December, 2020
The organism of behavior
A.P. Rabanal †
Behavior analysis relies on the idea of a science dealing with specific interactions between
the organism and its environment. Yet it is not always clearly defined what does
“organism” mean. It does not even seem to be an agreement on it within biologists beyond
the idea of a physically sustained and self-maintaining entity (Ruiz-Mirazo, Etxeberria,
Moreno and Ibáñez, 2000). While a technical and foundational concept of “organism” may
be sought in biology, whether or not it is of psychological interest is another issue. This is
not to deny species-intrinsic traits nor the role of neurobiological mechanisms, but to
stress that adaptative behavior is best exemplified in situationally-bounded organisms.
Within the behavioral community positions vary from those who accept organismal
variables (e.g. Donahoe and Palmer, 2004) to those who propose not considering them at
all (e.g. Roche and Barnes, 1997). I will contend that disagreements arise from the roles
the organism is said to have in behavioral settings. I will also argue for the organismal
level as appropriate for explaining behavior in an attempt to reconcile physiology with
behavior analysis through a selectionist approach.
Levels and Organization
Living systems are hierarchically structured in a set of successive organization levels from
the genome to the individual (Salomon, Berg and Martin, 2008) with elements belonging
to intermediate levels between genes and cells (e.g. proteomes or transcriptomes) or
between populations and ecosystems (e.g. communities) (Pavé, 2006). Biological
complexity is one of downward organization and should be explained in terms of both
reduction and integration. Bunge and Mahner (1997) propose the following composition
criteria of biological levels:
L1 = Elemental cellular level def= set of every elemental cell
L2 = Compound cellular level def= set of every compound cell
L3 = Organal level def= set of every (multicellular) organ
L4 = Multicellular organismic level def= set of every multicellular organism
L5 = Population level def= set of every biopopulation
L6 = Community level def= set of every community (or biocenosis)
L7 = Biosphere level def= set of every biosphere
1
December, 2020
Non-living elements encompass oxygen, water, soil, or minerals with factors to consider
such as spatial (resource distribution or physical geography) and temporal restraints
(circadian rhythms, lunar cycles, or seasonal changes). MacMahon, Phillips, Robinson and
Schimpf (1978) indicate that biological complexity culminates with the organism as an
ecological unit as levels not containing living systems are not properly biological. Levels
can be then taken as clusters:
L1 = Cellular level
L2 = Organismal level
L3 = Population level
L4 = Community level
L5 = Ecosystem level
Levels are sets and hence conceptual in nature. Conversely their components are
collections of living things from cells up to organs. We can further complement this
classification with a functional criterion. As basic units of life, cells are characterized by
their morphology and metabolism. Ensembled or associated cells with extracellular
macromolecules form compounds which perform specific functions. A complete organ is
a group of tissues with a same function (i.e. a parenchyma) and a supportive stroma.
Tissues and organs make up organ systems which accomplish complex coordinated
functions such as breathing, digesting, protecting the individual, or processing
information. The organism is thus a functional individual supported by subsystems
operating together.
Organisms can also be regarded as the highest unit of life as they are not proper
subsystems of other (Bunge and Mahner, 1997, p. 149). They are instead constrained by
contingencies to survive. Two or more organisms of the same species confined in space
and time with demographic parameters constitute a population where intraspecific
interactions as cooperation or competition arise (Pavé, 2006). Any system containing at
least one organism provided with the appropriate nutrients can nonetheless be an
ecological system by its own (e.g. the D. audaxviator specimen) (Strickland, 2008). A
community involves different species populating the same area and where symbiotic
interactions such as competition, predation, commensalism, mutualism, and parasitism
occur. Lastly, an ecosystem contains nonliving elements and is spatially limited leading
to the development of niches, immigration, emigration, or trophic dynamics.
Whereas cells communicate by signaling through direct contact or via a local regulator,
chemical compounds (e.g. neurotransmitters) or hormones in the blood torrent, for the
organism communication is rather a transaction of energy with the external environment.
The source of energy that powers most life such as electromagnetic waves can be traced
2
December, 2020
in the sun. Although cells capture, transfer, store and use energy, they do not produce it.
Most actions of an organism involve a series of energy transformations as kinetic energy
is converted to potential energy (Salomon, Berg, and Martin, 2008, p. 152). Heterotroph
organisms seek food sources and potential mates in their immediate surroundings. They
are open systems exchanging energy and releasing it by engaging in various activities.
The organism is the basic ecological unit along with communities but there is also a
qualitative break between them (Pavé, 2006, p. 47). Species share the highest level of
genetic similarities transmitted to their offspring while the community is genetically
heterogeneous. Biocenosis or communities are not living entities but rather a collection of
biosystems from prokaryotic cells (e.g. archeas or bacteria) to morphologically separated
individuals with joint metabolism (e.g. corals). Neither internal parasites nor certain algae
are proper parts of their hosts as in the case of lichens until each cyanobacterium separates
from their fungal filaments. A spatial restraining is ultimately imposed whether it is a
lipidic membrane or epidermal tissue as individuals selectively interact with their
environments. “Primitive organisms” may have evolved from replicator molecules by
satisfying the requirements of relative independence, division from an external
environment, and confinement of biochemical activity.
There are thus at least two meaning of “interaction”: one involving inter- or intraspecific
relationships affecting reproductive success; and another one involving the transference
of energy between the organism and its environment with the most proximate
components forming strongest interactions (MacMachon et al., 1978, p. 702). Yet Pavé
(2006, p. 46) suggests that basic interaction processes can be found in any level.
