Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 40
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS
EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY
RECENSIONS
Abstract
Dionysius Exiguus composed the earliest known computistical formulary written in Latin in . However, this formulary has not survived
in its original form. The editors of Dionysius’ computistical writings,
Wilhelm Jan and Bruno Krusch, published a corpus of argumenta
from a single manuscript, namely MS Oxford, Bodleian Library,
Digby under Dionysius’ name, since this was the only manuscript
known to them that preserved the original dating. Some of these
argumenta, however, contain dating clauses as late as , which
immediately cast doubt on their ascription to Dionysius. In fact, the
argumenta edited by Jan and Krusch should more precisely be
defined as a computistical formulary of , to be termed the Computus Digbaeanus of , which includes the original Dionysiac argumenta. This article, then, reconstructs the original Dionysiac corpus
on the basis of new manuscript evidence. Moreover, the different
stages of interpolations and additions that eventually led to the composition of the Computus Digbaeanus are analysed, and with this the
development of computistical formularies written in Latin in the
years from to .
Keywords
Dionysius Exiguus, Cassiodorus, Maximus Confessor, Bede, Hrabanus
Maurus, history of computus, computistical formularies, computistical
argumenta, Computus paschalis of , Computus Digbaeanus of ,
Computus Cottonianus of /, Computus Rhenanus of , Fragmentum Nanciacense, Sirmond manuscript, Irish computistics, AngloSaxon computistics, Frankish computistics.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 41
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Introduction
In the early centuries of Christianity, the West and the East followed
different Easter cycles, which led to conflicting dates for Easter Sunday
and continuous disputes between Rome and Alexandria.1 An attempt
to reconcile the two systems had failed in the mid-fifth century, when
Victorius of Aquitaine was order by the papal curia to establish an
Easter table that would solve the differences.2 Victorius’ system was
finally approved in Rome, and it became very popular in the West,
especially the Frankish kingdoms,3 but his decision to list two possible
dates for Easter Sunday in certain years did not solve the problem,
while even his unambiguous dates did not always correspond to the
Alexandrian ones.4 Then, in , Easter Sunday was supposed to fall
on luna according to Victorius,5 which was regarded as an unacceptable lunar age in the Alexandrian reckoning. It was presumably for
that reason that the papal curia decided in the previous year, , to
contact Dionysius Exiguus about this question.6 By this time, Dionysius had made a name for himself as a canonist and translator from
Greek into Latin,7 and it probably was precisely his reputation as
1 For the early history of the Easter controversy (technical and historical) see
Krusch (); Schwartz (); Mac Carthy (), xxxii–clxxvii; Ideler (–),
ii –; Schmid (); Ginzel (), –, –; Rühl (), –; Gentz
in PW , – (s.v. Ostern); Chaîne (), –; Jones (), –; Strobel
(); Wallis (), xxxiv–l; Declercq (), –; van de Vyver (); Grumel
(); Lejbowicz (), –.
2 Victorius’ Easter table and prefixed prologue are edited by Krusch (), –.
For the Victorian reckoning see Ideler (–), ii –; Schwartz (), –;
Ginzel (), –; Rühl (), –; Jones (), –; Wallis (), l–lii;
Declercq (), –; Declercq (), –.
3 The most explicit source for the adoption of the Victorian system can be found
for the Frankish kingdoms in form of the Acts of the Council of Orleans of (Concilium Aurelianense a. §: CCSL A, ; MGH Conc. , ): Placuit itaque Deo
propitio, ut sanctum pascha secundum laterculum Victori ab omnibus sacerdotibus uno
tempore celebretur. For the adoption and use of the Victorian system in the Latin West
see Krusch (); Poole (a); Schmid (), –; Jones (), –; Jones
(), –.
4 For the differences between the two systems see especially Schwartz (),
–; Ginzel (), ; Jones (), –.
5
Krusch (), .
6 Cf. Krusch (), –; Krusch (), ; Ginzel (), ; Jones (), ;
Jones (), ; Borst (), ; Wallis (), liii; Declercq (), –;
Declercq (), –.
7 For Dionysius’ life and work see Jülicher in PW , – (s.v. Dionysius
Exiguus); Mordek in LM , – (s.v. Dionysius Exiguus). For Dionysius’ origin
being Alexandrian/ Egyptian rather than Scythian see Zeller (), –.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 42
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
translator that persuaded the papal curia to ask for his help: In the end,
the task to be accomplished was to translate the Alexandrian Easter
table and instructions from Greek into Latin.8 Dionysius composed
his computistical works in two stages, and it is only the first that will
concern us here:9 ) He translated, converted, transformed, and continued the -year Easter table of Cyril of Alexandria for the subsequent -year period, from to , providing a manual for this
table in a prologue addressed to an unidentified bishop Petronius, and
adding a Latin translation of the letter of Proterius and a series of argumenta. ) After Dionysius had accomplished this task, the letter of
Paschasinus was found in the papal library, which made the papal curia
wonder about the workings of the -year lunisolar-cycle. Again, they
consulted Dionysius about this problem, and his reply in form of a letter of marks the second stage.
Now, the focus of the present article is on the above-mentioned
argumenta that Dionysius attached to his Easter table. Dionysius
introduced them in his prologue in the following way:10
Nec non et argumenta Aegyptiorum sagacitate quaesita subdidimus, quibus,
si forsitan ignorentur, paschales tituli possint facile repperiri; id est, quotus
annus sit ab incarnatione domini et quae sit indictio, quotus etiam lunaris
circulus, decennovenalis existat ceteri aeque simili supputationis compendio
requirentur.
‘We have also supplied argumenta, which we obtained through the
acuteness of the Egyptians, with whose aid the data of the columns of the
Easter table can easily be found, should they perhaps not be known;
namely, the year which happens to be from the incarnation of the Lord,
and which indiction this year happens to have, and also which year in the
cyclus lunaris and decemnovennalis it happens to be; and the data of the
other columns should likewise be sought by similar computational
methods.’
It is very unfortunate that Dionysius mentions only four argumenta
explicitly in this paragraph and does not supply the reader with a
comprehensive list. Such a list of all argumenta compiled by
Dionysius in would have saved modern scholars much trouble,
Cf. Neugebauer (), –; Neugebauer ().
Dionysius’ computistical writings were edited by Jan (), republished in
PL , –, and by Krusch (), –.
10 Krusch (), . The translation is mine. A different translation of this passage
can be found in Teres (), .
8
9
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 43
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
since the manuscript transmission of these argumenta is not
straightforward. Only two modern editions of them exist, one published by Wilhelm Jan in , the other by Bruno Krusch in ;11
both scholars edited these argumenta on the basis of a single manuscript, namely MS Oxford, Bodleian library, Digby , because this
was the only manuscript known to them that preserved the dating. Yet, this corpus of argumenta published by Jan and Krusch
contains only nine with dating clauses for , whereas the remaining seven have either no or later dating clauses, the latest for .
Still, Jan, and Krusch following him, decided to publish the entire
corpus among the computistical works of Dionysius Exiguus. This
corpus of argumenta, preserved uniquely in MS Oxford,
Bodleian Library, Digby , v–r, will be referred to as the Computus Digbaeanus of in the following.12
The Computus Digbaeanus is one of the earliest known corpora
of computistical formulae and / or short texts (which I will term a
computistical formulary in the following) written in Latin. The earliest is, in fact, the original corpus of the Dionysiac argumenta.
Unfortunately, the Dionysiac corpus has not survived in its original
form. The only other known formulary from the sixth century is the
so-called Computus paschalis of , controversially attributed to
Cassidorus.13 This formulary seems to be nothing but original
Dionysiac argumenta with the examples being accommodated to
match the chronological data of . Consequently, the Computus
paschalis of transmits valuable information about the extent of
the original Dionysiac corpus. From the entire seventh century, the
Computus Digbaeanus of and the so-called Computus Cottonianus of / are the only known formularies.14 Interestingly
See n .
For this text see pp. – below.
13 For this text see p. below.
14 For the Computus Cottonianus see pp. – below. Some of the argumenta of the
Computus Cottonianus with seventh-century dating clauses found their way into the
Computus Rhenanus of and from there into the tenth century Canones lunarium
decemnovennalium circulorum (cf. pp. –, especially n below). Other than that,
I am presently aware of only one further manuscript that contains argumenta with
seventh-century dating clauses, namely MS München, Bayerische Staatsbibliothek,
Clm : a section on folio r-v consists of the Dionysiac Argumenta I, II, V, and
VIII with explicit dating clauses for . These should be compared with the Computus Cottonianus and the Computus Rhenanus. The three argumenta of the Fragmentum
Nanciacense with dating clauses for were later incorporated into the Computus
Digbaeanus and are discussed in that context below (cf. pp. –, , ).
11
12
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 44
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
enough, the Computus Digbaeanus includes all the argumenta of the
original Dionysiac corpus, as far as can be established, and consequently also of the Computus paschalis; in fact, it preserves all
known argumenta with dating clauses for or earlier. Therefore, a
study of the Computus Digbaeanus actually results in a study of the
development of computistical formularies written in Latin over the
first years, i.e. from to .
Additionally, the Computus Digbaeanus marks a watershed in the
development of computistical formularies: The number of only
argumenta preserved in the Computus Digbaeanus is an impressive
witness to the slow process of development in this field over the first
years. However, this process accelerated rapidly in the last quarter
of the seventh century and then especially in the eighth and ninth centuries, a development in which the Computus Digbaeanus played a
major part: It had opened up the Dionysiac corpus which was previously strictly defined. This allowed further formulae and texts to be
added to that corpus, which were invented in considerable numbers
once the Dionysiac reckoning was introduced into Ireland and Britain,
and later into the Frankish kingdoms. In this process the original
Dionysiac argumenta lost their attribution and thus their authoritative
connotation, which led to them being revised either by the addition of
further explanations, or by generalisation; due to this revision they lost
their original phrasing and shape, while the corpus itself disintegrated
with selected argumenta being incorporated in larger computistical
formularies or compendia.
It is the purpose of this article, then, to analyse the different stages
in the development of computistical formularies before this significant
change occurred, i.e. in the years between and , by means of
examining the different layers of the Computus Digbaeanus. For this, it
is at first necessary to introduce the argumenta of the Computus
Digbaeanus at some length as the basis of discussion, and at the same
time the final stage of the development in question. The starting point
of this development, i.e. the original corpus of Dionysiac argumenta,
is, however, highly disputed. The different views on this first computistical formulary in Latin will be reviewed, before an attempt is made
to reconstruct that corpus. From that basis it will be possible to trace
the intermediary stages in the development from the original corpus of
Dionysiac argumenta of to the Computus Digbaeanus of . Concerning terminology, of the argumenta in question, the ones that are
likely to have been compiled by Dionysius himself are termed the
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 45
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Dionysiac argumenta,15 the ones that were later added are called the
pseudo-Dionysiac argumenta.
Description of the Computus Digbaeanus of
The Computus Digbaeanus of comprises folios v–r of the
ninth-century MS Oxford, Bodleian Library, Digby ; its provenance
is highly disputed.16 The beginning of this computus is well defined,
starting in the lower quarter of folio v, with the rest of the page
being left blank. Moreover, a title is given: Incipiunt argumenta de titulis pascalis egiptiorum investigata solercia ut praesentes indicent. The
end of this computus, however, can less easily be established. Jan and
Krusch in their editions believed that the Disputatio Morini, starting
on folio r, marked the end, arguing that this computus comprises
argumenta. But it should be noted that at least the inclusion of
Argumentum XVI is debatable, since it is the only one of these that
has a separate heading (De racione bissexti), and may thus have been
regarded as an independent treatise. The argumenta in question
have often been described, but the mathematical formulae have not
yet been satisfactorily explained in print.17 A proper understanding of
these argumenta is, however, vital for their assessment:
Argumentum I is divided into three paragraphs, of which only the first
is printed in the main body of the editions;18 § gives a formula for
15 This article will not assess the question whether Dionysius is rightly credited
with the composition of these argumenta, or whether he should only be credited with
their translation, which certainly is a matter of debate. From the citation given above
it seems, however, that Dionysius acted merely as translator. For this question see especially Neugebauer (); Pallarès (), ; Declercq (), –.
16 Cf. Dumville (), ; Dumville (); Ó Cróinín (b), ; Ó Cróinín
(d), –. For catalogue descriptions of this MS see Hunt and Watson (),
–; Lindsay (), ; Krusch (), –; Jones (), ; Borst (), –;
Borst (), –. See also Englisch (), .
17 For discussions and mathematical notations of these argumenta see Springsfeld
(), – (which is sometimes faulty); Neugebauer () (where Argumenta
I–VI, VIII–XI are explained as part of the Computus paschalis of ); Pedersen (),
(who only treats Argumenta II–V). The Latin text of these argumenta with English
and German translation respectively, as well as valuable mathematical commentary, is
provided by Michael Deckers and Nikolaus A. Bär on the world wide web: http://hbar
.phys.msu.su/gorm/chrono/paschata.htm and http://www.nabkal.de/dionys.html.
18 §: Krusch (), ll. –; § : Krusch (), variant c ll. – (ending with
conputa); §: Krusch (), variant c ll. – (starting with item ad aliam).
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 46
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
calculating the AD date from the indiction; the example given is
AD , the general formula:
⫻⫹⫹indiction of the present year⫽AD
It is composed of the following parameters: the fixed parameter indicates the number of years from Christ’s incarnation to the end of an
indiction cycle (AD ⫽Indiction ); from AD to AD another
indiction cycles have passed, hence ⫻; thus, the indiction of any
given year between and added to the sum ⫹⫻ equals the
number of years from the incarnation to the year in question.
It is obvious that the number of full indiction cycles between
AD and the year in question increases by one every years, and the
formula has to be adjusted accordingly, namely by increasing the multiplicand in the product ⫻ by one every years (e.g. is replaced
by in ). This provision is taken in §§ and , which are
omitted in Jan’s edition, and relegated to the apparatus in Krusch’s.19
Note that in a year with indiction either this number can be added
as the indiction of the present year or the multiplicand with can be
increased by one, which leaves indiction for the present year; the latter option is chosen in §.
Argumentum II gives a formula for calculating the indiction from the
AD date; the example given is AD , the general formula:
(AD⫹)mod⫽indiction (y mod z denotes the remainder after
division of y by z)
The fixed parameter is chosen because it is obviously necessary for
this calculation that the count of years starts with the beginning of an
indiction cycle; AD , however, has indiction , so another are added
to the AD date (BC ⫽indiction ); the modulo calculation, then,
eliminates all full indiction cycles, with the remainder being the indiction of the AD date in question.
Argumentum III is divided into two paragraphs.20 § gives a formula
for calculating the epact, i.e. the lunar age of March, from the AD
date; the example given is AD , the general formula:
(ADmod⫻)mod⫽epact
The logic behind this calculation is this: BC is the first year of a cyclus
decemnovennalis (i.e. the -year luni-solar cycle underlying the
Dionysiac reckoning); consequently, the remainder of the AD date
19
For these two paragraphs see the previous note and the discussion on pp. –
below.
20 §: Krusch (), ll. –; §: Krusch (), l. – l. .
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 47
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
divided by (ADmod) equals the number of years from the first
year of the cyclus decemnovennalis in which this AD date occurs; since
the first year of the cyclus decemnovennalis has epact , and since the
epact increases by per year in this -year cycle, ADmod is multiplied by ; the modulo calculation then eliminates all intercalated
lunar months of days, with the remainder being the epact of the
year in question.
§ gives a formula for calculating the epacts from the year in the
cyclus decemnovennalis;21 the examples given are the th and th year of
the cyclus decemnovennalis, neither of which agrees with AD , since
cyclic number corresponds to ⫹n⫻; the formula is:
((year in the cyclus decemnovennalis⫺)⫻)mod⫽epact
The logic is the same as for the formula in §: the first year of the cyclus
decemnovennalis has epact , hence the subtraction of ; the epact
increases by per year in this -year cycle, hence the multiplicand ;
the modulo calculation then eliminates the intercalated lunar
months of days.
Argumentum IV is also divided into two paragraphs.22 § gives a formula for calculating the concurrentes, i.e. the weekday of March,
from the AD date; the example given is AD , the formula:
(AD⫹[AD/]⫹)mod⫽concurrentes ([y] denotes the greatest
integer less than or equal to y)
The logic behind this formula is this: AD has concurrentes ; since the
concurrentes increase by one every year, the number of years from AD
(AD⫺) are added to the concurrentes of that year (), resulting in
AD⫺⫹⫽AD⫹; hence the parameter ; every fourth year, however,
the concurrentes increases by instead of due to the bissextile day,
hence the parameter [AD/] (i.e. an extra day is added for every fourth
year); since the concurrentes denote a weekday, and therefore never
exceed , the modulo calculation is then applied, with the remainder
being the concurrentes in question.
§ intended to simplify the calculation by counting the years not
from the incarnation, but from the year following the consulship of
Tiberius Iunior Augustus.23 It is argued that the fixed parameter had
then to be changed from to , thereby implying that the first year of
the new count has concurrentes . Moreover, since no parameter is
For this paragraph see pp. – below.
§: Krusch (), ll. –; §: Krusch (), ll. –.
23 For this paragraph see p. below.
21
22
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 48
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
added to the number of years to be divided by , the first year of the
new count has to be the first year in a four-year bissextile cycle, i.e. a
year immediately following a bissextile year. These chronological data
match AD .
Argumentum V gives a formula for calculating the year in the cyclus
decemnovennalis from the AD date; the example given is AD , the
formula:
(AD⫹)mod⫽year in the cyclus decemnovennalis
The fixed parameter is chosen, since it was obviously necessary for
this calculation that the count of years starts with the first year of a
cyclus decemnovennalis; AD , however, is the second year in such a
cycle, and thus is added to the AD date (BC ⫽first year in the cyclus
decemnovennalis); the modulo calculation, then, eliminates all full
-year cycles, with the remainder being the year in the cyclus decemnovennalis in question.
Argumentum VI gives a formula for calculating the year in the cyclus
lunaris from the AD date; the example given is AD , the formula:
(AD⫺)mod⫽year in the cyclus lunaris
Again, the count of years obviously has to start with the first year of a
cyclus lunaris; hence the fixed parameter ⫺, since a cyclus lunaris does
not start in AD , but two years later, in AD ; the modulo calculation the, eliminates all full -year cycles, with the remainder being the
year in the cyclus lunaris in question.
