Cicero and Dionysios the Elder, or The End of Liberty
Dr. W.M. Verbaal
Universiteit Gent
Dpt. : Romaanse talen (andere dan Frans)
Sect.: Protoromaans en Postklassiek Latijn
Ghent University
Dpt.: Romance Languages (other than French)
Sct.: Protoromance and Postclassical Latin
Blandijnberg 2
B - 9000 GENT
tel : xx32 / (0)9 / 264.40.35
fax : xx32 / (0)9 / 264.41.63
e-mail :
[email protected]
Cicero and Dionysios the Elder, or The End of Liberty
Latin writing often conceals more than might be uncovered by a mere philological and
historical approach. To understand the message of a text, traditional analyses ought to be
supported by the more recent requirements on the field of textual criticism and literary sciences.
Close reading, combined with a more structural textual analysis, may offer insights, which, from
a historical point of view, perhaps, might have no implications, but which, nonetheless, can
contribute to a better understanding of an author’s writing technics and of his intentions in
writing the text under discussion.
This article proposes a more complex reading of Cicero’s Tusculanae disputationes,
especially of the fifth book, taking as a point of departure Cicero’s handling of Dionysios of
Syracuse as a prototype of tyranny. The extraordinary emphasis put on this particular example
can, to our opinion, only be understood in its connection to the contemporary political situation,
dominated by Caesar’s victory. Close reading thus renders a striking actuality to the text and the
writing of Cicero’s philosophical masterpiece.
At different places in his œuvre, Cicero mentions Dionysios the Elder, tyrant of Syracuse
(406-367).1The frequency of Dionysios' appearance, especially in the later works belonging to
the so-called second philosophical period, seems to indicate that, by this time, the tyrant had
assumed a charged significance for Cicero. This article seeks to evaluate Cicero's rhetorical use
of Dionysios in an attempt to understand the message which he intends to transmit to the reader.
As the most elaborate evocation of Dionysios appears in the fifth book of the Tusculanae
disputationes, our analysis will concentrate on this work, without ignoring its historical and
literary context.
1
1. Dionysios and Cicero
A first observation ought to be made: Cicero never distinguishes clearly between the
elder and the younger Dionysios, between the father and the son. Although he must have been
conscious of the existence of two Syracusan tyrants with this name, he refers only once
explicitly to the first as superiorem illum Dionysium (Off. II.7.25), whereas he refers once
clearly to the younger one (Ad Fam. IX.18). Normally, however, he combines the tradition
attaching to both tyrants in one rhetorical unity of a Syracusan tyrant Dionysios, exemplifying
the strange combination of sanguinary cruelty with refined education2.
In the earlier works, Dionysios simply appears as the best historical example of cruel
despotism, in line with the semi-mythical Phalaris or with Alexander the Great, who brutally
murdered Callisthenes.3 In the later period, however, the tyrant takes on a new dimension as a
counterexample to true wisdom.4 He does not lose his despotic traits but from that point
Cicero concentrates more on the tension between Dionysios' refined education and the
consequences of his tyranny. In Tusculanae V this tension is most widely developed,
illustrated most clearly in the story of Damocles.
The reader of the Tusculanae has, on arrival at this passage, already passed four days
in the philosophical school of Cicero's Tusculum, and the fifth and last day is half done.
Today he is to learn that virtus suffices to assure the sage, everywhere and always, a blissful
life. As an illustration Cicero enumerates some counter-examples from recent Roman history.
Cinna's fourfold bloody consulship (87-84) is opposed to the much admired Gaius Laelius,
who was destined to become the protagonist of one of Cicero's subsequent treatises (Laelius
de amicitia) and who had been consul only once in 140 after having suffered a refusal the
year before. Marius' six consulates are contrasted with the attitude of Quintus Lutatius
Catulus, his colleague in the consulship, with whom he shared the victory over the Cimbri.5
2
This enumeration is crowned by the most extensive and liveliest portrait of the
Syracusan Dionysios in Cicero's entire œuvre.6 Even in the Tusculanae, this passage is
exceptional with respect to its dimensions. No figure is allowed such prominence in the
earlier books, although many names have been mentioned and several examples have been
presented to the reader, especially in the first book.7 Yet they consist without exception of
shorter anecdotes or of rather simple illustrations for specific philosophical theses. The
Dionysios whom the reader encounters in the fifth book is undeniably of greater importance
to Cicero. He himself constitutes the central figure in an entire series of anecdotes. He neither
illustrates any particular proposition, nor does he embody any philosophical school or theory.
