE.
Sextus Aebutius (RE 9). 160, 162,
244, 296
Gaius Aelius Paetus. See Staienus.
Statius Albius Oppianicus (RE 10).
Roman knight, stepfather of A.
Cluentius Habitus. 172–174,
176, 296, 306
Lucius Antonius (RE 23). Consul
41. Brother of the triumvir. 296,
299, 318
Marcus Antonius (RE 28).
143–87. Consul 99, censor 97.
Grandfather of the triumvir.
100, 109
Marcus Antonius (RE 30). Ca 82–
30. Consul 44, 34, 31, triumvir
rei publicae constituendae
43–33. 15–18, 20–22, 24, 27,
31, 38, 50, 74, 102, 103, 111,
183, 287–316, 318–322
Quintus Apronius (RE 5).
Henchman of Gaius Verres. 157,
162, 166, 266, 278, 305
Asclepiades (RE Asclepiades 16).
Witness against L. Valerius
Flaccus 59. 176
Marcus Atilius Bulbus (RE 34).
Senator. 174, 175
Atticus. See Pomponius.
Publius Autronius Paetus (RE 7).
Died after 58. Elected consul 66,
but accused and convicted de
ambitu. 205, 300
Avillius (RE 2). 214
Brutus. See Junius.
Lucius Caecilius Metellus (RE 72).
Died 221. Consul 251, 247. 90
Quintus Caecilius Metellus (RE 81).
Consul 206. 90
365
366
index of names
Marcus Caelius Rufus (RE 35).
Died 48. Praetor 48. Defended
by Cicero 56. 257, 259, 260,
271, 274, 276
Caesar. See Julius.
Lucius Calpurnius Piso Caesoninus
(RE 90). Died 43? Consul 58,
censor 50. Father-in-law of
Caesar the dictator. Accused by
Cicero 55. 229, 231, 233–237,
245, 246, 254, 266–271, 273,
276, 278, 280, 281, 293, 297,
299–301, 303, 304, 307, 316
Gaius Cassius Longinus (RE 59).
Ca 86–42. Praetor 44. One of
Caesar’s assassins. 289
Catilina. See Sergius.
Cato. See Porcius.
Chelidon (RE 1). Died before 70.
Mistress of Gaius Verres. 162,
305
Cicero. See Tullius.
Clodia (RE 66). Born ca 94. Sister
of P. Clodius Pulcher. 262–264,
266, 271, 276, 278, 305
Publius Clodius Pulcher (RE 48).
Died 52. Tribune 58. Accused by
Cicero 61. 183, 228, 229, 239–
245, 255–258, 260, 262–266,
269, 271, 273, 274, 278, 279,
281, 282, 293, 295, 300, 301,
304–307, 313, 316, 318
Sextus Cloelius (cf. Sex. Clodius RE
12). Henchman of P. Clodius
Pulcher. 266, 276, 305
Aulus Cluentius Habitus (RE
4). Born 103. Roman knight.
Defended by Cicero 66. 171,
176, 185, 201, 273
Lucius Cornelius Balbus (RE 69).
Consul 40. Defended by Cicero
56. 270
Lucius Cornelius Chrysogonus (RE
101). Freedman of Sulla the
dictator. 125–127, 129, 130,
133, 150, 163, 184, 193, 246,
270, 276, 293, 303–305
Publius Cornelius Dolabella (RE
141). 69–43. Consul 44. Cicero’s
son-in-law. 299, 305
Publius Cornelius Lentulus Sura
(RE 240). Consul 71. Adherent
of Catilina; executed 63. 204,
300
Publius Cornelius Scipio Aemilianus
Africanus (RE 335). Ca 185–
129. Consul 147, 134, censor
142. 165, 280
Lucius Cornelius Sulla Felix (RE
392). 138–78. Consul 88,
dictator 82–79. 76, 81, 116,
118, 126, 127
Publius Cornelius Sulla (RE 386).
Elected consul 66, but accused
and convicted de ambitu.
Defended by Cicero in 62. 200,
202, 206
Quintus Corniicius (RE 8). Died
42. Praetor ca 45. 287, 288
Curio. See Scribonius.
Gaius Erucius (RE 2). Prosecutor
in the trial of Sex. Roscius
Amerinus 80. 119–125, 154
Fabia (RE 172). Vestal virgin. Halfsister of Cicero’s wife Terentia.
189
index of names
Gaius Fannius Chaerea (RE 17).
Plaintiff in the trial of Q.
Roscius Gallus. 129, 130, 172,
236, 306
Marcus Fonteius (RE 12). Born ca
115. Preator ca 75, governor
of Gallia Narbonensis 74–72.
Defended by Cicero 69. 141,
142, 157
Aulus Gabinius (RE 11). Died 47.