Reproduction, induced degradation, competition, association, and adaptation are analog
processes to be traced from the cellular level. For instance, protein degradation can be
compared to predation; and metabolic cooperation to altruistic behavior. What matters is
whether organisms have emergent properties not attributable to their components. For
example, most body cells are replaced through development, but the individual remains
relatively the same once an adult. Lidicker (2007) enumerates some properties related to
the organism such as a coordinated trajectory, homeostasis, resources acquisition, mate
finding, or defense against potential menaces. Demographic density, social organization,
sex ratio, speciation, genetic heterogeneity, or evolutionary arms race are instead
populational constructs. We have to consider then to what extent behavior is an emergent
function of the organism as a whole not belonging to another level of organization.
Organisms and Environments
Compared with the idea of the organism as an assemblage or “vehicle” of replicators
(Dawkins, 1986), or the rather eccentric depiction of the individual as a “host” of responses
(Baer, 1976), the notion of the organism in psychology is usually confined to that of a “selfcontained biologically bounded individual” that may impose or not constraints on
learning (Roche and Barnes, 1997). It has even been said that there can be no complete
account of behavior without considering some biological characteristics of the individual
3
December, 2020
(Kanfer and Phillips, 1970). But psychological statements are usually regarded as
concerning learning contingencies without the need of further specifying a role for the
organism.
Individuals are of most importance from early behavioral ecology (Moen, 1973) to current
trends (Owens, 2006). One can set aside some of these topics as concerning biologists
insofar ecology studies the interactions of organisms and environments across all
ecosystems (Malmstrom, 2010). It happens that this is claimed to be the subject matter of
behavioral analysis as well. For instance, Woodworth (1958) defines psychology as the
scientific study of the activities of the organism in relation to the environment. For this
reason, Roche and Barnes (1997) disdain the loose organism-environment interaction
concept by calling for targeting only “special types of behavior”. But it would be easier to
consider that some approaches overlap with other disciplines just tackling distinctive
aspects of behavior.
Behavior analysis is a part of biology as responses refer to processes exemplified by living
organisms (Donahoe, 1996). It is no more dependent on physiology than physiology is on
cellular biology, or cellular biology on genetics. Yet it is neither less interdependent on them
than they are on each other. And although controversies remain whether endosymbionts
or insect colonies are organisms (see Pepper and Herron, 2008), there are no major
controversies in psychological settings as subjects of research are easily identified as
separate higher vertebrates. Nevertheless the organism can still be considered no more
than a container providing external protection for the organs. Body systems perform
complex functions such as breathing, digesting, excreting, or regulating bodily functions.
Sessile organisms as mussels can travel via water currents or have a motile phase during
their development as sponges. Tropisms and nastic movements are to be distinguished
from kineses and taxes which are orienting reflexes of motile organisms and dependent
upon current environments. It seems that organisms only move bringing everything
inside with them as once reached fetal viability the ability of the individual to survive
depends thereon its success in coping with nature outside the uterus.
From this follows that an “organism” is an individual that embraces the highest level of
organization of living forms. But it also keeps a functional control on the exchange of
matter and energy between the environment without which their internal milieu would
not survive. The exchange of gases occurs in cellular membranes and some organisms
must breathe in oxygen available in the environment. While metabolic reactions are
responsible for converting chemical energy to ATP, the energy itself is derived from
nutrients from external sources. Except for binary fission, budding, or sporulation,
reproductive success cannot be made without finding a proper mate. Sensorial deprive
can also be detrimental to individuals. Individuation processes instead encompass the
success of reproduction and development (Ruiz-Mirazo et al., 2000).
The notion of “organism” may be then looked up in its interaction with its surroundings
to increase its survival rate. The skin actually entails a pivotal role as there are no
4
December, 2020
functional relationships if environmental events or stimuli never reach the individual
(Moen, 1973, p. 18). But neither are if no appropriate input and output channels are
considered. Even Baer (1976) suggests that once the organism enters the operant chamber,
the concern is explaining behavior under contextual control with only a “single
parametric specification of the health or the organism” (p. 89). Palmer (2004) recommends
an analysis of transdermal processes (though and across the skin) as complementary
phases. Engaging with changing environments requires learning novel responses and
natural selection has provided us with a genetic endowment to reliably respond to
relatively stable biotopes as evolutionary strategies.
This is criticized by Bunge and Ardila (1987) for outputs are a function of both stimuli and
inner states. The same output can be expected only by monitoring the state of the animal
in each trial. Any transaction with an environment can be represented as O = M x I where
O refers to the output as a product of both the input I and the summarized properties M
of the organism (Bunge, 1975, p. 63). When M is nowhere stated, the model cannot explain
outcomes in terms of mechanisms but only control variation resorting to M = O x I-1. Yet
an interpretation of the role of organismal variables (internal states) would remain absent.
However not only physiological mechanisms (e.g. synaptic efficacies) are needed, but also
functional explanations:
A
S
C
R
C
S
Figure 1. Stimuli have been dubbed respectively as antecedent and consequent while the operant class
has been changed to a generic response class. Even if internal mechanisms supplement this account
with mediating processes, they do not substitute the need for specifying environmental contingencies.
Adapted from Zilio (2020).
Whether psychologists study the behavior of plants, flatworms, or computers; or if the
choice of the organism is merely incidental for facilitating experimental purposes raises
the issue of the idea of a “psychological organism”. Is the decision made upon ethical
restraints or the easiness in the handling of the animal? Or does the choice of a specific
organism add something to the experiment? The vast majority of animals are of no interest
for the psychologist but only those capable of learning. Therefore, only animals endowed
with a nervous system that enables them to react to their environments and learn upon
their consequences can be classified as subjects of interest (Bunge and Ardila, 1987, p. 29).