Argumentum VII lists the seven years of the cyclus decemnovennalis, in
which the Easter full moon falls in March; in the remaining twelve, the
Easter full moon falls in April.
Argumentum VIII gives a formula for establishing whether or not a
year is bissextile, calculated from its AD date; the example given is
AD , the formula:
ADmod⫽y; if y⫽, then AD is bissextile
The logic behind this formula obviously is that every AD date divisible by is bissextile.
Argumentum IX can be divided into two paragraphs.24 § gives a
formula for calculating the lunar age of Easter Sunday from the epact
and the Julian calendar date of Easter Sunday; the two examples given
are: ) a year with indiction , epact , Easter Sunday on March,
24
§: Krusch (), ll. –; §: Krusch (), ll. –.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 49
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
luna , and ) a year with indiction , epact , Easter Sunday on
April, luna ; these examples agree with AD and respectively;
the general formula is:
a) Easter Sunday falling on y March: (⫹epact⫹y)mod⫽lunar
age of Easter Sunday
b) Easter Sunday falling on z April: (⫹epact⫹z)mod⫽lunar
age of Easter Sunday
These two formulae can be explained in the following way:
a) If Easter Sunday falls on y March, then the Julian calendar day
difference between y March and March, the date of the
epact, equals the lunar day difference between the lunar age on
Easter Sunday and the epact; in mathematical terms:
y⫺⫽lunar age of Easter Sunday⫺epact; this is equivalent to
y⫺⫹epact⫽lunar age of Easter Sunday; since the lunar age of
Easter Sunday ranges between and , this is equivalent to
(⫺⫹epact⫹y)mod⫽lunar age of Easter Sunday; since
(⫺)mod⬅mod, the equation is equivalent to (⫹
epact⫹y)mod⫽lunar age of Easter Sunday.
b) If Easter Sunday falls on z April, then the Julian calendar day
difference between z April and March, the date of the epact,
is congruent modulo to the lunar day difference between the
lunar age on Easter Sunday and the epact (the modulo congruence is necessary here, since the epact and the lunar age of
Easter Sunday may occur in two successive lunations, with the
lunation ending between them consisting of lunar days);
in mathematical terms: (z⫹)mod⬅(lunar age of Easter
Sunday⫺epact)mod; this is equivalent to (z⫹⫹epact)
mod⬅(lunar age of Easter Sunday)mod; since the lunar age
of Easter Sunday naturally ranges between and , this leads to
the equation (z⫹⫹epact)mod⫽lunar age of Easter Sunday.
§ then seems to supply a confused explanation of the parameters
and fixed for March and April respectively.25
Argumentum X can also be divided into two paragraphs.26 § gives a
formula for calculating the weekday of any given Julian calendar date
25
26
Cf. pp. – below.
§: Krusch (), ll. –; §: Krusch (), ll. –.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 50
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
from the concurrentes of that year; the example given is a year with
indiction , concurrentes , and Easter Sunday on April; these data
agree with AD ; the general formula is:
Let y be the inclusive number of days from January to the Julian
calendar date in question; then (y⫹⫹concurrentes)mod⫽weekday of
that Julian calendar date.
This equation can be explained in the following way: Let z be the
weekday on January in the year in question; y⫺ denotes the exclusive number of days from January to the Julian calendar date in question; then (z⫹y⫺)mod⫽weekday of the Julian calendar date in
question; the exclusive number of days from January to the place of
the concurrentes, March, is , and since mod⫽, (z⫹)
mod⫽concurrentes; this is equivalent to z⫽(concurrentes⫺)mod,
which is equivalent z⫽(concurrentes⫹)mod (since ⫺mod⬅
mod); now, substituting z in the equation above with this result
leads to (concurrentes⫹y⫹)mod⫽weekday of the Julian calendar
date in question.
§ then explicitly states that this formula can be applied for any
given Julian calendar date of a year.
Argumentum XI gives a formula for calculating the epact from the AD
date; the example given is AD , the formula:
(ADmod⫻)mod⫽epact
The formula is exactly the same as in Argumentum III above.
Argumentum XII gives a formula for calculating the weekday of January
from the AD date; the example given is , the formula:
(AD⫺⫹[(AD⫺)/])mod⫽weekday on January
The method of this argumentum is basically the same as in Argumentum IV, with some important variations: The weekday of January
increases by one every year; hence the number of years from AD
(AD⫺) are added to the weekday on January of AD , which is
feria ; in every bissextile year the weekday increases by instead of ;
the bissextile day occurs in every AD divisible by ; but since the bissextile day occurs after January, the two day increase on that date
happens only in the following year; hence the parameter [(AD⫺)/],
which provides for an extra day being added for the years following a
bissextile year; since weekdays never exceed , the modulo calculation
is applied, which leads to the equation: (AD⫺⫹⫹[(AD⫺)/])
mod⫽weekday on January; since mod⬅mod, this is equivalent to (AD⫺⫹[(AD⫺)/])mod⫽weekday on January.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 51
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Argumentum XIII gives a formula for calculating the lunar age of January
from the year in the cyclus lunaris; the two examples given are the th
and th year of the cyclus lunaris, having luna and on January
respectively; these data do not agree with AD , but with AD and
, as will be seen further below; the general formula is:
(⫹year in the cyclus lunaris⫻⫹year in the cyclus lunaris⫻)
mod⫽luna on January
In years to of the cyclus lunaris the fixed parameter has to be
increased by from to .
The logic is this: The th year of the cyclus lunaris has luna on
January, hence the parameter ; the lunar age increases by per year,
here divided into the multiplicands and ; the modulo calculation
is then applied to eliminate all intercalated lunar months of days;
the saltus lunae occurs at the end of the th year of the cyclus lunaris,
which results in an increase of instead of lunar days between the
th and the th year; for that reason the fixed parameter is increased by
one for the three years following the saltus lunae.
Moreover, the period of time between the beginning of the first hour
of a day and moonrise is given in points for both dates (i.e. January of
the th and of the th year of the cyclus lunaris); this is discussed in detail
in Appendix II.
Argumentum XIV gives a formula for calculating the Julian calendar date
and weekday of the Easter full moon, as well as the Julian calendar date
and lunar age of Easter Sunday, from the epact and concurrentes of a given
year; the three examples outlined are the first three years of the cyclus
decemnovennalis (having epacts , , and ); the concurrentes assigned to
these years are , , and respectively, with the lunar and solar data
combined agreeing with AD to . The general formula is:
a) Easter full moon in March: ⫺epact⫽y March for Easter full
moon
(y⫹concurrentes⫹)mod⫽weekday of Easter full moon
b) Easter full moon in April: (⫺epact)mod⫽z April for Easter
full moon
(z⫹concurrentes⫹)mod⫽weekday of Easter full moon
With this information it was simple to calculate the Julian calendar
date and lunar age of Easter Sunday, which occurred on the Sunday
following the Easter full moon.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 52
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
The two formulae can be explained in the following way:
a) If the Easter full moon occurs on y March, then the Julian cal-
endar day difference between y March and March, the date
of the epact, equals the lunar day difference between the Easter
full moon (luna ) and the epact; in mathematical terms:
y⫺⫽⫺epact; this is equivalent to y⫽⫺epact, the first
part of the formula; then, the Julian calendar difference between
the Easter full moon (y March) and the place of the concurrentes
( March) is congruent modulo to the weekday difference
between the weekday of the Easter full moon and the concurrentes (the modulo congruence is necessary here, since the
weekday of the Easter full moon and the concurrentes may occur
in different weeks); in mathematical terms: (y⫺)mod⬅
(weekday of Easter full moon⫺concurrentes)mod; since
⫺mod⬅mod this is equivalent to (y⫹concurrentes⫹)
mod⬅(weekday of Easter full moon)mod; since the weekday
of the Easter full moon naturally ranges between and , this
leads to the equation (y⫹concurrentes⫹)mod⫽weekday of
Easter full moon, the second part of the formula.
b) If the Easter full moon occurs on z April, then the Julian calendar day difference between z April and March, the day of the
epact, is congruent modulo to the lunar day difference
between the Easter full moon (luna ) and the epact (the
modulo congruence is necessary here, since the epact and the
Easter full moon may occur in two successive lunations, with
the lunation ending between them consisting of lunar days);
in mathematical terms: (z⫹)mod⬅(⫺epact)mod; this
is equivalent to zmod⬅(⫺epact)mod; since z naturally
does not exceed (it ranges between and ) and mod⬅
mod, this leads to the equation z⫽(⫺epact)mod, the
first part of the formula; then, the Julian calendar day difference
between the Easter full moon (z April) and the place of the concurrentes ( March) is congruent modulo to the weekday difference between the Easter full moon and the concurrentes
(again, the modulo congruence is necessary here, since the
weekday of the Easter full moon and the concurrentes do certainly occur in different weeks); in mathematical terms:
(z⫹)mod⬅(weekday of Easter full moon⫺concurrentes)
mod; this is equivalent to (y⫹concurrentes⫹)mod⬅(weekday of Easter full moon)mod; since the weekday of the Easter
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 53
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
full moon naturally ranges between and , this leads to the
equation (x⫹concurrentes⫹)mod⫽weekday of Easter full
moon, the second part of the formula.
Argumentum XV describes the correspondence of the Roman
equinoxes and solstices with the conception and birth of Christ and of
John the Baptist, as well as with the passion of Christ. Moreover, it
gives a chronology of Christ’s life.
Argumentum XVI explains the bissextile increase of one point (defined
as a quarter of an hour) per month, amounting to hours in four
years (i.e. the hours of daytime). Moreover, it gives a curious mathematical explanation for the alledged hours bissextile increase per
year by dividing the hours of a year by , leaving a remainder of
just these hours.27
Previous Views on the Original Corpus of the
Dionysiac Argumenta
Which of these argumenta, then, can be classified as Dionysiac, i.e. as
belonging to the original corpus of argumenta compiled by Dionysius
Exiguus himself? Scholarly opinion on this important question varies
greatly:
The discussion about the Dionysiac argumenta really started with the
editio princeps of the Computus Digbaeanus by Wilhelm Jan in ,
which is a model of scholarship for its time, and still the best edition of
Dionysiac computistica available. He justified the ascription of these
argumenta to Dionysius in detail,28 but at the same time emphasized that
some of the argumenta published by him on the basis of the Computus Digbaeanus of (which he checked with the Computus Cottonianus
of /) appear to be later additions, while others appear to contain
later interpolations.29 About this pseudo-Dionysiac section he was
then more specific in the notes to each argumentum. Jan generally
applied four criteria to distinguish Dionysiac from pseudo-Dionysiac
argumenta:30 ) Agreement with the columns of the Dionysiac
27 For this calculation see especially Springsfeld (), ; Springsfeld (),
. Cf. also pp. – below.
28 Jan (), –.
29
Jan (), –.
30 Jan (), , –.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 54
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
Easter table; ) the reception of the argumenta by early medieval
computists, primarily Bede; ) the transmission of the argumenta;
) internal textual evidence, including dating clauses given in the examples. The strongest of these criteria obviously is the fourth: nine of the
first ten argumenta include examples that refer either explicitly to the year
(which is also the year mentioned in Dionysius’ prologue), or implicitly, with the chronological data corresponding to that year. The only
argumentum among the first ten that does not include a dating clause is
Argumentum VII. Interestingly enough, Jan did not comment on this
particular argumentum, and it must be presumed that he regarded it as
Dionysiac. Consequently, the first ten argumenta are Dionysiac according to Jan. Three of these, however, contained later interpolations:31
) Jan did not publish §§ and of Argumentum I, presumably because
he regarded them as later additions; unfortunately, he did not comment
on this omission, which appears strange considering the fact that these
paragraphs also appear in the Computus Cottonianus (albeit in accommodated and altered form), which Jan consulted for comparison; ) since §
of Argumentum III does not occur in the Computus Cottonianus, and
because it was introduced by the phrase Item aliud computum, Jan argued
that it was not part of the original argumentum; ) the same applies to §
of Argumentum IV, which is introduced by the phrase Item nuper inuentum, melius iudicaui, si breuiter patefiat, and which again does not appear
in the Computus Cottonianus; moreover, Jan thought that this paragraph
was not transmitted in full in his Leithandschrift; the mentioning of the
consulate of Tiberius Iunior Augustus combined with the chronological
data given led Jan to date this interpolation to c..32 In addition to these
three later additions, Jan was suspicious about § of Argumentum IX,
stating that it appears to be out of place here, but he left that problem for
others to solve.33
Concerning the remaining six argumenta, Jan restricted himself to a
general remark in a note on Argumentum XI rather than to comment on
each of these individually, apparently because he found them difficult
to understand:34 After outlining that this and the following argumentum transmit dating clauses for in the Computus Digbaeanus, for
Jan (), , –.
It seems quite probable that Jan did not establish this date himself, but simply
adopted the date written in a late hand in the margin to this paragraph in the manuscript (f r).
33 Jan (), .
34 Jan (), .
31
32
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 55
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
or in the Computus Cottonianus (i.e. one and a half centuries
later than the dating clauses found in the previous argumenta), he concluded very cautiously that these argumenta were either added or at
least emended by later computists.
The most detailed discussion about the authorship of these argumenta was written just years later by one of the most neglected scholars of late antique and early medieval computistics, Johannes van der
Hagen.35 Having no further manuscript evidence at hand, van der
Hagen based his study on Jan’s edition, which meant that he was not
aware of §§ and of Argumentum I. His approach is more textual and
mathematical, with the main new textual criterion introduced by him
being the question of the general format of an argumentum. It seems
that in his opinion an argumentum had to contain a mathematical formula. Consequently, he was very suspicious of every argumentum
among the in question that does not do so. Presumably on this
ground, he regarded Argumenta XV and XVI as pseudo-Dionysiac.
Concerning the only other argumentum of that sort, Argumentum VII,
he did not commit himself to an explicit statement of authorship. But
it appears that he regarded it as pseudo-Dionysiac, because it had no
formula, and because it appears out of place among argumenta that otherwise show very similar patterns. On this basis of structure he divided
the nine argumenta remaining of the ten classified by Jan as Dionysiac
into two groups: The first group consists of Argumenta I–VI and
VIII, for the reason that Argumentum I provides an algorithm for the
calculation of the AD date of a year, which is then used as the sole precondition for the formulae of all of remaingn six argumenta of this
group; in van der Hagen’s opinion this group is to be classified with certainty as Dionysiac, since the examples in all of these explicitly refer to
, i.e. the year in which Dionysius composed his prologue; concerning § of Argumenta III and IV, he agreed with Jan that they are later
interpolations, adding that § of Argumentum III does not fit into the
structure of the argumenta of this group, since the precondition in the
formula of this paragraph is the year of the cyclus decemnovennalis, not
the AD date; moreover, he dates § of Argumentum IV to the year .
The second group, then, consists of Argumenta IX and X. Since these
also have dating clauses for (though only implicit ones), van der
Hagen argues that videntur etiam esse Dionysii. His hesitance in
attributing them to Dionysius stems from the fact that these two
35
Van der Hagen (), –.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 56
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
argumenta do not share the structure of the previous ones, i.e. that their
precondition is not the AD date.
In contrast to Jan, van der Hagen discussed in detail the six argumenta that Jan had classified as pseudo-Dionysiac. First he treated
Argumenta XI and XII together, accepting Jan’s classification as pseudoDionysiac on the basis of the examples explicitly referring to the year
, while adding that Argumentum XI deals with a question that had
already been discussed in Argumentum III, namely the calculation of
the epact of a given year. He then connected Argumentum XIII with
Maximus Confessors’ Computus ecclesiasticus rather than Dionyisus’
works, a very interesting observation that has escaped the notice of later
scholars.36 Turning to Argumentum XIV, he argued that it might have
been composed by Dionyisus himself, because the chronological data
given agree with the years –; but since these are the first three
years of the Dionysiac Easter table, van der Hagen thought that these
examples may as likely have been composed by a later computist, who
found these three years suitable to illustrate his calculations. Finally, he
regarded Argumenta XV and XVI as pseudo-Dionysiac, because they
simply did not constitute argumenta in his sense of the word.
In , Bartholomew Mac Carthy supported Jan’s and van der
Hagen’s view that Argumenta XI–XVI must be regarded as pseudoDionysiac by introducing new manuscript evidence. He drew attention to the MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Vat. Lat. , which
preserves a fragment of the Dionysiac argumenta, ending with the
explicit Finiunt argumenta paschalium titulorum after Argumentum X.37
Unfortunately, he did not compare this fragment with Jan’s edition,
and thus did not comment further on its implications on the corpus of
Dionysiac argumenta.
Despite this new manuscript evidence, Bruno Krusch decided to
republish the entire Computus Digbaeanus among Dionysius’
computistical works in . His edition, the latest and standard
edition to this day, must be regarded as inferior to Jan’s for various
reasons, among them the fact that he did not compare the text with
the Computus Cottonianus as Jan had done.38 Krusch did not discuss
the authorship of these argumenta, which leaves the reader with the
impression that the ascription to Dionysius is valid for all ,
For this connection see pp. , , – below.
Mac Carthy (), lvi. For the manuscript see pp. – below.
38 Cf. also the verdicts on these editions by Jones (), –; Pallarès (),
–; Wallis (), liii.
36
37
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 57
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
save for the passages and examples specified as interpolated or
accommodated, namely § of Argumentum IV (with Krusch arguing
for a date c.), and the examples given in Argumenta XI and XII.39
All this is very surprising considering the fact that Krusch was the
first to draw attention to the correspondence of the Computus
paschalis of attributed to Cassidorus with the first ten Dionysiac
argumenta, which only led him to an analysis of Cassiodorus’
authorship of the Computus paschalis, not of Dionysius’ authorship
of the argumenta.40 Moreover, Lehmann’s article on the Computus
paschalis, published in and including an edition of that text,41
must have been known to him and would have had provided him
with previously unknown manuscript witnesses.