Consul 58. 229, 231–234, 236–
238, 246, 251, 253, 254, 257,
261, 266, 270, 271, 273–278,
281, 282, 292, 293, 299, 304,
306, 307, 309, 316
Gellius Poplicola (RE 1).
Stepbrother of L. Marcius
Philippus (consul 56). Adherent
of P. Clodius Pulcher. 255, 276,
307, 316
Gracchus. See Sempronius.
Lucius Herennius (RE 9). Roman
tradesman from Leptis in Africa.
272
Hermagoras of Temnos (RE 8).
Greek rhetorician. 98, 104
Isocrates (RE 2). Greek rhetorician.
97
Gaius Julius Caesar (RE 131).
100–44. Consul 59, 48, 46–44,
dictator 49–44. 76, 286, 288,
289, 298, 320, 321
Gaius Julius Caesar Octavianus
(RE 132). Born 63. Consul 13
times 43–2, triumvir rei publicae
constituendae 43–33, the later
emperor Augustus. 289, 312
Lucius Junius Brutus (RE 46a).
Consul 509. According to
367
tradition the founder of the
Republic. 93
Marcus Junius Brutus (RE 53).
Ca 85–42. Praetor 44. One of
Caesar’s assassins. 289
Lucius Licinius Murena (RE
123). Born ca 105. Consul
62. Defended by Cicero 63.
193–196, 199, 200, 204, 214,
225, 257, 258
Quintus Manlius (RE 34). Died
before 66. Triumvir capitalis ca
77, tribune 69. 203
Gaius Marius (RE 14). Ca 158–86.
Consul 107, 104–100, 86. 76
Metellus. See Caecilius.
Murena. See Licinius.
Sextus Naevius (RE 6). Roman
tradesman, plaintiff in the trial
of P. Quinctius 81. 127–129,
150, 151, 270, 304
Oppianicus. See Albius.
Piso. See Calpurnius.
Gnaeus Pompeius Magnus (RE 31).
106–48. Consul 70, 55, 52. 286,
288
Gnaeus Pompeius Strabo (RE 45).
Died 87. Consul 89. Father of
the preceding. 116
Titus Pomponius Atticus (RE 102).
110–32. Roman knight, close
friend of Cicero. 181, 240
Marcus Porcius Cato Censorius
(Cato the Elder; RE 9). 234–
149. Consul 195, censor 184.
49, 112, 146
Marcus Porcius Cato Uticensis
(Cato the Younger; RE 16). 95–
46. Praetor 54. 193, 195–200,
214, 232, 303, 332
368
index of names
Publius Quinctius (RE 16). Roman
tradesman. Defended by Cicero
81. 127–129, 163
Sextus Roscius (RE 6). Landed
proprietor at Ameria, murdered
81. 117–119, 121, 145, 157, 295
Sextus Roscius (Amerinus; RE 7).
Son of the preceding. Defended
by Cicero 80. 116–121,
124–127, 131, 141, 145, 149,
151, 157, 163, 168, 174, 177,
206, 246, 295, 296
Titus Roscius Capito (RE 12).
Relative of the Sex. Roscii. 125,
126, 145, 296
Quintus Roscius Gallus (RE 16).
Died ca 63. Comedian actor,
later Roman knight. Defended
by Cicero 77. 129, 130
Titus Roscius Magnus (RE 18).
Relative of the Sex. Roscii. 125,
126, 145, 296
Sassia (RE 1). Mother of A.
Cluentius Habitus. 185–187,
273, 298
Scipio. See Cornelius.
Gaius Scribonius Curio (RE 10). Ca
125–53. Consul 76. 308
Gaius Scribonius Curio (RE 11). Ca
84–49. Tribune 50. Son of the
preceding. Accused by Cicero
61. 308
Tiberius Sempronius Gracchus (RE
54). Died 133. Tribune 133. 76
Lucius Sergius Catilina (RE 23). Ca
108–62. Preator 68. Accused
by Cicero 63. 17, 30, 169, 170,
177–193, 200, 202, 203, 205,
207–210, 212–217, 221–227,
232, 233, 239, 252, 258,
276–278, 281, 287, 292, 293,
295, 298, 300, 302, 304–307,
312, 313, 319
Publius Sestius (RE 6). Born ca
95. Tribune 57, praetor 54?
Defended by Cicero 56. 233,
246
Gaius Aelius Paetus Staienus (RE 1).
Ca 108–before 66. Quaestor 77.
Juror in the trial of Oppianicus
74. 173, 174, 176, 187, 201, 236
Sulla. See Cornelius.
Publius Sulpicius Galus (RE 68).
280
Lucius Tarquinius Superbus (RE 7).