Until we have more insight on the adaptation and brain chemistry of other species (e.g.
reptiles and fishes) one may rely mainly on mammals and birds. Matthews (1985) claims
5
December, 2020
that what accredits a “psychological organism” is a minimal plasticity which enable it to
learn. Although “psychological events” are more than biological events, they are no less
than them. The “psychological subject” is a “biological organism” that engages in specific
environmental relations whether the contiguity and discrepancy requirements are met.
A morphological account of the organism would take the individual as a point in space
(Palmer, 2004). Psychology needs instead a functional account of the organismenvironment system as one cannot separate both as long as responses and stimuli are
codefined. The cell is morphologically (structurally) limited to the membrane, but
functionally related to the extracellular space where ions and organic molecules will
trespass the cytoplasm in order to ensure its survival. As skin, horns, carapaces, or scales
functionally interact with the environment, this perspective encompasses both physiology
and psychology as a feedback scheme through a behavioral (Fig. 1) or a biological
approach (Fig. 2):
A
S
O
C
C
S
R
Figure 2. An expanded biobehavioral paradigm when organismal variables (O) and inner states are
taken into account between antecedent stimuli and response classes, but not substituting the
contingencies which remains either on the internal or external environment of the individual.
It can be said that intraorganismal variables also learn to respond to external stimuli like
the immune suppression with the administration of saccharine sodium associated with
cytophospane. But the conditioning process is found in environmental contingencies.
Even more, organisms differ in their biological structures shaped by natural selection but
also in their behavior from one environment to another (Donahoe and Palmer, 2004, p.
18). Behavioral variation is retained by the ancestral environment but it is enriched
following birth by the individual environment. Although we lack “behavioral fossils”
such as changes of synaptic efficacies, we can find endocasts and permanent products
made by our ancestors. Yet it is ultimately the environment that favored some responses
over others due to selective pressures. Variability diminishes when an “action strategy”
is learned, but when consequences that usually follow it fails, there is an increase of
6
December, 2020
variability as it would have returned to an exploratory phase (Veá, 1990). Organisms that
learn to respond in appropriate ways to novel stimuli were more likely to leave offspring, so natural
selection favored organisms with plastic neural systems. And if different operants are selected in
similar environments, then the response repertoire is enlarged leading to adaptive behaviors of
increasing complexity. It is not superfluous to say that learning is no more nor less a
fundamental principle for adaptative behavior but a second kind of selection only behind
natural selection (Skinner, 1981). The evolution of species and the individual development
of the organism create the conditions upon which environmental contingencies operates
thus shedding light on the roles of biological variation for explaining behavior.
States and mechanisms
Every individual is embedded in an environment so we have to be aware of both the
biological characteristics of the organism and the physical surroundings where it develops
and learns. Organismal variables that may influence the trajectory of behavior can be
considered either: 1) internal states or biological conditions; or 2) intermediate mechanisms.
Certain physiological processes such as blushing, perspiring, crying, or sweating are
responses in themselves. As the organism is intermittently present in any behavioral
event, only variables that facilitates or interferes response functions such as chromosomal
alterations, early infections, age, nutritional state, neurological conditions, or physical
impairments are to be considered (Kanfer and Phillips, 1970). It is to notice that hereditary
factors and pre- and perinatal factors are themselves not mechanisms but variables that
adjust the CNS of the organism. They alter responding or impose constraints on learning which
remains a function of contingencies. Behavioral repertoires and learning histories are also
considered organismal variables as are retained in the organism (e.g. through
generalization of contextual cues via the strengthening of neural connection in the
associative cortex). All these are internal states that correlate or interfere with the
establishment of contingencies and thus are province of basic and applied
psychophysiology.
But organismal variables can also be considered mechanisms on par with environmental
events. This is not to say that motor responses are explained alone by neuromuscular
mechanisms, but rather that a response is explained by the environmental contingencies,
that is, by the circumstances that set the occasion for the emission of a motor response.
Physiological mechanisms mediate between the antecedent event and the consequent event
manipulated as contingencies (Fig 2). This can be seen as the most prosaic proposal of
reconciliation of behavior analysis and neurosciences (see also Zilio, 2013).
A somewhat sophisticated approach is proposed by Donahoe and Palmer (2004). Complex
behavior is said to emerge as the cumulative product of selective processes acting over
time akin to biological evolution. Simple responses can lead to complex phenomena such
as thinking or reminding due to the selecting effects of the individual environment. The
experimental analysis of behavior and research on the underlying physiological
7
December, 2020
mechanisms support this thesis. Temporal contiguity can be traced in the intracellular
events leading to LTP and the discrepancy requirement has its neural counterpart in the
increase of dopamine release from midbrain cells if these were not currently activated
(Donahoe, 2003, p. 10). The standard S-R scheme can be explained in terms of stimuli
acting upon receptors to produce activity in the primary sensory cortex. The stimulation
of the sensory and the motor association cortex ultimately led to activity in the primary
motor cortex causing measurable responses at the behavioral level (Donahoe and Palmer,
2014, p. 12).
The same proposal is exposed by Bunge and Ardila (1998): “Given a stimulus s acting on
an animal b, b contains a neural system n controlling the performance of an overt response,
in such a way that the latter is determined jointly by s and by the state of n at the time the
stimulus (or its transduction) reaches n” (p. 169). A purely functional account of behavior
is likely to be inviable without considering feedback mechanisms. An organism with a
different neural structure will presumably still accomplish the S-R scheme, but the task
will be restricted to prediction and control until we obtain information about its internal
states. However, while the notion of organismal events playing a mechanistic role is
present, understanding how the environment exerts discriminative control provides a
complete account of adaptative behavior.