He rather appears as the touchstone of Cicero's whole argument, which has filled the
preceding days. In order to make this clearer, the compository setting of the Tusculanae must
first be examined.
2. The Art of Writing Philosophy
Cicero informs us on his reasons for writing the Tusculanae in the first paragraphs of
the second book On divination, which will be finished less than one year later: 'Next, and in
the same number of volumes [as his De finibus], came the Tusculan Disputations, which
made plain the means most essential to a happy life. For the first volume treats of indifference
to death, the second of enduring pain, the third of the alleviation of sorrow, the fourth of other
spiritual disturbances; and the fifth embraces a topic which sheds the brightest light on the
entire field of philosophy since it teaches that virtue is sufficient of itself for the attainment of
happiness.'8
Death, pain, sorrow, perturbation and virtue: a simple and lucid programme giving no
cause for amazement. The creation of the book acquires another meaning, however, when the
date of its composition is taken into consideration. The Tusculanae were finished in the
3
autumn of 45, i.e. approximately half a year after the death of Cicero’s daughter Tullia, a loss
that plunged him into the depths of pain and distress.9 In his search for consolation, he found
no relief in any of the ancient works written to console those who are left behind. Thus he
decided to write a Consolatio himself.10 It meant a new start and in an amazingly short period
Cicero wrote some of his major philosophical works. Before the Tusculanae and in the same
year, he also finished the Hortensius, the four books Academica and the five books De finibus
bonorum et malorum. The Tusculanae were closely followed by the three books De natura
deorum. During the next year, the two books De divinatione, Cato Maior de senectute,
Laelius de amicitia, De fato, the lost De gloria and the three books De officiis came into
being.11
A clear line can be discovered in the writings of this so-called second philosophical
period. Reading the consolatory writings of the Greeks after the death of Tullia brought the
realization that the existing works did not suffice. They were incapable of relieving the pain
he felt. When he took up the pen himself, one of his aims was to find a remedy for this defect
in philosophical literature. Philosophy must have a practical purpose, otherwise Cicero’s
Roman critics after the publication of his Hortensius were right indeed: a man should not
spend his time and energy on these sorts of activities.12 For this reason, Cicero could not
afford to confine himself to a purely theoretical discourse, but rather looked immediately for
the practical application. If the Academica and De finibus were still strongly theoretical, the
Tusculanae constituted the first step towards their translation into practice. In the succeeding
writings this tendency was to continue.13
If Cicero attempted to concreticize the philosophical principles of the Hortensius, the
Academica and the De finibus in the Tusculanae, then the historical and biographical context
of the book must be taken into account, and perhaps to a greater extent than for the preceding
works. Now two facts have shaped the foundations for the composition of the Tusculanae.
4
First, it must be remembered that they were finished within several months of Tullia’s death.
The composition of the work seems to reflect the personal struggle and development through
which Cicero passed in these few months. After having coped with death in book I, he reflects
on how to deal with pain (book II) and with sorrow (book III, describing what today we might
call a depression). This leads to a position on each form of spiritual disturbance (book IV).
Whereas the first four books are basically negative in their opposition to disruptive or
destructive influences, book V strikes a more positive attitude: the blissful state of the sage.
The happiness of the sage has already figured in the first book, when Cicero evokes
briefly the glory of the spirit returning to its celestial home after the death of the body.14 ‘For
the beauty of that vision [of the heavenly regions] even here on earth called into being that
philosophy “of sires and grandsires,” as Theophrastus terms it, which was first kindled by
longing for knowledge. But theirs will be the chief enjoyment who, even in the days they
sojourned on earth amid the encircling gloom, longed all the same to pierce it by the keenness
of mental vision.’15 The celestial beatitude which, according to the first book, the sage will
enjoy in the afterlife, corresponds to the earthly happiness which is accorded to him in the
fifth book.