The last Roman king; traditional
dates of reign 534–510. 75, 93,
166, 319, 320
Terentia (RE 95). First wife of
Cicero. 189
Theophrastus (RE 7). Greek
rhetorician. 98
Tongilius (RE 1). Adherent of
Catilina. 215, 216
Marcus Tullius Cicero (RE 29).
106–43. Consul 63. passim.
Quintus Tullius Cicero (RE 31). Ca
102–43. Praetor 62. Brother of
the preceding. 249, 277
Lucius Valerius Flaccus (RE
179). Died ca 53. Praetor 63.
Defended by Cicero 59. 175,
176, 194
Publius Vatinius (RE 3). Born ca 95.
Consul 47. Accused by Cicero
56. 245–250, 254, 266, 281,
282, 304, 307
index of names
Gaius Verres (RE 1). Ca 115–43.
Praetor 74, governor of Sicily
73–71. Accused by Cicero 70.
17, 81, 116, 131–140, 142–146,
148–159, 161–166, 168, 177,
179, 183, 184, 204, 212, 219,
226, 227, 232, 238, 239, 244,
252, 259, 261, 263, 266, 268,
269, 271, 273, 292, 293, 296,
298–306, 316–319, 329
Volumnia (RE 17). Actress, mistress
of M. Antonius. 305
369
Index Locorum
This index includes all cited passages from the speeches and works by
Cicero as well as passages cited and work mentioned by other ancient
authors. Abbreviations follow in general the Oxford Classical Dictionary
(4th ed.). I have retained all Roman names in their Latin form.
Cicero
Speeches
34–36 262
35 271
38 262, 272
42 273
44 276
45–47 274
47 262, 271
49 262, 272
50 272
53 260
54 258
55 273
57 273
78 266
Balb. (Pro Balbo)
56 270, 271
Caecin. (Pro Caecina)
1–2 296
4 160
14 160
23 160, 297
30 160, 297
Cael. (Pro Caelio) 257–260
6 196, 257, 259
8 259
10–11 252
11 253
12–14 184
15 185
16 260
22 258, 269
25 257
27 246
29 260
29–30 259
30 257–259
31 271
32 262
Cat. (In Catilinam) 49, 169, 170,
177–193, 207–217, 219–226, 252
1.1 182
1.2–3 178
1.4 182, 187
1.5 178
1.7 178
1.8 183, 186
1.11 212
1.12 178
1.13 190, 191, 302
370
index locorum
1.14
1.15
1.16
1.17
1.18
1.20
1.22
1.23
1.25
1.26
1.31
191
186
187, 208
186
178
212
186, 298
208
184, 208, 298
208, 223
186
2.1
2.4
2.5
2.6
2.7
2.8
2.9
2.10
2.11
2.12
2.13
2.19
2.22
2.25
2.28
182
215
184
178
208, 220
192, 214
222, 224
192, 210, 222
184, 304
208
182
212
213
184, 211
184
3.1 178
3.4 186
3.7 207
3.11 207
3.16 186, 207
3.17 208
3.23 184
3.25 207
3.27 186
3.28 207
4.11–12
207
Clu. (Pro Cluentio) 171–177,
185–187, 201, 231, 236
11 172
12 185
15 186
23 172, 186
371
26–27 172, 173
28 173
29 172, 183, 250
30 172
35 173
36 173, 214
39 203
41 250
41–42 172
42 172
43 172
44 172
46 173
48 172
49 172
59 173
64 172
68 193
68–72 174
70 174
72 223
78 174
97 175
159 174
170 172, 208
Deiot. (Pro rege Deiotaro)
26–28 195
Div. Caec. (Divinatio in Caecilium) 132
3 150
6 148, 151, 152
11 138
27 134
38 154
42 136
Dom. (De domo sua) 244
2 230
3 230
5 230
9 262
12 230
23 230, 271
25 230, 266, 276
26 266
40 230
372
index locorum
47 230, 266
49 260
50 262
60 230, 271, 275
72 230
80 230
83 266
91 230
92 263
104 266
105 263
106 230
107 230
115 230
115–116 230
124 277
125 230
126 230, 254
130 230
133 230
137 230
139 244
144 268
Flac. (Pro Flacco) 175–177, 246
9–12 175
12 174, 176
23 175
24–27 175
35 176
90 209
Font. (Pro Fonteio)
27 175
34 157
34–35 142
37 141
38 49
40 141
Har. resp. (De haruspicum responsis)
242
1 258
2 245, 274
4 230, 242, 263
5 230
8 230, 242, 263
10 230
11 230, 266
26 262
27 230
28–30 262
30 230
37 230
38 230, 263, 271
