Academia.eduAcademia.edu

New Philosophies of Film: Thinking Images

2011

The relationship between film and philosophy has become a topic of intense intellectual interest. But how should we understand this relationship? Can philosophy renew our understanding of film? Can film challenge or even transform how we understand philosophy? New Philosophies of Film explores these questions in relation to both analytic and Continental philosophies of film, arguing that the best way to overcome the mutual antagonism between these approaches is by constructing a more pluralist film-philosophy grounded in detailed engagement with particular films and filmmakers. Sinnerbrink not only provides lucid critical analyses of the exciting developments and contentious debates in the new philosophies of film, but also showcases how a pluralist film-philosophy works in the case of three challenging contemporary filmmakers: Terrence Malick, David Lynch, and Lars von Trier. Table of Contents Preface \ Introduction: Why Did Philosophy Go To The Movies? \ Part I: The Analytic-Cognitivist Turn \ 1. The Empire Strikes Back: Critiques of “Grand Theory" \ 2. The Rules of the Game: New Ontologies of Film \ 3. Adaptation: Philosophical Approaches to Narrative \ Part II: From Cognitivism to Film Philosophy \ 4. Cognitivism Goes to the Movies \ 5. Bande à part: Deleuze and Cavell as Film-Philosophers \ 6. Scenes from a Marriage: Film as Philosophy \ Part III: Cinematic Thinking \ 7. Hollywood in Trouble: David Lynch’s INLAND EMPIRE \ 8. ‘Chaos Reigns’: Anti-cognitivism in Lars von Trier’s Antichrist \ 9. Song of the Earth: Cinematic Romanticism in Malick’s The New World \ Coda: ‘The Six Most Beautiful Minutes in the History of Cinema’\ Bibliography \ Filmography \ Index. Reviews: Reviewed by Jason M. Wirth in Notre Dame Philosophy Reviews (November 2012): http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/35702-new-philosophies-of-film-thinking-images/ Reviewed by Deborah Knight in The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, vol 70, no. 4 (Fall 2012): 401-403. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1540-6245.2012.01531_5.x/abstract [DOI: 10.1111/j.1540-6245.2012.01531_5.x] Reviewed by Adam Melinn in Philosophy in Review, vol. 32, no. 5 (2012): 428-430 http://journals.uvic.ca/index.php/pir/article/view/11591 Reviewed by Jane Stadler in the British Journal of Aesthetics: http://bjaesthetics.oxfordjournals.org/content/early/2012/07/31/aesthj.ays025.extract" "Both an excellent introduction and an original contribution to the field, New Philosophies of Film: Thinking Images covers a large range of theoretical positions with impressive adroitness. By offering incisive philosophical analyses alongside brilliant film readings, Sinnerbrink achieves that rare thing, a true marriage of the abstract and the concrete that will be of huge value to scholars and students alike." Professor John Mullarkey, Kingston University, London, UK "Robert Sinnerbrink’s New Philosophies of Film is a captivating, challenging, smart, and highly readable exploration of the aesthetic encounter between cinema and philosophy. As an introduction to the recent philosophical turn in film studies, the book offers a rich and insightful critical perspective on many influential developments in film theory such as cognitivism. As a contribution to the emerging field of philosophical engagement with film New Philosophies of Film shows that films can do more than just illustrate or serve as metaphors for philosophical ideas. Films are philosophically valuable in themselves insofar as they can engage in philosophizing as ‘thinking agents’. Furthermore, films can invite us to invest in them philosophically, to meet them in dialogue as philosophical discussion partners. This idea comes alive in Sinnerbrink’s exceptionally vivid examples, in which he analyzes the philosophical-aesthetic receptivity to the work of such filmmakers such as David Lynch, Lars von Trier and Terrence Malick. This book is a ‘must read’ not only for philosophers and film scholars, but also for anyone seriously enthusiastic about cinema." Tarja Laine, Assistant Professor, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands. "New Philosophies of Film is an ambitious attempt to overcome the Analytic-Continental divide in theorizing about film and to develop a new understanding of the relationship between film and philosophy. Beginning with a critical overview of recent developments in the philosophy of film and ending with interpretations that present film as a new mode of thinking, this book breaks new ground and will have to be reckoned with by anyone interested in film and philosophy." Thomas E Wartenberg, Professor of Philosophy, Mount Holyoke College, Massachusetts, USA."""