This may indicate that, in spite of the high speed with which he apparently finished the
Tusculanae, Cicero at no point lost sight of the literary and rhetorical requirements of
writing.16 The five books of the Tusculanae are organized according to a clear and austere
composition which is not only characterized by the linear argument exposed above17, but
which also shows a circular structure. Books I and V outline the principal idea of the entire
work: the sage has his share in beatitude before, in and after death. The intervening books
examine the factors which seem to disturb this happiness in life: pain, sorrow and passion. In
reality they serve only to throw extra light on the central theme of the whole work as
expressed in the first and last books. As regards the linear composition, they show how the
5
mind of the sage leaves less and less room for disturbing influences, thus enhancing the parts
dedicated to virtus, which alone constitutes true beatitude.18 Simultaneously, they close the
circle by which Cicero tries to demonstrate that the blessed death of the sage, as described in
book I, is only possible after a life of virtus.
Books I and V, then, complement each other. Their importance for a good
understanding of the work as a whole is not only expressed by their respective subject, but
also by their size. Together they form approximately half of the Tusculanae. In addition to
these elements, they alone contain illustrative examples. In book I (40:96-43:104), a heroic
attitude towards death is illustrated by the examples of Theramenes, Socrates, the Spartans,
Diogenes and Anaxagoras, all models for imitation. In book V, on the contrary, examples are
given for a despicable way of life. And no philosophers are introduced, but only figures from
recent Roman history, who enjoyed social success but whose attitude to life was so
reprehensible that no one ought to be envious of their fate. These negative examples are
crowned by Dionysios of Syracuse.
3. Dionysios the Wise Tyrant
Unlike the examples of the first book, where each stands on its own, the enumeration
in the fifth opens with two couples, each consisting of extreme opposites. Cicero opposes the
terror of Cinna’s fourfold consulship to Laelius’ integrity, Marius’ thirst for blood and
revenge to Catulus’ voluntary suicide, because he preferred to suffer injustice than to commit
it.19 After these two pairs of opposites, Cicero introduces Dionysios. It is striking that he does
not immediately oppose anyone to the tyrant. Only much later, when Dionysios has
disappeared from the scene, Archimedes is mentioned, who has figured in opposition to
Dionysios elsewhere.20 I will have to return to Cicero’s use of Archimedes in the Tusculanae.
6
There may be an internal reason for giving Dionysios no immediate opponent.
Although the tyrant is not inferior to Cinna or Marius with respect to his cruelty, he is
nonetheless expressly presented by Cicero as a man who meets all the qualities of a sage
which have been treated during the preceding five days. ‘And yet we are told on the authority
of trustworthy writers that this man was exceedingly temperate in his way of life and showed
intelligence and zeal in the conduct of public affairs.’21 Besides, he was a gifted musician and
writer of tragedies.22 Apparently Dionysios does not need an antipode: he himself embodies
both extremes!
Being perhaps something of a degenerate sage, he realizes very well that a blessed life
is not his share. The anecdote on his courtier Damocles offers the best possible illustration.
Damocles sees only the exterior and judges happiness from what is visible. Dionysios,
however, is aware that his visibile pleasures concern just the outside, that true bliss consists of
an inner peace which is lost to him forever. Even were he to abdicate, he could never again
trust anyone.23
Cicero could have stopped here. The anecdote on Damocles suffices to confirm the
portrait of the sage as it has been given somewhat earlier in this same fifth book. ‘Therefore if
there is a man able to regard the power of fortune, to regard all human vicissitudes that can
possibly befall, as so far endurable that neither fear nor worry touch him, and if the same man
should covet nothing, neither be disturbed by any empty pleasure in his soul, what reason is
there why he should not be happy? And if virtue makes this possible, what reason is there
why virtue of its own power alone should not make men happy?’24 Dionysios proves to
Damocles that his own desires have brought him into a continuous deadly fear, which makes
impossible any feeling of happiness.
