UNIVERSITY OF MIAMI
DISPUTES:
THE INCOMMENSURABLE GREATNESS OF MICRO-WARS
By
Felipe G. A. Moreira
A DISSERTATION
Submitted to the Faculty
of the University of Miami
in partial fulfillment of the requirements for
the degree of Doctor of Philosophy
Coral Gables, Florida
May 2019
©2019
Felipe G. A. Moreira
All Rights Reserved
UNIVERSITY OF MIAMI
A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of
the requirements for the degree of
Doctor of Philosophy
DISPUTES:
THE INCOMMENSURABLE GREATNESS OF MICRO-WARS
Felipe G. A. Moreira
Approved:
________________
Otávio Bueno, Ph.D.
Professor of Philosophy
Chair of the Philosophy Department
_________________
Michael Slote, Ph.D.
Professor of Philosophy
UST Professor of Ethics
________________
Berit Brogaard, Ph.D.
Professor of Philosophy
Director of the Brogaard Lab
for Multisensory Research
_________________
Mark Rowlands, Ph.D.
Professor of Philosophy
________________
Markus Gabriel, Habilitation
Professor of Philosophy
University of Bonn
_________________
Guillermo Prado, Ph.D.
Dean of the Graduate School
MOREIRA, FELIPE G. A.
Disputes:
The Incommensurable Greatness of Micro-Wars
(Ph.D., Philosophy)
(May 2019)
Dissertation supervised by Professor Otávio Bueno.
No. of pages in text. (285)
How is one to react to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in
disputes in metaphysics, such as the ones on whether there is evil, a thing-in-itself and
consciousness? This question drives this dissertation. In the introduction, that is, in chapter
1, it is argued that one is to react to the stated fact by adopting a conflictual craft. In
proposing a reading of Pyrrho of Elis, it is argued that this craft is a synthesis of the skeptic
craft and of the dogmatic one, and serves to formulate the metametaphysical system of
disputes. In making cases for the claims that characterize this system and in seeking to spell
out its pertinence to contemporary analytic and continental philosophy, the dissertation
proceeds by, in chapter 2, articulating an interpretation of two projects that have not been
carefully discussed in relation to one another: Friedrich Nietzsche’s libertarian project of
overcoming metaphysics and Rudolf Carnap’s egalitarian project of overcoming
metaphysics. In chapter 3, it is showed that continental philosophers have often been
influenced by the former but ignored the latter, whereas analytic philosophers have
constantly done the opposite. It is claimed, then, that one is to promote a synthesis of
Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s projects. Chapter 4 argues that those, such as Aristotle, who have
been neither exactly libertarians nor egalitarians have often resorted to “subtle” violence;
a kind of violence that is not as upfront as corporeal ones, such as that of shooting someone.
In criticizing “subtle” violence and addressing the works of Willard van Orman Quine,
Saul Kripke and Kit Fine, chapter 5 claims that disputes are micro-political conflicts, that
is, they are micro-wars that may be approached from a right-wing allegedly apolitical
stance or from a left-wing stance that seeks to show the political character of disputes.
Chapter 6 makes a case for the left-wing approach in proposing a heterodox reading of
Gilles Deleuze. In chapter 7, the dissertation’s conclusion, it is argued that micro-wars have
an incommensurable greatness because it seems impossible to measure persons’ overall
“amount” of emotions and/or time spent in dealing with disputes.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I would like to thank my adviser, Otávio Bueno, for the likewise “incommensurable
greatness” of his support. I believe that it was sometime around 2012-2013 that I started to
think that it could be interesting to pursue the work done here, that is, to read in connection
and to promote a synthesis of Friedrich Nietzsche’s and Rudolf Carnap’s projects of
overcoming metaphysics. Otávio was the first professor who, back in the Fall of 2014, did
not react with mockery, rudeness and/or some kind of not very “subtle” violence to the aim
of turning this (at first, very rough) inclination of mine into an actual dissertation. I am
extremely thankful to him for that as well as for his willingness to share with me his
outstanding and extensive philosophical knowledge, his Pyrrhonian objections, his
remarkable professional commitment to the task of advising me throughout these last four
to five years and his patience to read and give valuable comments on all the versions of
this dissertation. I am also extremely thankful to Otávio for having articulated Pyrrhonian
works that show that Brazilian philosophers do not need to spend their whole careers overly
paying respect to European and/or North American philosophers, without daring to
articulate stances of their own. Especially because of my poetic works, I am considerably
displeased with clichés. Nevertheless, I, after all, need to rely on a cliché, that is, to
acknowledge that, without Otávio’s support, I do not think that I would have been able to
write this dissertation, at least not in the USA and in the “left-wing way” that I did.
I also would like to thank the other members of my Ph.D. dissertation committee
—Berit (“Brit”) Brogaard, Michael Slote, Mark Rowlands and Markus Gabriel —for their
valuable comments, objections, support and open-mindedness toward my project. I am
especially grateful to Brit for having shared with me her more empirical approach to
iii
philosophy, and to Mark for our discussions, especially those on Gilles Deleuze and
personhood. I am especially thankful to Michael for having spelled out to me his own views
on open-mindedness and empathy in a way that has influenced me a lot, as I take that this
very dissertation shows. I am also especially grateful to Markus for having discussed with
me his views on the analytic-continental gap, while helping me to articulate a take of my
own on such matter. In advising and helping me to apply to a DAAD short-term research
grant, Markus also gave me the outstanding chance to work on the last details of this
dissertation while vising the University of Bonn. I am very grateful to him for this chance,
which significantly changed this dissertation in making me more aware that (at least outside
the USA) the “right-wing way” of doing philosophy is not as dominant as I once believed.
I also would like to thank Amie L. Thomasson, Christian J. Emden, Fernando
Muniz, Fernando Ribeiro, Guido Imaguire and Todd May for the valuable feedback they
provided on excerpts of this dissertation. From the Fall of 2013 up to the Fall of 2014, I
took classes at the University of Miami with Susan Haack, Bradford Cokelet, Elijah L.
Chudnoff, Nick Stang, Risto Hilpinen and Simon J. Evnine. I am grateful to these
professors for having more or less directly helped me shape the views supported here, albeit
mainly in reaction to theirs. I am also very thankful to the following professors with whom
from 2006 to 2013 I took classes in Paris Nanterre University, Federal University of Rio
de Janeiro, Pontifical Catholic University of Rio de Janeiro, Boston College, Tufts
University or Harvard Summer School: Daniel C. Dennett, David Lang, Eli Hirsch, Ethel
Rocha, Jacques Martineau, Jody Azzouni, Marco Ruffino, Peter J. Kreeft, Ronald K.
Tacelli, Stephen L. White, Vera Cristina de Andrade Bueno and William Wians; all of
these professors have influenced the way I practice philosophy. I am also very grateful to
iv
Steven F. Butterman for having invited me to attend his class on “queer poetry” in the Fall
of 2018, and for having given me a quite unique chance: that of discussing, in a really
inclusive context, my “metamodernist poetry”, while connecting this poetry of mine with
the kind of philosophy supported in this dissertation, especially in the sixth chapter.
Throughout the years I worked in this dissertation, I presented excerpts of it at
Federal Fluminense University, at the University of Miami’s Philosophy Research Forum,
at Federal University of Rio de Janeiro, at the University of Massachusetts Dartmouth’s
public event, Confronting Anti-Black Racism Through Transnational Activism and
Scholarship, at the University of Miami’s Modern Languages and Literature Graduate
Conference, Lands of Freedom? Oppressions, Subversions and Pursuits of Justice in a
Changing World, as well as at the Düsseldorf Graduate Workshop, What Do We Do When
We Do Metaphysics? I would like to thank the organizers of these events for the chance to
present my research, and all of those who attended and reacted to my presentations. I am
also especially grateful to all of my students who attended the several classes I taught at
the University of Miami from the Spring of 2015 up to the Fall of 2018. My belief is that
my students made me much more aware of my “problematic starting points”, more tolerant
regarding the views of “others”, and a more efficacious public speaker. I also would like
to thank all the referees of philosophical journals to which I submitted papers, and who
gave me interesting comments, objections, and/or indicated revisions. I am especially
thankful to the referees of Manuscrito, Nietzsche-Studien and Revue philosophique de la
France et de l'étranger who actually accepted to publish my work.
I am likewise grateful for the love and the emotional support of my parents and
sister, Amanda Moreira. I also very thankful for Amanda’s comments on all the chapters
v
of this dissertation. Last, but not least, I would like to thank Irene Olivero for all her love,
devotion, time, willingness and patience to philosophically discuss the issues addressed in
this dissertation, even when I was not exactly sober and/or making sense. Thank you all!
vi
PREFACE
In this dissertation, I systematically connect practically all the philosophical
interests I have had, since I started to intensively care about philosophy more or less
thirteen years ago, especially after I joined the Erasmus interchange program and visited
Paris Nanterre University from 2006 to 2007. In spelling out my “left-wing approach” to
disputes, the sixth chapter addresses the longest of these interests: the one I have had on
the works of Gilles Deleuze, the first philosopher who really caught my attention, and
inspired me to pursue a career in philosophy. Note that, back in 2008, I graduated from the
social communication bachelor’s program of Federal Fluminense University, after
submitting a monography on Deleuze. This dissertation’s sixth chapter, as well as a paper
of mine that is to appear in Revue philosophique de la France et de l'étranger by the end
of this year, are my ways to revise the views I held in this monograph in the light of the
further philosophical studies I have pursued and the “metamodernist poetry” I have further
articulated since then. Indeed, I dream that one day there will be an “ideal reader” of mine.
This is someone who is interested and has the education to feel and understand that my
poetic and philosophical works are deeply connected and reinforce one another.
Another quite long interest of mine is the one on Friedrich Nietzsche’s works. This
is to explain why I published a few short articles on Nietzsche as well as, while pursuing
and in the end earning my philosophy master’s degree from Pontifical Catholic University
of Rio de Janeiro, wrote a master’s dissertation on Nietzsche’s take on the mind body
problem and his views on health and disease. This took place from 2009 to 2011, while I
also pursued and ultimately earned a philosophy bachelor’s degree from Federal University
of Rio de Janeiro. During these years, I also started to be interested in the analytic
vii
interpreters of Nietzsche, and in analytic philosophy. This interest made me want to
immigrate to the USA, and join Boston College’s master program, whose consortium with
Tufts University’s program allowed me to take several classes on analytic philosophy.
Indeed, from 2011 to 2013, “my Boston years”, I primarily focused my studies on analytic
philosophy. More importantly, the philosopher from this tradition who has interested me
the most is Rudolf Carnap, as this very dissertation and my 2014 article published in
Manuscrito, “An Apology of Carnap”, indicate. For me, then, it felt, and it still feels
extremely “natural” to read in connection Carnap’s and Nietzsche’s apparently unrelated
projects of overcoming metaphysics, as I did in the second chapter of this dissertation as
well as in an article of mine that appeared in Nietzsche-Studien in 2018.
In fact, I think that this whole dissertation started out of a particular feeling of mine:
that a “conceptual persona” that promotes a synthesis of Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s projects
of overcoming metaphysics has something interesting to state both to analytic philosophers
and to continental philosophers. This conceptual persona, as I indicate in the sixth chapter,
may be called “Friedrich Carnap”, “Rudolf Nietzsche”, “Gilles A. G. Moreira”, “Felipe G.
A. Deleuze” or even “F.G.A.M.” (to put in the terms of several of my poems). This
dissertation (especially, its third chapter), then, is my way to spell out this persona’s
philosophy; a philosophy that (I think this is considerably obvious) runs in disagreement
with most analytic and continental philosophies that have been done throughout the
twentieth century and up to ours. Accordingly, as it might have been expected, I have
likewise confronted a lot of resistance from 2013 up to today, that is, throughout my
“Miami years”, when I started to promote the Nietzsche-Carnap synthesis, while taking
several classes, teaching classes of my own and working on the present Ph.D. dissertation.
viii
Hence, it is only half in jest that I state that if I were not committed to Nietzsche’s
aim of a non-resentful life, I would entitle myself to add a personal resentments section. I
am joking, but I am not joking, while underling that I am quite aware that to add such a
section would not be philosophically pertinent or “prudent”. Consequently, what I did was
to articulate another way to resist my “deep opponents”: that of interpreting and criticizing
the two kinds of philosophers these opponents of mine more or less unconsciously follow.
The first kind of philosophers I have in mind are those discussed in this dissertation’s fourth
chapter: the ones, such as (at least in my reading) Aristotle, Saint Anselm, David Hume,
Immanuel Kant, Ludwig Wittgenstein and Eli Hirsch, who express what I call the properly
dogmatic “subtle” violence. The second kind of philosophers I have in mind are the ones
discussed in this dissertation’s fifth chapter; those who, perhaps, avoid the properly
dogmatic “subtle” violence, but not the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence. My
reading is that this is the case with Willard van Orman Quine, Saul Kripke and Kit Fine.
What allowed me to address all the philosophers named in the last paragraph was
my background in the history of philosophy, achieved after taking several historical classes
at Federal University of Rio de Janeiro, Pontifical Catholic University of Rio de Janeiro
and Boston College. I underline that, over the last four years, I prepared and taught several
sections of Introduction to Philosophy, Modern Philosophy and Ancient philosophy at the
University of Miami. This helped me to articulate my own picture of the history of
metaphysics; the “Sisyphean picture” suggested here, especially in the fourth chapter.
Another dream of mine is that at least some of this dissertation’s readers will be convinced
(like I am) that it may be taken for granted that several (if not most) contemporary
philosophers constantly express the properly dogmatic or the pseudo-non-dogmatic
ix
“subtle” violence, as if such kinds of violence were inherent to the very practice of doing
philosophy, as if allegedly apolitical, but actually “right-wing approaches” to disputes were
ultimately the only rational, pertinent and/or possible approaches.
What I am trying to say is that I have a quite deep personal relation with the two
kinds of “subtle” violence criticized in this dissertation. Indeed, especially after I started to
feel the need to problematize the analytic-continental gap, I have personally struggled with
the properly dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence. I also need to
acknowledge that I myself may have expressed these two kinds of “subtle” violence more
than once toward both analytic philosophers and continental philosophers, especially in
non-academic contexts, such as those of bars. To put it in more “metamodernist” and/or
paradoxical terms, to write this dissertation was also an attempt to release myself from
myself. I also would like to emphasize that, in identifying and criticizing the properly
dogmatic or the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence, a hope of mine is that my research
“resonates” with the works of authors who have identified and criticized less explicit kinds
of xenophobic, classist, racist, sexist and/or transphobic violence; kinds of violence that, I
think, I have never personally experienced. What I mean is that, though I have been an
immigrant in the USA since 2011, I am aware that I have been quite white, heterosexual,
middle-class and protected by the academic environments I have been inserted. Yet, I still
hope that those who do not have had such “particular identities” of mine may find my views
on “subtle” violence pertinent. More directly, my feeling is that I do not need to explain
carefully what I mean and why I oppose “subtle” violence to those who have struggled
with less explicit xenophobic, classist, racist, sexist and/or transphobic kinds of violence.
x
I also feel the need to state that the fact that I wrote this dissertation as a foreigner
in the USA probably played a significant role, even though I cannot precisely describe the
significance of this role. Indeed, regardless of what I once believed, the fact that my
advisor, Otávio Bueno, is also Brazilian and we discussed this dissertation in Portuguese
helped me more than I thought it would. It is hard to explain why I feel like this or to
qualify the help I have in mind, especially given that I do feel comfortable and, in fact,
enjoy speaking and writing philosophy and poetry in English. It is also hard to explain why,
while writing this dissertation, I started to be interested in the more “properly Brazilian”
neo-Pyrrhonist tradition of authors, such as Otávio himself as well as Oswaldo Porchat.
Note that this tradition was not brought to my attention during the years I studied
philosophy in Rio de Janeiro, but, rather, only a few years ago by Otávio himself. Also
note that my reaction to neo-Pyrrhonism can be found in the very first chapter of this
dissertation, that is, in the introduction, where I articulate my “conflictual craft” by
opposing and promoting a synthesis of Pyrrho’s skeptic craft and the dogmatic craft.
The fact that I wrote this dissertation as a foreigner in the USA probably also
contributed to make me have two new interests that I did not have the space to carefully
address here. The first new interest is that on “subtly” colonialized non-European and nonNorth American philosophers who spend their whole careers overly paying respect to
European and/or North American philosophers, without daring to articulate stances of their
own. The second new interest is on the works of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, works
that are sometimes described as one of the grounds of colonization. As indicated in the
seventh chapter, that is, in this dissertation’s conclusion, I plan to do justice to these new
interests in the future in addressing Hegel’s deviant concepts of God and responsible agent.
xi
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Page
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ................................................................................... xiv
CHAPTER 1
INTRODUCTION: FROM PYRRONISM TO THE SYSTEM OF DISPUTES .. 1
1.1 Bare Wise Persons ..................................................................................... 1
1.2 The Core Features of the Skeptic Craft and of the Dogmatic Craft........... 14
1.3 Problematizing the Dogmatic and the Skeptic Craft.................................. 25
1.4 The Conflictual Craft ................................................................................. 31
1.5 The System of Disputes ............................................................................. 37
CHAPTER 2
OVERCOMING METAMETAPHYSICS: NIETZSCHE AND CARNAP.......... 47
2.1 The Climate of Animosity ......................................................................... 47
2.2 The Overcoming of Metaphysics ............................................................... 55
2.3 How Can an Overcoming of Metaphysics be Performed?......................... 71
2.4 Why is an Overcoming of Metaphysics to be Performed? ........................ 82
CHAPTER 3
THE WILL TO SYNTHESIS ................................................................................ 98
3.1 The New “Faith” ........................................................................................ 98
3.2 Synthesis .................................................................................................... 108
3.3 An Argument ............................................................................................. 123
CHAPTER 4
UNDENIABLE METAPHYSICAL CLAIMS, “SUBTLE” VIOLENCE AND
PERSONHOOD..................................................................................................... 131
4.1 A Curious Thing About Ontological Disputes........................................... 131
4.2 Dogmatists’ Writings and Narrow Conditions for Personhood ................. 140
4.3 Against Narrow Conditions for Personhood .............................................. 150
xii
CHAPTER 5
THE RIGHT-WING APPROACH TO METAPHYSICS ..................................... 163
5.1 Macro-Political Conflicts: The Charlottesville-Conflict ........................... 163
5.2 Micro-Political Conflicts: Disputes as Micro-Wars .................................. 174
5.3 The Right-Wing Political Practice of Depoliticization .............................. 194
5.4 The Critique of “Subtle” Violence ............................................................. 206
CHAPTER 6
THE LEFT-WING APPROACH TO METAPHYSICS........................................ 210
6.1 Deleuze’s Immaculate Conception ............................................................ 210
6.2 The Left-Wing Political Practice of Politicization..................................... 219
6.3 From the Modernist to the Metamodernist Way ........................................ 234
CHAPTER 7
CONCLUSION ...................................................................................................... 254
7.1 Restatement of the Claims of the System of Disputes ............................... 254
7.2 The Incommensurable Greatness of Disputes............................................ 255
7.3 Last Replies to Two Others of Mine .......................................................... 260
7.4 Hegel and Toward an Object-Level Metaphysics ...................................... 264
REFERENCES ...................................................................................................... 270
xiii
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS
Sextus Empiricus
The roman numbers after the abbreviation refer to the book, and the Arabic numbers refer to the
paragraph. For example, PH I 23 refers to paragraph 23 of the first book of Outlines of Skepticism.
PH
Outlines of Skepticism, translated and edited by Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes.
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Friedrich Nietzsche
The roman numbers after the abbreviation refer to the section. The Arabic numbers refer to the
paragraph. The Arabic numbers between brackets refer to the sub-section. For example, Thus
Spoke Zarathustra, section III, chapter 12 and subsection 4 is cited as Z III 12 [4].
A
The Anti-Christ, translated by Judith Norman and edited by Aaron Ridley and Judith
Norman. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
BGE
Beyond Good and Evil, translated by Judith Norman and edited by Rolf-Peter Horstmann
and Judith Norman. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2001.
EH
Ecce Homo, translated by Judith Norman and edited by Aaron Ridley and Judith Norman.
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
GM
On the Genealogy of Morality, translated by Carol Diethe and edited by Keith AnsellPearson. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2006.
GS
The Gay Science, translated by Josefine Nauckhoff, poems translated by Adrian Del Caro
and edited by Bernard Williams. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2001.
TI
Twilight of the Idols, translated by Judith Norman and edited by Aaron Ridley and Judith
Norman. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
WP
The Will to Power, translated by Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale and edited by
Walter Kaufmann. New York, Vintage, 1968.
Z
Thus Spoke Zarathustra, translated by Adrian Del Caro and edited by Adrian Del Caro
and Robert B. Pippin. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2006.
In the case of Nietzsche’s posthumous works, I also state the year in which the fragment was written
and propose translations of my own.
Nachlass Year of the Fragment, KSA
Sämtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe in 15
Bänden, edited by Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari,
Berlin, de Gruyer, 1967- 1977.
Rudolf Carnap
The Arabic numbers after the abbreviation refer to pages.
xiv
EML
“The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language”, translated by
Arthur Pap and edited by A. J. Ayer. In Logical Positivism, New York, The Free Press,
1959.
IAB
Intellectual Autobiography, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp. In The Philosophy of
Rudolf Carnap, Illinois, Open Court, 1963.
LOG
“Logic”. In Factors Determining Human Behavior, Cambridge, Harvard University
press, 1937.
LSW
The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, translated by Rolf
A. George, Illinois, Open Court, 2003.
xv
CHAPTER 1
INTRODUCTION: FROM PYRRONISM TO THE SYSTEM OF DISPUTES
1.1 Bare Wise Persons
“Bare wise persons”. This is the expression I would like to use to translate the Greek
word, “gumnosophistai”. 1 This word was used by Diogenes Laertius in his third century
CE Lives of Eminent Philosophers. 2 This work states that Pyrrho of Elis, who is believed
to have lived from 365-360 BC until around 275–270 BC, joined the conqueror Alexander
the Great in an expedition to India. This probably occurred around 327-326 BC. According
to Diogenes, it was then that, after Pyrrho encountered such “bare wise persons”, he
became a skeptic. Notice that Pyrrho left no writings. Hence, what I do is to follow his
interpreters in relying heavily on secondary sources, such as Diogenes’s Lives of Eminent
Philosophers itself as well as on the most detailed of these sources: Sextus Empiricus’
Outlines of Skepticism, written sometime around the second and third century CE.
Given that non-Pyrrhonist kinds of skepticism will not be addressed in this
dissertation, the term “skeptic” is applied as a short for the Pyrrhonist skeptic, the one who
adopts Pyrrho’s skeptic craft as opposed to a dogmatic craft, such as that of Aristotle. As
it is well-know, Aristotle was a dogmatist; he is believed to have lived from 384–322 BC,
worked as teacher of Alexander and was a contemporary of Pyrrho. 3 “Craft” is a term
1
This Greek word has been, traditionally, translated to “naked wise men”. However, I wish to rely on a more
gender-neutral vocabulary. This is why I replace the term “men” for “persons”, a term that will be carefully
addressed throughout this dissertation, especially in the fourth chapter. I also prefer the term “bare” over the
term “naked”. The reason is that “bare” hopefully reminds readers of the expression, “bare particular”. A
bare particular has been understood as a substance that merely instantiates universals but, in itself, has no
property of its own at all. A bare wise person, on the other hand, is one that, when stripped from one’s clothes
or any other cultural features, such as earrings and necklaces, still has the property of being a person.
2
Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, ed. James Miller, trans. Pamela Mensch, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2018: (9.61).
3
I am inclined to believe that Aristotle is, indeed, the first Western dogmatist whose writings are available
to us. Given that Plato’s works are dialogues, I am not inclined to attribute to him the dogmatic craft. I am
also not inclined to believe that Plato adopted a skeptic or the conflictual craft that I describe and support in
1
2
applied in the Greek sense of techne, a conjunction of disciplined practices. By a practice,
I understand what Sextus calls a “persuasion”, that is “a choice of life or of a way of acting
practiced by one person or by many”. 4 The skeptic craft and the dogmatic one will be
carefully described in what follows. Before I do so, however, let us consider that to adopt
either one of these crafts is a way to respond to a practical matter: how is one to react to
the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes? This
question drives this dissertation. Let me start, then, by spelling out what I mean by it.
“Disputes” is a term used here to cover theoretical as well as practical disputes that
have been associated with metaphysics. “Metaphysics” is a term that will be discussed in
detail in the next chapter. For the time being, I use it loosely. The theoretical disputes I
focused on are those that take place when opponents disagree (say, on the truth value or on
the persuasiveness) of at least one claim that has been associated with metaphysics. The
following is an example of such a claim: “there is evil”. This claim has received a lot of
attention, at least since late Antiquity. “Evil”, in the sense adopted here, is exemplified by
an apparently random and morally unjustifiable event, such as an earthquake or a plague
that kills thousands of people. The practical disputes I address are those that occur when
opponents disagree on at least one practice that has been associated with metaphysics. 5 An
what follows. Plato seems to have had a quite unique craft of his own that, despise the countless commentaries
of his works, has not been as influential as Aristotle’s. An upfronf evidence for this last claim is the fact that
philosophers have not usually articulated dialogues. In fact, this form of writing is usually not even regarded
as being “properly philosophical” today. I cannot discuss Plato’s works here. For such an inquiry, see, for
example, Fernando Muniz, A Potência da Aparência: um estudo sobre o prazer e a sensação nos Diálogos
de Platão, São Paulo, ed. Annablume, 2011.
4
PH I 145.
5
This dissertation deals exclusively with theoretical and practical disputes that have been associated with
“metaphysis”; several examples of such disputes will be given in what follows. This is to state that I am
neutral concerning disputes that have been associated with mathematics or the empirical sciences, such as:
what are the causes that make someone acquire an extraordinary mental ability, such as that of having the
power to recognize someone else’s pain more accurately than most people? For an approach to this issue, see
Berit Brogaard and Kristian Marlow, The Superhuman Mind: Free the Genius in Your Brain, New York,
Penguin, 2015.
3
example of such practice is the very one of dealing (e.g., in a dissertation) with the
theoretical dispute over the existence of evil as opposed to do something else, say, to focus
on a theoretical dispute over a distinct claim, such as the claim that “there is a thing-initself”. This claim has also received a lot of attention, at least since the 16th century and
especially after Immanuel Kant published his works in the 18th century. By a thing-in-itself,
it is to be understood one that exists independently or is not conditioned by any human
factor, such as the human mind, language, culture, history, struggle of classes, etc.
The term “person”, it is presupposed, may be applied in the sense of a being that
has personhood. Several conditions for personhood —including the very one of being able
to engage oneself in disputes —will be discussed in detail in the fourth chapter. For the
time being, the term “personhood” is also applied loosely in the sense of the property of
holding what the Greeks called logos, that is, reason, logic and/or language. This property
may be one that is not exclusively shared by human beings. As Thomas White and Mark
Rowlands indicate, other beings, such as animals, may also have personhood. 6 On my part,
I remain neutral on whether this is so. What is important here is to emphasize that, for this
dissertation’s purpose, a person, that is, a holder of logos, is to be understood as a legitimate
rational peer or at least as a potential legitimate rational peer. Hence, I take that to insinuate
that x falls short of personhood, say, in comparing x to a plant or an animal or suggesting
that x is a fool or insane, is to insinuate that x is not really a legitimate rational peer.
I likewise would like to use the term “other” in a way that is closely connected to
the notion of “person”. Now it is considerably important to underline that there has been a
long literature on the notion of “other”. Furthermore, this notion has been used in all kinds
6
Thomas White, In Defense of Dolphins: The New Moral Frontier, MA, Blackwell, 2007; and Mark
Rowlands, Can Animals be Persons?, forthcoming.
4
of senses, for instance, by the likes of Martin Buber, Franz Rosenzweig and Emmanuel
Levinas; thinkers whose works interest me a lot, but that I cannot address here. 7 What is
also important is to underline that it is not this dissertation’s aim to discuss the literature
on the “other” or the several senses in which this term has been applied. For my purposes,
it suffices to apply the term “other” as a relational notion according to which y is an other
with regard to x if, and only if: x and y are both persons who disagree regarding at least
one dispute (or, more broadly, any kind of conflict), and y’s sensibility regarding this
dispute or conflict is radically distinct from x’s inasmuch as y challenges x’s logos in
rejecting x’s presuppositions and/or ignoring, violating or interpreting x’s criterion to deal
with the dispute or the conflict at stake differently. The most precise way to apply the
notion of “other”, then, would by speaking in relational terms of one’s other, other of
someone or other regarding a person. These italicized expressions, though, may not be
very aesthetically appealing to some of this dissertation’s readers. Hence, I will simply
apply the term “other” as a short for these italicized expressions.
Some examples of criteria to deal with disputes are: recognition of what is logically
self-evident; accordance with scriptures; clearness and distinctiveness; consistency with
the latest results of mathematics and/or the empirical sciences; respect to the conditions for
cognitive experience; oppression acknowledgment, say, of class exploitation; accordance
with intuitions; respect to the rules of ordinary language; maximization of theoretical
virtues, such as “conservatism, generality, simplicity, refutability and modesty” 8; etc.
7
See Martin Buber, I and Thou, New York, Touchstone, 1970; Franz Rosenzweig, The Star of Redemption,
Indiana, Notre Dame Press, 1985; and Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority,
Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991.
8
Willard Van Orman Quine, Pursuit of Truth, Cambridge, Harvard University, 1992: pp. 20. For a detailed
discussion of these virtues, see Willard Van Orman Quine and J.S. Ullian, The Web of Belief, New York,
McGraw-Hill Education, 1978: pp. 40-48.
5
Imagine a person who argues that there is evil. Imagine that this person supports
that to defend so is to satisfy a criterion: accordance with scriptures. In this context, the
other might be someone who simply ignores or violates this criterion. Moreover, imagine
a person who defends that there is a thing-in-itself. Imagine that this person argues that to
claim so is to satisfy a distinct criterion, say, respect to the conditions for cognitive
experience. In this case, the other might be someone who interprets this criterion differently
in insisting that such conditions can only be respected by the one who rejects the existence
of a thing-in-itself. The other here might also be someone who rejects any criterion this
person might have for engaging oneself in the dispute over the existence of a thing-in-itself
in the first place, that is, this other may claim that it is impertinent to spend any time of
one’s life in discussing so, while insisting that there are matters that much more urgently
are deserving of attention, such as to debate the claim that “there is consciousness”. The
latter claim has been constantly disputed, at least since the middle of the 20th century. By
“consciousness”, to put in Thomas Nagel’s terms, it is to be understood a
phenomenological experience; one that has “a what is like to be” aspect. 9
A distinction that will play a seminal role in what follows is that between: Goddriven philosophers, such as Saint Augustine, Boethius, William of Ockham, Saint
Anselm, Saint Thomas of Aquinas and Duns Scotus; human-driven philosophers, such as
Kant, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels and, more recently, Jürgen
Habermas, Richard Rorty, Karl-Otto Apel and Angela Davis; and physicalist-driven
philosophers, such as Willard Van Orman Quine, Saul Kripke, Nagel, Daniel Dennett, Paul
9
Thomas Nagel, “What is it like to be a Bat?”, Philosophical Review 4, 1974: pp. 435-50.
6
and Patricia Churchland, Frank Jackson, Ned Block, David Chalmers, etc. 10 Respectively,
God-driven, human-driven and physicalist-driven philosophers have often focused on the
theoretical disputes over the existence of evil, a thing-in-itself and consciousness. These
philosophers will be further described in detail as the dissertation proceeds; this will
hopefully show that they have been others regarding one another. 11
For now, I underline that whether Pyrrho’s encounter with the aforementioned
“bare wise persons” is really a fact is not an issue that I approach here. What is crucial, for
my purposes, is to presuppose and add another factor to Diogenes’s account of Pyrrho; a
factor that cannot be explicitly found in Diogenes’s writings, but that I take to be a highly
plausible speculation. The factor is that Pyrrho adopted the skeptic craft after encountering
such “bare wise persons” because this radical encounter made Pyrrho recognize the
personhood of these persons as well as the importance of his others insofar as disputes are
at stake. What I mean is that I speculate that, after this encounter, Pyrrho concluded that
10
See Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures, Cambridge, The MIT
Press, 1990; Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, New Jersey, Princeton University Press,
1979; Karl-Otto Apel, Selected Essays, New Jersey, Humanities Press, 1996; Angela Davis, The Angela Y.
Davis Reader, Cambridge, Blackwell Publishers, 1998; Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object,
Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1960; Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Harvard University
Press, 1980; Thomas Nagel, “What is it like to be a Bat?”; Daniel Dennett, “Quining Qualia” in A. J. Marcel
and E. Bisiach (eds.), Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1988;
Consciousness Explained, New York, Little, Brown and Company Press, 1991; Paul Churchland, The Engine
of Reason, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1996; Patricia Churchland, Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy,
Cambridge, The MIT Press, 2002; Ned Block, “Troubles with Functionalism”, Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, volume IX, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1978; Frank Jackson,
“Epiphenomenal Qualia”, in David Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary
Readings, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2002; David Chalmers, The Conscious Mind: In search of a
Fundamental Theory, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1996; and The Character of Consciousness, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2010.
11
Let me emphasize that I do not wish to suggest that all philosophers are God, human or physicalist-driven
ones. This does not seem to be the case with several philosophers that will not be discussed in this dissertation,
such as Ancient philosophers, Eastern philosophers or Hegel. A more recent example of a philosopher who
resists being labelled a God, human or physicalist-driven philosopher is Markus Gabriel. He argues that
“existence = appearance in a field of sense”. Accordingly, Gabriel engages himself in an ontological dispute
that is not focused on by God, human or physicalist philosophers: that on whether there is what he calls a
“world”, that is, a “field of sense in which all other fields of sense appear”. Gabriel concludes that there is no
such a thing. See Markus Gabriel, Why the World Does Not Exist, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2015, pp. 73.
7
(1) It seems that:
(1-i)
Among the others, some are legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes
are at stake.
(1-ii) No person has settled a dispute once and for all, that is, in a way that
others could not rationally unsettle.
(1-iii) (1-i) and (1-ii) are extremely important points insofar as those who fail
to acknowledge them react in a quite unpersuasive manner to the fact
that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.12
To point toward (1-i) is no trivial move. Consider Alexander and members of his
troops. When confronted with those that Diogenes describes as “bare wise persons”, they
might have believed that such persons were not exactly “persons” or “wise”. My point here
is that, from the perspective of most Greeks, these beings were others. This is because they:
did not believe in the Greek Gods; never read Homeric poems; lived under political systems
quite distinct from those adopted in Ancient Greece; dressed themselves with non-Greek
vestments or did not dress themselves at all; had a color of skin distinct from that of most
Greeks; etc. Indeed, the sounds emitted by such beings who did not speak Ancient Greek
may not have been taken as evidence that they had a language of their own. Accordingly,
Alexander and/or members of his troops may have labelled them barbarians. To do so is to
reject (1-i); it is to suggest that these “bare wise persons” are ultimately uncivilized and,
consequently, not really legitimate rational peers concerning disputes.
12
In an article from 1802, Hegel somehow attributes a similar practice to skeptics in arguing as follows:
“what counts for the race as absolutely One and the same, and as fixed, eternal and everywhere constituted
in the same way, time wrenches away from it; most commonly [what does this is] the increasing range of
acquaintance with alien // peoples under the pressure of natural necessity; as, for example, becoming
acquainted with a new continent, had this skeptical effect upon the dogmatic common sense of the Europeans
down to that time, and upon their indubitable certainty about a mass of concepts concerning right and truth”.
See G.W.F. Hegel, “On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy, Exposition of its Different
Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One”, trans. H.S. Harris, in George di
Giovanni (ed.), Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Cambridge,
Hackett Publishing Company, 2000: pp.333. For a detailed take on Hegel’s view on skepticism, see Michael
N. Forster, Hegel and Skepticism, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1989.
8
To point toward (1-ii) is also no trivial move. In not taking their others to be
legitimate rational peers on disputes, Alexander and/or members of his troops might also
have believed that at least one dispute has indeed been settled once and for all. The same
can be stated about some Ancient Greeks who never joined expeditions to non-Greek cities.
Note that such Greeks may also have been inclined to believe that (1-i) and (1-ii) were
unimportant matters. The reason, they might have believed, is that one can react in a
persuasive way to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in
disputes, without taking (1-i) and (1-ii) into account. It follows that the action of pointing
toward (1-iii) is likewise no trivial action but, rather, a quite controversial one.
This dissertation seeks to spell out (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii). These points, I aim to
show in what follows, have been constantly problematized by those who over the last 2500
years or so of history of metaphysics have been called “philosophers” —a term that derives
from the Ancient Greek one “philosophos”, whose original meaning, as it is well known,
was “lover of wisdom”. It is also important to underline that those who are usually called
“philosophers” have not been influenced by Pyrrho. Over the last fifty years or so, a few
Brazilian philosophers have done otherwise. They are exceptions. They may be called neoPyrrhonists. Oswald Porchat, whose first works were published in the late 1960s, is an
example of someone who deserves to be labelled so. 13 The same can be stated about two
contemporary philosophers considerably influenced by him: Otávio Bueno and Plínio
Junqueira Smith.14 As it will be spelled out in what follows, I am influenced by neo-
13
Oswaldo Porchat, Rumo ao Ceticismo, São Paulo, Editora Unesp, 2007.
Otávio Bueno, “Davidson and Skepticism: How not to Respond to the Skeptic”, Principia 9, 2005; “Is the
Pyrrhonist an Internalist”, in Diego Machuca (ed.), New Essays on Ancient Pyrrhonism, Leiden, Brill, 2011;
“Disagreeing with the Pyrrhonist”, in Diego Machuca (ed.), Disagreement and Skepticism, New York,
Routledge, 2013; Otávio Bueno and Plínio Junqueira Smith, “Skepticism in Latin America”, in Edward N.
Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2016; and Plínio Junqueira Smith, Uma Visão Cética
do Mundo: Porchat e a Filosofia, São Paulo, Editora Unesp, 2017. Other non-Brazilian philosophers whose
14
9
Pyrrhonists insofar as I take dogmatism to be a non-starter. However, I am not a skeptic
and do not take that (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii) force one to adopt the skeptic craft. What I take
myself to be is something else. I call it a conflictual crafter. The reason is that my response
to the practical question that drives this dissertation (that is, “how is one to react to the fact
that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes?”) runs as follows:
(2) One is to adopt a conflictual craft, that is, a synthesis between the skeptic craft
and the dogmatic craft that serves to articulate the system of disputes.
By a synthesis between the skeptic and the dogmatic crafts, I understand a particular
task; one characterized by three features: first, instead of presupposing, this synthesis
brings to light the core features of the skeptic craft and of the dogmatic craft; second, I
problematize the dogmatic craft by means of the skeptic one and vice-versa so that the
shortcomings of these crafts are avoided; and, third, my synthesis still seeks to keep certain
(hopefully positive) aspects both of the skeptic craft and of the dogmatic one. 15 Let me
emphasize that in arguing for (2), I do not wish to suggest that the skeptic and the dogmatic
craft are the only two crafts present in the literature. Indeed, there may be several other
crafts that resist being labelled “skeptic” or “dogmatic” ones. The problem is that I simply
do not have the space to address all of such crafts here. What I do, then, is to focus on the
skeptic and the dogmatic craft, while spelling out my conflictual craft as an alternative.
works have also been influenced by Pyrrho include: Ezequiel de Olaso, “La crisis pirrónica de Hume”,
Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofía 3(2): 131-143, 1977; “Otra vez sobre el escepticismo de Hume”,
Manuscrito 1 (1), 1978: pp. 65-82; “Los dos escepticismos del vicario saboyano”, Manuscrito, 2(3), 1980:
pp. 7–23; “Thomas Hobbes y la recta razón”, Manuscrito, 4(1), 1980: pp. 29–35; “La investigación y la
verdad”, Manuscrito, 6(2), 1983: pp. 45–62; “Certeza y escepticismo”, in L. Villoro (ed.), El conocimiento
(Enciclopedia Iberoamericana de Filosofía, Vol. 20), Madrid, Trotta, 1999; as well as Robert J. Fogelin,
Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Jutification, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1994.
15
“Synthesis” is a term that is often associated with Hegel’s works. In using it in the stated sense, though, I
do not wish to suggest that I champion a Hegelian approach. As I indicate in 7.4, I aim to more precisely
spell out my agreements and disagreements with Hegel in a future project. Yet, I cannot pursue this task here.
10
Now notice that a system in the dogmatic sense, to put it metaphorically, aims to
be a palace for the Gods, such as the “Valhalla” described in Richard Wagner’s The Ring
of the Nibelung. Just like this palace would be immune to any human bombing, a system
in the dogmatic sense is supposed to be immune to any rational objection. A dogmatic
system, then, would be a conjunction of undeniable metaphysical claims. By this kind of
claim, it is to be understood one that may be associated with metaphysics and that each and
every person is to endorse in order to count as a legitimate rational peer concerning a certain
dispute at stake. I do not aim to articulate a dogmatic system. What I aim to do, instead, is
to formulate a system in a conflictual sense: that of a conjunction of deniable metaphysical
claims, that is, claims that may be associated with metaphysics but which are not rationally
undeniable ones. This is because my others are legitimate rational peers who, hence, may
rationally reject them. This system of mine, then, cannot be compared to a palace for the
Gods; this system is not immune to any rational objection. In fact, I, myself, might come
up with such an objection in the future. This is not to state that such a conflictual system is
useless, impertinent or uninteresting. Analogously, consider remarkable constructions,
such as the Egyptian pyramids, the Taj Mahal, the Neuschwanstein Castle, the Palace of
Versailles, Frank Lloyd Wright’s Fallingwater, Oscar Niemeyer’s Palace of Dawn, etc.
These constructions are not immune to any kind of bombing. Nevertheless, this has
not been taken as a reason for not building them. Metaphorically speaking, then, what I
have attempted to build is a system comparable to such constructions or at least a humbler
home; a humbler home in which I feel comfortable, I feel safe, and/or I feel almost currently
satisfied with myself. This is a useful, pertinent and interesting humble home of mine at
least insofar as I (who inhabit it) am concerned. This home, though, may hopefully likewise
11
strike others as being useful, pertinent and interesting, albeit such others may ultimately
want to build and live in distinct constructions of their own.
The system I have in mind deserves to be called a system because it has several
features in common with traditional projects that have been called systems, such as those
of Plato, Aquinas or Kant. To begin with, my system of disputes is not a purely negative
skeptic project. Instead, like the systems of Plato, Aquinas or Kant, the system of disputes
is characterized by a non-skeptical endorsement of several claims, such as (1), (2) and
eleven other ones that will be stated in 1.5. In seeking to articulate a view that may appeal
both to continental and to analytic contemporary philosophers, the system of disputes also
proposes a distinct reading of two projects that have been very influential, but not usually
discussed in relation to one another: the projects of overcoming metaphysics of Friedrich
Nietzsche (especially, in his late phase from 1883 up until his mental collapse in 1889),
and of Rudolf Carnap (especially, in 1920s-1930s). Analogously, in their respective
historical contexts, Plato, Aquinas and Kant also articulated distinct readings of projects
that were influential, but not usually discussed in relation to one another: respectively, the
projects of Heraclitus and Parmenides; the rational project of Ancient Greek philosophers
(e.g., Aristotle) and the faith project of the Jewish-Christian tradition; and the realist and
the idealist project. The systems of Plato, Aquinas and Kant also spelled out the
presuppositions and promoted a synthesis of the respective projects they addressed.
The system of disputes likewise seeks to synthesize Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s
projects of overcoming metaphysics into a new philosophy that, as far as I know, has never
been done before, at least not explicitly. However, insofar as in articulating it I dialogue
and aim to contribute to close the gap between the so-called continental and analytic
12
philosophers, I am in debt to several others who have proceeded in a similar way. 16 I have
in mind the likes of: Richard Rorty, Hilary Putnam (especially, the one from the 2008
Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to Life), Bernard Williams, Gary Gutting, Adrian W. Moore,
Markus Gabriel, etc. 17 What I mean is that had these philosophers not attempted to draw
all kinds of connections between analytic and continental philosophers, there would
arguably be no climate to write this dissertation. Also note that the practice of articulating
a system has been widely shared among philosophers, especially before the 20th century.
However, the system of disputes is also somehow transgressive or subversive.
This system deserves to be called so because it brings to light and problematizes
presuppositions of Nietzsche and Carnap that are taken for granted by these philosophers’
(sometimes unconscious) followers, such as: respectively, Michel Foucault and Jacques
Derrida; and David Lewis and Peter van Inwagen. 18 What I mean is that the very practice
of articulating this system while giving a significantly extensive and new historical
overview of the history of metaphysics, runs in tension with the practices of several (if not
most) contemporary continental and analytic philosophers. Analogously, in bringing to
16
The task of spelling out the requirements for qualifying a philosopher as “continental” or as “analytic” is
a hard one that will not be pursued here. For such an inquiry, see Søren Overgaard, Paul Gilbert, Paul and
Stephen Burwood, An Introduction to Metametaphysics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013: pp.
105-136. What this dissertation does is to follow a widely shared use of the expressions “continental
philosopher” and “analytic philosopher” according to which: Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger, Michel Foucault,
Gilles Deleuze and Jacques Derrida are continental philosophers, whereas Carnap, Willard Van Orman
Quine, Saul Kripke, David Lewis, Peter van Inwagen and Kit Fine are analytic philosophers.
17
Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1979; Hillary
Putnam, Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to Life, Indiana, Indiana University Press, 2008; Bernard Williams,
Ethics and the Limits of Inquiry, London, Routledge, 2006; Gary Gutting, What Philosophers Know: Case
Studies in Recent Analytic Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2009, Thinking the
Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011; Adrian W. Moore, The
Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012;
and Markus Gabriel, Why the World Does Not Exist and I am not a Brain, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2017.
18
Michel Foucault, History of Madness, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006; Jacques Derrida, Spurs:
Nietzsche's Styles/Eperons: Les Styles de Nietzsche, Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1979; David Lewis,
Philosophical Papers: Volume I, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1983; On the Plurality of Worlds, MA,
Blackwell, 1986; and Peter van Inwagen, “Freedom to Break the Laws”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy
XXVIII, 2004: pp. 334-350.
13
light and problematizing the assumptions of the respective projects they addressed, Plato,
Aquinas and Kant also ran in tension with the practices of the philosophers of their times.
While doing so, they also provided a quite extensive and new historical overview of the
history of metaphysics up until the moment they articulated their respective systems.
I call the system defended here the system of disputes because this system does not
commit itself to object-level beliefs that may be associated with metaphysics, such as
“there is evil”, “there is a thing-in-itself” and “there is consciousness”. Instead, the system
of disputes, as its name indicates, is one that only endorses metametaphysical claims
closely connected to disputes. There are two sorts of such claims. To begin with, there are
metametaphysical descriptive claims. These claims are about disputes, about approaches
to the disputes, about the very system of disputes articulated in this dissertation and/or
about reactions to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in
disputes. (1) is an example of this first kind of metametaphysical claim. There also are
metametaphysical normative claims, such as (2). These are practical claims on how one is
to react to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.
I emphasize that the italicized expression “one is to” is considerably vague. This is
so in that this expression does not spell out whether “one” refers to each and every person,
a group of persons or even a single person, such as myself. This is to state that a
metametaphysical normative claim is not to be understood as a sort of categorical
imperative that all persons are to follow in order to count as holders of logos. Instead, such
claim is to be understood as a practical suggestion; a practical suggestion that currently
strikes me as being persuasive and that with any luck will also strike others as being so.
14
Let me now use the rest of this introduction to introductorily justify (1) and (2) by
taking four steps. The first three steps are to spell out why the conflictual craft is a synthesis
between the skeptic and the dogmatic craft. Accordingly, I, first, spell out and compare the
core features of the skeptic and the dogmatic crafts. Second, I problematize the dogmatic
craft by means of the skeptic one and vice-versa so that the shortcomings of these crafts
are avoided. Third, I present, in contrast with the skeptic and the dogmatic craft, the
conflictual craft in aiming to show how the latter craft keeps certain (hopefully positive)
aspects of the former two crafts. My fourth step is to state and briefly explain the eleven
other claims, besides (1) and (2), that characterize the system of disputes that may be
articulated once the conflictual craft is embraced. These eleven claims will be justified in
the rest of the dissertation; (1) and (2) will likewise be further justified, as I proceed.
1.2 The Core Features of the Skeptic Craft and of the Dogmatic Craft
The skeptic, as indicated above, acknowledges that, since immemorial times,
persons have been engaged in disputes. The dogmatist also acknowledges so. Consider
Aristotle. In the first book of his Metaphysics as well as in the first book of his De Anima,
he addresses several aporiai, that is, logical stalemates that seem to make a question
ultimately unanswerable. In doing so, Aristotle also acknowledges that, since immemorial
times, persons have been engaged in disputes. However, the dogmatic way of reacting to
this fact is radically distinct from the skeptic one. This is so in at least five senses.
a. Appearances vs. Beliefs
The first sense in which the skeptic craft and the dogmatic craft are radically distinct
from one another is that the skeptic craft is an ongoing investigation into the issues that
15
have given rise to disputes. Skeptics, Sextus states, are simply “still investigating” these
issues. 19 This is why this investigation of skeptics has no predicable end. Moreover, the
skeptic investigation only bases itself on appearances. On the other hand, the dogmatic
craft is an inquiry that purports to have reached the end of an investigation. In other words,
the dogmatic craft, as its name indicates, is that of dogmatists; those who “in the proper
sense of the word think that they have discovered the truth” about at least one issue that
gave rise to at least one dispute. 20 In doing so, dogmatists do not merely live in accordance
with appearances. Rather, they also commit themselves to dogmas, that is, beliefs.
Note that I italicized the terms “appearances” and “beliefs”. I did so because it is
crucial to underline that, being a skeptic, Sextus does not have a theory that precisely spells
out how these two terms are to be understood. This is to state that Sextus does not spell out
necessary or sufficient conditions for appearance and for belief, let alone for truth. Instead,
he applies the terms “appearance” and “belief” in a considerably loose (if not extremely
vague) way. It follows that it is not surprising that Sextus’ writings themselves have given
rise to an exegetical dispute; one that has been going on for several centuries: the dispute
on how the appearance/belief distinct is to be read in the first place.
As Michael Forster spells out, some of Sextus’ readers are “urbane”, to use
Jonathan Barnes’s expression. 21 These readers of the likes of Kant and, more recently,
Michael Frede interpret that by a belief, Sextus only means “reason-based beliefs
concerning the supersensible”, such as the beliefs that there is a beginning of the world, an
19
PH I 3
Ibid.
21
Jonathan Barnes, “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist”, in Michael Frede and Myles F. Burnyeat (eds.), The
Original Sceptics: A Controversy, Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company, 1997: pp.61.
20
16
immaterial soul or a God. 22 “God” in this dissertation is to be understood in the Jewish,
Christian and/or Islamic sense of a being that has the properties of: being a “you”, that is,
something that human beings can address themselves to (e.g., in prayers); almightiness;
omniscience; moral perfection; eternity; immutability; omnipresence; being the creator of
all other beings, besides God; necessary existence; and uniqueness. 23 Now consider, once
again, Pyrrho’s encounter with the aforementioned “bare wise persons”. Imagine that
exclusively based on his senses (e.g., those of sight, hearing, taste, smell and touching),
Pyrrho recognized the personhood of these persons. An urbane reader might argue that, for
Sextus, Pyrrho’s recognition does not count as belief, but as an appearance. This reader
might also claim that, for Sextus, (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii) are merely appearances exclusively
based on sensible experience; not really beliefs. This is why the skeptic may embrace them.
On the other hand, as Forster also indicates, there are also those, like himself, Georg
Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and Myles Burnyeat, who interpret that by a belief, Sextus means
any kind of belief whatsoever. 24 Barnes labels these readers, among which Barnes himself
is also to be included, “rustic” readers. 25 According to the rustic reading, skeptics would
not commit themselves to even widely shared sense-based beliefs on the sensible. Note that
such beliefs that are not very easily distinguishable from appearances. Also note that rustic
22
Michael N. Forster, “Hegelian vs. Kantian Interpretations of Pyrrhonism: Revolution or Reaction?”,
Kritisches Jahrbuch der Philosophie Vol. 10, 2005: pp. 53. Also see Michael N. Forster, Kant and Skepticism,
New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2008; and Michael Frede “The Sceptic’s Beliefs”, in Michael Frede
and Myles F. Burnyeat (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, Cambridge, Hackett Publishing
Company, 1997.
23
For a more detailed discussion of these properties, see Peter van Inwagen, The Problem of Evil, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2006: pp.18.
24
See Myles F. Burnyeat, “Can the Sceptic Live his Scepticism?” in Explorations in Ancient and Modern
Philosophy Vol. 1, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012.
25
Jonathan Barnes, “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist”, pp.61.
17
readers may take that Pyrrho’s recognition that some “bare wise persons” are persons as a
belief; not as an appearance. The same would be the case with (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii).
It is likewise worth mentioning that there have been readers who have
problematized the widely shared urbane/rustic distinction proposed by Barnes. Ultimately,
these readers endorse a distinct formulation of the exegetical dispute on how Sextus’
distinction between appearance and belief is to be read. Consider, for instance, Gail Fine. 26
She argues that what is at stake in the stated exegetical dispute are two distinct possible
readings that are not precisely captured by Barnes’ distinction: the “some-belief view”
interpretation and the “no-belief view” one. 27 As its name indicates, those who adopt the
former reading take that skeptics can embrace some beliefs. Accordingly, the some-belief
view readers have the burden of spelling the beliefs skeptics can endorse.
For instance, it may be argued that skeptics can embraced sense-based beliefs, such
as the ones that the aforementioned “bare wise persons” are persons and the beliefs that (1i), (1-ii) and (1-iii). It could also be interpreted that skeptics exclusively embrace, not sensebased beliefs in general, but beliefs about their own affections, that is, beliefs about the
“feelings forced upon them by appearances”, such as the belief that it seems to oneself that
such “bare wise persons” are persons and that (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii). 28 “We [skeptics]”,
Sextus claims in arguably pointing to this direction, “report descriptively on each item
according to how it appears to us at the time”. 29 This last passage may also be read as
26
Gail Fine, “Scepticism, Existence, and Belief: A Discussion of R.J. Hankinson, The Sceptics”, in Oxford
Studies in Ancient Philosophy Vol 14, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1996.
27
Gail Fine, “Scepticism, Existence, and Belief”, pp.284.
28
PH I 13.
29
PH I 4.
18
evidence that skeptics can endorse any belief whatsoever as long as such belief is not
identified with a supposedly objective truth of the matter regarding the dispute at stake.
Another way to put this is by stating that the skeptic can have a belief as long as a
(so to speak) it seems to me operator is placed before it. What may, arguably, back up this
interpretation is the fact that, as indicated above, skeptics are those who are always “still
investigating” the issues that have given rise to disputes. Therefore, it could be argued that
skeptics cannot be committed to a belief that purports to be a truth able to end the
investigation at stake. “It seems to me” — a skeptic could state according to such reading
—that these “bare wise persons” are persons and that (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii).
In contrast, the readers who accept the no-belief view described by Fine have a
quite distinct burden: that of replying to the most traditional objection to the skeptic craft
according to which this craft self-refutes itself insofar as its adherents propose but fail to
live without having any belief whatsoever. I will further discuss this objection in what
follows. Before I do so, let me underline that it is not my aim to carefully address (let alone,
solve) the exegetical dispute on how Sextus’ distinction between appearance and belief is
to be read. As the last six paragraphs indicate, this is an extremely complex interpretative
dispute. Hence, in order to carefully address it, arguably, a whole new dissertation
primarily focused on Sextus’ exegesis would have to be written. I cannot do so here.
What I would like to do, instead, is to limit myself to remain neutral on “truth” and
to propose a plausible reading of the appearance/belief distinction. While doing so, I do
not wish to commit myself to any strong exegetical point, such as the point that this
plausible reading of mine is more persuasive than other ones present in the extremely
extensive literature on Sextus’ works; a literature that has centuries of age. The reading I
19
propose is that, for Sextus, an appearance is distinct from a belief insofar as: an appearance
is less controversial and, consequently, less likely to give rise to a dispute than a belief.