Philosophy in Review XXXII (2012), no. 5 Robert Sinnerbrink New Philosophies of Film: Thinking Images. New York: Continuum 2011. 264 pages $100.00 (cloth ISBN 978–1–4411–2257–5) The most commonly occurring questions within the contemporary philosophy of film are questions that challenge our approach to the discipline itself. Is the philosophy of film a subdivision of aesthetics or a unique field of study? Can cinema be presented as a form of analytic argumentation or is it primarily a narrative art? Should philosophical films be treated as thought experiments, allegorical examples or as primary source documents? Getting down to the real work of evaluating arguments is too often delayed by detours of rationalization, needlessly expending effort on justifying the process itself as having sufficient merit to our field. It is possible to engage in critical readings of philosophical films without continuously retracing the questions of what narrative is, what cinema is or even what the role of philosophy is in the twenty-first century. Robert Sinnerbrink’s approach presents a comfortable balance between the post-modern concern of ‘what is the philosophy of film’ and a more direct deconstruction of the pictures themselves. By applying the term ‘new wave’ to contemporary film theory Sinnerbrink attempts to replace the last century's psychoanalytic, continental approach with a newly configured “analytic-cognitivist paradigm”. The romantic aesthetics of cornerstone works such as Bazin’s Ontology of Film are supplanted here by the rationalist film-philosophies of Stanley Cavell and Gilles Deleuze. The book advocates a changing of the guard and Cavell and Deleuze are given the status of being figureheads for this ideological shift. New Philosophies of Film is primarily an explanation and assessment of current trends in the discipline, with the author’s own argumentative claims only peeking through occasionally. Clearly the author has aligned himself with Cavell, and in defending Cavell’s positions he is also working to define his own. Overall, the book seems to be suggesting that Cavell and Deleuze represent a new and more suitably broad approach to film-philosophy that includes narrative, aesthetic imagery, context, pedagogy, and metaphorical argumentation as necessary conditions. In addition to this, Sinnerbrink wants to enhance the element of communication between the mediums of cinema and philosophy. This means more than simply increasing the dialogue between experts in these two fields of study or creating new spaces for greater interdisciplinary crossover. The real goal of his project is to “allow film to communicate with philosophy in more aesthetically receptive ways... open up new ways of thinking with film, and thus help ameliorate philosophy’s traditional disenfranchisement with art.” (7) The book is structured very formally and with attention to process. Each chapter begins with an outline of what points will be made and how historically relevant examples (from both philosophers and filmmakers) will fit into those points. Within each section, many film references are utilized, sometimes even going so far as to describe the characters and restate the basic story lines. This approach comes to its pinnacle in the final section of the text, which is a 428 Philosophy in Review XXXII (2012), no. 5 detailed discussion of three films Sinnerbrink has selected as representing important examples of his film-philosophy. David Lynch’s Inland Empire, Lars Von Trier’s Antichrist, and Terrence Malick’s The New World are the features chosen for an in-depth evaluation. Sinnerbrink suggests that there is a sort of ethical purpose in his selection of non-mainstream, marginal art films. For these three examples, however, he does not explain what that ethical purpose is or how these specific choices are supported by that purpose. David Lynch’s films have always been a favorite for philosophical discussion. The exploration of Inland Empire contextualizes this terribly complex film as a thoughtful critique of the Hollywood industrial system. While this may be an important part of Lynch’s intended statement, it is not clear why the question of Hollywood’s disassociation from the European cinematic tradition would be an issue for contemporary philosophy. The deconstruction of Von Trier’s Antichrist provides a better example. Here the conversation manages to include elements of Aristotelian categorization, Freudian guilt and general questions concerning human responses to horror. Although this may not be the best archetype to utilize for a conversation about the genre of horror (the question of whether the film is a work of horror or something more along the lines of a classic tragedy is covered), it does allow Sinnerbrink to take some critical shots at Noël Carroll while also bringing the philosophies of Cynthia Freeland and Carl Plantinga to the conversation. The film serves as an excellent example of the book’s claims that viewers can be ‘shocked to thought’ and that exposure to such powerful imagery can serve as a unifying experience, aligning the audience against the growing nihilism and isolating subjectivity of the world. The third and final case study here is of Terrence Malick’s The New World. In a book that owes as much to Stanley Cavell as this one does, selecting a work by Malick (who studied under Cavell at Harvard) is an interesting move. This choice raises some important questions. Do the qualifications or the intentions of a filmmaker change the status of the work? Are Malick’s films more worthy of attention in this context merely because he can be labeled as a philosopher in the traditional, scholastic sense? These aesthetic issues are raised earlier in the book during a brief debate concerning Paisley Livingston’s intentionalist account. The author builds a strong argument against Livingston’s position that such films are little more than illustrations of pre-existing philosophical ideas and that therefore they do not really contribute to the growth of philosophical knowledge. After all, plenty of contemporary philosophy is guilty of the same offense—presenting new ways of illustrating pre-existing ideas. It is in a section of chapter six, titled Scenes from a Marriage: On the Idea of Film as Philosophy, that Sinnerbrink reveals his most direct argumentation. The New World itself is treated as a paradigm of the symbiotic unfurling of art and philosophical thought, symmetrically and subtly intertwined. Sinnerbrink writes, “the film enacts a kind of cinematic thinking that invites philosophical and aesthetic responses, while articulating a kind of thinking that resists translation into a ready-made thesis, position or argument.” (181) The problem with this claim is that while it does express the romantic enticement of thought provoking cinema, it does not give any hint as to what particular philosophical thoughts might be provoked by this particular film. Without specifying what the 429 Philosophy in Review XXXII (2012), no. 5 audience is being asked to think about, all that is really being stated is that this film ‘makes you think’, which may be true but does not explain why special attention is being given to this picture. This is not a shortcoming of New Philosophies of Film, it is its central idea exemplified. The process this book presents is not about analyzing the content or meaning of the images, or even of the stories themselves. Sinnerbrink’s idea is actually to take a deeper look at our engagement with films as both works of art and as experiences to reflect upon. Philosophy ought to be a social activity, not a private academic pursuit. If this is the case, then exposing groups of people to common images and narratives which aim to promote skeptical thoughts, aesthetic experiences or critical curiosity can only be a positive contribution to the way we practice philosophy. Adam Melinn Philadelphia University 430