But Cicero did not stop here. The image of an imperturbable, impassive man cannot
serve to characterize the perfect sage25. Thus, the anecdote on Damocles will not suffice to
7
describe the true misery of Dionysios. Cicero gives yet another, final illustration and refers to
the famous story of the Pythagorean friends Phintias and Damon.26 Dionysios’ wish to
become a third member in their friendship demonstrates best, according to Cicero, how well
the tyrant understood his own disaster. ‘How wretched it was for him to cut himself off from
the intimacy of friendship, from the enjoyment of social life, from any intimate intercourse at
all! Particularly in the case of a man who had received instruction from childhood and was
trained in the liberal arts.’27 In spite of his education, a truly human life had become almost
impossible to him. ‘He denied himself all the spiritual enjoyment of human life. He associated
with runaways, with criminals, with barbarians. He regarded no man who either felt worthy of
freedom, or had any wish at all to be free, as a friend.’28
4. A Roman Dionysios
This last remark closes the excursion on Dionysios and introduces at once the actuality
of Cicero’s personal life. For, in addition to Tullia’s death, a second element constantly plays
in the background of Cicero’s second philosophical period: the changed political situation in
Rome after the defeat of the senatorial armies by Caesar. It had become clear to Cicero that,
politically, there was no further place for him. On the 25th of September 47 he himself
experiences Caesar’s famous clementia. He travels to Brundisium to meet the victor of
Pharsalos on his return from Egypt. Letters have reassured him of Caesar’s attitude. He knows
that he has nothing more to fear from the man who recently still considered him an enemy and
partisan of his adversaries. And indeed, as soon as Caesar catches sight of him, he descends
from his chariot and walks along with Cicero. Nor does he evince any desire to detract from
Cicero’s claim to a triumphal procession or from his escort of twelve lictors, to which he has
every right as an imperator and onto which he has held obstinately since his return from his
proconsulship in Cilicia in January 49.29
8
Yet this benevolent attitude of Caesar’s has a more deadly effect on Cicero than open
enmity. Immediately after the encounter, Cicero sends away his lictors and renounces his
claim to a triumph.30 He knows now that his political career has finished. ‘I have dropped all
my concern for public affairs, all preoccupation with what to say in the Senate, all study of
briefs, and flung myself into the camp of my old adversary Epicurus.’31 In this forced
passivity, Cicero reverts to his books and his writing. He concentrates for the moment on
rhetorical treatises (Brutus, the Orator), evoking the time when words could sound in
freedom. Tullia’s death, then, brings him back to true philosophy and to his writing of the
Tusculanae and their portrait of Dionysios.
Now, it is remarkable that Dionysios crowns an enumeration of Roman examples out
of recent history. It must not have been difficult for the Roman reader of Cicero’s works to
see in Cinna’s fourfold and Marius’ sixfold consulship the preliminaries to the contemporary
political scene. Had not Caesar become consul for a third time in 46? Had he not been elected
dictator for ten years? But there was more: Caesar had every necessary attribute to become
another Dionysios. His was a good education and schooling, yet he strove for absolute power,
thus making himself into a Roman tyrant. According to Cicero, this meant absolute solitude
and the final deprivation of true friendship, which was only possible among people who
consider freedom of paramount importance. Shortly after his own pardon, Cicero had written
a laudation on Cato, the last champion of freedom. Caesar, apparently, felt obliged to answer
with an Anticato. Besides, the entire Tusculanae are dedicated to Brutus, Caesar’s confidant
but Cicero’s friend.32
If Cicero from his powerless position intended to show Caesar a way out of becoming
a Roman Dionysios, he could not have done better than by this work and its dedicatee. By
concluding a series of types of recent Roman potentates with the Syracusan tyrant, Cicero was
able to hold a mirror to Caesar’s face and to paint for him the dangers of absolute power, a
9
power that can trust no person in whom still breathes the spirit of freedom. Even in his
philosophical writing, Cicero remains the realist and pragmatist. And besides, he who knew
how to refine the Latin word and language when this could be done in freedom, also found
first how to use the power of that language to transmit his call for freedom when this could no
longer openly be uttered.
5. The Roman Archimedes
If one may read in the portrait of Dionysios a murmured warning intended for Caesar,
then the pages which follow also acquire a polyvalent meaning. Only after concluding the
excursus on Dionysios does Cicero introduce the Syracusan mathematician Archimedes
whom he contrasts elsewhere with the tyrant (Rep. I. 28). In this earlier work all emphasis
was placed on the opposition between concrete power and intellectual creativity, between the
temporary earthly stage and the perpetual works of the spirit.