Textual evidence points to this reading of mine. What I mean is that I interpret that
Sextus takes an appearance to be less controversial and, hence, less likely to give rise to a
dispute than a belief because he states that an appearance is “equally apparent to everyone
and agreed upon and not disputed”. 30 On the other hand, Sextus states that belief “is assent
to some unclear object of investigation in the sciences”. 31 Therefore, my reading is that he
takes belief to be quite controversial and, so, more likely to give rise to a dispute than an
appearance. It is also important to emphasize that Sextus states that “disputed items, insofar
as they have been subject to dispute, are unclear” and “on everything unclear there has
been an interminable dispute”. 32 Furthermore, consider that Sextus suggests that disputes
occur when everyday life is disrupted and “opposed accounts” are held. 33
In contrast, then, Sextus describes skeptics as those who live in accordance with
appearances insofar as they “set out without opinions [doxai] from the observance of
ordinary life”, that is, skeptics “live in accordance with everyday observances”. 34 There
are four kinds of such everyday observances. The first everyday observance is “guidance
by nature”. 35 This is the power to perceive appearances and to think about appearances.
Now consider someone seeking to satisfy one’s needs for food and drink. To do so is to act
in accordance with a “necessitation by feelings”. 36 This is the second everyday observance.
30
PH II 8.
PH I 13.
32
PH II 182 and PH II 8, respectively.
33
PH I 4.
34
PH II 254 and PH I 23, respectively.
35
PH I 23.
36
Ibid.
31
20
The third everyday observance is the “handing down of laws and customs”. 37 This is the
power to grasp the widely shared norms of one’s community, such as the norm that “piety
is good and impiety bad”. 38 The fourth everyday observance is the “teaching of kinds of
expertise”, such as that of playing a musical instrument. 39
I also would like to assume that the appearance/belief distinction is sensitive to
context, even though Sextus does not explicitly state so. The reason I make this move is
that, given my stated interpretation of this distinction, it is quite plausible to take this
distinction to be sensitive to context. Consider, once again, Pyrrho’s encounter with the
aforementioned “bare wise persons”. In most contexts of everyday life, the statement that
the latter are persons is a non-controversial “clear” appearance; one that is held by someone
who is guided by nature. The same can be stated about (1-i), (1-ii), (1-iii). In other more
dogmatic contexts, though, these three points themselves may count as beliefs. This is
because they may raise a theoretical dispute between the one who endorses them and an
opponent who believes that such “bare wise persons” are not persons, but, rather, lack
personhood and that, so, (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii) are to be rejected. Note that this opponent
could problematize the very criterion that allows one to conclude that some “bare wise
persons” are persons. For instance, this opponent may argue that accordance with one’s
sensible experience is not the criterion that is to be adopted in spelling out whether these
“bare wise persons” are persons. This is because one’s senses are not always reliable, that
is, a being could appear to be a person and still be something else that falls short of logos.
37
Ibid.
Ibid.
39
Ibid.
38
21
Moreover, this opponent may also claim that it is not at all clear that sensible experience is
enough to back up (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii); that other criterion is to be adopted to do so.
This is to state that one person’s appearance is another person’s belief (and viceversa). 40 Henceforth, then, the (much less philosophical loaded) term “claim” will be used
to refer to that which resists been qualified as an appearance or as a belief, that is, that
which may be an appearance in certain contexts, but a belief in others. Given that most
beliefs count as appearances in certain contexts and vice-versa, I will mainly speak in terms
of “claims” in what follows. Accordingly, I would like to describe (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii)
as claims; not as appearances or as beliefs. Moreover, my proposed reading is that skeptics
may merely insinuate, indicate or point toward without never explicitly making a case or
explicitly embracing (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii). The reason, as indicated above, is that there
are dogmatic contexts in which (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii) are beliefs that lead to disputes.
b. Undecidability and Strong Decision
The second sense in which the skeptic craft and the dogmatic craft are radically
distinct from one another is that, given (1), those who adopt the former craft seek to spell
out that disputes have seemed to be anepikritos, that is, undecidable. Note that to seek to
spell out so is not to be confounded with the attitude of stating that is “true” that disputes
are undecidable. Sextus calls those who make this move “Academics”, not skeptics. 41 I
will not address the academic craft here. What is crucial for my purposes, instead, is to
40
Note that Sextus was inserted in a context in which most people were pious in taking the Greek gods to
exist, and to be provident. Hence, the norm that one is to be pious counted for him as an appearance, that is,
as a way of handing down a custom. Sextus indicates so in stating that in “following ordinary life without
opinions, we [skeptics] say that there are gods and we are pious towards the gods and say that they are
provident”. See PH III 2.
41
PH I 3.
22
emphasize that dogmatists, on the other hand, believe that at least one dispute is decidable
once and for all. In doing so, they seem to contradict (1-i), (1-ii) and/or (1-iii). I will back
up this last claim much more carefully throughout the fourth and the fifth chapter. For now,
let me take it for granted, while also underlining that dogmatists are those who suggest that
their own works attest to the existence of at least one undeniable metaphysical claim. To
suggest so is to indicate that a strong decision regarding at least one dispute is attainable.
c. Equipollence and Strong Non-Equipollence
The third sense in which the skeptic craft and the dogmatic craft are radically
distinct from one another is that, given any dispute whatsoever, skeptics also aim to spell
out that it appears to exist an isostheneia, that is, an equipollence regarding the claims or
practices of the conflicting parties. This is to state that, given (1), skeptics aim to spell out
that such conflicting parties ultimately have equally rationally persuasive views.
Dogmatists, on the other hand, argue that there are strong ways of avoiding the
equipollency of their own claims or practices with those of their opponents. For dogmatists,
this could be done by showing that, regardless of context, their claims are more rationally
persuasive than their opponents’. This is because, for dogmatists, undeniable metaphysical
claims would be justified by one or a conjunction of first principles or starting points.
By a starting point, it is to be understood a “self-evident” likewise undeniable
metaphysical claim or criterion to deal with the dispute at stake that no person may
rationally reject and that ultimately justifies all other claims and practices endorsed by the
dogmatist. The dogmatist who endorses a single starting point may be called
foundationalist dogmatist. I call coherentist dogmatist the dogmatist who embraces a
conjunction of such starting points. On his part, Sextus states that skeptics aim to be
23
“philanthropic” regarding dogmatists; this is to state that skeptic “wish to cure by
argument, as far as they can, the conceit and rashness of the Dogmatists”. 42
The dogmatist’ conceit and rashness is that of taking oneself to be able to provide
an undeniable metaphysical claim, even though no such claim appears attainable. The
philanthropic skeptic cure is pursued by means of a tropos, that is, a mode. Sextus spells
out fifteen of such modes. He attributes ten of these modes to the “older skeptics”; he
attributes five modes to “the more recent Skeptics”. 43 The latter modes, Diogenes states,
are those of “Agrippa and his school”. 44 I will briefly comment on the tenth mode of the
older skeptics in what follows. Nevertheless, I emphasize that that the modes of Agrippa
have been traditionally understood as being the most challenging for dogmatists. This is
why I would like to primarily focus on them in this dissertation.
The first mode of Agrippa is that of dispute; it is to suggest that it appears that any
theoretical dispute at stake is an undecidable one in that claims about it that contradict or
run in tension with one another have been held. Indeed, there have been contrasting claims
even about what is a belief; what is an appearance; how beliefs are distinct from
appearances; etc. Agrippa’s second mode is infinite regress. This mode indicates that that
which is supposed to justify one’s claim about a theoretical dispute (e.g., a criterion to deal
with the dispute at stake) is itself in need of further justification, and so on ad infinitum.
The third mode of Agrippa may be called relativity. This mode serves to indicate
that one’s criterion to address the theoretical dispute at stake is not universally shared, but
relative to one’s own culture. This is why others may rationally reject this criterion.
42
PH III 280.
PH I 36 and PH I 164, respectively.
44
Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, (9.88).
43
24
Agrippa’s fourth mode is hypothesis. This mode aims to show that, in order to avoid the
infinite regress, one needs to ask one’s opponents for a concession “without proof” of a
hypothesis, say, a criterion to deal with the theoretical dispute at stake. 45 The fifth mode of
Agrippa is circularity: to show that, in order to avoid asking for a concession, one may
ultimately presuppose the very claim or the criterion to back up the claim that is been
theoretically disputed. In relying on such modes, skeptics seek to insinuate that dogmatists
are “sick” in believing that their claims are undeniable metaphysical ones.
d. Suspension of Judgment and Universal Judgment
Accordingly, there is a fourth sense in which the skeptic craft and the dogmatic
craft are radically distinct from one another: namely, skeptics seek to bring about at least
in themselves an epochē, that is, a suspension of judgment. On their parts, dogmatists
simply do not do so. Rather, what dogmatists do is to commit themselves to undeniable
metaphysical claims. In other words, they make supposedly universal judgments. Now let
me underline that to bring (at least in oneself) a suspension of judgment is not to be
committed to the normative claim that one should do so. Instead, it is to not commit oneself
to any claim whatsoever, including that very claim that one is to suspend judgment.
e. Tranquility and Fundamental Health
Finally, the fifth and last sense in which the skeptic craft and the dogmatic craft are
radically distinct from one another concerns what these crafts aim to achieve. Ultimately,
skeptics seek to experience an ataraxia. This is a feeling of tranquility, that is, “a freedom
45
PH I 168.
25
from disturbance or calmness of soul”; one that, skeptics insinuate, would arise after one
suspends judgment. 46 What dogmatists, on their parts, seek to achieve is something quite
different: they ultimately aim to experience what I would like to call a fundamental health.
By this kind of health, it is to be understood that of rationally thinking in accordance with
what all persons insofar as holders of logos think, act or should think and act.
1.3 Problematizing the Dogmatic and the Skeptic Craft
a. Against the Dogmatic Craft
I problematize the dogmatic craft by means of the skeptic craft. To do so is to follow
skeptics in stating, to speak like them, that “it appears to me” that dogmatists ultimately
suffer from the stated “conceit and rashness” identified by Sextus: that of taking oneself to
be able to provide at least one undeniable metaphysical claim, even though no such claim
appears attainable. 47 Notice that what points toward this objection to dogmatists is the very
acknowledgment of (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii). More precisely, what I mean is that I embrace
three claims. First, if, as (1-i) indicates, some others (who, I emphasize, are sometimes
other dogmatists themselves) are legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake,
it is hard to understand how dogmatists can obtain any undeniable metaphysical claim, that
is, it seems that certain others can and have actually constantly rationally rejected any
allegedly undeniable metaphysical claim proposed by dogmatists. Furthermore, notice that
the skeptic appeal to the aforementioned modes also points to this direction.
46
PH I 10. Moreover, note that the interpretation of the skeptic craft proposed here is quite influenced by
Burnyeat’s reading. As he states, this craft’s “sequence is: conflict – undecidability – equal strength – epoché,
and finally ataraxia”. See Myles F. Burnyeat, “Can the Sceptic Live his Scepticism?”, pp. 209.
47
PH III 280.
26
Hence, the second claim I have in mind is: if, as (1-ii) indicates, no person has
settled a dispute once and for all, dogmatists seem to be, indeed, “conceited” in suggesting
that their own works attest to otherwise. Third, it seems that dogmatists could only take
themselves to be able to obtain at least one undeniable metaphysical claim if they “rashly”
ignore (1-i) and (1-ii), say, by acting as if they did not have any others and, so, were able
to solve disputes once and for all. This action, though, is quite unpersuasive because (1-i)
and (1-ii) are, if not appearances in the sense embraced here, at least widely shared claims.
Like skeptics, then, I am simply not convinced that dogmatists have been able to discover
a truth of the matter or to attain a strong decision concerning any dispute whatsoever. I am
also not convinced that dogmatists are able to strongly avoid the equipollence of their views
with that of their opponents, such as their others. Accordingly, I am skeptical about the
possibility of universal judgments and that of reaching the dogmatic goal of achieving the
aforementioned universal health. In fact, I am inclined to believe that persons cannot obtain
this health because their others are always problematizing logos or what one takes to be so.
I highlight that this last claim as well as my objection to dogmatism will be further spelled
in more detail as the dissertation proceeds, especially, in the fourth and in the fifth chapter.
b. Against the Skeptic Craft
I also problematize the skeptic craft by means of the dogmatic one. Nevertheless, I
do not wish to do so in the most traditional way, that is, by embracing the stated traditional
objection to the skeptic craft according to which this craft self-refutes itself insofar as its
adherents propose but fail to live without having any belief. Notice that this objection can
be found in Diogenes’s Lives of Eminent Philosophers itself and was more recently
27
rearticulated by Burnyeat. 48 It is not this dissertation’s aim to discuss this objection in
detail. Yet, I emphasize that this objection depends on a reading of the appearance / belief
distinction insofar as those who endorse it suggest that belief involves an active volition to
endorse one practice over another one. This dissertation is neutral on whether belief is to
be characterized so, but a few points are likewise to be considered: the appearance / belief
distinction, as indicated above, is not precisely made by Sextus; this dissertation has used
the term “belief” in the stated sense of something “unclear” that leads to a theoretical
dispute; and the problematic claim that belief also involves an active volition is one that
leads to a theoretical dispute that skeptics may approach by means of the skeptic craft.
What will be presupposed, then, is that skeptics may live free of belief (in the stated
sense endorsed here). They may do so by, on the one hand, endorsing what they take to be
“clear” and uncontroversial appearances whenever they are inserted in everyday life
contexts. On the other hand, they may adopt the skeptic craft in suspending judgment and
not committing themselves to any “unclear” and controversial belief when they are within
more dogmatic contexts of theoretical disputes. What skeptics cannot do, as Sextus himself
acknowledges, is to live over and above appearances, that is, they need to embrace the four
kinds of everyday observances. In doing so, skeptics cannot be neutral regarding practices,
that is, they need to do something in taking one course of action instead of another one.
Notice that Sextus himself acknowledges that skeptics cannot be practically neutral;
skeptics “are not able to be utterly inactive”, he explicitly recognizes. 49 Indeed, the
impossibility of practical neutrality may be a “clear” and uncontroversial appearance. What
48
See Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, (9.102-105); and Myles F. Burnyeat, “Can the
Sceptic Live his Scepticism?”, pp. 205.
49
PH I 23.
28
Sextus does not acknowledge, though, is that the skeptic craft can be problematized by
means of the dogmatic one, not by endorsing the stated traditional objection, but by
pointing toward a properly skeptic kind of “conceit and rashness”: the conceit and rashness
of apparently wishing to achieve an ultimately impossible neutrality regarding practices,
while engaging oneself in the exclusively negative skeptical investigation and failing to
positively explicitly justify the practices that oneself inevitably actively endorses. Let me
carefully spell out what I mean by this alternative objection so that it becomes explicit that,
ultimately, the skeptic conceit and rashness is just as problematic as that of the dogmatists.
Consider Sextus’ discussion of the tenth mode of the old skeptics. This mode is
considerably similar to Agrippa’s relativity mode; it is that of opposing contrasting
“persuasions and customs and laws and beliefs in myths and dogmatic suppositions” to one
another. 50 For my purposes, it suffices to focus on Sextus’ discussion of custom, which he
understands as “a common acceptance by a number of people of a certain way of acting,
transgressors of which are not necessarily punished”. 51 Note that Sextus limits himself to
“oppose custom to custom”. His way of doing so is to stress that: “some of the Ethiopians
tattoo their babies, while we do not; the Persians deem it becoming to wear brightlycoloured full-length dresses, while we deem it unbecoming; Indians have sex with women
in public, while most other people hold that it is shameful”. 52 My reading is that Sextus’
discussion of such customs is evidence of the alternative objection.
To begin with, in endorsing the merely negative skeptic investigation, Sextus seems
to wish to achieve an ultimately impossible neutrality regarding practices. This is so insofar
50
PH I 145.
PH I 146.
52
PH I 148.
51
29
as he simply does not care to spell out what he would do in a context in which he actually
had to decide between accepting or rejecting the stated customs, that is, Sextus does not
discuss whether he actively endorses the practices of tattooing a baby, wearing brightlycoloured full-length dresses or having sex with women in public. As if he could remain
practically neutral regarding these practices and/or all other practices, what Sextus limits
to do is to attempt to bring about at least in himself a suspension of judgment that would
cause tranquility, that is, he indicates that to endorse or to not endorse the stated customs
are equally rationally persuasive courses of actions. However, as Sextus acknowledges,
skeptics “are not able to be utterly inactive”. 53 Hence, skeptics, like everybody else, need
to endorse practices. I object, then, that the skeptic craft simply fails to positively explicitly
justify the practices that skeptics inevitably endorse in the end, such as the very practices
of tattooing or not tattooing a baby; wearing or not wearing brightly-coloured full-length
dresses; having or not having sex with women in public; etc. So, a skeptic’s decision of
adopting a practice as opposed to any other one is a barely justified decision. Arguably,
this decision may be even an arbitrary one. Two other examples point to this direction.
First, imagine that Pyrrho was next to Alexander when the latter’s troops were
positioned to fight those of the Indians. Imagine that, in relying on the skeptic craft and
seeking to achieve tranquility, Pyrrho suspended judgment on whether this fight is to be
held, that is, Pyrrho felt that to fight or not to fight the Indians were equally rationally
persuasive courses of action so that no strong decision for one course of action or the other
could be obtained. However, Pyrrho still had to act, say, by joining Alexander’s troops;
trying to stop them in spelling out the skeptic craft; running away from the battle; remaining
53
PH I 23.
30
paralyzed; crying in desperation; etc. I object, then, that in relying on the skeptic craft and
apparently wishing to achieve an impossible neutrality concerning all of these practices,
Pyrrho would fail to positively explicitly justify whatever practice he actively endorsed in
the end. This is why his choice of one course of action, instead of another one, would be a
barely justified choice. Arguably, his choice could even be a quite arbitrary one.
Second, imagine a male guard who works at the U.S. / Mexico border and turns out
to be a skeptic. Imagine that this guard suspends judgment on the dispute on whether
children of illegal Mexican immigrants caught in the border are to be separated from their
parents. He feels that the decisions of separating and of not separating these children from
their parents are equipollent, that is, their “levels” of rational persuasion are similar. Hence,
from this guard’s perspective, neither one of these decisions seems a strong one. In fact, he
feels that more right-wing politicians, such as Donald Trump or Jair Bolsonaro, are just as
rationally persuasive as more left-wing ones of the likes of Barack Obama or the former
Brazilian president, Luis Inácio Lula da Silva. Indeed, let me underline that, as the neoPyrrhonists, Bueno and Junqueira Smith themselves, state, another neo-Pyrrhonist,
“Porchat (in conversation)”, goes as far as holding that “the skeptic could have any political
doctrine, including a radical one: from extreme right to extreme left.” 54
However, note that the imagined guard still needs to act, say, by enforcing the law
that children of illegal immigrants caught in the border are to be separated from their
parents; turning the blind eye on this law and not enforcing it; quitting his job; etc. My
view, then, is that in relying on the skeptic craft and apparently wishing to achieve an
impossible neutrality concerning all of these practices, this guard would also fail to
54
Otávio Bueno and Plínio Junqueira Smith, “Skepticism in Latin America”, pp. 9.
31
positively explicitly justify the practice he actively ultimately endorses; his practice would
also be a barely justified practice and, perhaps, even an arbitrary practice. To put in the
Portuguese language of neo-Pyrrhonists themselves, this is to state that a skeptic seems to
aim, but inevitably fail to be an “isentão”, someone who takes no practical party once a
dispute arises. Ultimately, skeptics simply take a barely justified or even arbitrary stance.
Note, though, that a, so to speak, hardcore skeptic could still insinuate that to a have
barely justified or even an ultimately arbitrary stance is just as rationally appealing as
having a justified and non-arbitrary stance; that, indeed, to attempt and fail to be an
“isentão” is just as rationally appealing as to not do so in taking any other kind of position.
I also have a reply to the hardcore skeptic, but I would like to postpone its articulation until
this dissertation’s conclusion. I do so under two assumptions. First, in order to more
persuasively reply to the hardcore skeptic, I need to establish several other points so that
my own stance becomes explicit. Second, I take that most of this dissertation’s readers are
not skeptics. Hence, they may be sufficiently convinced by my alternative objection.
1.4 The Conflictual Craft
I now characterize the conflictual craft in contrast to the skeptic and the dogmatic
one. This will serve to spell out in which sense the former craft keeps certain aspects of the
latter two crafts while avoiding both the dogmatic and the skeptic conceit and rashness.
a. Neither Appearances nor Beliefs but Claims
The conflictual craft is neither a skeptic ongoing investigation exclusively based on
appearances nor a dogmatic inquiry that purports to have a particular kind of belief: an
undeniable metaphysical claim. Like the skeptic craft, the conflictual craft is a kind of
32
investigation. Nonetheless, a conflictual crafter is someone who acknowledges the
impossibility of practical neutrality, that is, the impossibility of being an “isentão”. This is
why, like the dogmatist, the conflictual crafter explicitly seeks to justify whatever claims
and/or practices one ultimately positively endorses. In doing so, the conflictual
investigation provisionally stops the investigation. This is so insofar as the conflictual
crafter settles for a claim and/or practice justified by whatever imperfect justificatory
resources one currently has at his or her disposal. Indeed, this dissertation itself is,
ultimately, a report of how I can currently justify my views on the disputes addressed here.
What I mean by an imperfect justificatory resource is a resource that backs up a
claim and/or a practice in a way that currently strikes the conflictual crafter as being
persuasive, even though this might change in the future and no end of the process of
justification of one’s practices and claims seems predictable. In fact, this justificatory
process may be one whose end is unpredictable or that is only bounded by the conflictual
crafter’s own finitude. 55 This is why conflictual crafters are never completely epistemically
satisfied; they never cease to attempt to justify their very own claims and practices,
regardless of their very likely impossibility of convincing all of their others or even
themselves once and for all. An example of an imperfect justificatory resource that I
endorse is that of claiming that basic empirical observation of the history of metaphysics
backs up (1); this observation will be spelled out in much more detail as I proceed. For
now, consider that another imperfect justificatory resource endorsed here is that of claiming
55
There might be some resemblances between the conflictual craft, and infinist views, such as Peter Klein’s.
This is not an issue that can be addressed here. For infinitism, see Peter Klein, “How to be an Infinitist about
Doxastic Justification”, Philosophical Studies 134.1, 2007.
33
that my readings of the skeptic and the dogmatic craft back up (2). Distinct from skeptics,
I am not neutral on all claims. I take (1) and (2) to be more persuasive than their denials.
This last move is controversial. This is so insofar as my others reject it; say, in
suggesting that their others are not legitimate rational peers; in taking themselves to have
solved a dispute once and for all; by taking the acknowledgement of (1-i) and (1-ii) to be
ultimately irrelevant and/or by claiming that the conflictual craft is not a synthesis of the
skeptic and of the dogmatic one able to articulate the system of disputes. Distinct from
skeptics, though, I do not take the fact that my others will disagree with whatever move I
make, with whatever criterion I propose or with whatever claim I endorse as a reason for
seeking an ultimately impossible practical neutrality. Rather, this is merely a reason for
recognizing myself as inevitably inserted into what I would like to call a conflictual
community: a community in which theoretical and practical disputes constantly take place,
and for every member x, there is another member y so that x and y are others of one another.
A few examples of conflictual communities are: that of all holders of logos; the Western
community; the community of all contemporary philosophers or, even more narrowly, the
community of all philosophers in a philosophy department, such as that of the University
of Miami or of the University of Bonn themselves. Also notice that the fact that the
conflictual craft takes for granted that persons have always been inserted into such
conflictual communities is a first reason for calling this craft a conflictual craft.
b. Neither Undecidability nor Strong Decision but Weak Decision
The conflictual craft neither seeks to skeptically spell out that disputes have seemed
undecidable nor purports to dogmatically achieve a strong decision concerning them, that
is, one that suggests that one’s own work attests to the existence of at least one undeniable
34
metaphysical claim. Instead, the conflictual crafter is the one who takes oneself to be able
to achieve a weak decision regarding disputes, that is, one that relies on merely deniable
metaphysical claims, such as (1) and (2), backed up by imperfect justificatory resources,
such as the very ones mentioned in the last sub-section. Another way to put this is by stating
that conflictual crafters take that claims can be rationally supported, but not in an ultimately
rationally undeniable way, as dogmatists have always wished. Note that a weak decision,
then, does not lead to the ultimate end of the dispute at stake. Rather, this decision is merely
one that is contextually accepted by some interlocutors but rejected by others, such as those
who do not even grant that the dispute that one aims to address is a pertinent way to spend
some time of one’s life in the first place. What I mean, then, is that a weak decision does
not purport to end conflict in convincing all persons once and for all in ending the dispute
at stake. This is, accordingly, a second reason for calling my craft a conflictual one.
c. Neither Equipollence nor Strong Non-Equipollence, but Weak NonEquipollence
The conflictual craft neither seeks to skeptically spell out the equipollence of
conflicting parties’ claims or practices, nor purports to strongly avoid the equipollency of
one’s own claims and practices with those of opponents, say, by suggesting that one’s own
claims are, regardless of context, more persuasive than those of one’s opponents. Instead,
what the conflictual crafter does is to weakly avoid the equipollency of one’s own claims
and practices with those of one’s opponents. This can be done by recognizing that the
conflictual crafter’s claims and practices are not immune to the skeptic modes, and that
their “level” of rational persuasiveness varies with context. In other words, a conflictual
crafter is someone who acknowledges that one’s own claims and practices are rationally
35
persuasive in certain contexts, such as those in which interlocutors share the conflictual
crafter’s sensibility regarding disputes; take the conflictual crafter’s moves to be pertinent
and even interesting; grant that the authors the conflictual crafter discusses are relevant and
deserving of attention; do not ask for a definition of each and every term applied; do not
entitle themselves to be rude with the conflictual crafter; are educated enough to understand
the points the conflictual crafters seeks to establish; etc. There are contexts in which
interlocutors do not have such characteristics. In such contexts, conflictual crafters grant
that their views lack in rational persuasion and, so, may even intensify conflict by bringing
more dissensus. This consequence, though, is very likely practically inevitable. Thus,
conflictual crafters embrace it. This is a third reason for calling their craft a conflictual one.
d. Neither Suspension of Judgment nor Universal Judgment but Particular
Judgment
Accordingly, the conflictual craft neither aims to bring about a suspension of
judgement, nor purports to make universal judgments. Rather, this craft seeks to back up
particular judgments, that is, deniable metaphysical claims, such as (1) and (2). Consider,
then, that if Sextus were a conflictual crafter, he would rely on rationally deniable claims
in seeking to avoid the stated alternative objection while justifying his own practices
regarding tattooing or not tattooing babies, wearing brightly-coloured full-length dresses
or having sex with women in public. Accordingly, when confronted with Alexander’s
troops, Pyrrho would have proceed in a similar manner, were him to be a conflictual crafter,
that is, he would rely on deniable metaphysical claim in imperfectly justifying a course of
action. The same would have been done by the guard in the U.S./ Mexico border, were him
a conflictual crafter as opposed to a skeptic. In doing so, he would accept the impossibility
36
of not running into conflict with anyone, not even with others. Indeed, to live, for
conflictual crafters, is basically to live in constant conflict with such others. This is,
accordingly, a fourth reason for calling my craft conflictual craft.
e. Neither Tranquility nor Fundamental Health but Singular Health
Finally, the conflictual craft neither seeks the skeptic’s tranquility nor the
dogmatist’s fundamental health. Indeed, given that persons have been inserted into all sorts
of conflictual communities, I tend to think that it is impossible for them to actually fulfill
these goals; it is simply “unrealistic” to even aim to do so. The reason is that persons who
are inserted into conflictual communities are constantly running into theoretical and
practical disputes, especially with others. Hence, it is quite hard to believe that anyone
living in such communities could achieve the state of mind of tranquility or express a
fundamental health. Now note that this last considerably weak claim is to be distinguished
from a much stronger claim: the claim that skeptics as well as dogmatists have always
implicitly naively attempted to bring about a non-conflictual community in which there are
no theoretical and practical disputes, and that no one is an other of anyone else.
I am not committed to this stronger claim. However, I would like to state that I tend
to agree with Forster when he speculates that Pyrrho might have had “at bottom a yearning
for something from the past”, that is, an Archaic non-conflictual Ancient Greek
community. 56 In fact, I also tend to think that a dogmatist also yearns for something similar:
a future non-conflictual community in which all persons unanimously agreed with the
dogmatist’s views on disputes. I cannot back up in detail these tendencies of mine in this
56
Michael N. Forster, “Hegelian vs. Kantian Interpretations”, pp. 70.
37
dissertation. However, let me underline that it seems that only in a non-conflictual
community, one could achieve the skeptic tranquility or the dogmatic fundamental health.
Let me also underline the fifth and last reason for calling my craft a conflictual one:
I, in a more “realist vein”, do not aim to bring about a non-conflictual community into
existence, but, rather, seek to achieve a goal that is more likely attainable than the skeptic
and the dogmatic one for who anyone who is inserted into a conflictual community. The
goal I have in mind is that of bringing about at least in myself a singular health: that of
thinking and acting with accordance with what properly characterizes myself in a way that
currently strikes me as being persuasive and that may also be persuasive and helpful for
other legitimate rational peers who are part of the conflictual communities I am inserted.
1.5 The System of Disputes
I claim, then, that the conflictual craft serves to formulate a neither skeptic, nor
dogmatic system of disputes; thirteen claims characterize this system. (1) and (2) are the
first two claims I have in mind. The eleven other ones will be supported by all sorts of
imperfect justificatory resources, as the dissertation proceeds. However, before I start
doing so, I would like to use this section to state and briefly explain such claims. This will
allow readers to be aware of what is about to come in the next almost 300 pages.
The third claim of the system of dispute is a metametaphysical descriptive claim:
(3) Nietzsche and Carnap champion contrasting reactions to the fact that, since
immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes. While doing so, they
both endorse, but interpret differently an overcoming metametaphysics
characterized by three metametaphysical normative claims:
(3-i)
An overcoming of metaphysics is to be performed.
(3-ii)
This overcoming is to be performed by adopting a method of
38
linguistic analysis that is suspicious of the metaphysical use of
language and interprets such use through a different use of language
that aims to avoid metaphysics.
(3-iii)
This overcoming is to contribute to the political task of resisting
“diseased” metaphysical practices and promoting “healthy” nonmetaphysical ones.
Nietzsche’s reaction is what may be called a libertarian reaction: that of
theoretically defending claims that are to provoke dissensus, while practically resisting
egalitarian practices and promoting libertarian ones. An egalitarian practice is one that
privileges communitarian tendencies to either consciously or unconsciously contribute to
create a really universal community, while seeking to attenuate one’s own’s singularity
and/or the singularity of others, especially, deviants whose practices violate the norms of
merely particular communities. By a merely particular community, I understand a
considerably narrow community that exclusively seeks to defend the interests of a
considerably narrow group of persons, such as that of all white, male, heterosexual, rich
North Americans or Europeans. A really universal community is one that seeks to defend
the interests of all beings or at least persons, regardless of their race, nationality, etc.
By a libertarian practice, it is to be understood one that privileges individualistic
tendencies. These are tendencies to either consciously or unconsciously act in accordance
and contribute to bring about (or, to put it in Nietzschean terms, to affirm) one’s own
singularity and/or the singularities of others, while problematizing the constrains that any
kind of community imposes upon such singularities. I read that, in symmetrical contrast to
Nietzsche, Carnap embraces an egalitarian reaction to the fact that, since immemorial
times, persons have been engaged in dispute. This reaction is to theoretically defend claims
39
regarding which consensus is to be reached, while practically resisting libertarian practices
and promoting egalitarian ones. The fourth claim of the system of dispute is that:
(4) The contrast between Nietzsche’s libertarian and Carnap’s egalitarian reaction
is to be considered, not only by the few scholars who are interested in both of
these philosophers’ works, but by a far larger group of philosophers that
includes: those who have addressed the continental-analytic gap; those who are
concerned with the development of the history of 20th and 21st century
philosophy; and/or those who are interested in the works of the likes of
Foucault, Derrida, Lewis and/or van Inwagen.
Notice that this claim is a normative metametaphysical one. The same is the case
with the fifth claim of the system of disputes: namely,
(5) One is to do a synthesis of Nietzsche’s libertarian and Carnap’s egalitarian
reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in
disputes.
Another way to state (5) is by claiming that one is to act in accordance with a tendency; a
tendency that —in contrast with Nietzsche’s “will to power” and Carnap’s “will to order”
that will be addressed in the next chapter —I call the will to synthesis. The will to synthesis
is the tendency to either consciously or unconsciously embrace the very contradictory
conflict between one’s communitarian tendencies (or will to order) and one’s
individualistic tendencies (or will to power), while seeking to maximize and achieve a
balance that prudently satisfies both of these tendencies, even if to perfectly achieve such
a balance may be ultimately impossible for inevitably imperfect persons. Another way to
state this is by claiming that one acts in accordance with the will to synthesis when one
aims to be an open-minded person who is both a libertarian and an egalitarian (as opposed
to a more close-minded conservative person who is neither a libertarian nor an egalitarian).
The sixth claim of my system is also a metametaphysical descriptive claim:
40
(6) There is no undeniable metaphysical claim, but a properly dogmatic “subtle”
violence.
By a “subtle” violence, it is to be understood one that is distinct and not as easily
identifiable as corporeal upfront forms of violence, such as that of punching someone. The
properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, I aim to show in what follows, is that of Aristotle and
several of his more or less conscious followers, such as Saint Anselm, David Hume, Kant,
Ludwig Wittgenstein and, more recently, Eli Hirsch. These are philosophers who adopt the
dogmatic craft or crafts similar to it and suggest that their writings attest to the existence
of at least one undeniable metaphysical claim, while not explicitly endorsing and, perhaps,
even contradicting (1-i) and/or (1-ii). This is to read that these philosophers do not merely
suffer from a “conceit and rashness”, as Sextus suggests, but, rather, in expressing a
“subtle” violence, insinuate that their others are not legitimate rational peers insofar as
disputes are at stake, and/or that one’s works settle at least one dispute once and for all.
In providing textual evidence from writings by the philosophers named in the last
paragraph, I aim to show that this insinuation has been quite pervasive in the history of
metaphysics, and that those who embrace it are neither libertarians nor egalitarians but,
rather, conservatively act in discordance with the will to synthesis. The seventh claim of
the system of disputes is the metametaphysical descriptive claim that, as the contrasts
between the works of Nietzsche, Carnap and their respective followers indicate,
(7) Disputes are micro-political conflicts analogous to macro-political conflicts,
that is, they are micro-wars.
By a micro-war, I understand a micro-political conflict analogous to a macro one.
An example of a macro-political conflict is the quarrel on whether the bronze equestrian
41
statue of the former confederate general Robert E. Lee is to be removed from a public park
in Charlottesville, Virginia, USA. I presuppose that three features characterize a macropolitical conflict: first, a significant social importance, that is, not only a single individual,
family or group of acquaintances care about the conflict but, rather, hundreds, thousands,
millions or even billions of people; second, parties involved in a macro-political conflict
explicitly pressure a significant group of people (beyond their families or group of
acquaintances) to change their practices by sometimes even resorting to violence, such as
that of marching with torches and screaming words of order; and, third, in a macro-political
conflict, there is an explicit presence of normative issues, say, on which criterion is to be
adopted to deal with the macro-conflict at stake in the first place.
On the other hand, a micro-war, that is, a micro-political conflict is one that merely
implicitly has these very three features. This is to state that this conflict is one whose
significant social importance is not upfront. Moreover, the parties engaged in a micropolitical conflict pressure a significant group of people to change their practices without
relying on upfront kinds of violence, even if more “subtle” kinds of violence may be used.
Finally, in micro-political conflicts, normative issues are not very openly present but,
rather, need to be made explicit by quite specialized readers of the conflict at stake.
The system of disputes’ eighth claim is the metametaphysical descriptive one that
(8) There has been a right-wing allegedly apolitical approach to disputes that,
perhaps, avoids the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, but still expresses the
pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence.
I make a case for this claim by addressing the views of three allegedly apolitical
philosophers on the theoretical dispute on whether, independently of the way entities are
42
described, they have essences: Quine, Kripke and Kit Fine. 57 By a pseudo-non-dogmatic
“subtle” violence, I understand that of not explicitly contradicting (1-i) and (1-ii), while
still, nonetheless, contradicting (1-iii). This is done by those whose views are quite
unpersuasive insofar as they ignore or at least do not consider that: among the others, some
are legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake and no person has settled a
dispute once and for all. A right-wing approach is to be understood as one that is less
tolerant than a left-wing approach because right-wingers privilege their needs for selfdefense over their powers to show empathy toward others; left-wingers do the opposite in
being more open-minded that more close-minded right-wingers.
It is assumed that empathy and self-defense are mental states that both have a
passive as well as an active component. I am inspired by Michael Slote in assuming that to
passively empathize is to feel the suffering of someone else (e.g., that of an other) or at
least to recognize that this suffering exists.58 To actively empathize is to act under the
influence of this suffering in ceasing to give or at least attenuating the importance of one’s
particular identities so that this suffering is reduced. A particular identity (e.g., to be from
the South of the USA) is one shared by some, but not all persons. To passively self-defend
oneself is to feel that others are a threat to one’s particular identities or to one’s life. To
actively self-defend oneself is to act under the influence of this feeling so that one’s life
and/or particular identities are protected. I also argue that right-wingers who express the
57
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object; Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity; and Kit Fine “Essence
and Modality”, in Philosophical Perspectives Vol. 8, 1994: pp.1-16.
58
Michael Slote, From Enlightenment to Receptivity: Rethinking our Values, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 2013; “Philosophy’s Dirty Secret: What Virtue Epistemology Needs to Learn about Human
Irrationality”, forthcoming; and “Philosophical Sin”, forthcoming.
43
pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence are neither libertarians, nor egalitarians, but,
instead, conservatively act in discordance with the will to synthesis in contradicting (5).
The ninth claim of the system of dispute is a metametaphysical normative one: that
(9) The properly dogmatic and the pseudo non-dogmatic “subtle” violence are to
be avoided.
Those who express either of one of these two kinds of “subtle” violence, I highlight, are
this dissertation’s deep opponents as opposed to merely superficial ones. I assume that x is
a deep opponent regarding y if and only if x and y are others regarding one another and
disagree regarding the practices that are to be endorsed in the first place. More directly,
they disagree on how one is to spend the time of one’s life. Hence, this dissertation’s deep
opponents are those who are my others and express either one of the two kinds of “subtle”
violence, while making it very hard for me to engage myself in the very task of articulating
the system of disputes, say, those who, practically speaking, are unwilling to accept into a
graduate program, invite to give a talk, hire as a faculty member and/or publish someone
who aims to articulates this system. I underline that the notion of a deep opponent is closely
connected, but distinct from that of other. Consider that one of my others is a Chinese
philosopher who contradicts any claim or criterion endorsed here; someone who has been
educated and worked in China, while reacting mainly to Confucius and those influenced
by him, whose views, unfortunately, I currently ignore and do not have the proper
education to address. Imagine, though, that this Chinese philosopher is not my deep
opponent in that: his practices do not run in tension with mine; he does not pressure me to
cease to do philosophy as I aim to do; and I also do not pressure him do drop his practices.
44
I take that x is a superficial opponent regarding y if and only if x and y agree on the
practice of engaging themselves on a certain dispute, while holding conflicting claims on
the dispute at stake. Consider two physicalist-driven philosophers, say, Nagel and
Dennett. 59 They are superficial opponents of one another. While theoretically disagreeing
on the existence of consciousness, they have practically agreed on the practice of pursuing
this discussion in the first place. Deep opponents of both Nagel and Dennett are those who
are others regarding these philosophers and oppose the very practice of spending a
considerable amount of one’s life in discussing the existence of consciousness. I emphasize
that this dissertation is focused on my deep opponents; not on the superficial ones.
I make cases for the tenth, eleventh and twelfth claims of my system by applying
Gilles Deleuze’s particular method of reading (his “immaculate conception”) to Deleuze’s
works themselves. 60 This method of reading is that of: on the one hand, using the author’s
writings as evidence to support exegetical claims while, on the other hand, making
problematic interpretative moves. Examples of such problematic moves are: to translate
the author’s terminology to a distinct terminology the author never adopted; to justify these
translated claims in manners the author never openly embraced; to connect passages by the
author that are not obviously connected to one another; to spell out the author’s view on
disputes the author never explicitly approached; etc. The tenth and eleventh claims of my
system are both metametaphysical normative ones. Respectively, they run as follows:
(10)
A left-wing political practice of politicization that deals with micro-wars by
59
Thomas Nagel, “Dennett: Content and Consciousness” and “Dennett: Consciousness Dissolved”, in Other
Minds: Critical Essays 1969-1994, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995; and Daniel Dennett, “Quining
Qualia” and Consciousness Explained.
60
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic” in Negotiations, 1972-1990, trans. Martin Joughin, New York,
Columbia University, 1995.
45
avoiding the properly dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle”
violence is to be pursued as an alternative to the right-wing allegedly
apolitical approach.
(11)
The left-wing political practice of politicization is to be prudently pursued
in a metamodernist way as opposed to a modernist way.
The twelfth claim is the descriptive metametaphysical claim that
(12)
This very dissertation illustrates how one can do so.
A modernist way of pursing the left-wing practice of politicization is one that presupposes
that philosophers are to: rely on alternative uses of language; impersonate their others in
their writings; and point toward a new context, say, one in which all persons would
understand their others to be part of a really universal conflictual community as opposed
to threats to merely particular communities. In seeking to do so, modernist philosophers
aim to self-defend themselves from opponents (e.g., right-wingers) in pressuring them to
think and act differently. Modernist philosophers may also go as far as shocking or
embarrassing their opponents. “Shock” is a term used here in the sense of the feeling of
being deeply offended by someone or something that disrespected something that one
values deeply, such as a statue that represents one’s historical heritage; a criterion to deal
with disputes, such as accordance with one’s intuition; a reading of a respected author; etc.
“Embarrassment” is applied in the sense of an attenuated kind of shock: the feeling of being
upset by someone or something that disrespected something that one values deeply.
By a metamodernist way of pursing the left-wing practice of politicization, it is to
be understood one that: identifies that the modernist assumptions have become widely
shared norms (especially among philosophers influenced by Nietzsche, such as Foucault,
Derrida and Deleuze himself); problematizes the modernist assumptions in spelling that
46
those who take them for granted today face the risk of proceeding as inverted right-wingers
who privilege their needs for self-defense over their powers to show empathy toward those
who ignore the modernists assumptions or norms of political correctness; and paradoxically
still satisfies the modernist assumptions. As it will be indicated throughout this dissertation,
metamodernist philosophers may likewise shock or embarrass opponents of theirs.
The system of disputes’ last claim is also a metametaphysical descriptive one:
(13)
Disputes have an incommensurable greatness.
I claim that disputes have a greatness in the sense that, since immemorial times, persons
have deeply cared about disputes in being strongly emotionally compelled to spend a
considerable amount of their lives’ times in addressing disputes. This greatness is
incommensurable because no common unit of measurement to quantify over it seems
obtainable, that is, it seems impossible to measure persons’ overall “amount” of emotions
and/or time spent in dealing with disputes. 61 Now I would like to use all sorts of imperfect
justificatory resources to back up (3) through (13). More precisely, in the second chapter,
I deal with (3). I establish (4) and (5) in the third chapter. (6) is supported in the fourth
chapter. Cases for (7), (8) and (9) are to be found in the fifth chapter. In the sixth chapter,
I would like to argue for (10), (11) and (12). Finally, the seventh chapter, that is, this
dissertation’s conclusion spells out reasons for (13) as well as for taking that the
conjunction of all the claims of the system of disputes with my cases for them further justify
the two claims already introductorily defended in this introduction, that is, (1) and (2).
61
I will always apply the term “incommensurable” in the stated sense. There have been, however, several
other uses of such term and of other terms closely related to it, such as “incommensurability”. I cannot address
this issue here. For such a research, see Ruth Chang, “Incommensurability (and Incomparability)”, in Hugh
LaFollette (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics, New Jersey, Wiley-Blackwell, 2013: pp. 2591-2604.
CHAPTER 2
OVERCOMING METAMETAPHYSICS: NIETZSCHE AND CARNAP 62
2.1 The Climate of Animosity
A core feature of twentieth-century philosophy, as the introduction already
indicated, was a climate of animosity between the practitioners of what appear to be two
considerably distinct kinds of philosophy: so-called “continental philosophy” and so-called
“analytic philosophy.” Hence, contemporary continental and analytic philosophers have
constantly been deep opponents of one another, that is, they have, to say the least, disagreed
on which disputes are to be pursued in the first place. Friedrich Nietzsche is considered a
key figure of continental philosophy, while Rudolf Carnap is widely regarded as one of the
main representatives of analytic philosophy. Accordingly, as the next chapter aims to show,
continental philosophers, such as Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida, have been
influenced by Nietzsche but practically ignored Carnap. On the other hand, many analytic
philosophers have not paid much attention to Nietzsche. Instead, they have developed their
projects in the light of Carnap’s, even when they do not explicitly state so. This is the case,
as the next chapter also aims to show, with David Lewis and Peter van Inwagen. It is
therefore not surprising that work connecting Nietzsche and Carnap is largely lacking.
As such, it is also not surprising that there is a widely shared assumption that
Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s projects of overcoming metaphysics have little in common, even
though this assumption is rarely examined in detail. The reading supported here is that
Nietzsche’s project and Carnap’s, indeed, are quite distinct from one another insofar as
they champion contrasting reactions to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have
62
This chapter is an expanded version of an article of mine. See Felipe G. A. Moreira, “Overcoming
Metametaphysics: Nietzsche and Carnap”, Nietzsche-Studien, Volume 47, Issue 1, Nov. 2018: pp. 240-271.
47
48
been engaged in disputes. Nietzsche relies on a presupposition: that one is to react to the
stated fact by, theoretically speaking, defending claims that are to provoke dissensus,
while, practically speaking, resisting egalitarian practices and promoting libertarian ones.
As stated in the introduction, an egalitarian practice is one that privileges one’s
communitarian tendencies over one’s individualistic tendencies. In Nietzsche’s words,
these tendencies are “herd instincts” and “instincts for the wild”, respectively. 63
I appeal to textual evidence in imperfectly justifying all my exegetical claims about
Nietzsche and Carnap. This includes the exegetical claim that the former presupposes that
one is to defend claims that provoke dissensus. This exegetical claim is backed up by
textual evidence that indicates that Nietzsche takes consensus to lack value. Hence, the
“philosophers of the future” are not even to aim at reaching such consensus. 64 Note that
were all persons to do so, perhaps, disputes would disappear insofar as no one would
attempt to convince anyone else of one’s claims. Indeed, Nietzsche goes as far as implying
that philosophers of the future would not even care about what their opponents think about
their views. In Nietzsche’s words: “‘my judgment is my judgment: other people don’t have
an obvious right to it too’ —perhaps this is what such a philosopher of the future will
say”. 65 Nietzsche also states that “we must do away with the bad taste of wanting to be in
agreement with the majority”. 66 This would be because “‘good’ is no longer good when it
comes from your neighbor’s mouth. And how could there ever be a ‘common good’! The
term is self-contradictory: whatever can be common will never have much value”. 67
63
BGE 202 and GM II 16, respectively.
BGE 42, 44, 210.
65
BGE 43.
66
Ibid.
67
Ibid.
64
49
Nietzsche concludes, then, that, “in the end, it has to be as it is and has always been: great
things are left for the great, abysses for the profound, delicacy and trembling for the subtle,
and, all in all, everything rare for those who are rare themselves”. 68
My reading, then, is that Nietzsche also presupposes that one is to resist egalitarian
practices and promote libertarian ones. Consider Nietzsche’s take on “socialist fools and
nitwits”. 69 The latter, he claims, are engaged in a “brutalizing process of turning humanity
into stunted little animals with equal rights and equal claims”. 70 Nietzsche also describes
the statement “equal rights for everyone” as a “poisonous doctrine”. 71 He likewise
criticizes the constrains that communities place upon persons. Indeed, a person would be a
“prisoner” in a community. 72 This is because communities would be herds comparable to
prisons insofar as they would not allow one to act in accordance with one’s individualistic
tendencies. Ultimately, herds would oppress such tendencies. In Nietzsche’s words,
Those terrible bulwarks with which state organizations protected themselves against the
old instincts of freedom —punishments are a primary instance of this kind of bulkwark —
had the result that all those instincts of the wild, free, roving man were turned backwards,
against man himself”. 73
It follows that, for Nietzsche, a herd would be a “declaration of war against all the
old instincts on which, up till then, [one’s] strength, pleasure and formidableness had been
based”. 74 It also follows that Nietzsche describes himself as “warlike by nature” in the
particular sense of someone who promotes libertarian practices that do or at least seek to
68
Ibid.
BGE 203.
70
Ibid.
71
BGE 203.
72
GM II 16.
73
Ibid.
74
Ibid.
69
50
do justice to such old instincts. 75 No similar move can be found in Carnap’s works. In fact,
consider his 1963 Intellectual Autobiography. In this work, Carnap explicitly underlines
that, after serving in the German forces during World War I, he ceased to be “uninterested
and ignorant in political matters”. 76 It was then that his “political thinking” became
“pacifist, anti-militarist, anti-monarchist, perhaps also socialist”. 77 Carnap also goes as far
as stating that “all of us in the [Vienna] Circle were strongly interested in social and
political progress. Most of us, myself included, were socialists”. 78
Regardless of the Vienna Circle’s influence in contemporary analytic philosophy,
this last passage points to a striking difference between the circle’s members and several
(if not most) contemporary analytic philosophers, such as Willard Van Orman Quine, Saul
Kripke and Kit Fine. The latter (at least in their writings) have been neither strongly
interested in social and political progress, nor called themselves socialists. 79 The
importance of this point will be spelled out in the fifth chapter. For now, I emphasize that
Carnap (especially in his works from the 1920s to the 1930s focused on here) contradicts
Nietzsche in relying on a distinct presupposition: that one is to react to the fact that, since
75
EH I 7.
IAB 9.
77
Ibid.
78
IAB 22.
79
The same can be stated about several contemporary analytic philosophers who describe themselves as
being inspired by Carnap. See, for example, David Chalmers, “Ontological Anti-Realism”, in David
Chalmers (ed.), David Manley (ed.) and Ryan Wasserman (ed.), Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2009; Huw Price, “Metaphysics After Carnap: The Ghost Who Walks?”, in David Chalmers
(ed.), David Manley (ed.) and Ryan Wasserman (ed.), Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
2009; Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance and Realism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011; and Amie L.
Thomasson, Ontology Made Easy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2015. Note that these philosophers have
all focused on the 1950s Carnap, especially in Rudolf Carnap, “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology”, Revue
Internationale de Philosophie Vol 4, 1950: pp. 20-40. A revised version of this paper is: Rudolf Carnap,
“Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology”, in Meaning and Necessity: A Study of Semantics and Modal Logic,
Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1956. For a discussion of the differences between these versions, see
Susan Haack, “Some Preliminaries to Ontology”, Journal of Philosophical Logic Vol. 5, Issue 4, 1976: pp.
457-474. For a case for the claim that Eli Hirsch’s deflationism is less persuasive that of the 1950s Carnap,
see my own Felipe G. A. Moreira, “An Apology of Carnap”, Manuscrito (Unicamp), Vol 37, Número 2,
2014: pp.261-289.
76
51
immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes by, theoretically speaking,
defending claims regarding which consensus is to be reached; while doing so, one is to,
practically speaking, resist libertarian practices and promote egalitarian ones.
Carnap presupposes that one is to defend claims on which consensus is to be
reached in that his works contain passages, like the following one from his autobiography:
Even in the pre-Vienna period, most of the controversies in traditional metaphysics
appeared to me sterile and useless. When I compared this kind of argumentation with
investigations and discussions in empirical science or in the logical analysis of language, I
was often struck by the vagueness of the concepts used and by the inconclusive nature of
the arguments. I was depressed by disputations in which the opponents talked at cross
purposes; there seemed hardly any chance of mutual understanding, let alone of agreement,
because there was not even a common criterion for deciding the controversy. 80
This passage suggests that Carnap was depressed with practices held by philosophers, or,
more narrowly, “metaphysicians” in a properly Carnapian sense that will be spelled out in
what follows. These practices, he insinuates, would be less valuable than those of empirical
scientists and logicians. The reason would be that the two latter ones would have more
often reached consensus among one another. Hence, Carnap implies that philosophers are
to attempt to be more similar to empirical scientists and logicians, that is, they are to seek
to reach consensus with one another, instead of relying on distinct incompatible criteria to
deal with disputes. As Carnap states in his 1928 Der logische Aufbau der Welt: “in
philosophy we witness the spectacle (which must be depressing to a person of scientific
orientation) that one after another and side by side a multiplicity of incompatible
philosophical systems is erected”. 81 Thus, Carnap might have been suspicious of this very
dissertation’s aim of articulating a system of disputes. The same can be stated about
Nietzsche who states: “I distrust all systematizers and avoid them. The will to a system is
80
81
IAB 44-45.
LSW xvii.
52
a lack of integrity.” 82 In the next chapter, yet, I indicate how the system of disputes still
does justice to both Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s project of overcoming of metaphysics.
For the time being, though, I emphasize that Carnap, practically speaking, also
resists libertarian practices and promotes egalitarian ones. He associated libertarian
practices to, among others, philosophers themselves who erect the aforementioned
“incompatible philosophical systems” and, as it will be made explicit in what follows, to
Nazi-like politicians. 83 Such libertarian practices would be “sterile and useless” for they
would not contribute to the creation of a really universal community. Therefore, instead of
articulating unique views of their own, like Nietzsche suggests, Carnap argues that
philosophers are to contribute to a common effort. That Carnap is committed to this
practice is indicated by the fact that the 1929 Vienna Circle’s manifesto —The Scientific
Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle —puts the “emphasis on collective efforts”. 84
Indeed, this manifesto itself is the result of one of such efforts, bringing together
Carnap, the other two authors who signed the manifesto, Hans Hahn and Otto Neurath, and
further members of the Vienna Circle, such as Herbert Feigl, Friedrich Waismann, and
Philipp Frank, who also contributed to its writing. 85 This manifesto champions a
“specifically scientific attitude”. 86 The focus of this attitude is on defending that “‘what
82
TI I 26. Note that, nevertheless, some of Nietzsche’s interpreters have claimed that Nietzsche himself
implicitly articulated a system. See, for example, Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, New York,
Columbia University Press, 1983; and John Richardson, Nietzsche’s System, Oxford, Oxford University Press
1996.
83
See, especially, LOG.
84
Rudolf Carnap, Hans Hahn and Otto Neurath, “Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis [The
Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle]”, in Otto Neurath, Marie Neurath (ed.) and Robert
S. Cohen (ed.), Empiricism and Sociology, Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1973: pp. 306.
85
For a detailed discussion of the roles that each of the philosophers mentioned played in the development
of the Vienna Circle’s Manifesto, see Thomas Uebel, “On the Production, History, and Aspects of the
Reception of the Vienna Circle's Manifesto”, Perspectives on Science Volume 16, Number 1, Spring 2008:
pp. 70-102.
86
Rudolf Carnap, Hans Hahn and Otto Neurath, “Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung”, pp. 304.
53
can be said at all, can be said clearly’ (Wittgenstein),” and “if there are differences of
opinion, it is in the end possible to agree, and therefore agreement is demanded”. 87 I read
this passage as Carnap’s way of promoting the practice of at least attempting to make
dissensus among philosophers decrease. This is to state that Carnap aims, as he indicated
in his 1934 “On the Character of Philosophic Problems”, to make “philosophical conflict”
or “philosophical combat” disappear. 88 One way to achieve this would be by adopting a
use of language with greater clarity than conventional language.
Hence, it seems against this background that it would be uninteresting to explore
the connections between Nietzsche and Carnap; that it would be much more pertinent to
deal with these figures separately, as most of Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s readers have done
throughout the 20th century and even today. Three reasons make me resist this conclusion.
The first reason, as it will be spelled out in detail, is the textual evidence that Carnap read
and sometimes even held a positive view of Nietzsche’s writings. Given the influence that
Carnap and Nietzsche have had on 20th century as well as in contemporary philosophy, I
tend to go as far as believing that this textual evidence already provides sufficient
justification for an inquiry that connects the views of these two philosophers.