39 230, 264
42 230, 255
43 258
44 242, 246
45 230
48 230, 263
53 230
57 230
59 256
61 322
In Clod. (In Clodium et Curionem)
240–245
F5 241
F21 240
F22 241
F23 240
Leg. agr. (De lege agraria)
1.2 209
1.7 209
1.9 184
1.22 207
2.37
2.92
2.95
2.97
2.103
184
182
188
184
211
Mil. (Pro Milone) 49, 265
3 230
12 230
13 263
24 230
30 230
32 265
35 250
40 245
index locorum
42 109, 250, 296
55 244
72–73 265
73 230, 263
76 230, 268, 269
77 258
78 230
85 245, 263
87 263, 265
89 239, 283
Mur. (Pro Murena) 193–200, 214,
225, 232
11 195
13 195–197, 332
14 199
17 182
28 186
Phil. (Orationes Philippicae) 290–322
2.1 295
2.3 301
2.4 296
2.6 314
2.8 297
2.9 295
2.15 294, 296, 299, 301, 315
2.18 295
2.19 295–297
2.24 294
2.29–30 297
2.42 295
2.43 294
2.44 295, 306
2.44–45 294, 308
2.45 299
2.47 294, 301, 315
2.50 294, 316
2.57–58 294
2.58 305
2.61 305
2.63 294
2.65 297, 316
2.66 298
2.67 303
2.68 296, 301
2.69 304
373
2.70 301
2.71 299, 315
2.76 294, 306
2.77 301
2.81 297
2.81–82 296, 297
2.86 306, 321
2.85–87 320
2.87 319
2.90 295, 296, 319
2.96 319
2.97 298
2.99 294, 296, 301
2.105 299, 311
2.111 306
2.115 298, 299
2.117 298, 319
3.1 318
3.2 295
3.3 295
3.2–5 319
3.10 296, 318
3.12 301, 306, 320
3.13 295
3.15 301, 312
3.18 296
3.25 295, 298, 317
3.28 295, 296, 299, 301
3.28–29 320
3.30 315
3.31 295, 303
3.34 294
3.34–35 322
3.35 299
3.36 322
4.3 295, 319
4.11 320
4.15 295
5.10
5.16
5.20
5.21
5.22
5.24
295
294
301
320
297
297
374
index locorum
5.33
5.37
5.38
5.42
299, 315
295
320
295
6.4 298, 299, 301, 315
6.6–7 296
6.11 298
6.13 296
6.18 295
6.19 320
7.3–5 294
7.15 294
7.15–16 294
8.12
8.16
8.21
8.25
320
295
295
296
9.15
295
10.7 320
10.11 295
10.18 320
10.20 320
11.1 305
11.2 294, 305
11.5 305
11.6 295
11.7 305
11.8–9 319
11.9 295, 299
11.10 296, 305
11.37 295
12.13 301
12.15 295
12.15–16 322
13.10 295, 296, 299
13.14 313
13.17 294, 299, 320, 321
13.17–18 319
13.18 298
13.19
13.24
13.29
13.31
14.7
14.9
312
312
295
306, 320, 321
295, 296
294, 318
Pis. (In Pisonem) 235–237
1 235, 236, 307
12 230
13 246, 266, 275, 276
18 274, 275
20 266
21 230
22 195, 230, 276, 278, 279
25 231, 237
27 230
28 262
33 230
37 267
39 230
42 230, 267, 277
45 230
48 271
49 230
50 230
53 230
57 230
59 230, 267
62 230
66 268
67 270
68 252
68–69 254
69 268
70–71 230
71 278
72 230
78 230
82 274
86 230
88 274
89 230
93 245
95 263
index locorum
Planc. (Pro Plancio)
87 243, 244
Prov. cons. (De provinciis
consularibus) 268
6 268
8 230, 273
11 230, 276
14 230
16 230
24 258, 271
43 230
Q Rosc. (Pro Roscio comoedo) 129,
130, 231, 236
20 129
Quinct. (Pro Quinctio) 127–130
9 147
11 127
53 147
56 151
59 150, 163
79 151
83 147
88 151
92 128
93 129, 163
94 151
95 128
Rab. perd. (Pro Rabirio perduellionis
reo)
4 182
7–9 195
Red. pop. (Post reditum ad populum)
1 230
13 230, 271
20 227
Red. sen. (Post reditum in senatu)
231–235
11 230, 253, 262, 277
12 232, 261, 276
13 231, 232, 235, 275, 276
13–14 235, 271, 300
375
14 267
14–15 230
15 230, 267
19 230
25 230
Rosc. Am. (Pro Sexto Roscio
Amerino) 117–131
7 123
8 125
11 119
12 123, 151
17 123, 125
28 123
33 186
38 120, 157
39 124, 161, 163, 299
52 163
62 149, 183
67 149
68 125, 207
70–71 118
75 125, 128, 151, 297
88 123
95–96 123
101 147
104 123
117 136
118 126, 296
122 126
134 127, 164, 165, 276