Manuscript studies of computistical texts were then generally
brought to a new level by Charles W. Jones in the late s and early
s. Concerning the Dionysiac argumenta, he drew special attention
to two manuscripts from Mainz (now in the Vatican library: MSS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. and Pal. Lat. ), the Vatican manuscript introduced into the discussion by Mac Carthy, and
the so-called Sirmond manuscript, i.e. MS Oxford, Bodleian Library,
Bodley .42 Unfortunately, he never discussed the transmission of
the Dionysiac argumenta in these manuscripts in detail, nor did he test
his own views on them with van der Hagen’s thorough study, which he
knew.43 He simply and persistently argued that only the first nine
argumenta can be regarded as Dionysiac,44 which is fairly surprising,
since the first ten rather than nine appear as one body in every manuscript he had drawn attention to.45 An explanation for this opinion is
left wanting, and he never commented on possible later interpolations
within these nine argumenta. Nevertheless, his view was later accepted
39 Krusch (), (where he mistakenly places the mentioning of the consulship
of Tiberius Iunior Augustus in Argumentum VIII rather than Argumentum IV ), –.
40 Krusch (), –. For the Computus paschalis of see the following note
and p. below.
41 Lehmann (), reprinted in Lehmann (), with the section on the Computus paschalis on pp. –.
42 Jones (), , ; Jones (), –. Jones (), gives an extensive
list of MSS containing Dionysius’ computistical writings, stating at the end that the
Palatine MSS ‘provide valuable evidence about the argumenta’. Yet, of the three Palatine MSS listed by him only the two mentioned above contain the argumenta. For
these MSS see p. below.
43 Jones (), .
44 Jones (), , , .
45 Cf. Jones (), ; Jones (), , and pp. – below.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 58
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
by Wesley Stevens, Peter S. Baker and Michael Lapidge, Dan Mc
Carthy, and, as will be seen below, also by Joan Gómez Pallarès.46 Few
statements can be gathered about some of the argumenta Jones
regarded as pseudo-Dionysiac: For Argumentum XI he gave the same
reasoning as van der Hagen, arguing that it includes a dating clause for
, and that the problem of this argumentum (the calculation of the
epact) had already been dealt with in Argumentum III, and ‘Dionysius,
who is always most concise, would hardly have given two argumenta
for the same thing; had he done so, he would certainly have given
them together’;47 concerning Argumentum XIII he argues that it is a
‘complex and unsatisfactory’ tract originating in the seventh century.48
Consequently, Jones’ criteria for dismissing certain argumenta as
pseudo-Dionysiac primarily are the late dating clauses on the one
hand, the belief in Donysius’ competence, clarity and precision on the
other. The lack of the latter convinced Jones that Argumentum XVI
must be pseudo-Dionysiac;49 concerning Argumentum XIV he merely
stated that it is probably not Dionysiac, but ‘older than Bede’.50
In , Alfred Cordoliani compared the argumenta attributed to
Dionysius with the Computus paschalis and what he regarded as
the Computus Cottonianus.51 But since the focus of his study was on the
Computus Cottonianus, he did not comment on the authorship of
the other two texts.
Undoubtedly the mathematically most skilled scholar of computistics, Otto Neugebauer, was the first to use the Computus paschalis of
as evidence for the Dionysiac argumenta, in an article published in
.52 In his opinion, the Computus paschalis is nothing but a faithful
reproduction (‘a word-by-word copy’) of the original corpus of
Dionysiac argumenta, in which only the examples were accommodated to . Since the Computus paschalis comprises Argumenta I–VI
and VIII–X of the argumenta in question (and not all of them
completely), Neugebauer regarded these as the original corpus, to
which he seems to have added Argumentum XI. Considering that
46 Stevens (), , ; Baker and Lapidge (), xli; Mc Carthy (), –;
for Pallarès () cf. pp. –.
47 Jones (), .
48 Jones (), .
49 Jones (), .
50 Jones (), .
51 Cordoliani ().
52 Neugebauer (), especially .
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 59
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Argumentum XI does not appear in the Computus paschalis, that it
contains a dating clause for , and that the problem described in it
was already discussed in Argumentum III, the inclusion of this argumentum among the original Dionysiac corpus appears rather misguided. Neugebauer’s argument here seems to be that Argumentum XI
deals with ‘Easter computus’, while Argumenta VII, XII–XVI do not.53
This argument does not convince the reader, especially since Argumentum XIV, e.g., deals with the calculation of the Easter full moon and
Easter Sunday. His other arguments for not including Argumenta
XII–XVI among the original Dionysiac corpus are textual (different
style and different terminology compared to the previous ones).54 It
seems that Neugebauer was not aware of §§ and of Argumentum I,
since he worked from Jan’s edition of the text, but he quite rightly
stated that the chronological data of § of Argumentum III, which does
not appear in the Computus paschalis, agrees with the years and
.55 Concerning § of Argumentum IV, which does also not appear
in the Computus paschalis either, he argued that the mentioned consul
Tiberius Iunior Augustus has to be identified with the Byzantine
emperor Tiberius, who ruled from to . Hence, according to
Neugebauer the formula given in this paragraph was applicable to the
years counted from onwards, and was probably invented during
Tiberius’ reign. Yet, the altered formula does not work for years
counted from , so that Neugebauer’s interpretation must be
regarded as unlikely.56 § of Argumenta IX and X do not feature in
Neugebauer’s discussion.
In an article on Dionysius’ dating-system, Gustav Teres, using Jan’s
edition of the argumenta (which he mistakenly ascribes to Benjamin
Hoffman), seems not to have studied Jan’s notes in detail, since he
Neugebauer (), , , .
Neugebauer (), .
55 Neugebauer (), –.
56 Neugebauer’s argument ((), ) for the modification of the parameter in
the formula of § of Argumentum IV (which represents the concurrentes of AD ⫺) to
in § is the fact that ⬅mod. I do not understand the logic of Neugebauer’s
argument. If he meant that the weekday difference between AD and was , then
he calculated wrongly, not taking bissextile years into consideration. Anyway, the
parameter in § of Argumentum IV clearly indicates that the concurrentes in the first
year of the count were ; moreover, since no parameter is added to the number of years
to be divided by four, the first year of the count is supposed to be a year following a
bissextile year; both criteria do not agree with , the year given by Neugebauer, since
it was the second year after a bissextile year, having concurrentes . Cf. p. above and
p. below.
53
54
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 60
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
treated the entire corpus without distinction as originally Dionysiac.57
The only reason for this treatment appears to be the fact that these
argumenta are published among the works of Dionysius Exiguus,
which illustrates the risk an editor takes when publishing dubious
material among the original work of an author.
Dáibhí Ó Cróinín, in his edition of the Irish computistical
textbook De ratione conputandi, pointed out the fact that this textbook
and Argumentum XVI discussed similar concepts, which led him to
argue that this argumentum was ‘undoubtedly Insular’, ‘possibly Irish’
in origin.58
In , Joan Gómez Pallarès drew particular attention to the
Computus Cottonianus of / as an important witness for the
Dionysiac argumenta, as Jan had done in . This computus (at least
as published by Pallarès) contains the first of the argumenta in
question, none of which preserving the original dating clause of .
Pallarès edited the section of this computus in which these argumenta appear, comparing their readings with Jan’s and Krusch’s editions in that process.59 But this comparison of the Computus
Digbaeanus (i.e. the argumenta as published by Jan and Krusch) with
the Computus Cottonianus did not lead him to any conclusion about
the authorship of the argumenta in question. He simply followed Jones
in arguing that the first nine are authentic, because they incorporate a
dating clause () that agrees with Dionysius’ other writings; since the
same, according to Pallarès, cannot be said about the remaining argumenta, one should be careful with attributing these to the Scythian
monk.60 This argument obviously fails to convince, because the example in Argumentum X also refers to (though implicitly), and no
other reason is given why it should be excluded form the original corpus. Moreover, the differing chronological data in § of Argumenta III
and IV are not mentioned.
Arno Borst, in his book about the Carolingian calendar
reform, argued in passing that the argumenta incorporating dating
clauses for have to be attributed to Dionysius, while he located the
addition of § of Argumentum IV to Italy, dating it to , and the addition of arguably the last six argumenta to Ireland, dating it to .61
Teres (), especially –.
Walsh and Ó Cróinín (), , .
59 For the edition see Pallarès (), –. Cf. p. below.
60 Pallarès (), .
61 Borst (), .
57
58
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 61
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
In this view he is followed by Kerstin Springsfeld, who more
specifically stated that Argumenta I–X are Dionysiac because of their
dating clauses (save for § of Argumentum IV, which, according to her,
is datable to , and probably added to the corpus in Italy), the
remaining six, however, pseudo-Dionysiac, presumably composed in
Ireland in .62 She possibly saw confirmation for this view in the
manuscript evidence, since she was aware of two manuscripts that
transmitted Argumenta I to X as an entity, namely the Sirmond manuscript (MS Oxford, Boldeian Library, Bodley ) and MS Vatican,
Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. .63 Interestingly enough, Springsfeld observed that the chronological data in § of Argumentum III do
not agree with the year , but she did not draw the conclusion that
this section may not be Dionysiac.64 Concerning Argumentum XIV she
argued that it may have been Dionysiac, as the examples given agree
with –, basically repeating van der Hagen’s observation. The
only reason, in her opinion, that could speak against Dionysius’
authorship of this argumentum is that certain irregularities occur at the
end of it; yet, it should be noted that these irregularities only exist in
Krusch’s edition, not in the manuscript from which h worked.65 The
fact that she connected some of the concepts found in Argumenta XV
and XVI with Irish computistica may have convinced her to ascribed
the whole body of the last six argumenta to an Irish anonymous.66
As mentioned above, Faith Wallis had earlier, in , drawn special attention to the Sirmond manuscript for this question, arguing
62 Springsfeld (), –, the Irish origin of Argumentum XIV explicitly on
pp. , , , .
63 Cf. Springsfeld (), , . When discussing the Dionysiac argumenta,
she referred to Jones’ table of contents of the Sirmond manuscript (Springsfeld
(), ).
64 Springsfeld (), .
65 Springsfeld (), . Note that her argument here contradicts her statement
on pp. , , , that Argumentum XIV is of Irish provenance. The two irregularities in Argumentum XIV mentioned by Springsfeld are the following: ) It is argued
that the Julian calendar date of the Easter full moon falls on a certain, previously calculated number of days a Kalendis Januarii; but it is obvious from the context that the
calends of either March or April are meant, depending on the year in question; in fact,
Januarii is Krusch’s own (and wrong) addition, as he clearly indicates in the apparatus.
) It is argued that if the previously calculated number of days happens to be , then
the Easter full moon occurs XXX die Aprilis; this is obviously an impossible reading,
since the Easter full moon falls between March and April; in fact, Aprilis is
Krusch’s correction, as he clearly indicates in the apparatus; the manuscript gives the
correct a Kl (referring to the calends of March).
66 Springsfeld (), .
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 62
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
that the corpus of the first ten argumenta found in it has to be regarded
as Dionysiac, while disregarding the following Argumentum XIV as
pseudo-Dionysiac.67 Unfortunately, Wallis did not discuss these argumenta any further, and thus did not mention the chronological and
textual problems within these ten argumenta as outlined by Jan, van
der Hagen, and Neugebauer.
In recent years, the interest in the Dionysiac argumenta has led to
the reproduction of their text on the world wide web. On one of these
sites, Nikolaus Bär provided Krusch’s text with a German translation
and some commentary.68 In his Schlußbemerkung, he argues that only
the first nine argumenta formed the original Dionysiac corpus, and
among these § of Argumenta III, IV and IX represented later additions, without giving further details. He was more specific only in his
notes to § of Argumentum IV, repeating Krusch’s argument that this
addition must date from the year or later. It seems that his opinion
on the original corpus is a more detailed adoption of Jones’ view, and
thus equally unsatisfactory, especially in terms of Argumentum X,
whose implicit dating clause for is left unexplained.
The most differentiated treatment of this question since the days of
van der Hagen can be found in a brief note by George Declercq in his
article about the Dionysiac reckoning, published in .69 He followed
Neugebauer’s approach by arguing that the Computus paschalis of
represents the original corpus of Dionysiac argumenta (not adding Argumentum XI, as Neugebauer had done). He found confirmation for this
view in the fact that every single one of these argumenta, and no other
among the in question, includes a dating clause for . Hence, in
Declercq’s opinion § of both Argumenta III and IV, Argumentum VII,
probably § of Argumentum IX, and Argumenta XI to XVI are pseudoDionysiac. As every scholar before him, however, he seems not to have
been aware of §§ and of Argumentum I, being deceived by the editions; at least, he did not include them in his discussion.
Summary
This reassessment of scholarly opinion on the original corpus of the
Dionysiac argumenta illustrates that the basis of discussion generally
was the Computus Digbaeanus of , the Computus Cottonianus of
Wallis (), lxxiv.
www.nabkal.de/dionys.html
69 Declercq (), .
67
68
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 63
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
/, and the Computus paschalis of , while the important
manuscript evidence mentioned by Jones was sometimes referred to in
passing, but never analysed in detail. Moreover, Jan’s and van der
Hagen’s discussion of Dionysius’ authorship, both published in the
early eighteenth century, remain the best studies of this question to
this day, even though they are based on only a fractional amount of the
evidence known to us today. The neglect of these studies during the
past century or so led to widely differing comments on the extent of
the Dionysiac corpus of argumenta, with only Neugebauer and
Declercq commenting on this question in some detail. Yet, since both
scholars touched this question only in passing and in the end did not
agree, neither their accounts, nor the valuable, but outdated discussions of Jan and van der Hagen can be regarded as authoritative in this
question. The lacuna of a proper analysis of the extent of the
Dionysiac corpus of argumenta will be dealt with in the following,
since only such an analysis can provide the essential basis of the
present study.
Manuscript Evidence for the Original Corpus
of the Dionysiac Argumenta
As the previous discussion has shown, only five manuscripts containing argumenta with the original dating clause of , the year in which
Dionysius evidently composed his prologue, have been discovered
over the past three centuries.70 For that reason alone, these five manuscripts obviously are the primary witnesses for what may have been the
original corpus of the Dionysiac argumenta. Since the two existing editions of the argumenta are based on only one of these five manuscripts,
and none of the remaining four has ever been analysed in detail concerning the extent and structure of the original Dionysiac corpus,
these are discussed here first. But it has also become apparent in the
preceding discussion that some of the later recensions, most notably
the Computus paschalis of and the Computus Cottonianus of /,
also preserve valuable information concerning this question. Yet, these
later recensions are numerous; for that reason they will be classified in
70 The sole manuscript witness for the Dionysiac argumenta listed by Cordoliani
(), is MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Reg. Lat. , fols –, which is,
in fact, a later recension and does not include the dating. The same holds true for
MS Basel, Universitätsbibliothek, F III k, mistakenly mentioned by Springsfeld
(), , , to include the Dionysiac argumenta. Cf. p. below.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 64
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
terms of their relevance for the transmission of the original Dionysiac
corpus of argumenta and analysed in these categories. Finally, an
overview of this manuscript evidence is provided as the basis for establishing the original structure and subsequent development of the
Dionysiac argumenta.
MSS Preserving the Original Dating Clause of
Group A – MS Oxford, Bodleian Library, Digby , v–r (Computus Digbaeanus of ):
This manuscript formed the basis for Jan’s and Krusch’s edition of the
argumenta, as well as the present analysis, and is discussed in detail
above.71 Concerning the dating clauses, nine of the argumenta
transmit the original date , namely Argumenta I–VI and VIII
explicitly, Argumenta IX and X implicitly. § of Argumentum IV, Argumentum XIII, and Argumentum XIV incorporate implicit dating
clauses for , , and to respectively, as is discussed elsewhere.72 The data given in § of Argumentum III mentions the th and
th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis (corresponding to ⫹n⫻),
while Argumenta XI and XII explicitly refer to . As mentioned
above, this computus has an incipit, but no clearly defined end.73 The
incipit reads: Incipiunt argumenta de titulis pascalis egiptiorum investigata solercia ut praesentes indicent.
Group B – MSS Oxford, Bodleian Library, Bodley , r–v
(Sirmond Manuscript); Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. ,
v–v; Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. , r–v; Vatican,
Biblioteca Apostolica, Vat. Lat. , –:
Characteristically, the manuscripts of this group transmit Argumenta I
to X identical in structure and content to the Computus Digbaeanus
(including §§ and of Argumentum I, which are not included in the
main body of the text in the editions), but contrary to that computus
these ten argumenta are here strictly defined by incipits and explicits
as a single corpus; to this corpus Argumentum XIV is attached, in the
same version as in the Computus Digbaeanus.74 Hence, the dating
See pp. – above.
See pp. , , .
73 Cf. pp. – above.
74 The facsimile of MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. , v–v in
Appendix III (Plate ) may serve as an illustration of the strictly defined corpus of
Argumenta I–X with Argumentum XIV attached that is the characteristic feature of
Group B texts.
71
72
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 65
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
clauses in these manuscripts are the exact same as in the Computus
Digbaeanus.
Jones drew attention to the three manuscripts that contain the full
text, while Mac Carthy had earlier referred to a fragment that included
only the second half of it.75 The most important of these manuscripts
probably is MS Oxford, Bodleian Library, Bodley , which Jones
had identified as once in the possession of Jacques Sirmond and studied by the famous early modern scholars of chronology, Petavius and
Bucherius, in the seventeenth century, but which was subsequently
regarded as lost in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.76 The
manuscript itself was written in Vendôme in the eleventh century, but
Jones argues that a large part of this manuscript represents the corpus
of computistical texts used by Bede for his composition of De temporum ratione, among them the argumenta in question.77 Hence, at least
in Jones opinion, ‘it is definitely possible that O is a copy of a manuscript written before A.D. ’.78 If this view is accepted, then this
manuscript would contain the oldest known witness of the corpus of
argumenta attributed to Dionysius. The first ten argumenta are clearly
defined as one body in this manuscript by the incipt Incipiunt argumenta Grecorum de titulis paschalibus inuestigata solertia and the
explicit Expliciunt argumenta paschalium titulorum. Argumentum XIV
occurs as a separate item after that, headed Incipit calculatio quomodo
repperiri posit, quota feria .i. singulis annis .xiiii. luna paschalis, id est
circuli decennouenalis and concluded with the phrase Haec argumenta
hic finiuntur.