The second reason for not separating Nietzsche and Carnap is that Neurath
explicitly claimed that “Nietzsche and his critique of the metaphysicians took an active part
in the flourishing of the Vienna School”. 89 There is also a third reason for resisting the
assumption that it is not worth comparing Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s views: despite the
87
Ibid.
Rudolf Carnap, “On the Character of Philosophic Problems”, trans., William M. Malisoff, Philosophy of
Science Vol 1, No. 1, Jan., 1934: pp. 15 and 16, respectively.
89
Otto Neurath, Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische, Vienna, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1981:
pp. 652.
88
54
differences mentioned above, and several others that will be discussed later, some scholars,
over the last twenty five years or so, have indicated that Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s
conceptions of philosophy are marked by significant similarities.
According to Steven D. Hales, Nietzsche and Carnap “are interested in undermining
metaphysics, both think that there is something wrong with ordinary language that leads us
into error, both consider metaphysics to be ‘not yet science’ (TI III 3), and both prefer
historical and empirical analyses to metaphysical speculation”. 90 Along similar lines
Michael Friedman stated that “it is possible that Carnap, too, made a connection between
‘overcoming metaphysics’ and Nietzsche”. 91 Moreover, Gottfried Gabriel observes that
“with Carnap, so to speak, Frege’s Begriffsschrift lies on the desk and Nietzsche’s
Zarathustra on the bedside table”. 92 Abraham Stone “carefully” speculates that “Carnap’s
statement that the ‘future belongs to our attitude’ [might be one of] Nietzschean rational
faith” 93. On his part, Carl Sachs claims that “Carnap appeals to Nietzsche as anticipating,
though no doubt in a confused form (because lacking the tools of modern logic), the
overcoming of metaphysics that has finally become possible with logical empiricism”. 94
Finally, Thomas Mormann goes as far as defending that “Nietzsche influenced
considerably [Carnap’s] thought-style and even the content of his philosophizing”. 95
90
Steven D. Hales, “Nietzsche on Logic”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. 56, No. 4,1996:
pp. 828.
91
Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways, Illinois, Open Court, 2000: pp. 23.
92
Gottfried Gabriel, “Carnap’s ‘Elimination of metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language’: A
Retrospective Consideration of the Relationship between Continental and Analytic Philosophy”, in Paolo
Parrini (ed.), Wesley C. Salmon (ed.), Merrilee H. Salmon (ed.), Logical Empiricism: Historical and
Contemporary Perspectives, Pennsylvania, University of Pittsburgh Press, 2003: pp. 36.
93
Abraham D. Stone, “Heidegger and Carnap on the Overcoming of Metaphysics”, in Stephen Mulhall,
Martin Heidegger, London, Ashgate Publishing, 2006: pp. 232.
94
Carl B. Sachs, “What is to be Overcome? Nietzsche, Carnap, and Modernism as the Overcoming of
Metaphysics”, History of Philosophy Quarterly Vol 28, Issue 3, 2011: pp. 312.
95
Thomas Mormann, “Carnap’s Boundless Ocean of Unlimited Possibilities: Between Enlightenment and
Romanticism”, in Pierre Wagner (ed.), Carnap’s Ideal of Explication and Naturalism, New York, Palgrave
Macmillan, 2012: pp. 72.
55
If the remarks above are correct, and I am inclined to assume that they are, we are
faced with a question that has not received much attention: can we articulate a persuasive
reading of Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s views on metaphysics which does not ignore their
obvious differences, while spelling out their underlying similarities? This chapter aims to
back up a positive answer. I do so by articulating an interpretation according to which:
(3) Nietzsche and Carnap, as indicated above, champion contrasting reactions to
the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.
While doing so, they both endorse, but interpret differently an overcoming
metametaphysics characterized by three metametaphysical normative claims:
(3-i)
An overcoming of metaphysics is to be performed.
(3-ii)
This overcoming is to be performed by adopting a method of
linguistic analysis that is suspicious of the metaphysical use of
language and interprets such use through a different use of language
that aims to avoid metaphysics.
(3-iii)
This overcoming is to contribute to the political task of resisting
“diseased” metaphysical practices and promoting “healthy” nonmetaphysical ones.
This is, as stated in the introduction, the system of disputes’ third claim. Now let me explain
what I mean and seek to imperfectly back this claim up throughout the rest of this chapter.
2.2
The Overcoming of Metaphysics
“For me personally”, Carnap states in his Intellectual Autobiography,
“Wittgenstein was perhaps the philosopher who, besides Russell and Frege, had the
greatest influence on my thinking”. 96 That Carnap never mentions Nietzsche as one of his
influences can be explained by the context of his autobiography. Carnap moved to the
United States in 1935, and he was still alive there when his autobiography was published
96
IAB 25.
56
in 1963. During the 1950s, “McCarthyism”—the persecution of anything deemed “antiAmerican” and “subversive” by Senator Joseph McCarthy through congressional hearings
and FBI investigations—marked intellectual life throughout the United States. George A.
Reisch showed that the influence of this policy of intellectual oppression on American
philosophy departments cannot be underestimated. Such policy, Reisch argues, contributed
to “the decline in North American of so-called public intellectuals and the growth of
research universities as the main institutions of intellectual life in North America”. 97
Note that, distinct from the Vienna circle members and others, such as Charles W.
Morris, those educated and/or employed by such institutions (especially in analytic
philosophy departments) have often taken themselves to be politically neutral. As Reisch
indicates, this may have been one of the very reasons for why the latter’s careers have
flourished, whereas that of philosophers, such as Neurath, Frank and Morris, “suffered […]
a professional decline in the decades after the war”. 98 For complex reasons that I cannot
approach here, Carnap’s career did not suffer such decline. Indeed, despite his stated
socialist inclinations, he was often depicted “as a professional, apolitical philosopher
during and after the Cold War”. 99 Yet, around 1954-1955, Carnap himself was investigated
by the FBI under the pretense that he was engaged in “subversive political activity”. 100
The fact that these investigations even occurred made Carus conclude that “Carnap
was careful not to associate his academic works with anything that might attract
unwelcome attention from authorities or university administrations”. 101 As Gabriel also
97
George A. Reisch, How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: to the Icy Slopes of Logic,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005: pp. 369.
98
Ibid., pp. 382.
99
Ibid., pp. 369.
100
Ibid., pp. 274.
101
A. W. Carus, Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press 2007: pp. 36.
57
emphasizes, it is very likely that Carnap felt the need to adapt his work to the new
philosophical context in which he had adhered. 102 From the 1930s to the 1960s, most
American philosophers were not familiar with Nietzsche’s works. In fact, many American
philosophers might have associated Nietzsche with some sort of transgressive thinking
and/or Nazism. 103 Therefore, it is plausible to assume that Carnap felt that to mention
Nietzsche in this American context would be problematic if not outright offensive.
Before his immigration, Carnap refers positively to Nietzsche in two of his
published works. The first is his 1928 Der logische Aufbau der Welt, where Carnap
mentions Nietzsche’s name three times. First, Carnap agrees with “Nietzsche [Wille]
§§276, 309, 367 ff.” that the “self is not implicit in the original data of cognition” and he
goes as far as quoting and endorsing the following passage of what was then assumed to
be Nietzsche’s book The Will to Power: “it is merely a formulation of our grammatical
habits that there must always be something that thinks when there is thinking and that there
must always be a doer when there is a deed”. 104 Second, Carnap endorses and quotes a
passage by Wilhelm Schuppe: “‘the thinking of the individual begins with total impression
[that is, a conjunction of several sensations] which only reflection analyses into their simple
102
Gottfried Gabriel, “Carnap’s ‘Elimination of metaphysics”, pp. 56.
To dissociate Nietzsche from Nazism was one of the main aims of Walter Kaufmann Nietzsche:
Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1950. This work gave rise to
the English-speaking tradition of Nietzsche scholarship. For a discussion of Nietzsche’s reception in this
American context, see Jennifer Ratner-Rosenhagen, American Nietzsche: A History of an Icon and His Ideas,
Chicago, Chicago University Press, 2012: pp. 219-62.
104
LSW 105. The passage Carnap refers to can be found in Nachlass 1887, KSA 10 [58] as well as in WP
477. Note that The Will to Power was edited by Nietzsche’s sister, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche. She put
together several of Nietzsche’s fragments by relying on one of the plans that he left for a work which was
supposed to be entitled “The Will to Power.” Elisabeth organized two editions of the book. The first is from
1901, and has 483 fragments. The second is from 1906; it contains 1067 fragments. It is hard to determine
which one of the two versions Carnap read (if any). This is because, in the bibliography to Der logische
Aufbau der Welt, Carnap cites Nietzsche’s book as having been published in 1887. Carnap’s references to
Nietzsche can be found on pages 105, 108 and 261 of the latest English edition of the Aufbau released in
2003. According to Mormann, Carnap used a “rather apocryphal edition of Nietzsche’s The Will to Power
(edited by Max Brahn)”. See Thomas Mormann, “Carnap’s Boundless Ocean”, pp. 73.
103
58
elements [e.g., a particular visual sensation]’”. 105 Carnap claims that Hans Cornelius
endorsed this view and took “Nietzsche” to be a predecessor of it. 106
Third, Carnap objects to Descartes that the “sum does not follow from the cogito;
it does not follow from ‘I experience’ that I am’, but only that an experience is”. 107 “A
similar denial of [the self’s] activity in the original [experiential] state of affairs,” Carnap
states, “is found in Nietzsche [Wille] §§304, 309”. 108 I agree with Carnap’s reading of
Nietzsche here. Nietzsche, indeed, claims that “people are following grammatical habits
[…] in drawing conclusions, reasoning that ‘thinking is an activity, behind every activity
something is active, therefore’”. 109 “It is”, Nietzsche concludes, “a falsification of the facts
to say that the subject ‘I’ is the condition of the predicate ‘think’”. 110
The second published work in which Carnap mentions Nietzsche is the one that the
champions of the interpretative tendency have focused on, Carnap’s 1931 “Überwindung
der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache” (henceforth, “Überwindung der
Metaphysik”). 111 My reading also focuses on this piece, whose conclusion is that:
Our conjecture that metaphysics is a substitute, albeit an inadequate one, for art, seems to
be further confirmed by the fact that the metaphysician who perhaps had artistic talent to
the highest degree, viz. Nietzsche, almost entirely avoided the error of that confusion. A
large part of his work has predominantly empirical content. We find there, for instance,
historical analyses of specific artistic phenomena, or an historical psychological analysis
of morals. In the work, however, in which he expresses most strongly that which others
express through metaphysics or ethics, in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, he does not choose the
misleading theoretical form, but openly the form of art, of poetry. 112
105
LSW 108.
Ibid.
107
Ibid., 261.
108
Ibid.
109
BGE 17.
110
Ibid.
111
Rudolf Carnap, “Überwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache”, Erkenntnis Vol 2,
1931: pp. 219-241.
112
EML 80.
106
59
Nietzsche, Carnap claims, is a metaphysician. Nonetheless, he would have been
significantly different from other metaphysicians, such as “Fichte, Schelling, Hegel,
Bergson [and] Heidegger”. 113 In contrast to the latter, Carnap claims that Nietzsche would
have often adopted two non-metaphysical procedures––an empirical procedure and an
explicitly poetic procedure that can be found in his Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
Moreover, Nietzsche would have practically never made a move that Carnap
associates with the other metaphysicians named in the last paragraph—that of confounding
the roles of metaphysics and poetry; “Nietzsche clearly separates the two [Nietzsche hat
beides deutlich getrennt]”. 114 The latter quote is from an unpublished manuscript by
Carnap entitled Lectures in Europe (Items 18-29). In this text, Carnap’s notes to
“Überwindung der Metaphysik” can be found. In his unpublished manuscripts, Carnap
refers to Nietzsche at other occasions. I will return to these manuscripts later.
For now, let me commit myself to the following disjunction: either the conclusion
of “Überwindung der Metaphysik” is evidence that, in adopting an egalitarian practice,
Carnap aimed to spell out agreements between his own position and that of an opponent
(that is, Nietzsche) 115, or this conclusion is Carnap’s way of insinuating that Nietzsche was
indeed one of his influences after all. The latter option, suggested by Sachs, becomes as
persuasive as the former as soon as we take into account that Carnap’s article is concerned
with the Überwindung of metaphysics. 116 The connections between Carnap’s philosophy,
113
Ibid.
Rudolf Carnap, “Lectures in Europe (Items 18-29)”, Unpublished Manuscript (1929-37), University of
Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: (RC110-07-21). Carnap’s manuscripts remain
unpublished and are held by the Archive of Scientific Philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh’s Hilman
Library. All translations are my own.
115
As Mormann claims, Carnap was “always engaged in the business of building bridges and finding ways
of reconciling apparently irreconcilable philosophical positions”. See Thomas Mormann, “Carnap’s
Boundless Ocean”, pp. 63.
116
See Carl B. Sachs, “What is to be Overcome?”. pp. 312.
114
60
on the one hand, and Kant and neo-Kantianism, on the other, have been pointed out by
many commentators. 117 Yet, “Überwindung” is not a word Kant or the neo-Kantians used
in the sense of overcoming metaphysics. Kant’s project is concerned with the limits, or the
very possibility of metaphysics, not its “Überwindung”. Most importantly, this word is
pervasive throughout and characteristic of Nietzsche’s works. Thus, given the textual
evidence that Carnap read Nietzsche, two conclusions become plausible: that Carnap was
aware of “Überwindung” as a distinctly Nietzschean term and that he aimed to (so to speak)
sound “Nietzschean” in using this term in the title of “Überwindung der Metaphysik”.
From 1870, when “Überwindung” appears for the first time in Nietzsche’s
notebooks, until 1889, when it is used for the last time in Ecce Homo, 109 is the number
of times Nietzsche uses this term. 118 These uses are more recurrent in the notebooks. I
cannot analyze all of them. What I do is to focus on a single passage from Nietzsche’s
notebooks in 1885. In this passage, he relies on the very same expression found in Carnap’s
article; “Überwindung of metaphysics”. 119 In spelling out what Nietzsche means by this
expression, and in highlighting his commitment to (3-i), (3-ii) and (3-iii), I will proceed by
connecting several passages of Nietzsche’s late phase. A coherent view of what Nietzsche
meant by “metaphysics” will be, then, outlined. This procedure is problematic. Yet, similar
ones have been adopted by many readers of Nietzsche. 120 One heuristic reason for this
117
See, for example, Alan W. Richardson, Carnap’s Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the
Emergence of Logical Empiricism, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1998; Michael Friedman,
Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999; and A. W. Carus, Carnap
and Twentieth-Century Thought.
118
See Nachlass 1870, KSA 5 [23]) as well as EH I 4.
119
Nachlass 1885, KSA 40 [65].
120
See, for example, Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as
Literature, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1985, Patrick Wotling, Nietzsche et le problème de la
civilisation, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1995, Wolfgang Müller-Lauter, Nietzsche: His
Philosophy of Contradictions and the Contradictions of His Philosophy, Illinois, University of Illinois Press,
61
approach has been emphasized by John Richardson: “the strongest kind of claim any single
reading [of Nietzsche] can plausibly make for itself [is] to pick one voice or aspect in
Nietzsche’s writings, and show how to see that voice as somehow dominant, somehow
trumping or subordinating the many other incompatible voices also there”. 121 The voice in
Nietzsche’s writings that I wish to focus on sometimes sounds proto-Carnapian.
Neither Carnap nor Nietzsche explicitly spell out the meaning of Überwindung.
Moreover, in his 1936 presentation of logical positivism for an English-speaking audience,
Language, Truth and Logic, A. J. Ayer translated Überwindung as “elimination”. 122 This
is also the word adopted in the only translation into English of Carnap’s “Überwindung der
Metaphysik”, the 1959 translation of Arthur Pap. On the other hand, “overcoming” is the
translation used by many recent interpreters of “Überwindung der Metaphysik” and by all
English translators of Nietzsche. I am inclined to agree that Überwindung is more
accurately translated by “overcoming” than by “elimination”, but I think the best
translation is not a single English word but a phrase: the challenging process of attempting
to triumph over an obstacle or an opponent. For the sake of consistency, though, I would
like to follow the standard use of “overcoming” as a translation of Überwindung.
It might seem that the remarks made in the previous paragraph are relevant only for
translators, but it is indeed the case that different translations of Überwindung as either
“overcoming” or “elimination” lead to radically different interpretations. Referring to
“elimination”, Ayer and Pap suggested that Carnap aimed to perform what might be called
an eradication of metaphysics. By this, I understand a relation that obtains whenever a
1999: John Richardson, Nietzsche’s System and John Richardson, Nietzsche’s New Darwinism, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2004; etc.
121
John Richardson, Nietzsche’s New Darwinism, pp. 9.
122
A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic, London, Dover Publication, 1936.
62
philosopher articulates a philosophical position that cannot be called metaphysical in any
sense whatsoever. Note that “metaphysics” is an extremely equivocal term. The same can
be stated about its cognates (e.g. “metaphysical”) and about expressions that contain the
term “metaphysics”, such as “overcoming of metaphysics.” What I wish to stress out is
that, since ancient Greek philosophy, several meanings have been associated with
“metaphysics,” among them: an inquiry into first principles, the science of being qua being,
an unscientific investigation that violates the conditions for cognitive experience, an
ideology comparable to religion that ultimately serves the interests of the dominant class,
a phallogocentric practice, etc. So, it seems that Carnap’s statement “there is no unanimity
whatever […] on what is meant by ‘metaphysics’” was as correct in 1928 as it is in 2019.123
More importantly, if Carnap aimed to perform an eradication of metaphysics, it
would be easy to object, following Hilary Putnam, that Carnap ultimately failed in his
attempt to formulate a philosophical project that has nothing in common with metaphysics
in any of its several senses. 124 Putnam seems to assume that Carnap used “metaphysics” in
the sense of an inquiry that articulates statements which violate the verification principle.
In Carnap’s “Überwindung der Metaphysik”, this principle is defined as follows: a word is
meaningful if and only if it is part of, or reducible to, the words contained in “protocol
sentences”. 125 So, a statement with words that violate this principle is a meaningless one.
Protocol sentences refer to what is immediately observable or verifiable. Carnap’s
“Überwindung der Metaphysik”, yet, is neutral with regard to the content and the form of
123
LSW 295.
Hilary Putnam, “Philosophers and Human Understanding,” in Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers
Vol 3, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981.
125
EML 63.
124
63
such protocol sentences. 126 As Putnam points out, several of the statements endorsed by
Carnap himself also violate the verification principle. 127 Indeed, this principle itself cannot
be verified so that Carnap’s project would still be “metaphysics” in Putnam’s sense.
Moreover, had Nietzsche been engaged in an eradication of metaphysics, a similar
objection could be raised against his position: that his project is a failure in that he aims,
but fails to articulate a philosophy that has no content in common with metaphysics in any
of its several senses. This is what Martin Heidegger means when he describes Nietzsche as
“the last metaphysician of the West”. 128 Consider the following statement by Nietzsche:
(NM) “The innermost essence of being is will to power”. 129
Heidegger uses the term “metaphysics” in the sense of an inquiry into Being. 130 I would
like to presuppose a reading according to which, for Heidegger, Being is an universal
identity, that is, one that is shared by all entities (e.g., human beings, animals, natural kinds,
artifacts, etc.) and ultimately characterizes them insofar as entities. I underline that I use
the term “entity” in a loose way that is to cover all sorts of beings, objects or things
philosophers have talked about, such as evil, a thing-in-itself and consciousness. 131
126
For a detailed account of Carnap’s view on protocol sentences, and of his dispute with Neurath, see
Thomas Uebel, “Reconstruction as Elucidation? Carnap in the Early Protocol Sentence Debate”, Synthese
Vol 93, No. 1 / 2, Carnap: A Centenary Reappraisal, Nov., 1992: pp. 107-140, A. W. Carus, Carnap and
Twentieth-Century Thought as well as George A. Reisch, How the Cold War.
127
For a discussion of this problem, see Rudolf Carnap, “On the Character of Philosophic Problems”. For a
detailed reply to Putnam’s objection on behalf of Carnap, see Thomas Ricketts, “Carnap’s principle of
tolerance, empiricism, and conventionalism”, in Bob Hale (ed.) and Peter Clark (ed.), Reading Putnam,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1994.
128
Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche: Volumes Three and Four, New York, Harper Collins, 1991: pp. 8. Also see
Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche: Volumes One and Two, New York, Harper Collins, 1991.
129
Nachlass 1888, KSA 14 [80].
130
Ibid.
131
In doing so, I remain neutral on whether there are specific conditions for the individuation of entities. For
a discussion of this matter, see Willard Van Orman Quine “Speaking of Objects”. Proceedings and Addresses
of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 31 (1957-1958): pp. 5-22.
64
Under Heidegger’s influence, I take that another feature of God-driven
philosophers is that they focus on the theoretical dispute over the claim that: Being is to
stand in some sort of non-causal relation with God. I would like to use the expression “some
sort of non-causal relation” as a schematic place holder for all kinds of relations described
by idioms, such as: identity idioms (e.g., “is identical to” or “is token or type identical to”);
semantic idioms (e.g., “has a meaning reducible to that of”); modal idioms (e.g., “could
not have existed if there was no”); epistemic idioms (e.g., “is conditioned by”); and
properly metaphysical idioms (e.g., “is the very principle of” or “participates in”).
Note that, when relying on such idioms, God-driven, human-driven and physicalistdriven philosophers have the burden of more precisely spelling what they mean by them.
On my part, this is not a task that I pursue in this dissertation. 132 It is also important to
notice that, if it is granted that evil exists, another theoretical dispute arises for God-driven
philosophers: namely, they have to explain how evil and God can coexist or, in other words,
they are to spell out how there can be evil if Being is to stand in some sort of non-causal
relation with God. Another characteristic of human-driven philosophers is that they focus
on a distinct theoretical dispute: that over the claim that Being is to stand in some sort of
non-causal relation with that which conditions human experience. Some purported
examples of such conditions are: Kant’s transcendental subject; struggle of classes; a
particularly human psychology or logos; language, history and culture; institutional power
relations; white supremacy; patriarchal gender oppression; etc. Moreover, consider that if
it is granted that a thing-in-itself exists, human-driven philosophers are to deal with another
132
For recent takes on properly metaphysical idioms, see Jessica M. Wilson, “Grounding-Based Formulations
of Physicalism”, Topoi 37, 2018; and Jonathan Schaffer, “Ground Rules: Lessons from Wilson”, in Kenneth
Aizawa (ed.) and Carl Gillet (ed.), Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground, London, Palgrave,
2016.
65
dispute: that of explaining the non-causal relation between such a thing-in-itself and that
which conditions human experience or, in other words, the dispute of spelling out how can
there be a thing-in-itself, if Being is some sort of non-causal relation with these conditions.
In addressing statements such as (NM), Heidegger interprets Nietzsche as doing
“metaphysics” in the Heideggerian sense. 133 Nietzsche, though, would not have understood
Being as God or as human-driven philosophers have done. Rather, Nietzsche would have
believed that, not only human beings have individualistic tendencies, but that Being is to
stand in some sort of non-causal relation with the ultimately individualistic will to power.
I am inclined to agree with Heidegger that this is, indeed, what (NM) indicates. The same
can be stated about the fact that Nietzsche calls the “will to power” the “essence of life”:
one that would be constituted by “spontaneous, aggressive, expansive, re-interpreting, redirecting and formative forces”. 134 Indeed, let me go as far as taking this passage as an
indication that Nietzsche was a human-yet-physicalist-driven philosopher.
This is because though he still associates Being to an apparently human factor, such
as a “will”, he calls such a will, one of power and describes power in terms of “forces”. In
doing so, Nietzsche somehow anticipates and points toward a distinct theoretical dispute
that 20th and 21st century physicalist-driven philosophers have privileged: that over the
claim that Being is to stand in some sort of non-causal relation with a neither divine, nor
properly human entity. The particles postulated by physics are examples of neither divine,
nor properly human entities. Furthermore, note that if the existence of consciousness is
133
For other readings that take Nietzsche to be doing “metaphysics” in senses closely related to, but not
exactly identical with Heidegger’s, see Peter Poellner, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 1995; and John Richardson, Nietzsche’s System. On the other hand, for readings that
dissociate Nietzsche’s project from “metaphysics” see Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature,
and Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990.
134
GM II 12. For detailed discussions of Nietzsche’s will to power, besides Heidegger’s books on Nietzsche,
see Peter Poellner, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, and John Richardson, Nietzsche’s System.
66
acknowledged, physicalist-driven philosophers run into the distinct theoretical dispute over
the non-causal relation that consciousness has with such entities. A more Heideggerian
way of articulating this dispute is by asking: how does consciousness exist if Being is some
sort of non-causal relation with neither divine, nor properly human entities, like particles?
It is not my aim, then, to put into question Heidegger’s view that Nietzsche
understood the will to power as Being. 135 Moreover, my goal is not to problematize
Putnam’s view that Carnap was himself committed to statements that violate the principle
of verification. What is crucial for this dissertation’s purposes is that even if Heidegger’s
and Putnam’s views are correct, Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s projects do not need to be read
as failures inasmuch as they aimed but failed to perform an eradication of metaphysics. It
is more persuasive to attribute both to Nietzsche and to Carnap the aim of performing what
may be called an overcoming of metaphysics. This is a relation that obtains whenever a
philosopher articulates a philosophy that seeks to have no content in common with
metaphysics in the specific sense of “metaphysics” adopted by this philosopher (as opposed
to any other sense of metaphysics that an interpreter attributes to the philosopher at stake).
This means that we can read Nietzsche’s project, on its own terms, as being
successful, since he aimed and succeed in performing an overcoming of metaphysics in the
sense that he uses the term. In short, Nietzsche does not use “metaphysics” in a
Heideggerian sense; rather, Nietzsche uses “metaphysics” in a Nietzschean sense, referring
to a set of claims first articulated by Socrates and/or Plato, such as the claims that “causal
135
As Friedman remarks, “in the mid to late 1930s, in connection with his work on Nietzsche and his
increasing concerning with technology, Heidegger began to use the expression ‘overcoming metaphysics’ to
characterize his own philosophical ambitions”. To discuss Heidegger’s overcoming, though, is not a task that
I can pursue in this dissertation. See Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways, pp. 23.
67
efficacy” exists, that the “will is a faculty”, and that the “I” is a “substance”. 136 It is not my
goal to discuss all of these claims. What I would like to do, instead, is to focus on three of
such claims that are particularly characteristic of metaphysics in Nietzsche’s sense of the
term. The first of these claims is that there are hierarchical oppositions of values.
In Nietzsche’s words, “the fundamental belief of metaphysicians is the belief in
oppositions of values”. 137 “Truth-error”, “the will to truth-the will to deception”, “selflessself-interest” and “wisdom-covetous leer” are some of the oppositions that Nietzsche has
in mind. 138 Metaphysicians would have assumed that the first term in the aforementioned
oppositions is more valuable than the second term. A second claim that would characterize
metaphysics is one that most contemporary analytic philosophers would associate with
epistemology, not metaphysics. The claim is that one is to pursue “certainty”.139
Metaphysicians would “prefer a handful of ‘certainty’ to an entire wagonload of pretty
possibilities”. 140 In fact, Nietzsche continues, “there might even be puritanical fanatics of
conscience who would rather lie dying on an assured nothing than an uncertain
something” 141. Although Nietzsche does not explicitly spell out what he means by
“certainty”, I would argue that he understands this as a phenomenon which occurs
whenever a claim does not require any further “support” in convincing even skeptics. 142
A third claim that would characterize metaphysics is that there is a “true world”.143
Nietzsche suggests that those who share this view embrace some sort of realism. Realism,
136
TI III 5.
BGE 2.
138
Ibid.
139
GS V 347, BGE 10.
140
BGE 10.
141
Ibid.
142
GS V 347.
143
EH P and TI IV.
137
68
in this respect, is the conjunction of two claims: there are entities, such as God or particles,
that are not conditioned by the stated examples of what conditions, and these entities or at
least some of their properties can be known by means of these conditions. A characteristic
that God-driven philosophers and most physicalist-driven philosophers share is that of
often presupposing realism. Nietzsche also speaks in terms of an “illusory world”. 144 With
this expression, it is not clear whether he refers to strong or to weak idealism. The former
is the claim that there are no entities that exist independently or that are not conditioned,
that is, this is the claim held by the likes of Johann Gottlieb Fichte that there is no thingin-itself. Weak idealism is the Kantian claim that though such things-in-themselves exist,
human beings cannot know them in themselves, but only conditionally. Note that another
feature of human-driven philosophers is that they often endorse strong or weak idealism.
It follows that Nietzsche’s overcoming of metaphysics may be read as the task of
practicing a philosophy that aims to put into question the three claims that he associates
with metaphysics. It also follows that my reading is that Nietzsche is committed to (3-i). I
claim that the same is the case with Carnap, even though he interprets this statement very
differently from Nietzsche. Indeed, my reading is that, like Nietzsche’s project, we may
read Carnap’s project as successful on its own terms. This is to state that he does not aim
to overcome what Nietzsche, Putnam or Heidegger calls “metaphysics”; rather, what
Carnap aims is to overcome what he himself calls “metaphysics”—a term that Carnap does
not use in the exact same sense in his 1928 Der logische Aufbau der Welt and in his 1957
remarks to “Überwindung der Metaphysik”, originally published in 1931.
144
TI IV.
69
“Metaphysics,” Carnap states in 1928, is “the result of a nonrational, purely
intuitive process”. 145 This is what I call the first Carnapian sense of metaphysics: Carnap
dissociates rationality from metaphysics in depicting it as an intuitive (emotional or
volitional) activity. For Carnap, “rational” is a term that mainly or, perhaps, exclusively
refers to the inquiries in the formal sciences —that is, logic and mathematics —and in the
empirical sciences. These inquiries would be theoretical ones that seek to answer what
Carnap calls in his 1934 “Theoretische Fragen und praktische Entscheidungen”
“theoretical questions”. 146 Two examples of such questions are: “Is 2 + 2= 4?” and “Are
spiders arthropodes?” Carnap’s view is that answers to theoretical questions have truthvalues. The same would not be the case with regard to practical questions.
Practical
questions
would
concern
what
Carnap
calls
“decisions
[Entscheidungen]”, such as the decision to adopt a certain empirical theory over another
one. 147 In his 1937 article “Logic”, Carnap spells outs three conditions for thinking to be
“logical” or “reasonable”: “clarity, consistency and adequacy to evidence”. 148
Metaphysicians—in the sense of philosophers who practice metaphysics in the first
Carnapian sense—would disrespect these conditions. This is because, in appealing to
irrational intuitions, they would rely on a considerably mysterious barely justificatory
resource, perhaps, comparable to those of taking oneself to be, like an Ancient Greek poet,
inspired by a muse; or purporting, like a prophet, to have a direct sensible access to God.
145
LSW 295.
Rudolf Carnap, “Theoretische Fragen und praktische Entscheidungen”, Natur und Geist, Dresden 2.
Jahrgang Nummer 9, September 1934: pp. 257-260.
147
Ibid., pp. 257.
148
LOG 108.
146
70
In the 1957 remarks to “Überwindung der Metaphysik”, Carnap attaches a second
meaning to metaphysics: that metaphysics is an inquiry which embraces a claim that most
contemporary analytic philosophers would also associate with epistemology, not with
metaphysics. The claim is that we can obtain a “knowledge of the essence of things which
transcends the realm of empirically founded, inductive science”. 149 Without providing
textual evidence, Carnap problematically attributes this claim to “Fichte, Schelling, Hegel,
Bergson [and] Heidegger”. 150 These philosophers are Carnap’s main targets; they would
be metaphysicians, since they would have practiced metaphysics in the first and in second
Carnapian senses. Carnap never precisely spells out what he means by an “essence”. This
is also a problematic move, given that this term, as it will be discussed in the fifth chapter,
has been traditionally applied in at least two senses: that of a necessary property, and that
of a real definition, that is, a definition that ultimately or properly characterizes what an
entity is. Regardless of which of these two senses or any other one Carnap had in mind
when using the term “essence”, my reading is that his article “Überwindung der
Metaphysik” is concerned with an overcoming of metaphysics, whose task is that of
problematizing a view purportedly shared by Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, Bergson and
Heidegger. The view is that they are engaged in a theoretical inquiry able to use irrational
intuitions to provide a sort of mysterious knowledge of the essence of things; a sort of
mysterious knowledge that would be neither mathematical nor empirical knowledge. 151
149
EML 80.
Ibid.
151
I am also inclined to follow Adrian W. Moore in believing that Carnap’s project strongly resembles
Hume’s: both describe metaphysics as falling short of standards of knowledge that only formal sciences
(mathematics and logic) and the empirical sciences could fulfill. See Adrian W. Moore, The Evolution of
Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012: pp. 279.
150
71
2.3
How Can an Overcoming of Metaphysics be Performed?
Nietzsche and Carnap implicitly answer the question of how to overcome
metaphysics by endorsing distinct readings of (3-ii), that is, in order to perform an
overcoming of metaphysics, one is to adopt a method of linguistic analysis. Note that to
endorse this method is not to embrace weak or strong idealism. Rather, it is to put into
question the very way philosophers in general —including human-driven philosophers
themselves —have articulated their views, while engaging themselves in disputes.
Three features characterize the method I have in mind. The first is an attitude of
suspicion concerning the metaphysical use of language. For Nietzsche, a metaphysical use
of language inclines one to accept claims that he takes to be particularly characteristic of
metaphysics. As indicated in the last section, Nietzsche sees the metaphysical use of
language as falling into the category of “grammatical habits”. 152 His aim is to step back
from such habits by not taking for granted the assumptions apparently implied by them. He
even goes as far as stating that his contemporaries still follow God-driven philosophers in
believing in God because their grammatical habits incline them to do so.
“I am afraid”, Nietzsche states in this sense, “that we have not got rid of God
because we still have faith in grammar”. 153 The previously mentioned passage from
Nietzsche quoted in Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt likewise indicates Nietzsche’s
commitment to the stated attitude of suspicion. Nietzsche suggests that philosophers have
been inclined to adopt assumptions about the self since grammar has seduced them to do
so. Nietzsche’s attitude of suspicion is likewise present in the preface to Beyond Good and
152
153
Nachlass 1887, KSA 10 [58], BGE 17.
TI III 5.
72
Evil, where he states the following: “what actually served as the cornerstone of those
sublime and unconditional philosophical edifices that the dogmatists used to build” might
have been “some word-play perhaps, [and] a seduction [Verführung] of grammar”. 154
A similar insight lies at the very core of Carnap’s project. Consider:
(PS-i) Caesar is a prime number.
Carnap addresses this statement by arguing that “the fact that the rules of grammatical
syntax are not violated easily seduces [verführt] one at first glance into the erroneous
opinion that one still has to do with a statement, albeit a false one”. 155 Metaphysicians
would also have fallen prey to a similar seduction while endorsing the metaphysical use of
language. For Carnap, such a use of language makes metaphysicians inclined to believe
that metaphysics is a theoretical rational process, and/or that metaphysics is able to provide
a mysterious knowledge of the essence of things that is neither mathematical nor empirical.
This helps explain why metaphysicians make claims, such as the following one presented
in Heidegger’s 1929 lecture “What is Metaphysics?”:
(PS-ii) “The nothing nothings”. 156
The second feature that the analysis of language has to possess in order to overcome
metaphysics is a collection of the metaphysical uses of language. The aim of this collection
154
BGE P.
EML 68. For an objection to Carnap’s interpretation of (PS-i) as meaningless, see Elisabeth Camp, “The
Generality Constraint and Categorical Restrictions”, Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 54, No. 215, April 2004:
pp. 209-231.
156
This is how Arthur Pap translates the sentence “Das Nichts nichtet”. See Rudolf Carnap, “Überwindung
der Metaphysik”, pp. 230 as well as EML 70. Heidegger’s sentence itself is “Das Nichts selbst nichtet”. See
Martin Heidegger, “Was ist Metaphysik?”, in Gesamtausgabe: I. Abteilung: Veröffentlichte Schriften 19141970 Band 9 Wegmarken, Frankfurt, Vittorio Klostermann, 1976: pp. 114. Also consider Martin Heidegger,
“What is Metaphysics?”, trans. David Farrel Krell, in David Farrel Krell (ed.), Basic Writings, New York,
Harper Collins Publishers, 1993.
155
73
is to indicate the particularity that makes metaphysical language seductive in the first place.
Nietzsche fulfills this aim by emphasizing that metaphysicians have relied on terms, such
as: “Being, the Unconditioned, the Good, the True, [and] the Perfect”. 157 On his part,
Carnap collects the following “specifically metaphysical terms” in order to spell out the
particular nature of metaphysical language: “‘the Idea’, ‘the Absolute’, ‘the
Unconditioned’, ‘the Infinite’, ‘the being of being’, ‘non-being’, ‘thing in itself’, ‘absolute
spirit’”, etc. 158 I emphasize that, as indicated above, in Carnap’s article “Überwindung der
Metaphysik”, Nietzsche himself is depicted as a “metaphysician”. 159 This may be
interpreted as suggesting that Carnap believed that Nietzsche also relied on metaphysical
terms; the “will to power” is an example that Carnap might have had in mind. Nevertheless,
Carnap never explicitly states which statements by Nietzsche, if any, are metaphysical in
the first and/or second Carnapian sense, and it is therefore hard to understand how Carnap
would have read a statement, such as (NM). I will not speculate on this matter here.
Instead, I am going to emphasize what is explicit: in the conclusion of
“Überwindung der Metaphysik”, Carnap claims that Nietzsche’s uses of language were
mostly either scientific or poetic. The scientific use would be characterized either by its
use of tautologies (as in a formal science, like logic or mathematics) or by its aim of
providing empirical knowledge (as in the empirical sciences). The following two
statements exemplify these two characteristics of the scientific use: respectively,
(S-i) 1+1 = 2
(S-ii) Spiders are arthropodes.
157
TI III 4.
EML 67.
159
Ibid., 80.
158
74
For Carnap, (S-i) is an analytic, a priori, and necessary statement, which belongs to the
formal sciences. (S-ii) would be a synthetic, a posteriori, and contingent statement, which
belongs to the empirical sciences. Carnap, then, endorses a dual picture of science. 160
Consider that statements that have the same features of (S-ii) are recurrent in
Nietzsche’s works. An example is the following statement from The Genealogy of Morals:
(NS) “The Romans were the strong”. 161
In contrast to the scientific use of language, the poetic use of language is characterized by
the aim to provide a special expression of emotions. Consider the following line by Arthur
Rimbaud: “L’étoile a pleuré rose au cœur de tes oreilles”. This verse can be translated to:
(P) The star has wept rose-colored in the heart of your ears.
Carnap reads Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra as an example of a poetic use of
language and he might have used the following as a particularly poignant example:
(NP) “The desert grows: woe to him who harbors deserts!” 162
The third and last feature that the analysis of language has to possess in order to
overcome metaphysics is an interpretation of the metaphysical uses of language by means
of another use whose aim is to avoid metaphysics. As indicated above, Nietzsche aims to
avoid metaphysics in the Nietzschean sense and, in order to achieve this, he relies on what
160
This is another reason for claiming Carnap’s project resembles Hume’s, as indicated by Adrian W. Moore,
The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things. Moreover, note that Carnap’s dual picture
of science is problematized by Willard Van Orman Quine, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, Philosophical
Review Vol 60, No 1, Jan 1951: pp. 20-43.
161
GM I 6.
162
Z III 16 [2].
75
might be called a medical-philosophical use of language. Carnap, on the other hand, seeks
to avoid metaphysics in the first and the second Carnapian senses. In order to do so,
however, he (perhaps, considerably surprisingly) interprets metaphysical uses of language
through a metalinguistic use of language that, not unlike Nietzsche, reads metaphysical
language as a symptom that metaphysicians are somehow sick, that is, self-delusional.
The main characteristic of Nietzsche’s medical-philosophical use of language is a
technical distinction between “health” (Gesundheit) and “sickness” (Krankheit). 163 While
health would be an individualistic tendency toward harmony, sickness would be a
communitarian tendency toward disharmony. Nietzsche also claims that an organism is
healthy whenever a “dominating passion” rules all others. 164 When this occurs, Nietzsche
argues that “the co-ordination of the inner systems and their operation in the service of one
end is best achieved”. 165 An organism is sick when an “antagonism of the passions” takes
place. Nietzsche describes this situation as an “inner ruin” and as physiological
“anarchism”. 166 What Nietzsche also suggests is that to be healthy is to live in accordance
with what he as Heidegger indicates may have taken to be Being: the will to power. “What
is good?”, Nietzsche asks, answering: “Everything that enhances people’s feeling of power,
will to power, power itself” 167. He also suggests that to be sick is to fail to exist in
accordance with the will to power; it is to cease to strive for the affirmation of one’s own
163
Nachlass 1888, KSA 14 [65].
Nachlass 1888, KSA 14 [173].
165
Nachlass 1888, KSA 14 [157].
166
Ibid. For a more detailed take on Nietzsche’s notions of health and disease, see Daniel R. Ahern, Nietzsche
as Cultural Physician, Pennsylvania, Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995. Also see my own Felipe G.
A. Moreira, Nietzsche como se sem metáfora: mente, corpo, doença e saúde na obra nietzschiana,
Unpublished Master Dissertation, Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro, Rio de Janeiro, 2011.
167
A 2.
164
76
singularity in negating oneself while acting in accordance with a “herd instinct”. 168 When
Nietzsche asks “What is bad?”, his response is: “Everything stemming from weakness”. 169
Nietzsche’s objection to Plato and Socrates, then, is not of an ethical, epistemic or
metaphysical kind. Rather, in relying on his medical-philosophical use of language
Nietzsche articulates what I would like to call a clinical objection: Plato’s metaphysical
use of language attests to the fact that Plato and Socrates were sick. Nietzsche takes
“Socrates and Plato as symptoms of decay, as agents of Greek disintegration, as pseudoGreek, as anti-Greek”. 170 He also sees “signs of Socrates’s decadence not only in [his]
admitted chaos, and anarchy of his instincts, but in the hypertrophy of logic as well as in
his emblematic rachitic spite”. 171 “Everything about [Socrates] is exaggerated”, Nietzsche
concludes. 172 This exaggeration gives rise to the “most bizarre of all equations”, that is, the
“Socratic equation of reason = virtue = happiness”. 173
Socrates’s equation maps onto what Nietzsche regards as the Christian “herd” of
the later 19th century. Accordingly, he claims that “Christianity is Platonism for the
‘people’” and “a hangman’s metaphysics”. 174 As such, it is not surprising that Nietzsche
should have relied on his medical-philosophical use of language in interpreting that “all the
[Christian] concepts of ‘God’, ‘the soul’, ‘virtue’, ‘sin’, the ‘beyond’, ‘truth’, ‘eternal life’”
are “lies from the bad instincts of sick natures”. 175 In fact, it is because of their sick
physiological egalitarian disharmony that Christians apply the predicates “evil” (böse) and
168
G I 2.
A 2.
170
TI II 2.
171
TI II 4.
172
Ibid.
173
Ibid.
174
BGE P, and TI VI 7, respectively.
175
EH II 10.
169
77
“good” (gut) in a particular way: evil refers to selfishness, while goodness refers to
selflessness. 176 For Nietzsche, then, 19th century European culture was the result of a
tradition that started with Socrates and Plato. This tradition entails degeneration and has
bred “the domestic animal, the herd animal, the sick animal: man, ––the Christian”. 177
Hence, Nietzsche sees some of his others —that is, anyone who champions
egalitarian practices, such as Socrates, Plato and Christians in general— as deep opponents
who would be attacking his as well as everybody else’s (including their own’s)
individualistic tendencies. My reading, then, is that Nietzsche uses his clinical vocabulary
as a way to self-defend himself from such opponents and as a means to pressure them to
change their practices of being in ultimate discordance with the will to power. Indeed, it is
not an exaggeration to claim that Nietzsche aimed to shock or embarrass these deep
opponents of his in derogatorily describing them with expressions, such as “sick animals”
and “herd animals”. Given that Nietzsche does so, it is also plausible to read that he
somehow proceeds like a dogmatist. This is because, as opposed to a conflictual crafter,
such as myself, Nietzsche does not explicitly endorse and may have even contradicted (1i), even though I do not find any passage in which Nietzsche suggests that his works attests
to the existence of an undeniable metaphysical claim or in which he contradicts (1-ii). As
stated above, (1-i) is the claim that, among the others, some are legitimate rational peers;
(1-ii) is the claim that no one has a settle a dispute once and for all. My point, then, is that,
in calling his others sick, Nietzsche may be interpreted as someone who does not take these
others, such as Socrates, to be legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake.
176
177
GM I 7.
A 3.
78
The main characteristic of Carnap’s metalinguistic use of language is the aim to
establish the conditions under which words and statements are cognitively meaningful. In
pursuing this aim, the article “Überwindung der Metaphysik” relies on three assumptions.
The first is that, since it can be taken for granted that the formal and the empirical sciences
provide knowledge, the question is how to determine which use of language can serve this
purpose. The second assumption is that all words and statements have “non-cognitive
(expressive) meaning”, but only some words and statements have “cognitive meaning”.178
Note that, in his “Logic”, Carnap also embraces this distinction.179 The third assumption is
that only cognitively meaningful statements are useful for science.
Carnap’s metalinguistic use is characterized by the following conditions for
cognitive meaning. A word has cognitive meaning if and only if it fulfills two conditions.
One is syntactical: the rules of modern logic must not be violated while connecting the
word to other words within a statement. According to Carnap, the syntactic rules of modern
logic are stricter than those of ordinary grammar: “If grammatical syntax corresponded
exactly to logical syntax”, he claims, “pseudo-statements could not arise”. 180 His point is
that the syntactic rules of ordinary grammar differentiate among “the word-categories of
nouns, adjectives, verbs, conjunctions, etc”. 181 Nevertheless, these rules do not spell out all
the specificities of each and every word that fall into these categories. For example, the
syntactic rules of grammar do not determine that the noun “prime number” cannot be the
property of a person. The syntactic rules of modern logic, on the other hand, do not permit
178
EML 80.
LOG 109.
180
EML 68.
181
Ibid.
179
79
a statement, such as (PS-i). It is important to emphasize that, by making this assumption,
Carnap quite problematically seems to attach a theory of meaning to logic. 182
The second condition for a word to be cognitively meaningful is semantical, that is,
the aforementioned verification principle cannot be violated. If a word violates either or
both of these conditions, it is a meaningless one which appears without having a cognitive
meaning. Tautologies, such as (S-i), are true merely in virtue of their meaning.
Contradictions are negations of tautologies. It follows that, for Carnap, they would be false
solely by virtue of their meaning or form. Both tautologies and contradictions are
cognitively meaningful statements which “say nothing about reality”. 183
A statement that is neither a tautology nor a contradiction, and that aims to say
something about reality, has cognitive meaning if and only if it fulfills a syntactic condition
and a semantic one. The syntactic condition is that the statement must not violate the rules
of modern logic; the semantic condition is that the statement’s nouns must be words that
have cognitive meaning. (S-ii) would, thus, be a standard cognitive empirical statement. A
statement that disrespects one or both of the conditions mentioned above is a “pseudostatement” which is neither true nor false but simply meaningless. 184 (PS-i) would be a
standard example, since it disrespects the syntactic condition for cognitive meaning by
attributing to Caesar a property —being a prime number —that persons cannot have. (PSii) would likewise be a standard pseudo-statement. For Carnap, the word “nothing” in this
statement seems to be syntactically used as a noun. However, whether this is actually the
182
To approach the particularities of Carnap’s interpretation of modern logic is a task that I cannot pursue
here. For such an inquiry, consider Erich H. Reck, “Carnap and Modern Logic,” in Michael Friedman (ed.)
and Richard Creath (ed.) Cambridge Companion to Carnap, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2007.
183
EML 68.
184
Ibid., 61.
80
case would be hardly determinable. The reason is that Heidegger does not explicitly state
alternative rules that would govern the syntax of the noun “nothing”.
Semantically, Heidegger would also not have been clear with regard to the meaning
of “nothing”. As a consequence, “nothing” in (PS-ii) would be a meaningless word for two
reasons: first, the word violates the syntactic rules of modern logic; second, it is impossible
to reduce it to the words contained in protocol sentences. Carnap interprets Heidegger’s
neologism “nothings” in a similar fashion. Syntactically, this word appears to be used as a
verb. Yet, whether this is the case would also be hardly determinable. This is because
Heidegger would not have spelled out alternative rules that would govern the syntax of the
verb “to nothing”. “Nothings”, then, would violate the rules of modern logic. Semantically,
the meaning of “nothings” would also not have been explained by Heidegger. 185
Most importantly, Carnap does not limit himself to claiming that metaphysical uses
of language (like Heidegger’s) are meaningless. He takes a step further that most of his
commentators have not fully recognized: he adopts a quite Nietzschean approach of using
a clinical vocabulary in order to diagnose those who adopt a metaphysical use of language
as being sick. In “deluding himself” and “succumbing to self-delusion”, Carnap claims, the
“metaphysician suffers from the illusion that the metaphysical statements say
something”. 186 Metaphysicians are intellectually confused; they mistakenly assume
themselves as being engaged in a rational, theoretical inquiry like that of scientists when
in fact they are only engaged in an irrational, emotional practical activity. This confusion
is a sign of the metaphysical disease: the disease of taking oneself to be able to rationally
185
For more detailed comments on Carnap’s reading of Heidegger, see Michael Friedman, A Parting of the
Ways and Abraham D. Stone, “Heidegger and Carnap on the Overcoming of Metaphysics”.
186
EML 79, my emphasis.
81
justify pseudo-statements that lack cognitive meaning, instead of recognizing that, like
poetic statements, metaphysical statements are limited to expressive meaning.
It is evident that Carnap does not rely on a clinical vocabulary as consistently as
Nietzsche does. Yet, the article “Überwindung der Metaphysik” is not the only work in
which Carnap employs this vocabulary. In his “Theoretische Fragen und praktische
Entscheidungen”, he states, for instance, that “philosophical and religious metaphysics are
in certain circumstances a narcotic, dangerous and harmful to reason”. 187 As Thomas
Mormann noted, this passage “reminds one not only of Marx but also of Nietzsche (cf. The
Gay Science, Book 3, §147)”. 188 “What do savage tribes today take over first of all from
the Europeans?”, Nietzsche asks in this passage. “Liquor and Christianity, the narcotics of
Europe”, he answers. “And from what do they perish most quickly?”, he also asks. “From
European narcotics”, he responds. A similar clinical vocabulary can be found in Carnap’s
“Logic” in which he argues that logic’s “task is to serve a spiritual hygiene, cautioning
men against the disease of intellectual confusion”. 189 Logic, Carnap continues, “has the
ungrateful duty, whenever it finds symptoms of this disease, to pronounce the unwelcome
diagnosis”. 190 The unwelcome diagnosis would be that metaphysicians are sick; they are
“deceiving themselves” in believing that they are able to provide some sort of mysterious
knowledge of the essence of things that is neither mathematical nor empirical. 191
Hence, similarly to Nietzsche, Carnap takes some of his others, such as Heidegger,
to be deep opponents whose practices are to be resisted. In contrast to Nietzsche, though,
187
Rudolf Carnap, “Theoretische Fragen und praktische Entscheidungen”, pp. 260, my emphasis.
Thomas Mormann, “Carnap’s Boundless Ocean”, pp. 73.
189
LOG 118, my emphasis.
190
Ibid., my emphasis.
191
Ibid., 101.
188
82
Carnap’s opponents are those who promote libertarian practices. I will discuss this last
point more carefully in the next section. For now, I read that Carnap also self-defends
himself from his deep opponents by pressuring them to think and/or act differently in his
1920s-1930s writings, such as “Überwindung der Metaphysik”. He also seems to seek to
shock or embarrass such opponents by derogatorily describing them by means of a clinicalpolitical vocabulary characterized by expressions, such as “self-delusion”. In doing so,
Carnap’s procedure may be interpreted to be somehow dogmatic, even though he neither
suggests that his works attest to the existence of an undeniable metaphysical claim nor
contradicts that claim that no person has settle a dispute once and for all. What I mean is
that, distinct from a conflictual crafter, such as myself, Carnap could be plausibly
interpreted as someone who does not explicitly embrace and, perhaps, even contradicts the
claim that, among the others, some are rational legitimate peers. This takes place because
Carnap insinuates that metaphysicians (in the Carnapian senses) are not legitimate rational
peers insofar as disputes are concerned, but would, rather, be suffering from a sickness.
2.4
Why is an Overcoming of Metaphysics to be Performed?
Nietzsche and Carnap also have to face the question why an overcoming of
metaphysics is to be performed. They answer this question by endorsing different versions
of (3-iii): to overcome metaphysics is to contribute to the political task of resisting diseased
metaphysical practices and promoting healthy non-metaphysical ones. By a political task,
I understand one that: first, aims to have a significant social importance, even if merely for
the members of a particular field, such as the philosophical field; second, this task seeks to
pressure a significant group of people to change their practices, say, by labelling such
practices sick or even going as far as resorting to upfront violence or at least to “subtle”
83
violence; and, third, a political task relies on considerably controversial normative claims
that others or one’s deep opponents simply do not embrace, such as (3-i), (3-ii) and (3-iii).
That Nietzsche is engaged in a political task is considerably explicit —“great
politics” is what he calls this.192 Moreover, note that, in articulating this “great politics”,
Nietzsche does not merely “awaits” what he calls the “philosophical physician”, a figure
who would “set himself the task of pursuing the problem of the total health of a people,
time, race or of humanity”. 193 Rather, he proceeds himself like a philosophical physician
in endorsing (3-iii). The situation is more difficult in the case of Carnap. Unlike Neurath,
Carnap was not quite explicit with regard to political matters, especially after he
immigrated to the United Stated in 1935. He noted in his 1963 autobiography, for instance:
“we [the members of the Vienna Circle with the exception of Neurath] liked to keep our
philosophical work separated from our political aims”. 194 “In our view”, he continued,
“logic, including applied logic, and the theory of knowledge, the analysis of language, and
the methodology of science, are, like science itself, neutral with respect to practical aims,
whether they are moral aim for the individual, or political aims for society”. 195
This last passage seems to back up the widely shared claim that Carnap’s attempt
to overcome metaphysics is politically neutral. Like Michael Friedman, I would argue in
contrast that Carnap “just as strongly agrees with his more activist friend and colleague
[Neurath] that philosophy can and should serve social and political aims in its particular
historical context”. 196 Furthermore, as Thomas Uebel emphasizes, Carnap was an “activist”
192
BGE 208, 241, etc.
GS, P 2.
194
IAB 22.
195
Ibid.
196
Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways, pp. 16.
193
84
and his emphasis on the value neutrality of logic and science is “often misinterpreted”.197
Carnap, to put it more sharply, does not say that philosophy has no political role to play.
What he suggests, rather, is that there is a distinction between theoretical questions and
practical decisions so that, when dealing with the former, logic is neutral with regard to the
latter. This is not to state that logic has no practical role to play. Consider the passages I
quoted in the last section in which Carnap relies on a clinical vocabulary; they attest that
logic and scientific philosophy pursue a practical aim: that of resisting sick metaphysical
libertarian practices, while promoting healthy non-metaphysical egalitarian ones.
Of course, Nietzsche and Carnap do not have a common political motivation;
Carnap’s “activism”, to use Uebel’s term, ultimately runs counter to Nietzsche’s
intentions. 198 Indeed, I would like to go as far as claiming that the core of their
disagreement is of a political kind. For Nietzsche, as indicated above, the sick metaphysical
practices that are to be resisted are egalitarian ones. 199 These are altruistic practices that do
not exist in accordance with the will to power, since they overvalue a communitarian (or,
in Nietzsche’s terms) “herd” equality. This excessive valorization of communitarian
equality would have resulted in the disharmony of modern European culture.
Metaphysicians (in Nietzsche’s sense) and the “socialist fools” mentioned in this chapter’s
introduction would show signs of this disharmony. 200 The same would be the case with
Christians. Nietzsche’s aim, then, is to articulate a philosophy that promotes harmony in
doing justice to one’s “instincts for the wild” and pointing toward an “overman”
197
Thomas Uebel, “Carnap, Philosophy and ‘Politics in its Broadest Sense’”, in Richard Creath, Carnap and
the Legacy of Logical Empiricism, Dordrecht, Springer, 2012: pp. 133.