Roles and Functions
In multicellular animals, an immense number of regulatory mechanisms have evolved.
All organs and tissues function for the maintenance of constant conditions in the internal
environment (Hall, 2016, p. 4). Some of these major body functions comprises extracellular
fluid transport, nutrients provision, removal of metabolic end products, protection, and
reproduction. Of particular importance and directly related to behavior are the
musculoskeletal system and the regulation of body functions by both the nervous and the
endocrine system. The former provides the organism with motility and external
protection while the latter detect energy changes in the environment, are involved in
locomotion and regulate internal cellular functions.
The notion of “biological function” can be traced in ethological concerns for proximate
causes (mechanisms) and adaptation values albeit it has an ancient origin. (For a historical
review of the term see Toepfer, 2011). It usually means the activity of a component of a
system so it can be identified with the set of processes occurring in it (Bunge and Mahner,
1997, p. 155). Different functions may fulfill a same biological role (e.g. claws, jaws, or
stingers for protection). Pumping blood, beating, and emitting cardiac sounds are specific
functions of the heart in the cardiovascular system but supplying oxygen and nutrients
through blood circulation are their role.
Functions describe processes or activities rather than traits (i.e. inherent properties) and
are enacted by a biological system at an emergent level. (See also Farnsworth, Albantakis
and Caruso, 2017). Behavioral responses are functions performed by an organism within
8
December, 2020
the context of a population, a community, or an ecosystem. Social behavior and
interspecific activities are displayed in populational and communitarian dynamics. As
every organism is a member of a larger ecosystem, it can also interact with its physical
environment (e.g. great apes foraging techniques from antlers or rocks which can play a
role for hunting).
Thomas (2017, p. 16) opposes causal roles to selection functions so explanation of a
biological function is to be found within its evolutionary history. This does not deny that
functions of a system are identified with the processes occurring within. It simply expands
the focus on whether such activity played a significant role during evolution, or whether
it was a byproduct, or perhaps a spandrel. Selected effects favor certain processes as
mechanisms over others for increasing inclusive fitness or reproductive success so are of
special interest of evolutionary biologists while other accompanying effects may be of
interest for the physiologist and the physician. It is the case of the function of a component
of the visual system such as the eye. It may have contributed to the general fitness of an
organism by enhancing light detection. But the functions of their components (cornea,
sclera, pupil, iris, lens or retina) are the many activities they perform (light refraction,
dilatation, accommodation, aberrations decrease). A minor refractive error may have no
played a significant evolutionary role but is certainly of concern for the ophthalmologist.
Structures with no apparent function (e.g. deer antlers) may play a significant role (e.g.
sexual selection or protection from the environment). Conversely, the appendix carries
out immunological activities, but its role is apparently insignificant (Bunge and Mahner,
1997, p. 156). Furthermore, functions of a trait are intrinsic properties of individuals, but
roles are related to the part they play in larger environments (e.g. payoffs, kin selection,
or prey adaptation). For avoiding confusion with its current usage, one can designate the
“biological role” as the evolutionary or physiological functions of a biosystem whereas
“function” will simply mean an activity that is carried out without raising the issue of its
evolutionary origin but what it does and how it operates (Thomas, 2017, p. 17).
In matters of explanation, behavioral analysts are concerned with ultimate and proximate
causation whereas the former is the domain of both evolutionary biology (phylogeny) and
developmental psychology (ontogeny) and the latter involves the discovery of
mechanisms as a domain of physiology and behavioral neuroscience. Yet changes in the
immediate environment alter synaptic efficacies that in turn influence behavior. Both
environmental stimuli and neural mechanisms are deemed as proximate causes for
learned behavior (Schlinger, 2015, p. 2). This leads us back to Skinner (1981) proposing
that selection by consequences parallels natural selection by shaping and maintaining
behavior not in the species, but in the organism. Behavior analysis addresses learning and
adaptative behavior with respect to environmental contingencies while physiology
accounts for the biological processes that underlie functional environmental-behavior
relationships.
9
December, 2020
The organism as an open system interacts with its external environment and is subject to
external and internal disturbances. Although cells interact with the outside thanks to their
semipermeable membranes, the organism is the last living element in the process of
energy conversion as it is not a proper part of any emergent system. An individual
endowed with a physiological machinery constantly engages with a changing
environment settling the occasion for natural selection to occur.
Going back to systems physiology, one can advert that all processes of the organism
usually refer to the internal milieu as if it were auto-efficacious (i.e. without an explicit
reference to external cues, trigger signals, or environmental stimuli). It seems like a matter
of common sense that olfactory receptors cannot transduce any chemical information if
there is no object to be perceived except for olfactory hallucinations due to temporal or
orbitofrontal lesions. The nervous system has evolved to meet the demands of interacting
with and adapting to the environment with specific cortical areas (e.g. the frontal
association cortex) largely programmed by learning experiences so it is reasonable to
believe that all organ systems act in coordination.
What has been reviewed so far will be used to exemplify some global properties of each
system and argue to what extent the organismal level is to be considered the domain
where behavior occurs in a more evident way. The integrative systems (e.g. the nervous
and endocrine system) and some other will help us illustrate our view. While some of
them overlap, we will focus on the most important elements for pedagogic purposes.