Six years later, in his introduction to Bede’s computistical works,
Jones then listed manuscripts that contain Dionysius’ computistical
texts complementary to the manuscripts used by Jan and Krusch. At
the end of that list he drew special attention to the Palatine
manuscripts in the Vatican as primary witnesses for the study of the
Dionysiac argumenta.79 Yet, of the three Palatine codices mentioned in
Cf. pp. – above.
Jones ().
77 The Dionysiac argumenta are item in Jones’ table of contents of this manuscript; in his opinion items – constitute Bede’s computus. Jones (), especially
; Jones (), –. Cf. Wallis (), lxxiv; Springsfeld (), –, ;
Ó Cróinín (a), . For other descriptions of this manuscript see Jones (),
–; Borst (), –; Borst (), ; Mc Carthy and Breen (), –;
Peden (), xl–xli.
78 Jones (), . Cf. Ó Cróinín (a), .
79 Jones (), . Cf. also p. above.
75
76
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 66
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
his list only two actually contain the argumenta, both from Mainz or
its vicinity, written in the early ninth century. Of these two, MS Pal.
Lat. is regarded as a copy of MS Pal. Lat. .80 This is confirmed by the text of the argumenta, in which these two manuscripts
differ only in form, not in content: The argumenta frame an extensive
Easter table from to in MS Pal. Lat. , while they are separately copied in MS Pal. Lat. . Argumenta I to X are clearly defined
as one corpus in both codices by the incipit Incipiunt argumenta
Graecorum de titulis paschalibus Aegyptiorum investigata solertia and the
explicit Expliciunt argumenta paschalium titulorum. This corpus is then
followed by Argumentum XIV, headed Incipit calculatio.81
Earlier, at the turn of the century, Bartholomew Mac Carthy was
the first to realise the importance of a fragment that survived in the
Vatican MS Vat. Lat. for the extent of the corpus of Dionysiac
argumenta.82 This fragment is famous among scholars of Old Irish, for
it contains a considerable number of Old Irish glosses, but it has never
been systematically studied by any modern computist.83 Old Irish
scholars tend to argue that the language of the glosses is datable to the
eighth century, and that it does not seem likely that these glosses were
copied.84 Therefore, if an eighth century date is assigned to this
fragment, it is the oldest surviving manuscript witness of the
argumenta. The fragment starts on page of the manuscript, which
preserves the second half of Argumentum VIII, as well as Argumenta IX
and X complete in the same form as in the Computus Digbaeanus,
80 For descriptions of MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. see Schuba
(), – (arguing for Mainz, early saec. IX); Mittler (), ; Lindsay (),
(Mainz, before ); Jones (), (Mainz, c.); Borst (), –; Borst
(), – (in both accounts Borst argues for Mainz, between and ). For
descriptions of MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. see Schuba (),
– (Trier and Mainz, saec. IX1); Lindsay (), (Trier, ); Jones (),
(Trier and Mainz, saec. IX1); Springsfeld (), – (first part, including the
Dionysiac argumenta, Trier, ); Borst (), –; Borst (), – (in both
accounts Borst argues that the part including the Dionysiac argumenta was written in
Trier in ). For MS Pal. Lat. being a copy of MS Pal. Lat. see Mittler
(), ; Borst (), .
81 Cf. Appendix III (Plate ).
82 Cf. p. above.
83 For descriptions of this manuscript see Zimmer (), xxx; Stokes and Strachan
(–), ii xii; Kenney (), –; CLA , (No. ). Charles W. Jones, CCSL
A, xiii lists this manuscripts among computistical texts that ‘may have lain within
Bede’s range’, but ‘as yet not satisfactorily studied’. This codex also contains a fragment
of the calculus of Victorius of Aquitaine, cf. Peden (), xl.
84 Stokes and Strachan (–), ii xii; Kenney (), .
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 67
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
including the implicit dating clauses for . Argumentum X is then
followed by the explicit Finiunt argumenta paschalium titulorum,
which also marks the end of this page. Page then contains Argumentum XIV with the implicit dating clause for –, breaking off after
three quarters of the text.85 According to these details it must be presumed that the manuscipt from which this fragment originates
included the first ten Dionysiac argumenta as a strictly defined corpus,
with Argumentum XIV attached, as it appears in the other three codices
of this group.
Early Recensions of the Argumenta
Recension A – The Computus paschalis of :
According to its editor, Paul Lehman, this corpus of argumenta survives in five manuscripts.86 Since it is incorporated in the second book
of Cassiodor’s Institutiones in every single one of these codices, it is
assumed that Cassiodor himself may have been the author.87 Now, by
comparing the Computus paschalis with the Dionysiac argumenta in
their published form (i.e. with the Computus Digbaeanus), Otto
Neugebauer has pointed out that the Computus paschalis is nothing
but a copy of these argumenta, with only two major differences: Argumenta VII, XI–XVI are missing in the Computus paschalis (as they represent argumenta that were later added to the original Dionysiac
corpus), and the examples in the remaining Argumenta I–VI, VIII–X
were modified to match the year instead of .88 Yet, if the edition
The full text of p. and half of p. , including all Old Irish glosses, are edited in
Zimmer (), –; Stokes and Strachan (–), ii –.
86 Lehmann (), ; Cordoliani (). The five manuscripts are: MS Karlsruhe,
Badische Landesbibliothek, Aug. CLXXI, v–v; MS Milano, Biblioteca
Ambrosiana, D inf., r-v; MS Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale, Lat. , v–v;
MS Würzburg, Universitätsbibliothek, M. p. misc. F. a, v–v. For the mistaken
addition to this list of MS Padua, Biblioteca Antoniana, I , v–r in CCSL, Clavis
patristica A, , which stems from this codex being the only one mention under
Cassidorus’ Computus in Thorndike and Kibre (), , see n below.
87
For the debate concerning Cassidorus’ authorship and the incorporation of this
corpus of argumenta in the second book of the Institutiones see Krusch (), –;
Poole (b), –; Lehmann (), –; van de Vyver (), –; Neugebauer
(), , .
88 For Neugebauer’s problematic view that Argumentum XI was also part of the
original Dionysiac corpus, even though it does not appear in the Computus paschalis,
see p. above.
85
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 68
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
of the Computus paschalis of is compared with Group A-B texts,
further significant textual differences become apparent (some of which
are noted by Neugebauer himself 89): the Computus paschalis conflates
§§ and of Argumentum I, while § of Argumenta III, IV, IX, and X
do not feature in this text. As regards the incipits and explicits of the
Computus paschalis, these vary greatly among the five manuscripts,
none of which agrees with the ones in Group A-B texts.90
Recension B – MS Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale, Nouvelle acquisition
, r–r (The Computus Parisinus of /):
One important witness for the Dionysiac argumenta has escaped
the attention of modern scholars. In the ninth century MS Paris,
Bibliothèque Nationale, Nouvelles acquisition , r–r from
Fleury or Auxerre the Dionysiac argumenta are transmitted in a recension of .91 This recension comprises a clearly defined corpus of argumenta identical to the corpus of Group B, with Argumenta VII and VIII
being switched. This switch is noteworthy in so far as it demonstrates
that the early ninth-century editor of this corpus apparently regarded
Argumenta I–VI and VIII as somehow connected, presumably because
of the fact that only these seven include explicit dating clauses.92 The
dating clauses have been accommodated to the year or , with
few exceptions: No explicit dating clause is given in Argumentum I,
while the number of indiction cycles that have passed since AD
(namely ) dates this recension to the period between and
inclusively; § of Argumentum III gives the th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis as example, which agrees with ; § of Argumentum IV still
preserves the count of years from the year following the consulship of
Tiberius Iunior Augustus, which refers to ;93 Argumentum IX gives
data that only matches / (: indiction – in MS –, epact ,
Easter Sunday on March, luna ; : indiction , epact ,
Easter Sunday on April, luna ); Argumentum X still preserves the
89 Neugebauer ((), –) notes that § of Argumenta III and IV are not part
of the Computus paschalis. Cf. also p. above.
90 For the incipits and explicits of the Computus paschalis see Lehmann (), , .
91 For this manuscript see Krusch (), (St.-Benoît-sur-Loire in Fleury,
saec. IX); Jones (), (Fleury, saec. IX); Borst (), – (Fleury or Auxerre,
the latter more likely, c.); Borst (), – (Fleury or Auxerre, c.).
92
This structure of the Computus Parisinus strengthens van der Hagen’s view
(Hagen (), ) that Argumenta I–VI and VIII are to be regarded as an entity. For
this question see p. above and p. below.
93 For this dating see p. below.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 69
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
chronological data of (indiction , concurrentes , Easter Sunday on
March). This preservation of the chronological data for proves
that the original Dionysiac argumenta were the exemplar, and not, e.g.,
the Computus paschalis of , while the unaltered inclusion of § of
Argumentum IV (and in fact the entire structure of this Computus Parisinus) demonstrates that the examplar was, in fact, a Group B text.
These ten argumenta are clearly defined as one corpus in the manuscript by a blank line before the first argumentum (probably to be later
filled by a heading) and by the explicit Explicit argumenta paschalium
titulorum.94 In contrast to Group B texts, however, this corpus is not
immediately followed by Argumentum XIV here, which appears in a different part of the codex (fols r-v).
Recension C – Binding fragment of MS Nancy, Bibliothèque municipale, () (The Fragmentum Nanciacense of ):
An important manuscript witness for the pseudo-Dionysiac argumenta, discovered years ago, has hitherto been overlooked by
scholars of early medieval computistics. In , the French palaeographer Henri D’Arbois de Jubainville discovered a binding fragment
in the Bibliothèque municipale de Nancy written in an Irish hand of
the late eighth or early ninth century;95 later palaeographers have
argued for Bobbio as the provenance of the codex to which this flyleaf
is attached.96 It contains computistical formulae, sporadically glossed
in Old Irish. These glosses have made this fragment famous among
scholars of Old Irish,97 but it has never received any attention by
modern computists. The recto side of this fragment consists of four
passages:98 ) The first deals with the length of moonlight per lunar
day. ) The second passage explains how to calculate the lunar age on
Cf. the facsimile in Appendix III (Plate ).
D’Arbois de Jubainville ().
96 The shelf-mark of this codex was when this binding fragment was discovered
by D’Arbois de Jubainville (and this number is repeated in all subsequent discussion
of the Old Irish glosses found on this flyleaf ), but it was changed soon thereafter, in
, to () (cf. Favier (), ). For a description of this codex see Favier
(), –; Lindsay (), ; Bischoff (), ; Zimmer (), xxx–i; Stokes
and Strachan (–), ii xii; Kenney (), .
97 The Old Irish glosses are edited in D’Arbois de Jubainville (); Zimmer
(), ; edited and translated in Stokes and Strachan (–), ii ; edited, translated and discussed in Gaidoz (), – and D’Arbois de Jubainville (). For the
Irish context of this fragment see also Zimmer (), xxx–i; Stokes and Strachan
(–), ii xii; Kenney (), .
98 A facsimile of this fragment is reproduced in Appendix III (Plate ) below.
94
95
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 70
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
the calends of each month for any given year from fixed regulars for
each month99 and the epact of the year in question; the epact of the
example given is , i.e. the th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis.
) The third passage demonstrates how to calculate the epact from the
AD date, which ultimately derives from Argumentum III; the example
given is AD ;100 this calculation is followed by a list of weekday
regulars for the calculation of the weekday on the calends of each
month for any given year, starting with October,101 and another list of
the lunar regulars for the calculation of the lunar age on the calends
of each month, starting with September, which is identical to the list
given in the previous passage.102 This passage is followed by the
explicit Finit argumenta igitur, which is then followed by the incipit
Alia argumenta nuper inuenta incipiunt amen. ) The fourth passage
gives formulae for calculating the day of the month and weekday of
luna of the March lunation from the lunar age of February and the
concurrentes respectively; this luna was significant, because it had
the exact same relation to the initium quadragesimae (the beginning
99 These lunar regulars are listed from September to August, and they are identical
in order and numerical value to the same list given in the Bobbio Computus ,
(PL , , ), Dial. Neustr. (Borst (), ), Lect. comp. I (Borst (),
–), Lib. comp. II (Borst (), ), Computus of Pacificus of Verona §
(Meersseman and Adda (), ). Bede lists these regulars from January to December in De temporum ratione (Jones (), –), as do some manuscripts of Lect.
comp. and Hrabanus Maurus, De computo (CCCM , ), copying Bede. The
Computus Rhenanus of has both lists (MS Köln, Diözesan- und Dombibliothek,
, v–r; MS Wolfenbüttel, Herzog-August-Bibliothek, Weißenburg , r;
for this text see pp. – below).
100 The AD date is not explicitly mentioned, but for calculation purposes implicitly given as ⫻⫹⫻⫹ (⫽); the epact is then correctly calculated as .
101 Usually this list begins with March in computistical texts: So in the Bobbio
Computus , (PL , , ); Dial. Neustr. (Borst (), ); Lect. comp.
I (Borst (), –); Lib. comp. II (Borst (), ); Computus of Pacificus
of Verona § (Meersseman and Adda (), ). Bede lists these weekday regulars
from January in De temporum ratione (Jones (), ), as do some manuscripts
of Lect. comp. and Hrabanus Maurus, De computo (CCCM , ), copying Bede.
The Computus Rhenanus of has both lists (MS Köln, Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, , v; MS Wolfenbüttel, Herzog-August-Bibliothek, Weißenburg , r;
for this text see pp. – below). Interestingly enough, the only computistical text to
my knowledge that has the same list of weekday regulars as this fragment, i.e. beginning with October, is the Computus Cottonianus of / (f v, cf. n below), while
it also appears as a gloss to Willibrord’s Easter table (MS Paris, Bibliothèque
Nationale, Lat. , r) and in the Irish influenced MS München, Bayerische
Staatsbibliothek, Clm , v.
102
Cf. n .
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 71
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
of the Lenten fast) as the Easter full moon had to Easter Sunday; in
fact, this argumentum seems to be an adaption of Argumentum XIV to
the initium calculation; the first example given (for this luna occuring in February) is the first year of the cyclus decemnovennalis, having
concurrentes (and no provision is made for this year being bissextile),
which agrees with AD , , and ; since palaeographers argue
that the script of this fragment can be dated to the late eighth or early
ninth century, seems to be the most likely date for this argumentum nuper inventum, and thus the whole fragment may be dated to
c.; yet, I would not rule out the possibility of dating this fragment
to c., especially since the previous passage contains a dating clause
for ; of the second example (for this luna falling in March) only
the first two lines survive.
The verso side of this fragment, then, is the one that concerns us
here. It contains only part of the last sentence of Argumentum XI, as
well as Argumenta XII and XIII complete. A finit-clause (Finit amen
finit) appears after Argumentum XIII, clearly marking the end of a corpus of argumenta. The date given in the examples of Argumenta XII
and XIII is , explicitly for the former, implicitly for the latter (the
lunar data matches /: th and th year of the cyclus lunaris, having
epact and respectively).
It is obvious from this analysis that the original manuscript contained at least the end of the second example of the last argumentum of the recto side, as well as Argumentum XI in the lacuna
between the recto and the verso side. Furthermore, it seems plausible to suggest that the incipit before the last argumentum on the
recto side does not correspond to the explicit on the verso side: The
incipit refers to ‘recently invented argumenta’, followed by an
argumentum with a dating clause for AD , , or , while the
argumenta on the verso side have dating clauses for AD . Therefore I would suggest that another explicit and incipit occurred in
the now lost part immediately before Argumentum XI. This would
imply that Argumenta XI to XIII were regarded as an entity in this
fragment.
The primary importance of the verso side of this fragment is twofold: ) It preserves the earliest known dating clause for Argumenta
XII and XIII, namely ; previously, on the basis of the Computus
Digbaeanus, was regarded as the earliest date at least for Argumentum XII, while the few scholars who studied Argumentum XIII found
it impossible to date it with any certainty; in fact, Argumentum XIII
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 72
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
of the Computus Digbaeanus preserves the implicit dating clause for
given in the Fragmentum Nanciacense, which suggests that the
author of the Computus Digbaeanus worked from an exemplar of
Argumenta XI to XIII of as transmitted in this fragment, accommodating the explicit examples (i.e. the ones explicitly mentioning
AD as the precondition), but not Argumentum XIII with its
implicit data; consequently, it can be safely assumed that Argumenta
XI to XIII are at least as old as . ) Some details of Argumentum
XIII, especially the mentioning of certain numbers of points, have
caused modern scholars some trouble, and they have never been
explained satisfactorily; the Fragmentum Nanciacense provides a different perspective on these difficulties, which are discussed in detail in
Appendix II.
Since this important piece of evidence for the pseudo-Dionysiac
argumenta has never been transcribed in full, I provide such a transcription in Appendix I.
Recension D: The Computus Parisinus of / is a rare exception of
a late recension of the Group B corpus. Generally, the argumenta had
a different fate from the last quarter of the seventh century onwards:
the corpus as preserved in Group B disintegrated, and the argumenta
found their way disconnectedly into textbooks, formularies or compendia. Recension D, then, includes every text of whatever form that
transmits a later recension of one or more Dionysiac argumenta without preserving the Group B corpus.
Since the innumerable texts of this recension obviously do not
provide any information about the original corpus of Dionysiac
argumenta, I will discuss them only briefly here. Such a discussion
is nevertheless necessary, since quite a few texts and manuscripts
that fall into this category have been connected to the original corpus of the Dionysiac argumenta by scholars of computistics, so that
their relation to this corpus needs to be clarified. Moreover, the following analysis is designed to illustrate how the argumenta were
transmitted once the process of disintegration of the corpus had
started.