198
Ibid.
199
For a detailed take on Nietzsche’s objections to egalitarianism, see John Richardson, Nietzsche’s System,
pp. 165.
200
BGE 203.
85
(Übermensch) that would no longer let the herd make him sick. 201 No similar aim is
pursued by Carnap or Neurath.
Consider Neurath’s 1946 reply to Horace Kallen’s objection that the unity of the
sciences aimed at by logical positivism pointed toward totalitarianism. 202 Neurath
addresses an issue regarding which Nietzsche had a lot to state —that of priests’ influence
upon the masses. Neurath’s view is that “if priests and rulers have a language of their own,
they become separated from the ruled masses, and it is just the unification of language that
is a step forward to some democratic possibilities”. 203 For Nietzsche, though, the problem
is not that priests and rulers have acted in an anti-democratic way; rather, the real problem
would be that these figures have actually spread those religious concepts that have created
the sick masses which endorse the egalitarian values associated with democracy.
Carnap, on the other hand, moves into a distinctly non-Nietzschean direction. He
suggests that the sick practices that need to be resisted are of a libertarian kind. These
practices would confound rationality and irrationality, theoretical questions and practical
decisions as well as the “cognitive” and the “expressive function” of sentences. 204 These
sick practices, Carnap suggests, constitute an anti-democratic selfishness that renders it
difficult to achieve a universal communal equality. Now note that Mormann claims that
“evidence for Nietzsche’s early influence [on Carnap] can be found in the 1921-1922
manuscript Vom Chaos zur Welt 205 that Carnap himself considered as the ‘nucleus of the
201
GM II 16 and Z P 3, respectively.
Horace M. Kallen, “The Meanings of ‘Unity’ Among the Sciences, Once More”, Philosophy and
Phenomenal Research Vol 6, No 4, June., 1946: pp. 493-496.
203
Otto Neurath, “The Orchestration of the Sciences by the Encyclopedism of Logical Empiricism”,
Philosophy and Phenomenal Research Vol 6, No 4, June., 1946: pp. 502. See also Otto Neurath,
Philosophical Papers 1913-1946, Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1983.
204
LOG 109.
205
Rudolf Carnap, “Ms.‘Vom Chaos zur Wirklichke’ (mit Notizen zum Konstitution-System”), Unpublished
Manuscript (1921-1926), University of Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: RC 081-05-01.
202
86
Aufbau’”. 206 “In Chaos”, Mormann argues in a way that I am inclined to endorse, “Carnap
subscribed to a pseudo-Nietzschean ‘will to order’ (for him apparently more appealing than
the original ‘will to power’) that was the ‘irrational starting point’ of the orderly
constitution of the world the philosopher attempted to realize”. 207 Perhaps, then, a way to
describe what Carnap takes to be sick practices is by stating that these practices do not exist
in accordance with this will to order. By such a will to order, I read that the Carnap of
“Chaos” had in mind either a synonym of what I have described as one’s communitarian
tendencies (or herd instincts), or, more problematically, a distinct conception of Being.
According to this conception, Being is to stand in some sort of non-causal relation
with the will to order, that is, the will to protect oneself from chaos by, in the human case,
acting in accordance and contributing to the creation of a really universal community. Were
Carnap actually committed to this view, he would also be a human-yet-physicalist-driven
philosopher in a sense quite similar to the one above attributed to Nietzsche, that is, though
Carnap would still associate Being to something apparently human, such as a “will”, he
would have indicated that the universal identity of all beings is to stand in some sort of
non-causal relation to a neither divine, nor human entity. Carnap’s published writings,
though, never explicitly endorse any conception of Being. In fact, as indicated above, he
often suggests that those who embrace such conceptions rely on quite mysterious barely
justificatory resources that cannot be comparable to those of mathematicians, logicians
and/or empirical scientists. So, it is more persuasive to call Carnap a proto or even, indeed,
a physicalist-driven philosopher in a distinct sense. The sense is that of being one of the
firsts to explicitly address the theoretical dispute over the following claim ultimately
206
207
Thomas Mormann, “Carnap’s Boundless Ocean”, pp. 73.
Ibid.
87
embraced by Carnap himself: “for all scientific statements [e.g., one from psychology, such
as “Mr. A is angry”], there is an equipollent statement of the language of physics”. 208
Let me now underline that I do not think that it is an exaggeration to claim that
Carnap believes metaphysicians (in his two senses) to be agents of chaos. This is because
they would appeal to people’s irrational emotions in rendering any kind of rational inquiry
barely achievable. Hence, metaphysicians would not merely be self-delusional “musicians
without musical ability”. 209 They would be much worse than that. Indeed, if
metaphysicians were merely artists without artistic ability, it would be hard to understand
why Carnap advocates for an overcoming of metaphysics in the first place. That is: why
would anyone want to resist mere musicians without musical ability or poets with no poetic
taste? There seems to be no persuasive political reason to engage oneself in such a
resistance.
My reading, then, is that Carnap understands metaphysicians to be quite similar to
the “priests and rulers” considered by Neurath; they act in an authoritarian way by relying
on an obscure use of language that renders any refutation impossible and that separates
them from the rest of the community. 210 In his 1937 “Logic”, Carnap further highlights the
political dangers of metaphysics, when he compares metaphysicians to Nazi-like
politicians. Both would seek to advance “illogical thinking” which confounds theoretical
questions and practical decisions as well as the “cognitive” and the “expressive function”
of sentences. 211 Ultimately, the main difference between metaphysicians and such Nazi-
208
See Rudolf Carnap, “Les Concepts psychologiques et les concepts physiques sont-ils foncierement
differents?”, trans. Robert Bouvier, Revue de synthese (Paris), t. 10, no. 1, April 1935: pp. 46. My translation.
209
EML 80.
210
Otto Neurath, “The Orchestration of the Sciences”, pp. 502.
211
LOG 110.
88
like politicians would be their distinct abilities to influence others. In Carnap’s words,
metaphysicians’ “doctrines and the confusions arising from their failures to distinguish
between cognitive and expressive function of sentences produce relatively little harmful
effects upon human destiny”. 212 In “politics”, though, a similar attitude would have
“serious practical consequences”. 213 Carnap illustrates his point by imagining that a
specific “creed is promulgated in a certain country”. 214 The creed resembles the ideological
commitments of National Socialism, and runs as follows: “‘there is only one race of
superior men, say the race of Hottentots, and this race alone is worthy of ruling other races.
Members of these other races are inferior, so that all civil rights are to be denied them so
long as they inhabit the country’”. 215
Carnap’s view is that this claim is similar to a metaphysical pseudo-statement, such
as (PS-ii). Although the claim “certainly has the appearance of an assertion,” it has “no
cognitive meaning and exercises merely a volitional function”. 216 Carnap concludes that
“it is […] of great practical importance for understanding the effective appeal of political
war-cries like the above to note that they take the form of misleading pseudo-assertions”. 217
“This is to be explained”, he continues, “by the fact that many men respond less readily to
what are obviously commands than to such assertations or pseudo-assertions, especially
212
Ibid.
Ibid., 111.
214
Ibid.
215
Ibid. “Hottentots” is a name that 17th century Dutch colonizers gave to the Khoikhoi people of Southern
Africa. Today, this term is considered derogatory and offensive. What Carnap knew about the Khoikhoi
people is uncertain. He does not make any reference to their history and the colonial violence they have been
subjected to. Arguably, in using the term “Hottentots” Carnap contradicts his own egalitarian values. For a
take on the Khoikhoi people, see Emile Boonzaier, Candy Malherbe, Andy Smith, Penny Berens, The Cape
Herders: A History of the Khoikhoi of Southern Africa, Ohio, Ohio University Press, 1997.
216
LOG 110.
217
Ibid., 112.
213
89
when the latter are accompanied by powerful emotional appeals”. 218 Against this
background, Friedman is right to argue that “there can be very little doubt […] that
Carnap’s attacks on Heidegger, articulated and presented at a critical moment during the
last years of the Weimar Republic, have more than purely philosophical motivations”. 219
As Critchley claims, Carnap’s objection to Heidegger “is not just a theoretical
disagreement, but also one expression of the social and political conflicts that so deeply
scarred the last century”. 220 Indeed, as stated above, Carnap emigrated to the United Stated
in 1935, since “with the beginning of the Hitler regime in Germany in 1933, the political
atmosphere, even in Austria and Czechoslovakia, became more and more intolerable”. 221.
“The Nazi ideology”, he underlines, “spread more and more among the German-speaking
population of the Sudeten region and therewith among the students of our university and
even among some of the professors”. 222 On the other hand, Heidegger had an ambiguous
relationship to the Nazis. 223 What Carnap himself knew about Heidegger’s (now welldocumented) involvement with the Nazis is uncertain. 224 It is obvious, however, that
Carnap reads the Nazi-like credo quoted above and Heidegger’s metaphysical statement,
(PS-ii), along the same lines. They would both be symptomatic signs that those who
articulated such statements champion sick libertarian practices that are to be resisted. 225
218
Ibid.
Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways, pp. 21.
220
Simon Critchley, Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
2001: pp. 102.
221
IAB 33.
222
Ibid.
223
On this ambiguity, see, for instance, Victor Farias, Heidegger and Nazism, Philadelphia, Temple
University Press, 1989; and Jacques Derrida, Of spirit: Heidegger and the question, Chicago, Chicago
University Press, 1989.
224
See Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways.
225
On my part, I tend to disagree with Carnap’s reading of the Nazis. Although it is not my aim to articulate
an interpretation of the Nazis here, I am inclined to believe that they were not libertarians at all but, rather,
conservatives in a sense that will be carefully spelled out throughout the fifth and the sixth chapter.
219
90
In contrast to Carnap, Nietzsche claims, as indicated above, that the healthy
practices that are to be promoted question communitarian principles of equality. Such
libertarian practices promote individual freedom insofar as they seek to do justice to the
“instincts for the wild”. Nietzsche’s description of the “nobles” can serve as a prominent
example. The latter, he claims, occasionally “enjoy the freedom from every social
constraint”. 226 In doing so, they exhibit signs of a war-like healthy physiology that is in
harmony with itself. In Nietzsche’s words,
The chivalric-aristocratic value judgments are based on a powerful physicality, a
blossoming, rich, even effervescent good health that includes things needed to
maintain it, war, adventure, hunting, dancing, jousting and everything else that
contains strong, free, happy action. 227
This is to state that healthy practices are those that seek to provoke in the herd some sort
of healthy chaos, as opposed to the diseased chaos of overpraising a herd instinct, like sick
Christian animals would have done.
I do not wish to suggest that Nietzsche promotes a return to the noble way of life.
It seems more persuasive to argue that, in order to bring harmony back to his own
degenerated culture, Nietzsche thought that it would be necessary to adopt his above stated
reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons are engaged in disputes. To create
a philosophy guided by this reaction would be a way to pursue a health comparable to that
of the nobles. This new philosophy would have to rely on several kinds of statements. This
includes scientific, poetic and (arguably) metaphysical statements (in the Heideggerian
sense). Indeed, nothing in Nietzsche’s writings indicates that he thought it wise for
philosophers to follow Carnap in adopting a use of language that could clearly distinguish
226
227
GM I 11.
GM I 7.
91
among scientific, poetic and metaphysical statements. What Nietzsche’s new philosophy
seeks is to overcome metaphysics in the Nietzschean sense of the term. He rejects, then,
the claim that there are hierarchical oppositions of values, and he discards the “Socratic
equation” by suggesting that human beings need reason, virtue and happiness as much as
they need irrationality, vice and sadness. 228 The same applies to the other oppositions
considered above and to Nietzsche’s own opposition between health and sickness: humans,
he states, “need the sick soul as much as the healthy”. 229 Nietzsche also claims that “health
and sickness are not essentially different, as the ancient physicians and some practitioners
even today suppose”; rather, “there are only differences in degree” between them. 230
Likewise, Nietzsche doubts the traditional hierarchical distinction between “theory
and practice”: “fateful distinction as if there were an actual drive for knowledge that,
without regard to questions of usefulness and harm, went blindly for the truth; and then,
separate from this, the whole world of practical interests”. 231 As a consequence, he would
be inclined to problematize oppositions that feature prominently in Carnap’s thought, such
as those between rationality and irrationality, theoretical questions and practical decisions,
cognitive function and expressive function of sentences, etc. 232 Arguably, Nietzsche would
claim that Carnap overvalues the first terms of these oppositions over the second ones, so
that Carnap’s own work shows signs of a sick herd instinct quite similar to the thought of
228
TI II 4.
GS III 120. For an account of Nietzsche’s view on the soul, see Günter Abel, “Consciousness, Language,
and Nature: Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Mind and Nature”, in Manuel Dries (ed.) and P. J. E. Kail (ed.),
Nietzsche on Mind and Nature, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2015. For a take on the connection between
Nietzsche’s view on the mind-body problem and his notions of health and disease, see my own Felipe G. A.
Moreira, Nietzsche como se sem metáfora: mente, corpo, doença e saúde na obra nietzschiana.
230
Nachlass 1888, KSA 14 [65].
231
Nachlass 1888, KSA 14 [142].
232
For a discussion of Dewey’s rejection of these Carnapian oppositions, see Alan Richardson, “Carnapian
Pragmatism”, in Michael Friedman (ed.) and Richard Creath (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Carnap,
Cambridge, Cambridge University press, 2007: pp. 312.
229
92
Socrates or Plato. For Nietzsche, then, Carnap would likely be seeing as a metaphysician
(in the Nietzschean sense) who fears and oppresses the “instincts for the wild”.
Nietzsche also sees little point in the pursuit of certainty. What he often suggests is
that, instead of articulating detailed and/or tedious arguments, philosophers should appeal
to their opponents’ emotions. To do so is to be more open to the use of upfront rhetorical
devices, such as that of relying on a series of aphorisms and explicitly articulating poetic
statements, like (NP). On his part, Carnap also does not pursue certainty. Instead, he
endorses a view by Neurath that he associates with the “left wing of the Circle”: “the
totality of what is known about the world is always uncertain and continually in need of
correction and transformation”. 233 Distinct from Nietzsche, though, Carnap obviously aims
to avoid upfront rhetorical devices; his aim is to convince others by relying on what he
takes to be exclusively rational means. This is why Nietzsche would likely exclude Carnap
from the philosophers of the future, that is, Carnap, would be another philosopher of the
past who still values and pursues consensus by articulating detailed arguments.
Finally, Nietzsche also puts into question the claim that there is a true world, albeit
without endorsing either a strong or a weak idealism. Consider the following remark: “the
true world is gone: which world is left? The illusory one, perhaps?... But no! we got rid of
the illusory world along with the true one!”. 234 This passage is particularly challenging to
interpret, but it seems to me compatible with a thesis Carnap explicitly endorsed throughout
his career: namely, that the dispute between any kind of realism, such as those often
233
IAB 57. “Scientific philosophy,” Hans Reichenbach also states, “refuses to accept any knowledge of the
physical word as absolutely certain”. See Hans Reichenbach, The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, California,
University of California Press, 1951: pp. 304. For a discussion of the left Vienna circle, see Thomas Uebel,
“Political Philosophy of Science in Logical Empiricism: the Left Vienna Circle”, Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science 36, 2005: pp. 754-763.
234
TI IV.
93
presupposed by God and physicalist-driven philosophers, and any kind of idealism, such
as those embraced by human-driven ones, is ultimately irrelevant. In Der logische Aufbau
der Welt, Carnap uses the verb “to construct” in order to emphasize that the formal and
empirical sciences are neutral with regard to this dispute. Carnap raises the following
question: “does thinking ‘create’ the objects, as the Neo-Kantian Marburg school teaches,
or does thinking “merely apprehend” them, as realism asserts?”.235 Carnap’s answer to this
question is that “construction theory employs a neutral language and maintains that objects
are neither ‘created’ nor ‘apprehended’ but constructed”. 236 Now let me once again be very
careful in stating that the last passage by Nietzsche might plausibly be read as pointing into
a similar direction, that is, as indicating that Nietzsche also sought to articulate a
philosophy that is neutral about realism and idealism.
As such, I do not think it is very relevant to ask whether Nietzsche took the will to
power to be a realist concept that, so to speak, “carved reality at its joints” or whether he
viewed it as a commitment to some sort of idealism that merely depicted or even falsified
reality. Nietzsche sometimes indicates that disputes such as this are absurd. Consider his
remarks on those who “say that the external world is the product of our organs”:
But then, Nietzsche states, our body, as a piece of this external worlds, would really be the product
of our organs! But then our organs themselves would really be —the product of our organs! This
looks to me like a thorough reductio ad absurdum: given that the concept of a causa sui is something
thoroughly absurd. So does it follow that the external world is not the product of our organs –? 237
Accordingly, I take that the role of the will to power as a concept is not the resolution of
traditional disputes between any kind of realism and any kind of idealism. Rather, in
235
LSW 10.
Ibid. For critiques of Carnap’s neutralism, see Stathis Psillos, Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks
Truth, New York, Routledge, 1999; and Otávio Bueno, “Carnap, Logicism, and Ontological Commitment”,
in Sorin Costreie (ed.), Early Analytic Philosophy: New Perspectives on the Tradition, Dordrecht, Springer,
2016.
237
BGE 15.
236
94
relying on the notion of the will to power, Nietzsche aims to articulate new disputes. An
example of such disputes Nietzsche cares about is the political question on whether
philosophers are to promote healthy practices that do justice to the will to power. Carnap
never addressed this question in his published works. In his unpublished manuscripts,
however, he indicates his strong disagreements with Nietzsche’s political views.
In his early manuscript Schema für den 9. Rundbrief from 1918, Carnap mentions
a “contrast” (Gegensatz) between those who champion a “perpetual war” (Ewiger Krieg)
and those who champion an “perpetual peace” (Ewiger Frieden). 238 He associates
“Nietzsche” with the former as well as with “brutal-chauvinistic-utopian” (BrutalChauvinistisch-utopistisch) “slogans” (Schlagworte). 239 In the same manuscript, Carnap
also mentions Nietzsche’s name under a table entitled “individualistic morality”
(individualistische Sittlichkeit); he indicates that Nietzsche takes “war as a moral necessity”
(Krieg als sittliche Notwendigkeit). 240 Carnap notices that the ideal of this individualistic
morality is a “master-man (will to power)” (der Herrenmensch (Wille zur Macht)). 241 Note
that the term Carnap uses here, “Herrenmensch”, is not the same as Nietzsche’s
“Übermensch”; “Herrenmensch” clearly belongs to the vocabulary of Nazi ideology.
An individualist morality, Carnap also contends, views “combat” (Kampf) as a
“heroic activity” (heroische Tätigkeit) and as “the only effective way of selecting and
testing one’s efficiency” (die einzige wirksame Auslese und Erprobung der Tüchtigkeit)
(ibid). In the same 1918 manuscript, Carnap likewise states that one of the reasons the ideal
238
Rudolf Carnap, “Schema für den 9. Rundbrief”, Unpublished Manuscript (1918), University of Pittsburgh,
Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: RC 081-22-05.
239
Ibid.
240
Ibid., code: RC 081-22-08.
241
Ibid.
95
of a “heroic life” (heroischen Lebens) arises lies in an insight that he associates with
Nietzsche: “though Christian morality is only preached in favor of the masses of the weak,
the true meaning of all life lies in the development of an ingenious, self-reliant personality”.
In the original German words, this passage runs as follows: christliche Moral nur
zugunsten der Masse der Schwachen gepredigt wird, der wahre Sinn alles Lebens aber in
der Entwicklung der genialen, nur auf sich gestellten Persönlichkeit liegt. 242
In a manuscript entitled Lectures in Europe (Items 43-54) —dated to 1929 —
Carnap, furthermore, associates Nietzsche’s name with those who value “strength of
personality”
(Stärke
der
Persönlichkeit)
and
champion
“aristocratic
ethics”
(aristokratische Ethik) and “heroism” (Heroismus). 243 Nothing suggests that Carnap has
any sympathy with these views. Carnap also suggests that the healthy practices that ought
to be promoted are those that Nietzsche would take to be sick ones. Carnap’s nonmetaphysical healthy practices are those that do not confound rational and irrational tasks,
theoretical questions and practical decisions as well as the cognitive and the expressive
functions of sentences. Such practices altruistically and usefully contribute to making
society more equal, peaceful, and/ or less chaotic. In short, they run in accordance with the
will of order or, as Nietzsche would say, they are expressions of a “herd instinct”.
Carnap points to this direction when he notes that he has always been driven by an
“implicit lasting attitude” in arguing that “the main task of an individual seems to me the
development of his personality and the creation of fruitful and healthy relations among
human beings”. 244 “This aim”, he continues, “implies the task of co-operation in the
242
Ibid., code: RC 081-22-09.
Rudolf Carnap, “Lectures in Europe (Items 43-54)”, Unpublished Manuscript (1922-1933), University of
Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: RC 110-07-49.
244
IAB 22, my emphasis.
243
96
development of society and ultimately of the whole of mankind towards a community in
which every individual has the possibility of leading a satisfying life and of participating
in cultural goods”. 245 Hence, it is not surprising that Carnap wants a “gradual development
toward a world government”. 246 Carnap’s way to contribute toward this goal is by
championing the overcoming of metaphysics in the two Carnapian senses of this term. This
overcoming is informed by his egalitarian reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times,
persons have been engaged in disputes. In championing this reaction, what Carnap seeks,
then, is to create a new philosophy more useful to the rest of society and less dangerously
similar to the political claims of Nazi ideology. Indeed, to put in Alan Richardson’s terms,
Carnap’s view is that this new philosophy is also useful in that it “offers tools to
science”. 247
Once we have embraced a scientific philosophy, Carnap claims, “the various
concepts of the various branches of science are clarified; their formal-logical and
epistemological connection are made explicit”. 248 For him, then, poets and scientists
already champion healthy practices useful to society. This is why neither poets nor
scientists would be self-delusional. Poets would aim and provide a special expression of
emotions by means of statements like (P) and (NP), while scientists would aim and likewise
provide knowledge by means of statements like (S-i), (S-ii) and (NS). Philosophers are also
to play a useful role in this context: they are not to use a cognitively meaningless language
that dangerously and chaotically confounds rationality and irrationality, theoretical
245
Ibid.
Ibid., 83.
247
Alan Richardson, “Carnapian Pragmatism”, pp. 304.
248
EML 60.
246
97
questions and practical decisions and the cognitive and the expressive functions of
sentences. Carnap’s “faith” is that his scientific philosophy would “win the future”. 249
249
LSW xiii.
CHAPTER 3
THE WILL TO SYNTHESIS 250
3.1 The New “Faith”
My “faith”, to paraphrase Rudolf Carnap, is that, in the future, the continentalanalytic gap will be lost in the past. In the present, though, this future appears a bit remote.
One reason for that was already indicated in 2.1: throughout the last century and up to ours,
several continental philosophers, such as Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida, were
influenced by Friedrich Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction to the fact that, since immemorial
times, persons have been engaged in disputes. These philosophers, on the other hand, did
not pay much (if any at all) attention to Carnap’s egalitarian reaction. Consider, for
instance, Foucault’s 1961 History of Madness. 251 This work deals with a theoretical dispute
that most analytic philosophers, practically speaking, have simply not considered: that on
how and why some claims about madness, mentally disordered or allegedly mentally
disordered people became widely shared throughout the 17th and up to the 20th century.
Examples of such claims are: the meaning and the reference of the term “madness”
have not significantly changed over the last four centuries or so; in diagnosing someone as
being mentally disordered, psychiatrists have usually respected scientific standards that
have not significantly changed over the last four centuries or so; and psychiatry has not
mainly served to isolate those (e.g., men who engage in sexual intercourse with other men
or women who refuse to get married or constantly cheat on their husbands) who have a
deviant behavior. In aiming to articulate a thought-provoking history of psychiatry,
250
I presented previous versions of this chapter in a talk at Federal University of Rio de Janeiro as well as at
the University of Miami’s Philosophy Research Forum.
251
Michel Foucault, History of Madness, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006.
98
99
Foucault defends the denials of these claims. In doing so, it is plausible to read Foucault as
someone who aimed to provoke dissensus, and to even shock or embarrass, especially the
community (or the “herd”) of those who have presupposed the stated claims.
Practically speaking, by simply publishing the History of Madness, Foucault seems
to resist an egalitarian practice: that of isolating the so called “sick” or “mentally
disordered” in mental institutions for the sake of protecting the supposedly “healthy” or
“mentally sane” rest of the community. He also seems to promote the libertarian practice
of problematizing these institutions under the basis that they are ultimately hypocritical
ones, that is, while speaking in the name of apparently “peaceful” notions of “science”
and/or “treatment”, such institutions would have fought a quite violent “war” against
persons (especially deviants) in overly constraining and even pathologizing their
singularities. 252 As several interpreters, such as Gary Gutting and Todd May, indicate, then,
I take that Foucault was quite inspired by Nietzsche. 253 Ultimately, he often appears to
point to Nietzsche’s political task of resisting the “diseased” egalitarian practices and
promoting the “healthy” libertarian ones.
I tend to read that this is also the case with Derrida. Consider, for instance, his take
on Nietzsche himself, the one of his 1978 Spurs: Nietzsche’s Styles. 254 In this work, as in
most of his writings, Derrida addresses a theoretical dispute that, practically speaking,
analytic philosophers have likewise not usually discussed: the dispute over the claim that
there are exegetical claims about certain texts (especially, philosophical ones) that cannot
252
For a detailed take on Foucault’s views on violence, see Leonard Lawlor From Violence to Speaking Out:
Apocalypse and Expression in Foucault, Derrida and Deleuze, Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press, 2016.
253
Gary Gutting, Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
2011; and Todd May, Between Genealogy and Epistemology: Psychology, Politics, and Knowledge in the
Thought of Michel Foucault, Pennsylvania¸ Pennsylvania State University, 1993.
254
Jacques Derrida, Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles / Eperons: Les Styles de Nietzsche, Chicago, Chicago
University Press, 1979.
100
be rationally contradicted by persons. Throughout his works, Derrida suggests that no such
claim can be obtained. A claim that seems to contradict this suggestion, and (at least by the
time Derrida was writing) was canonical among Nietzsche’s interpreters is: Nietzsche has
sexist views on women. Derrida problematizes this reading. He does so by considering
other passages of Nietzsche’s works rarely taken into account, reading famous passages
anew and pointing toward the plausibility of a unique thought-provoking interpretation.
The alternative interpretation I have in mind is: Nietzsche’s philosophy is
“feminine” and, indeed, more “feminine” than that of most so-called feminists who still
have a considerably “phallogocentric” thinking. In suggesting so, it is plausible to read that
Derrida seeks to provoke dissensus and even to shock or embarrass, especially the
community or the herd of those who embraced (or “constructed”) the canonical reading.
Practically speaking, then, Derrida seems to resist such community’s egalitarian practice
of taking for granted Nietzsche’s canonical reading, say, for the sake of establishing a
common criterion to evaluate exegetical claims about Nietzsche’s writings. He also
implicitly promoted the libertarian practice of problematizing educational philosophical
institutions, especially French ones that focus on the history of philosophy and use
standardized tests on such history to hire professors as well as to evaluate students. I tend
to think that Derrida’s point is that, in implicitly speaking in the name of a quite narrow
notion of logos, such institutions excessively constrain their members’ singularities,
especially the ones of those whose ways of thinking are too “feminine”. This would be so
because these institutions would have turned canonical readings into canons as if the
supporters of these readings were authorities who are never to be contradicted. Therefore,
101
Derrida seems to suggest that this situation would render the articulation of thoughtprovoking interpretations of philosophical writings, like his own readings, extremely hard.
Now note that, to paraphrase John Richardson’s aforementioned claim about
Nietzsche (see 2.2), it appears that: the strongest kind of claim any single reading of
Foucault or Derrida can plausibly make for itself is to pick one voice or aspect of their
writings, and show how to see that voice as somehow dominant, somehow trumping or
subordinating the many other incompatible voices also there. The above exegetical remarks
about Foucault and Derrida, I would like to presuppose, are imperfect justificatory
resources; they are hopefully enough to back up the claim that one of such of voices of
theirs is a Nietzschean voice. It is not this dissertation’s aim, though, to articulate detailed
readings of Foucault and Derrida that show how this voice dominates others, such as, say,
Foucault’s more Kantian voice; Derrida’s more Jewish voice, both Foucault’s and
Derrida’s more egalitarian voices that run in tension with their Nietzschean ones; etc.
What is crucial here is to emphasize that basic observation shows that, in analytic
philosophy contexts (e.g., those of several (if not most) philosophy departments in the
United Stated) norms, such as the following one, are usually implicitly embraced: one is
not to even mention the likes of Foucault or Derrida, unless it is to mock the alleged
“absurdity” of their writings, that is, this mockery is quite acceptable and perhaps even
encouraged by several analytic philosophers who, nevertheless, have never carefully
addressed the writings of these French philosophers or taken Nietzsche’s libertarian
reaction into account. Basic observation also indicates that, in continental philosophy
contexts, such as those of several philosophy departments in France or literature ones in
the United States, distinct norms are often endorsed. An example is the norm that one is to
102
not even mention analytic philosophers, unless it is to mock the alleged “naivety” of their
thinking. This is to state that certain mockeries are also embraced by some continental
philosophers, especially those who ignore Carnap’s egalitarian reaction to the fact that,
since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes. It follows that what counts
as a “serious philosopher” varies quite radically from analytic to continental contexts.
Another reason why a future with no continental-analytic gap appears a bit remote
is that Carnap’s reaction has been taken for granted by several analytic philosophers who,
nonetheless, practically ignored Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction. Examples of such
philosophers are David Lewis and Peter van Inwagen. Notice that these two philosophers
have often been described as champions of a neo-Quinean approach, that is, one mainly
influenced, not by Carnap himself, but by his most famous disciple: Willard Van Orman
Quine. I underline that, in the fifth chapter, I will spell out several significant political
differences between Carnap and Quine that are not considered by contemporary analytic
philosophers, including those who have been described as being inspired by Carnap, such
as the likes of David Chalmers, Huw Price, Eli Hirsch and Amie Thomasson. 255
For now, though, I would like to indicate some Carnapian features in Lewis’s 1986
On the Plurality of Worlds. 256 This book’s focus is on a theoretical dispute that, practically
speaking, most continental philosophers have ignored: that on whether there are concrete
possible worlds neither spatial-temporally nor causally connected to ours. Lewis endorses
modal realism; the thesis that these worlds exist. Arguably, modal realism has caused more
255
David Chalmers, “Ontological Anti-Realism”, in David Chalmers (ed.), David Manley (ed.) and Ryan
Wasserman (ed.), Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009; Huw Price, “Metaphysics After
Carnap: The Ghost Who Walks?”, in David Chalmers (ed.), David Manley (ed.) and Ryan Wasserman (ed.),
Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009; Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance and Realism,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011; and Amie L. Thomasson, Ontology Made Easy, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2015.
256
David Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds, MA, Blackwell, 1986.
103
dissensus, is more thought-provoking and even more shocking than Foucault’s history of
psychiatry or Derrida’s reading of Nietzsche. Yet, I do not think that Lewis aimed to
provoke dissensus or to shock his readers. In defending modal realism, his aim seems to be
that of reaching consensus. Under the influence of Robert Nozick, Lewis does so by
criticizing coercive uses of language; those that function as implicit threats in ultimately
rendering any kind of “democratic” debate improbable. What characterizes such coercive
use of language are expressions, such as: “you have or must believe the conclusion of my
knockdown argument”. 257 According to Lewis, there seems to be no knockdown argument
in philosophy “or [at least] hardly ever [given that] Gödel and Gettier may have done it”.258
Lewis also presupposes that philosophers are to “measure the price” in attempting
to achieve a common philosophical “equilibrium” 259. By this business-man metaphor
(“measure the price”), Lewis means that after opponents have understood one another’s
philosophical claims as well as articulated their respective arguments and counterarguments, they should take another step: that of comparing their contrasting conjunction
of claims in seeking to spell out which one of them maximizes theoretical virtues.
Influenced by Quine, Lewis presupposes that the theoretical virtues that need consideration
are: “conservatism, generality, simplicity, refutability and modesty”. 260 Lewis does not
precisely spell out whether such virtues have the same or distinct weights. He likewise does
not justify why one is to attempt to maximize such theoretical virtues in the first place.
257
Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1981: pp. 4; and David
Lewis, Philosophical Papers: Volume I, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1983: pp. x. Also see Robert
Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New Jersey, Basic Books, 1974.
258
David Lewis, Philosophical Papers: Volume I, pp. x.
259
Ibid.
260
Willard Van Orman Quine, Pursuit of Truth, MA, Harvard University Press, 1992: pp. 20.
104
What seems utmost important, for him, is that a common philosophical
“equilibrium” is to be reached whenever, after measuring the price of their respective
conjunction of claims, two or more philosophers are convinced that one of such
conjunctions maximizes theoretical virtues in being more likely true than its alternatives.
As indicated in the last chapter, I am influenced by George A. Reisch. This is so in that I
take that, especially after World War II, several (if not most) analytic philosophers who
have been educated and/or employed in research universities in the United States have
taken themselves to be politically neutral. The same, I am inclined to believe, is the case
with those who have studied and/or worked in British or Australian universities. I do not
think that Lewis is an exception to this alleged apolitical analytic tradition. 261 Therefore, I
do not wish to attribute to him a conscious commitment to Carnap’s political task of
promoting “healthy” egalitarian practices, while resisting “diseased” libertarian ones.
However, note that, regardless of his alleged political neutrality, Lewis promotes at
least one egalitarian practice shared by Carnap by simply publishing On the Plurality of
Worlds: the practice of doing philosophy by defending one’s views with detailed arguments
whose rules of inference are widely shared by the community, while opposing and seeking
to convince one’s opponents —at least the superficial opponents who, in Lewis’s case, are
those who, practically speaking, grant that modal realism is to be discussed in the first
place, that is, those who accept that one is to spend some time of one’s life by discussing
modal realism, instead of, say, dealing with other disputes, such as the ones that Nietzsche,
Foucault or Derrida address. In taking this practice for granted, Lewis implicitly resists the
libertarian practice of doing philosophy differently, say, in following Nietzsche, Foucault
261
In conversation, though, Michael Slote told me that Lewis was dismayed by the American Philosophical
Association anti-Vietnam stance and, accordingly, withdrew himself from this organization.
105
or Derrida in relying on more upfront rhetorical devices that challenge any interpretation
and problematize widely shared, but (in these philosophers’ views) very narrow or
simplistic views on what counts, to begin with, as an “argument”, “science”, “logos”, etc.
Examples of such more upfront rhetorical devices are those of: articulating a
conjunction of thought-provoking aphorisms without providing any explicit justification
for them; relying on several poetic statements, such as (NP) discussed in the last chapter,
without explicitly spelling out their meanings; problematizing the distinction between
literal and metaphorical senses; often ironically playing with the dual sense of certain
words; not defining the meaning of technical terms and shifting their senses with context;
mocking one’s opponents in seeking to spell out how hypocritical or at least ignorant they
really are in presupposing simplistic notions of “argument”, “science”, “psychiatric
treatment”, “reason”, “logos”, “justification”, “clarity”, etc. Regardless of whether Lewis
is aware, then, he problematically points to Carnap’s political task and, hence, contradicts
Nietzsche’s. My reading is that the same is the case with van Inwagen.
Regardless of van Inwagen’s apparently and/or purported political neutrality,
throughout his works, he promotes the same egalitarian practice promoted by Carnap and
Lewis. While also criticizing coercive uses of language and pointing toward the
impossibility of knockdown arguments in philosophy, van Inwagen implicitly likewise
resists the same allegedly libertarian practice resisted by Carnap and Lewis. 262 Consider
his 2004 essay, “Freedom to Break the Laws”. This essay explicitly reminds one of
Carnap’s depression. As explained in 2.1, this is the depression concerning the
overwhelming lack of consensus in philosophy that cannot be found in logic and in the
262
Peter van Inwagen, “Freedom to Break the Laws”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXVIII, 2004: pp. 350.
106
empirical sciences. 263 Van Inwagen approaches a traditional theoretical dispute that the
likes of Foucault and Derrida have simply not focused on: that on whether free will and
determinism are compatible. For van Inwagen, this is not the case, whereas Lewis points
to a distinct direction in claiming that free will is, indeed, compatible with determinism.264
Consider that van Inwagen also problematizes the aim pursued by Lewis of
measuring the price while attempting to achieve a common philosophical equilibrium. The
problem, van Inwagen argues, is that even philosophers from the same period (e.g.,
American philosophers who were born in the 1940s, such as van Inwagen and Lewis
themselves) and tradition (e.g., the English-speaking analytic tradition) have not usually
reached a common philosophical equilibrium. 265 Regardless of whether this is so or
whether van Inwagen’s argument for this claim is persuasive, what matters for this
dissertation is that he still seeks to achieve and values consensus. This is attested by the
fact that, counter to Nietzsche, van Inwagen still aims to affect “people’s opinions” on free
will and determinism. 266 This is why, in pursing this goal, he seeks to convince his
opponents —at least the superficial ones, like Lewis himself —that incompatibilism is true
or at least more likely true, plausible or at least persuasive than compatibilism.
What I draw, then, is the fourth claim of the system of disputes; the claim that
(4) The contrast between Nietzsche’s libertarian and Carnap’s egalitarian reaction
is to be considered, not only by the few scholars who are interested in both of
these philosophers’ works, but by a far larger group of philosophers that
includes: those who have addressed the continental-analytic gap; those who are
concerned with the development of the history of 20th and 21st century
263
Ibid., 334-335.
See David Lewis, “Are We Free to Break the Laws?” in Philosophical Papers: Vol. II, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 1986.
265
Peter van Inwagen, “Freedom to Break the Laws”, pp. 340-343.
266
Ibid., pp. 350.
264
107
philosophy; and/or those who are interested in the works of the likes of
Foucault, Derrida, Lewis and/or van Inwagen. 267
My hope, then, is that this group of philosophers, practically speaking, grants me that this
chapter’s practice is pertinent, that is, that, instead of following several (if not most)
continental and analytic philosophers in point toward Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction,
implicitly indicating a commitment to Carnap’s egalitarian one, taking for granted
Nietzsche or Carnap’s political tasks and/or a-critically embracing the stated norms, I am
being pertinent in addressing a distinct kind of theoretical dispute that has not received
attention. The dispute I have in mind is that over the system of disputes’ fifth claim:
(5) One is to do a synthesis of Nietzsche’s libertarian and Carnap’s egalitarian
reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in
disputes.
Now I would like to, first, explain what I mean by this metametaphysical normative claim.
Then, I would like to back it up by relying on an imperfect justificatory resource: the quite
traditional one of articulating an argument in the traditional sense of a conjunction of
premises that establish a conclusion by means of certain widely shared rules of inference.
267
Some philosophers who are part of this group are: Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature,
New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1979; Hillary Putnam Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to Life, Indiana,
Indiana University Press, 2008; Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Inquiry, London, Routledge,
2006; Gary Gutting, What Philosophers Know: Case Studies in Recent Analytic Philosophy, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 2009, Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2011; Adrian W. Moore, The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012; Markus Gabriel, Why the World Does Not Exist, Cambridge,
Polity Press, 2015, and I am not a Brain, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2017; Todd May, Reconsidering
Difference: Nancy, Derrida, Levinas, Deleuze, Pennsylvania, Penn State Press, 1997; Daniel Nolan, David
Lewis, Kingston, McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2005; those who contributed to Jack Reynolds (ed.),
James Chase (ed.), Ed Mares (ed.), and James Williams (ed.), Postanalytic and Metacontinental: Crossing
Philosophical Divides, London, Continuum International Publishing Group, 2010; Scott Soames, The
Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Volume 1: The Founding Giants, New Jersey, Princeton University Press,
2014; The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Volume 2: A New Vision, New Jersey, Princeton University
Press, 2017; those who articulated the essays gathered in John A. Keller, Being, Freedom, and Method:
Themes from the Philosophy of Peter van Inwagen, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2017; etc.
108
3.2 Synthesis
By the practice of doing a synthesis between Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction and
Carnap’s egalitarian one, to put it in a Nietzschean-like metaphorical way, it is to be
understood one comparable to that of preparing a drink. I think, for instance, about
Caipirinha. This is a mix of the Brazilian quite heavy alcoholic drink, cachaça, with three
other “Apollonian” ingredients that attenuate cachaça’s “Dionysian” effects: lemon, sugar
and ice. Let us say that cachaça stands for Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction, whereas the
other ingredients represent Carnap’s egalitarian one. To put it in a more Carnapian-like
literal way, the practice of doing a synthesis between Nietzsche’s reaction and Carnap’s is
that of fulfilling three tasks: first, bringing these contrasting reactions to light, instead of
merely presupposing them, like several continental and analytic philosophers have done
especially after World War II; second, problematizing Nietzsche’s reaction by means of
Carnap’s and vice-versa so that the shortcomings of their projects are avoided; and, third,
still seeking to keep (hopefully positive) aspects of Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s projects of
overcoming metaphysics. The first chapter and 3.1 were my ways of attempting to fulfill
the first of these tasks. I would like to spell out what I mean by the other two tasks now.
Consider that, in relying on his libertarian reaction, Nietzsche sometimes goes as
far as suggesting that persons are to not even attempt to justify their claims or practices; it
would simply not be valuable to be a herd animal in seeking to do so. In Nietzsche’s words,
“honorable things, like honorable people do not go around with their reasons in their hand.
It is indecent to show all five fingers. Nothing with real value needs to be proved first”. 268
There may be passages by Foucault or Derrida that also point to this excessively libertarian
268
TI II 5, my emphasis.
109
direction, even though, instead of giving up the search for any kind of “proof”, these French
philosophers might have merely attempted to problematize what counts as a “proof” as
well as to revise traditional notions of “proof” in relying on the stated upfront rhetorical
devices. On my part, I would like to explicitly object, under the influence of Carnap’s
egalitarian reaction, that the last quoted passage by Nietzsche is a shortcoming of his
project: a shortcoming that indicates that he, indeed, “imprudently” over praises
individualistic tendencies over communitarian ones. The notion of “prudence” will be
discussed in the sixth chapter but, for the time being, I would like to apply it in loose way.
What is important now is to emphasize that Nietzsche “goes too far” in his
libertarianism. Note that he imprudently over praises the likes of “Napoleon”,
“Alcibiades”, “Caesar” and “Hohenstaufen Frederick II”. 269 Under the basis that they
would have lived in accordance with the will to power, Nietzsche takes these types to have
been standards of health, regardless of the overwhelming and not subtle at all violence they
spread. This is not a view that can be found in Foucault’s or in Derrida’s writings. On my
part, I would like to align myself with analytic philosophers to a certain extent. Let me do
so by explicitly claiming that Nietzsche’s view on Napoleon, Alcibiades, Caesar and
Hohenstaufen Frederick II appears to be an “absurd” view that, indeed, provides reasons
for taking Nietzsche to be a proto-Nazi, as Carnap (see 2.4) suggests in his manuscripts. 270
269
BGE 199 and BGE 200.
Note that Bertrand Russell also suggests that Nietzsche is a proto-Nazi. “Suppose”, Russell states, “we
wish — as I certainly do —to fund arguments against Nietzsche’s ethics and politics, what argument can we
find? These are weight practical arguments, showing that the attempt to secure his ends will in fact secure
something quite different. Aristocracies of birth are nowadays discredited; the only practicable form of
aristocracy is an on organization like the Fascist or the Nazi party. Such an organization rouses opposition,
and is likely to be defeated in war; but if it is not defeated it must, before long, become nothing but a police
State, where the rulers live in terror of assassination, and the heroes are in concentration camps. In such a
community faith and honour are sapped by delation, and the would-be aristocracy of supermen degenerates
into a clique of trembling poltroons”. As this passage indicates, Russell and Carnap had quite similar political
views. See Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy, New York, Simon & Schuster, 1945: pp. 770.
270
110
In other words, if Nietzsche took the likes of Napoleon and Caesar to be standards of health,
perhaps, he could have stated the same about Adolf Hitler or Benito Mussolini.
So, against Nietzsche and in embracing the conflictual craft described in the
introduction (see 1.4), I would like to explicitly underline that I am, indeed, committed to
the search for justifications (even if merely imperfect ones) for (1) through (13) as well as
for the practices endorsed here. I also do not praise the likes of Napoleon, Alcibiades,
Caesar, Hohenstaufen Frederick II, Hitler, Mussolini, etc. Moreover, throughout the
dissertation, I rely on Carnap in problematizing Nietzsche’s suggested libertarian picture
of philosophy according to which philosophers have practically only valued
communitarian tendencies and ignored individualist ones. As Carnap indicates (see 2.1),
the mere fact that incompatible systems have been erected points to a distinct direction.
Given that I champion the conflictual craft, I also wish to avoid contradicting (1-i),
that is, the claim that, among the others, some are legitimate rational peers. So, distinct
from Nietzsche, I unambiguously underline that I do not think that those, such as Socrates,
who in Nietzsche’s view overvalue egalitarian practices are not legitimate rational peers
insofar as disputes are concerned. As indicated in 2.3, it is plausible to read Nietzsche as
someone who dogmatically suggests otherwise. Let me also underline that I am not
committed to an over-libertarian claim that sometimes is associated with Nietzsche,
Foucault and/or Derrida: that mental and educational institutions are simply to be
abolished, given that they over constrain people’s singularities. I also do not aim to discuss
whether Nietzsche and/or his followers were really committed to this claim. I tend to think
For a take on Russell’s political views, consider Thomas L. Akehurst, The Cultural Politics of Analytic
Philosophy: Britishness and the Spectre of Europe, London, Continuum, 2010.
111
that these philosophers’ writings are simply quite ambiguous about this claim. Hence, I
would have to spend several pages in spelling out whether they really embrace it.
On his part, Carnap relies on his egalitarian reaction in going as far as claiming that
those who do metaphysics (in the two Carnapian senses) rely on a cognitively meaningless
use of language, that is, a use of language that disrespects Carnap’s early conditions for
cognitive meaning embraced in the 1931 “Überwindung der Metaphysik” and discussed in
2.3. Carnap, as it is well-known, attenuates such conditions, at least as early as in his 1937
“Logical Syntax of Language”. In the latter work, he embraces the “Principle of Tolerance:
It is not our business to set up prohibitions, but to arrive at conventions”. 271 He also states
that “in logic, there are no morals”. 272 The reason is that “everyone is at liberty to build up
his own logic, i.e., his own form of language, as he wishes. All that is required of him is
that, if he wishes to discuss it, he must state his method clearly, and give syntactical rules
instead of philosophical arguments”. 273 Also consider the 1950s Carnap, such as the one
of “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology”. It is not my aim to address this essay in detail
here. 274 However, it is safe to assume that this paper suggests the following broader late
condition for cognitive meaning: words and statements have cognitive meaning if and only
if they respect the syntactical and semantical rules of any conventional formal language
whatsoever. The late Carnap calls these formal languages “linguistic frameworks”.
Note that, like most contemporary analytic philosophers, Lewis and van Inwagen
embrace neither Carnap’s early nor his late conditions for cognitive meaning. On my part,
271
Rudolf Carnap, Logical Syntax of Language, London, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co Ltd, 1937, pp.
51.
272
Ibid., pp. 52.
273
Ibid., my emphasis.
274
I address this paper more carefully in Felipe G. A. Moreira, “An Apology of Carnap”, Manuscrito
(Unicamp), Vol 37, Número 2, 2014: pp.261-289.
112
under the influence of Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction, I would like to explicitly object to
these conditions. I do so by taking them to be a shortcoming of Carnap’s project; a
shortcoming that shows that, throughout his career, he imprudently over praises
communitarian tendencies over individualist ones in taking for granted the problematic
assumption that only formal languages conventionally adopted by a community that
masters the precise rules of such languages lead to cognition. To use Carnap’s terms, this
assumption is one that requires “philosophical arguments”. In often suggesting otherwise,
Carnap appears “naïve”. In making this last claim, I align myself with continental
philosophers to a certain extent. I am also on the side of continental philosophers in taking
that it seems quite “naïve” to follow Carnap in believing that formal languages, such as
those that Carnap articulated throughout his career, are “clearer” than ordinary ones.
In fact, as others, such as Karl-Otto Apel, indicate, it appears that it is inevitably by
means of ordinary languages that formal ones are to be interpreted in the end. 275 Hence, it
seems “naïve” to believe that the adoption of formal languages will decrease the level of
dissensus in philosophy. As Lewis and van Inwagen themselves indicate, the history of 20th
and 21st century analytic philosophy attests to the opposite, that is, the adoption of formal
languages has not made analytic philosophers achieve consensus with one another. In fact,
they seem to disagree as much as continental philosophers. 276 Contrary to Carnap, then, I
am not committed to any condition for cognitive meaning. I also do not aim to articulate
or rely on a formal language. Indeed, it is important to add that, contrary to Carnap’s
275
See Karl-Otto Apel, Selected Essays Volume Two: Ethics and the Theory of Rationality, New Jersey,
Humanities Press, 1996.
276
Consider, for instance, only the replies to Lewis’s modal realism, such as: Gideon Rosen, “Modal
Fictionalism”, Mind, Vol. 99, No. 395, Jul., 1990: pp. 327-354; Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra, “Modal Realism
and Metaphysical Nihilism”, Mind, 113 (452), 2004: pp. 683-704; Otávio Bueno and Scott Shalkowski,
“Modalism and Theoretical Virtues: Toward an Epistemology of Modality”, Philosophical Studies 172,
2015: pp. 671-689; etc.
113
intentions, the adoption of such languages by faculty members of philosophy departments
in the USA, the UK and Australia has, arguably, not fulfilled any “socialist” purpose, but,
rather a quite elitist one: that of creating a considerably narrow community of analytic
philosophers who are practically only interested in discussing with other analytic
philosophers about allegedly “specific” disputes by means of formal or quasi-formal
languages whose rules are simply ignored by non-analytic philosophers. It is also not this
dissertation’s goal to deal with the epistemic dispute over the conditions for knowledge.
Moreover, throughout the dissertation, I rely on Nietzsche in putting into question
Carnap’s suggested egalitarian picture of philosophy according to which philosophers have
practically only valued individualist tendencies and ignored communitarian ones. As
Nietzsche indicates, the fact that philosophers have taken Socratic or Platonic values for
granted points to another direction. As stated above, I am a conflictual crafter who takes
others to be legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake. So, I also depart from
Carnap’s project because I claim that those who over-value libertarian practices, such as,
arguably, Heidegger, are legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are concerned. As
also indicated in 2.3, Carnap may be interpreted as someone who points to a distinct
direction. Finally, I also do not presuppose, as Carnap often does (see 2.2), that “rational”
is a term that mainly or, perhaps, even exclusively refers to the inquiries in the formal
sciences and in the empirical sciences. This is, as I take that most contemporary analytic
philosophers themselves would concur, a quite narrow use of the term “rational”: a use that
likewise requires “philosophical arguments” that are simply lacking in Carnap’s works.
The system of disputes, yet, still seeks to do justice to Carnap’s project of
overcoming metaphysics. The reason is quite simple: in seeking to justify (1) through (13)
114
and the very practices performed by this dissertation, I am simply not doing metaphysics
in either one of the two Carnapian senses stated in 2.2. To begin with, I am sympathetic to
Carnap’s view that, to say, the least, it is quite unpersuasive to back up object-level
metaphysical claims (e.g., there is evil, a thing-in-itself or consciousness) by engaging
oneself in a neither mathematical nor empirical inquiry, but a rather “purely intuitive
process”. 277 It is important to underline, though, that Carnap does not precisely spell out
what he means by such a “purely intuitive process”. As indicated in 2.2, what he does,
instead, is to merely suggest that this process would be an emotional process as opposed to
the rational justificatory process found in the formal and in the empirical sciences. It is also
important to underline that, more recently, there has been a lot of debate on what is an
intuition and on whether an intuition is a reliable justificatory resource insofar as, not only
the disputes associated with metaphysics focused on here are concerned, but also several
other quarrels on other areas of philosophy, mathematics and/or logic. Consider Herman
Cappelen and Elijah Chudnoff; their works attest to the presence of such ongoing debate. 278
On my part, I cannot provide a detailed discussion of intuitions. Instead, I limit
myself to make a distinction between two uses of intuition-talk exclusively regarding the
disputes associated with metaphysics considered here. I call them the dogmatic use and the
conflictual use. The dogmatic use is that of suggesting that one’s intuition about a dispute
is universally shared by all persons and, hence, provides a rationally undeniable
justification for one’s claim regarding the dispute at stake. The conflictual use is that of
taking an intuition about a dispute to be simply the tendency of being persuaded by a certain
277
LSW 295.
See Herman Cappelen, Philosophy Without Intuitions, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012; and Elijah
Chudnoff, Intuiton, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013.
278
115
claim, regardless of argument. Such a tendency is not universally shared by all persons
and, consequently, merely provides a considerably imperfect justificatory resource that
might be challenged by others who simply do not share one’s intuition about the dispute at
stake. I think that Carnap’s objection to metaphysics becomes much more persuasive if by
a “purely intuitive process”, it is interpreted that what he meant was a process of justifying
one’s claims by very problematically adopting the dogmatic use of intuition-talk.
On my part, I am inspired by Carnap in opposing this dogmatic use under the basis
that, to say the least, it lacks persuasiveness insofar as basic observation of the history of
metaphysics indicates that persons have had all sorts of contrasting intuitions about
disputes. I am not alone in making this last move. Consider Lewis; he points to a similar
direction in problematizing any kind of “‘linguistic intuition’, which must be taken as
unchallengeable evidence” 279. This is not to state that I oppose myself to the conflictual
use of intuition-talk that merely purports to provide challengeable evidence that others
might and are likely to put into question. In fact, I would like to go as far as stating that I
take (1) through (13) to be quite “intuitive” claims in this conflictual sense. Also notice
that there are several philosophical writings in which it is simply very hard to understand
whether the author adopted a dogmatic or a conflictual use of intuition-talk. In addressing
works by Quine, Saul Kripke and Kit Fine, I will discuss this matter in the fifth chapter.
For now, I underline that, as indicated in 1.1, the claims of the system of disputes
are not object-level metaphysical ones, but, rather, metametaphysical claims of two kinds:
descriptive and normative ones. In backing them up, I take myself to proceed empirically,
that is, as a singular kind of observer —that of the history of metaphysics itself or, in other
279
David Lewis, Philosophical Papers: Volume I, pp. x, my emphasis.
116
words, the history of disputes that have occurred since immemorial times. This is someone
whose data are philosophical writings themselves; someone whose specialty is that of
having the proper philosophical education to interpret such writings that have been
articulated, since Ancient Greece up to our time. In spelling out such interpretation (that is,
in observing such writings), the observer of the history of metaphysics is the one who seeks
to imperfectly justify one’s descriptive and normative metametaphysical claims. There is
nothing “mysterious”, “irrational”, “exclusively emotional” and/or derogatorily
“metaphysical” in the two Carnapian senses about such procedure of mine. 280
Indeed, this dissertation, to a certain extent, aligns itself with Carnap’s political task
implicitly followed by the likes of Lewis and van Inwagen. This is because I follow them
in aiming to: avoid relying on a coercive use of language that threats the possibility of any
“democratic” dialogue; promote the traditional egalitarian practice of articulating detailed
arguments (in the traditional sense) to justify my views, while objecting to those of others
who disagree with my views; and resist overly libertarian practices. Examples of such
practices are those of insinuating that one is to not justify one’s view; going as far as
implying that mental and educational institutions are to be abolished; and adopting the
stated upfront rhetorical devices. In other words, it is evident that my procedure has simply
not been that of articulating aphorisms or poetic statements, such as (NP). I have not put
into question the distinction between literal and metaphorical senses. Instead, whenever I
use a metaphor, I explicitly indicate so. I have also not played with the dual sense of certain
words. I have also spelled out the meaning of all the technical words adopted here. In
280
As it will be indicated in 7.4., the connections with this procedure and those of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel is an issue which I would like to approach in the future. The same is the case with two other disputes:
that on whether my procedure could also be used to back up object-level metaphysical claims, and that on
whether there can be a precise distinction between the latter claims and metametaphysical ones.