135 129, 246
150 150
Scaur. (Pro Scauro)
6 257
8 273
15 269
19 269
Sest. (Pro Sestio)
16 230, 274
17 236, 246
18 233, 253
19 235
20 230, 238, 254, 273, 277
21–22 235
376
index locorum
22
23
24
26
36
38
39
73
93
96
100
110
111
112
116
133
134
138
230, 237, 273
267
246, 269, 270, 273
261, 262, 277
230
230
260, 265
258
230, 277
229
123
255
276
230, 295
262, 278
255
248
230
Sull. (Pro Sulla) 200–207, 251
17 186, 298
69 200
70 202, 307
71 204, 205
74 206
75 203, 206
76 207
77 206
79 201
Tog. cand. (In toga candida)
F10 220
F18 189
F19 221
Tull. (Pro Tullio)
8–9 147
46 147
Vat. (In Vatinium) 246–250
1 247
2 247
4 248
5 248
7 247
9 248
10 248
11
13
17
30
32
39
247, 254, 307
249
247
245
254, 255
249
Verr. (In Verrem) 131–168
1.2 136
1.13 148
1.14 154, 155, 219
1.35 136
1.36 137
1.42 152
1.47 136
1.50 137
1.56 138, 300
2.1.7 150
2.1.9 142, 155, 156
2.1.22 139
2.1.32–33 156
2.1.34 139, 212
2.1.41 139
2.1.48 152
2.1.58 148
2.1.62–63 139
2.1.62 153–155, 158, 219
2.1.63 154
2.1.64 219
2.1.65 153
2.1.66–70 164
2.1.68 154, 158
2.1.72 137
2.1.74 137
2.1.76 148, 154
2.1.78 154, 156
2.1.82 139, 166
2.1.86 148, 153
2.1.87 145
2.1.94 148
2.1.101 139, 156, 261
2.1.111 137
2.1.122 166
2.1.140 162
2.1.153 137
2.1.154 146, 151
index locorum
2.2.2 139, 146
2.2.9 150, 166
2.2.16 156
2.2.17 145
2.2.18 137
2.2.36 148
2.2.40 154
2.2.42 137, 148
2.2.50 137
2.2.68 137
2.2.78 139
2.2.82 151, 219
2.2.84 146
2.2.97 148, 152
2.2.110 219
2.2.114 146
2.2.119 135
2.2.134 139, 146, 154
2.2.135 154
2.2.136 148
2.2.174 136
2.2.192 139, 153, 159
2.3.1–4 134
2.3.5 140, 302
2.3.6 141, 155, 261
2.3.8 154, 161
2.3.22 151
2.3.23 135, 139, 162, 252, 266
2.3.24 278
2.3.24–25 166
2.3.30 139
2.3.31 162, 166
2.3.40 146
2.3.60 153, 154, 157
2.3.65 162
2.3.76–77 166
2.3.84 139, 146
2.3.97 137
2.3.111 145
2.3.115 166
2.3.122 137
2.3.126 150
2.3.146 136
2.3.151 146
2.3.152 145, 147, 152, 183
2.3.160–161 164
2.3.161
2.3.187
2.3.195
2.3.207
2.3.217
2.3.221
377
139
139, 148
137
139
139
152
2.4.6 261
2.4.18 154
2.4.20 155, 219
2.4.34 148
2.4.38 148, 150
2.4.39 148
2.4.41 154
2.4.49 137
2.4.51 166
2.4.60 143, 147
2.4.68 147
2.4.71 164, 261
2.4.72 219
2.4.75 148
2.4.78 151
2.4.81 167
2.4.83 146, 156, 165, 219
2.4.90 161
2.4.99 148
2.4.102 219
2.4.112 153, 300
2.4.115 153
2.4.123 166
2.4.139 137, 139
2.4.144 155
2.4.151 139
2.5.4 143
2.5.11 146
2.5.13 136
2.5.26 164, 219
2.5.27 163
2.5.27–28 164
2.5.28 158, 164
2.5.30 164, 252
2.5.30–31 165
2.5.31 163
2.5.32 152, 162
2.5.33 157
2.5.34 155, 158, 162, 263
378
index locorum
2.5.39 156, 273
2.5.40 161, 163
2.5.42 150
2.5.63 165
2.5.65 136, 141
2.5.80–83 154
2.5.83 165
2.5.85 156
2.5.86 139, 163, 164
2.5.87 165
2.5.91 148
2.5.92 164
2.5.94 139, 165, 232, 238
2.5.103 166
2.5.104 162
2.5.107 162
2.5.113 151
2.5.115 137
2.5.116 137
2.5.121 150
2.5.122 146
2.5.137 152, 163, 164, 252
2.5.139 149
2.5.160 139
2.5.189 144, 151
Other Works
Att. (Epistulae ad Atticum)
1.12–14 239
1.13.5 49
1.16.8 239, 240
1.18.3 229, 239
2.1 181
2.1.3 50
2.9.2 249
4.2.2 50
4.3 229
4.7 229
10.10 305
10.16 305
15.22 305
Brut. (Brutus) 97
23 112
53 93
60 49
91 49
129 49
312 131
De or. (De oratore)
1.128 96
1.194 89
1.202 110
2.32 98
2.35 109
2.43–51 100
2.46 102
2.116 258
2.178 114
2.182 113, 114
2.184 69, 112
2.209 114
2.237 110
2.242 325