In fact, the Computus Digbaeanus marks the first stage in the
disintegration of the Dionysiac argumenta: Even though the Group
B corpus is preserved, the addition of further argumenta without
clearly marking off the original corpus by means of explicits, incipits or simple headings left the extent of this corpus undefined.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 73
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Once the corpus had opened up, it was quite natural that more
newly-invented formulae and texts were added, not only to the end
of the original corpus, but also into it; moreover, the examples were
then usually accommodated to the annus praesens of the later compiler. This process, which seems to have started in the last quarter
of the seventh century, led to the development of ever growing
compilations of computistical texts, in which the original
Dionysiac argumenta only played a minor role. Yet, at the early
stage of this development, the Dionysiac argumenta that were
included in these compilations usually lost their original dating
clause, but remained unaltered otherwise. But once they were
clearly disconnected from the Dionysiac corpus, they lost their
authoritative attribution, and were then more liable to alteration.
Consequently, from the beginning of the eighth-century compilers
and authors of computistical textbooks, formularies and compendia started to rephrase the Dionysiac formulae, usually by adding
more details and explanations to the calculations, or by generalising them.
The earliest witness to this process of progressive disintegration
of the Group B corpus and eventual alteration of the original argumenta is the famous Computus Cottonianus of /, preserved in
one of the few eighth-century computistical codices, namely MS
London, British Library, Cotton Caligula A XV, whose provenance
appears to be northern France.103 Pallarès has published the section
of this text that includes Argumenta I to XIV, and compared it with
Jan’s and Krusch’s editions. Yet, the section published by him does
not comprise the entire computus, since Pallarès was only interested
in the transmission of the argumenta ascribed to Dionysius, and thus
broke off right in the middle of folio r;104 his choice for breaking
Cf. Lindsay (), (arguing that this manuscript was written in France, in
); CLA , (No. ; Lowe argues that it was ‘probably written in North-east
France, in a centre with Insular connexions; copied from an exemplar written
A.D. , the year mentioned on fol. ’; earlier in this passage he describes the script
as ‘pre-Carolingian French minuscule, saec. VIII2’); Jones (), (northern
France, saec. VIII); Pallarès (), –. It is the oldest manuscript preserving the
Dionysiac argumenta in the original or as a recension (a recension in this case); cf.
Borst (), –.
104
Pallarès (), –. He also defines the Computus Cottonianus as comprising
fols r–r of this manuscript in two articles of and , now reprinted in
Pallarès (), where the relevant references can be found on pp. and respectively
(in both cases he mistakenly gives f v as the beginning).
103
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 74
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
off at this point was possibly also influenced by the fact that the
following item, i.e. the Suggestio Bonifati primiceri, is the only item
in this computus that is published separately;105 yet, this short item,
having neither incipit nor explicit that would distinguish it from the
rest, seems rather to be an integral part of this computus. In my
opinion, folios r–r should be identified as a cohesive formulary,
to be termed the Computus Cottonianus of /: the beginning of
this formulary is clearly defined by the fact that folio v is left
blank, and thus a new text starts on folio r; a later hand adds the
heading Cassiodorus de computo paschali, an obviously mistaken attribution; the first page after folio r, on which the end of an argumentum agrees with the end of a page, is folio r; no other feature
can be found before this page that would mark the end of the text; at
the bottom of folio r, then, a different hand adds a list of ‘canonical’ and ‘uncanonical’ lunar ages, i.e. the epacts on January of the
Victorian reckoning and the lunar ages that do not occur on that
date in the Victorian -year luni-solar cycle respectively; this later
addition filling a previously blank space marks the end of this formulary; on fol. v, then, starts a recension of the so-called Acts of the
Council of Ceasarea.106
Now, the Computus Cottonianus contains every argumentum of
the Group B corpus, and at the same time Argumenta I–XIV, as well
as § of Argumentum XVI of the argumenta of the Computus Digbaeanus, most of which are here accommodated to / and preserved in a structure disrupted by additional argumenta: The
computus begins with Argumenta I to VIII (accommodated to ,
and § of Argumenta III and IV omitted), followed by Argumentum
XIV (including the chronological data for to ); this is followed
by a text on the Julian calendar limits for the Easter New moon, the
Easter full moon, and Easter Sunday; then, Argumenta XI and XII are
given (accommodated to ); attached to Argumentum XII (which
deals with the calculation of the weekday of January) is a formula
to calculate the weekday of the calends of any given month by
adding the concurrentes of a year to given regulars for each month;107
105 This text is edited from this codex and five other manuscripts by Krusch
(), –.
106 For the Acts of the council of Caesarea see Krusch (), –; Jones (),
–; Wilmart (); Strobel (), –.
107 This list of regulars, starting with October, is uncommon and has a parallel in
the Fragmentum Nanciacense. Cf. n above. It is transcribed and discussed in
Pallarès (), –, who places it in a rather unlikely Arabic context.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 75
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
this is followed by Argumenta IX (with chronological data for
and ), X (preserving the chronological data for ), and XIII
(preserving the chronological data for , and the number of puncti
as given in the Computus Digbaeanus108); the remaining part of this
computus consists of arguments and texts previously unconnected
with the Dionysiac argumenta, with the exceptions of § of Argumenta XVI and III, the latter preserving the original chronological
data of Group A-B texts.
This description illustrates the degree of disintegration achieved by
the Computus Cottonianus: the Dionysiac argumenta were embedded
among numerous other formulae and texts without distinction, while
most of the examples were accommodated to the annus praesens of the
compiler. Consequently, some late seventh and early eighth century
computists got to know these argumenta through a formulary like the
Computus Cottonianus rather than through the Group B corpus. In fact,
the Computus Cottonianus seems to have been quite influential in transmitting Insular computistical knowledge in general, and the Dionysiac
algorithms in particular.109 Its role as one of the earliest Insular sources
for Frankish computistics and the extent of its influence have yet to be
established, since it plays no part in Arno Borst’s source analysis of
eighth century Frankish computistical texts. Direct dependency on the
Computus Cottonianus can be found in a computistical formulary
which is preserved in two late eighth- and early ninth-century
manuscripts from Cologne and probably Worms, i.e. MS Köln,
Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, , v–v and MS Wolfenbüttel,
Herzog-August-Bibliothek, Weißenburg , r–v respectively.110
108 For this problem and the possibility that the Computus Digbaeanus and the
Computus Cottonianus are products from the same computistical school, see
Appendix II.
109 Cordoliani had, quite mistakenly, connected the Computus Cottonianus with
Spanish computistics: Cordoliani (); Cordoliani (). This view was corrected
by Pallarès (), –, –, .
110 For descriptions of MS Köln, Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, see Jaffé and
Wattenbach (), –; Weber Jones (), –; van Euw (a) (arguing for
Cologne, c.); Bischoff (), (probably Cologne, saec. VIII./XI.); Jones (),
(Cologne, c.); Springsfeld (), (Cologne, –); Borst (), –;
Borst (), (Borst argues in both accounts for Cologne, shortly after ); facsimiles are available on the world wide web: www.ceec.uni-koeln.de. For descriptions
of MS Wolfenbüttel, Herzog-August-Bibliothek, Weißenburg see Butzmann
(), – (Weißenburg, saec. IX1); Borst (), – (possibly Worms, early
saec. IX).
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 76
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
The latest dating clause in this formulary is , and thus we may
term it the Computus Rhenanus of .111 This formulary is an
excellent example for the fate of the Dionysiac argumenta in
computistical compendia of the eighth and later centuries: It copies
Bede’s version of Argumentum I, then gives a version of Argumentum
II for , of Argumentum VI for , of § of Argumentum III
implicitly for (th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis), of § of
Argumentum IV for and of Argumentum V for ; this is
followed by a generalised version of Argumentum II, of § of
Argumentum III and IV, and of Argumenta V, VI, and VIII; then,
among other passages copied from the Computus Cottonianus, it
transmits the latter’s recension (though for instead of ) of
Argumenta VIII, I, and (obviously without dating clause) VII;
finally, the first part of Argumentum XIV is given. Hence, even
though most of the Dionysiac argumenta are included in this
formulary, none appears in its original form, since the compiler
worked from various later recensions of them.
111 This formulary has not yet been identified as such, and is consequently
unpublished. In the descriptions of the Cologne codex, it is denoted as Canones
lunarium decennovalium circulorum in Jaffé and Wattenbach (), , and
divided into two parts (fols. v–v and fols. v–v) in van Euw (a),
, with reference to the pseudo-Bedan Canones lunarium decemnovennalium circulorum (PL , –) for the first part. Butzmann (), describes this
formulary of MS Weißenburg more precisely as consisting to a large degree of
the pseudo-Bedan Canones lunarium decemnovennalium circulorum, with various
insertions. In fact, the entire Canones lunarium decemnovennalium circulorum are
part of the Computus Rhenanus, in which it constitutes c. half of the text, and likewise only half of the argumenta of the Computus Cottonianus that are transmitted
in the Computus Rhenanus can also be found in the Canones lunarium decemnovennalium circulorum. Yet, the relationship between these two texts is rather the other
way round, with the Canones being a partial copy of the Computus Rhenanus: The
Canones survive in only one manuscript to my knowledge, namely the th century
MS Köln, Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, , r–r (for facsimiles see
www.ceec.uni-koeln.de). This codex shows direct dependency on MS Köln,
Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, , and consequently the Canones are copied
from the Cologne version of the Computus Rhenanus. Jones, in his discussion of
the Canones in (), –, neither refers to the two Cologne codices, nor to the
Wolfenbüttel MS. Borst, in his monumental edition of Frankish computistical
texts (), published argumenta of the Computus Rhenanus in three different
texts, using excerpts from the Cologne version of this computus in his edition of
the Lectiones sive regula conputi (Lect. comp.), Annalis libellus (Lib. ann.), and Libri
computi (Lib. comp.), and excerpts from the Wolfenbüttel version only in his edition of Lect. comp. Accordingly, all four of these texts share common material, but
every single one of them deserves a separate treatment, the Computus Rhenanus of
included.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 77
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
In general, the textual closeness to the original argumenta that is still
preserved in the Computus Cottonianus was lost in the eighth and early
ninth centuries, because the authors and compilers of computistical
texts and formulae felt that the argumenta either needed more explanations, or should rather be more generalised. Hence, many of the published computistical text from that period include Dionyisac
algorithms, but the wording usually varies considerably from the original. Moreover, as has been illustrated in the case of the Computus
Rhenanus of , the formulae were usually copied or altered from an
intermediary exemplar, not from the original. Through these intermediary texts the Dionysiac and pseudo-Dionyisac algorithms remained
very popular. Some of these can be found in the major computistical
works of the eighth and early ninth centuries: Bede’s De temporibus and
De temporum ratione, the Bobbio Computus, the Frankish texts Lectiones
sive regula conputi (Lect. comp.), Annalis libellus (Lib. ann.), Libri computi (Lib. comp.), Liber calculationis (Lib. calc.), the Computus of
Pacificus of Verona, and Hrabanus Maurus’ De computo.112 They also
appear in considerable variation in MS Basel, Universitätsbibliothek, F
III k (with examples for ), which Springsfeld described misleadingly as containing the original Dionysiac argumenta,113 MS Vatican,
Biblioteca Apostolica, Reg. Lat. (with examples for ), which is
the only manuscript listed by Cordoliani for the original Dionysiac
argumenta,114 and MS Padua, Biblioteca Antoniana, I , which is
mistakenly listed as a manuscript witness of the Computus paschalis
112 Bede’s De temporibus (Jones (), –), De temporum ratione , , ,
, , (Jones (), , , –, ) ; Bobbio Computus – (PL ,
–); Lect. comp. IIII –, V , VI (Borst (), –, –); Lib. ann. , ,
, , , , , (Borst (), –, , –, –); Lib. comp. II –b, III
(Borst (), –, ); Lib. calc. – (Borst (), –); Computus of
Pacificus of Verona §§–, , , , , , (Meersseman and Adda
(), –, , ); Hrabanus Maurus’ De computo , , , , ,
(CCCM , , –, , , –).
113 Springsfeld (), , . Her statement seems ultimately to derive from Jones
(), , who states more precisely: ‘The same rubrics with altered formulae in Ba,
fo. v, from an exemplar written A.D. .’
114
Cordoliani (), . As so often, Cordoliani trusted the incipit more than
the actual content. At least from the dating clauses he should have realised that this
is, in fact, a later recension. The incipit reads (MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica,
Reg. Lat. , r): Incipiunt argumenta de titulis paschalibus Aegiptiorum inuestigata sollertia, quae Dionisius conposuit utraque lingua Grece uidelicet et Latine eruditus.
This text is somehow related to the argumenta in the Basel MS mentioned in the previous note (I have not yet worked out the relationship), which have a very similar
incipit.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 78
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
of .115 Moreover, the computistical excerpts from MS Paris,
Bibliohèque Nationale, Nouvelle acquisition (including a recension of Argumentum I from ) and MS Léon, Biblioteca de la Catedral, N. (including a recension of Argumentum I from ) published
by Pallarès fall into this category.116
In summary, the texts of this recension do provide valuable
information about the later transmission of the Dionysiac algorithms, but only limited insight into what may have constituted the
original corpus of Dionysiac argumenta. Yet, especially the earliest
texts of this recension, which are the most likely to have had the
original Dionysiac corpus as their exemplar, show an interesting feature by grouping Argumenta I–VIII without their later additions,
sometimes excluding Argumentum VII: In the Computus Cottonianus Argumenta I–VIII, without the later additions to Argumenta
III and IV, appear as one body at the beginning of the text, with all
examples being accommodated to (Argumentum VII obviously
has no dating clause). Bede’s De temporibus of gives a generalised version of Argumenta I–VI and VIII, in which only the first
paragraph appears in the case of multi-paragraphed argumenta.117
The same holds true for the Lectiones sive regula conputi (Lect.
comp.) of , even though § of Argumentum III occurs slightly
later in the text, as it does in the Computus Cottonianus.118 This fact
obviously raises the question, whether some seventh and eighth century computists regarded only Argumenta I–VI and VIII as originally Dionyisac.119 If they did, the question about the reason and
source behind this view remains, since no manuscript is known that
115 CCSL, Clavis patristica III A, lists MS Padua, Biblioteca Antoniana, I ,
v–r as a witness for the Computus paschalis of , referring to Thorndike and
Kibre (), . There, the incipit Si nosse vis quotus annus est ab is attributed to the
Computus paschalis. Yet, this incipit cannot be found on the mentioned folios of the
Padua MS, which, in fact, are part of Hrabanus Maurus’ De computo. It may well be
that Thorndike and Kibre actually meant MS Padua, Biblioteca Antoniana, I ,
v–r, with this incipit occurring on f v. Yet, the argumentum introduced by this
incipit continues to calculate as the annus praesens; this and the following argumenta have no connection to the Computus paschalis other than that both texts include
later recensions of the Dionysiac argumenta.
116 Pallarès (), –.
117 Bede, De temporibus (Jones (), –).
118 Lect. comp. IIII –, V (Borst (), –).
119 It should be remembered that van der Hagen (), , regarded only this group
of argumenta as certainly belonging to the original Dionysiac corpus. Cf. p. above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 79
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
transmits only these argumenta with the original dating clause
for .
Overview
After this discussion of all known manuscripts and texts that contain information about the original corpus of the Dionysiac argumenta, it seems appropriate to facilitate the reader with an overview
of the details of this analysis, which is done in table form here
(Figure ). At the same time, Figure will serve as the basis for the
following discussion of the extent of the original corpus and the different layers of additions that are part of the Computus Digbaeanus
of .
Defining, Dating and Placing Dionysiac
and Pseudo-Dionysiac Argumenta
From the manuscript evidence summarized in Figure above the
following conclusions can be drawn: Since Argumenta XI–XIII only
appear in the Computus Digbaeanus (Group A) and the Fragmentum
Nanciacense (Recension C) and incorporate seventh-century dating
clauses, they can safely be regarded as pseudo-Dionysiac; the same is
valid for Argumenta XV and XVI, which have no dating clauses, but
appear only in the Computus Digbaeanus of the texts listed above.
Consequently, Argumentum XIV is embedded among pseudoDionysiac argumenta in that formulary; moreover, it appears separated
from the main corpus of argumenta by an explicit and incipit in Group
B, and does not appear in any of the recensions.120 For these reasons it
seems that it should also be classified as pseudo-Dionysiac, but the
implicit dating clause for to suggests that it needs more analysis. Of the first ten argumenta, only the parts that appear in all groups
and recensions and include a dating clause for , the year in which
Dionysius evidently wrote his prologue, can, at this stage, be safely
considered as Dionysiac, namely § of Argumentum I, Argumentum II,
§ of Argumenta III and IV, Argumenta V, VI, VIII, and § of Argumenta IX and X. Yet, doubt remains concerning the last mentioned,
since they are not included in the recensions of these argumenta in
Note that in the Paris MS, Argumentum XIV is physically disconnected from
Recension B (Computus Parisinus of /). Cf. p. above.
120
I
§
Group A
x
x
II
III
x
x
Recension A
Recension B
post
y
z
z
cd
()
,
of
cd
()
of
VI
VII
VIII
IX
X
()
x
(/) x
() x
()
x
(/) x
() x
()
VIII
()
(/)
()
() x
pre
x
Recension C
§
Group A
Group B
Recension A
Recension B
Recension C
XI
XII
XIII
XIV
XV
XVI
(/)
()
()
x
x
partially
(/)
Figure 1 The extent and chronological details of the Dionysiac and pseudo-Dionysiac argumenta according to their primary witnesses.
AD dates explicitly mentioned in the argumenta stand alone, while implicit dates are given in brackets. If an argumentum contains no
dating clause, x stands for its inclusion in the respective corpus of argumenta, y and z for its inclusion in variation, while a blank space indicates that it is not included. ‘, of cd’ denotes the th and th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis, which represents the chronological data
given in that argumentum. Roman numerals indicate that the argumentum with that number appears in that place in the respective corpus.
Page 80
Argumentum
3:56 PM
cd
()
VII
9/10/09
,
of
V
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
Group B
IV
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
Argumentum
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 81
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Bede’s De temporibus and the Lectiones sive regula conputi (Lect. comp.),
and they appear disconnected from the first eight argumenta in the
Computus Cottonianus. Thus, all the paragraphs and argumenta, which
cannot readily be attributed to Dionysius, as well as the evidently
pseudo-Dionysiac argumenta need to be analysed in detail concerning
their most likely date and place of composition and their addition to
the Dionysiac corpus. It is apparent from the manuscript evidence that
whichever parts of the first argumenta were later added to the original corpus, these additions happened before the corpus as defined in
Group B and Recension B (Computus Parisinus of /) found a
wider distribution, and hence before further argumenta were attached
to this strictly defined corpus. Therefore, the controversial passages
among the first ten argumenta are analysed and summarised first,
followed then by Argumenta XI to XVI.