117
addition, in order to avoid misunderstandings, I have not mocked my opponents. Rather,
what I will do in the next chapters is to very explicitly (and with no irony) object to my
deep opponents’ practices, that is, to the very way they have done philosophy. Indeed, the
only word I use in a sort of ironic way are is the word “subtle” within the expression
““subtle” violence”, that is, as I proceed, I wish to make explicit that the kinds of violence
I have in mind are not really subtle, but merely less easily identifiable than corporeal kinds
of violence. This is why I always apply the term “subtle” within quotation marks.
What I mean is that, distinct from Nietzsche and his French followers, such as
Foucault and Derrida, I have adopted a considerably simple use of the English language
that hopefully more persons (or at least philosophers, both analytic and continental ones)
can understand, and is less likely to be called “obscure”. I will provide further reasons for
embracing this perhaps more “democratic” use of language in the sixth chapter as well as
for acknowledging that this use (like most, if not all, philosophical ones) is still an “elitist”
use insofar as it is naïve to think that those who have not attended College are likely to
easily follow my points. In the sixth chapter, I also explicitly reply to those who still think
that my use of language is “obscure” at least with regard to those of analytic philosophers
whose uses of language are allegedly more “ordinary”. For now, to put it once again in
more Nietzschean-like metaphorical terms, what is crucial is to emphasize the following:
the fact that I am no pure cachaça drinker does not me make me a lemonade drinker.
What I mean by this is that I likewise seek to do justice to Nietzsche’s project of
overcoming metaphysics. The reason is also quite simple: in seeking to justify (1) through
(13) and the very practices performed by this dissertation, I am likewise not doing
metaphysics in the Nietzschean sense spelled out in 2.2 To begin with and as indicated by
118
the fact that I do not commit myself to object-level metaphysical claims, I follow Nietzsche
(as well as Carnap, like indicated in 2.4) in remaining neutral on any kind of dispute over
any kind of realism (“true world”) and any kind of idealism (“illusory world”). In addition,
this dissertation is neutral on the disputes (see 1.1 and 2.2) that God-driven, human-driven
and physicalist-driven philosophers have focused on. Note that the bibliography on such
disputes is simply too extensive. 281 I do not purport to have anything to add to it in here.
What I do, rather, is to articulate, and deal with other metametaphysical disputes that have
received less attention. In the next chapters, I aim to make this even more explicit. In doing
so, it is to become evident that I am not at all micro-politically neutral insofar as I explicitly
wish to criticize the right-wing approach to disputes, while endorsing the left-wing one.
For now, let me also grant Nietzsche that the pursuit of certainty makes little sense.
As indicated in 1.4, conflictual crafters are aware that the existence of some others as
persons indicates that certainty does seem to be obtainable (at least not insofar as the
disputes related to “metaphysics” addressed here are concerned). This occurs because
others are those who reject any criterion one may propose. Hence, I agree with Carnap (see
2.1) in believing that philosophers have neither established any common non-controversial
criterion to deal with their disputes, nor articulated compatible systems. Nonetheless, I
would like to take a further step that Carnap himself never takes in an upfront manner: that
of explicitly recognizing myself as being likewise unable to establish such a non-
281
For all kinds of takes on God-driven, human-driven and physicalist-driven disputes, see the texts
respectively collected at: Michael Peterson, The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings, Indiana, Notre Dame
University Press, 2017; Karl Ameriks, The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 2000; and David Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and
Contemporary Readings, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2002.
119
controversial criterion or to erect a system that would be compatible with others. The
consequences of this move will be more explicitly spelled out in the next chapters.
Finally, and perhaps most importantly, I am also aligned with Nietzsche’s project
of overcoming metaphysics insofar as I seek to avoid some hierarchical oppositions of
value, such as those often presupposed by philosophers at least since Plato’s allegory of
the cave, say, between rationality and irrationality, clarity and darkness, etc. The reason
the term “some” was emphasized will be spelled in what follows. First, let me dare to state
that I problematize such hierarchical oppositions of values quite differently and perhaps
even more radically than Nietzsche himself. Consider that, regardless of his view (already
discussed in 2.4) that one needs “health” as much as one needs “sickness”, Nietzsche
constantly overvalues dissensus over consensus. He also often overvalues libertarian
practices over egalitarian ones as well as individualistic tendencies over communitarian
ones. In short, Nietzsche claims that to be in accordance with the will to power is more
valuable than to be in accordance with Carnap’s will to order. In doing so, Nietzsche
establishes a new hierarchical opposition of value of his own. The same can be stated about
Carnap himself. As indicated above, in contrast to Nietzsche, he overvalues consensus,
egalitarian practices, communitarian tendencies and the will to order over dissensus,
libertarian practices, individualistic tendencies and the will to power, respectively. I avoid
this move. My way of doing so is by supporting (5), a claim that can also be stated as:
(5)` One is to act in accordance with the will to synthesis.
In coining such a will to synthesis, I aim —metaphorically speaking once again—
to do a caipirinha in mixing Nietzsche’s will to power with Carnap’s will to order.
However, it is crucial to stress out that I do not need to go as far as taking the will to
120
synthesis to be another human-yet-physicalist conception of what Heidegger calls Being
(as discussed in 2.2), that is, I am not committed to the claim that Being is to stand in some
sort of non-causal relation with the will to synthesis. To establish this highly controversial
object-level point would require more than I settle myself to achieve in this dissertation.
Here, I am also not doing metaphysics in the Heideggerian sense discussed in 2.2. For my
purposes, the will to synthesis may be understood as a bit less metaphysically loaded
notion: the tendency (already stated in 1.5) to either consciously or unconsciously embrace
the very contradictory conflict between one’s communitarian tendencies (or will to order)
and one’s individualistic tendencies (or will to power), while seeking to maximize and
achieve a balance that prudently satisfies both of these tendencies, even if to perfectly
achieve such a balance may be ultimately impossible for inevitably imperfect persons. Note
that individualist tendencies and communitarian ones seem to be present in all persons.
Moreover, these tendencies may be called by other names, say, respectively, the one
principle and the many principle; or the identity principle and the singularity principle.
Note that were all persons able to perfectly satisfy either their individualist
tendencies (the many or the singularity principle) or their communitarian tendencies (the
one principle or the identity principle), disputes would likely end: persons, as Nietzsche
wishes, would either fulfill the task of ceasing to care about what their opponents think
about their views in ultimately isolating themselves from any community or herd; or, as
Carnap wishes, they would satisfy the task of embracing a common widely shared noncontroversial criterion to solve disputes in ultimately nullifying anything that is unique
about themselves. To be in accordance with one’s will to synthesis is to acknowledge
oneself as being unable to do either one of these tasks perfectly; it is to recognize oneself
121
as failing to fulfill the former task because of one’s urges to engage oneself in the latter
(and vice-versa). To put it metaphorically, it is to take oneself as being both a bird of prey
and a little lamb that needs a herd. It follows that to be in accordance with the will to
synthesis is to seek what might be ultimately impossible: to actualize an ideal community
that would include all beings or at least all persons and whose norms and institutions would
not constrain but allow all singularities to be expressed. Indeed, I would like to go as far as
imagining that this ideal community would be one in which the very distinction between
egalitarianism and libertarianism would cease to matter. This is so insofar as one’s
individualistic tendencies would confound themselves with communitarian ones and viceversa). Ultimately, then, the will to power would be identical to the will to order.
Also note that to defend that one is to act in accordance with the will to synthesis
is to establish another hierarchical opposition of values: that between doing so, like I
purport to do; and failing do to so, as most philosophers have done, like the next two
chapters aim to show. Indeed, it might be ultimately impossible to avoid all hierarchical
oppositions of values; one would have to fulfill what may be the ultimate wish of skeptics,
that of being neutral regarding practices themselves. Thus, I have not stated above that I
avoid all hierarchical oppositions of value, but only some of them, such as the very ones
supported by Nietzsche and by Carnap. It also important to underline that I do not take that
my deep opponents who fail to act in accordance with the will to synthesis to not be
legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake. Instead, I acknowledge the
legitimate rational stance of such deep opponents of mine while, still, aiming to pressure
them to drop their practices and at least accept the way I want to spend some of the time of
122
my life in engaging myself on practices distinct from theirs. This will become more explicit
as I proceed, especially in the sixth chapter and in the dissertation’s conclusion.
For now, notice that a third way to state (5) runs as follows:
(5)``
One is to react to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been
engaged in disputes, by: defending claims that are both to provoke dissensus
with some persons (say, one’s superficial and deep opponents) and which
are to be consensually embraced by others (say, one’s deep allies who
embrace both one’s practices and claims), while promoting some egalitarian
as well as libertarian practices and resisting other likewise egalitarian and
libertarian practices.
This is to state that I expect that (1) through (13) will simultaneously provoke dissensus
(and perhaps, even shock or embarrass) some persons and be consensually accepted by
others. Let me emphasize that, under the influence of Carnap’s egalitarian reaction and
political task, I already indicated above that I seek to avoid using coercive use of language,
while promoting at least one egalitarian practice and resisting excessively libertarian ones.
Under the influence of Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction and his political task, I state that I
also seek to promote at least one libertarian practice similar to those championed by
Foucault and Derrida: that of problematizing the excessive constraints philosophical
institutions (e.g., departments of philosophy, journals and publishing companies) impose
upon the singularities of their members, especially, say, “trans-non-binary-philosophers”.
Trans-non-binary philosophers are those who, like myself, and the likes of Richard
Rorty, Hilary Putnam, Bernard Williams, Gary Gutting, Adrian W. Moore and Markus
Gabriel, are interested in responding both to the continental tradition and to the analytic
tradition. 282 What I mean is that I do not feel much more inclined towards any of these two
282
Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature; Hillary Putnam, Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to
Life; Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Inquiry; Gary Gutting, What Philosophers Know and
123
traditions —a feeling that, I almost wish to be naïve enough to believe, more easily arises
in those who, like myself, were born neither in wealthy English-speaking countries, such
as the United States, the UK and Australia, nor in wealthy continental European ones, such
as France and Germany. 283 What I also mean is that I feel like an other regarding both the
continental and the analytic tradition. Hence, I take that, to say the least, it is quite “absurd”
and/or considerably “naïve” to address exclusively one of these traditions, as if the other
did not exist. Accordingly, I resist the excessively egalitarian practice of those who do so,
say, for the sake of overly paying respect to the ones who take the aforementioned norms
for granted, while relying on strategically narrow bibliographies that consider either the
continental tradition or the analytic one but never both of them. My “faith”, then, is also
that “serious philosophers” would simply stop relying on such narrow bibliographies.
3.3 An Argument
I endorse (5) because of a four-premise deductive argument whose first premise is:
P.1
An explanation for the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have
been engaged in disputes is that they have relied on problematic starting
points.
Thinking the Impossible; Adrian W. Moore, The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things;
and Markus Gabriel, Why the World Does Not Exist and I am not a Brain.
283
I emphasize the phrase “I almost wish to be naïve enough to believe” because there appears to be kinds of
colonialism that make several non-North American and non-European philosophers, such as Brazilian
philosophers, spend their whole careers overly paying respect to analytic or continental philosophers, say, as
if their roles in life was to interpret, defend and, more or less, a-critically spread the latter philosophers’
works. Neo-Pyrrhonists, such as Oswaldo Porchat and Otávio Bueno, seem to be one of the few exceptions
to this situation. I cannot, though, approach the problem of this kind of colonialism here. Consider,
nonetheless, Pierre Bourdieu and Jessé de Souza; they have both argued, that in taking for granted
assumptions of European and/or U.S. sociologists, Brazilian sociologists have constantly misrepresented
Brazil’s reality. Also consider that it could objected that my very aim to connect analytic and continental
philosophy is one of someone who has also been colonized. This is an interesting objection that I aim to
address in a future project, say, one in which conditions for calling a person or a work colonized are spelled
out in detail. See Jessé de Souza, A tolice da inteligência brasileira: ou como o país se deixa manipular pela
elite, São Paulo, Leya, 2015; and Pierre Bourdieu, Escritos de educação, Rio de Janeiro, Vozes, 1998.
124
A starting point, as stated in 1.2, is a “self-evident” undeniable metaphysical claim or
criterion to deal with a dispute: one that no person may rationally reject and that ultimately
justifies all other claims and practices endorsed by the one who proposes the starting point.
By a problematic starting point, on the other hand, it is to be understood one that merely
imperfectly justifies all other claims, and practices endorsed by the one who proposes it.
This is to state that such problematic starting points are not undeniable metaphysical claims
or non-controversial criteria to deal with disputes. Rather, such points may be easily
problematized by others who simply do not grant one’s underlying assumptions. The last
chapter as well as the above sections of this chapter are my ways of imperfectly justifying
the claim that: the libertarian reaction is a problematic starting point of Nietzsche and his
followers, such as Foucault and Derrida, whereas the egalitarian reaction is a problematic
starting point of Carnap and those influenced by him, such as Lewis and van Inwagen.
Note that the philosophers named in the last phrase are not the only ones who have
embraced problematic starting points. Consider God-driven, human-driven and physicalistdriven philosophers. These philosophers, as indicated above, are deep opponents of one
another. This is so insofar as they simply do not agree on the practical dispute concerning
which disputes are to be approached in the first place, that is, the practical dispute on how,
to begin with, one is to spend the time of one’s life. My view is that God-driven, humandriven and physicalist-driven philosophers are likewise ultimately unable to justify their
implicit views on such practical dispute, without appealing to any problematic starting
point. Take into account God-driven philosophers. They have presupposed as a problematic
starting point either the claim that one is to address the God-driven disputes or any other
claim that imperfectly justifies this practical proposal. Examples of such imperfect
125
justifications are claims, such as the following ones: one is to respect Christian scriptures;
one is to think and act in accordance with such scriptures as well as not contradict the
science of one’s time; one is to spell out that there is a harmony between logos and faith;
one is to release oneself from evil (at least to the extent that human beings can do so) in
being less prone to sin and becoming oneself more “holy”; one is to ultimately aim to
satisfy God’s will itself, like biblical figures, such as Abraham, have aimed to do; etc. 284
Human-driven philosophers have also presupposed as a problematic starting point
either the claim that one is to address the human-driven disputes or any other claim that
imperfectly justifies why one is to do so in the first place. Examples of such claims are:
one is to “critically” spell out what conditions human experience; one is to not take oneself
as being able to think over and above such conditions; one is to strive toward a more just
political community in showing that these conditions are contingent ones that have
ultimately served to exclude people, such as those who come from the lower classes,
women or black-skinned people; given that God does not exist, the only will one may
satisfy is that of thinking and acting in accordance with a human logos; etc. 285
Physicalist-driven philosophers are similar to God-driven and human-driven. This
occurs because they have also presupposed as a problematic starting point the claim that
one is to deal with physicalist-driven disputes or at least one claim that imperfectly backs
up this attitude, such as: one is to think in accordance with the assumption that
contemporary empirical sciences (especially, physics) are an ultimately authority
284
For more recent takes on problematic starting points, such as these, consider Alvin Plantinga, God,
Freedom, and Evil, New York, Harper and Row, 1974; as well as Peter van Inwagen, The Problem of Evil,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006.
285
For a detailed discussion of problematic starts points embraced by human-driven philosophers, such as
these, see Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, London,
Continuum, 2008.
126
concerning what there is and, hence, provide knowledge of thing-in-themselves; one is to
proceed in a way that is analogous to those of mathematicians and/or empirical scientists;
one is to contribute to make approaches to disputes as respectable as those of
mathematicians and/or empirical scientists to their disagreements; one has to react to what
physicalist-driven philosophers (who usually work in research universities in wealthy
English-speaking countries) have published over the last fifty years; etc.
What I mean is that physicalist-driven philosophers have often presupposed that
philosophers’ purpose is to pursue the last paragraph’s goals. God-driven and humandriven philosophers have simply not done so, that is, they presuppose that philosophers are
to proceed differently. More directly, they take that to do philosophy is to do something
distinct than what physicalist-driven philosophers have done. It follows that, in observing
the history of metaphysics, I simply do not recognize any philosopher whatsoever who has
been able to start without presupposing any problematic starting point. Indeed, were
anyone able to do so while approaching any dispute, it is very likely that at least one dispute
would have been solved once and for all. However, this does not seem to be possible.
The second premise for my argument for (5) runs as follows:
P.2
If P.1, it might be ultimately impossible for persons not to implicitly
embrace (5).
I used and italicized the term “might” because my observation of the history of metaphysics
only backs up an empirical claim —that philosophers have relied on problematic starting
points. This claim is not to be confounded with a much more problematic modal claim:
namely, that it is simply impossible for philosophers to not rely on problematic starting
points. I do not need to embrace this claim, that is, I do not want to make any predictions
127
concerning how future philosophers (say, from one thousand years from now) will proceed.
What I do is to claim that to implicitly embrace (5) is to perform two practices.
First, it is to resist at least one egalitarian practice, while promoting at least one
libertarian practice; respectively, say, the egalitarian practice of following an established
tradition that does not embrace a claim that one aims to defend; and the opposite libertarian
practice of committing oneself to at least one claim that has the feature of provoking some
dissensus insofar as not all persons embrace it. Note that this is a feature of Nietzsche’s
libertarian reaction insofar as this reaction was obviously not accepted by all, that is,
analytic philosophers, such as Carnap, Lewis and van Inwagen, have evidently not
embraced it. This is also a feature of Carnap’s egalitarian reaction. This is so insofar as this
reaction was also not accepted by all; the likes of Foucault and Derrida, for instance, do
not embrace it. In fact, note that the stated claims that God-driven, human-driven and
physicalist-driven philosophy have implicitly adopted as problematic starting points also
have the feature of provoking some dissensus because not all persons have embraced them.
The second practice is to resist at least one libertarian practice, while promoting at
least one egalitarian practice; respectively, say, the libertarian practice of causing dissensus
with all persons; and the practice of defending at least one claim that has a particular
feature: that of causing some consensus insofar as there is at least one person (besides the
ones who proposes the claim) who agrees with oneself. This is also a feature of Nietzsche’s
libertarian reaction. As indicated above, this reaction has been embraced by Foucault and
Derrida. Therefore, not all persons have disagreed or been shocked by Nietzsche. In fact,
he has been one of the most influential philosophers of all times. Carnap’s egalitarian
reaction has also obviously caused some consensus insofar as analytic philosophers, such
128
as Lewis and van Inwagen, have been influenced by it. Furthermore, consider once again
all the stated claims that God-driven, human-driven and physicalist-driven philosophy have
implicitly adopted as problematic starting points. All of these claims have caused some
consensus insofar they have evidently been accepted by more than one person.
So, what I empirically claim insofar as the observer of the history of metaphysics
is that, since immemorial times, persons have performed the two practices described in the
last two paragraphs, that is, this observation indicates that it might be impossible for
persons to do otherwise. What, on the other hand, no one has done is to argue that:
P.3
It is more valuable (and more “realist”) to be self-aware of oneself in
explicitly embracing (5) than to lack self-awareness in implicitly doing so.
To paraphrase Nietzsche, this premise implies that it is more valuable to become who we
already are as persons than to aim to be something we might be ultimately unable to be,
such as: someone or something that exclusively values dissensus, libertarian practices,
individualistic tendencies and the will to power, while ignoring one’s urges for consensus,
egalitarian practices, communitarian tendencies and the will to order. To paraphrase
Carnap, P.3 implies that it is more valuable to be self-aware of oneself than to succumb to
self-delusion. By self-delusion here, it is to be understood the action of taking oneself to
be able to exclusively value consensus, egalitarian practices, communitarian tendencies
and the will to order, while ignoring one’s needs for dissensus, libertarian practices,
individualistic tendencies and the will to power. To paraphrase both Nietzsche’s and
Carnap’s clinical vocabulary, what I would like to suggest with P.3. is that the singular
healthy mentioned in 1.4 that I pursue is that of imperfectly managing to do justice to the
will to synthesis. Accordingly, what I do is to take that “sickness” is to be applied to those
129
who act in discordance with such will. This sickness is superficially expressed whenever
one is imprudent in either following Nietzsche (and perhaps, the likes of Foucault and
Derrida too) in being “too libertarian” or doing the opposite, that is, to imprudently follow
Carnap (and perhaps, the likes of Lewis and van Inwagen too) in being “too egalitarian”.
However, it is important to emphasize the following: as this very chapter purports
to have shown, I have obviously been influenced by Nietzsche, Foucault and Derrida as
well as Carnap, Lewis and van Inwagen, even though I problematize their problematic
starting points. So, regardless of the upfront differences between these philosophers, what
this chapter has aimed to make explicit is that my disagreements with them are all
secondary ones. The same can be stated about those who might suspend judgement on (1)
through (13) but embrace the very practice of discussing these claims or at least that of
allowing me to do so. On the other hand, the deep opponents of this dissertation are those
who express a much deeper “sickness” that disaccords with the will to synthesis more
intensively. The “sickness” I have in mind takes place when one manages to be neither
libertarian nor egalitarian, but a close-minded conservative in expressing the kinds of
“subtle” violence mentioned in 1.5. I will address my deep opponents in the next two
chapters. For the time being, I emphasize once again that in calling them “sick”, I merely
wish to pressure them to drop their practices. However, as already indicated above, I take
these deep opponents of mine to be legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake.
The fourth and last premise for my argument for (5) is that:
P.4
If the consequent of P.2 is the case as well as P.3, (5).
By modus ponens from P.1 and P.2, the consequent of P.2 follows. Hence, a conjunction
between P.3 and this consequent can be inserted. By modus ponens from this conjunction
130
and P.4, P.4’s consequent follows. Hence, my argument’s conclusion is: (5), the system of
dispute’s fifth claim according to which one is to do a synthesis of Nietzsche’s libertarian
and Carnap’s egalitarian reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have
been engaged in disputes. This is to state, as (5)` indicates, that one is to act in accordance
with the will to synthesis. This is also to state, as (5)`` indicates, that one is to react to the
fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes, by: defending
claims that are both to provoke dissensus with some persons and which are to be
consensually embraced by others, while promoting some egalitarian and libertarian
practices as well as resisting other likewise egalitarian and libertarian practices.
CHAPTER 4
UNDENIABLE METAPHYSICAL CLAIMS, “SUBTLE” VIOLENCE AND
PERSONHOOD 286
4.1 A Curious Thing About Ontological Disputes
“A curious thing”, to paraphrase Willard Van Orman Quine, about ontological
disputes is that they often only arise after at least one problematic claim is made or at least
taken seriously. 287 Consider the ontological disputes that God-driven, human-driven and
physicalist-driven philosophers have focused on: respectively, those on whether there is
evil, a thing-in-itself and consciousness. Respectively, these disputes only arise after the
following highly controversial claims are embraced or taken seriously: Being (in the
Heideggerian sense stated in 2.2) is to stand in some sort of non-causal relation with God;
Being is to stand in some sort of non-causal relation with that which conditions human
experience; and Being is to stand in some sort of non-causal relation with a neither divine
nor properly human, such as the particles postulated by physics. Once these claims (also
discussed in 2.2) are embraced or at least taken seriously, a tension arises: that between the
practice of embracing such claims and that of endorsing the existence of evil, a thing-initself and consciousness. Apparently, one cannot have both of these practices consistently.
It is not surprising, then, that a traditional stance has been the eliminativist approach
of rejecting the existence of the entity at stake while supporting or at least keeping an open
mind concerning the highly controversial claim that apparently runs in tension with the
entity’s existence. Consider that God-driven, human-driven and physicalist-driven
286
This chapter is an extended version of a talk I gave at the 2018 Düsseldorf Graduate Workshop, What Do
We Do When We Do Metaphysics?.
287
Willard Van Orman Quine, “On what there is”, The Review of Metaphysics Vol. 2. No. 5, Sep., 1948: pp.
21.
131
132
philosophers extremely distinct from one another, such as Saint Augustine, Johann Gottlieb
Fichte and Daniel Dennett, have all endorsed the eliminativist approach. Respectively,
these philosophers rejected the existence of evil, of a thing-in-itself and that of
consciousness. 288 It is not this dissertation’s aim, though, to discuss the persuasiveness of
these moves. Indeed, as indicated above (see 3.2), the goal of making a significant
contribution to the ontological disputes on evil, a thing-in-itself or consciousness is a
considerably hardly achievable one, given the extensive literature on such issues.
Accordingly, what I propose to do, instead, is to develop a distinct kind of
eliminativist approach: that of rejecting the existence of an entity whose existence has
rarely been discussed, while keeping an open mind concerning another highly controversial
claim that apparently runs in tension with this entity’s existence and has likewise rarely
been addressed. I will spell out this highly controversial claim in what follows. First,
consider the entity whose existence has rarely been discussed that I have in mind. I call it
an undeniable metaphysical claim. As stated above (see 1.1), an undeniable metaphysical
claim is one that may be associated with metaphysics and that each and every person is to
endorse in order to count as a legitimate rational peer concerning a certain dispute at stake.
Note that, distinct from the ontological disputes over evil, a thing-in-itself and
consciousness, the one over the existence of such undeniable metaphysical claim is not an
object-level dispute. Rather, this is a descriptive metametaphysical dispute that concerns
288
Saint Augustine, Enchiridion on Faith, Hope, and Love, trans., Albert C. Outler, London, Aeterna Press,
2014: chapter 4; Johann Gottlieb Fichte, The Science of Knowledge, trans., Peter Heath and John Lachs,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982: pp 45 (I, 472); and Daniel Dennett, “Quining Qualia” in A.
J. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds.), Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1988.
Note that these three works were respectively written around 420, 1794-1795 and the late 1980s.
133
what philosophers, such as Aristotle and his more or less unconscious followers, have
suggested about their works.
What I empirically conclude as an observer of the history of metaphysics is that
most Western philosophers have not carefully observed this history. It is not surprising,
then, that they have more or less unconsciously followed Aristotle in adopting the dogmatic
craft discussed in 1.2 or crafts quite similar to the dogmatic one, while suggesting that their
works attest to the existence of at least one undeniable metaphysical claim. The following
claims are examples of claims that, as it will be shown in what follows, Aristotle, Saint
Anselm, David Hume, Immanuel Kant, Ludwig Wittgenstein and Eli Hirsch have
respectively suggested to be undeniable metaphysical ones: there are no impossible entities
(that is, those that have and lack the very same property, such as that of being and not being
round); God exists; religious and/or metaphysical claims are superstitions; critical
philosophy spells out the transcendental conditions for cognitive experience; disputes arise
due to our failure to understand the logic of our language; and ordinary language is not
committed to mereological sums, such as that of a person’s nose and the Eiffel Tower. 289
Whether any of such claims is true or persuasive is irrelevant for my purposes.
What I aim to do is to support the system of disputes’ sixth claim according to which
289
Aristotle, Metaphysics, in Jonathan Barnes (ed.), Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 2: The Revised
Oxford Translation, trans. W.D. Ross, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1984; Metaphysics: Books 19, trans. Hugh Tredennick with the original Greek text, MA, Harvard University Press, 1933; Saint Anselm,
Proslogion with A reply on behalf of the fool, trans. M. J. Charlesworth, with the original Latin text; Indiana,
University of Notre Dame Press, 1979; Proslogion, trans. Thomas Williams, Indiana, Hackett Publishing,
1995; David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 2007; Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1998; Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus-Logico-Philosophicus, London,
Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1974; and Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance and Realism, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2011.
134
(6) There is no undeniable metaphysical claim, but a properly dogmatic “subtle”
violence. 290
The properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, as stated above (see 1.5), is that of suggesting
that one’s own writings attest to the existence of at least one undeniable metaphysical
claim, while not explicitly endorsing and, perhaps, even contradicting (1-i) and/or (1-ii).
Respectively, these are the claims that: among the others, some are legitimate rational
peers, and no person has settled a dispute once and for all. This is to state that those who
express the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence insinuate that: pace (1-i), their others are
not really legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake, and/or, pace (1-ii), one’s
works, indeed, settle at least one dispute permanently. I call the properly dogmatic violence
a “subtle” one because this violence’s existence is not as easily identifiable as that of
corporeal upfront forms of violence, such as those of punching or shooting a person. So,
distinct from, say, a drunk man who picks up a fight in a bar or a robber who shoots the
owner of a convenient store, the philosophers who, I claim, perform the properly dogmatic
“subtle” violence are not usually depicted as properly violent persons. In arguing that such
philosophers have expressed a “subtle” violence, then, it might be objected that I defend a
counter-intuitive claim; one that, assuming the conflictual use of intuition-talk discussed
in 3.2, some people, regardless of argument, are not inclined to endorse. I start to try to
make these people shift their intuitions to my side by mentioning three kinds of writings.
First, consider the works of Carl Schmitt, Walter Benjamin, Hannah Arendt,
Emmanuel Levinas, Frantz Fanon, Jacques Derrida, Jan Assmann and Richard
290
Of course, I cannot discuss all allegedly undeniable metaphysical claims that may be used to problematize
(6). I take, yet, that in what follows I provide a significant extensive overview of such claims. This overview
is an imperfect justificatory resource that backs up (6) in the best way I can currently develop.
135
Bernstein. 291 They have all identified and criticized all sorts of violence, including, but also
going beyond upfront corporeal kinds of violence. In doing so, these philosophers have
already problematized what counts as violence in the first place. Second, consider the likes
of Martin Luther King, Malcolm X, Angela Davis and Cornel West.292 A common feature
that pervades their writings is that of suggesting that violence against black-skinned people
does not merely refer to upfront corporal violence, such as that of punishing slaves by
flagellating their backs. Instead, other forms of violence, such as that of looking with
disgust to two black-skinned people kissing in the street, are also to be considered. The
same is the case with racist “jokes”. Third, consider the feminist literature articulated by
Simone de Beauvoir, Catherine MacKinnon, Linda Alcoff, Gayle Rubin, Sally Haslanger,
Julia Serano, etc. 293 These authors have also claimed that women, gays, transgendered
and/or non-binary people have suffered not merely upfront kinds of violence, such as that
of being beaten; it also has to be acknowledged that these groups have suffered other kinds
of violence, such as that of being constantly interrupted in debates. In arguing for (6), I am
291
See Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1996; Walter
Benjamin, Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings, vol 1: 1913-1926, Cambridge, Harvard University Press,
1996; Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, New York, Median Book, 1958; Emmanuel Levinas,
Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991; Franz Fanon,
The Wretched of the Earth, New York, Grove Press, 2004; Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, London,
Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1978; Jan Assmann, The Invention of Religion: Faith and Covenant in the
Book of Exodus, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2018; and Richard Bernstein, Violence: Thinking
Without Banisters, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2013.
292
Martin Luther King, A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches, New York, Harper
Collins Publishers, 1986; Malcolm X, Malcolm X Speaks: Selected Speeches and Statements, New York,
Merit Publishers and Betty Shabazz, 1965; Angela Davis, The Angela Y. Davis Reader, MA, Blackwell
Publishers, 1998; and Cornel West, The Cornel West Reader, New York, Basic Civitas Book, 1999.
293
Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, London, Lowe and Brydone, 1953; Catherine MacKinnon, Are
Women Human?, MA, Harvard University Press, 2006; Linda Alcoff, Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and
the Self, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006; Gayle Rubin, Deviations: A Gayle Rubin Reader, North
Caroline, Duke University Press, 2011; Sally Haslanger, Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social
Critique, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012; Julia Serano, Outspoken: A Decade of Transgender
Activism and Trans Feminism, Oakland, Switch Hitter Press, 2016; etc.
136
inspired by the authors mentioned in this paragraph and hope that others influenced or at
least aware of their works are inclined to acknowledge the existence of “subtle” violence.
Under the influence of Friedrich Nietzsche, I claim that the properly dogmatic
“subtle” violence is an anti-libertarian kind of violence. This occurs because those who
express it implicitly seek to constrain their others’ singularities, while implicitly speaking
in the name of a community of holders of logos and not acknowledging that others are
likewise part of this community. These others, dogmatists have suggested, have defended
rationally indefensible metaphysical claims that threat the community of all holders of
logos. In short, dogmatists are not libertarians. This is because they simply do not seek to
establish a unique criterion of their own to deal with disputes while problematizing the
constrains imposed by any kind of community. Rather, what dogmatists aim is to rely on
criteria that allegedly are shared by all members of such community of holders of logos.
The problem, this chapter aims to show, is that dogmatists have a quite narrow view
on what counts as a holder of logos. This is because they simply do not recognize that the
community of all holders of logos is a conflictual community, that is, a community in
which, as stated in 1.4, theoretical and practical disputes constantly occur and for every
member x, there is another member y so that x and y are others of one another. Under the
influence of Rudolf Carnap, then, I also claim that the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence
is also an anti-egalitarian “subtle” violence. The reason is that, in expressing it, dogmatists
have not contributed to the creation of a really universal community, while attenuating their
own singularities. What dogmatists have done, instead, has been to, implicitly, defend the
interests of a quite narrow community; that of those who agree with their allegedly
undeniable metaphysical claims and/or their criteria or reasons for embracing them.
137
It follows that those who express the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence,
ultimately, act in deep discordance with the will to synthesis. In other words, Aristotle and
his more or less unconscious followers neither maximize their individualistic tendencies
(that is, the many or the singularity principle), nor their communitarian ones (that is, the
one or the identity principle). In still other words, they are neither libertarians, such as
Nietzsche, nor egalitarians, such as Carnap. Instead, they are conservatives who more or
less implicitly seek to defend the interests of the aforementioned quite narrow community,
regardless of their own singularities or of the interests of a really universal community.
To rely on a clinical vocabulary similar to Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s, this is what I
take to be the properly dogmatic “sickness”. As indicated in 3.2, it is crucial to emphasize
again that in calling dogmatists sick, I do not wish to (dogmatically) suggest that dogmatists
are not legitimate rational peers regarding disputes. I also do not wish to (dogmatically)
suggest that I am able to solve a dispute once and for all. Instead, I am a conflictual crafter
who merely takes dogmatists to be deep opponents whose practices I wish to change. In
calling them “sick”, I am pressuring them to do so while still recognizing their personhood.
Now note that the dispute on whether there are undeniable metaphysical claims is
one that arises mainly for someone who endorses or at least takes seriously a controversial
claim that has rarely been discussed. The claim is that the Sisyphean picture of the history
of metaphysics is the most persuasive picture of such history. 294 According to this picture,
the history of metaphysics can be metaphorically compared to the process of a Sisyphean
294
According to Greek mythology, Sisyphus was a king who was punished by being compelled to roll an
immense rock up a hill. He then had to watch the rock roll back down. Such actions had to be repeated
eternally. For readings of this myth, see Albert Camus, The Myth of Sisyphus: And Other Essays, New York,
First Vintage International Edition, 1991; and Thomas Nagel, “The absurd”, in Mortal Questions, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1979.
138
hell as follows: every time a philosopher (e.g., a God-driven one, such as Anselm) endorses
a criterion (e.g., respect to scriptures) to approach a theoretical dispute (e.g., the one on
whether God exists) in pushing a rock up a hill with a claim about a dispute at stake (e.g.,
that God exists), another philosopher (e.g., a human-driven one, such as Kant) makes the
rock roll down once again in interpreting the supposedly shared criterion differently or
simply proposing another one (e.g., accordance with the transcendental conditions for a
judgment to be a cognitive one). This distinct criterion leads the philosopher to endorse a
distinct claim on the dispute at stake, say, that “God exists” is not even a cognitive claim.
Indeed, every time a philosopher (e.g., a human-driven one, such as Kant) endorses
a practice in pushing a rock up a hill in formulating a dispute (e.g., that on whether there
are things-in-themselves), another philosopher (e.g., a physicalist-driven one, such as
Thomas Nagel) makes the rock roll down once again in endorsing a distinct practice that
leads to a distinct kind of dispute (e.g., the one on whether consciousness exists). This
distinct practice is just as justified or as unjustified as the previous one, since both of them
are ultimately backed up by the problematic starting points discussed in 3.3. Philosophers,
the Sisyphean picture adds, are persons who have rejected one another’s claims rationally.
However, they have not done so conclusively in stopping the Sisyphean-hell like process
in establishing at least one undeniable metaphysical claim or practice. What philosophers
have done, instead, has been merely to endorse deniable metaphysical claims and practices
that can be rationally rejected by persons, such as their others. Nothing indicates that
someone will be able to stop the Sisyphean-hell like process in doing otherwise.
Dogmatists, then, have misdescribed their works; they have overestimated these works of
theirs in adopting what may be called an eliminativist attitude: that of suggesting that their
139
works show that one can react to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been
engaged in disputes by simply putting an end to these disputes or at least to one of them.
Note that if the Sisyphean picture is the case, there seems to be no strong notion of
philosophical progress according to which contemporary works of philosophy have more
“knowledge”, are closer to the “truth” and/or are “significantly superior” than past
philosophical works insofar as disputes are stake. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and,
more tentatively and recently, Timothy Williamson point to such a strong notion of
philosophical progress. 295 On my part, I tend to think that the very theoretical dispute over
the claim “there is philosophical progress” is one that cannot be approached by means of a
non-controversial criterion endorsed by all persons. What I mean is that, according to the
Sisyphean picture, no non-controversial criterion for what counts as philosophical progress
appears obtainable; that whatever a philosopher embraces as some sort of “unit to measure”
philosophical progress (e.g., “amount” of knowledge or “closeness” to the truth) will itself
rely on a problematic starting point. It is not this chapter’s aim, though, to reply to the likes
of Hegel and Williamson in detail while making a case for the Sisyphean picture.
What I aim to do is just to show that one is to keep an open mind regarding the
Sisyphean picture insofar as (6) follows, by modus tollens, from:
P.1
295
If there is no properly dogmatic “subtle” violence or an undeniable
metaphysical claim exists, there also has to be a narrow condition for
personhood, that is, a necessary, but not sufficient condition according to
which to be a person, one must endorse an (allegedly) undeniable
metaphysical claim.
“In many areas of philosophy”, Williamson claims, “we know much more in 2007 than was known in
1957; much more was known in 1957 than in 1907; much more was known in 1907 than was known in 1857”.
See Timothy Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy, MA, Blackwell, 2007: pp. 280. Also consider Georg
Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy 1825-6: Volume I: Introduction and Oriental
Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009; Lectures on the History of Philosophy Volume II: Greek
Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006; Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume III:
Medieval and Modern Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009.
140
P.2
However, there is no narrow condition for personhood.
Let me now imperfectly justify P.1 and P.2 in the next two sub-sections, respectively.
4.2 Dogmatists’ Writings and Narrow Conditions for Personhood
Consider Aristotle’s way of addressing the ontological dispute on whether there are
impossible entities. In addressing this dispute in his Metaphysics, Aristotle suggests that
his works attest to the existence of an undeniable metaphysical claim: namely, there are no
impossible entities. In his words, translated by W.D. Ross, “the same attribute cannot at
the same time belong and not belong to the same subject and in the same respect”.296
Aristotle goes as far as stating that this claim is the “most indisputable of all principles”.297
Notice that there is no evidence that he takes himself to be expressing any kind of “subtle”
violence in stating so. On my part, then, I read that if Aristotle’s works are, indeed, free of
the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence or if the claim that there are no impossible entities
is, indeed, a metaphysical undeniable one, there has to be a narrow condition for
personhood that Aristotle’s “opponent” violates. 298 The narrow condition is that for one to
be a person, one must endorse the very claim that there are no impossible entities.
Aristotle points to this narrow condition. This occurs because he appears to take
himself to be able to refute once and for all the “opponent” who rejects that there are no
impossible entities, and who “will only say something”. 299 If this opponent “says nothing”,
Aristotle continues, “it is absurd to attempt to reason with one who will not reason about
anything, in so far as he refuses reason. For such a man, as such, is seen already to be no
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Γ 3, 1005b 19-20.
Ibid., Γ 4, 1006a 4-5.
298
Ibid., Γ 4, 1006a 13.
299
Ibid.
296
297
141
better than a mere plant [φυτῷ]”. 300 By the expression “say something”, I interpret that
Aristotle means “to be able to make meaningful utterances”. If an opponent is able to do
so, Aristotle insinuates, such an opponent must endorse the claim that there are no
impossible entities. Otherwise, this opponent is not really a legitimate rational peer insofar
as the dispute on the existence of impossible entities is concerned. In stating that “some
think Heraclitus” believes that there are impossible entities, Aristotle indicates that this
might have been the case with Heraclitus and his followers. 301 Protagoras and “those who
share the views of Protagoras” would also have believed in the existence of impossible
entities. 302 Aristotle also seems to imply that they would be “no better than a mere plant”.
Now note that, as it is well-known, Aristotle never used the term “metaphysics.”
Nevertheless, two neutral senses —very distinct from the derogatory ones adopted by
Nietzsche and Carnap —of the word “metaphysics” have often been associated with his
works, especially with his so-called Metaphysics; a title given not by Aristotle himself, but
by that the first century C.E. editor who assembled the writings we currently call
Metaphysics and who may have been the first to coin the term, “metaphysics.” The two
neutral senses of “metaphysics” are: “the science of being qua being” and “an inquiry into
first principles.” Therefore, it can be argued that for Aristotle, Heraclitus, Protagoras and
their respective followers are “non-metaphysicians” in a derogatory sense. This is so
insofar as they would have failed to think in accordance with this science and/or inquiry.
Consider Anselm’s way of addressing the ontological dispute on whether God
exists. More than a thousand years after Aristotle wrote his Metaphysics, Anselm also
Ibid., Γ 4, 1006a 13-15, my emphasis.
Ibid., Γ 3, 1005b 25.
302
Ibid., Γ 4, 1007b 22.
300
301
142
suggests that his work attest to the existence of an undeniable metaphysical claim: namely,
the very claim that God exists. Notice that Anselm deals with the following passage of
scriptures: “The fool [insipiens] says in his heart, ‘There is no God’”. 303 In the third chapter
of his 1077-1078 Proslogion whose translation by Thomas Williams was adopted here,
Anselm asks the following questions: “So then why did the fool [insipiens] say in his heart,
‘There is no God,’ when it is so evident to the rational mind that you [that is, God] among
all beings exist most greatly? Why indeed, except because he is stupid [stultus] and a fool
[insipiens]?” (my emphasis). In raising these questions, Anselm does not seem to take
himself to be expressing a “subtle” violence regarding those who deny God’s existence.
My reading, then, is that if Anselm’s works, indeed, express no properly dogmatic
“subtle” violence or if the claim that God exists is, indeed, a metaphysical undeniable one,
there has to be a second narrow condition for personhood. The condition —apparently
suggested by Anselm, while raising the questions of the last paragraph —is that to be a
person, one must endorse the very claim that God exists. Otherwise, one is a “stupid and a
fool”, that is, someone who is not really a legitimate rational peer insofar as the dispute on
God’s existence is at stake. Now let me emphasize that Anselm’s terms (“stupid” and
“fool”) are distinct and, arguably, less aggressive than Aristotle’s (“no better than a mere
plant”). To put it metaphorically, though, Aristotle’s terms echo in the writings of
Anselm’s, and those of several other philosophers who more or less unconsciously follow
Aristotle and his dogmatic craft. This is the case with Hume’s, regardless of the fact that,
distinct from Aristotle and Anselm, he takes himself to be an “anti-metaphysician”, and
associates with his opponents’ works and uses the term “metaphysics” in a derogatory way.
303
See Psalms 14:1 and 53:1, my emphasis.
143
Consider the very last paragraph of Hume’s 1748 An Enquiry Concerning Human
Understanding. Hume summarizes his take on the dispute on whether what he calls
religious and/or metaphysical claims, such as “God exists” or “there are miracles”, are
superstitions. Hume’s view is that this is the case. He reaches this conclusion because, for
him, a belief is either a relation of ideas or a matter of fact. Examples of the former and the
latter, respectively, are: the mathematical claim that “2 +2 = 4”, and the empirical claim
that “the sun rose yesterday”. Since religious and/or metaphysical claims would be neither
relations of ideas nor matters of fact, they would be superstitions. Accordingly, it is not
surprising that Hume argues that any book “of divinity or school metaphysics” that only
contains superstitions is to be committed “to the flames”. 304 This book, Hume goes as far
as emphasizing, “can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion”. 305
It may be taken for granted that Hume does not believe to be expressing a “subtle”
violence in making this last claim. What he suggests, instead, is that his own works attest
to the existence of an undeniable metaphysical claim: the very claim that religious and/or
metaphysical claims are superstitions. I interpret, then, that if this is so or if Hume’s works
do not after all express a properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, there must be a third narrow
condition for personhood. According to this third condition, to be a person, one must
endorse Hume’s very claim that religious and/or metaphysical claims are superstitions.
Otherwise, one is not really a rational peer concerning the dispute over the epistemic status
of religious and/or metaphysical claims, but, rather, relies on books that “contain nothing
but sophistry and illusion”. Hence, almost seven hundred years after Anselm’s Proslogion
and in an atheist manner, Hume’s term (“sophistry”) still echoes Aristotle’s.
304
305
David Hume, Enquiry 12, §34.
Ibid., my emphasis.
144
Notice that Aristotle and, before him, Plato’s Socrates have contributed to change
the original meaning of the term “sophist”. In making this last claim, this dissertation relies
on Ancient philosophy scholars, such as W. K. C. Guthrie. 306 Guthrie argues that at first
the term “sophist” was usually applied in Ancient Greece in the non-derogatory sense of a
“wise man”. Yet, starting in the fifth century BCE, a derogatory sense began to be attached
to the word “sophist”: that of a “charlatan.” This is an unserious teacher who for the sake
of profit and/or fame, tricks others into believing in fallacious arguments and/or absurd
claims, that is, sophistries. Plato’s Socrates as well as Aristotle sometimes describe the
likes of Protagoras as making such sophistries. On his part, Hume suggests that only
“ignorant and barbarous nations” would take a sophistry seriously. 307 Indeed, Hume goes
as far as stating that “when we believe any miracle of Mahomet or his successors [that is,
in relying neither on a relation of ideas nor on a matter of fact, but in “religion” or
“metaphysics”] we have for our warrant the testimony of a few barbarous Arabians”. 308
Let us also take Kant into account. In the last chapter of his 1783 Prolegomena to
Any Future Metaphysics whose translation by Gary Hatfield was adopted here, Kant claims
that “critique stands to the ordinary school metaphysics precisely as chemistry stands to
alchemy, or astronomy to the fortune-teller’s astrology”. 309 This passage attests to the fact
that Kant uses the term “metaphysics” in a derogatory sense quite related to Hume’s and
Carnap’s: that of a pre-scientific or unscientific inquiry. In seeking to know things-inthemselves, this inquiry would disrespect the transcendental conditions for judgments to
306
W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1971: pp. 27.
David Hume, Enquiry 10, §20, my emphasis.
308
David Hume, Enquiry 10, §24, my emphasis.
309
Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics: With Selection from the Critique of Pure
Reason, trans. Gary Hatfield, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2004: (4:366).
307
145
be cognitive ones. For Kant, metaphysis would merely provide non-cognitive judgments,
such as “there is an immaterial soul that persists after the body’s death” and “God exists”.
So, Kant —distinct from Aristotle and Anselm, and like Hume, Carnap and
Nietzsche —often uses the term “metaphysics” to refer to the works of his opponents: those
regarding which he seeks to differentiate his own project. The latter is what he calls
“critique” or “critical philosophy”, that is, a purported scientific inquiry comparable to
mathematics and to the empirical sciences that would spell out the transcendental
conditions for cognitive experience. It is not surprising, then, that Kant claims that “in
metaphysics [in the last paragraph’s sense], we have to retrace our path countless times,
because we find that it does not lead where we want to go, and it is so far from reaching
unanimity in the assertions of its adherents that it is rather a battlefield (Kampfplatz)”.310
This last passage is part of the preface of the 1787 second edition of Kant’s Critique of
Pure Reason, whose translation by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood was adopted here.
Kant further depicts the “battlefield” he has in mind as “one that appears to be
especially determined for testing one’s powers in mock combat [Spielgefechte]”. 311 Note
that the expression “mock combat” (Spielgefechte) also “echoes” Aristotle’s terms insofar
as Kant implies that his opponents are engaged in a non-serious and even infantile activity.
Indeed, the combat Kant has in mind would be a mock combat because “on this battlefield
no combatant has ever gained the least bit of ground, nor has any been able to base any
lasting possession on his victory”. 312 This passage shows that Kant’s picture of the history
310
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, B xiv-xv, my emphasis.
Ibid., my emphasis.
312
Ibid.
311
146
of metaphysics somehow resembles the Sisyphean one. However, the view of someone,
such as myself, who tends to endorse this picture is extremely distinct from Kant’s.
Champions of the Sisyphean picture claim that it might be impossible to stop the
Sisyphean hell-like process that characterizes the history of metaphysics. To use Kant’s
metaphor, there seems to be no way out of the battlefield so that Kant himself and all other
mature philosophers are serious (as opposed to mock) combatants in it. Kant, on the other
hand, describes himself as putting an end to the battlefield. To use my own metaphor, Kant
takes himself as being able to close the Sisyphean-hell like process in turning philosophy
into a science as if all philosophers before him were unserious children and he were the
first serious really mature philosopher. It is not surprising, then, that in the 1781 first
preface of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant goes as far as stating the following: “I make
bold to say that there cannot be a single metaphysical problem that has not been solved
here, or at least to the solution of which the key has not been provided”. 313
This last passage is further evidence that Kant took his own works to attest to the
existence of at least one undeniable metaphysical claim: namely, the very claim that his
critique spells out the transcendental conditions for cognitive experience. Note that Kant
does not seem to take himself to be expressing any kind of “subtle” violence in suggesting
that his opponents are mock combatants whose claims lack cognitive value. My reading,
then, is that if his works do not express the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence and/or
attest to the existence of at least one undeniable metaphysical claim, there has to be a fourth
narrow condition for personhood. The condition is that to be a person, one must endorse
Kant’s very own claim that his critique spells out the transcendental conditions for
313
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A xiii.
147
cognitive experience. Otherwise, one is not really a legitimate rational peer insofar as the
dispute over such conditions is at stake but, instead, proceeds in a pre-scientific or
unscientific way that, ultimately, cannot really be taken seriously and is infantile.
It is likewise not very surprising, then, that even in his pre-critical phase in a letter
from April 8th of 1766 to Moses Mendelssohn, Kant states the following about
“metaphysicians”: “I cannot conceal my repugnance, and even a certain hatred, toward the
inflated arrogance of whole volumes full of what are passed of nowadays as insights”. 314
In the same letter, Kant likewise “echoes” Aristotle and, even more explicitly, Anselm in
claiming that his 1766 Dreams of a Spirit-Seer pursues “a merely negative purpose, the
avoidance of stupidity (stultitia caruisse)”. 315 Now let me underline that my view is that
philosophers may suggest that their works attest to the existence of undeniable
metaphysical claims, even when they do not derogatorily describe their opponents.
Consider the first Wittgenstein of the 1921 Tractatus-Logico-Philosophicus.
Although he does not explicitly describe his opponents in a derogatory way, he suggests
that the following claim is a metaphysical undeniable one: disputes arise due to our failure
to understand the logic of our language. Wittgenstein suggests so because in “echoing” the
quoted passage of the first preface of Kant’s Critique Pure Reason, he states that he “found,
on all essential points, the final solution of the problems”. 316 The problems Wittgenstein
has in mind are all of those “problems of philosophy”. 317 In 4.0030 of the Tractatus,
314
Immanuel Kant, Correspondence, trans. Arnulf Zweig, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1999:10:70, my emphasis).
315
Ibid., 10:71. Also see Immanuel Kant. Dreams of a Spirit-Seer: Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics,
trans. Emanuel F. Goerwitz, New York, The Macmillan Co, 1900. Moreover, consider that in addressing the
mentioned letter by Kant, Karl Popper calls “Kant’s attack upon metaphysics” a “violence”. See Karl Popper,
The Open Society and its Enemies: New One Volume Edition, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1994:
pp. 252.
316
Wittgenstein, Tractatus, pp. 4, my emphasis.
317
Ibid., pp.3.
148
Wittgenstein gives an example of the kind of problem he has in mind. The example is a
dispute on “whether the good is more or less identical than the beautiful”. 318 In seeking to
provide a “final solution” to this dispute and indeed to all (or at least most) other disputes,
Wittgenstein himself is engaged on a metametaphysical dispute: the one on why disputes
arise in the first place. Wittgenstein’s way of addressing this matter is by arguing that these
disputes arise because of “our failure to understand the logic of our language”. 319
This last claim is what Wittgenstein labels a “final solution.” In doing so, he does
not seem to take himself to be expressing a “subtle” violence regarding his opponents. This
is to state that if the Tractatus is, indeed, free of the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence
or if Wittgenstein’s final solution is, indeed, an undeniable metaphysical claim, there has
to be a fifth narrow condition for personhood. According to this condition —apparently
suggested by Wittgenstein insofar as he speaks in terms of a “final solution”, albeit he does
not derogatorily describe his opponents —, to be a person, one must endorse the claim that
disputes arise because of our failure to understand the logic of our language. Otherwise,
one is not really a legitimate rational peer concerning the dispute on why disputes arise in
the first place but, rather, someone who fails to understand the obvious: the very logic of
our language, that is, a language that is to be understood by all holders of logos.
It is important to underline that there still are contemporary philosophers who
suggest that their own works attest to the existence of undeniable metaphysical claims.
Consider Hirsch’s take on the dispute on whether ordinary language is committed to
mereological sums, that is, the dispute on whether mereological sums are objects in the
ordinary sense of the term “objects”. Hirsch’s view is that this is not the case. David Lewis,
318
319
Ibid., pp. 23.
Ibid, pp. 4, my emphasis.
149
according to Hirsch, claims otherwise. “Lewis is one of the most influential deniers of […]
‘common sense sanity’”, Hirsch states. 320 So, Hirsch further argues that: “I think the short
and decisive rebuttal of Lewis’s view is that if you try to tell ordinary folk about the
gerrymandering objects [that is, mereological sums] which, on Lewis’s account, they are
supposedly committed to, they will look for the nearest place to commit you to”. 321
This last passage is evidence that, more than two thousand years after Aristotle
wrote his so-called Metaphysics, philosophers still “echo” his terms. This occurs in that
Hirsch likewise suggests that his opponent, Lewis, is not really a legitimate rational peer
insofar as what is at stake is the dispute on whether ordinary language is committed to
mereological sums. Lewis would somehow be “insane” in needing to be committed to a
mental institution. This is because Lewis defends that mereological sums are objects in the
ordinary sense of the term “objects;” ordinary language would be ultimately committed to
these sums in Hirsch’s reading of Lewis’s view. Notice that Hirsch also “echoes” Kant and
Wittgenstein in speaking in terms of a “decisive rebuttal”. 322 Nothing in Hirsch’s writings
indicates that he takes himself to be expressing a “subtle” violence in speaking so.
My interpretation of Hirsch’s writings, then, is similar to those I propose of the
several other more or less unconscious followers of Aristotle. More explicitly, if Hirsch’s
works do not express any properly dogmatic “subtle” violence or if the claim that ordinary
language is not committed to mereological sums is a metaphysical undeniable one, there
must be a sixth narrow condition for personhood: that to be a person, one must endorse the
320
Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance, pp. 42, my emphasis. For further comments on this passage, see my own
Felipe G. A. Moreira, “An Apology of Carnap”, Manuscrito (Unicamp), Vol 37, Número 2, 2014: pp.261289.
321
Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance, pp. 42.
322
Ibid, my emphasis.
150
claim that ordinary language is not committed to mereological sums. Otherwise, one, like
Lewis, denies what Hirsch calls “common sense sanity” in not really being a legitimate
rational peer concerning the dispute on whether ordinary language is committed to
mereological sums. 323 What follows, then, is P.1, the claim that if there is no properly
dogmatic “subtle” violence or, as Aristotle and his followers suggest, an undeniable
metaphysical claim exists, there also has to be a narrow condition for personhood.
4.3 Against Narrow Conditions for Personhood
However, there is no narrow condition for personhood. This is P.2. The reason for
endorsing this premise is that narrow conditions for personhood seem to be ultimately
arbitrary ones. This is so in the sense that: philosophers who are interested in defending
certain metaphysical or metametaphysical claims seem to have constantly suggested that
the claims they defend must be endorsed for someone or something to be a person. Yet,
there seems to be no persuasive reason for embracing these suggestions. In fact, the six
philosophers addressed in the last section have never explicitly presented these reasons;
they have never explicitly argued for narrow conditions for personhood, instead, as
indicated above, they have only suggested, insinuated or pointed to these conditions.
This chapter, though, faces an objection: that the proposed reading of all the
passages quoted in the last section is too literal. This is so insofar as these passages were
taken as evidence that philosophers have suggested narrow conditions for personhood.