An entirely different image of Archimedes appears in the Tusculanae. ‘I shall call up
from the dust and his measuring-rod an obscure, insignificant person belonging to the same
city, who lived many years after, Archimedes. When I was quaestor I tracked down his grave,
which was unknown to the Syracusans (as they totally denied its existence), and found it
enclosed all round and covered with brambles and thickets.’ The account follows of Cicero’s
search for Archimedes’ tomb: how, on the basis of some small fragmentary senarii, he knew
that a globe and a cylinder crowned it, how he thus recognized the stela outside the ramparts,
exposed it and ascribed it to the philosopher thanks to some corroded verses. ‘So you see, one
of the most famous cities of Greece, once indeed a great school of learning as well, would
have been ignorant of the tomb of its most ingenious citizen, had not a man of Arpinum
pointed it out.’33 The protagonist of this entire episode is not Archimedes but Cicero himself.
10
What is emphasized is not the philosophical and scientific knowledge of the Greek, but rather
the respect for tradition and the practical insight of the Roman.
One wonders if this passage has no other sense than offering simply another example
of Cicero’s self-praise. What might be its place within the overall argument of the fifth book?
Cicero has been treating the opposition between the happiness of the sage and the misery of
the powerful, of which Dionysios of Syracuse offered a vivid example. Yet the oblivion to
which Archimedes had been relegated cannot be a true counterweight to the lasting fame of
the tyrant. It rather seems to undermine Cicero’s thesis. Unless, that is, Cicero aims at some
other, less overt link between the two Syracusans.
If Cicero’s portrait of Dionysios may be read as a warning for Caesar, his own
discovery of Archimedes’ tomb also hides a more profound meaning. The series of
contrasting personalities which started with the couples Cinna / Laelius and Marius / Catulus
is then crowned in a double sense: first with the historical and explicit opposition between
Dionysios and Archimedes, but also with the inherent contrast between Caesar and Cicero.
Cicero’s search for virtus, based on a life of knowledge and truth, takes a visible form in his
success in saving Archimedes from oblivion. Caesar, on the contrary, in his striving for power
and tyranny, seems to succeed in bringing back to life the inner dissension and terror of
Dionysios’ existence. Just as Cicero’s practical disposition (as symbolized by his
quaestorship) is always founded on his longing for truth and virtue (symbolized by the weedgrown tomb of the mathematician), so can it be understood from the story of Dionysios what
hovers underneath Caesar’s ambition.
If we admit such a reading, it will be understandable that, immediately after the
anecdote from Cicero’s quaestorship, follows a portrait of the perfect sage.34 He ought to
dispose of a sharp intelligence and a strong desire to know the truth, which will lead to a
threefold spiritual offspring: ‘one centred in the knowledge of the universe and the
11
disentanglement of the secrets of nature; the second in distinguishing the things that should be
sought out or avoided in framing a rule of life; the third in judging what is the consequence to
every premise, what is incompatible with it, and in this lies all refinement of argument and
truth of judgement.’35
These spiritual efforts lead the sage to study the celestial spheres, first the stars, but
afterwards also the ordering principle which is itself the foundation of all natural phenomena.
Thus he achieves ‘the knowledge enjoined by the god at Delphi, that the mind should know
its own self and feel its union with the divine mind, the source of the fulness of joy
unquenchable.’ By this knowledge he knows what to strive for, what to avoid, thus reaching a
state of contemplating the world around him in perfect inner quiet. Then he participates in the
virtue which makes life truly blessed.36
This inner peace is closely connected to a third study in the advancement of wisdom:
knowledge of the dialectic methodology, which befits the sage best as his most joyful
occupation. ‘But this is the occupation of leisure: let the wise man we have imagined also
pass to the maintenance of the public weal. What course more excellent could he take, since
his prudence shows him the true advantage of his fellow citizens, his justice lets him divert
nothing of theirs to his own family, and he is strong in the exercise of so many different
remaining virtues? Add to this the fruit which springs from friendships in which learned men
find the counsel which shares their thoughts and almost breathes the same breath throughout
the course of life, as well as the charm of daily social intercourse.’37
The portrait of the sage has become the mirror image of that of Dionysios, especially
in the two last stages. The inner peace contrasts sharply with the continuous fear of Damocles
/ Dionysios. The riches of friendship which the wise man enjoys stand out against Dionysios’
desperate wish to enter into the friendship of Damon and Phintias. The excursion on the tyrant
of Syracuse thus finds its end only with this portrait of the perfect sage, which concludes at
12
the same time the series of antipodes which opened with the pair Cinna and Laelius.