2.266 231
2.334 89
2.347 89
2.349 103
3 97
Fam. (Epistulae ad familiares)
9.12.2 49
12.22 287, 288
Fin. (De inibus)
2.27 155
Inv. rhet. (De inventione rhetorica)
98–102
1.2 98
1.6 98
1.22 104
1.27 105
1.32 147, 151
1.34 105
1.35 47, 105
1.36 105
2.28 106
2.32 106, 129
2.33 121, 122
2.34 106
index locorum
2.35–36 106
2.36 206
2.42 106
2.50 202
Leg. (De legibus) 110
1.43 155
3.7 70
3.30–32 110
Off. (De oficiis)
1.128 155
1.129 250
1.150 279
2.49–51 134
2.51 19
Orat. (Orator ad M. Brutum)
37 100
59 274
128 48
379
Part. or. (Partitiones oratoriae) 188
48–49 258
69–70 109
69–97 102
71 114
71–73 103
82 188
Q Fr. (Epistulae ad Quintum fratrem)
2.1 229
2.1.11 50
2.3 229
2.4.1 249
Rep. (De re publica)
1.2 90
3.4 110
4.10 279
5.1 107
Top. (Topica)
73 107
78 108
Other Ancient Authors
M. Antonius
De ratione dicendi 98
App. (Appianos)
B Civ. (Bella civila)
4.19–20 291
Apul. (Apuleius)
Apol. (Apologia)
74–75 254
Arist. (Aristoteles) 68
Rhet. (Rhetoric) 47, 97–99, 112–114
1.2. 258
1.9 102
1.2.4 112
1.15 258
Asc. (Asconius)
Mil. (Pro Milone)
41.9–42.4 49
Tog. cand. (In toga candida)
91.19–23C 189
Ps. Asc. (Pseudo-Asconius)
In Verrem
205 132
223 132
Auctor ad Herennium 101
Rhet. Her. (Rhetorica ad Herennium)
98–104
1.3 98
1.8 104, 273
380
index locorum
1.13 105
2.5 122
2.24 105
2.25 105
3.11 102, 103
3.15 100, 103
Catull. (Catullus)
29.2 214
106 127
Justin. Justinianus
Inst. (Institutiones)
4.18.6 118
Q. Cicero
Comment. pet. (Commentariolum
petitionis)
10 277, 278
16 118
Dig. (Digesta)
3.1.1 284
48.9.9 118
Festus (ed. Lindsay)
418.8–18 218
Gell. (Gellius)
NA (Noctes Atticae)
3.1 277
6.12.5 280
11.2 147
13.16.1 80
15.28 117
18.9.1 147
Juv. (Juvenalis)
10.125 291
Liv. (Livius)
1. Praef. 2. 147
Praef. 6–13 74
4.8.2 79
34.4.1–2 147
39.8.6–7 232
Ov. (Ovidius)
Ars am. (Ars amatoria)
3.433–434 233
3.767–768 276
Platon 97, 112
Gorgias 98
Phaedrus 54, 98
Plaut. (Plautus) 130
Capt. (Captivi)
2.2.287 151
Curc. (Curculio)
35–38 219
Truc. (Truculentus)
2.2.35 237
Plin. (Plinius the Elder)
H.N. (Naturalis historia)
7.130 107
7.139–140 90
Plin. (Plinius the Younger)
Ep. (Epistulae)
20.6–8 49
L. Plotius Gallus
De gestu 98
Plut. (Plutarchos)
Ant. (Antonius)
17 290
Cic. (Cicero)
3 119
3.6 131
29–34 229
48 291
Pol. (Polybios) 84
6 78
6.2. 77
6.9–10 78
6.14.10 80
6.52 87, 88
31.25 280
index locorum
Quint. (Quintilianus)
Inst. (Intitutio oratoria)
2.17.21 171
3.7.2 102, 241, 242
4.2.69 218
5.10.28 121
6.2.8 48
10.112 19
11.1.84 266
12.6.4 117
Sall. (Sallustius) 44
Cat. (Bellum Catilinae) 179
1.1 283
2.8 283
3 187
4 179
5 187
5.8 147
6 184
10 76
10.4 147
11.3 147, 277
12.2 216
13.3 216
14.2 214
Iug. (Bellum Iugurthinum)
41 76
41.9 147
Sen. (Seneca the Elder)
Controv. (Controversiae)
1.praef. 8–9 251, 275
1.praef. 10 274
Sen. (Seneca the Younger) 44
Dial. (Dialogi)
1.6.1 148
2.17.3 274
7.7 284
Ep. (Epistulae)
5.1.2 251
51 271
52.12 250
60.4 283
122.7 251
Q Nat. (Quaestiones naturales)
7.31 282
Tac. (Tacitus)
Ann. (Annales)
11.2 252
Dial. (Dialogus de oratoribus)
36 92
Val. Max (Valerius Maximus) 44
4.1 149
4.2.5 239
4.3.pr. 149
6.1 219
7.7.7 277
8.5.5 239
9.1.7 239
Vell. (Velleius Paterculus)
2.45 229
2.64 291
2.69.3 248, 249
381
Denna avhandling är tillkommen inom ramen för Forskarskolan i historia.