Instead of doing so, the objection continues, these passages should be read metaphorically,
that is, not as serious claims that there are narrow conditions for personhood. Rather, these
323
Ibid, my emphasis.
151
passages should be interpreted as emotional outburst passages. By this, it is to be
understood a passage that has one or both of the following features. First, the passage
indicates that its author feels strongly emotionally invested in the metaphysical or
metametaphysical claim at stake. This is because the passage is evidence that the author
shows some animosity or even hatred (as it is explicit in the letter by Kant quoted above)
concerning those who contradict the claim the author supports. Second, the passage is
evidence that the author overestimates the level of persuasiveness of a metaphysical or a
metametaphysical claim, that is, the passage implies that a merely hardly deniable or even
a highly controversial metaphysical or metametaphysical claim is an undeniable claim.
It may be conceded to the objector that the metaphorical reading of the passages
quoted in the last section is as persuasive as the literal one. Regardless of which of these
readings is the most persuasive one, though, P.2 is to be endorsed. This is because, as stated
above, narrow conditions for personhood are ultimately arbitrary ones in the stated sense.
Furthermore, note that even if the metaphorical reading trumps the literal one, P.1 is still
to be embraced. This takes place because this premise’s consequent follows from its
antecedent, regardless of whether all the six philosophers discussed above were actually
committed to narrow conditions of personhood. What is crucial here is that, as the last
section indicates, Aristotle and his followers have all more or less explicitly problematized
(1-i) and (1-ii) in insinuating that their others are not really rational peers insofar disputes
are concerned and/or that their own works settle at least one dispute permanently.
For my purposes, then, it is ultimately irrelevant whether Aristotle and his followers
really believe that their others are “no better than plants”, “stupid”, etc, or terms, such as
these, are to be read as derogatory metaphors whose literal meanings not even dogmatists
152
themselves take to hold true of their others. Analogously, consider a racist who calls a
black-skinned person a “monkey” or a sexist who calls a woman a “bitch”. What is most
important for the authors of the black movement and/or feminist ones mentioned in this
chapter’s introduction is not to discuss whether such a racist and such a sexist literally
believe so or merely rely on some sort of derogatory metaphor in using these terms.
What is relevant is that the racist and the sexist express some sort of violence in
using terms, such as “monkey” and “bitch”. In other words, they proceed in a not very
subtle violent way; one that may only be called “subtle” ironically, as I have done here.
My view is that the case with dogmatists is analogous. In relying on terms, such as “plant”
or “fool”, they express a properly dogmatic “subtle” violence regarding their others. In
doing so, they suggest that others are not legitimate rational peers when disputes are
concerned. Indeed, as indicated above, this “subtle” violence may be expressed, even by
philosophers, such as Wittgenstein, who do not use derogatory terms to describe their
opponents.
Yet, another objection arises: that P.2 is a trivial premise. The first reason for
claiming so is that if the literal reading is the case, philosophers have merely suggested
narrow conditions for personhood; they have never argued for them. So, P.2 is a trivial
premise in that no philosopher (including the six ones addressed in the last section) rejects
it. The second reason for taking P.2 to be a trivial premise is that if the metaphorical reading
is the case, it also seems to follow that no philosopher has defended P.2. My reply is that
even if P.2 is a trivial premise, this is not a disadvantage; the opposite is the case in that an
argument that has this kind of premise is likely to be more persuasive. In fact, the very
dispute on whether P.2 is a trivial premise is quite unimportant for my purposes. What is
153
crucial is that (6) follows, by modus tollens, from P.1. and P.2, regardless of whether the
literal or the metaphorical reading is the case. (6), as indicated above, is the claim that there
is no undeniable metaphysical claim, but a properly dogmatic “subtle” violence. (6) is no
trivial claim. The reason is that this claim’s denial has been widely believed, since Ancient
Greece up to today by all the more or less unconscious dogmatic followers of Aristotle.
This is to state that the denial of (6) can be attributed to all the six philosophers
addressed in the last section, regardless of whether the literal or the metaphorical reading
is the case. The reason is that there is no evidence that these philosophers take themselves
to be expressing any kind of “subtle” violence. In addition, the passages quoted in the last
section are sufficient evidence that all of them have suggested that their own works attest
to the existence of at least one metaphysical undeniable claim. To put it metaphorically,
these philosophers have suggested that their own works are able to stop at least partially
the Sisyphean hell-like process of the history of metaphysics. It follows that dogmatists
have misdescribed their works. This is so in that they have overstated what these works of
theirs manage to accomplish. To argue for (6), then, is to put the self-imagine of dogmatists
into question in spelling out that they are not self-aware that all of them are ultimately
caught in the Sisyphean hell-like process of the history of metaphysics, despite their more
or less unconscious wishes to stop this process. To show this is likewise no trivial task.
P.2 is also to be embraced because several traditional criteria adopted by
philosophers to approach disputes are violated once a narrow condition for personhood is
endorsed. Consider accordance with scriptures, a criterion adopted by Anselm as well as
by all other God-driven philosophers. The only narrow condition for personhood that seems
to be backed up by this criterion is that suggested by Anselm himself: that to be a person,
154
one must endorse the metaphysical claim that God exists. Note that in suggesting this
condition, Anselm considers only one passage of scriptures already quoted above: that “the
fool says in his heart, ‘There is no God’”. This passage, nonetheless, is not necessarily
evidence that scriptures endorse Anselm’s narrow condition mentioned in this paragraph.
Indeed, this is what another God-driven philosopher, Saint Thomas of Aquinas, claims.
Consider Aquinas’s Summa Theologica written from 1265 to 1274, whose 1920
translation by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province was adopted here. In the first
article of the second question of this work’s first part, Aquinas claims that the “the opposite
of the proposition ‘God is’ can be mentally admitted: ‘The fool said in his heart, There is
no God’ (Psalm 53:1). Therefore, that God exists is not self-evident”. 324 This passage may
be read as Aquinas’ way of problematizing Anselm in that it implies that there are persons
who reject that God exists; that even the so-called “fool” is a legitimate rational peer
regarding the dispute on God’s existence. Indeed, the existence of this “fool”, Aquinas
implies, is evidence that Anselm’s narrow condition for personhood is not the case.
Consider another traditional criterion endorsed by human-driven philosophers,
such as Karl Marx or, more recently, by all the black movement and/or feminist authors
mentioned in this chapter’s introduction: oppression acknowledgement. This criterion, I
assume, is satisfied whenever one spells out and resists practices of oppression. Examples
of these practices that rely on upfront kinds of violence are the following ones: to colonize
and kill millions of native Americans; to kidnap from Africa and enslave black-skinned
people; to embrace the Jim Crow laws; to not allow black-skinned people to vote or to
make it hard for them to not become criminals and end up going in and out of jail
324
Saint Thomas of Aquinas, The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. Fathers of the English
Dominican Province, Indiana, Christian Classics, 1981.
155
throughout their lives; to underpay and exploit poor workers in forcing them to work in
inhumane conditions; to make it hard for women to fulfill more than domestic tasks or to
not give them the right to vote; to suggest that the vast majority of Mexicans who immigrate
to the USA are dangerous, say, they are robbers, drug dealers and/or rapists; etc.
Other examples of practices of oppression related to professional philosophy, and
that resort to less easily identifiable kinds of violence are: to mock in writings, talks and/or
classes philosophers who do not belong to one’s tradition and/or time or that contradict
one’s claims; to not accept into Graduate programs those who study and/or are influenced
by these philosophers; to also not employ or to not allow one’s opponents to publish in
philosophical journals; to make strange noises in philosophy conferences in seeking to
intimidate those who disagree with one’s views; etc. I claim that oppression
acknowledgment may be satisfied by the one who speculates that those who have
championed these practices have often presupposed narrow conditions for personhood
which imply that others are not legitimate rational peers or even that such others are not
exactly persons. This presupposition, it may be speculated, is what ultimately legitimated
and made practices of oppression tolerable and even praised in the West, say, as a sign of
masculinity. What I mean is that narrow conditions for personhood are dangerous.
Consider another traditional criterion widely shared among physicalist-driven
philosophers or, more broadly, analytic ones, such as Wittgenstein and Hirsch themselves:
respect to the rules of ordinary language. As Mark Rowlands claims, “the category of the
metaphysical person [that is, what has been simply called “person” here] is as mottled and
messy as one could imagine”. 325 This is so, Rowlands continues, in that “there are a variety
325
Mark Rowlands, Can Animals be Persons?, forthcoming: pp. 15.
156
of ingredients that might go into making an individual a person in the metaphysical sense,
and the relative importance of each is, to say the least, not immediately clear”. 326 This is
why it could be argued that in order to show what is the ordinary use of the term “person,”
an empirical research would have to be performed. In determining what has been the most
recurrent use of the term “person” within English-speaking countries, this research would
establish which use is really entitled to be called the ordinary one.
This research would also have to establish three other points. First, what are in all
non-English speaking countries (e.g., France, Italy or Brazil) the most recurrent uses of
foreign terms (e.g., the French term “personne,” the Italian term “persona” or the
Portuguese one “pessoa”) that have usually been translated to the English term “person”
and which, therefore, also deserve to be called ordinary ones. Second, whether the ordinary
use of the term “person” in English-speaking countries is different from that of the foreign
terms mentioned in the last phrase. Third, if this is the case, which of these ordinary uses
is the most relevant regarding the dispute on whether P.2 is to be embraced and that on
what is a person. Yet, I do not know anyone who has done such an empirical research into
the term “person” and I cannot do so here. Let me, however, consider two other options.
The first option is to argue that, before the adequate empirical research is
accomplished, respect to the rules of ordinary language simply cannot be used as a criterion
to approach the dispute on whether P.2 is to be accepted or the dispute on what is a person
in the first place. The second option is to claim that, regardless of the lack of a detailed
empirical research, philosophers can spell out what is if not exactly an ordinary, at least a
widely shared use of the term “person” by following a more informal method adopted by
326
Ibid.
157
several analytic philosophers. This method is one that Simon Evnine adopts while
addressing the dispute on what is a person. As Evnine states, this is the method of simply
“asking the reader to consider the concept [of “person”] and confirm that the [offered]
conditions […] are indeed necessary conditions for the application of that concept”. 327 I
am neutral on the dispute on which of the two options mentioned in this paragraph is the
most persuasive one. However, it is important to emphasize that if the second option is
endorsed, P.2 appears (at least for me) to follow. Consider the ordinary concept of “person”
and the question: is any narrow condition for personhood (like the six ones discussed in
the last section) a necessary condition for the application of the ordinary concept, “person”?
My hope is that this dissertation’s readers are inclined to answer this question negatively.
Consider another criterion to deal with disputes that, as it will be showed in the next
chapter, is widely shared by analytic philosophers, such as Quine, Saul Kripke and Kit
Fine: accordance with intuitions. Assuming once again the conflictual use of intuition-talk,
I take that at least some of this dissertation’s readers agree that narrow conditions for
personhood imply a quite “counter-intuitive” claim: that at least one human being who
most people would take to be a person is not a legitimate rational peer insofar as a dispute
is concerned. Consider the six narrow conditions for personhood suggested by Aristotle,
Anselm, Hume, Kant, Wittgenstein, and Hirsch. Respectively, they imply that the
following human beings are not legitimate rational peers: Heraclitus, Protagoras, their
followers and Graham Priest who argues that impossible entities exist 328; atheists; theists;
practically all philosophers who articulated their works before Kant and most physicalistdriven ones who suggest that empirical sciences, such as physics, provide knowledge of
327
328
Simon J. Evnine, Epistemic Dimensions of Personhood, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2008: pp. 10.
Graham Priest, Doubt Truth to be a Liar, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006.
158
things-in-themselves; practically all philosophers who articulated their works before
Wittgenstein; and David Lewis. “Intuitive”, then, is a term that may be used to qualify the
distinct claim that all these human beings are, indeed, legitimate rational peers, and that it
is a “subtle” violence to suggest otherwise merely because they contradict one’s claims.
I underline, however, that this is not to state that all others are legitimate rational
peers on all disputes. There are, indeed, others who are not really rational peers regarding
disputes, say, those who are under the influence of heavy drugs; those who are simply
unaware of what is at stake in the dispute at hand; those who do not have the appropriate
philosophical education, etc. It is not my aim, though, to spell out necessary or sufficient
condition for someone to have such an education. Indeed, I do not think that this is an easy
task. What I would like to do, instead, is to illustrate my view with a contemporary
example. Imagine sexy youtubers who, in posting videos in which they appear shirt-less,
manage to become famous by making pseudo-philosophical funny remarks about disputes,
albeit their almost complete lack of education in the field. I do not wish to suggest that
these youtubers are actually really legitimate rational peers. They are only, so to speak,
bare; not bare wise persons. My point regarding Aristotle and his more or less unconscious
followers is that they often suggest that all of their others —including sophisticated
philosophers who have an appropriate philosophical education and, indeed, have spent a
significant amount of the times of their lives in studying disputes —are like these youtubers
who are mainly seeking money and/or fame. To rely on a conflictual use of intuition-talk
once more, the view supported here is that this is simply not a very “intuitive” suggestion.
Consider a third criterion widely shared among physicalist-driven philosophers:
maximization of theoretical virtues, such as conservatism, generality, simplicity,
159
refutability and modesty. If this criterion is adopted on the dispute on whether P.2 is the
case, it also appears that this premise is to be endorsed. To begin with, philosophers who
deny P.2 violate at least two theoretical virtues: refutability and modesty. They violate
refutability because they seem to presuppose that the very metaphysical or
metametaphysical claim they aim to defend must be supported for one to be a person. They
also violate modesty. In embracing a narrow condition for personhood, they make a quite
arrogant move: that of suggesting that their works attest to the existence of an undeniable
metaphysical claim. To put in Quine’s terms, this contradicts the “experimental spirit” of
being willing to revise one’s view, once further evidence is presented. 329 Now whether
Quine really has such a spirit is another issue that will be discussed in the next chapter.
For now, note that conservativism is also, arguably, violated by the one who rejects
P.2. The term “arguably” was emphasized because conservatism is a relational concept.
Accordingly, a narrow condition for personhood can only be conservative regarding a
certain context in which the condition is already embraced. Some narrow conditions for
personhood (e.g., Anselm’s) might be conservative regarding certain contexts (e.g., those
in which theists compose a majority), while failing to be so in other contexts (e.g., those in
which atheists compose a majority). However, no narrow condition for personhood is
conservative regarding all contexts. Whether the one who embraces P.2 satisfies generality
and simplicity is hardly determinable. To put it in more direct words, it seems that the
endorsement of P.2 does not make one’s view more general or simple than that of the one
who rejects this premise. However, given the reasons mentioned in this and in the last
paragraph, the endorsement of P.2 maximizes more theoretical virtues than its rejection.
329
Willard Van Orman Quine, “On what there is”, pp. 38.
160
Now note that a conjunction between P.2 and a disjunction could be inserted. The
disjunction is that either there are only broad conditions for personhood or there is no
condition for personhood at all, that is, logos resists definition. By a broad condition for
personhood, it is to be understood a necessary, but not sufficient condition that practically
all human beings satisfy. This includes all philosophers named in this dissertation (at least
during the time they wrote the works considered here). As Thomas White and Rowlands
indicate, even some animals, such as dolphins, may satisfy such broad conditions.330
Indeed, the only human beings who may disrespect a broad condition are those, such as:
fetuses (if it is granted that they are human beings); infants; some of those that psychiatry
describes as severally mentally disordered; the ones who are on the last stages of
Alzheimer's dementia or any other disease that strongly affects one’s mental capacity, etc.
Broad conditions for personhood, then, do not imply the stated “counter-intuitive” claim.
The following are examples of broad conditions for personhood proposed by
Evnine (2008) are: “Finitude, Belief, Agency, and Second-Ordinality”. 331 This is to state
that, if Evnine is right, to be a person, one must be spatiotemporally finite. Moreover, one
must have beliefs, assuming any broad notion of belief according to which all the
metaphysical and metametaphysical claims discussed here as well as their denials count as
beliefs. Third, one must be able to perform “individual intentional actions” as well as that
of “engaging in relatively long-term plans and projects and deliberating about actions,
plans, and projects”. 332 Finally, one must have “the ability of have beliefs about beliefs,
330
Thomas White, In Defense of Dolphins: The New Moral Frontier, MA, Blackwell, 2007; and Mark
Rowlands, Can Animals be Persons?
331
Simon J. Evnine, Epistemic Dimensions of Personhood, pp. 16.
332
Ibid., pp. 14.
161
both one’s own and other people’s”. 333 Four other examples of broad conditions for
personhood discussed by Rowlands are: “consciousness, cognition, self-awareness and
other-awareness condition”. 334 This is to state that someone who accepts these conditions
takes that to be a person, first, one must be “the subject of conscious mental states”. 335
Second, one must be able to “engage in cognitive processes”. 336 Third, one “must be
conscious or aware of itself”. 337 Fourth, one “must be able to recognize other persons as
such, and act appropriately toward them because of this recognition”. 338 Other examples
of broad conditions for personhood that I am incline to embrace are: that to be a person,
one must have the power to engage oneself in these very disputes that have occurred since
immemorial times; and that to be a person, one must have individualistic and
communitarian tendencies, even though not all persons seek to maximize both of these
tendencies in being in accordance with the will to synthesis, as I propose.
It is not this dissertation’s goal to discuss whether any of the aforementioned broad
conditions is more adequate or persuasive than any other condition, or whether any of such
conditions can be subsumed to another one. It is worthy to emphasize, though, that
throughout the last century up to ours, several other analytic philosophers, such as Daniel
Dennett, Kathleen Wilkes, Robert Brandon, Carol Rovane, Tom Beauchamp and White,
have endorsed all sorts of broad conditions for personhood. 339 Nevertheless, as it might
333
Ibid., pp. 15.
Mark Rowlands, Can Animals be Persons?, pp. 27.
335
Ibid., pp. 18.
336
Ibid., pp. 19.
337
Ibid., pp. 21.
338
Ibid., pp. 23.
339
Daniel Dennett, “Conditions of Personhood,” in Amélie O. Rorty, (ed.). The Identities of Persons, CA:
University of California Press, 1976; Kathleen Wilkes, Real People: Personal Identity without Thought
Experiments, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1988; Robert Brandon, Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing,
and Discursive Commitment, MA, Harvard University Press, 1994; Carol Rovane, The Bounds of Agency:
An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1998; Tom Beauchamp,
334
162
have been expected given the Sisyphean hell-like process that, I tend to think, characterizes
the history of metaphysics, these philosophers have disagreed on which broad conditions
are to be endorsed. On my part, I remain neutral on this dispute of theirs. One reason for
being so is that if the informal method described by Evnine is the method to be adopted
while addressing this dispute (and all the authors named in this paragraph have more or
less implicitly assumed so), it seems that all authors named in this paragraph proposed
equally persuasive as well as unpersuasive broad conditions for personhood.
What is crucial for my purposes is that this dissertation only needs to commit itself
to a weaker claim: that the disjunction that either there are only broad conditions for
personhood or there is no condition for personhood at all may be inserted in P.2.
Accordingly, this is what I would like to do, while emphasizing that (6) follows, by modus
tollens, from P.1 and P.2 and that, if this is so, one is to keep an open mind regarding the
claim that the most persuasive picture of the history of metaphysics is the Sisyphean one.
“Hume on the Nonhuman Animal”, Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 24, 1999: pp. 322-35; and Thomas
White, In Defense of Dolphins: The New Moral Frontier.
CHAPTER 5
THE RIGHT-WING APPROACH TO METAPHYSICS
5.1 Macro-Political Conflicts: The Charlottesville-Conflict
Consider the Charlottesville-conflict. This is the conflict on whether the bronze
equestrian statue of a former confederate general, Robert E. Lee, is to be removed from a
public park in Charlottesville, Virginia, United States. Two approaches to this conflict are
the left-wing approach and the right-wing approach. To put in Willard Van Orman Quine’s
terms, these approaches deal with “the balance of tolerance” differently. 340 The left-wing
approach is that of those who tend to be more tolerant; those who tend to privilege their
powers to show empathy toward their others over their needs for self-defense. The rightwing approach is that of those who tend to be less tolerant in doing the opposite in
privileging self-defense over empathy. Another way to understand the left-wing / rightwing distinction I have in mind is by claiming that those who champion the former tend to
be more open-minded, whereas the champions of the latter tend to be more close-minded.
I would like to presuppose that empathy and self-defense refer to conscious or
unconscious feelings that have a passive and an active component. As Michael Slote
indicates, to passively empathize is to feel the suffering of someone (e.g., an other), or at
least to recognize that this suffering exists. 341 To actively empathize is to act under the
influence of this suffering in ceasing to give or at least attenuating the importance of one’s
particular identities so that this suffering is reduced. To passively self-defend oneself is to
feel that others are a threat to one’s own particular identities, or even to one’s very life. To
340
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary, MA Harvard
University Press, 1987: pp. 207.
341
Michael Slote, From Enlightenment to Receptivity: Rethinking our Values, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 2013; “Philosophy’s Dirty Secret: What Virtue Epistemology Needs to Learn about Human
Irrationality”, forthcoming; and “Philosophical Sin”, forthcoming.
163
164
actively self-defend oneself is to act under the influence of this feeling in seeking to protect
one’s life and/or conserve one’s particular identities. By a particular identity, it is to be
understood one shared by some, but not all entities. As indicated in 2.2, I call an identity
shared by all entities and that ultimately characterizes them insofar as entities a universal
identity. As also indicated in 2.2, God-driven philosophers suggest that to be into some sort
of non-causal relation with God is an universal identity, whereas human and physicalistdriven philosophers point to distinct directions: respectively, that to be into some sort of
non-causal relation with that which conditions human experience is a universal identity;
and that a universal identity is that of being in some sort of non-causal relation with a
neither divine nor human entity, such as the particles postulated by psychics.
To be Southern or descendent of Confederate soldiers, on the other hand, are
particular identities. The same is the case with the identity of being someone who endorses
a criterion to deal with disputes (e.g., accordance with intuitions) that others do not endorse.
It is important to emphasize that a particular identity is an implicit kind of communitarian
or, to put in Friedrich Nietzsche’s terms, herd constrain. This occurs because someone who
has or is recognized by a certain community as having a particular identity is expected to
use language, behave and even to feel in a certain matter. Consider someone who has or is
recognized by the contemporary American Southern community as having the particular
identity of being a heterosexual male. This community implicitly coerces this person; it
implicitly imposes upon him the norm that he is not supposed to wear or to even want to
wear pink shirts, say, as opposed to white ones, black pants, blue suits, etc. 342
342
In giving this example, I am inspired by Julia Serano, Outspoken: A Decade of Transgender Activism and
Trans Feminism, Oakland, Switch Hitter Press, 2016: pp. 264.
165
Imagine a left-winger and a right-winger who share some particular identities. They
are both white-skinned, cisgender, heterosexual, Christian, middle-class males who were
born and raised in Charlottesville. They are also descendants of soldiers who from 1861 to
1865 fought in the American Civil War alongside the defeated confederate forces
championed by Lee. Imagine that, passively, the left-winger feels or at least recognizes the
existence of the suffering of some of his others, say, black-skinned people who take that
Lee’s statue represents an endorsement of slavery, the segregationist Jim Crow laws
enforced in the Southern states after the Civil War up to the 1960s and/or, to say the least,
“problematic” ongoing attitudes, such as that of policemen who are more inclined to use
physical force against black-skinned people than against white-skinned ones. Actively, the
left-winger acts under the influence of this feeling. He does so by ceasing to give or at least
attenuating the importance of his own particular identities, especially that of being a
descendant of confederate soldiers. So, the left-winger stops taking seriously the implicit
communitarian constrain shared in Southern states according to which such descendants
are to feel proud of their heritage and show signs of this proudness in public spaces.
Indeed, the left-winger suspects the philanthropic intents of Paul Goodloe McIntire.
This is the man who bought the land of the current Charlottesville park in 1917, named this
park Lee Park and commissioned Lee’s statue from Henry Shrady, the sculptor who
worked on it from 1917 to 1922. Notice that Lee’s statue would only be inaugurated in
1924, after another sculptor, Leo Lentelli, also worked on it. The left-winger favors the
decision from June of 2017 of the Charlottesville City Council to change the name of the
park from Lee Park to Emancipation Park. The latter name, the left-wing believes, is a
much better one. This is so insofar as it represents, not an endorsement, but a condemnation
166
of slavery, the Jim Crow Laws and the aforementioned “problematic” attitudes. The leftwinger is also firmly convinced that Lee’s statue is to be removed and opposes those who
organized the rally of August 11th and 12th of 2017, that is, the Unite the Right Rally against
the statue’s removal. In fact, the left-winger goes to this rally to counter-protest it. He seeks
to embarrass the rally’s champions in screaming words of order, say, “Black lives matter”.
Imagine that, on the other hand, the right-winger passively feels that some of his
others (e.g., black-skinned people in general or those who champion the removal of Lee
statue) are a threat to his very life and/or at least to his particular identities, especially that
of being a descendant of confederate soldiers. Such others of his, the right-wing believes,
make it very hard for him to follow the implicit communitarian constrain widely shared in
Southern states that descendants of confederate soldiers are to feel proud of their heritage
and explicitly show signs of this proudness of theirs in public spaces. Actively, then, the
right-winger acts under the influence of this feeling of self-defense in detriment of his
power to show empathy. In order to protect his very life and/or his particular identities, he
opposes those who put into question the philanthropic intents of Paul Goodloe McIntire.
Moreover, imagine that the right-winger opposes the decision of the Charlottesville
City Council to change Lee Park’s name to Emancipation Park. For him, this is, to say the
least, an extremely disrespectful decision, not only regarding Lee, but also the confederate
soldiers who fought on his side as well as these soldiers’ descendants, including the rightwinger himself. He, then, joins the Unite the Right Rally. In marching with a torch
alongside hundreds of others who share particular identities with him, the right-winger
screams words of order, such as “blood and soil”, “you will not replace us”, “white lives
167
matter” and/or “Jews will not replace us”. Indeed, perhaps, he even goes as far as getting
himself involved in fist fights with those who counter-protest the Unite the Right Rally.
Note that, throughout this dissertation (starting in 1.5), I have associated the term
“libertarian” to Nietzsche, that is, someone who privileges the individualistic tendencies of
either consciously or unconsciously acting in accordance and contributing to affirm one’s
own singularity and/or those of others, while problematizing the constrains communities
impose upon such singularities. I have opposed libertarians to egalitarians, such as Rudolf
Carnap, that is, a philosopher who in my view privileges communitarian tendencies to
either consciously or unconsciously contribute to create a really universal community,
while seeking to attenuate one’s own’s singularity and/or the singularity of others.
In contemporary United Stated, nonetheless, “libertarian” is sometimes applied in
the sense of someone who endorses traditional Republican-party policies, such as that of
defending the right to bear guns; passing more restrict immigration laws; cutting taxes;
reducing public subsidies to health insurance; problematizing affirmative actions;
decreasing government’s aids, such as loans, for those who attend educational institutions;
promoting military interventions in foreign countries, such as Middle-Easter ones; etc.
Hence, “egalitarian” is also sometimes used in reference to those who oppose these
policies, say, in embracing traditional Democratic-party policies that contradict them.
It is not my aim, though, to discuss whether any use of the terms “libertarian” and
“egalitarian” is more “ordinary” or “legit” than mine. Indeed, I tend to believe that points
quite similar to the ones I made about the term “person” in 4.3 can be made about
practically all philosophical terms and that, hence, appeals to “ordinary language” are
highly problematic. Regardless of whether this is so, yet, what is crucial, for my purposes,
168
is to imagine that the left-winger is unsympathetic to the stated Republican-party policies.
Such policies, he believes, have overprivileged the needs for self-defense of those who
have particular identities similar to his over their powers to show empathy toward their
others who do not have such identities. Such others, the left-winger is persuaded, have
more often being killed for unjustified reasons and have had a harder time to come to
United States, to support their families, to treat their health problems, to get in and pay
their College’s debts because of these Republican policies. The left-winger also believes
American military interventions have had mainly negative effects, such as that of making
young middle-Eastern men more inclined toward terrorism. On this turn, the right-winger
endorses Republican policies. His view is that such policies have made it easier for him to
defend himself and his family; to live in a safer country; to spend and invest his stipends
with his own needs, not those of others; to get in and be more fairly treated by educational
institutions; to make the Middle East and the rest of the world a better place; etc.
What is also crucial is to imagine that the left-winger seeks to be in accordance with
his will to synthesis, while being both a libertarian and an egalitarian in this dissertation’s
sense. This is to state that he is a more open-minded person who embraces the very tension
that he is in aiming to be both in accordance with Nietzsche’s will to power and Carnap’s
will to order, that is, he seeks to maximize and to do justice both to individualistic
tendencies (that is, the many or singularity principle) and to communitarian tendencies
(that is, the one or identity principle), even if it may be ultimately impossible for a person
to perfectly do so. This is to state that the left-winger seeks to act in accordance and
contribute to affirm his own singularity or those of others insofar as beings who exist over
169
and above their particular identities and the implicit communitarian constrains they impose
upon their behaviors, that is, he problematizes or seeks to problematize such constrains.
Indeed, the left-winger has a considerably Utopian Nietzschean aim: that of making
people simply cease to care about these constrains in being in accordance with what is
singular about them. To do so, to use metaphors already used in 3.2, is to become a pure
cachaça drinker or a bird of prey that establishes one’s own criteria for anything, say, for
what counts as a proper moral behavior, beauty, etc. On the other hand, to continue to speak
metaphorically, the left-winger also seeks to be a lemonade drinker or a little lamb that
follows a community’s criteria for anything. This is to state that the left-winger
paradoxically also pursues a likewise Utopian Carnapian aim: that people or, more broadly,
beings in general lived in accordance with universally shared norms, regardless of what is
singular about them. Hence, while seeking to attenuate his own’s singularity and/or the
singularity of others, the left-winger also paradoxically aims to act in accordance and
contribute to create a really universal community. Given that right-wingers do not do so,
the left-winger takes them to be deep opponents of his. This is why he resists them, while
aiming to make them drop their practices in ultimately ceasing to be right-wingers.
A more direct way to state this is by imagining that the left-winger wishes that rightwingers were no longer xenophobes, classists, racists, sexists, transphobes, fascists who
cowardly and insensitively accept (in the left-winger’s view) unacceptable policies, such
as the one discussed in 1.3 of separating immigrant children from their parents and that of
constantly using the state’s power to spread a sort of biological or pseudo-biological
controversial claim: that people are born, to put in Donald Trump’s terms, either as
170
“winners” or as “losers” who are responsible for their own destiny and, consequently, merit
what they have accomplished, regardless of any social constrain they might have faced. 343
Imagine that the right-winger, on his part, does not take these policies to be
unacceptable ones —after all, he believes, there have been those who have been successful,
regardless of social adversity and those who came to the United States illegally are to be
punished for such a behavior; otherwise, people will continue to illegally cross the U.S. /
Mexico border. Moreover, the right-winger does not believe that the last paragraph’s
italicized terms are to be applied to him. Indeed, he feels considerably shocked or
embarrassed when he is described by such words. The matter is that the right-winger simply
does not seek to be in accordance with the will to synthesis, that is, he is a more closeminded person who aims to maximize neither his individualistic tendencies nor his
communitarian ones. This is to imagine that the right-winger is what I would like to call a
conservative, regardless of other possible uses the term “conservative” may have.
Negatively speaking, the right-winger is a conservative because he is simply no
libertarian in this dissertation’s sense. This is so insofar as he does not seek to act in
accordance with what is ultimately singular about himself or others. What he values the
most, instead, are the particular identities that he shares with others, such as the identities
of being white-skinned, from the South of the U.S., decedent of confederate soldiers,
cisgender, heterosexual, Christian, etc. Negatively speaking once again, the right-winger
is a conservative also because he is no egalitarian in this dissertation’ sense. This is because
the community whose members’ interests he seeks to defend is an extremely narrow one.
343
For a more detailed take on the close connection between right-wing policies and biological or pseudobiological discourse, see Jason Stanley, How Fascism Works: The Politics of Us and Them, New York,
Random House, 2018.
171
This narrow community only includes and aims to defend the interest of those who
share particular identities with the right-winger, that is, those who also seek to satisfy the
norms implicitly implied by such identities, such as the norm that descendants of
confederate soldiers are to feel proud of their heritage and explicitly show signs of this
proudness of theirs in public spaces. As stated above, the right-winger also consciously or
unconsciously privileges his need for self-defense over his power to show empathy toward
others. Indeed, the right-winger thinks that to do otherwise is imprudent because this
attitude puts one’s very life in danger or at least one’s particular identities and the implicit
communitarian constrains they imply. Positively speaking, the right-winger is a
conservative because he presupposes that such constrains are to be maintained. So, he takes
left-wingers to be deep opponents who must be resisted, and he aims to make them drop
their practices. More directly, he takes left-wingers to be anti-patriotic hypocrites; racists
against whites; heterophobes; oversensitive users of politically correct language or even,
to put in the non-politically terms right-wingers appreciate, “degenerated whores, faggots
and communists”; etc. I will address political correctness in the next chapter.
For now, note that the Charlottesville-conflict is an example of a macro-political
conflict. As stated in 1.5, three features characterize this kind of conflict. First, a macropolitical conflict explicitly has a significant social importance, that is, not only a single
individual, family or group of acquaintances care about it. Instead, a macro-conflict is one
that matters for hundreds, thousands, millions or, perhaps, even billions of people. As the
worldwide media coverage of the Charlottesville-conflict indicates, this quarrel has had a
social importance. The second feature of a macro-political conflict is that the conflicting
parties involved in the conflict seek to pressure a considerably large group of people (that
172
is, beyond their one’s own families or group of acquaintances) to change their practices.
While doing so, parties involved in a macro-conflict might even go as far as resorting to
upfront violence. This is also the case with the Charlottesville-conflict. In pressuring
opponents to drop their practices, parties involved in this conflict have marched with
torches, screamed words of order, fist-fought one another, etc. In the end, several people
got injured. In fact, a 32-year old woman, Heather Heyer, died after being hit by a car
driven by James Alex Fields Jr., a 20-year old who describes himself as a neo-Nazi and
was condemned on December of 2018 for first degree murder.
The third feature of a macro-political conflict is that it explicitly involves normative
issues. This feature is also present in the Charlottesville-conflict. First, because whether
one is to engage oneself in this conflict in the first place is a normative matter. Given that
in the past countless statues have been erected and removed without causing any conflict,
it may be argued that one is not to spend any time of one’s life in discussing about Lee’s
statue, that, to begin with, there simply are more urgent matters to be addressed. Moreover,
those who do not believe so in addressing the Charlottesville-conflict have disagreed on
whether Lee’s statue is to be removed. This is another normative issue. The same is the
case about another quarrel conflicting parties on the Charlottesville-conflict have
disagreed: the one on which criterion, to begin with, is to be used in addressing this conflict.
Consider that right-wingers have often relied on, say, the proud criterion according
to which one is to be proud of one’s historical heritage, whereas left-wingers have
frequently endorsed, say, the care criterion; one that states that one is to care about those
who are hurt by one’s historical heritage. Some conflicting parties may also have endorsed
a common criterion, say, the balance criterion according to which one must find a balance
173
between being proud of one’s heritage and caring about others who are hurt by it. Yet,
macro-right-winger and macro-left-wingers seem to have interpreted this criterion
differently in reaching no consensus on what counts as a balance in the first place.
Hence, the Charlottesville-conflict is a macro-political conflict. This claim, I
expect, will not face much significant resistance, and is not a very controversial one. The
same cannot be stated about the system of disputes’ seventh, eight and ninth claims: that
(7) Disputes are micro-political conflicts analogous to macro-political conflicts,
that is, they are micro-wars.
(8) There has been a right-wing allegedly apolitical approach to disputes that,
perhaps, avoids the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, but still expresses the
pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence.
(9) The properly dogmatic and the pseudo non-dogmatic “subtle” violence are to
be avoided.
The reason I expect to find resistance to (7), (8) and (9) is related to a fact
acknowledged by Socrates in the second book of Plato’s Republic. 344 The fact is that it is
easier to read big letters than little ones. Socrates’s view is that, analogously, it is easier to
understand a just city than a just man because it would simply be easier to observe the
phenomenon of justice in a larger scale as opposed to a smaller one. It is not my goal to
discuss whether this is so. What I would like to do, instead, is to confront the resistance to
(7), (8) and (9) by backing up the similar analogies that just like it is easier to read big
letters than little ones, it is easier to: first, acknowledge the existence of macro-political
conflicts than that of micro-political conflicts; second, identify a right-wing approach to
macro-political conflicts than to micro ones; and, third, criticize the upfront kinds of
344
Plato, The Republic of Plato (2nd edition), trans., Allan Bloom, New York, Basic Books, 1991: 368d, to
use the standard quotation method for Plato.
174
violence present in macro-political conflicts than the “subtle” ones at stake in micropolitical conflicts. Let me carefully spell out these analogies out by explaining what I mean
and imperfectly justifying (7), (8) and (9) in the next three sub-sections, respectively.
5.2 Micro-Political Conflicts: Disputes as Micro-Wars
A micro-political conflict has (on a smaller scale) the very same features that (on a
larger scale) can be found in a macro-political conflict. As indicated in 1.5, this is to state
that a micro-political conflict, like a macro-political one, is characterized by three features:
social importance; conflicting parties that aim to influence a significant group of people’s
practices; and presence of normative issues. Yet, whereas in a macro-political conflict these
features are very explicit and, so, considerably easily identifiable, these three features are
merely implicit and, so, very hardly identifiable in a micro-political conflict. Indeed, the
very parties involved in a micro-political conflict are often unaware of such features. The
same does not usually occur with parties involved in macro-political conflicts. Consider
the left-winger and the right-winger; it is not problematic to assume that they are both
aware that they are political agents engaged in a macro-political conflict with one another.
It is not surprising, then, that (7) has never been explicitly defended. 345 What
philosophers (at least, roughly, around the 17th century) have traditionally supported,
345
This is not to state that philosophers have not addressed the political assumptions of approaches to
metaphysics or pointed toward other theses closely connected to (7). Consider the following philosophers
who have inspired me: Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony and Solidarity, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1989; Michael Friedman, A Parting of the Ways, Illinois, Open Court, 2000; George A. Reisch, How
the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: to the Icy Slopes of Logic, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2005; Thomas L. Akehurst, The Cultural Politics of Analytic Philosophy: Britishness and
the Spectre of Europe, London, Continuum, 2010; David Plunkett, “Conceptual History, Conceptual Ethics,
and the Aims of Inquiry: A Framework for Thinking About the Relevance of the History / Genealogy of
Concepts to Normative Inquiry”, Ergo: Vol 3, no. 2 (2016): pp. 27-64; Sally Haslanger, Resisting Reality:
Social Construction and Social Critique, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012; etc.
175
instead, is the following disjunction: disputes are analogous to the disagreements of
mathematicians and/or empirical scientists, or at least one person deals with disputes in a
way that is analogous to the manner mathematicians and/or scientists have dealt with their
disagreements. Consider that, in the first paragraph of his 2nd Meditation released in 1641,
René Descartes likens his project to that of Archimedes in suggesting that he is such a
person. In his 1748 An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (see Book 1, §15),
David Hume points to a similar direction in suggesting that his project is considerably
similar to Newton’s. In the second preface of the 1887 edition of the Critique of Pure
Reason (see B xxii), Kant compares his critique to Copernicus’s revolution. This indicates
his commitment to the stated disjunction. More recently, Quine and others influenced by
him, such as David Lewis, Timothy Williamson and Theodore Sider have all pointed to a
similar direction. 346 On my part, I would like to remain neutral on the stated disjunction.
In order to do otherwise, I would have to engage myself in a challenging task that,
as indicated in 1.1, is not pursued here: that of articulating a reading about the
disagreements of mathematicians and empirical scientists. For my purposes, it suffices to
endorse a conditional: that if the disagreements of mathematicians and/or empirical
scientists are not micro-political conflicts analogous to macro-political ones, disputes are
not analogous to such disagreements. There may be reasons (even strong ones) for
endorsing this conditional’s antecedent. To discuss these reasons, though, is another
challenging task that I do not pursue. What is crucial is to emphasize that albeit I have
described myself in 3.2 as the observer the history of metaphysics, I would like to remain
346
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object; David Lewis, Philosophical Papers: Volume I, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 1983; On the Plurality of Worlds, MA, Blackwell, 1986; Timothy Williamson, The
Philosophy of Philosophy, MA, Blackwell, 2007; and Theodore Sider, Writing the Book of the World, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2011.
176
neutral on whether this procedure of mine is analogous to those of empirical scientists
and/or mathematicians. Note that the three previous chapters have already pointed to (7).
This is because it has hopefully been spelled out that Nietzsche and Carnap have
been ultimately engaged in a micro-political conflict, a micro-war, on how one is to do
philosophy. This micro-war has continued throughout the 20th century up to today insofar
as continental and analytic philosophers have been influenced either by Nietzsche’s
libertarian reaction or by Carnap’s egalitarian one to the fact that, since immemorial times,
persons have been engaged in disputes. It has also been insinuated that those who express
the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence are not exactly politically neutral. This chapter’s
aim, though, is to make a much more explicit case for (7) by making two new moves.
The first move is to exclusively focus on a single dispute that may seem (especially
for those who have endorsed the aforementioned disjunction) apolitical, perhaps, even
obviously apolitical. I call it the essence dispute: that on whether, independently of the way
entities are described, they have essences. The points I make about this dispute, it will be
indicated throughout this section, generalize to all disputes mentioned in this dissertation.
Henceforth, for short, I will refer to these disputes simply as all disputes. As indicated in
2.1, let me underline again that I use the term “entity” in a loose way that is to cover all
sorts of objects or things philosophers have talked about, such as evil, things-in-themselves,
consciousness, undeniable metaphysical claims, cyclists, the number 9, Socrates, the set
whose sole member is Socrates (henceforth, for short, singleton Socrates), etc.
The second move is that of exclusively focusing on three approaches to the essence
dispute that were articulated in the second half of the 20th century: those of Quine’s 1960
Word and Object; Saul Kripke’s 1980 Naming and Necessity; and Kit Fine’s 1994 article,
177
“Essence and Modality”. 347 Note that these philosophers share the following particular
identities: they have been described as analytic philosophers; they are supposedly apolitical
philosophers; they have been educated and worked in universities in wealthy Englishspeaking countries, such as the United States and the UK; they have not usually discussed
macro-political conflicts; they have presupposed that they did not have to justify
themselves for not discussing these matters; 348 they have been very influential within the
narrow community of those who share these particular identities with them; and, indeed,
in an anti-cosmopolitan way, they have primarily (if not practically, exclusively) addressed
the views of those who are likewise part of this community of theirs. In other words, Quine,
Kripke and Fine rely on strategically narrow bibliographies that do not include, say,
German and French continental philosophers, such as Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,
Karl Marx, Nietzsche, Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Gilles Deleuze, etc. 349 Also note
that I do not aim to approach three other disputes quite closely related to the essence one
that are also discussed by Quine, Kripke and Fine: respectively, the dispute on whether
modal logic is useful; the dispute on whether proper names have meaning and/or refer to
347
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1960; Saul Kripke, Naming
and Necessity, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1980; and Kit Fine “Essence and Modality”, in
Philosophical Perspectives Vol. 8: 1994: pp.1-16.
348
In contrast, consider Foucault’s debate with Chomsky. More precisely, the moment in which Foucault
answers Fons Elders’ question on why “he is so interested in politics” by stating the following: “I can’t
answer the question of why I should be interested; I could only answer it by asking why shouldn’t I be
interested? Not to be interested in politics, that’s what constitutes a problem. So instead of asking me, you
should ask someone who is not interested in politics and them your question would be well-founded, and you
would have the right to say, ‘Why, damn it, are you not interested?’”. Noam Chomsky and Michel Foucault,
The Chomsky-Foucault Debate: On Human Nature, New York, The New Press, 2006: pp. 37, my emphasis.
349
This did not impede Quine from signing a letter published at The Times in May 9th of 1992 against
Derrida’s nomination for an honorary degree by Cambridge University.
178
essences; and the dispute on whether there is a useful metaphysical idiom of grounding that
cannot be identified with modal notions, such as that of supervenience. 350
To begin with, the essence dispute, like all disputes, has a significant social
importance; not merely a single individual, family or group of acquaintances has cared
about it. At least since Ancient Greece, hundreds, thousands or perhaps even millions of
philosophers (or, more broadly, people in general) have given a lot of importance to this
dispute. Hence, they have spent a significant amount of their lives in dealing with it. Note
that they have not merely done so privately, say, in sharing their thoughts in personal
diaries or discussing them with family members, beloved ones or acquaintances. What
philosophers, such as Quine, Kripke and Fine, have done is to deal with the essence dispute
publicly. What I mean is that they have taught about this dispute in educational institutions;
they have dealt with this dispute in giving public lectures, publishing books and/or papers
in philosophical journals that in principle may be accessed by all persons. This is not to
state that the essence dispute has the same social importance of the Charlottesville-conflict.
The latter conflict has currently gathered much more attention than the former one.
Nonetheless, this is not a reason for taking that the essence dispute has no significant social
importance. Rather, this is merely a reason for taking this dispute to be a micro-political
conflict as opposed to a macro-political conflict. The same is the case with all disputes.
Furthermore, conflicting parties on the essence dispute have pressured a significant
amount of people to change their practices, say, by even going as far as resorting to
violence. Of course, the violence I have in mind is not of an upfront corporeal kind, such
350
See Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object; Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity; and Kit Fine,
“Guide to Ground”, in Fabrice Correia and Benjamin Schnieder (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding:
Understanding the Structure of Reality, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012.
179
as the ones expressed in the Unite the Right Rally. In the essence dispute, like in all
disputes, the kinds of violence that often are at stake are “subtle” ones, such as the properly
dogmatic “subtle” violence discussed in the last chapter. As stated above in 1.5 and 4.1,
this is the violence of using one’s writings to suggest that there is at least one undeniable
metaphysical claim, while not explicitly endorsing and, perhaps, even contradicting (1-i)
and/or (1-ii). Respectively, these are the claims that, among the others, some are legitimate
rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake; and that no person has settled a dispute once
and for all, that is, in a way that others could not rationally unsettle. To reject these claims,
then, is to insinuate that others are not really legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes
are at stake, and/or that one’s works, ultimately, settle at least dispute once and for all.
I am influenced by Quine in assuming that the principle of charity is that according
to which a text’s reader is to attempt to make most of the text’s statements true or at least
plausible and/or persuasive. 351 In embracing this principle, I claim that, while pressuring
their opponents to change their practices, Quine, Kripke and Fine, perhaps, avoid the
properly dogmatic “subtle” violence. This last claim is not very easy to sustain. Consider
Quine’s take on the essence dispute. According to him, this dispute is to be dismissed.
Quine’s argument for concluding so will be addressed in what follows. First, I approach
his way of dealing with his opponents, that is, the significant social group of thousands (if
not millions or even billions) of philosophers and persons in general who have relied on
terms, such as “essences”, “necessary attributes” or “internal relations”, and who make a
distinction between these terms and “accidents”, “contingent attributes” or “external
relations”. 352 This is a “distinction,” Quine states in seeking to pressure his opponents to
351
352
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, pp. 35.
Ibid., 199.
180
drop their practices of embracing this distinction, “that one attributes to Aristotle (subject
to contradiction by scholars, such being the penalty for attributions to Aristotle)”. 353
In this passage, it seems that Quine relies on a slightly coercive use of language of
the sort, as indicated above (see 3.1), criticized by the likes of Robert Nozick, David Lewis
and Peter van Inwagen. Indeed, my interpretation is that Quine not very subtly mocks
Aristotle and/or Aristotelian scholars in that he insinuates four points: that whether
Aristotle actually made the stated distinction is quite irrelevant; that the exegetical dispute
concerning whether this is so is not a very important one; that accordance with Aristotle’s
works is an ultimately useless criterion to deal with the essence dispute; and that historical
studies of the history of philosophy are ultimately quite irrelevant for contemporary
philosophers. In the end, Quine concludes by going as far as stating that “however
venerable the [accident-essence] distinction, it is surely indefensible”. 354
Note that the term “indefensible”, to speak metaphorically, “echoes” Immanuel
Kant’s claim that “there cannot be a single metaphysical problem that has not been solved
here”; Ludwig Wittgenstein’s “final solution” and Eli Hirsch’s “decisive rebuttal”
discussed in 4.2. Indeed, the accident-essence distinction would be “baffling” in provoking
an “appropriate sense of bewilderment”: a sense that Quine seeks to make explicit by
underlying that alleged essences of cyclists and mathematicians are that of being twolegged and that of being rational, respectively. 355 Quine asks his readers to imagine
someone who would be both a cyclist and a mathematician. He, then, argues that “there is
no semblance of sense” in rating some attributes of this person “as necessary and others as
353
Ibid.
Ibid., 199-200, my emphasis.
355
Ibid., 199, my emphasis.
354
181
contingent”. 356 Hence, these passages by Quine may be read as evidence that —like
Aristotle, after all —he likewise expresses the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence.
Also notice that if this is so, Quine’s works would, then, attest to George
Santayana’s famous phrase: “those who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat
it”. 357 This is because, like Aristotle after all, Quine would suggest that his writings attest
to the existence of an undeniable metaphysical claim: namely, that the accident-essence
distinction makes no sense. Quine would also imply that those who defend the
“indefensible” accident-essence distinction are not really legitimate rational peers insofar
as the essence dispute is at stake, and/or that his works settle this dispute once and for all.
Let us also consider Kripke’s take on the essence dispute. His view, distinct from
Quine’s, is the traditional Aristotelian one: that entities have essences as well as accidents,
independently of the way they are described. Accordingly, while pressuring his opponents,
such as Quine and the several hundreds or even thousands influenced by Quine, to endorse
this distinction, Kripke commits himself to the very kinds of claims Quine takes to cause
“bewilderment”. Two examples of such claims are that to be odd is an essence or a
necessary property of the number 9, and that to be the number of planets in our solar system
is an accident or a “contingent property” of the number 9. 358 Kripke’s argument for
embracing these claims will likewise be discussed in what follows.
For now, note that Kripke makes the following (arguably) slightly coercive and
(evidently) ironic claim: “people [like Quine himself, it is crucial to add] who think the
356
Ibid., my emphasis.
George Santayana, The Life of Reason, New York, Prometheus Books, 1998: pp. 82
358
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 40. Note that back in 1970 when Kripke gave the lectures at
Princeton University that became known as Naming and Necessity, Pluto was still considered a planet. Hence,
scientists understood our solar system to have nine planets, not eight as it is believed today.
357
182
notion of accidental property unintuitive have intuition reversed, I think”. 359 This passage
may be read as evidence that Kripke also follows Aristotle in a much more implicit way
that has not been noticed: that of expressing the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence. This
is to interpret that Kripke suggests that his own works attest to the existence of an
undeniable metaphysical claim: that entities have essences and accidents, independently of
the way they are described. It is plausive to read Kripke in such a way because he states
that to have “intuitive content” is “very heavy evidence in favor of anything”. 360 “I really
don’t know,” he continues, “what more conclusive evidence one can have about anything,
ultimately speaking”. 361 So, Kripke may be read as insinuating that his opponents on the
essence dispute are not really legitimate rational peers. This is because Kripke’s opponents
would have “intuition reversed”. In fact, given that Kripke relies on what is supposed to be
the most “conclusive evidence”, that is, his non-reversed intuition, he may be read as
suggesting that his works settle the essence dispute once and for all. I also underline that
Kripke neither explicitly spells out what he means by an intuition, nor relies on the
distinction made above (see 3.2) between the dogmatic and the conflictual use of intuitiontalk. Given the passages quoted in this paragraph, the latter use may be attributed to him.
Also consider Fine’s view on the essence dispute: that, regardless of whether
entities have essences independently of the way they are described, the notion of essence
is not to be conflated with that of a necessary property. As Fine indicates, several
philosophers or people in general (perhaps, even millions of them) have presupposed
otherwise. Arguably, this is the case with Quine and Kripke insofar as, indicated above,
359
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 42, my emphasis.
Ibid.
361
Ibid, my emphasis.
360
183
they may have believed that terms, such as “essence” and “necessary property”, are
interchangeable. In doing so, they may have suggested a biconditional: that an entity has a
property necessarily if and only if this property is the entity’s essence. On his part, while
implicitly pressuring his opponents to change their practices, Fine rejects this biconditional.
Fine’s view is that it is not the case that if an entity has a property necessarily, this property
is the entity’s essence. For him, only the converse would be the case.
Fine’s view, then, is that an entity’s essence is to be understood, not in modal terms,
but as a “real definition” that spells out what the entity ultimately is just like a verbal
definition would spell out what a word ultimately means. 362 I postpone to a few paragraphs
below the presentation of Fine’s argument for claiming so. For now, I focus on Fine’s
description of his opponents. “I am aware”, Fine argues, “that there may be readers
[perhaps, like Quine and Kripke themselves] who are so in the grip of the modal account
of essence that they are incapable of understanding the concept in any other way”. 363 “One
cannot, of course”, Fine continues, “argue a conceptually blind person into recognizing a
conceptual distinction, any more than one can argue a colour blind person into recognizing
a colour distinction”. 364 Indeed, there would be an “absurdity involved in attempting to
recover the essential properties of things from the class of necessary truth”. 365
These passages, then, seem to back up a reading according to which Fine expresses
the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, while suggesting that his own works attest to the
existence of at least one undeniable metaphysical claim: the very one that, regardless of
whether entities have essences independently of the way they are described, the notion of
362
Kit Fine, “Essence and Modality”, pp. 3.
Ibid., 5, my emphasis.
364
Ibid., my emphasis.
365
Ibid., 9, my emphasis.
363
184
essence is not to be conflated with that of a necessary property. In fact, consider Fine’s
expression, “conceptually blind person”. This expression echoes Aristotle’s (“no better
than a mere plant”) and Anselm’s (“stupid” and “fool”) discussed in 4.2 insofar as Fine
suggests that his opponent is impaired in being “conceptually blind”. This is to state that
Fine may likewise be read as someone who suggests that his others are not legitimate
rational peers concerning the essence dispute and/or that his take on this dispute is a once
and for all one. In assuming the principle of charity, though, this is not how I would like to
read Fine. This is to state that, regardless of the passages quoted in the last two paragraphs,
I do not wish to attribute to him the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence.
Instead, my reading is that Fine, perhaps, avoids expressing this kind of violence.
At least two passages of “Essence and Modality” appear to back up this reading of mine.
The first passage runs as follows: “it seems to be possible to agree on all modal facts and
yet disagree on the essentialist facts”. 366 The second passage is that in which Fine states
that: “it seems to me that far from viewing essence as a special case of metaphysical
necessity, we should view metaphysical necessity as a specially case of essence”. 367
Perhaps, these two passages would not have been made by someone who more or less
unconsciously follows Aristotle. From the latter, one would expect a much stronger claim,
such as: ultimately, only a stupid fool no better than a mere plant understands essence as a
special case of metaphysical necessity (as opposed to the opposite) or rejects that it is
rational to agree on all modal facts and still disagree on the essentialist facts.
In presupposing the principle of charity, I also do not attribute to Kripke and Quine
the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence. Instead, I claim that, perhaps, they avoid such
366
367
Ibid., 8, my emphasis.
Ibid., 9, my emphasis.
185
violence, regardless of the passages by them quoted above. I read them so because there
are also excerpts from Kripke and Quine that problematize the attribution of a properly
dogmatic “subtle” violence to them. Consider once again a passage by Kripke already
quoted above: that “people who think the notion of accidental property unintuitive have
intuition reversed, I think”. 368 Perhaps, the expression, “I think”, is not one that would be
expected from a dogmatist. The latter is expected to show no signs of uncertainty regarding
one’s own views. In using the expression “I think”, this is what Kripke does. Kripke also
claims that the feature of being “wrong” is “probably common to all philosophical
theories”. 369 Therefore, he does not take himself to be providing a philosophical theory,
but merely a “better picture” on the issues he approaches. 370 This move is not to be
expected from a dogmatist. A dogmatist, instead, is expected to describe one’s works, not
as a “better picture”, but as putting an end to the Sisyphean hell-like process described in
the last chapter and that, I tend to think, characterizes the history of metaphysics.