Dionysios thus is contrasted with the sage, represented by Archimedes, and in contrast with
Dionysios’ alter ego, the Roman Caesar, the portrait of the sage also implies a matching alter
ego for the Greek, the Roman Cicero.
6. Philosophical Virtue
The true argument of the fifth book in the Tusculanae thus ends with a passionate but
indirect evocation of the tensions from which Cicero suffers in his own life, and in the
political life of Rome. Rarely have the politics of wisdom and public interest been contrasted
so sharply with a politics of power and self-interest. The entire Greek philosophical tradition
from Socrates to Archimedes is recruited to the cause of the Roman republican tradition. They
alone can represent a spiritual world which will allow man to enjoy a true state of bliss. But as
such they collide with the personal longing for power of a politician such as Caesar, even
though Cicero still seems to hope for a change for the better. He still considers Caesar as a
possible sage.
Yet, should this hope prove to be vain, Cicero gives us to understand that a wise man
is always superior to all political and earthly forms of power. Even submitted to torture the
sage will not yield, as is confirmed by all philosophical schools without regard to other
differences between them. His joy is not of this world and thus cannot be damaged here on
earth. This is the ultimate fact which Cicero wants to demonstrate in his work.38 And even
when all possible physical pains are piled upon man, there always remains a last resort. ‘For
my part I think that in life we should observe the rule which is followed at Greek banquets:
“Let him either drink”, it runs, “or go!” And rightly; for either he should enjoy the pleasure of
tippling along with the others or get away early, so that a sober man may not fall victim to the
13
violence of those who are heated with wine. Thus by running away one can escape the
assaults of fortune which one cannot face.”39
Death is always a possibility for the sage. He does not consider it a threat, rather a
reward. Thus is the circle rounded. The life of the sage is crowned in his death. Undoubtedly,
Cicero will have had the image of Cato in his mind as an exhortation to confront his own
possible destiny. He wrote his Tusculanae to strengthen himself and to testify to his intention,
for the sake of freedom, of public interest, of truth, of the right to true friendship, not to recoil
from torture or death, should Caesar turn out to be indeed another Dionysios. The Tusculanae
are thus not so much a philosophical treatise, lacking great profundity, as a sincere confession
of this inwardly torn man confronted by the actual demands of history. ‘In doing this I cannot
readily say how much I shall benefit others. At any rate, in my cruel sorrows and the various
troubles which beset me from all sides, no other consolation could have been found.’40
1
In all, Dionysios is mentioned some twenty times in the Ciceronian œuvre, almost all mentions appearing in the
later works, after 55. During this year Cicero must have read the historical work of Philistus of Syracuse († 357).
See his first mentioning Philistus in De oratore II.57. Around the same time, he mentions his preference for
Philistus in comparison to Callisthenes in a letter to his brother Quintus, dated by Shackleton Bailey on 14th of
February 54: D. R. Shackleton Bailey (ed), Cicero: Epistulae ad Quintum fratrem et M. Brutum (Cambridge
1980) 69.
2
This becomes very clear in his use of the story about Phintias and Damon, belonging to the stories around the
younger Dionysios but connected to the older one in Cicero’s account.
3
See In Verrem II.5: Dionysios is just an example of a ‘crudelis tyrannis’, typical for Sicily.
4
This second period starts after the reading of Philistus around 55, see Ad Quintum II.12 and De oratore II.57. In
both passages, emphasis is put more onthe historian than on the tyrant but in the De republica, written after 54
Dionysios appears twice as an example of the opposition of tyranny to democracy (Rep. I.28 and III.12).
5
Tusc V.54-56.
6
Tusc V.57-63.
7
For the meaning of the examples in the Tusculanae in a rhetorical sense, see A.E. Douglas, “Form and Content
in the Tusculan Disputations.” in Cicero the philosopher. Twelve papers. ed. by J. G. F. Powell (Oxford-New
York 1995), 197-218, esp. 199.