§§ and of Argumentum I: The first editor of the Dionysiac argumenta, Wilhelm Jan, did not include these two paragraphs in his edition, even though they appear in his sole manuscript witness, while the
second editor, Bruno Krusch, relegated them to the apparatus.121
Thus, both editors did not regard them as genuinely Dionysiac. This
is an odd treatment of these paragraphs considering that both editors
had no scruples in publishing argumenta with seventh-century dating
clauses in the same corpus. Anyway, the reason for discarding these
paragraphs seems to have been their content: as outlined above,122 the
formula given in § needed to be modified every years. The need for
this modification is explained in general terms in §, including the
example of the next modification, i.e. the increase of the multiplicand
by from to , which would become necessary in . §, then,
expands this example to the subsequent modification, i.e. the increase
of the multiplicand by from to , which would become necessary in . Moreover, § gives more mathematical details about the
application of the algorithm in years of such a modification, in this
case the year : instead of adding indiction in this year, the multiplicand by is increased by one; in subsequent years, however, the
indiction will then have to be added again until indiction is reached;
at this point the multiplicand by will again have to be increased by
one, from to , which would become necessary in . Consequently, the argument for discarding these paragraphs as pseudoDionysiac seems to be that they deal with problems that would not
121
122
Jan (), ; Krusch (), .
Cf. p. above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 82
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
need to concern Dionysius at his time of writing. Additionally, these
detailed further explanations seem out of place considering the short
and concise descriptions of the following formulae.
Yet the formula given in § could only be fully understood and
applied in subsequent years with at least the additional explanations outlined in §. Moreover, the parameter calculated in Argumentum I, i.e.
the AD date, is the sole precondition of the following six argumenta
(II–VI and VIII); consequently, the correct calculation of this parameter
was vital, and the algorithm was not complete without the explanation
of the modifications that become necessary every years. This need for
further details alone explains the different structure of Argumentum I
compared to the plain formulae of the subsequent ones. If §§ and are,
however, considered together, the discussion of the modifications to the
algorithm seems indeed unnecessarily extensive compared to the very
brief and precise style of the subsequent argumenta. Moreover, every
detail concerning the modifications to the algorithm was readily and
precisely explained in §; § only supplies further nuances, which are
illustrated by the example of the year . On these textual grounds it
seems to me that only § was part of the original corpus of Dionysiac
argumenta, while § was added in or just before the year . This view
is supported by the manuscripts evidence: while both paragraphs occur
in Groups A and B and in adapted form in Recension B, § does not
appear in Recension A, i.e. the Computus paschalis of , which is a crucial recension for this analysis of the shape of the original Dionysiac corpus. In consequence, this implies that a paragraph was added to the
original corpus as early as c., while the author of the recension of
worked from the original, pre-c. corpus; but it seems also possible
that this third paragraph was added at a later stage, with its author
regarding an extension of the example of § as the best way of providing
more details for the modification of the formula given in §.
§ of Argumentum III: There are various conclusive reasons for dismissing this paragraph as pseudo-Dionisiac: it does not appear in
Recension A; it explicitly states that it was invented later (Item alium
computum nuper inuentum); the calculation differs from the general
structure of calculating from the AD date; the chronological data
refers to the th and th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis, which is
incompatible with , the date given in § of this argumentum. The
data corresponds, in fact, with ⫹n⫻.123 Since this paragraph
123
Cf. pp. , above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 83
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
appears in Groups A and B, as well as Recension B, it seems plausible
to suggest that it was inserted at this place before the argumenta
received a wider circulation, i.e. before the end of first quarter of the
th century. The th year of the cyclus decemnovennalis occurred in the
following years in the period between and : , , , ,
and . Of these, none is really close to the date suggested for the
addition of § of Argumentum I, i.e. ca. . In fact, the similarity in
style of the first sentence of this paragraph (cited above) with the first
sentence of § of Argumentum IV, which can be dated to or shortly
thereafter, seems to suggest that the paragraph in question here was
composed close to this date. Hence, I regard as the most likely date
for its invention, and that it was then added to the Dionysiac corpus
in or slightly later than .
§ of Argumentum IV: That this paragraph is a later addition is explicitly expressed in its first sentence: It was invented later for the purpose
of simplifying the calculation of the preceding paragraph (Item nuper
inventa melius iudicavi, si brevius patefiat). This simplification was
achieved by counting the years not from Christ’s incarnation, but from
the first year after (post) the consulship of Tiberius Iunior Augustus;
because of this change in the precondition, the fixed parameter given
in the algorithm had to be modified accordingly from to . Since the
number of years was counted inclusively, this fixed parameter denotes
the concurrentes of the first year of the count minus one. Moreover, the
count of years in the formula of § obviously starts with the first year
in a four-year bissextile cycle, i.e. a year following a bissextile year
(namely AD ), since no parameter is added to the number of years to
be divided by four, i.e. every fourth year of the count was bissextile; as
no further modifications in this respect are mentioned in §, the same
must be valid for the first year of the new count.124 Hence, the first
year after the consulship of Tiberius was supposed to have concurrentes
and to follow a bissextile year. Various suggestions have been made
concerning the AD date of the year in question, but these suggestions
were almost never accompanied by any further explanation.125 There
For the details of the algorithm cf. p. above.
A late hand in the margin of MS Oxford, Bodleian Library, Digby , r notes
‘AD ’, which was adopted by Jan (), ; the present analysis proves that this is
the correct date. Van der Hagen (), regards as the date in question. Krusch
(), , argues for , and is followed in this view by Borst (), ;
Springsfeld (), ; Bär, http://www.nabkal.de/dionys.html. Neugebauer (),
, makes a case for . Cf. pp. – above.
124
125
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 84
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
can be hardly any doubt that the Tiberius referred to in this passage is
the Byzantine Emperor Tiberius Constantinus. According to the generally accepted chronology, Tiberius ruled from to .126 Yet, of
these years only agrees with the above mentioned chronological
data, and thus this must have been the year regarded as the first year
after Tiberius’ reign by the author of this paragraph. Consequently,
this paragraph seems to have been composed in or shortly thereafter, presumably in a place in or with close connections to the Byzantine Empire; since it was apparently added before this corpus got a
wider distribution, some place in Italy with the just mentioned attribution seems to be most likely.127
Argumentum VII: It should be remembered that Dionysius compiled the argumenta to provide algorithms for calculating the data of
the columns of his Easter table.128 From that perspective, Argumentum VII seems well placed here, since it deals with the Easter full
moons, which are listed in the column following the years of the
cyclus lunaris, the topic of Argumentum VI. Yet, van der Hagen
doubted that this argumentum had been part of the original
Dionysiac corpus for the reason that it has a structure different from
the other argumenta, as it provides no formula, but only a list.129
More conclusive than this argument is the manuscript evidence:
Argumentum VII does not occur in Recension A and in a different
place in Recension B. Consequently, this argumentum appears to be
a later addition, which was presumably inserted into the corpus in
or after , i.e. the possible date for the earliest addition (§ of
Argumentum I ), but before it got a wider circulation in the early
seventh century. It seems rather unlikely that it was added at the
same time as § of Argumenta III and IV, since the phrasing is different, as is the quality of the argumentum (formula vs list). As will
be discussed in the following, it may have been added at the same
time as § of Argumentum IX.
Argumentum IX: As mentioned earlier, two aspects suggest that this
and the following argumentum may not be Dionysiac: ) In some
later transmissions of the Dionysiac algorithms Argumenta I–VIII
126 For Tiberius and the period of his reign see Schreiner in LM , –
(s.v. Tiberios).
127 Borst (), ; Springsfeld (), also argues for Italy. Cf. p. above.
128 See the citation given on p. above.
129 Van der Hagen (), .
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 85
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
appear as a well-defined group, while these two argumenta either do
not appear at all, or are transmitted disconnected from this group;130
) the structure of these two argumenta is strikingly different to the
previous ones, since they do not have the AD date as their precondition. On the other hand, there are many conclusive arguments that
Argumentum IX was part of the original Dionysiac corpus: it supplies
an algorithm to calculate the lunar age of Easter Sunday, which constitutes one of the columns in the Dionysiac Easter table, and which
was, at the same time, the most debated question in the Easter controversy; the chronological data of the two examples given in this
argumentum agree with and ;131 Argumentum IX is included in
all Groups and Recensions, especially also in Recension A (again in
considerable variation);132 most conclusive of all, Argumentum IX is
referred to and applied in the Suggestio of Bonifatius, the chancellor
of the papal curia, to pope John I, written in .133 From this evidence there cannot be any doubt that this argumentum was certainly
part of the original Dionysiac corpus.
Yet the question remains whether this holds true for all parts of this
argumentum. The reason for outlining two examples instead of just
one is that different fixed parameters had to be applied, depending on
whether Easter Sunday fell in April or March.134 Thus, both examples
were necessary to understand the algorithm, and for that reason alone
both were quite certainly part of the original argumentum. Serious
doubts exist, however, concerning the second paragraph of this argumentum. Scholars have generally avoided a discussion of this paragraph, and if they commented on it, opinions on the meaning of this
paragraph vary, and it is yet to be explained convincingly.135 The key
to an understanding of this paragraph may lie in an interpretation of
Argumentum IX to be found in the Lectiones sive regula conputi (Lect.
comp.): chapter VI of that text consists of a generalised version of §
Cf. p. above.
Cf. p. above.
132 Cf. p. above.
133 Krusch (), –.
134 Cf. p. above.
135
Comments on this paragraph can only be found on the world wide web:
Deckers (http://hbar.phys.msu.su/gorm/chrono/paschata.htm) suggests that this
paragraph deals with the calculation of the lunar age of any given day of January, while
Bär (http://www.nabkal.de/dionys.html) rather thinks that this paragraph is supposed
to point out that the algorithm of § of this argumentum can also be applied for
calculating the lunar age of any given day of a year.
130
131
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 86
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
of Argumentum IX, followed by a slightly altered version of § of that
argumentum, which is then followed by the interpretation in
question.136 The editor of this text, Arno Borst, lists five manuscripts
for this interpretation, none of which is older than the middle of the
ninth century, while the dating clause of the oldest version suggests
that it was first composed in .137 According to this interpretation,
§ of Argumentum IX explains nothing but a different composition of
the fixed parameters in the algorithm of §.138 Only the fixed parameter for April is discussed: if is added to the number of months from
September to December ( inclusively), then the sum is ; if the last
two days of December are added to this, then the sum is ; this is the
fixed parameter applied for calculating the lunar age of Easter Sunday,
if the latter happens to fall in April. It is very striking that a discussion
of the fixed parameter for March is left wanting in this interpretation,
which is the most confusing part of § of Argumentum IX. In that part
of § it is argued that in bissextile years instead of has to be added
to the number of months from September to December ( inclusively). But a bissextile year obviously makes no difference to the lunar
calculation explained in § of this argumentum. If the early ninth century interpretation reproduces the original meaning of §, then ‘bissextile years’ has rather to be read as ‘years in which Easter Sunday falls
in March’; the reading would then basically be that the March regular
consist of the number of months between September to December
Lect. comp. VI (Borst (), –).
Lect. comp. VI D (Borst (), ). The five manuscripts are: MS Bern,
Burgerbibliothek, (Fleury, ); MS Karlsruhe, Landesbibliothek, Augiensis
CLXVII (Soissons/ Laon, c.); MS Köln, Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, 2
(Cologne, ); MS London, British Library, Harley (Fleury, c.); MS
St. Gallen, Stiftsbibliothek, (northern France, c.). Borst seems also to include
MS Ge, but since no variants are given for this MS, I suspect that it should rather have
been listed among the manuscripts in which this passage does not occur. All manuscripts give the dating clause for (epact , Easter Sunday on April, luna )
except for the Bern MS, in which the dating clause is accommodated to (epact ,
Easter Sunday on April, luna ).
138 This interpretation is supported by the fact that different explanations for the
fixed parameters in this algorithm were composed as early as : Boniface, the
chancellor of the papal curia in his Suggestio to pope John I of , explained the fixed
parameter for April as consisting of the number of months from September to April
divided by (/⫽) plus the five days that the Egyptian year of days is
shorter than the Julian calendar year of (Krusch (), –). Hence, § of Argumentum IX was probably just one of a number of different explanations for the fixed
parameters in this algorithm, but obviously the only one that made its way into the
Dionysiac corpus of argumenta.
136
137
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 87
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
( inclusively) ⫹ a fixed parameter of ⫹ the last two days of
December, adding up to . The author of § may have regarded the
first example given in § of this argumentum as a bissextile year, which
led him to the assumption that the fixed parameter for March had to
be applied in every bissextile year. Whatever the case may be, the mentioning of the bissextile year is totally misplaced in this context (since
it makes a difference in weekday, but not in lunar calculations), and it
appears that the compiler of this paragraph did not fully understand
the preceding examples. Consequently, it seems very likely that § of
Argumentum IX represents a later, confused addition, which is confirmed by the fact that it does not appear in Recension A. As for a possible date for the addition of this paragraph, it obviously found its way
into the Dionysiac corpus before the emended corpus as represented in
Group B and Recension B got a wider distribution, i.e. before the end
of the first quarter of the seventh century. This paragraph cannot really
be connected with § of Argumenta III and IV, since their precise
chronological argument is not matched by the confused explanation
here. Moreover, the purpose of this paragraph was not to add a new or
simpler formula, but to provide additional explanation to the existing
argument. Hence, if this paragraph was added at the same time as any
of the other additions, I would tend to connect it with Argumentum
VII, but not with § of Argumentum I and § of Argumentum X, which
are more technical, and very precise. In the end, however, the most
likely scenario seems to be that it was added separately.
Argumentum X: As has been mentioned in the discussion of Argumentum IX, Argumentum X does not appear in some later transmissions of the Dionysiac argumenta, and its structure is strikingly
different compared to the first seven argumenta (I–VI, VIII), which
casts doubts on its inclusion in the original corpus. Additionally,
Argumentum X deals with weekday calculation, and thus is not
immediately connected to any column in the Dionysiac Easter table.
Yet, the example given here is to calculate the weekday of Easter Sunday of ,139 and thus this argumentum may have been included in
the corpus as a method for double-checking the solar Easter data, and
thus would have had an immediate application for the Easter table (it
could obviously also be used for calculating the weekday of the Easter
full moon). Moreover, the implicit date in this argumentum suggests
that it was part of the original corpus, and more decisively it figures
139
Cf. p. above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 88
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
in Groups and Recensions A and B discussed above. However, § of
this argumentum does not feature in Recension A. In this paragraph
it is argued that the weekday of any given Julian calendar date from
January to December can be calculated with the algorithm of §;
this algorithm is here outlined again, this time not by means of an
example, but in general terms. Such a generalisation of the preceding
formula is not given for any of the other argumenta, and it does not
fit into Dionysius’ general scheme of explaining the parameters of his
Easter table. For these reasons, as well as the fact that this paragraph
is not transmitted in Recension A, I believe that this paragraph also
represents a later addition, which may be connected to § of Argumentum I, as will be argued in the following; at least it was added to
the Dionysiac corpus before that got a wider distribution in form of
the Group B corpus.
Argumenta I–X: In summary, of the argumenta preserved in the
Group B corpus, §§ and of Argumentum I, Argumentum II, § of
Argumenta III and IV, Argumenta V, VI, and VIII, and § of Argumenta IX and X can be regarded as Dionysiac and seem to have
formed the original corpus of Dionysiac argumenta. On the other
hand, § of Argumentum I, § of Argumenta III and IIII, Argumentum VII, and § of Argumenta IX and X have been identified as
pseudo-Dionysiac. But can these additions be classified, i.e. were
some of these added at the same time? Only § of Argumenta III
and IV can be connected with some degree of certainty, since both
have very similar phrasing in their first sentence, and they are the
only additions that provide new formulae. Because of these formulae, § of Argumentum III can be dated implicitly to , § of
Argumentum IV to or shortly thereafter. Hence, it seems that
these two paragraphs were added to the corpus in or shortly
thereafter. As for the place of this addition, the reference to the
Byzantine emperor Tiberius Constantinus in § of Argumentum IV
suggests a place that was either part of the Byzantine empire, or at
least in close contact with it. We need not to assume that the original corpus had travelled very far at this early stage, so some place
in Italy, either under Byzantine rule or with strong Byzantine connections, seems most likely. As for the remaining four additions, §
of Argumentum I and § of Argumentum X have a quality distinctly
different from the other two, since they provide further detailed
technical explanations from the hand of a skilled computist, while
Argumentum VII is a mere list, which could have been compiled
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 89
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
from any Easter table, and § of Argumentum IX is a confused
explanation of the fixed parameters of the preceding algorithm.
Thus, if these four additions were to be grouped, I would be
inclined to connect § of Argumentum I with § of Argumentum X,
and Argumentum VII with § of Argumentum IX. § of Argumentum I suggests the date for its addition, but it may well have
been added retrospectively; I would not rule out the possibility
that § of Argumentum I and § of Argumentum X were added at
the same time as § of Argumenta III and IV. Argumentum VII and
§ of Argumentum IX, however, seem to me to be disconnected
from the other four additions.
All this must obviously remain very speculative. Nevertheless,
for the outlined reasons I would at least propose that § of Argumenta III and IV were added to the corpus in or shortly thereafter, § of Argumentum I and § of Argumentum X earlier or at the
same time, while Argumentum VII and § of Argumentum IX were
presumably added later, but before the end of the first quarter of the
seventh century; all these additions seem to have been included
before the corpus, as it is now preserved in Group B and
Recension B, left Italy.
The complexity of the different levels of the just discussed first ten
argumenta has been noted in passing by only very few scholars, most
notably Jan and van der Hagen, and, more recently, Neugebauer and
Declercq. Concerning the subsequent Argumenta XI to XVI in the
Computus Digbaeanus, however, recent scholars like Borst and Springsfeld believe that they were possibly invented, but certainly added to
the corpus in , presumably in Ireland.140 This view needs serious
revision, as the following discussion will show.