Breathing in
Pulmonary respiration provides oxygen to the tissues of the organism and remove carbon
dioxide via exhalation. Inhalation of air rich in oxygen into the body starts in the nasal
passage and is completed from the alveoli up to the nostrils and then out of the body. The
structure of the respiratory system is suited to its primary function: transportation of gases
in and out of the organism (Barret and Ganong, 2019). The basic composition of the lungs
can be identified with pulmonary endothelial cells from which the system develops:
Level
Cellular
Tissular
Organal
Systemic
Organismal
Physical
substrate
Pulmonary
endothelial cells
Endothelium
Lungs
Respiratory
system
Organism
Form the inner
layer of the lung
vasculature
Provide a
barrier between
circulating
blood and
parenchyma but
also perform
some metabolic
tasks
Gas exchange to
the
bloodstream.
They later
release carbon
dioxide back
into the
atmosphere
Coordinates
and integrates
the upper and
lower
respiratory
tracts for
pulmonary
ventilation.
Breathing in
from oxygen
resources found
in the
immediate
environment
Function
10
December, 2020
It is to notice that in this example only main organs are considered without neglecting
others (e.g. the nasal cavity that filters large particles and humidify air). It is neither
limited but superposed with the muscular system as it involves the pharyngeal muscles
and the diaphragm. Respiration itself is regulated by the nervous system which adjusts
the rate of alveolar ventilation and controls the bronchiolar musculature (Hall, 2016, p.
505). The role of the organism is to breath in from an oxygen-enriched atmosphere by
staying outdoors, counting on an artificial respirator, or avoiding a vacuum in space
because there is nothing there to inhale. Technically only the lungs respirate or ventilate
albeit they cannot inflate without the diaphragm. It is neither the specific function of the
individual to breathe, but rather to provide their organs with the external resources
needed for the process to begin with.
Mating
Level
Cellular
Physical
substrate
Sperm cells
Function
Haploid fusion
when fertilizing
an egg cell
Tissular
Organic
Systemic
Organismal
Penis, scrotum
and testicles
Male
reproductive
system
Organism
Production and
ejaculation of
semen
Sexual
intercourse
Mating with an
available
partner
(Cannot divide)
11
Sexual acts can be enhanced by signals such as erotic stimuli which can be provided by
imagination. Yet this second example is a bit deceitful because sexual reproduction
usually involves two distinct organisms. The external or internal organs of the male
reproductive system are also developed from the intermediate mesoderm while sperm
and androgens are produced by the testes which are themselves composed of mesothelial
cells. The example illustrates that the process itself requires at least two organisms. Female
individuals are not fertilized but their eggs. Conversely, flirting, dating, and mating are
directed towards reproduction, but are themselves not performed by the sperm cell but
by a human individual (or preferably a duetto).
Getting stressed
Hormone-behavior relationships are of concern for behavioral endocrinology. In turn,
endocrine physiology is concerned with the maintenance of various aspects of
homeostasis (Barret and Ganong, 2019). Input (sensory) systems and output (muscular)
systems are mediated by an integrator system such as the central nervous system while
hormones influence all these systems (Nelson, 2010, p. 97). As molecules, they are
chemical messengers released by glands for regulating or controlling bodily functions.
December, 2020
Cells are influenced by hormones, so hormones rather belong to a chemical level of
organization. The brain regulates the hormonal activity of the body, but hormonal
changes may also alter neuronal activity. As the CNS can be considered an internal locus
of control, the importance for behavior lies not in the endocrine system as such but in the
neuroendocrine supersystem.
Level
Cellular
Tissular
Organic
Systemic
Organismal
Physical
substrate
Endocrine cells
Epithelial tissue
Hypothalamus
and endocrine
glands
HPA, HPT or
HPG axes
Organism
Function
Secrete or
inhibit the
release of
glucagon and
insulin.
Neuroendocrine
cells receive
neuronal inputs
and release a
neurohormone
into the
bloodstream
Arrange
secretory cells
to form glands
Release of
epinephrine
from the
adrenal medulla
and
norepinephrine
from the SNS.
CRH or ACTH
are later
released
Neuroendocrine
integration of
the cascade of
hormones for
regulating
bodily processes
Waiting in a
traffic gridlock
12
Endocrine cells do not form glands but are rather secreted by them and the hypothalamus
connects the endocrine with the nervous system. Regardless, every interacting element
leading to the final outcome are represented in their respective levels. Consider a behavior
such as waiting in a gridlock when in hurry. As a stressor it can typically elicit an
unspecific response. The individual must cope with the demanding environment (i.e.
coping strategies in psychological jargon) by relieving stress via exercises, yoga, leisure,
relaxing, or changing sleep habits. All these activities are performed within a society
holding consumer goods, services, or entertainment industry while processes occurring
within the skin involve the coordination of hormone secretion and the neural control of
behavior.
How does a molecule reaching the brain change gene expression or cellular function is of
interest for the physiologists, but behavior analysts deal with signal triggers, responses,
and consequences that follow them providing a contextual account of the occurrence of
behavior. Behavioral endocrinology best illustrates that reduction strategies should
integrate our knowledge of hormones and the influence of behavior-environment
relations to hormone concentration in the blood.
December, 2020
Moving
The vernacular meaning of “behavior” usually confine it to observable motor outputs of
an organism. But consider the following case: A tutor is concerned with the temper tantrums
of her child so she asks a specialist why her toddler does them. Tantrums seems to fulfill a behavioral
function, i.e. receive attention, or getting access to tangibles. But if the specialist offers a
neurobiological explanation for something that lies in the environment of the child, he or she will
not be providing a proper explanation. It is not because a neuromuscular system that the child
tantrums, but through it. For behavior analysts, any kind of engaging with the environment
counts as behavior, so there are motor, cognitive, and emotional responses. Each one will
presumably diverge in their mechanisms (i.e. motor behavior is related to the
neuromuscular system while frontal and cortico-thalamic areas are related to cognition).