8
Div. II.1.2: ‘Totidem subsecuti libri Tusculanarum disputationum res ad beate vivendum maxime necessarias
aperuerunt. Primus enim est de contemnenda morte, secundus de tolerando dolore, de aegritudine lenienda
tertius, quartus de reliquis animi perturbationibus, quintus eum locum complexus est, qui totam philosophiam
maxime illustrat; docet enim ad beate vivendum virtutem se ipsa esse contentam.’ Latin text according to the
Loeb Classical Library (1959), p. 370 with the English translation by William Armistead Falconer, p. 371.
9
For the background of grief in Cicero’s writing of the Tusculanae, see Stephen A. White, “Cicero and the
Therapists”, in Powell (above, n.7), 219-246, esp. 224-225.
10
Att XII.14.3. For the lost Consolatio, see White (above, n.9) 223-224.
11
For a chronology of the writings in Cicero’s second philosophical period, see the list in Powell (above, n.7)
xiii-xvii.
12
Fin I.1.
13
For the importance of the Tusculanae in Cicero’s philosophical project, see Philippe Muller, “La cinquième
« Tusculane », une philosophie sans transcendance.” in Nomen Latinum: mélanges de langue, de littérature et de
14
civilisation latines offerts au professeur André Schneider à l'occasion de son départ à la retraite, ed. by Denis
Knoepfler (Genève 1997), 45-54, esp. 46. A more balanced opinion on the coherence of the works in Cicero’s
second philosophical period is expressed by J.G.F. Powell, “Introduction: Cicero’s Philosophical Works and
their Background.” in Powell (above, n.7), 1-35, esp. 7.
14
Tusc I.43-49, where Cicero resumes concisely the theme which he treated in the Somnium Scipionis.
15
Tusc I.45: ‘Haec enim pulchritudo etiam in terris patritam illam et avitam, ut ait Theophrastus, philosophiam
cognitionis cupiditate incensam excitavit. Praecipue vero fruentur ea, qui tum etiam, cum has terras incolentes
circumfusi erant caligine, tamen acie mentis dispicere cupiebant.’ Latin text throughout according to M.Tulli
Ciceronis Tusculanarum Disputationum Libri Quinque, by Thomas Wilson Dougan and Robert Mitchell Henry,
2 Vols. (Cambridge 1905,1934) vol. I 59-60. English translation throughout by J.E. King in Cicero, Tusculan
Disputations, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, Mass., 1960) 55.
16
A brief but incisive treatment of some rhetorical aspects of the Tusculanae can be found in Douglas (above,
n.7) 197-218.
17
For a concise summary of the linear composition, see Muller (above, n.13) 47-48.
18
Muller (above, n.13) 49-50.
19
Tusc I.55-56.
20
Cf. Rep I.28.
21
Tusc V.57: ‘Atqui de hoc homine a bonis auctoribus sic scriptum accepimus, summam fuisse eius in victu
temperantiam in rebusque gerundis virum acrem et industrium.’ Douglas (above, n.7) 248-49, King (above, n.15)
483.
22
Tusc V.63.
23
Tusc V.62.
24
Tusc V.17: ‘Quodsi est qui vim fortunae, qui omnia humana, quaecumque accidere possunt, tolerabilia ducat,
ex quo nec timor eum nec angor attingat, idemque si nihil concupiscat, nulla ecferatur animi inani voluptate,
quid est cur is non beatus sit? et si haec virtute efficiuntur, quid est cur virtus ipsa per se non efficiat beatos?’
Douglas (above, n.7) 216-17, King (above, n.15) 443.
25
Cf. the remark of the auditor and Cicero’s decision to continue his argument in Tusc V.17-18.
26
Cicero refers thrice to the story of the two Pythagoreans: De finibus II.24.79, De officiis III.10.45 and in the
Tusculanae, which seems to be the first mentioning.
27
Tusc V.63: ‘Quam huic erat miserum carere consuetudine amicorum, societate victus, sermone omnino
familiari, homini praesertim docto a puero et artibus ingenuis erudito.’ Douglas (above, n.7) 255, King (above,
n.15) 489.