Argumenta XI to XIII: The opinion that Argumenta XI to XVI were
possibly composed and added to the corpus in is based on the
fact that Argumenta XI and XII in the Computus Digbaeanus contain dating clauses for that year, which have been the earliest dating clauses for these argumenta known to modern scholars of
computistics. Yet, an important piece of evidence, discovered
years ago, has been overlooked by these scholars, namely the Fragmentum Nanciacense discussed above.141 This fragment suggests
that the three Argumenta XI to XIII formed an entity, and that they
140
141
Cf. pp. – above.
Cf. pp. – above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 90
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
were probably invented in , if not earlier. would have been
a very appropriate date for the composition of new argumenta,
since the Dionysiac Easter table ended in the following year, ,
and the continuation of that Easter table made re-calculations
necessary.142
Having established as the most likely date for the composition
of Argumenta XI to XIII, the question of their provenance remains.
This early date obviously suggests that they were composed somewhere in Italy or Spain, because these were the only Latin speaking
places where the Dionysiac reckoning was accepted at that time.
Rome, the Frankish kingdoms, Christian Kent and Northumbria
would rather have followed the Victorian reckoning, while the ()year Easter reckoning still prevailed in Ireland and the British kingdoms, as well as Pictland.143 In fact, two facts speak strongly for the
western Mediterranean world in general, and Italy in particular: ) The
provenance of the manuscript to which the Fragmentum Nanciacense is
attached is believed to be Bobbio, and the same may be true for this
flyleaf;144 ) in Argumentum XIII computistical methods are applied,
which are also described by Maximus Confessor in his Computus ecclesiasticus of , and which may ultimately go back to fifth century
north African computistics.145 Maximus wrote his computitistical
treatise in the North African part of the Byzantine Empire and therefore this argumentum may also have been composed in a place under
Byzantine control, or at least with close connections to the Empire,
somewhere between Bobbio and North Africa.
There is no evidence that this group of Argumenta XI–XIII was
attached to the Dionysiac corpus (or rather the Group B corpus)
142 For the end of the Dionysiac Easter table see Krusch (), . The necessary
re-calculations are explained by Dionysius himself in his prologue (Krusch (), ).
Since Argumenta XII and XIII deal with the calculation of the solar and lunar data for
January, it seems to me that these argumenta were invented to add columns for
January to the continuation of the Dionysiac Easter table. Columns for the feria and
luna of January can be found in later Easter tables of the Dionysiac reckoning, e.g.
in an Easter table for – transmitted in MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica,
Pal. Lat. , v–r; MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Pal. Lat. , v–r;
MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Reg. Lat. , r–v.
143 Unfortunately, there is no authoritative study on the adoption of the different
Easter reckonings in Western Europe. Valuable, but often outdated information on
this question can be found in: Krusch (); Poole (a–b); Schmid (); Schmid
(); Jones ().
144
Cf. n above.
145 Cf. Appendix II below.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 91
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
before it was included in the Computus Digbaeanus in ;
consequently it seems to me that this group of Argumenta XI–XIII and
the Group B corpus had disconnected histories before .
Argumentum XIV: This argumentum is one of the most popular in
early computistical literature. The reason for this popularity obviously is its concise method for calculating the Julian calendar date
and the weekday of the Easter full moon, as well as the Julian calendar date and lunar age of Easter Sunday. Its earliest version provides
an implicit dating clause for to , and it is this version which
accompanied the Dionysiac argumenta in Group B and which was
then incorporated in the Computus Digbaeanus and the Computus
Cottonianus.146 The chronological data were later adapted to match
the years –, which was probably done very close to these
years.147 Another and more detailed version of this argumentum was
composed in and is commonly ascribed to Alcuin.148 Moreover,
numerous variations of his argumentum can be found in later computistical texts and manuscripts.
Even though the implicit dating clause of the earliest version suggests as the date of composition, there are good reasons to doubt
this. If it was composed in , one would expect it to be quite naturally included in the corpus of Dionysiac argumenta. Yet, it is not part
of, nor does it travel with Recension A of , and neither is it connected with Recension B; moreover, even though this argumentum is
attached to Group B texts, it is at the same time markedly separated
from the main corpus of argumenta. Consequently, there is no evidence that it became part of a larger corpus of argumenta before its
inclusion in the Computus Digbaeanus and the Computus Cottonianus.
Thus, from the existing evidence the incorporation of Argumentum
XIV into a larger corpus can be dated to .
From the manuscript evidence it seems, then, that Argumentum XIV
was composed and attached to the Dionysiac argumenta after the inclusion of all additions to its main body, i.e. after the Group B corpus was
established, but before this corpus got a wider distribution, since it is
This version is discussed in detail on pp. – above.
This version can be found, e.g., in MS Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale, Lat.
, r-v (cf. Springsfeld (), ); MS München, Bayerische Staatsbibliothek,
Clm , v–v. The characteristic of this version is that the concurrentes given in
the three examples are , , and respectively.
148 For this version see especially Jones (), –, –; Springsfeld (),
–, –.
146
147
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 92
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
attached to every Group B text. Hence, I would suggest the late sixth or
early seventh century for its composition, before the Group B corpus
with Argumentum XIV attached left Italy. This is confirmed by the fact
that the algorithm described in Argumentum XIV was at least partially
known to Maximus Confessor in ;149 it is possible that Maximus
worked directly from Argumentum XIV; on the other hand, it is at least as
likely that the algorithm itself was an old invention of the Greek speaking
East (with Alexandria as its computistical centre), but that it became
known to the Latin speaking West only by the late sixth or early seventh
century through Argumentum XIV. Either way, this would again suggest
that Argumentum XIV was composed (in Latin) in a centre somewhere in
Italy that was part of, or at least in contact with the Byzantine Empire.
The examples for to in this argumentum were then obviously chosen because they represent the first three years in the Dionysiac Easter
table, which were regarded as appropriate, neutral examples.
Argumenta XV and XVI: It has been suggested so far that none of the
previous argumenta was actually composed in . Consequently, only
Argumentum XV and XVI may have been original contribution by the
author of the Computus Digbaeanus, and therefore only these two argumenta may provide a clue about the provenance of this computus. They
are not argumenta in van der Hagen’s strict sense, since they do not supply mathematical algorithms; for that reason they can also not be dated
with certainty. From the evidence of the Computus Digbaeanus, it
seems, however, quite certain that these argumenta were composed
either in or earlier. Argumentum XV deals with theological explanations of the equinoxes and solstices, as well as the chronology of Christ’s
life. Argumentum XVI discusses the bissextile day, including a curious
division of the hours of a year by to explain the annual increase
of the bissextile day. Now, the topic of Argumentum XV was prominent
in Bede’s De temporum ratione, as well as in Irish computistical textbooks of the late seventh and early eighth century, and from these
sources it found its way into Frankish computistics.150 The division
Cf. Maximus Confessor, Computus ecclesiasticus I (PG , –).
Cf. Bede, De temporum ratione (Jones (), ); Munich Computus
(MS München, Bayerische Staatsbibliothek, r–r; an edition is forthcoming) f r;
Computus Einsidlensis (MS Einsiedeln, Stiftsbibliothek, (), –) pp. –;
Bobbio Computus , (PL , , ); Lib. comp. I b (Borst (),
); Lib. calc. (Borst (), ). For the recently discovered Computus Einsidlensis see Warntjes () and now also Bisagni and Warntjes (). For the theological explanations of the equinoxes and solstices discussed in this argumentum see also
Strobel (), –.
149
150
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 93
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
given in Argumentum XVI, however, curious as it is, cannot be found in
Bede’s computistical writings, but was particularly popular in Irish
computistical textbooks contemporary to the Computus Digbaeanus,
and then later in Frankish computistics, drawing on these Irish
sources.151 From this perspective it seems that one has to consider Ireland rather than Anglo-Saxon England or the continent for the provenance of the Computus Digbaeanus.
On the other hand, it is a very curious fact that only the dating
clauses of Argumenta XI and XII were accommodated to the annus
praesens of in the Computus Digbaeanus. The reason for this may
have been that the compiler knew about the significance of the
date, and did not want to undermine Dionysius’ authority by changing the dating clause. Only Argumenta XI and XII, then, explicitly
referred to a year other than , namely , and the compiler saw no
reason why he should not accommodate this to his annus praesens. Yet,
he seems not to have been computistically skilled enough to change
the implicit dating clause of Argumentum XIII, which still preserves
the dating. Anyway, the fact that the compiler of the Computus
Digbaeanus actually worked on two of these argumenta is interesting in
itself. None of the Irish computistical textbooks mentions any of the
algorithms given in the first argumenta; the calculations in these
textbooks are executed by strikingly different and simpler methods. In
fact, the term annus domini itself is not mentioned in any of them, and
neither is the term concurrentes, both being absolute essentials for an
understanding of the Dionysiac formulae. From the evidence of these
textbooks it seems that Irish computists applied methods of calculation to the Dionysiac reckoning that they had already used for the latercus (the ()-year reckoning) and the Victorian reckoning; these
had proven their value over decades, if not centuries, and Irish computists felt no need to adopt formulae based on new chronological
concepts they were unfamiliar with, like annus domini. For these
reasons I suspect that the Computus Digbaeanus was compiled in an
Anglo-Saxon centre rather than an Irish one, considering especially that Bede used the Dionysiac argumenta as early as .152 Yet,
151 Munich Computus fols v–r; Computus Einsidlensis p. (for this passage
cf. Bisagni and Warntjes (), –); Bobbio Computus , (PL , –);
Dial. Burg. (Borst (), ); De Bissexto (PL , –; for this text see especially Springsfeld (), –); Lib. comp. I f (Borst (), ).
152
Bede, De temporibus (Jones (), –). For further arguments for an
Anglo-Saxon authorship of the Computus Digbaeanus see Appendix II.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 94
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
as mentioned above, the division given in Argumentum XVI does
not appear in Anglo-Saxon, but is prominent in Irish computistica.
Therefore, my best guess is that the Computus Digbaeanus was
compiled in an Anglo-Saxon centre in Ireland, such as Rath Melsigi,
but monastics centres in Anglo-Saxon England certainly cannot be
ruled out.153
Conclusion
This article has demonstrated that the text published as the argumenta
attributed to Dionysius, i.e. the Computus Digbaeanus of , comprises not only the original Dionysiac corpus, but also different layers
of additions, which illustrate (if not represent) the development of
computistical formularies written in Latin from to . The different stages in this development are the following:
1) The original Dionysiac corpus of is the first known computistical formulary written in Latin. It has not survived in its original extent in any manuscript, but can be reconstructed,
primarily on the basis of Recension A (the Computus paschalis of
), as consisting of the following argumenta: §§ and of
Argumentum I, Argumentum II, § of Argumenta III and IV,
Argumenta V, VI, and VIII, § of Argumenta IX and X.
2) In the course of the sixth and possibly early seventh century, §
of Argumentum I, § of Argumenta III and IV, Argumentum VII,
153 The provenance of the manuscript (which is highly disputed; cf. n above)
is irrelevant for the question of the provenance of the Computus Digbaeanus, since a
text could have travelled anywhere in the years between the composition of the
text and that of the codex. For Anglo-Saxon centres in Ireland in general, and Rath
Melsigi in particular, see especially Ó Cróinín (), reprinted in Ó Cróinín (),
–. It should be noted that the hypothesis of the Computus Digbaeanus being
composed in an Anglo-Saxon centre in Ireland depends heavily on the evidence of
Argumentum XVI, which, in the end, may not even have been part of Computus Digbaeanus proper (cf. p. ?? above); additionally, even though the curious mathematical
explanation of the annual bissextile increase outlined in Argumentum XVI cannot be
found in Bedan computistica, it is, interestingly enough, attributed to a certain
Theodore in the Computus Einsidlensis p. ; if the identification of this Theodore
with Theodore of Tharsus, archbishop of Canterbury (as proposed by Bisagni and
Warntjes (), –) is accepted, then the Computus Digbaeanus may as likely
have been composed in Anglo-Saxon England in general, in Theodore’s Canterbury
school in particular.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 95
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
§ of Argumenta IX and X were added to the original corpus.
Only the addition of § of Argumenta III and IV can be dated
with some certainty to or slightly later; it has been suggested
that § of Argumentum I and § of Argumentum X were presumably added at the same time or earlier (possibly ), while
Argumentum VII and § of Argumentum IX may have been
added later. All these additions seem to have been composed
and integrated in the original corpus before that corpus got a
wider distribution outside of Italy; § of Argumenta III and IV
probably originated in a centre under Byzantine control, or at
least with some connection to the Empire. This body of argumenta is transmitted as a strictly defined corpus in Group B
texts and Recension B (the Computus Parisinus of /).
3) Argumentum XIV was then attached to this Group B corpus,
presumably in the late sixth or early seventh century, in all
likelihood also in Italy, possibly in a Byzantine centre, or a
centre with contact to the Empire. Yet, this argumentum was
kept strictly separated from the main corpus, as witnessed in
Group B.
4) Argumenta XI to XIII were in all likelihood composed as a group
in (as illustrated in Recension C, i.e. the Fragmentum Nanciacense), in Bobbio or some other Italian centre with Byzantine
connections. There is no evidence that this group was connected with or even attached to the Group B corpus before its
inclusion in the Computus Digbaeanus, but it is not unlikely
that it left Italy in a manuscript which also included the Group
B corpus.
5) Finally, the group of Argumenta XI to XIII was inserted between
the Group B corpus and Argumentum XIV, and Argumenta XV
and XVI were added to this enlarged corpus; additionally, the
marked separation of these groups was abandoned. This newly
defined corpus of argumenta survived uniquely as the Computus Digbaeanus of , which was probably compiled in an
Anglo-Saxon centre, possibly rather in Ireland (such as Rath
Melsigi) than in Anglo-Saxon England proper, though the latter
option can by no means be ruled out.
The abandonment of the strict definition of the Group B corpus in
basically opened this corpus up to further additions, which ultimately led to its complete disintegration. The earliest witness to this
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 96
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
disintegration is the Computus Cottonianus of /. Even though the
phrasing of the argumenta remained essentially unaltered in this text,
almost all of the original dating clauses were already accommodated to
the annus praesens of the compiler. Not long after that, in , Bede
began the process of generalising these argumenta, in which only the
algorithms remain unchanged. In the eighth and ninth century, then, the
Dionysiac formulae were usually only known through later recensions.154
Appendices
Appendix I: Argumenta XI–XIII in the Fragmentum Nanciacense (Nancy,
Bibliothèque Municipale, ())
⬍Argumentum XI⬎
. . . ⬍rem⬎anent VII: septima luna in XI Kalendas Aprilis . . .
⬍Argumentum XII⬎
Si uis nosse diem Kalendarum Ianuarium per singulos annos quota
sit feria, sume annos ab incarnatione Domini nostri Ihesu Christi, ut
put⬍a⬎ annos DCXXV; deduc assem, remanent DCXXIIII. Hos per
quartam partem partire, et quartam, quam partitus es, adiecies super
DC⬍XXIIII⬎, fiunt DCCLXXX. Hos partiris per septem, remanent
III; tertia feri⬍a⬎ Kalendarum die Ianuarii. Si IIII, quarta feria; si V,
quinta feria; si VI, sexta ⬍fe⬎ria; si asse, dominicus; si nihil, sabbatum.
⬍Argumentum XIII⬎
Si uis scire, quota sit luna Kalendis Ianuariis, scito quotus lunaris
ciclus lunaris XV est. Tene tibi unum, id est, ipsam diem Kalendas
Ia⬍nu⬎arias, et deduces quinques deciis, V quinques, faciunt LXXV;
quos ⬍ad⬎iecias super unum, et fiunt LXXVI. Item ducis sexies
deciis, V sexies, faciunt LXL; quos adiecias super LXXVI, et fit
numerorum summa CLX⬍VI⬎, in quibus partiris tricissima, remanent XVI; sexdecima luna est in Kalendis Ianuariis, et puncta XLII.
Isto modo per X et VIIII ciclos lunares conputa⬍bis⬎ semper in
Kalendis Ianuariis, ut quota sit luna absque errore re⬍pperi⬎es.
Dum autem ueneris ad XVII ciclum lunarem et duxeris quinques
deciis ⬍se⬎ptus super Kalendas Ianuarias, qui faciunt dies LXXXV.155
154 For a brief sketch of the fate of the Dionysiac formulae from the late seventh to
the early ninth century see pp. – above.
155 Here follows mistakenly: Deinde d⬍u⬎cis sexies, octuagenta v.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 97
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Si partiris sexagissima et adiecias ipsum as⬍sem⬎, fiunt LXXXVI.
Deinde duces sexies deciis septus, fiunt CII; quos adiecias ⬍super⬎
LXXXVI, et fiunt CLXXXVIII. Partiris ibi tricissima, remanent VIII;
octaua luna est in Kalendis Ianuariis et puncta XXIIII. Sic et in XVIII
et XVIIII ciclo facies. A primo uero ciclo lunari usque in XVII non
partiris sexaginsimam partem ne in errorem incedas. Finit Amen
fini⬍t⬎.
Appendix II: Explanation of Argumentum XIII
Argumentum XIII has puzzled modern computists over the past three
hundred years and has never been satisfactorily explained in every
detail. Jan admitted that he did not entirely understand Argumenta XI
to XVI,156 and this was arguably especially true for Argumentum XIII.
It seems that the number of points mentioned in this argmentum irritated him more than anything else; since he did not know how to
interpret these numbers, he referred to Bede (De temporum ratione ),
who described the increase and decrease of moonlight by four points
per day (with five points defining an hour), and to Argumentum XVI,
where an hour is defined as consisting of four points; he then left it to
the reader to establish, which of these two theories was to be applied
to make sense of the points mentioned in this argumentum, if any
sense could be made of them. Additionally, Jan notes various variants
(especially in numbers) from the Computus Cottonianus, illustrating
that even medieval copyists were confused by this text. Van der Hagen,
then, drew attention to the fact that this argumentum has parallels with
the Computus ecclesiasticus of Maximus Confessor. At the same time,
he pointed out that the algorithm of Argumentum XIII can be found in
De temporum ratione , but that Bede does not mention any superfluous points.157 It is through this chapter in De temporum ratione that
the formula given in Argumentum XIII is generally well explained,158
and I have described the general method in detail above.159 This
Jan (), .