Motor responses can be considered the most expressive aspects of any activity
corresponding to an overt realization, e.g. reflexes, habits, or skills.
Level
Cellular
Tissular
Physical
substrate
Myocites
Function
Cardiac,
skeletal or
smooth muscle
cells have a
basic
contractile
function.
Organic
Systemic
Organismal
Skeletal muscle
Musculoskeletal
system
Organism
Through motor
neurons and in
response to
neurotransmitters,
the striated
muscle contracts
in a region.
By connecting
to the skeleton,
it allows
movement and
the
maintenance of
posture and
position of the
whole body.
Moving
through the
environment
(Not
applicable)
Here are not considered cellular origins of bones (osteoblasts, osteoclasts and osteocytes)
nor is mentioned that there will be no voluntary movement without the action of the
nervous system. But it is implicit that the organism moves in its environment through
orientation reflexes or by changing from one place to another. If behavior were reduced
to motor responses, behavior analysis would be limited to striated muscle physiology.
Approximative or withdrawal behavior within an environment still involves responding
to spatial restraints and the skeletal muscle would not suffice to answer why did the
chicken cross the road.
Thinking
Covert responses are usually considered nonbehavioral as if they were of another nature
(or even nonphysical). A “computational level” is called upon for accounting for
information-processing tasks and behavioral goals in terms of input/output functions as
a fancy term for referring to what a system does. It is distinguished from a
“implementational level” (i.e. physical structures, operations, or mechanisms); and an
13
December, 2020
“algorithmic level” postulated as a middle term for carrying out “representations”.
Design principles articulated in this level provide accounts of what phenomena may be
produced compared to what does actually perform them (Bechtel and Shagrir, 2015).
Neural mechanisms implement psychological functions although “not every
implementation will satisfy the conditions for the algorithm (design)” (p. 321). The wellknown Baddeley-Hitch model of memory illustrates the “algorithmic level” enriched with
findings of neurosciences. (See Chai et al., 2018) while the computational level can be
represented by a recall function R(x,y) without specifying an algorithm of transformation
nor its mechanism.
For cognitive psychology, the representational level deals with “structures, rules or
mental processes” that causally mediate input/output functions. It is therefore “centralist”
for being interested in every event that happens inside the [mind of the] organism. A
behavioral (nonmediational) “algorithmic” level may be supplemented by a functional
diagram or a neuronal network model. It would be neither a “centralist” nor
“peripheralist” model but an “interactive” model. If certain processes cannot be
topographically identified with the functions of a specific organ, there is only one place
for these in the hierarchy of organization, that is, the organismal level.
Putting the CNS as the last example is strategic because it is common to reduce behavior
(or “mental processes”) to the action of the brain or some part of it. If the rationale of the
argument has been followed so far, it will be seen that even covert responses are better
explained relating them to the organism. “Cognition” refers to any process by means of
which the sensory income is transformed, reduced, elaborated, stored, recovered, or used
involving events such as thinking, imagining or planning. “X does y” is quickly identified
with the activity of spinal motor neurons that induce voluntary activity or body
movements. It is obvious that jumping a fence involves the musculoskeletal system. But
it seems less obvious that “x reminds y” is also something x is currently doing or
performing.
The brain as an information-processing organ describes global properties of a system.
Activities in the nervous system are initiated by experiences that excite sensory receptors
but also fulfills an effector role by contracting skeletal muscles, smooth muscle in the
internal organs or secreting hormones to many parts of the body (Hall, 2016, p. 577).
Integrative functions are sometimes posited for accounting for “higher mental activities”
as memory or learning. However it is possible to give a behavioral account of cognitive
processes such as the provision of previously selected stimuli guiding present responses;
or problem solving as supplementing or manipulating stimuli until a contingency (a
question) is satisfied. (See Donahoe and Palmer, 2014). They are context-dependent
activities and analyzed in terms of contingential relations. As every biological function,
they do have a physiological basis. Memory involves the strengthening of synaptic
connections and the contribution of second messenger systems on the prefrontal cortex
and the lateral and anterior temporal cortex (Barret and Ganong, 2019).
14
December, 2020
But it is a matter of recognizing the synaptic mediators as mechanisms of behavioral
responses without neglecting that these are also guided by the environment. Such is the
case that destruction of portions of the cerebral cortex does not necessarily prevent a
person from having thoughts at all, but it does reduce their depth and the degree of
awareness of the surroundings (Hall, 2016, p. 745). Cognitive events are behaviors of the
organism and should be interpreted as another form of engaging with its environment.
Level
Cellular
Tissular
Organic
Systemic
Physical
substrate
Sensory, motor or
interneurons and
glial cells
Nuclei and nerve
tracts
Cerebrum,
brainstem,
cerebellum and
spinal cord
Central
nervous
system
Function
Sensory neurons
receive and
transmit signals.
Motor neurons
connect to skeletal
and smooth
muscle.
Interneurons
connect spinal
motor and sensory
neurons. Glia
provide structural
and metabolic
support.
Association fibers
connect a cortical
area within the
same hemisphere.
Commissural fibers
connect it with the
corresponding area
in the opposite
hemisphere.
Projection tracts
connect the cortex
with lower parts of
the brain and the
spinal cord.
The brain processes
and coordinates
sensory information.