28
Tusc V.63: ‘Omni cultu et victu humano carebat; vivebat cum fugitivis, cum facinerosis, cum barbaris;
neminem, qui aut libertate dignus esset aut vellet omnino liber esse, sibi amicum arbitrabatur.’ Douglas (above,
n.7) 256, King (above, n.15) 491.
29
Otto Seel, Cicero. Wort – Staat – Welt. Stuttgart 1953) 258-59. Karl Büchner, Cicero. Bestand und Wandel
seiner geistigen Welt. (Heidelberg 1964) 321-22.
30
Manfred Fuhrmann, Cicero and the Roman Republic. (Oxford 1990) 144.
31
Fam IX.20.1: ‘Nam omnem nostram de re publica curam, cogitationem de dicenda in senatu sententia,
commentationem causarum abiecimus, in Epicuri nos, adversarii nostri, castra coiecimus.’ Latin text and English
translation according to D.R. Shackleton Bailey, Cicero. Letters to Friends, 3 Vols. , Loeb Classical Library
(Cambridge, Mass., 2001) vol. II 214-15.
32
This link of Dionysios with Caesar and the dedication to Brutus has been made before by Winfried Schindler,
“Die Erzählung vom Damokles-Schwert-eine lateinische Parabel ? : Cicero : Tusculanen V 61-62.” in Der
Altsprachliche Unterricht 37.6 (1994) 71-79, in which it is connected to a second manner of hermeneutic
reading, characterized as the Brechtian way: 75-78. The writer even wants to read the Damocles-episode as an
exhortation to murder the tyrant, which may be attractive in reading the passage with scholars, but which forces
the otherwise interesting treatment of the theme a trifle too much.
33
Tusc V.64-66: ‘Ex eadem urbe humilem homunculum a pulvere et radio excitabo, qui multis annis post fuit,
Archimedem. Cuius ego quaestor ignoratum ab Syracusenis, cum esse omnino negarent, saeptum undique et
vestitum vepribus et dumetis indagavi sepulcrum. ... Ita nobilissima Graeciae civitas, quondam vero etiam
doctissima, sui civis unius acutissimi monumentum ignorasset, nisi ab homine Arpinate didicisset.’ Douglas
(above, n.7) 256-58, King (above, n.15) 491-93.
34
Tusc V.68-72.
35
Tusc V.68: ‘unus in cognitione rerum positus et in explicatione naturae, alter in discriptione expetendarum
fugiendarumque rerum et in ratione vivendi, tertius in iudicando, quid cuique rei sit consequens, quid repugnans,
in quo inest omnis cum subtilitas disserendi, tum veritas iudicandi.’ Douglas (above, n.7) 259-60, King (above,
n.15) 495.
15
36
Tusc V.70-71: ‘illa a deo Delphis praecepta cognitio, ut ipsa se mens adgnoscat coniunctamque cum divina
mente se sentiat, ex quo insatiabili gaudio compleatur.’ Douglas (above, n.7) 262, King (above, n.15) 496.
37
Tusc V.72: ‘Sed haec otii. Transeat idem iste sapiens ad rem publicam tuendam. Quid eo possit esse
praestantius, cum contineri prudentia utilitatem civium cernat, iustitia nihil in suam domum inde derivet, reliquis
utatur tot tam variisque virtutibus? Adiunge fructum amicitiarum, in quo doctis positum est cum consilium
omnis vitae consentiens et paene conspirans, tum summa iucunditas e cotidiano cultu atque victus usu.’ Douglas
(above, n.7) 264, King (above, n.15) 499.
38
Tusc V.73-118.
39
Tusc V.118: ‘Mihi quidem in vita servanda videtur illa lex quae in Graecorum conviviis obtinetur: “Aut
bibat,” inquit, “aut abeat.” Et recte. Aut enim fruatur aliquis pariter cum aliis voluptate potandi aut, ne sobrius in
violentiam vinolentorum incidat, ante discedat. Sic iniurias fortunae quas ferre nequeas defugiendo relinquas.’
Douglas (above, n.7) 302, King (above, n.15) 543-45.
40
Tusc V.121: ‘In quo quantum ceteris profuturi simus non facile dixerim, nostris quidem acerbissimis doloribus
variisque et undique circumfusis molestiis alia nulla potuit inveniri levatio.’ Douglas (above, n.7) 304, King
(above, n.15) 546.
16