Van der Hagen (), .
158 Cf. Jones (), , –; Wallis (), (both argue somewhat misleadingly that the lunar age of January is in the first year of the cyclus lunaris; correct is
rather that the fixed parameter in the formula refers to the lunar age of January of
the preceding, i.e. the th and final year (cf. p. above); they are confused by the fact
that Bede started the cyclus lunaris a year early in his description of it in De temporum
ratione ; for this inconsistency in Bede’s account see also Pillonel-Wyrsch (),
–).
159 Cf. p. above.
156
157
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 98
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
formula became quite popular in eighth- and early ninth-century
computistics, since it can also be found in the Bobbio Computus,
Lectiones sive regula conputi (Lect. comp.), Annalis libellus (Lib. ann.),
Libri computi (Lib. comp.), Liber calculationis (Lib. calc.), and
Hrabanus Maurus’ De Computo.160
Nevertheless, the formula is not as clearly and plausibly explained
in Argumentum XIII as it is in these other computistical texts (with the
exception of Lect. comp.), which is primarily due to the fact that different computistical techniques are used in Argumentum XIII; moreover,
some additional details are mentioned in Argumentum XIII, like the
superfluous points, that cannot be explained by any of the other versions of the formula. How confusing the account in Argumentum XIII
appears to the modern computist is illustrated by the fact that Springsfeld could not make sense of Argumentum XIII, even though she
explains the same algorithm in Lib. ann. perfectly.161 Still, good mathematical discussions of this argumentum by Nikolaus A. Bär and
Michael Deckers can now be found on the world wide web.162 Yet, Bär
does not discuss the problem of the meaning of the points, while
Deckers cautiously suggests that they may refer to the annual increase
of the saltus lunae.
In general, there are three aspects that make this argumentum difficult to understand:
1) The first is the partition of the multiplicand into and
(i.e. ⫽⫹). This may slightly confuse the reader, but it obviously makes no difference in the calculation. Such a partition is
very uncommon in early medieval computistics, since it does not
really simplify the algorithm. Van der Hagen had drawn attention
to the fact that Maximus Confessor referred to people who
followed the same practice;163 yet, for their calculations this
Bobbio Computus prefix (PL , ); Lect. comp. V (Borst (), ;
Borst argues that this chapter deals with the calculation of the lunar age of any given
Julian calendar day; yet, the algorithm given rather refers to the calculation of the
lunar age of January; interestingly enough, the multiplicand is here also divided
into and , as in Argumentum XIII ); Lib. ann. (Borst (), ); Lib. comp.
IIII (Borst (), ); Lib. calc. (Borst (), ) ; Hrabanus Maurus, De
Computo (CCCM , ).
161 Springsfeld (), –, –.
162 Nikolaus A. Bär: http://www.nabkal.de/dionys.html; Michael Deckers:
http://hbar.phys.msu.su/gorm/chrono/paschata.htm.
163 Maximus Confessor, Computus ecclesiasticus I , , II , (PG , –,
–, –).
160
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 99
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
partition of into and was a necessity.164 Since the formulae
described by Maximus Confessor are different from the one in
Argumentum XIII, but similar in their method of calculation, it
may be inferred here that the author of Argumentum XIII came
from a similar, if not the same computistical school as the computists referred to by Maximus Confessor. Since Maximus Confessor wrote his treatise in North Africa, and since the computistical
methods described by him ultimately go back to fifth-century
Northern African computistics,165 the author of Argumentum XIII
possibly also came from that region; at least it is hardly likely that
this argumentum was composed outside the western Mediterranean world.166
2) More problematic is the second example given in Argumentum
XIII. After explaining the algorithm by means of the th year of
the cyclus lunaris, which undoubtedly refers to the annus praesens of the composition of this argumentum, i.e. AD ,167 the
author does not choose the following year as his second example, but rather the th of the cyclus lunaris. The reason for this is
that for the th to the th year an alteration of the formula
became necessary, which the author wanted to illustrate here:
the saltus lunae is applied in the th year, which led to an
increase of instead of lunar days between the th and th
year; consequently, had to be added to the existing formula.168
Now, this addition of was executed in the most unlikely manner in this argumentum, namely by arguing that the product of
the year in the cyclus lunaris multiplied by has to be divided by
and the integer from that division has then to be added to
the product. This division by was to be applied only for years
to of the cyclus lunaris. Now, since the products of ,
and multiplied by range between and (⫻⫽,
⫻⫽, ⫻⫽), the integer when divided by is in
all three cases. This odd division by is a reminiscence of
calculations described by Maximus Confessor, in which
164 For these calculations see especially Schwartz (), –. Maximus
Confessor himself (Computus ecclesiasticus I (PG , –)) calculated the lunar
age of January from the year in the cyclus decemnovennalis without partitioning the
multiplicand .
165
See especially Schwartz (), .
166 For this question see also p. above.
167 For this annus praesens see p. above.
168 For this alteration of the algorithm see also p. above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 100
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
/⫽/ denoted the increase of the saltus per year, i.e. the year saltus of the Supputatio Romana, and again points to North
African computistics.169 Because of this association of the division by with the saltus lunae, the addition of one that
resulted from the saltus lunae being applied in the th year of
the cyclus lunaris is described in these odd terms here.
Unfortunately, this second example is not transmitted uncorrupted in the three primary witnesses of Argumentum XIII, i.e.
the Fragmentum Nanciacense, the Computus Digbaeanus and
the Computus Cottonianus. The problem is that in all three
accounts the fixed parameter in the algorithm, which was
introduced in the first example, is not mentioned in this second example: The Fragmentum Nanciacense calculates consistently without this fixed parameter, thus establishing the lunar
age for January of the th year of the cyclus lunaris; in the
Computus Digbaeanus and the Computus Cottonianus this
parameter is silently added: in the Computus Digbaeanus
⫹⫽, in the Computus Cottonianus ⫹⫽, eventually resulting in luna on January of the th year of the cyclus
lunaris.
How, then, did this corruption occur? There cannot be any
doubt that the original Argumentum XIII mentioned this
fixed parameter , since the second example was designed to
demonstrate the impact of the saltus lunae, i.e. the extra addition of , on this calculation; the formula would de facto not
have been altered, if this fixed parameter was omitted. Consequently, Argumentum XIII must have been tampered with
later, and for a specific reason: In the original Argumentum
XIII the saltus lunae was applied before January of the th
year of the cyclus lunaris, presumably at the end of the previous November lunation; yet, a different tradition also existed,
namely to apply the saltus at the end of the following March
lunation, i.e. after January of the th year of the cyclus
lunaris. Hence, I suspect that followers of this March place
of the saltus altered this example for calculating the lunar age
of the th year of the cylus lunaris by omitting the fixed
parameter , and thus arrived at luna , which they regarded
See especially Maximus Confessor, Computus ecclesiasticus I , II (PG ,
–, –) and Schwartz (), –.
169
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 101
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
as correct, rather than luna . This altered version of the
original Argumentum XIII is transmitted through the Fragmentum Nanciacense, and this alteration may well have been
executed in Bobbio.170 It was such an altered version, then,
that received a wider distribution throughout Western
Europe, while it was later silently corrected by followers of
the November place of the saltus, presumably by Anglo-Saxon
computists, as illustrated in the Computus Digbaeanus and
Computus Cottonianus.171
3) Yet the aspect that puzzled modern commentators on Argumentum XIII most is the mentioning of the points. First of all it
needs to be pointed out that the Computus Digbaeanus and the
Computus Cottonianus transmit identical numbers, which disagree with the numbers of points given in the Fragmentum
Nanciacense. As will be presently seen, this is due to the fact that
different concepts are are uunderlying these two versions of
Argumentum XIII. I will deal with both in turn:
a) The Computus Digbaeanus and the Computus Cottonianus
give i) luna and points on January of the th year of
the cyclus lunaris and ii) luna and points on January of
the th year of the cyclus lunaris. What is meant by these
points here is the exact time of the day at which the moonrise occurs, i.e. the number of points between the beginning
of the first hour of that day and moonrise. The algorithm is
explained in Frankish computistics, namely in the Computus
Rhenanus of , Lectiones sive regula conputi (Lect. comp.),
Annalis libellus (Lib. ann.), Libri computi (Lib. comp.), Liber
170
In later computistics, the March place of the saltus lunae was a specifically
Irish application, while the November place became standard in Anglo-Saxon computistics. This is not only evident from Irish and Bede’s computistical textbooks (as
well as Alcuin’s letters), but it is also explicitly expressed by the Irish computist
Dicuil, writing in the Frankish kingdoms in – (Dicuil, Liber de astronomia I
(Esposito (), reprinted in Esposito (), ): Etsi lunarem saltum in vigesimo
quarto die mensis Novembris, secundum Anglos, complere volueris [ . . .]. Sed si secundum Grecorum ac Latinorum regulam, quam mea gens in Hibernia in hac ratione semper custodit, praedictum saltum in vigesimo secundo die mensis sequentis, iuxta primum
tempus creationis lunae rationabiliter observaveris. The Irish may well have adopted a
practice that was earlier followed in some Italian centres with Irish connections, most
notably Bobbio.
171 For the association of the place of the saltus lunae in November with AngloSaxon computistics see the previous note. For further arguments for an Anglo-Saxon
authorship of the Computus Digbaeanus see p. above.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 102
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
calculationis (Lib. calc.):172 Count the number of days from
January to the day in question; add the product of the year
of the cyclus lunaris in which this day occurs multiplied by ;
divide this sum by ; then the remainder denotes the number of points between the beginning of the first hour and
moonrise; in mathematical terms:
(number of days from January⫹year in cyclus
lunaris⫻)mod ⫽ points between beginning of first
hour and moonrise
If this theory is applied to the examples in Argumentum
XIII, then the results are exactly the numbers of points
mentioned:
i) the number of days from January to January is
(counted inclusively); the year of the cyclus lunaris is ,
and ⫻⫽; hence, (⫹)mod⫽, i.e. the number
of points given in Argumentum XIII; since points equal
hour in this algorithm, this means that on January in
the th year of the cyclus lunaris the moon rises in the first
point of the fourth hour of the day.
ii) the number of days from January to January is
(counted inclusively); the year of the cyclus lunaris is ,
and ⫻⫽; hence, (⫹)mod⫽, i.e. the number of points given in Argumentum XIII; since points
equal hour, this means that on January in the th year
of the cyclus lunaris the moon rises in the first point of the
sixth hour of the day.
Again, this algorithm shows parallels to the calculations
described by Maximus Confessor, even though the applications are different.173 Nevertheless, the feature of multiplying the year of the cyclus lunaris by and dividing the
product by seems in both cases to be a reminiscence of
the -year saltus of the Supputation Romana, since
/⫽/. The general idea of this division seems to
172 Computus Rhenanus (MS Köln, Diözesan- und Dombibliothek, , v;
MS Wolfenbüttel, Herzog-August-Bibliothek, Weißenburg , r; for this text see
pp. – above); Lect. comp. V (Borst (), ); Lib. ann. (Borst (), );
Lib. comp. IIII (Borst (), ); Lib. calc. (Borst (), ). Borst’s commentary to these chapters is misleading.
173 Cf. Maximus Confessor, Computus ecclesiasticus I , II (PG , col. –,
–) and Schwartz (), –.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 103
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
have been to calculate the impact of the saltus lunae on
the lunar calculation of any given year of the cyclus
lunaris, even though the -year saltus had obviously no
connection to a -year luni-solar cycle. The wrong
application of mechanisms used for the Supputatio
Romana to a -year luni-solar cycle, and thus the close
resemblance with calculations described by Maximus
Confessor (ultimately deriving from fifth-century North
African computistics) appears to suggest that this algorithm either originated in North Africa in Maximus
Confessor’s time or earlier, or that methods introduced
by North African computists later found their application in the West.
b) On the other hand, the equivalent passage in the Fragmentum
Nanciacense reads ‘luna and points’ and ‘luna and
points’. These numbers of points can be explained by an
uncommon system for calculating the length of moonlight per
lunar day. The common theory of this question in the early
Middle Ages is that the length of moonlight increases and
decreases with the waxing and the waning of the moon by
points per lunar day: the length of moonlight for luna is
points, for luna points, etc. until it is points for luna ;
from luna it then decreases by points, so that it is points
for luna , etc. until it is points for luna ; of these points
constitute an hour, so that the longest period of moonlight is
hours on luna . This theory can be found in the Bobbio
Computus, De temporum ratione, Annalis libellus (Lib. ann.),
Libri computi (Lib. comp.), the Computus of Pacificus of
Verona, and Hrabanus Maurus’ De computo.174 The theory
applied in the Fragmentum Nanciacense version of Argumentum
XIII is slightly different in that it can be established that the
increase and decrease of the length of moonlight is points per
lunar day rather than : for luna : ⫻⫽ points, for luna :
⫻–⫻⫽ points. In this theory it seems that an hour is
Bobbio Computus (PL , ); Bede, De temporum ratione (Jones
(), –); Lib. ann. , (Borst (), –); Lib. comp. IIII (Borst (),
);, Computus of Pacificus of Verona §§– (Meersseman and Adda (),
–); Hrabanus Maurus, De computo (CCCM , –). For this theory cf.
Jones (), ; Springsfeld (), ; Pillonel-Wyrsch (), – (including
a rather meaningless comparison with modern observations).
174
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 104
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
defined as consisting of points rather than , so that the
longest period of moonlight, i.e. for luna , would be
points⫽¼ hours, which can be compared to the hours
given in the common theory. Now, this interpretation of the
numbers of points in the Fragmentum Nanciacense would have
to remain speculative, were it not for the fortunate fact that the
theory described is transmitted in a computistical MS, namely
the often cited mid-eighth century (and therefore one of the
oldest computistical codices that have survived) MS London,
British Library, Cotton Caligula A , v:
Incipit de luna quantum lucit in noctae
Momenta XII faciunt uncia una, et uncias III faciunt puncto I,
et puncti quattuor faciunt ora una.
Luna prima lucet uncias VIIII, qui faciunt punctis III; luna
secunda hora et dimidia lucet; luna tertia horas II et uncias
III; luna quarta horas III lucet; luna quinta horas III et
uncias VIIII; luna sexta horas IIII et uncias sex; luna septima horas V et uncias III; luna octaua horas sex; luna nona
horas sex et uncias VIIII; luna X horas septem et uncias sex;
luna XI horas VIII et uncias III; luna XII horas nouem;
luna XIII horas VIIII et uncias VIIII; luna XIIII horas X et
uncias sex; luna XV horas XI et uncias III; luna XVI horas
XI; luna XVII horas X et uncias III; luna XVIII horas X et
uncias VI; luna XVIIII horas VIIII et uncias VIIII; luna XX
horas nouem; luna XXI horas VIII et uncias III; luna XXII
horas VII et uncias VI; luna XXIII horas VI et uncias VIIII;
luna XXIIII horas sex; luna XXV horas V et uncias tres;
luna XXVI horas IIII et uncias VI; luna XXVII horas III et
uncias VIIII; luna XXVIII horas tres; luna XXVIIII horas II
et uncias III; luna XXX hora una.
Note that this passage agrees with the theory outlined
above only in its first half, namely by recording a consistent
increase of moonlight by points per lunar day from luna
to luna . In the second half, however, this passage is
inconsistent by recording a decrease of only one point from
luna to , an increase (!) of a point from luna to luna
, and a decrease of points from luna to luna . It
may well be that the copyist was only familiar with the
common theory, realised when copying the data for luna
that the theory he copied does not agree with what he was
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 105
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
used to ( ¼ instead of hours of moonlight for luna ),
and then tampered with the following data to get closer to
his own data.
A few words remain to be said about the transmission of Argumentum XIII. As has been pointed out above, it seems that the original
argumentum (a) has not survived, since the mentioning of the fixed
parameter was deliberately omitted in the second example (I denote
this version, in which the fixed parameter was omitted in the second
example, as b). Moreover, since two different concepts for the calculation of the mentioned points are applied in the surviving recensions of
this argumentum, the question remains which of these concepts was
applied in a. Since the methods of calculation used in the concept
transmitted in the Computus Digbaeanus and the Computus Cottonianus have parallels with the general algorithm of this argumentum,
I believe that the number of points transmitted in these two texts represent the original. They remained unaltered in b, and were only
changed according to a different concept when copied in the Fragmentum Nanciacense. The deliberate omission of the fixed parameter in b
was retained in the Fragmentum Nanciacense, since this seems to have
suited the computistical custom of the Irish copyist. In the Computus
Digbaeanus and the Computus Cottonianus, however, this parameter
was silently added, because their compilers, being probably trained in
an Anglo-Saxon computistical milieu, followed the same practice as the
author of the original argumentum. Since this silent addition was made
in different parts of the calculation, it seems unlikely that Argumentum
XIII of the Computus Cottonianus was directly copied from the Computus Digbaeanus. Hence, the content of these three versions suggests the
following basic stemma (Figure ), even though only a proper edition of
Argumentum XIII can solve the question of their relation:
FPO
Figure 2 Tentative stemma of the early transmission of Argumentum XIII.
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 106
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
Appendix III: Facsimiles
Plate 1 Argumenta I–X as a strictly defined corpus with Argumentum XIV
attached as found in Group B texts (here MS Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica,
Pal. Lat. , v–r). (Continued)
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 107
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Plate 1 (Continued)
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 108
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
Plate 1 (Continued)
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 109
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Plate 2 The Computus Parisinus of AD / (MS Paris, Bibliothèque
Nationale, Nouvelle acquisition , r–r). (Continued)
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 110
COMPUTUS AND ITS CULTURAL CONTEXT IN THE LATIN WEST, AD 300–1200
Plate 2 (Continued)
Chapter 02.qxp:Chapter 02.qxp
9/10/09
3:56 PM
Page 111
THE ARGUMENTA OF DIONYSIUS EXIGUUS AND THEIR EARLY RECENSIONS
Plate 3 The Fragmentum Nanciacense (MS Nancy, Bibliothèque
municipale, ()).