Forskarskolan i historia är en av de nationella forskarskolor som tillkom på
regeringens initiativ hösten 2000. Forskarskolan genomförs i samarbete mellan
Lunds universitet, Linnéuniversitetet samt Malmö och Södertörns högskolor med
Lunds universitet som värdhögskola. Från och med hösten 2011 ingår även
Göteborgs universitet i samarbetet.
Doktorsavhandlingar från
Forskarskolan i historia:
Stefan Persson, Kungamakt och bonderätt. Om danska kungar och bönder i riket
och i Göinge härad ca 1525–1640, Makadam förlag, Göteborg 2005
Sara Edenheim, Begärets lagar. Moderna statliga utredningar och heteronormativitetens genealogi, Symposion, Eslöv 2005
Mikael Tossavainen, Heroes and Victims. The Holocaust in Israeli Historical
Consciousness, Department of History, Lund 2006
Henrik Rosengren, “Judarnas Wagner”. Moses Pergament och den kulturella
identiikationens dilemma omkring 1920–1950, Sekel Bokförlag, Lund 2007
Victor Lundberg, Folket, yxan och orättvisans rot. Betydelsebildning kring demokrati i den svenska rösträttsrörelsens diskursgemenskap, 1887–1902, Bokförlaget
h:ström – Text och Kultur, Umeå 2007
Tommy Gustafsson, En iende till civilisationen. Manlighet, genusrelationer, sexualitet och rasstereotyper i svensk ilmkultur under 1920-talet, Sekel Bokförlag,
Lund 2007
Jesper Johansson, ”Så gör vi inte här i Sverige. Vi brukar göra så här”. Retorik
och praktik i LO:s invandrarpolitik 1945–1981, Växjö University Press, Växjö
2008
Christina Jansson, Maktfyllda möten i medicinska rum. Debatt, kunskap och
praktik i svensk förlossningsvård 1960–1985, Sekel Bokförlag, Lund 2008
Anne Hedén, Röd stjärna över Sverige. Folkrepubliken Kina som resurs i den
svenska vänsterradikaliseringen under 1960- och 1970-talen, Sekel Bokförlag,
Lund 2008
Cecilia Riving, Icke som en annan människa. Psykisk sjukdom i mötet mellan
psykiatrin och lokalsamhället under 1800-talets andra hälft, Gidlund, Hedemora
2008
Magnus Olofsson, Tullbergska rörelsen. Striden om den skånska frälsejorden
1867–1869, Sekel Bokförlag, Lund 2008
Johan Östling, Nazismens sensmoral. Svenska erfarenheter i andra världskrigets
efterdyning, Atlantis, Stockholm 2008
Christian Widholm, Iscensättandet av Solskensolympiaden – Dagspressens konstruktion av föreställda gemenskaper vid Stockholmsolympiaden 1912, Bokförlaget h:ström – Text och Kultur, Umeå 2008
Ainur Elmgren, Den allrakäraste ienden. Svenska stereotyper i inländsk press
1918–1939, Sekel Bokförlag, Lund 2008
Andrés Brink Pinto, Med Lenin på byrån. Normer kring klass, genus och sexualitet i den svenska kommunistiska rörelsen 1921–1939, Pluribus, Lund 2008
Helena Tolvhed, Nationen på spel. Kropp, kön och svenskhet i populärpressens
representationer av olympiska spel 1948–1972, Bokförlaget h:ström – Text och
Kultur, Umeå 2008
Lennart Karlsson, Arbetarrörelsen, Folkets hus och offentligheten i Bromölla
1905–1960, Växjö University Press, Växjö 2009
Stefan Nyzell, ”Striden ägde rum i Malmö”. Möllevångskravallerna 1926. En studie av politiskt våld i mellankrigstidens Sverige, Malmö högskola, Malmö 2009
Louise Sebro, Mellem afrikaner og kreol. Etnisk identitet og social navigation i
Dansk Vestindien 1730–1770, Historiska institutionen, Lund 2010