It is involved in
motor control and
regulation of
autonomic
functions. The cord
manages messages
from the brain to
other parts of the
body and from
sensory receptors to
the brain. It also
coordinates reflexes
alone.
Organismal
Organism
(Covert)
Detect energy
changes and
control
movement
Providing
with
substitute
stimuli when
studying
(Overt)
Rehearsal of
a lecture
Mechanisms at different levels are not denied insofar the modus operandi does not preclude
other explanatory variables. Furthermore, all (learned) functions of behavior can be
interpreted as involving access to tangibles, escape, avoidance, social attention, or sensory
(automatic) stimulation (see Iwata and Dozier, 2008). As behavioral processes are related
to habituation, sensitization, discrimination, generalization, stimulus equivalence, or
substitution, variables controlling these responses are accounted as context-dependent.
Organisms within Contexts
Behavior is defined as a set of responses under contextual control so it is identified with a
unitary organism-environment system. Skinner (1981) stated that behavior evolved by
furthering the interchange between the organism and environment as a biological
function like others. But under a much wider range of conditions, responding to novel
settings may have required a principle of selection related to the individual development.
The idea of each organism differentially responding to the same physical event constitutes
15
December, 2020
a tenet for most contextual approaches to behavior. The context of the organism is its
“psychological setting” and constitutes the portion of the environment which can be
divided in analytical units even when some are not directly manipulated (Fig 3):
Environment
Context
Organism
Figure 3. The organism-in-context depiction simplifies the organism-environment system. Not all
physical events are functional but only those that reach the organism and control its behavior.
The organism interacts in and with a past and current situational context which conforms
a “behavioral stream” for each individual. Learning history and the conditions where a
response was trained constitute past selections. A rat can be trained in a spatial-learning
paradigm to follow a trail when a red light is on. The rat has its own environment and
selectively responds to it and although contextual stimulus or cues do not directly control
a response, they can alter the outcome if prepotent enough.
The context is inclusive as it encompasses all possible variables that control behavior. Zilio
(2020) has argued that mechanicism is compatible with contextualism as the search for
explanatory mechanisms can be found in both physiological and environmental settings.
How selectionism fares with this? Complex behavior is the outcome of variation and
selection. What are selected are stimuli-response relations and retained via rehearsal or
supplementary cues enabled by neural circuits (e.g. hippocampal synaptic tagging). The
selectionist framework is thus a causal model of explanation, while contextualism sets the
analytic concepts and rules for predicting and controlling psychological events in a
variety of settings although are closely related concepts (Fox, 2006).
Organismal factors are often subsumed as contextual variables, i.e., factors that are
present when the learning occurs and should be controlled. A similar strategy is found in
neuropsychology where the nervous system is seen either as an independent variable for
behavioral disorders; or as a dependent variable for exploring the impact of injury,
learning, and development of the brain. Roche and Barnes (1997, p. 611) denounce that
considering the organism may astray the legitimate goals of the behavior analyst. For
example, hands are not intelligently designed for baking but enabled by the joint action
of the musculoskeletal system. Yet it is explained by pointing to environmental
16
December, 2020
contingencies. This is the rationale concerning processes such as thinking, reminding, or
imagining which are covert responses although may be enabled by the prefrontal cortex
to avoid teleological implications. One can even put the organism in brackets while
exploring response-environment interactions but for giving a full account of learning and
adaptation we are to supplement our research with biological data fostering both
functional and mechanismic explanations.
Summary
The notion of the “organism as a whole” is a vague theoretical concept as it allegedly
refers to emergent functions not properly attributable to any of its parts (Bernat, 2019).
True is that the total organism and the organism as a whole are not to be confused as the
amputation or loss of an organ may diminish a function or even its quality of life, but the
individual remains one. It would be easier to dispense the usage of “organism as a whole”
referring to it simply as an organism and considering organismal variables either as bodily
conditions or physiological mechanisms albeit a molar perspective is more than evident.
It is also meaningless to speak of “half an organism” in the same sense of a brain cross
section or a portion of kidney. This is meaningful in an anatomical (or morphological)
sense, but not in a functional sense. If the organismal level is linked to the establishment
of relations with the environment by integrating and coordinating mechanisms and inner
states, the role and nature of the organism discussed here allows for a deepening of our
accounts of behavior as a relational property. A science of behavior is after all concerned
with the functional relations between an organism and its environment and how neural
and hormonal systems mediate these (Moore, 2002). But restricting research to the
physiological machinery tends to ignore contextual contingencies whereas behavior of
organisms is primarily found in orderly environment-responses relations.
The biology which most concerns psychologists (or psychobiologists) is thus organismal
biology for explaining how living systems develop and function under an array of
circumstances. Behavioral functions are processes under contextual control. This does not
imply diminishing the legitimacy of the rest of behavioral sciences, but rather
emphasizing that psychological or behavioral analysis seeks to study a specific
phenomenon, that is, that of interaction with an environment based on the principles of
learning. And although it is just one branch among others, it is not a small thing to say
that by adapting to an environment it prepares the conditions for development and
natural selection to occur.
17
December, 2020
REFERENCES
Baer, D. M. (1976). The organism
98. https://doi.org/10.1159/000271519
as
host. Human
Development.
19(2):
87–
Barrett, K. E., & Ganong, W. F. (2019). Ganong's review of medical physiology. New York,
McGraw-Hill Medical.
Bechtel, William & Shagrir, Oron. (2015). The Non-Redundant Contributions of Marr's Three
Levels of Analysis for Explaining Information-Processing Mechanisms. Topics in cognitive
science. 7: 312-333. 10.1111/tops.12141.