Quine, it is also important to underline, endorses a view of the left-wing Vienna
circle already discussed in 2.4. The view, as Carnap puts it, is that “the totality of what is
known about the world is always uncertain and continually in need of correction and
transformation”. 371 This is, I interpret, the lesson that Quine takes from a metaphor of Otto
Neurath. 372 In Quine’s words well-known words, “Neurath has likened science to a boat
368
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 42, my emphasis.
Ibid., 64.
370
Ibid., 93.
371
IAB 57.
372
Notice that Word and Object has the following passage by Neurath as its epigraph: “Wie Schiffer find
wir, die ihr Schiff auf offener See umbauen muffen, ohne es jemals in einem Dock zerlegen und aus bellen
Beftandteilen neu errichten zu können”. This passage can be translated as follows: “We are like seamen
having to rebuild their ship on the open sea, without ever being able to dismantle it in a dock and rebuild it
from scratch”. See Otto Neurath, “Protokollsätze”, Erkenntinis Vol. 3 (1932): pp. 206.
369
186
which, if we are to rebuild it, we must rebuild plank by plank while staying afloat in it”.373
Quine has a particular way of describing this action of rebuilding a boat afloat, that is, the
scientific community’s action of rejecting some scientific theories and endorsing others.
Quine’s way is that of spelling out that scientific theories are embraced insofar as they
maximize theoretical virtues, such as “conservatism, generality, simplicity, refutability and
modesty”. Hence, theories that fail to do so, on the other hand, would be rejected. 374
Like Lewis, Quine sometimes suggests that philosophers are to approach disputes
in a similar way. In my reading, this is what he means by the claim that “the philosopher
[at least the one who proceeds, like Quine] and the scientist are in the same boat”. 375 In a
less-known passage, Quine also states that “philosophy enjoys less firmness and
conclusiveness than astrophysics, so that there is some lack of professional consensus as
to what even qualified as responsible philosophy”. 376 These passages by Quine are also not
to be found in writings by dogmatists, such as the ones discussed in the last chapter. Such
dogmatists are more likely to argue or suggest much stronger claims, such as: science can
provide necessary claims, not merely contingent ones; the same can be stated about one’s
own metaphysical claims; and “responsible philosophy” provides undeniable metaphysical
claims that are as rationally undeniable as empirical and/or mathematical claims.
The reading supported here, though, is that the works of Quine as well as those of
Kripke and Fine express a second kind of “subtle” violence already mentioned in 1.5. I call
it the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence. This is the violence of avoiding the properly
373
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, pp. 3.
Willard Van Orman Quine, Pursuit of Truth, Cambridge, Harvard University, 1992: pp. 20. For a detailed
discussion of these virtues, see Willard Van Orman Quine and J.S. Ullian, The Web of Belief, New York,
McGraw-Hill Education, 1978: pp. 40-48.
375
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, pp. 3.
376
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quiddities, pp. 209.
374
187
dogmatic “subtle” violence in, perhaps, embracing (1-i) and (1-ii), while still contradicting
(1-iii). As indicated in 1.1, the latter is the claim that (1-i) and (1-ii) are extremely important
points insofar as those who fail to acknowledge them react in a quite unpersuasive manner
to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes. What I
mean is that the one who rejects (1-iii) suggests two points: that the existence of persons
who are others as well as legitimate rational peers is irrelevant, and that the same can be
stated about the claim that no person has settled a dispute once and for all. Accordingly,
the one who rejects (1-iii) reacts to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have
been engaged in disputes, by taking a dismissivist attitude. This is the attitude of simply
ignoring or acting as if this fact did not matter, say, because those who disagree with oneself
have, after all, “baffling” views, “intuition reversed”, are “conceptually blind”, etc.
The dismissivist attitude is embraced by those who, like Quine, Kripke and Fine,
simply do not pay much attention to the history of metaphysics and/or to methodological
matters while: first, embracing a controversial criterion to deal with disputes (e.g.,
accordance with intuitions) as if this criterion were universally shared by all persons, that
is, as if one could start without embracing any problematic starting point; and, second,
making supposedly persuasive claims about disputes, regardless of whether there are others
who interpret one’s criterion differently or simply do not accept it. Accordingly, Quine,
Kripke and Fine proceed as if God-driven simply did not exist or were not really worth
replying to. 377 They also simply do not address human-driven philosophers or continental
377
Arguably, nonetheless, most non-philosophers think quite similarly to God-driven philosophers. This
claim is backed up by a 2012 demographic study of the Pew Research Center. According to this study, 84 %
of the human beings alive in 2010 were religious at that time. This amounts to a total of 5.8 billion people.
The Pew study also concluded that there are “2.2 billion Christians (32% of the world’s population), 1.6
billion Muslims (23%), […] and 14 million Jews (0.2%) around the world as of 2010”. On my part, then, I
follow Markus Gabriel in believing that “we can no longer afford not to understand religion, as we effectively
live in an epoch of religious wars”. For the same reason, the God driven approach can neither be ignored, nor
188
philosophers, such as Nietzsche and those influenced by him, as if practically all of their
legitimate rational peers were physicalist-driven philosophers and/or had more or less the
very same aforementioned particular identities shared by Quine, Kripke and Fine. Note
that, in attributing the dismissivist practice to Quine, Kripke and Fine, I am influenced by
someone who also has these particular identities of theirs: namely, Peter van Inwagen who
claims that “present-day analytical philosophers tend simply not to permit the fact that
philosophical disagreement is irresoluble to come to their attention”. 378
On my part, I claim that the writings of Quine, Kripke and Fine express the pseudo
non-dogmatic “subtle” violence. This is, perhaps, the “subtlest” of all kinds of “subtle”
violence. Now, in order to further distinguish the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence
from the properly dogmatic one, an analogy with a more macro-conflict may be helpful.
Imagine two kinds of bullies during a school recess: popular student-athletes who verbally
and physically harass unpopular students in explicitly stating that they are, say, “losers” to
think and act how they do; and popular theater-students who very quietly make mean
comments to one another about unpopular students, giggle once they pass in front of them
and do not invite them to parties. Dogmatists who embrace the eliminativist attitude and
express the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence are analogous to the popular studentathletes. On their parts, those who endorse the dismissivist attitude and express the pseudonon-dogmatic “subtle” violence are analogous to the popular theater-students.
depicted as an unimportant one that is no longer adopted; key political figures themselves, such as Osama
bin Laden, and George W. Bush, also seem to think in a way considerably similar to that of God-driven
philosophers. See the Pew Research Center’s “The Global Religious Landscape”, published online on 2012
and (as of March 3rd of 2019) available at: http://www.pewforum.org/2012/12/18/global-religious-landscapeexec/. Also see Markus Gabriel, Why the World Does Not Exist, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2015: pp. 145.
378
Peter van Inwagen, “Freedom to Break the Laws”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXVIII, 2004: pp. 335.
189
The essence dispute also involves normative issues. These issues, though, are not
as explicitly present in this dispute as they are in the Charlottesville-conflict. Indeed, the
essence dispute is a descriptive dispute on whether, independently of the way entities are
described, they have essences; not a normative dispute on whether entities are to have
essences. My point, though, is that philosophers involved in the essence dispute presuppose
views on and, hence, implicitly address at least two normative issues. The first normative
issue concerns a practical matter: namely, whether one is to address the essence dispute (as
opposed to any other dispute) in the first place. Note that Quine, Kripke, Fine simply take
for granted that they may spend some of time of their lives in doing so. On the other hand,
deep opponents of theirs disagree with this attitude. In fact, such opponents may go as far
as claiming that the books and/or papers Quine, Kripke and Fine published about the
essence dispute were not to be articulated (not to mention published) in the first place. The
reason, these opponents believe, is that there are much more urgent matters, that is, matters
that deserve much more attention than the essence dispute. It is important to emphasize
that anyone engaged in any dispute seems to have or presuppose a view on the practical
dispute on whether the dispute at stake (as opposed to any other) is to be addressed.
The second normative issue is that, once it is granted that one may practically
engaged oneself in the essence dispute, a new practical dispute arises: that on which
criterion is to be adopted to deal with the essence dispute in the first place. Note that similar
practical disputes arise for anyone engaged in any dispute. In other words, the dispute on
which criterion is to be adopted when dealing with a dispute is inevitably implicitly present,
even though parties involved in the dispute may not be aware of such issue in “naively”
taking their criteria for granted. Also note that Quine, Kripke and Fine endorse
190
incompatible criteria to deal with the essence dispute. This is because they interpret what
counts as an “intuition” differently. 379 Now I underline that, in dealing with the essence
dispute, Quine does not use terms, such as “intuition” and its cognates, like “intuitively”,
“intuitive” or “intuitiveness”. However, I still interpret that he presupposes that accordance
with intuition is the criterion to be adopted when dealing with the essence dispute.
The reason I make this move is that, as indicated above, Quine states that the
accident-essence distinction is “baffling” and provokes an “appropriate sense of
bewilderment”. These expressions, I interpret, are Quine’s way of indicating that the
accident-essence distinction is a very counter-intuitive one. His quite simple argument is
that, given that this is so, this distinction should be dismissed. The same, then, would have
to be done regarding the essence dispute, given that this dispute relies on such distinction.
As indicated above, Quine seeks to spell out the counter-intuitiveness of the accidentessence distinction by imagining someone who is both a mathematician and cyclist. He
presupposes that philosophers who endorse the accident-essence distinction take
mathematicians to be “necessarily rational and not necessarily two-legged”. 380 Such
philosophers would also take cyclists to be “necessarily two-legged and not necessarily
rational”. 381 “Is this concrete individual”, that is, a mathematician-cyclist, Quine asks
“necessarily rational and contingently two-legged or vice-versa?”. 382 For Quine, this
379
Note that Herman Cappelen claims that though analytic philosophers have relied heavily on intuition-talk,
they do not take intuition as evidence or a source of evidence of philosophical theories. If this is so,
accordance with intuitions is not a criterion to approach disputes widely shared. I cannot discuss Cappelen’s
view in this dissertation. See Herman Cappelen, Philosophy Without Intuitions, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 2012. For an objection to Cappelen that I am inclined to endorse, see Berit Brogaard, “Intuitions as
Intellectual Seemings”, in Analytic Philosophy Volume 55, Issue 4 (December 2014): pp. 382–39.
380
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, pp. 199.
381
Ibid.
382
Ibid.
191
question is extremely odd. Consequently, this very question would show that the accidentessence distinction is, indeed, an extremely counter-intuitive one.
Notice, though, that it is simply not clear whether Quine relies on a dogmatic or on
a conflictual use of intuition or intuition-like talk when adopting expressions, such as
“baffling” and “appropriate sense of bewilderment”. As it might have been expected from
a pseudo-non-dogmatic, Quine’s use of language, like Kripke’s, is quite unprecise in this
regard. It follows that, in Word and Object, it is not clear: whether he takes this “sense of
bewilderment” to be universally shared and, hence, able to provide a rationally undeniable
justification for his take on the essence dispute; or whether Quine is aware that what is
“baffling” for oneself is “intuitive” for others so that to state that a claim seems “baffling”
ultimately merely provides, to say the least, a considerably imperfect justification.
On his part, Kripke relies heavily and very explicitly on intuition-talk, even though,
as stated above, it is also unclear whether he makes a dogmatic or a conflictual use of such
talk; Kripke’s use of language is also quite imprecise on this issue. Notice that Kripke’s
argument for embracing the accident-essence distinction is also a quite simple one and, in
the end, surprisingly similar to Quine’s. Kripke’s argument is that, given that the accidentessence distinction is intuitive (that is, after all, only someone with “intuition reversed”
does not endorse it), the distinction is to be embraced. 383 Kripke does not address the person
who is both a mathematician and cyclist. What he does, instead, is to give examples that
are supposed to show the extreme intuitiveness of the accident-essence distinction, such as
that to be odd is an essence of the number 9 and that to have originated from a particular
“biological sperm and egg” is an essence of Queen Elizabeth. 384
383
384
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 42.
Ibid., pp. 112.
192
Like Kripke, Fine also explicitly relies on intuition-talk without stating what he
means by an “intuition” or spelling out whether his use of intuition-talk is a dogmatic or a
conflictual use as if this issue did not matter. As indicated above, Fine’s view, though, is
not Kripke’s. Fine claims that, regardless of whether entities have essences independently
of the way they are described, the notion of essence is not be conflated with that of a
necessary property. This conclusion would follow from the premise that “intuitively” there
are entities that have necessary properties that are not identical to their essences. 385 In
proceeding in a way that resembles Quine’s and Kripke’s, Fine discusses a case that is
supposed to make his intuition evident: the case of Socrates, and the singleton Socrates.
It is “necessary, according to standard views within modal set theory”, Fine claims,
“that Socrates belongs to singleton Socrates if he exists”. 386 The reason, Fine continues, is
that “necessarily, the singleton exists if Socrates exists and, necessarily, Socrates belongs
to singleton Socrates if both Socrates and the singleton exist”. 387 Hence, those who believe
that the notion of essence is to be understood in modal terms would have to conclude that
to be part of Socrates singleton is, not only a necessary property of Socrates, but also his
very essence. In Fine’s view, this conclusion is extremely counter-intuitive. This is why it
would be “inappropriate” to conflate the notion of a necessary property with that of
essence. 388 An essence would have to be understood as a real definition. According to Fine,
Aristotle himself indicates so in stating “in the Metaphysics 1031a12 […] that ‘definition
385
Kit Fine, “Essence and Modality”, pp. 4.
Ibid.
387
Ibid.
388
Ibid., 8.
386
193
is the formula of essence’”, even though Aristotle would also sometimes suggest otherwise
by likewise pointing toward a modal interpretation of the notion of essence. 389
Notice that, recently, there has been a lot of empirical work on whether intuitions
vary with nationality, class, gender, race, etc. 390 For my purposes, though, this empirical
inquiry is not very relevant. What is crucial here is that Quine, Kripke or Fine do not spell
out necessary and/or sufficient conditions for something to be an intuition. What is also
crucial is that they presuppose accordance with intuition as a criterion to deal with the
essence dispute and, ultimately, simply interpret this criterion differently from one another.
Another more explicit way to put this is by stating that Quine relies on what might be called
intuitionQuine, Kripke embraces intuitionKripke and Fine endorses intuitionFine. It follows that
it is not surprising that they do not agree on the essence dispute, that is, how could they,
given that they simply do not embrace a common criterion to deal with this dispute?
What is surprising, instead, is the fact that Quine, Kripke and Fine simply do not
explicitly acknowledge that intuitionQuine, intuitionKripke and intuitionFine are distinct from
one another and not universally shared, not even by the quite narrow community of those
who have particular identities similar to theirs and they care to mention in their writings. It
follows that Quine, Kripke and Fine rely on what may be called overly imperfect
justificatory resources, whose lack of persuasiveness is explicit, at least for those who are
aware of the fact that, since immemorial times (as opposed to, say, the 1960s, 1980s or
1990s) persons have been engaged in disputes; those who proceed as observers of the
history of metaphysics in carefully studying this history and suspecting that the essence
389
Ibid., 2.
See, for example, the essays gathered at Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols, Experimental Philosophy:
Volume I, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2008.
390
194
dispute, like any other, would have been solved long ago, were persons to have the very
same universally shared intuition about it. To put it metaphorically, my view is that there
would be an easy way to stop the Sisyphean-hell like process that (arguably) characterizes
the history of metaphysics, if there were a universally shared intuition about the essence
dispute, that is, it seems extremely “unrealistic” to believe that there is such an intuition
and only someone who has not carefully observed the history of metaphysics could take
one’s intuition to be of such kind. Given that, as the very works of Quine, Kripke and Fine
indicate, persons have had all sorts of contrasting intuitions about essence, we appear to be
all part of such Sisyphean-hell like process whose end is unpredictable.
More importantly, it follows that the essence dispute is a micro-political conflict
or, as I prefer to put it, a micro-war whose political character is merely implicit and, hence,
hardly identifiable. This a reason for embracing (7) in taking that all disputes are similar to
the essence dispute insofar as they are micro-wars analogous to macro-political conflicts.
5.3 The Right-Wing Political Practice of Depoliticization
I claim that the approaches to the essence of dispute of Quine, Kripke and Fine also
attest to the eighth claim of the system of disputes, (8), there has been a right-wing allegedly
apolitical approach to disputes that, perhaps, avoids the properly dogmatic “subtle”
violence, but still expresses the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence. Let me start to
explain what I mean and to imperfectly justify this claim by underlying that my wish is not
that of suggesting that Quine, Kripke and Fine have views on macro-political conflicts.
Consider a 1993 interview by Quine. When asked by Steven Vita of Veery whether
philosophy has “any business” with “social/political concerns,” Quine’s reply was: “I don’t
195
think my philosophy does”. 391 Kripke and Fine, I think it is quite safe to presuppose, would
give similar answers. In fact, in an informal interview from February 25th of 2001 that can
be found online at David Boles, Blogs, Kripke is quoted by Andreas Saugstad as having
stated that “a lot of philosophy does not have relevance to life”; he suggests that this is also
the case with his own philosophy. 392 My reading is that what Kripke means is that his
philosophy simply does not address any macro-political conflict. I do not challenge that
the same is the case with Fine’s philosophy. What I do, instead, is to claim that Quine,
Kripke and Fine are supposedly apolitical philosophers in a quite specific sense.
The sense is that they do not acknowledge or are not aware that, in dealing with the
essence dispute, they are themselves engaged in a micro-war characterized by: its implicit
social importance; conflicting parties’ aims to change the practices of a significant amount
of people; and presence of normative issues. Analogously, these philosophers are like those
who, say, march with torches, scream words of order and fist-fight others in actively
participating in the Unite the Right, while still, nonetheless, taking themselves to be
politically neutral. Accordingly, what I mean by the claim that Quine, Kripke and Fine
champion practices of depolicization is that these philosophers deal with the essence
dispute by acting: first, as if this dispute did not have a social importance (and, say, they
were merely stating their views privately among a few beloved ones or acquaintances);
second, as if they were not pressuring their opponents to change their practices while
expressing the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence regarding their others (and, say,
their uses of language were “peaceful” uses that are not at all offensive regarding hundreds,
391
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quine in Dialogue, MA, Harvard University Press, 2008: pp. 34.
As of January 28th of 2019, this interview could be found in the following website:
https://bolesblogs.com/2001/02/25/saul-kripke-genius-logician/#comments.
392
196
thousands or even millions of their actual or potential readers); and/or, third, as if they did
not presuppose views on normative issues, such as the practical disputes on why one is to
do deal with the essence dispute, and on which criterion is to be adopted in doing so.
Note that there are those who, to begin with, are simply not very interested in the
essence dispute and do not engage themselves on it. Also note that, throughout the 20th
century up to today, this dispute has been dealt in a way very distinct from Quine’s,
Kripke’s and Fine’s by those who are also never mentioned in these philosophers’
strategically narrow bibliographies that practically only include those who have particular
identities similar to theirs. I once again have in mind the likes of Simone de Beauvoir,
Martin Luther King, Malcolm X, Angela Davis, Cornel West, Catherine MacKinnon,
Linda Alcoff, Gayle Rubin, Sally Haslanger, Julia Serano, etc. 393 Regardless of their
differences, these activists and/or philosophers have more or less explicitly addressed the
essence dispute by embracing a distinct criterion. I call it oppression acknowledgement.
As stated in 4.3, this criterion is satisfied whenever one spells out and resists practices of
oppression, such as that of spreading the stereotype that Mexicans are dangerous, that is,
that to be dangerous is the very essence of Mexicans. It is also crucial to underline that
those who embrace oppression acknowledgement are not interested in the examples of
essence-talk considered by Quine, Kripke or Fine. What matters for them, instead, is to
393
Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, London, Lowe and Brydone, 1953; Martin Luther King, A
Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches, New York, Harper Collins Publishers, 1986;
Malcolm X, Malcolm X Speaks: Selected Speeches and Statements, New York, Merit Publishers and Betty
Shabazz, 1965; Angela Davis, The Angela Y. Davis Reader, MA, Blackwell Publishers, 1998; Cornel West,
The Cornel West Reader, New York, Basic Civitas Book, 1999; Catherine MacKinnon, Are Women Human?,
MA, Harvard University Press, 2006; Linda Alcoff, Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2006; Gayle Rubin, Deviations: A Gayle Rubin Reader, North Caroline, Duke
University Press, 2011; Sally Haslanger, Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2012; Julia Serano, Outspoken: A Decade of Transgender Activism and Trans
Feminism, Oakland, Switch Hitter Press, 2016; etc.
197
spell out whether talk about the essences of underprivileged groups (e.g., black-skinned
people, women, Jews, Latinos, etc) has served to legitimatize practices of oppression, such
as the one just stated. This is not an issue that Quine, Kripke or Fine discuss or mention.
However, it is worth to address passages from Quine’s 1985 autobiography, The
Time of My Life: An Autobiography, that point to the stereotype that to be dangerous is an
essence of Mexicans. In the passages (surprisingly, rarely mentioned) that I have in mind,
Quine recalls his mother’s “honorary Uncle Ellis”. 394 “‘Never turn your back on a
Mexican’, Uncle Ellis used to say, if my mother was to be believed, and believed indeed
she was, implicitly”, Quine remembers. 395 In visiting Mexico in 1941, Quine also recalls
his mother’s Uncle Ellis. He states that “the average townsman was an Indian with a dash
of Spanish. He wore a sarape, either impaled as a poncho or shawl-wise, and a big
sombrero. If elegant he might wear a holster and a pearl-handled pistol”. 396 “Echoes of
Uncle Ellis: ‘Never turn your back on a Mexican’”, Quine goes as far as emphasizing. 397
The “echoes” I expect readers to hear are those of the current American President,
Donald Trump. As it is well-known, he has promised to build a wall in the U.S. / Mexico
border. In a speech in June 16th of 2015 in New York, he stated that Mexicans are “bringing
drugs, they’re bringing crime, they’re rapists, and some, I assume are good people”. I
emphasize that I am neutral on whether oppression acknowledgement is the best criterion
to deal with the essence dispute. What is crucial for my purposes is to make explicit that
Quine, Kripke and Fine are implicitly engaged in a normative quarrel with those who they
394
Willard Van Orman Quine, The Time of My Life: An Autobiography, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1985:
pp. 128.
395
Ibid., my emphasis.
396
Ibid., 153.
397
Ibid., my emphasis.
198
simply do not care to mention; those who simply do not grant that accordance with any
kind of intuition (say, intuitonQuine, intuitionKripke or intuitionFine) is the criterion that, to
begin with, is to be adopted when dealing with the essence dispute. What I also would like
to emphasize is that, regardless of their differences, Quine, Kripke and Fine all champion
right-wing micro-political practices, when addressing the essence dispute.
Before I spell out what I mean by this last claim, it is important to underline that
the distinction between left-wingers and right-wingers is not a very strict one. This
distinction is, rather, one merely of degree. This can be spelled out by considering what
may be called a political spectrum whose left-extremity and right-extremity are occupied
by the left-winger-in-itself and the right-winger-in-itself, respectively. In the exact middle
of such a political spectrum, imagine that there lies a centrist-in-itself. The left-winger-initself deals with the balance of tolerance in an ultimately imprudent way in exclusively
showing empathy toward others and ultimately disregarding any need for self-defense. To
put it metaphorically, the mind of the left-winger-in-itself is simply “too open” like an open
field. The right-winger-in-itself exclusively privileges one’s need for self-defense and
shows no empathy toward his others. Hence, to put it metaphorically again, the mind of
right-winger-in-itself is simply “too close”, like a vault. The centrist-in-itself deals with the
conflict between empathy and self-defense in showing an equal “amount” of the two.
It is safe to presuppose that no actual person can be identified with the left, the right
or the centrist-in-itself. It seems, instead, that actual people never exactly fall in the
extremities or in the very middle of the political spectrum, that is, they are always more or
less inclined toward the left or the right-extremity. For instance, the historical Jesus Christ
seems to have been quite close to the left-extremity, whereas Julius Caesar seems to have
199
been considerably close to the right-extremity. Barack Obama seems to fall out of the
center of the spectrum by being a bit more inclined toward the left-extremity. The same is
the case with the Southern left-winger mentioned in this chapter’s introduction or the
former Brazilian president, Luis Inácio Lula da Silva. Like the Southern right-winger,
Donald Trump or Jair Bolsonaro seem to be more inclined toward the right-extremity.
Moreover, it may be impossible to precisely measure an individual’s overall
“balance of tolerance”, to put in Quine’s terms again. 398 This happens because people, I
take it for granted, have constantly acted as left-wingers concerning one micro or macropolitical conflict, but as right-wingers regarding other ones, that is, one may be quite openminded about a conflict, while being quite close-minded regarding a distinct conflict. What
I mean is that someone who tends to privilege empathy over self-defense in certain
occasions might do otherwise in others and vice-versa. For instance, a white person who
seems to be often more inclined to privilege one’s needs for self-defense might sometimes
be somehow “off-guard” in a foreign country in entitling oneself to accept an invitation to
go into the house and have a cachaça with a “mulatto”. 399 It follows that it is more careful
to qualify approaches to conflict or practices (as opposed to people) as being from the left,
398
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary, pp. 207.
Consider that Quine lived in Brazil from 1941 to 1942. He learned how to speak and even published a
book in Portuguese: O Sentido da nova lógica (The Sense of the New Logic). In Quine’s autobiography, he
recounts his experiences in my hometown, Rio de Janeiro, such as the time in which he “was wondering how
to get through the solid ring of houses that girdled the base of [a] hill”. Quine tells, then, the following: “I
saw a black woman with laden head go through a doorway that proved to lead between houses rather than
into a house. The path meandered up the hill and I followed it to the top. There I talked with a mulatto who
was raking the arid little fenced yard in front of his humble house. He invited me in and we had a tot of
cachaça, the colorless cane spirit that is the common man’s tipple in Brazil. He was in the navy and proudly
showed me his identification card. Along with his photograph and other data, it indicated his color. There
were preto (black), mulato, pardo, and branco (white). His was ticked off as pardo”. Another “curious thing”,
to paraphrase Quine once again, is the fact that Quine describes the man he met as a “mulatto”, even though
the man’s navy card indicated that he was a “pardo”. In Portuguese, a “mulato” is someone whose skin color
is darker than that of a “pardo”. See Willard Van Orman Quine, The Time of My Life: An Autobiography, pp.
168; and “On what there is”, The Review of Metaphysics Vol. 2. No. 5, Sep., 1948: pp. 21.
399
200
right or center. I do not claim, then, that Quine, Kripke or Fine are right-wing persons.
What I argue is that, regardless of their differences, Quine’s, Kripke’s and Fine’s
approaches to the essence dispute are right-wing ones analogous to the right-wing approach
to the Charlottesville-conflict. This is to state that, in dealing with the essence dispute, these
philosophers embrace practices that are less inclined toward the left-extremity and more
inclined toward the right-extremity of the political spectrum.
Consider Quine’s approach once again. What the passages by him quoted above
indicate is that, passively, he seems to feel or deals with the essence dispute as if his others
were a threat, if not to his very life, at least to one of his particular identities. Notice that
Quine’s others are not exactly those of the Southern right-winger, albeit there might be
some overlaps. Quine’s others are those who strongly disagree with his take on the essence
dispute, say, they, to begin with, simply do not grant that one is to spend any time of one’s
life in discussing this issue; they do not endorse Quine’s presupposition that accordance
with intuitionQuine is the criterion to deal with this dispute in the first place; they do not
think that to focus on the person who is cyclist and a mathematician is a pertinent move
when the essence dispute is at stake; they simply do not have intuitionQuine; they defend
what Quine takes to be “indefensible”; and/or they do not have all the aforementioned
particular identities that Quine shares with Kripke and Fine; etc.
The particular identity of Quine that is relevant is also not to be confounded with
those that matter on the Charlottesville-conflict, such as that of being a descendant of
confederate soldiers. Quine’s relevant particular identity is that of being a champion of the
empiricist tradition of the likes of David Hume and the logical positivists, such as Carnap
and Neurath. This is to state that, regardless of Quine’s objections to these philosophers
201
and of the fact that he ignores Carnap’s and Neurath’s political views discussed in the
second chapter, he takes himself to belong to their tradition. In Quine’s interpretation,
members of this tradition deal or should deal with disputes in a way that is analogous to
the way empirical scientists and/or mathematicians approach their disagreements. The
latter, the Quine of Word and Object interprets, have no need for what he calls “intensional
objects”, such as meanings, propositions and essences. 400 He suggests, then, that those who
share with him the particular identity of being empiricists are to endorse intuitionQuine.
Actively, then, Quine seeks to protect his particular identity of being a champion
of the empiricist tradition by acting under the influence of the feeling that his others are a
threat. What backs up this last claim is the textual evidence provided in the last section,
that is, the evidence that, in dealing with the essence dispute, Quine champions a
dismissivist attitude regarding the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been
engaged in disputes. He simply acts as if this fact did not matter or could simply be ignored.
While doing so, he perhaps avoids the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, but not the
pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence. More directly, Quine acts under the assumption
that he may disregard the fact that some others are legitimate rational peers insofar as
disputes are concerned and that, especially given so, Quine’s very take on the essence
dispute is not a once for one take. Of course, this is not an upfront kind of violence, such
as those expressed by the Southern right-winger of marching with torches, screaming
words of orders, fist-fighting, etc. However, Quine’s procedure concerning the essence
dispute (a micro-political conflict, a micro-war) is analogous to the way this right-winger
deals with the Charlottesville-conflict. This is to read that, ultimately, Quine and the right-
400
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, pp. 206.
202
winger (respectively, in a micro-scale and in a macro-scale) privilege their needs for selfdefense over their powers to show empathy toward their others. Note that it is extremely
hard to see, to put in Quine’s own terms, the “experimental spirit” of this attitude. 401
I read Kripke along similar lines, as my take on the passages by him addressed
above indicates. What I mean is that, passively, Kripke also seems to feel or deals with the
essence dispute as if his others were a threat, if not to his life, at least to one particular
identity of his: that of being a champion of the counter-empiricist tradition. This tradition
is that of defending what its champions take to be “common sense” by using analytic
resources (e.g., that of differentiating distinct theories of proper names) that (allegedly)
show the shortcomings of empiricism, such as its (allegedly) disrespect to the intuitions of
the “ordinary man” and its (allegedly) unwarranted defense of materialism. 402 Actively,
Kripke appear to seek to protect this particular identity of his. Like Quine, he does so by
championing a dismissivist attitude regarding the fact that, since immemorial times,
persons have been engaged in disputes. In doing so, he also perhaps avoids the properly
dogmatic “subtle” violence, but not the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence.
Kripke’s others are those who strongly disagree with his take on the essence
dispute, say, they, to begin with, simply do not grant that one is to spend any time of one’s
life in discussing this matter; they do not endorse Kripke’s presupposition that accordance
with intuitionKripke is the criterion to deal with this dispute in the first place; they do not
think that to focus on the examples focused by Kripke is a pertinent move when the essence
dispute is at stake; they do not have intuitionKripke; they take it to be an overly imperfect
justificatory resource to speak in the name of an “ordinary man” as if such a man were
401
402
Willard Van Orman Quine, “On what there is”, pp. 38.
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 41.
203
more inclined toward intuitionKripke as opposed to intuitionQuine , intuitionFine or any other
intuition; they wonder whether the “ordinary man” Kripke has in mind is a right-winger or
a left-winger; and/or they get annoyed by the “jokes” of Naming and Necessity; etc.
The passages by Fine quoted above likewise attest to the fact that he, like Quine
and Kripke, ultimately adopts a right-wing approach to the essence dispute. My reading is
that, passively, Fine seems to feel or deals with the essence dispute as if his others were a
threat, if not to his life, at least to one of his particular identities. The particular identity I
have in mind here is that of being a champion of a neo-Aristotelian tradition. By this, I
understand a tradition that understands itself to be engaged in “metaphysics” in a way
allegedly inspired by Aristotle: that of an inquiry that relies on a priori-methods; has a
considerably general subject-matter; uses “transparent concepts” (that is, those, such as
identity, that are not significant distinct from what they are concepts of); is concerned with
the nature of things and aims to play a “role as a foundation for what there is”. 403
Note that, in allegedly following Aristotle, this tradition contradicts Quine in
having no reservation concerning the use of intensional concepts or even hyper-intensional
ones, like “essence” turns out to be in Fine’s interpretation. 404 By Fine’s others, it is to be
understood those who strongly disagree with his take on the essence dispute. In other
words, those who: do not believe that one is to spend any time of one’s life in discussing
this dispute; simply do not endorse Fine ’s presupposition that accordance with intuitionFine
is the criterion to deal with this dispute in the first place; do not think that to focus on the
403
Kit Fine, “What is Metaphysics?”, in Tuomas E. Tahko (ed.). Contemporary Aristotelian Metaphysics,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012: pp. 8-25.
404
To distinguish extensional, intensional and hyperintensional notions from one another and to spell out the
distinct approaches to metaphysics these notions imply are tasks that I cannot pursue here. For such an
inquiry, see Daniel Nolan, “Hyperintensional metaphysics”, Philosophical Studies, October 2014, Volume
171, Issue 1: pp 149-160.
204
Socrates/Socrates singleton example is a pertinent move when the essence dispute is at
stake; simply do not have intuitionFine; are offended by Fine’s claim that to reject this
intuition is to be “conceptually blind”; and/or find the fact that Fine (like Kripke and Quine)
address the problem of essence, without mentioning oppression acknowledgment an
extremely “problematic” move, to put it in polite terms; etc. Actively, Fine appears to seek
to self-defend himself from such others in aiming to protect, if not his life, at least this
particular identity of being a neo-Aristotelian. I claim so because, as the textual evidence
provided above indicates, he also adopts the dismissivist attitude in, perhaps, avoiding the
properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, but not the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence.
Note, nonetheless, that the fact that Quine, Kripke and Fine disagree on a theoretical
dispute and implicitly champion slightly distinct traditions (that is, the empiricist, the
counter-empiricist and the neo-Aristotelian one, respectively) is not to be overestimated.
Indeed, as Slote (in conversation) emphasizes, Kripke might after all agree with Fine’s
distinction between necessary properties and essences, even though Kripke himself does
not explicitly make such distinction in Naming and Necessity. As Slote (in conversation)
also indicates, Kripke might likewise agree with Quine’s reading of the mathematiciancyclist example, regardless of the fact that he disagrees with Quine’s view that modal
vocabulary is to be simply dismissed. What I mean is that Quine, Kripke and Fine are
merely superficial opponents of one another. This is to state that, practically speaking, these
philosophers have benefited one another in publicly reacting to one another’s works; have
studied and been employed by similar departments; published on similar journals; dealt
with similar disputes; embraced quite similar methods of justification; etc. Quine’s,
Kripke’s and Fine’s deep opponents have not done so, that is, such deep opponents of theirs
205
are those who they do not care to mention and who do not share the dismissive attitude
concerning the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.
Analogously, on a macro-level, consider any right-wing party, such as the American
Republican party. Such parties have had all kinds of internal disagreements and distinct
factions within themselves. This has not been a reason for overestimating such differences
in failing to emphasize right-wing parties’ deep opponents: namely, left-wing parties.
Like the approach of the right-winger to the Charlottesville-conflict, then, those of
Quine, Kripke and Fine to the essence dispute are neither libertarian nor egalitarian ones
(in this dissertation’s sense). Their approaches are not libertarian ones because they do not
seem to act in accordance with what is singular about themselves, say, in attempting to deal
with disputes in a way that resists being associated with any tradition in articulating an
ultimately unique criterion to deal with disputes. What Quine, Kripke and Fine propose are
criteria that the members of their respective traditions or herds are likely or at least are
supposed to endorse, that is, accordance with intuitionQuine, intuitionKripke and intuitionFine.
Once again, though, the differences between these philosophers is not to be overestimated;
the fact that they share distinct intuitions is not to hide the distinct fact that they all act in
accordance with the assumption that philosophers are to speak in the name of intuitions,
without explicitly determining whether a dogmatic or a conflictual use is at stake.
Quine’s, Kripke’s and Fine’s approaches to the essence dispute are also not
egalitarian ones. This is because the communities whose criteria they aim to satisfy and
whose members’ interests they implicitly seek to defend are extremely narrow
communities: respectively, the empiricist community of those who proceed in way similar
to Quine’s (say, by embracing intuitionQuine); the anti-empiricist community of those whose
206
procedure remind one of Kripke’s (say, in endorsing anti-intuitionKripke); and the neoAristotelian community of the ones who do philosophy similarly to Fine (say, in taking
intuitionFine for granted). More broadly, they all seek to defend the interests of a slightly
larger community that includes the ones mentioned in the last phrase, that is, a community
that presupposes that the dismissivist reaction is persuasive in accepting Quine’s, Kripke’s
and Fine’s procedures. Hence, what appears to be utmost important for Quine, Kripke and
Fine, then, is not to defend the interest of a really universal community. Rather, what seems
to matter, for them, is to defend their particular identities as champions of their respective
considerably narrow communities and/or of the aforementioned slightly larger community.
It follows that, regardless of their superficial theoretical disagreements, Quine, Kripke and
Fine have all practically proceed as close-minded conservatives on the essence dispute. 405
5.4 The Critique of “Subtle” Violence
Now consider a passage by Ned Block: “You ask: What is it that philosophers have
called qualitative states? I answer, only half in jest: As Louis Armstrong said when asked
what jazz is, ‘If you got to ask, you ain’t never gonna get to know’”. 406 The critique of
“subtle” violence I would like to make in endorsing (9) —that is, the claim that the properly
dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence are to be avoided —is a quite
simple one. Ultimately, such a critique consists of a paraphrase of Block’s passage. In other
words, you ask: Why are the properly dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle”
405
I am also inclined to believe that Aristotle and his more or less unconscious followers addressed in the
last chapter have also proceed as micro-right-wingers regarding disputes. Unfortunately, I do not have the
space to carefully back up this problematic claim in this dissertation. My hope, though, is that this chapter as
well as the last one have provided some reasons for others to share this inclination of mine.
406
Ned Block, “Troubles with Functionalism”, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, volume IX,
Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1978: pp. 281.
207
violence to be avoided? I answer, only half in jest: As João Gilberto might have said when
asked what Bossa Nova is, “If you got to ask, you ain’t never gonna get to know”.
By arguing so, I do not wish to rely on a dogmatic use of intuition-talk while
suggesting that one is to endorse (9) because it runs in accordance with an allegedly
universally shared intuition, say, intuitionMoreira. I acknowledge that those who do not
endorse (9) and/or (1-i), (1-ii) and (1-iii) are legitimate rational peers when disputes are at
stake. What I do, instead, is to rely on a conflictual use of intuition talk in emphasizing that
(9) appears at least to me to be an appealing claim that does not require much justification.
Let me also underline once again that I do not take any claim of the system of
disputes to be an undeniable metaphysical claim. To put it metaphorically, this dissertation
does not purport to put an end to the Sisyphean-hell like process that, I tend to think,
characterizes the history of metaphysics; rather, it merely aims to be one way of engaging
oneself in such a process by expressing the singular health mentioned in 1.3 and in 3.2 and
which will still be further described in what follows. What I take myself to have done, then,
is to have relied throughout this dissertation on an imperfect justificatory resource that
(inevitably imperfectly) backs up (9). The resource I have in mind is that of proceeding as
an observer the history of metaphysics in seeking to spell out a likewise (inevitably
imperfect) observation of this history according to which philosophers have constantly
expressed (on a smaller-scale) “subtle” kinds of violence that are analogous to non-subtle
(large-scale) kinds of violence. The latter kinds of violence are usually criticized, that is, I
take that even the likes of Quine, Kripke or Fine do not endorse the right-wing macro and
upfront violence of marching with torches, screaming words of order, fist-fighting, etc.
208
This chapter’s micro-political goal is, then, to criticize “subtle” violence while
pressuring the likes of Quine, Kripke and Fine to drop their right-wing micro-political
practices of depoliticization. Note, though, that I have not used terms, such as “right-wing”,
“conservative”, “close-minded” and their corollaries derogatorily. Indeed, if Quine, Kripke
and Fine are inclined to endorse the right-wing conservative approach to the
Charlottesville-conflict or to other macro-conflicts, the claim that they champion a rightwing conservative approach to the essence dispute is not to count as an objection. In this
case, this claim serves to spell out an aspect of these philosophers’ work that has not been
brought to light by their interpreters. 407 The aspect is that they endorse at least one approach
to a micro-political conflict consistent with their views on macro-political conflicts.
In fact, Quine sometimes gives hints that he is also a conservative regarding macropolitical conflicts, albeit he refrains from determining “where to strike the delicate balance
of tolerance”. 408 The passages about Uncle Ellis attest to this. The same can be stated about
Quine’s interview for Veery mentioned above. Quine acknowledges that John Rawls’s
philosophy is “genuinely philosophical and worthwhile”. 409 Yet, “I don’t agree with his
politics: he’s too liberal for me”, Quine underlines. 410 As Hilary Putnam states in a 1988
review of Quine’s 1987 Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary, “although
Quine steers clear of political themes for the most part, there is one beautifully formulated
statement of his conservative creed —the essay on Freedom”. 411 In this essay, Quine states
that “freedom to remodel society, gained by revolution, can be a delicate affair. Society up
407
See Peter Hylton, Quine, New York, Routledge, 2007; Scott Soames Analytic Philosophy in America:
And Other Historical and Contemporary Essays, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2014; etc.
408
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quiddities, pp. 210.
409
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quine in Dialogue, pp. 34.
410
Ibid., my emphasis.
411
Hilary Putnam, “Misling” (review of Quine’s Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary).
London Review of Books (April 21, 1988): pp. 11.
209
to that point, if stable at all, was stable in consequence of the gradual combining and
canceling of forces and counter-forces”. 412 “The constraint imposed by social tradition”,
Quine concludes “is the gyroscope that helps the keep of state on an even keel”. 413
I suspend judgment on whether Kripke and Fine are also inclined toward right-wing
approaches to macro-political conflicts. Their writings simply do not mention any of these
conflicts. Hence, I do not wish to speculate on what they might think about them. What I
do is to claim that if Kripke and Fine do not endorse right-wing approaches to macroconflicts, they are also to revise their approaches to the essence dispute. What they are to
do, in order to be coherent, is to aim to articulate a left-wing micro-political approach to
micro-political conflicts, that is, to micro-wars. This task is pursued in the next chapter.
412
413
Willard Van Orman Quine, Quiddities, pp. 69.
Ibid.
CHAPTER 6
THE LEFT-WING APPROACH TO METAPHYSICS 414
6.1 Deleuze’s Immaculate Conception
In his 1973 “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, Gilles Deleuze calls his method of reading
an “immaculate conception”. 415 Metaphorically speaking, this method is an action of
“taking an author from behind and giving him a child”. 416 The “child” stands for the
resulted reading: one that deserves to be called the author’s “own offspring” in that it uses
the author’s writings as evidence in supporting exegetical claims. 417 However, the reading
that results from an immaculate conception is also “monstrous”. 418 This is because it also
interprets passages from the author’s texts in problematic ways, say, it translates the
author’s terminology to a distinct terminology the author never adopted; it justifies such
claims in manners the author never endorsed (at least not in an upfront way); it connects
passages by the author that are not very obviously connected to one another; it ends up
spelling out the author’s view on issues that the author never explicitly addressed; etc.
Deleuze claims that his book on Henri Bergson illustrates his immaculate
conception. 419 The same can be stated about his readings of David Hume, Friedrich
Nietzsche, Baruch Spinoza, Michel Foucault and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.420 Note that
414
This chapter is an expanded version of an article of mine that is to appear in Revue philosophique de la
France et de l'étranger by the end of 2019. A short version of this chapter was also presented at the University
of Miami’s 2018 Modern Languages and Literature Graduate Conference, Lands of Freedom? Oppressions,
Subversions and Pursuits of Justice in a Changing World.
415
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic” in Negotiations, 1972-1990, trans. Martin Joughin, New York,
Columbia University, 1995: pp.5.
416
Ibid.
417
Ibid.
418
Ibid.
419
Ibid. See Gilles Deleuze, Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, NY, Zone Books,
1998.
420
See Gilles Deleuze Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, trans.
Constantin V. Boundas, New York, Columbia University Press, 1991; Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh
Tomlinson, London, Athlone Press, 1983; Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin, NY,
210
211
Deleuze is not precise on the proportion between the “non-monstrous” and the “monstrous”
aspects of his readings. This does not seem particularly relevant to him. What he takes to
be crucial is whether the reading that adopts the immaculate conception “relates a book [or
a text] directly to what’s Outside”. 421 This can be done by spelling out what in the text is
hopefully pertinent for the interpreter’s context as opposed to that of the text’s author.
Deleuze’s interpreters are, then, confronted with a dilemma. While reading
Deleuze’s texts, they can either (a) embrace Deleuze’s immaculate conception as well, or
(b) dismiss this method while relying on more traditional methods that aim to accurately
represent Deleuze’s writings. Option (a) was adopted by Alain Baudiou and Slavoj
Zizek. 422 Option (b) has been taken, for instance, by Todd May, Gary Gutting and Adrian
W. Moore. 423 These options are equally “non-monstrous” and “monstrous”. The reason is
that neither interpreters who endorse option (a), nor those who embrace option (b) read
Deleuze’s writings in their own terms. This is the case with those who endorse option (a)
because they, metaphorically speaking, take Deleuze himself from behind and give him a
child. Those who embrace option (b) also do not read Deleuze’s writings in their own
terms. This is because, in seeking to accurately represent Deleuze’s writings, they
contradict these writings in disregarding that Deleuze believes “in the power of falsity” and
Zone Books, 1990; Foucault, trans. Sean Hand, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1998; and The
fold: Leibniz and the baroque, trans. Tom Conley, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1992.
421
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp.8.
422
Alain Baudiou, Deleuze: The Clamor of Being, trans. Louise Burchill, Minneapolis, University of
Minnesota Press, 1999; and Slavoj Zizek, Organs Without Bodies: Deleuze and Consequences, New York,
Routledge, 2004.
423
Todd May, Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005; Gary
Gutting, Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy since 1960, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011;
and Adrian W. Moore, The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 2012.
212
rejects any “lamentable faith in accuracy and truth”. 424 Note, yet, that it may be impossible
for an interpreter to express such a “lamentable faith” when reading Deleuze’s works.
What justifies this last claim is the fact that, like Friedrich Nietzsche, Michel
Foucault and Jacques Derrida, Deleuze constantly relies on the upfront rhetorical devices
discussed in 3.1 Consider, for example, the following statements from works by Deleuze,
Deleuze and Félix Guattari or Deleuze and his wife, Denise Paul “Fanny” Grandjouan:
(D-1) “Politics precedes being”. 425
(D-2) The one who is from the right-wing “starts from the self, and to the extent
that one is privileged, living in a rich country, one might ask, what can we
do to make this situation last? One senses that dangers exist, that it might
not last, it’s all so crazy, so what might be done for it to last?”. 426
(D-3) “In the West, the standard that every majority presupposes is: 1) male, 2)
adult, 3) heterosexual, 4) city dweller… […] A majority, at the limit, is
never anyone, it’s an empty standard”. 427
(D-4) “It’s too easy to be antifascist on the molar level, and not even see the fascist
inside you”. 428
(D-5) “Practice does not come after the emplacement of the terms and their
relation, but actively participates in the drawing of the lines”. 429
(D-6) “To be on the left” is “a matter of perception” and “being by nature […] or
never ceasing to become minoritarian. […] First, you see the horizon. And
you know that it cannot last, that it’s not possible; these millions of people
are starving to death, it just can’t last. […] The left is never of the majority
as left, and for a very simple reason: the majority is something that
presupposes […] a standard”. 430
424
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp.11.
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Brian
Massumi, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1987: pp.203.
426
This passage is part of the eight-hour long series of interviews that Deleuze gave to Claire Parnet from
1988 to 1989, L’Abécédaire de Gilles Deleuze. This work has not been published in literary form, but it is
available in DVD under the title, Gilles Deleuze: from A to Z, trans. Charles Stivale, Cambridge, The MIT
Press, 2011. The passages from the Abécedaire quoted here are from the section “G comme gauche”,
henceforth, (ABC-G).
427
(ABC-G).
428
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, pp.160.
429
Ibid.
430
(ABC-G).
425
213
(D-7) “How necessary caution is, the art of dosages, since overdose is a
danger”. 431
(D-8) “What do my relations with gays, alcoholics, and drug-users matter, if I can
obtain similar effects by different means?”. 432
(D-9) “I feel like a pure metaphysician”. 433
(D-10) “In Christ’s love, there was a […] an ardor to give without taking anything.
[…] There was something suicidal about him”. 434
(D-11) “Philosophy and schizophrenia have often been associated with each other.
But in one case the schizophrenic is a conceptual persona who lives
intensely within the thinker and forces him to think, whereas in the other
the schizophrenic is a psychosocial type who represses the living being and
robs him of his thought”. 435
(D-12) Philosophy “turns its back against itself so as to summon forth a new earth,
a new people”. 436
(D-13) “The use of philosophy is to sadden. A philosophy that saddens no one, that
annoys no one, is not philosophy. It is useful for harming stupidity [bêtise],
for turning stupidity into something shameful”. 437
In backing these statements up, Deleuze never explicitly developed arguments in the
traditional sense of the term “argument”, that is, a conjunction of premises that justify a
conclusion by means of a widely shared rule of inference. The same can be stated about
practically all other statements found in Deleuze’s works. Indeed, as May claims,
431
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, pp.215.
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp.11.
433
Gilles Deleuze, “Réponses à une Séries de Questions (Novembre 1981)”, in Arnaud Villani, La guêpe et
l’orchidée: essai sur Gilles Deleuze, Paris, Éditions Belin, 1999: pp.130, my translation.
434
Gilles Deleuze and Denise Paul “Fanny” Grandjouan, “Nietzsche and Saint Paul, Lawrence and John of
Patmos”, in Essays Critical and Clinical, trans., Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco, London, Verso,
1998: pp.50.
435
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell,
NY,
Columbia University Press, 1994: pp.70.
436
Ibid., 99.
437
Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, pp.106. Also see Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche et la Philosophie,
Presses Paris, Universitaires de France, 1962: pp.120.
432
214
“philosophy, as he does it, is not about argument” in the traditional sense. 438 Let me
underline, though, that it is not my aim to compare options (a) and (b) in detail.
What I would like to do, instead, is to claim that the fact that Deleuze himself relied
on the immaculate conception throughout his career is sufficient reason to imperfectly
justify the claim that, in following Baudiou and Zizek, one is to adopt option (a), that is,
one is to apply Deleuze’s particular method of reading (his “immaculate conception”) to
Deleuze’s works themselves. This is not to state that one is not to adopt option (b) in a
context distinct from the one of this dissertation or that I would go as far as objecting to
those, such as May, Gutting and Moore, who have adopted this option. Indeed, consider
that, throughout this dissertation, I have relied on quite traditional methods of reading in
backing up exegetical claims about all sorts of philosophers, such as Pyrrho of Elis, Rudolf
Carnap, Aristotle, Willard Van Orman Quine, Saul Kripke, Kit Fine, etc. I also would like
to suspend judgment on whether one may use Deleuze’s immaculate conception while
reading authors who have never themselves adopted this method of reading.
Moreover, let me underline that were I to adopt option (b), my reading of Deleuze
would be along the lines of those briefly proposed about Foucault and Derrida in 3.1, that
is, I would read Deleuze as someone who was influenced by Nietzsche’s libertarian
reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.
Hence, I would claim that, like Foucault, Deleuze was interested, theoretically speaking,
in defending claims whose purpose was that of provoking dissensus and even shocking the
French community of health care specialists of his time, roughly, from the 1940s, when
Deleuze was a student, up to the early 1990s, when he got cancer and ended up killing
438
Todd May, Gilles Deleuze, pp. 22.
215
himself. I would argue that, practically speaking, by publishing the 1972 Anti-Oedipus and
the 1980 A Thousand Plateaus (both co-authored with Guattari), Deleuze resisted an
egalitarian practice and promoted a libertarian practice: respectively, that of isolating the
so-called “mentally disordered” in mental institutions for the sake of protecting the
supposedly “mentally sane” majority; and that of problematizing such institutions under
the basis that they overly constrained the singularities of deviants, like Antonin Artaud who
would not have “succeed for himself” to resist such constrains and collapsed. 439
Were I to adopt option (b), I would also read that, like Derrida, Deleuze also had
the theoretical aim of defending exegetical claims that provoke dissensus and even shock
the French academic philosophical community of his time. In relying on traditional
methods of reading and focusing on the history of metaphysics, this community was
championed by the likes Martial Gueroult and Ferdinand Alquié, philosophers who have
established the canonical French readings of traditional philosophers, such as René
Descartes and Spinoza. 440 I would interpret, then, that, practically speaking, by publishing
his books on Bergson, Hume, Nietzsche, Spinoza, Foucault and Leibniz, Deleuze resisted
this community’s egalitarian practice of endorsing canonical readings, say, for the sake of
establishing a common criterion to evaluate exegetical claims in standardized tests on the
history of metaphysics. So, I would read that Deleuze embraced the libertarian practice of
problematizing the constrains that French educational philosophical institutions placed
439
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, pp. 164. Also see Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and Helen R. Lane,
London, The Athlone Press Ltd, 1984.
440
See Martial Gueroult, Descartes’ Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of Reason Volume 1:
The Soul and God; Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984; Philosophy Interpreted According to
the Order of Reason Volume 2: The Soul and the Body. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985;
and Ferdinand Alquié, La Découverte métaphysique de l'homme chez Descartes, Paris, PUF, 1950, and
Nature et vérité dans la philosophie de Spinoza, Les Cours de Sorbonne, Paris, CDU, 1965.
216
upon its members’ singularities. Such constrains would have made it hard for unique
readings of the history of metaphysics to be developed. In Deleuze’s words, members of
French philosophical institutions would have believed that “‘you can’t seriously consider
saying what you yourself think until you’ve read this and that, and that on this, and this on
that”’. 441 Deleuze’s immaculate conception was his way of resisting this attitude.
This chapter’s aim, yet, is not to further spell out the last two paragraphs’ exegetical
claims about Deleuze. A distinct goal is pursued: while adopting option (a), I propose a
particular reading of (D-1) to (D-13). This reading: translates these claims to this
dissertation’s terminology; imperfectly justifies them in ways never explicitly proposed by
Deleuze; systematically connects such claims to one another; and, ultimately, spells out
Deleuze’s view on matters he never explicitly addressed. In doing so, then, my wish is not
that of suggesting that Deleuze was, indeed, explicitly committed to the claims I attribute
to him. To put it metaphorically, what I mean is that I do not seek to paint a sort of
“representative” portrait of Deleuze, such as Leonardo da Vinci’s “Mona Lisa”. My view
is that the claims I attribute to Deleuze can be drawn out, but not explicitly found in his
writings. My point is that he has inspired me to endorse these claims and, indeed, that, after
Nietzsche and Carnap, he is the philosopher who has influenced me the most. To put it
metaphorically, my aim is to paint a quasi-abstract portrait of Deleuze comparable to
Francis Bacon’s portraits, such as his “Portrait of George Dyer Talking”. 442 In doing so,
my goal is to imperfectly justify the system of disputes’ tenth, eleventh and twelfth claim:
(10)
441
A left-wing political practice of politicization that deals with micro-wars by
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp.5.
Note that Deleuze himself wrote a whole book on Francis Bacon. See Giles Deleuze, Francis Bacon: The
Logic of Sensation, trans. Daniel W. Smith, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 2005.
442
217
avoiding the properly dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle”
violence is to be pursued as an alternative to the right-wing allegedly
apolitical approach.
(11)
The left-wing political practice of politicization is to be prudently pursued
in a metamodernist way as opposed to a modernist way.
(12)
This very dissertation illustrates how one can do so.
I carefully explain and imperfectly justify (10) in section 6.2. I do the same with (11) and
(12) in section 6.3. Before I start to pursue this task, though, I emphasize that this chapter
seeks to connect Deleuze’s works in a pertinent way to two contexts outside of them.