Simon Larsson, Intelligensaristokrater och arkivmartyrer. Normerna för vetenskaplig skicklighet i svensk historieforskning 1900–1945, Gidlund, Hedemora
2010
Vanja Lozic, I historiekanons skugga. Historieämne och identiikationsformering
i 2000-talets mångkulturella samhälle, Malmö högskola, Malmö 2010
Marie Eriksson, Makar emellan. Äktenskaplig oenighet och våld på kyrkliga och
politiska arenor, 1810-1880, Linnaeus University Press, Växjö 2010
Anna Hedtjärn Wester, Män i kostym. Prinsar, konstnärer och tegelbärare vid
sekelskiftet 1900, Nordiska museets förlag, Stockholm 2010
Malin Gregersen, Fostrande förpliktelser. Representationer av ett missionsuppdrag i
Sydindien under 1900-talets första hälft, Historiska institutionen, Lund 2010
Magnus Linnarsson, Postgång på växlande villkor. Det svenska postväsendets organisation under stormaktstiden, Nordic Academic Press, Lund 2010
Johanna Ringarp, Professionens problematik. Lärarkårens kommunalisering och
välfärdsstatens förvandling, Makadam förlag, Göteborg 2011
Carolina Jonsson Malm, Att plantera ett barn. Internationella adoptioner och assisterad befruktning i svensk reproduktionspolitik, Lunds universitet, Lund 2011
Fredrik Håkansson, Standing up to a Multinational Giant. The Saint-Gobain
World Council and the American Window Glass Workers’ Strike in the American
Saint Gobain Corporation in 1969, Linnaeus University Press, Växjö, Kalmar
2011
Christina Douglas, Kärlek per korrespondens. Två förlovade par under andra
hälften av 1800-talet, Carlssons, Stockholm 2011
Martin Kjellgren, Taming the Prophets. Astrology, Orthodoxy and the Word of
God in Early Modern Sweden, Sekel Bokförlag, Lund 2011
Anna Rosengren, Åldrandet och språket. En språkhistorisk analys av hög ålder
och åldrande i Sverige cirka 1875-1975, Södertörns högskola, Huddinge 2011
Åsa Bengtsson, Nyktra kvinnor. Folkbildare och politiska aktörer. Vita bandet
1900–1930, Makadam förlag, Göteborg 2011
Anna Nilsson, Lyckans betydelse. Sekularisering, sensibilisering och individualisering i svenska skillingtryck 1750–1850, Agerings bokförlag, Höör 2012
Anna Alm, Upplevelsens poetik. Slöjdseminariet på Nääs 1880–1940, Historiska
institutionen, Lund 2012
Rasmus Fleischer, Musikens politiska ekonomi. Lagstiftningen, ljudmedierna och
försvaret av den levande musiken, 1925–2000, Ink bokförlag, Stockholm 2012
Andreas Tullberg, ”We are in the Congo now”. Sweden and the Trinity of Peacekeeping during the Congo Crisis 1960–1964, Lunds universitet, Lund 2012
Matilda Svensson, När något blir annorlunda. Skötsamhet och funktionsförmåga
i berättelser om poliosjukdom, Lunds universitet, Lund 2012
Peter K. Andersson, Streetlife in Late Victorian London. The Constable and the
Crowd, Lund University, Lund 2012
Mikael Häll, Skogsrået, näcken och Djävulen. Erotiska naturväsen och demonisk
sexualitet i 1600- och 1700-talens Sverige, Malört förlag, Stockholm 2013
Johan Stenfeldt, Dystopiernas seger. Totalitarism som orienteringspunkt i efterkrigstidens svenska idédebatt, Agerings bokförlag, Höör 2013
Maria Nyman, Resandets gränser. Svenska resenärers skildringar av Ryssland under 1700-talet, Södertörns högskola, Huddinge 2013
Kajsa Brilkman, Undersåten som förstod. Den svenska reformatoriska samtalsordningen och den tidigmoderna integrationsprocessen, Artos, Skellefteå 2013