Bernat, J. L. (2019). Refinements in the Organism as a Whole Rationale for Brain Death. The
Linacre Quarterly. XX(X): 1-12.
Bunge, M. (1975). Teorías fenomenológicas. Teoría y realidad. 2da. ed. Barcelona: Ariel: pp. 5586.
Bunge, M. and Ardila, R. (1987). Philosophy of Psychology. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Bunge, M. and Mahner, M. (1997). Foundations of Biophilosophy. Berlin and New York: Springer
Science & Business Media.
Chai, W.J, Abd Hamid, A., and Abdullah, J.M (2018) Working Memory From the
Psychological and Neurosciences Perspectives: A Review. Front. Psychol. 9:401. doi:
10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00401.
Dawkins, R. (1986). Replicators and Vehicles. Brandon, R., and Burian, R. (Ed.) Genes,
Organisms, Populations. Cambridge MA, The MIT Press.
Donahoe, J. (1996). On the Relation Between Behavior Analysis and Biology. The Behavior
analyst, 19(1):71-73.
Donahoe, J. W. (2003). Selectionism. Lattal, K.A. & Chase, P.N. (Eds.). Behavior Theory and
Philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers: 103-128.
Donahoe, J.W. and Palmer, D.C. (2004) Learning and Complex Behavior. Ledgetop Publishing,
Richmond.
Farnsworth, K. D., Albantakis, L., & Caruso, T. (2017). Unifying concepts of biological function
from molecules to ecosystems. Oikos, 126(10), 1367–1376. doi:10.1111/oik.04171
Fox, E. (2006). Constructing A Pragmatic Science of Learning and Instruction with Functional
Contextualism. Educational Technology Research and Development. 54. 5-36.
Hall, J. (2016). Guyton and Hall Textbook of Medical Physiology. 13th ed. United States of America:
Elsevier.
Iwata, B. A., & Dozier, C. L. (2008). Clinical application of functional analysis
methodology. Behavior analysis in practice, 1(1): 3–9. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03391714
18
December, 2020
Kanfer, F. H., & Phillips, J. S. (1970). Learning foundations of behavior therapy. New York: John
Wiley.
Lidicker, W. (2007) Levels of organization in biology: on the nature and nomenclature of
ecology's fourth level. Biol. Rev. 83: 71-78.
MacMahon, J., Philipps, D., Robinson, J., and Schimpf, D. (1978). Levels of Biological
Organization: An Organism-Centered Approach. BioScience. 28(11). Nov.: 700-704.
Malmstrom, C. (2010). Ecologists Study the Interactions
Environment. Nature Education Knowledge 3(10): 88.
of
Organisms
and
Their
Matthews, G. (1985). The idea of a psychological organism. Behaviorism. 13(1): 37-52.
Moen, A. N. (1973). Wildlife Ecology: An Analytical Approach. San Francisco, W. H. Freeman and
Company.
Moore, J. (2002). Some Thoughts on the Relation Between Behavior Analysis and Behavioral
Neuroscience. The Psychological Record. 52. 261-279.
Nelson, R.J. (2010). Hormones and Behavior: Basic Concepts. Encyclopedia of animal behavior.
97-105. 10.1016/B978-0-08-045337-8.00236-9.
Owens, I. (2006). Where is behavioral ecology going? Trends in ecology and evolution. 21: 356361. 10.1016/j.tree.2006.03.014.
Palmer, D. (2004). On the Organism-Environment Distinction in Psychology. Behavior and
Philosophy. 32: 317-347
Pave, Alain. (2006). Biological and Ecological Systems Hierarchical Organisation. Pumain, D.
(Ed.). Hierarchy in Natural and Social Sciences. Netherlands: Springer-Verlag: pp. 39-70.
Pepper, J. & Herron, M. (2008). Does Biology Need an Organism Concept? Biol. Rev. 83: 621627.
Roche, B., and Barnes, D. (1997). The Behavior of Organisms? Psychol Rec 47, 597–618.
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03395248
Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Etxeberria, A., Moreno, A. et al. (2000). Organisms and their place in
biology. Theory Biosci. 119-209. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-000-0017-1
Salomon, E., Berg, L., Martin, D. (2018) Biology. 11th ed. Boston: Cengage Learning.
Schlinger HD (2015) Behavior analysis and behavioral neuroscience. Front. Hum.
Neurosci. 9:210. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00210.
Skinner, B. F. (1981). Selection
http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.7244649
by
Consequences.
Science,
213:
501-504.
Strickland, E. (2008, October 2010). Deep in a Goldmine, an Ecosystem of One. Discover.
https://www.discovermagazine.com/planet-earth/deep-in-a-goldmine-an-ecosystem-of-one
19
December, 2020
Thomas, P.D. (2017). The gene ontology and the meaning of biological function . Methods
Mol. Biol. 1446: 15–24. doi:10.1007/978-1-4939-3743-1_2.
Toepfer G. (2011) Funktion. Metzler, J.B. (Ed.) Historisches Wörterbuch der Biologie.
Stuttgart: 644-692.
Veá, J. J. (1990). Variabilidad conductual y comportamiento adaptativo. Rev. de Psicol. Gral. y
Aplic. 43(4): 443-449.
Woodworth, R.S. (1958) Dynamics of Behavior. New York: Holt Trinehart and Winston.
Zilio, Diego. (2013). Filling the gaps: Skinner on the role of neuroscience in the explanation of
behavior. Behavior and Philosophy. 41: 33-59.
Zilio, D. (2020). Mechanisms within contexts: First steps toward an integrative approach.
Behavior and Philosophy. 47: 34-66.
20