The first context is that of Deleuze’s interpreters themselves, such as: all the ones
named above, that is, Baudiou, Zizek, May, Gutting and Moore; as well as Nathan Widder;
Véronique Bergen; John Protevi; those who contributed with the essays gathered in the
2014 Deleuze and Metaphysics; and hundreds (or perhaps even thousands) of others.443
Among Deleuze’s interpreters, an exegetical tendency can be quite easily identified. This
tendency is that of focusing on Deleuze’s views on object-level metaphysical disputes,
such as whether being is univocal; what is the virtual if there is such an entity; whether
there is a difference in itself over and above any condition settled by human entities; what
are the possible and the impossible; whether Deleuze is a sort of human-driven philosopher
or a quite peculiar kind of physicalist-driven one; etc. On the other hand, not much has
been published on Deleuze’s take on metametaphysical disputes, such as the one focused
on here on which criterion, to begin with, one is to be adopted in addressing disputes. This
443
Alain Beaulieu (ed.), Edward Kazarian (ed.) and Julia Sushytska (ed), Deleuze and Metaphysics, Lanham,
Lexington Books, 2014; Nathan Widder, “The rights of simulacra: Deleuze and the univocity of being”,
Continental Philosophy Review 34, 2001: pp. 437–45; Véronique Bergen, L’Ontologie de Gilles Deleuze,
Paris, Editions L'Harmattan, 2001; and John Protevi, Political Physics: Deleuze, Derrida and the Body
Politic, New York, The Athlone Press, 2001.
218
chapter, then, aims to fill this gap by spelling out that Deleuze proposes an alternative
criterion. I call it accordance with the left-wing political practice of politicization.
The second context this chapter aims to connect Deleuze’s works to is that of
analytic philosophers, such as Quine, Kripke and Fine, who deal with disputes by more or
less unconsciously championing the right-wing political practice of depoliticization
discussed in the last chapter. As indicated in 3.1, there has been a lot of animosity between
analytic philosophers and continental ones. Moreover, as also indicated in 3.1, some
continental philosophers have been influenced by Nietzsche’s libertarian reaction, while
ignoring Carnap’s egalitarian reaction. On their parts, analytic philosophers have often
done the opposite. Hence, it is not surprising that, among such philosophers, an objection
against the likes of Foucault, Derrida and Deleuze is widely shared, even though not
usually explicitly stated in writing. I call it the obscurity objection according to which these
French philosophers have simply no criterion to approach disputes. What they have,
instead, is an obscure use of language by means of which they ultimately perform
authoritarian practices, such as that of more or less arbitrarily endorsing claims, such as
(D-1) to (D-13), and allowing oneself to have followers who uncritically repeat one’s
claims as if they were undeniable religious dogmas. 444 Note that this objection is quite
similar to Carnap’s objection to Martin Heidegger, already discussed in the second chapter.
444
Consider, for instance, that, without naming the authors he has in mind, Timothy Williamson points to the
obscurity objection. He states that: “when law and order break down, the result is not freedom or anarchy but
the capricious tyranny of petty feuding warlords. Similarly, the unclarity of constraints in philosophy leads
to authoritarianism. Whether an argument is widely accepted depends not on publicly accessible criteria that
we can all apply for ourselves but on the say-so of charismatic authority figures. Pupils cannot become
autonomous from their teachers because they cannot securely learn the standards by which their teachers
judge”. See Timothy Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy, MA, Blackwell, 2007: pp. 290. For
objections to French authors closely-related to the obscurity one, also see Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont,
Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals’ Abuse of Science, NY, Picador, 1998; and John Searle,
“The Word Turned Upside Down”, The New York Review of Books, October 27th, 1983.
219
It is important to emphasize that: first, it is not my aim to spell out whether and/or
how Heidegger might have replied to Carnap’s objection; second; it is also not my aim to
show whether and/or how Derrida, Foucault or other French authors very influenced by
Nietzsche, such as Georges Bataille, Pierre Klossowski or Maurice Blanchot, could resist
the obscurity objection; and, third, I suspend judgment on whether interpreters who adopt
option (b) may reply to this objection on Deleuze’s behalf. 445 What I would like to do,
instead, is to commit myself to the claim that, if option (a) is embraced, it is possible to
attribute to Deleuze the stated alternative criterion to deal with disputes, accordance with
a left-wing political practice of politicization. It follows that, once this criterion is attributed
to this, to put it metaphorically, immaculately conceived Deleuze of mine, a reply on his
behalf to the obscurity objection may be provided.
6.2 The Left-Wing Political Practice of Politicization
What (D-1) has inspired me to think and, consequently, what I would like to draw
out of this statement is the system of disputes’ seventh claim: that disputes are micropolitical conflicts analogous to macro-political conflicts, that is, they are micro-wars.
Given that this claim arises out of a translation of Deleuze’s writing into this dissertation’s
terminology, I would like to rename it (MCC 1). (MCC) is short for monstrous child claim.
(D-2) through (D-13) will receive similar translations to claims of this kind in what follows.
Before I do so, nonetheless, let me underline that (MCC 1) was already imperfectly
justified in the last chapter. The same can be stated about the following claim:
445
Georges Bataille, On Nietzsche, New York, Suny Press, 2015; Pierre Klossowski, Nietzsche and the
Vicious Circle, London, Athlone Press, 1997; Maurice Blanchot, The Space of Literature, Nebraska,
University of Nebraska Press, 1989; Michel Foucault, History of Madness, Oxford, Routledge, 2006; and
Jacques Derrida, Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles / Eperons: Les Styles de Nietzsche, Chicago, Chicago University
Press, 1979.
220
(MCC 2)
A right-wing approach to a macro or to a micro-political conflict is
a practice characterized by its champions’ tendency to privilege
their needs for self-defense over their powers to show empathy
regarding their others. This is to state that such champions,
passively, feel or act as if their others were a threat to their particular
identities or even lives. Furthermore, actively, right-wingers act
under the influence of this feeling in seeking to protect their lives
and/or to conserve their particular identities.
I draw (MCC 2) out of (D-2), that is, (MCC 2) is what (D-2) has inspired me to think. I
would like to further back up (MCC 2) and my forthcoming translations of (D-3) to (D-13)
by considering another macro-political conflict. I call it the immigration-conflict: the one
on whether illegal immigrants in France (the so-called sans-papiers) are to be deported. In
addressing this issue, I aim to further back up points suggested in the last chapter.
Consider, then, a right-wing approach to the immigration conflict. This approach is
that of the Parisian right-winger, someone who has particular identities, such as: to be male;
to be adult; to be cisgender; to be heterosexual; to be white-skinned; to have been born and
raised in Paris; to speak French; to be a French citizen; to have attended a public French
university; to be from a high or middle-class; to be Christian, etc. Imagine that the Parisian
right-winger, passively, feels that his others are a threat to his life and/or to his particular
identities. Actively, then, he acts under the influence of this feeling in seeking to protect
his life and/or to conserve his particular identities. He does so by opposing the presence of
illegal immigrants in France, that is, those who are not Christians; do not come from a high
or middle class; have not attended public French or any university at all; are not French
citizens; were not born and raised in Paris; are not white-skinned, etc. For the right-winger,
these illegal immigrants are not to receive the same benefits the French state has provided
to French citizens. The state, he believes, is not to provide, say, health care or education
221
for illegal immigrants. This is because, in doing so, the state would over privilege illegal
immigrants in detriment of French citizens, such as the right-winger himself.
The Parisian right-winger, accordingly, supports conservative politicians, such as
Marine Le Pen, who promise, if elected, to deport illegal immigrants. In fact, he takes
himself to be doing his part in attempting to intimidate illegal immigrants in public places,
such as streets, supermarkets, squares and subway stations. Imagine that, when confronted
with such immigrants, the right-winger goes as far as screaming slurs or words of order,
such as “go back to where you belong, go back to Africa”. He also joins anti-immigration
protests, and, perhaps, even gets involved in fist-fights with those who favor the presence
of illegal immigrants in France. In the end, the right-winger may beat illegal immigrants.
He may also throw stones at their houses. He might even go as far as burning their shops.
As stated above (see 5.1), I take that a particular identity is an implicit kind of
communitarian or herd constrain. This is because those who have or are publicly
interpreted as having a particular identity are expected to use language, behave and even
to feel in accordance with this identity. Another way to put this is by stating that to have a
particular identity is to be implicitly bounded by certain norms publicly attached to such
an identity. These norms are, so to speak, “in the air” in that they are presupposed by
majorities at given contexts. This is why I read that Deleuze in (D-3) calls the conjunction
of all such norms a “standard” that such majorities implicitly seek to fulfill and which,
consequently, oppresses those (that is, minorities) who fail to do so. Note that a majority
is distinct from a really universal community. A majority is the most amount of people
which, at a given context, presuppose certain norms while seeking to defend their own
222
interests as opposed to those of each and every being or at least each and every person.
Hence, a majority is a quite narrow community, such as that of all right-wingers in Paris.
Note that if one has or is taken to have the identity of being a heterosexual French
woman in Paris, the majority in this context implicitly supposes that one is to follow the
norms attached to this identity, such as those of using and wanting to use makeup, dresses,
panties, etc. On the other hand, if one has particular identities similar to those of the
Parisian right-winger, this very same majority in this very same context implicitly assumes
that one is to follow the distinct norms attached to such identities, such as that of not using
or wanting to use makeup, dresses, panties, etc.
Let us also imagine that the Parisian right-winger, like the Southern right-winger,
seeks to fulfill and conserve all the norms implicitly attached (or, at least, that he takes to
be implicitly attached) to his particular identities. I take that is pertinent to imagine so
because a considerably basic observation of the history of the West appears to attest to a
fact that the likes of Karl Marx as well as Simone de Beauvoir, Martin Luther King,
Malcolm X, Angela Davis, Cornel West, Catherine MacKinnon, Linda Alcoff, Gayle
Rubin, Sally Haslanger and Julia Serano have all more or less explicitly emphasized.446
Let us read that Deleuze also acknowledges the fact that I have mind: namely, that
(MCC 3)
446
It appears that, throughout the history of the West, majorities have
Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, London, Lowe and Brydone, 1953; Martin Luther King, A
Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches, New York, Harper Collins Publishers, 1986;
Malcolm X, Malcolm X Speaks: Selected Speeches and Statements, New York, Merit Publishers and Betty
Shabazz, 1965; Angela Davis, The Angela Y. Davis Reader, MA, Blackwell Publishers, 1998; Cornel West,
The Cornel West Reader, New York, Basic Civitas Book, 1999; Catherine MacKinnon, Are Women Human?,
MA, Harvard University Press, 2006; Linda Alcoff, Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2006; Gayle Rubin, Deviations: A Gayle Rubin Reader, North Caroline, Duke
University Press, 2011; Sally Haslanger, Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2012; Julia Serano, Outspoken: A Decade of Transgender Activism and Trans
Feminism, Oakland, Switch Hitter Press, 2016; etc.
223
presupposed that all concrete persons (that is, those that exist in time
and space) are to satisfy Western norms that ultimately none of
them, but only an abstract object (that is, one that is supposed to
exist over time and space) could fulfill. This abstract object deserves
to be called the white-man-in-itself.
I draw (MCC 3) out of (D-3). Notice that concrete white men who have particular
identities similar to those of the Parisian right-winger have never perfectly satisfied the
Western norms Deleuze has in mind. Yet, they have fallen short of doing so much less
explicitly than the concrete others of the white man who have suffered with all kinds of
practices of oppression, such as that of being underpaid and exploited by French citizens
who, when dealing with illegal immigrants, entitle themselves to misapply labor laws.
Deleuze suggests, then, that the abstract object mentioned in (MCC 3) deserves to be
named the white-man-in-itself: an entity that behaves, uses language and even feels how
each and every person is supposed to behave, use language and feel in accordance with all
kinds of Western majorities. 447 Another way to put this is by claiming that this entity
satisfies all Western criteria for knowledge, morality, beauty, solving disputes, etc. By the
others of the white man, I understand those who have existed in time and space and have
particular identities, such as: to be native American; to be black-skinned; to be female; to
be transsexual; to come from a low class; to be an illegal immigrant in France, etc.
Note that, like the Southern right-winger, the Parisian right-winger is neither a
libertarian Nietzschean, nor an egalitarian Carnapian. He is no libertarian because he does
not aim to act in accordance and contribute to affirm his own singularity or those of others.
447
Of course, the dispute on whether this abstract entity exists as well as the traditional one over any kind of
Platonism versus any kind of nominalism is not at stake here. For a detailed take on the latter, see Guido
Imaguire, “In Defense of Quine’s Ostrich Nominalism”, in Grazer Philosophische Studien 89, 2014, and
Priority Nominalism: Grounding Ostrich Nominalism as a Solution to the Problem of Universals,
Switzerland, Springer, 2016.
224
What he aims, instead, is to attenuate such singularities of his while contributing with the
community constituted by the majority that conserves and seeks to satisfy the Western
norms that ultimately only the white-man-in-itself can fulfill. A metaphorical way to state
this is by claiming that the Parisian right-winger is the “slave” of this abstract object. He is
the server of a majority. Hence, he is also no egalitarian. This occurs because, instead of
seeking to defend the interests of a really universal community, the Parisian right-winger
only cares about the interests of an extremely narrow community that, ultimately, only
includes those who share particular identities with him and seek to satisfy the norms or
what they take to be the norms implied by such identities. An example of such norm is that,
if one who has the identity of being a French citizen, one is to, accordingly, defend French
citizens in detriment of non-French citizens, such as illegal immigrants. Thus, the Parisian
right-winger, like the Southern right-winger, deserves to be called a conservative.
What (D-4) has inspired me to think is a claim that was suggested in the last chapter:
(MCC 4)
It has often happened that one opposes right-wing approaches to
macro-political conflicts, such as the Charlottesville-Conflict or the
immigration conflict, but (perhaps unconsciously) endorses
analogous right-wing approaches to micro-political conflicts, that is,
micro-wars, like disputes.
As indicated in the last chapter, arguably, this has been the case with Kripke and Fine,
albeit I do not wish to speculate on their views on macro-political conflicts they have never
cared to address. What I would like to speculate, though, is that perhaps most contemporary
analytic philosophers would never go as far as Quine in publicly suggesting (in a more
macro-level) that Mexicans are dangerous and that, hence, one is to follow his mother’s
225
Uncle Ellis’ advice: “never turn your back on a Mexican”. 448 I will provide other reasons
to back up this speculation in the next section.
For now, I emphasize that those who champion right-wing approaches to microwars have suggested that they have, to put it metaphorically, some sort of “shortcut to what
there is”, that is, an allegedly extremely persuasive criterion to deal with disputes, such as
accordance with intuitonQuine, accordance with intuitonKripke or accordance with intuitonFine.
Accordingly, as indicated in the last chapter, champions of this approach assume that they
may ignore those who ignore or violate such criterion, say, because their others would have
“baffling” views, “intuition reversed”, be “conceptually blind”, etc. I also emphasize that
those who champion right-wing approaches to micro-wars serve Western majorities;
majorities that presuppose that one is supposed to do philosophy in accordance with the
implicit norms attached to certain particular identities. Consider some particular identities
of Quine, Kripke and Fine: respectively, that of being a champion of the empiricist
tradition; a champion of the counter-empiricist tradition; and a champion of the neoAristotelian tradition described above. Three norms implicitly attached to these identities
or that Quine, Kripke and Fine seem to assume to be attached to these identities,
respectively, are: that one is to satisfy accordance with intuitonQuine; one is to satisfy
accordance with intuitonKripke and one is to satisfy accordance with intuitonFine. I read that,
respectively, Quine, Kripke and Fine aim to satisfy these norms in implicitly defending the
interests of the narrow community of those who, to begin with, presupposes such norms.
Let us read that by (D-5), what Deleuze and Guattari really mean is that
(MCC 5)
448
Philosophers have often championed micro-political practices of
Willard Van Orman Quine, The Time of My Life: An Autobiography, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1985:
pp. 153.
226
depolicization in not acknowledging or not been aware of
themselves insofar as micro-political agents engaged in micropolitical conflicts.
As indicated by the system of disputes’ eighth claim, this is exactly what I take to be the
case with Quine, Kripke and Fine. It follows that if these philosophers have championed
right-wing political practices of depolicization when dealing with micro-political conflicts,
such as the essence dispute, there is a reason for embracing (10), that is, the claim that a
left-wing political practice of politicization that deals with micro-political conflicts by
avoiding the properly dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence is to be
pursued as an alternative to the right-wing allegedly apolitical approach. The reason I have
in mind is: it appears to be motivated to resist or, at least, to show that there is a distinct
approach to disputes. Indeed, let me dare to state that even philosophers who have endorsed
the micro-right-wing approach may want to change the way they do philosophy, that is,
they may want to embrace such alternative approach, if they are not inclined toward rightwing approaches to macro-political conflicts, such as those of the Southern right-winger
and the Parisian right-winger. In case such philosophers are after all persuaded by the latter
approaches, I think that there is not much I can do to make them revise their practices.
This last claim will be addressed in more detail in the conclusion. For now, I start
to spell out (10) in reading that by (D-6) what Deleuze means is that, as indicated above:
(MCC 6)
A left-wing approach to a macro or to a micro-political conflict is a
practice characterized by its champions’ tendency to privilege their
powers to show empathy over their needs to self-defend themselves
from their others. As Michael Slote indicates, these champions:
passively, feel or at least recognize the existence of the suffering of
other people, including others. Actively, in order to contribute to
make this suffering cease to exist, left-wingers act under the
227
influence of this suffering in ceasing to give or at least attenuating
the importance of their own particular identities. 449
Consider, then, the approach to the immigration-conflict of the Parisian left-winger,
someone whose practices are quite similar to those of the Southern left-winger. Imagine
that, like the Parisian right-winger, the Parisian left-winger has particular identities, such
as: to be male; to be adult; to be heterosexual; to be white-skinned; to have been born and
raised in Paris; to speak French; to be a French citizen; to have attended a public French
university; to be from a high or middle-class; to be Christian; etc. Distinct from the Parisian
right-winger, nonetheless, the Parisian left-winger, passively, feels or at least recognizes
the existence of the suffering of his others, such as illegal immigrants in France. Actively,
he acts under the influence of the suffering of these people in ceasing to give or at least
attenuating the importance of his own particular identities. This is to state that the Parisian
left-winger is more open-minded, whereas the Parisian right-winger is more close-minded.
The Parisian left-winger starts to do so by emphasizing a fact that right-wingers
tend to ignore: that illegal immigrants in France have constantly ran away from wars and/or
poverty in their own home-countries and faced all kinds of struggles once they arrived in
France. The Parisian left-winger, then, simply ceases to take seriously a claim that Western
majorities have often presupposed: that the French state is to primarily protect the interests
of its own citizens as opposed to those of illegal immigrants. Hence, to put in Deleuze’s
terms, “he is or becomes minoritarian” in voting for politicians who promise to guarantee
the rights and integrate illegal immigrants into French culture. He also seeks to pressure
those who threat (sometimes, the very life of) illegal immigrants. Imagine, then, that the
449
Michael Slote, From Enlightenment to Receptivity: Rethinking our Values, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 2013; “Philosophy’s Dirty Secret: What Virtue Epistemology Needs to Learn about Human
Irrationality”, forthcoming; and “Philosophical Sin”, forthcoming.
228
left-winger screams words of order against the words of order of right-wingers, say, he
screams “filthy racist” against those who scream “go back to Africa” in public spaces. He
also counter-protests marches against illegal immigration. He joins pro-immigration
protests. In proceeding so, the Parisian left-winger seeks to problematize the Western
norms that can only be perfectly satisfied by the white-man-in-itself.
Another way to describe the Parisian left-winger, then, is by metaphorically stating
that he is not the “slave” of this entity. This occurs because he does not aim to serve the
interests of a majority that oppresses minorities that fail to be in accordance with a standard.
What the left-winger seeks to be is a libertarian Nietzschean. This is someone who aims to
be his own, to put it metaphorically once again, “master” in being in accordance with what
is singular about himself over and above his own particular identities and the implicit
norms attached to them. In other words, he aims to be someone who ultimately creates and
satisfies one’s own standard; one’s own criteria for knowledge, beauty, morality, dealing
with disputes, etc. Paradoxically, though, the left-winger is also an egalitarian Carnapian.
This occurs because he likewise seeks to attenuate his own singularities as well as those of
others in striving toward the creation of a really universal community that would really
defend the interests of all as opposed to those of the narrow communities defended by rightwingers. What I mean is that the Parisian left-winger also seeks to be the “slave” of this
really universal community. This is to state that, in short, he aims to be in agreement with
the will to synthesis, even though he may be ultimately unable to do so perfectly.
Then, I draw out of Deleuze’s works or these works have inspired me to articulate
a left-wing approach toward micro-wars. This approach is analogous to those of the
Parisian left-winger and the Southern left-winger to their respective macro-political
229
conflicts. So, this approach is to appeal to those who are already convinced that the latter
approaches are more pertinent than those of right-wingers. This is to read that Deleuze
deals with disputes by, passively, feeling or at least recognizing the existence of the
suffering of other people, especially that of those who are others. Such others are: those
who simply do not agree with any criterion one may propose; those who do not share one’s
intuitions; do not speak what one assumes to be ordinary language or seek to maximize
one’s theoretical virtues; those who, consequently, ignore or disrespect norms concerning
how disputes are to be approached or, more broadly, how philosophy is to be done; those
who have not often been accepted into undergraduate or graduate educational programs of
philosophy; those who have failed to pass public philosophy tests, such as the French
“agrégation de philosophie”; those who have rarely published their writings or been invited
to speak at philosophical conferences; those who have not been hired by universities in
wealthy countries, such as the USA, the UK, Australia, Germany and/or France itself; those
who, to begin with, do not grant that the disputes one approaches are motivated; etc.
I also read that Deleuze addressed disputes by, actively, acting under the influence
of the suffering of his others or at least under the influence of the recognition of the
existence of this suffering. In doing so, he aimed to cease to give or at least to attenuate the
importance of his own particular identities, like that of being a member of any
philosophical tradition, such as that of being a French continental philosopher educated in
a French university or being someone able to articulate works that satisfy widely shared
criteria to deal with disputes. Indeed, from a left-wing perspective, these criteria, such as
accordance with any kind of intuition, respect to the rules of ordinary language or
maximization of theoretical virtues, are ultimately quite irrelevant. What is relevant, from
230
the left-wing perspective, is to negotiate with others by attempting to understand and even
feel what they take to be intuitive, ordinary language or a theoretical virtue. Hence, from
the left-wing perspective, over-simplistic broad appeals to an “experimental spirit”,
“common sense”, or to what is “conceptually obvious” are to be dismissed; there is not
much properly “experimental”, “common sensical” or “conceptually obvious” about works
that champion right-wing supposedly apolitical approaches to micro-wars.
It follows that I am inspired or draw out of Deleuze’s works a way of avoiding the
properly dogmatic “subtle” violence. This may be done by the left-winger on microdisputes who, distinct from Aristotle and his more or less unconscious followers, does not
seek to defend one’s own particular identities and the implicit norms attached to them by
speaking in the name of a philosophical tradition and suggesting a narrow condition for
personhood. A left-winger on micro-wars, rather, acknowledges that some others are
legitimate rational peers and that, given that this is so, no person has settled a dispute once
and for all by making an undeniable metaphysical claim. This is also to suggest that those
who have dealt with disputes are all inserted in the Sisyphean-hell like process of the
history of metaphysics: oneself is no exception to this process insofar as one’s very claims
are not undeniable metaphysical ones. A left-winger, then, is a conflictual crafter who
acknowledges one’s impossibility of not relying on problematic starting points.
I also draw out of Deleuze’s works a way to avoid the pseudo-non-dogmatic
“subtle” violence. This can be done by acknowledging the importance of (1-i) and (1-ii):
respectively, the claims that some others are legitimate rational peers; and that it seems
impossible to solve disputes once and for all. Hence, in order to have a persuasive view,
one is to take these claims into account when reacting to the fact that, since immemorial
231
times, persons have been engaged in disputes. I claim, then, that the pseudo-non-dogmatic
“subtle” violence may be avoided by the conflictual crafter. In carefully, but inevitably
imperfectly observing the history of metaphysics and all kinds of methodological issues,
this is someone who concludes that, regardless of whether philosophers have been aware,
they have been micro-political agents, that is, they have been engaged in micro-wars.
Deleuze, then, embraces a political practice of politicization: that of recognizing oneself as
a micro-political agent engaged in such micro-wars while seeking to spell out the lack of
political neutrality of allegedly apolitical philosophers, such as Quine, Kripke and Fine.
My “immaculate conceived reading”, then, is that Deleuze’s goal was to be a
particular kind of micro-political agent engaged in such micro-wars: an agent that
articulates and endorses an ultimately unique criterion of his-my own to deal with microwars. I call it accordance with the very left-wing political practice of politicization just
described. Note that, on the one hand, to adopt this criterion is to be a libertarian
Nietzschean. This occurs insofar as no philosopher has explicitly adopted this criterion and,
consequently, this move is very likely to cause dissensus and, perhaps, even to shock or
embarrass, especially, supposedly apolitical philosophers who are actually right-wing ones.
To put it metaphorically, then, to endorse this criterion is to seek to be one’s own “master”
insofar as disputes are concerned. This is to state that the left-winger on micro-wars aims
to be in accordance with what is ultimately singular about oneself over and above any
philosophical tradition, such as the analytic tradition or the continental tradition. To aim so
is to promote the libertarian practice of establishing one’s own norms on how disputes are
to be approached or, more broadly, on how philosophy is to be done while violating several
232
norms of the continental tradition and the analytic tradition, such as the norm that one is to
rely on strategically narrow bibliographies that only mention one of these traditions.
Paradoxically, though, to adopt accordance with a left-wing practice of
politicization as a criterion to deal with disputes is also to be an egalitarian Carnapian. This
occurs because to propose this criterion is also, as indicated above, to seek to achieve
consensus with others by seeking to negotiate with their criteria, that is, with whatever they
take to be intuitive, an ordinary use of language, a theoretical virtue, etc. Hence, the leftwinger, metaphorically speaking, also aims to be a “slave”, but not one of a majority, such
as that of a particular philosophical tradition. The goal of the left-winger is to serve a really
universal community. This is to state that this philosopher also promotes an egalitarian
practice: that of, while attenuating one’s singularities, to contribute to the creation of this
really universal community that would defend the interests of all beings or at least all
persons as opposed to those of a mere majority that, say, shares one’s intuitions, respects
one’s rules of ordinary language, seeks to maximize one’s theoretical virtues, etc. To
pursue this egalitarian practice, then, is to seek to act in accordance with the much more
cosmopolitan norm that one is supposed to have a bibliography as plural and extensive as
possible. Accordingly, I have addressed Brazilian neo-Pyrrhonists; several continental
philosophers; several analytic philosophers; and those who resists being qualified by such
terms and who simply contradict one’s intuitions, disrespect what one takes to be the rules
of ordinary language and do not maximize what one presupposes to be theoretical
virtues. 450 This is to state that the left-winger seeks to be open-minded in achieving the
450
Unfortunately, though, I did not discuss the views of eastern philosophers; my current education simply
does not allow me to do so.
233
singular health of being in accordance with the will to synthesis, regardless of one’s likely
impossibility of perfectly satisfying one’s individualist and communitarian tendencies.
It follows that my immaculate conceived reading of Deleuze is hopefully pertinent
to two contexts outside of that of his works: that of his interpreters who have focused on
his views on object-level metaphysical disputes as well as that of analytic philosophers
who have embraced the obscurity objection against Deleuze. The reason is that, in spelling
out that Deleuze endorses accordance with the left-wing political practice of politicization
as a criterion to deal with disputes, this reading of mine: first, shows a distinct aspect of
Deleuze’s works that his interpreters have not yet taken into account; and, second, provides
a reply to the obscurity objection on Deleuze’s behalf by indicating that he (or at least the,
so to speak, deformed child that arises out of my immaculately conceived reading) had an
alternative criterion of his own to deal with disputes and, hence, did not champion the
aforementioned authoritarian practices. This monstrous child of mine, then, does not
proceed, like a “warlord”, without having any sort of “constrain in philosophy”, to put in
Timothy Williamson’s terms, but, rather, articulates an alternative constrain of his own. 451
In doing so, Deleuze also aimed to show resistance and self-defend himself from
those who champion right-wing allegedly apolitical approaches to micro-wars. I spell this
out in the next section by addressing two ways by means of which the left-wing political
practice of politicization can be pursued: the modernist way and the metamodernist way.
451
See Timothy Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy, pp. 290.
234
6.3 From the Modernist to the Metamodernist Way
An imprudent practice is a sort of suicidal practice; one that is very likely to lead
to the practitioner’s death or that at least severely puts at risk something that the practitioner
cares deeply, such as a marriage, a family, a career, etc. A prudent practice is one that does
not do so. Consider the practices of having sexual intercourse, drinking alcohol or taking
drugs. These practices can be imprudent ones, say, when one has “one partner too many”,
when one has “one drink too many” or takes “one drug too many”. On the other hand, when
one manages to have sexual intercourse, to drink or take drugs without excessively doing
so, one’s practice is a prudent one. Hence, what I draw out of (D-7) is the claim that
(MCC 7)
Prudent practices are to be preferred to imprudent ones. 452
The reason is simple: the latter can ultimately lead the practitioner to death. Now it is very
important to emphasize that the distinction between prudent and imprudent practices
cannot be very precisely made. Rather, this distinction is one of degree. Moreover, there is
no precise definition of “one partner, drink, drug or anything else too many”, that is, one
who has never had a Caipirinha may need to stop after the first one, whereas more
experienced drinkers may drink it throughout the night. What I mean is that each person
needs to figure out what counts as a prudent or as an imprudent practice for oneself. The
action of doing so is a craft or, in Deleuze’s and Guattari’s words, an “art” in the Greek
452
In conversation, Irene Olivero has pointed out that this is not always the case, insofar as there may be
macro-political-conflicts, say, that of fighting against the Italian fascist regime of the 1930s and 1940s,
regarding which it may be inevitable (insofar as resistance is at stake) for left-wingers to proceed imprudently
in being willing to sacrifice their own lives. This is an interesting point that cannot be addressed in this essay,
which remains neutral on whether there are counter examples to (MCC 7).
235
sense stated above (see 1.1) of a conjunction of disciplined practices or ways of doing
something. Henceforth, the term “artist” as opposed to the term “crafter” will be used in
the sense of someone who deeply masters a craft in practicing it in a prudent way.
Note that the “harsh critic” referred in the text by Deleuze mentioned in this
chapter’s first paragraph is Michel Cressole. 453 Cressole claims that Deleuze is “someone
who’s always just tagged along behind, taking it easy, capitalizing upon other’s people’s
experiments, on gays, drug-users, alcoholics, masochists, lunatics, and so on, vaguely
savoring their transport and poisons without ever taking any risks”. 454 My reading is that
the core Deleuze’s reply to Cressole is to be drawn out of (D-8) by claiming that:
(MCC 8)
Deleuze never purported to be an artist of sexual intercourse,
drinking or drug-use. In fact, his sexual, drinking or drug-use
practices are ultimately irrelevant.
What is relevant is Deleuze’s practice of doing metaphysics; his practice of dealing with
micro-wars by means of the left-wing political practice of politicization. This is because
(MCC 9)
Deleuze is (or at least wishes to be) the artist of such micro-wars.
I draw (MCC 9) out of (D-9). Now consider the immigration-conflict once again.
Imagine that the left-winger on this macro-political conflict goes as far as fostering in his
apartment in Paris an illegal immigrant who has particular identities, such as: to be male;
to be adult; to be cisgender; to be heterosexual; to be brown-skinned; to have been born
and raised in a Muslim country; to speak Arab and French with an African accent; to be a
citizen of a Muslim country; to have not attended a university; to come from a low class;
453
454
Michel Cressole, Deleuze, Paris, Éditions Universitaires, 1973.
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp. 11.
236
to have experienced poverty throughout his life; to have ran away from a war; to be
Muslim; etc. Imagine that the illegal immigrant has a right-wing attitude toward those who
have particular identities similar to those of the Parisian left-winger himself, that is, those
who are not Muslims; have not ran away from wars; have not experienced poverty; have
disrespected norms of the Qur’an or at least what the illegal immigrant takes to be such
norms; etc. Imagine that, passively, the illegal immigrant feels that his others are a threat
to his particular identities (especially, that of being a Muslim) and even to his very life.
Actively, he acts under the influence of this feeling, say, by planning and ultimately
championing a terrorist attack in Paris that kills hundreds or even thousands of people,
including people regarding which the Parisian left-winger cares deeply, such as family
members or close friends. It follows that the Parisian left-winger has an imprudent
approach to the immigration-conflict. He is no artist of this macro-political conflict. This
is because he, ultimately, simply ignores his own needs for self-defense in placing himself
too far left within the political spectrum mentioned in the last chapter at 5.3
Hence, this left-winger’s imprudent attitude is comparable to that of the historical
(MCC 10)
Jesus Christ who seems to have championed similar imprudent
approaches toward some of the macro-political conflicts of his time,
such as the one on how to resist the Roman oppression while
revising the Jewish law.
I draw (MCC 10) out of (D-10). In doing so, I wish to further underline that Deleuze, as
indicated by (MCC 7), endorses prudent left-wing approaches to political-conflicts as
opposed to imprudent ones. Indeed, I read that he takes that the mere fact that imprudent
practices are sort of suicidal ones that are likely to lead one to death or, at least, to the loss
of something that one cares deeply is sufficient reason for avoiding them and pursuing
237
prudent practices. To put it in Nietzsche’s terms, what Deleuze seeks to establish is an
approach to micro-wars of a “Roman Caesar with the Christ’s soul”, that is, someone who
shows empathy toward others but still cares about one own’s need for self-defense. 455 I do
not think that it is impossible to draw out of Deleuze’s works a “Caesar-yet-Christ” driven
approach to the immigration-conflict. Yet, it is not easy to do so. As the European and the
American immigration crisis indicate, it is hard to determine the requirements for an
approach to the immigration-conflict to be qualified as a prudent one. To do so or to discuss
what kind of state policies on the immigrant-conflict are to be adopted today are not aims
pursued here. I also do not wish to spell out what counts as a prudent left-wing political
approach toward the Charlottesville-conflict. I am also neutral on whether the Southern
and the Parisian left-winger are to use upfront kinds of violence regarding right-wingers.
What I would like to do, instead, is to claim that an imprudent left-wing approach
to micro-wars is analogous to the Christ-driven approach of the left-winger who fosters a
terrorist in his house. This is so in that imprudent left-wingers on disputes also risk, if not
their lives, at least something that they care deeply, such as their careers insofar as members
of a philosophy faculty. This occurs when, for the sake of increasing the level of tolerance
in philosophy, one disrespects the norms on how philosophy is to be done in resorting to
not very subtle kinds of violence. Imagine that a supposedly apolitical, but actually microright-wing philosopher is invited by one’s faculty colleague to give a talk on an issue that
micro-right-wingers like to discuss, say, the distinction between extensional, intensional
and hyperintensional notions. As expected, the right-winger speaks in the name of an
“experimental spirt”, “common sense” and/or of what is “conceptually obvious” and
455
Nachlass 1884, 27 [60], my translation.
238
presupposes that one’s view is motivated mainly because it contradicts that of another
right-winger who recently published a paper about a similar issue in a specialized journal.
An imprudent micro-left-wing approach would be that of the one who invites to the
talk a non-philosopher left-wing activist who strongly and even passionately agrees with
left-wing approaches to macro-conflicts and who: often interrupts the micro-right-winger,
say, in asking for definitions of each and every term used or by raising aggressive
questions; makes disapproving sounds or coughs while aiming to spell the lack of
motivation of the speaker’s view; cursers and/or mocks the speaker supposedly nonproblematic conceptions of “science” or “common sense”; ultimately, throws objects, such
as pens or even chairs, at the right-winger etc. My Deleuze does not propose the adoption
of such not very subtle kinds of violence; it is simply imprudent to resist in such a way.
Now, before I spell out the kind of prudent resistance my Deleuze takes to be
justified, it is crucial to emphasize that the actual Deleuze himself practiced philosophy at
a particular context quite distinct from the North American one in which this dissertation
is inserted. Deleuze’s context was that of France, roughly, from 1940s up to early 1990s. I
read that, in this context, a prudent left-wing approach to disputes could be pursued in a
modernist way. Indeed, I tend to believe that it can be historically observed that this way
was adopted, not only by Deleuze and Guattari, but by several other 20th century French
philosophers influenced by Nietzsche, such as Bataille, Klossowski, Blanchot, Foucault
and Derrida. This way deserves to be named a modernist one because the three features
that characterize it resemble features easily found in the writings of late 19th century poets
who have been described as modernistic ones. I have in mind the likes of Charles
Baudelaire, Paul Verlaine, Tristan Corbière, Arthur Rimbaud, Stéphane Mallarmé, etc.
239
The first modernist feature is the adoption of a use of language that is alternative
regarding the uses endorsed by one’s tradition. Consider once again the aforementioned
upfront rhetorical devices that, as (D-1) through (D-13) indicate, can be easily found in
Deleuze’s writings as well as in the writings of all the other aforementioned French
philosophers significantly influenced by Nietzsche. I take that, roughly, from the 1940s up
to the 1990s, to rely on such devices was, indeed, to rely on an alternative use of language
regarding those of most French philosophers, such as Gueroult and Alquié. Analogously,
to articulate a verse, such as Rimbaud’s “the star has wept rose-colored in the heart of your
ears” already discussed in 2.3, was likewise to adopt an alternative use of language
regarding verses traditionally adopted by poets before the 19th century.
The second modernist feature is the impersonation of at least one other by means
of philosophical writings that, say, seek to emphasize that some others are persons who are
legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are at stake. This can be done by,
metaphorically speaking, painting a quasi-abstract portrait (comparable to Francis
Bacon’s) of them. To use another metaphor, Deleuze aims his writings to strike his readers
as if one of their others were knocking at their doors in the middle of the night in demanding
to have the existence of their personhood as well as the importance of this personhood
acknowledged. Note that this second modernist feature can likewise be considerably easily
found in Deleuze’s writings, especially in those he co-authored with Guattari, such as the
Anti-Oedipus. This is because, as (D-11) indicates, Deleuze aimed to impersonate or, to
put in his terms, to embrace the “conceptual persona” of an other of the white man: the socalled mentally disordered schizophrenic. Therefore, what (D-11) inspires me to think, that
is, what I would like to draw out of this statement is the claim that:
240
(MCC 11)
It has to be underlined, though, that the conceptual persona of the
schizophrenic impersonated in Deleuze’s writings is distinct from
someone psychiatrists would describe as a schizophrenic; the former
is a way by means of which Deleuze seeks to prudently adopt a leftwing political practice of politicization, whereas the latter is
someone who has been isolated and suffered in mental institutions.
I also underline that the second modernist feature can be easily found in the writings
of other French philosophers influenced by Nietzsche. Consider once again the Foucault
of History of Madness. I read that he also aimed to impersonate an other of the white man,
that is, he aimed to embrace the conceptual persona of a mad person or even of the ultimate
other of reason: madness itself, one that cannot be identified with the madness attributed
to the so-called mentally disordered. The Derrida of Spurs: Nietzsche’s Styles also appears
to aim to embrace a conceptual persona who is an other of the white man: that of an ultimate
feminine woman whose way of thinking would be over and above “phallogocentrism” and,
hence, distinct from that of any actual woman. Analogously, starting in the 19th century
with the named French modernist poets and continuing throughout the 20th century, poets
have also constantly impersonated all kinds of others of the white man, such as blackskinned people, Jews, Latinos, women, transsexuals, drug-users, immigrants, kids,
criminals, mentally disordered people, animals, etc. Some of the poets I have in mind are:
Guillaume Apollinaire, Giuseppe Ungaretti, Fernando Pessoa, E.E. Cummings, Florbela
Espanca, Manuel Bandeira, Antonin Artaud, André Breton, Tristan Tzara, Federico García
Lorca, Francis Ponge, Langston Hughes, Carlos Drummond de Andrade, João Cabral de
Melo Neto, Charles Bukowski, Paul Celan, Pier Paolo Pasolini, Sylvia Plath, Allen
Ginsberg, Haroldo de Campos, Ferreira Gullar, and several others.
The third modernist feature is that of praising and pointing toward a utopian new
context, such as one in which others would simply be recognized as members of a really
241
universal community as opposed to threats to a narrow majority. Hence, what (D-12)
inspires me to think or what I would like to draw out of this statement is the claim that:
(MCC 12)
Philosophers are to praise and point toward a utopian new
context. 456
This is, I read, what Deleuze has attempted to do throughout his career. Hence, I am
inclined to follow Frederic Jameson in reading that Deleuze was “in many ways a
quintessential modernist, passionately committed to the eruption of the genuinely, the
radically, and, dare one even say, the authentically New”. 457 This is also more or less
explicitly the case with the aforementioned French philosophers influenced by Nietzsche
as well as with the named poets. Indeed, consider the last verse of Baudelaire’s 1857 Les
Fleurs du mal in its original French words: “Au fond de l’Inconnu pour trouver du
nouveau!”. This verse can be translated to English as: “To the depths of the Unknown to
find something new!”. I do not think that I exaggerate in claiming that this verse was some
sort of imperative for French Nietzschean philosophers and modernist poets, that is, they,
throughout the 20th century, have all more or less been unconsciously influenced by
Baudelaire in likewise praising and engaging themselves in the search for something new.
What I draw out of (D-13) is the claim that, in championing the left-wing political
practice in a prudent modernist way characterized by the three described features,
(MCC 13)
456
Philosophers are to pursue a goal similar to that of modernist poets:
to shock or embarrass their readers, especially right-wing ones, in
pressuring them to change the way they have proceed.
For a detailed take on Deleuze’s utopian politics, see Paul Patton, “Utopian Political Philosophy: Deleuze
and Rawls”, Deleuze Studies, Vol. 1, Issue 1, 2008: pp 41-59.
457
Fredric Jameson, A Singular Modernity: Essay on the Ontology of the Present, New York, Verso, 2002:
pp. 4.
242
To pursue this goal, then, is to: first, recognize that, among the others, some are deep
opponents who, practically speaking, attack the very way one aims to spend some of the
time of one’s life, say, by making it very hard for one to deal with disputes in accordance
with the left-wing practice of politicization and expressing the singular health of being in
agreement with the will to synthesis; and second, self-defend oneself from such deep
opponents by making references to issues that they are likely to ignore (e.g., caipirinha and
Bossa Nova), while describing them by means of a clinical-political vocabulary somehow
similar, but less dogmatically loaded than Nietzsche’s and Carnap’s. The vocabulary that
I have in mind and endorse is illustrated by the claim that: like macro-right-wingers, those
who adopt right-wing allegedly apolitical approaches to disputes make the actualization of
a utopian new context or even some sort of change toward such a context very hard, while
excessively disrespecting the will to synthesis in a way that, from the perspective of the
kind of health I pursue, seems to ultimately “sickly” require philosophical treatment.
Throughout this dissertation, I have attempted to imperfectly justify this last claim
while pointing toward such a treatment: a distinct way of dealing with disputes. My
Deleuze also does so while emphasizing that such a procedure does not express a “subtle”
violence, but, rather, is a procedure of self-defense regarding those who express the
properly dogmatic or the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence, that is, those who
champion right-wing allegedly apolitical approaches to disputes while more or less
implicitly suggesting that everybody is to do philosophy like they do, say, by respecting
the narrow conditions for personhood they suggest; whatever they take to be intuitive;
whatever they call “ordinary language”; whatever they take to be able to maximize
theoretical virtues or even sharing the pre-modernist aesthetic values (e.g., elegance or
243
simplicity) they presuppose, etc. 458 Let me also underline that the self-defense procedure I
attribute to Deleuze acknowledges that even one’s deep opponents whose practices one
wishes to change are still legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes are concerned;
legitimate rational peers who, ultimately, indicate that the very claims one defends are not
undeniable metaphysical claims, but merely deniable metaphysical claims.
It is not my goal to challenge that Deleuze himself may have, indeed, succeed to be
or to become the artist of micro-wars by championing a left-wing political (Christ-yetCaesar driven) practice of politicization in a modernist way. The very fact that, albeit the
resistance of analytic philosophers, Deleuze has been one of the most read, translated and
respected philosophers of the second half of 20th century attests to this. What is much more
disputable, though, is that contemporary philosophers, such as myself, are to follow
Deleuze in pursuing the left-wing approach to micro-wars in a modernist way. As (11)
indicates, this is not how I think. What I would like to claim, instead, is that a
metamodernist way (as opposed to a modernist one) of prudently pursuing the left-wing
practice of politicization is to be drawn out of Deleuze’s works.
Notice that the term “metamodernism” is not as popular as “post-modernism” and
“post-modern”. The latter two terms have been applied in all kinds of senses, including
derogatory senses that champions of the obscurity objection have often used to refer,
among others, to Nietzsche and French philosophers influenced by him, such as Deleuze
458
Note that one of the reasons Quine gives for rejecting abstract objects is they offend “the aesthetic sense
of us who have a taste for desert landscapes”. Also consider that Williamson supports the “aesthetic
evaluation of theories (elegance, simplicity, …)”, while emphasizing that: “of course, it is notoriously hard
to explain why aesthetic criteria are a good methodological guide, but it would be dangerously naïve to
abandon them for that reason”. See Willard Van Orman Quine, “On what there is”, The Review of
Metaphysics Vol. 2. No. 5, Sep., 1948: pp. 23; and Timothy Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy, pp.
285 and 289. For a detailed take on the role of aesthetic values when a choice between contrasting
metaphysical views is at stake, see Jiri Benovsky, Meta-metaphysics: On Metaphysical Equivalence,
Primitiveness, and Theory Choice, Switzerland, Springer International, 2016.
244
himself. Also notice that I have not used the terms “post-modernism” and “post-modern”.
Hence, I take that the burden of spelling out what these terms mean falls on the shoulders
of those who have done so, not on mine. I also underline that it is not the case that the term
“metamodernism” has never been used; Mas’ud Zavarzadeh may have been the first to do
so. 459 This dissertation is not particularly influenced by him or by any other author who
has used the term “metamodernism”. By a metamodernist way of pursuing the left-wing
approach to disputes, it is to be understood one that arises out, is foreclosed and turns the
modernistic way against itself. This can be done by practicing a philosophy characterized
by three metamodernist features closely related but distinct from the modernist ones.
The first metamodernist feature is: instead of presupposing the modernist features,
to become historically aware that they have become widely shared and ultimately
normative ones among French philosophers influenced by Nietzsche. What I mean is that
philosophers of this tradition are somehow expected to adopt an alternative use of
language, impersonate at least one of the others of the white man and praise and point
toward a utopian new context, such as one in which such others would be recognized as
members of a really universal community as opposed to threats to actual majorities.
Analogously, contemporary poets are likewise expected to write poems that have features
quite similar to the modernist features, that is, Baudelaire and all the other modernist poets
named above are part of a, perhaps, even “oppressive” aesthetical tradition now.
It follows that contemporary philosophers whose uses of language are similar to
those adopted by the members of the French Nietzschean tradition do not exactly rely on
alternative uses of language. Rather, in resorting to the aforementioned upfront rhetorical
459
Mas’ud Zavarzadeh, “The Apocalyptic Fact and the Eclipse of Fiction in Recent American Prose
Narratives”, in Journal of American Studies: Vol. 9, No. 1, April, 1975: p.69-83.
245
devices, their uses of language are somehow standard ones regarding this tradition.
Moreover, to impersonate in one’s writings a schizophrenic or any other of the white man
is no longer to impersonate an other with regard to this tradition. The reason is that
philosophers, such as Foucault, Derrida and Deleuze himself, have already constantly done
so. For a similar reason, it is also no longer new to praise and point toward the
aforementioned utopian new context, that is, Deleuze and other French philosophers
influenced by Nietzsche have also often done so for almost one hundred years or so.
It follows that, though those who adopt a modernist way of pursuing the left-wing
approach to disputes might still be able to shock or embarrass the ones who are not familiar
with the French Nietzschean tradition, they are not likely to do so with those who are aware
of it. Analogously, poems by all the aforementioned poets might still shock or embarrass
readers who are unaware that since the 19th century, throughout 20th century and up to our
time, poets have relied on alternative uses of language, impersonate their others as well as
praise and point toward a utopian new context. Indeed, as indicated above, to proceed in
such a way became a, perhaps, even aesthetically “oppressive”, norm among poets.
Analogously, it is not exaggerated to claim that to practice a philosophy that has
the three modernist features is also a, perhaps, “oppressive” norm among philosophers
influenced by Nietzsche, albeit such procedure may still shock or embarrass right-wing
philosophers who are, say, practically only familiar with the writings of contemporary
analytic philosophers. Indeed, perhaps, it might be quite easy to shock or embarrass these
philosophers. The same can be stated about the Southern, the Parisian right-winger, the
ones who have recently protested in Brazil against the “Queer Museum” exposition focused
246
on queer art or, more broadly, anyone who has more or less ignored the modernist poetry
and art that has been published and exposed for more than one hundred years.
The second metamodernist feature is to indicate that —given that the modernist
assumptions are widely shared within the continental tradition, especially that of French
philosophers influenced by Nietzsche —the ones who currently presuppose them face the
risk of proceeding as inverted right-wingers. Inverted right-wingers are the ones who,
passively, feel that those who ignore or disrespect the modernist norm that one is to do a
philosophy that has the modernist features are a threat, if not to their lives, at least to their
particular identity of being champions of the modernist way of pursuing the left-wing
approach. In order to protect this particular identity of theirs or even their lives, inverted
right-wingers, actively, act under the influence of this feeling, say, by endorsing and not
showing much empathy toward those who disrespect the stated modernist norm and/or the
norms of political correctness. The latter are gradually becoming dominant all over the
world. According to such norms, one is to be as tolerant as possible in not shocking or
embarrassing anyone, especially the others of the white man. Given these norms, as
indicated above, it is extremely unlike to find passages by contemporary analytic
philosophers that follow Quine in suggesting that Mexicans are dangerous. To put it more
explicitly, yesterday’s “jokes” became today’s “offensive remarks”. Accordingly,
contemporary analytic seem to be gradually becoming champions of political correctness.
Note that these norms of political correctness may be used against Deleuze’s
writings themselves. Consider a passage quoted in this chapter’s very first paragraph:
Deleuze’s way of metaphorically describing his “immaculate conception” as an action of
247
“taking an author from behind and giving him a child”. 460 Inverted right-wingers who
entitle themselves to take any reference to sex as being shocking may be inclined to claim
that this passage offends those who have actually being raped. On my part, my reading is
that, instead of being a metaphor for a violent rape, this passage is a metaphor for an act of
love; an act of love that a lover takes regarding someone the lover cares deeply in seeking
to procreate with so that the reader’s own DNA and that of the author are conjoined into a
new being. I emphasize that Deleuze only applies his immaculate conception method to
authors who influenced him; not to his deep opponents, such as Immanuel Kant. 461
I also speculate that basic historical observation attests that a transition is taking
place in the West. What characterizes this transition is that it is becoming more recurrent
to observe others of the white man living in ways that, for several centuries, appeared to
be the exclusive right of concrete white men. Consider, for instance, someone who is a
descent of Muslim Arabs but has lived one’s whole life in Paris; someone who speaks
French with no accent, has attended French public universities and has a successful career,
say, as a lawyer or a physician. Also consider a black-skinned female who has studied in
elitist and quite expensive American institutions and works at a job that pays more than
two hundred thousand dollars a year. Regardless of right-wing efforts, I take that it is
empirically considerably evident that cases such as these are becoming more recurrent.
What also characterizes the aforementioned transition is the fact that the abstract
object mentioned in (MCC 3) is gradually starting to no longer deserve to be called the
460
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp.6.
As Deleuze states, his “book on Kant’s different”. This is because, instead of using his immaculate
conception method, Deleuze “did it as a book about an enemy that tries to show how his system works”.
Gilles Deleuze, “Letter to a Harsh Critic”, pp.6. Also see Gilles Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, trans.
Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, London, Athlone Press, 1984.
461
248
white-man-in-itself. This is because concrete white men are starting to no longer be the
ones who less explicitly fail to satisfy Western norms presupposed by all kinds of
majorities; the end of slavery and of the Jim Crow laws; the fact that women have the right
to vote in most countries and that homosexuality is no longer usually described as a mental
disorder and/or a crime; the fact that husbands who beat their wives are today more often
denounced than in the past and that a lot of women in the West are financially independent
from their fathers or husbands; the election of Barack Obama in the States, the #MeToo
movement, all kinds of affirmative actions and the fact that universities have often
organized inclusiveness conferences and talks about xenophobia, classism, racism, sexual
harassment and transphobia are just a few signs of this. Another sign, as the Charlottesvilleconflict indicates, is that concrete white-skinned males appear to think that such norms of
political correctness make it hard for them to act or use language, as they have done.
Perhaps, then, the abstract object mentioned in (MCC 3) will soon need to be
renamed, say, the lamb-in-itself. By this, I understand an entity that, like the white-manin-itself, behaves, uses language and even feels how each and every person is supposed to
behave, use language and feel in accordance with all kinds of Western majorities. Distinct
from the white-man-in-itself, the lamb-in-itself does so by being as tolerant as possible in
not shocking or embarrassing anyone, especially the others of the white man who have
constantly suffered with practices of oppression throughout the history of the West. Those
who more explicitly disrespect such norms of political correctness, then, may be called the
others of the lamb-in-itself. Moreover, note that these others may be either males or
females; white-skinned or black-skinned; heterosexuals or non-heterosexuals; Europeans
or non-Europeans; North Americans or non-North Americans; etc.
249
Now let me emphasize that, distinct from macro-right-wingers, I embrace the
transition from the standard of the white-man-in-itself to that of the lamb-in-itself. To put
it in upfront terms, I do prefer to live in a community in which Quine’s remarks about
Mexicans are taken to be offensive ones as opposed to irrelevant points or even “jokes”. I
also prefer to live in communities in which xenophobic, classist, racist, sexist and/or
transphobic behavior is oppressed, not praised, say, as a sign of masculinity. Yet, I also
underline that new oppressions seem to be brought about by this new standard of the lambin-itself, such as that of censuring modernist poetry or art in general, under the basis that
they violate the new rules of political correctness in being too offensive, especially to the
others of the white man. 462 My point is that inverted right-wingers are, to put it
metaphorically, the “slaves” of this lamb-in-itself; they are conservatives as opposed to
libertarians or egalitarians. They are not libertarians because they do not seek to be in
accordance with what is singular about themselves or others. They are also not egalitarians
because they do not seem to seek to defend the interests of a really universal community,
but merely those of gradually increasing majorities that respect the new rules of political
correctness. 463 Another way to state this is by claiming that inverted right-wingers are quite
intolerant or considerably close-minded regarding their others who violate these new rules.
The third metamodernist feature is that of paradoxically still satisfying or at least
aiming to satisfy the modernist norm that one is to do a philosophy that has the three
modernist features. This is what this dissertation has aimed to do. To begin with, this is to
462
Note that under the basis that Balthus’s 1938 painting, “Therese Dreaming”, praises pedophilia, thousands
of people signed, in 2017, a petition for the removal of this painting from New York’s Metropolitan Museum
of Art. The museum, however, did not remove the painting.
463
To put in Zizek’s terms, inverted right-wingers appear to wish for a “society immobilized by the concern
for not hurting the other, no matter how cruel and superstitious this other is and in which individuals are
engaged in regular rituals of ‘witnessing’ their victimization”. See Slavoj Zizek, Violence: Six Sideways
Reflections, New York, Pecador, 2008, pp. 130.
250
state that I have pursued a prudent left-wing approach to disputes in a metamodernist way
insofar as I have relied on a use of language that is or at least aims to be alternative
regarding the ones endorsed by the two traditions within which this dissertation is more
likely to be inserted: the analytic and the continental one. The use of language adopted here
is alternative regarding those of the analytic tradition because neo-Pyrrhonists and
continental German and French philosophers have been mentioned and discussed,
metaphors have been used and no supposedly “clear” formal language was adopted.
I also do not speak in the name of an “ordinary language”. Indeed, this chapter
aimed to problematize accordance with such a language as a criterion to deal with disputes
in the first place. So, I reply to the possible objection that my use of language is not an
“ordinary” one by not granting that to adopt a use that is supposed to be an “ordinary” one
is a value in the first place. The reason is that others are those who, to begin with, do not
agree with whatever one takes to be an ordinary use of language. Hence, the language I
wish to speak is one that is more open to such others, even though I am aware that, as stated
in 3.2, my use of language is still quite an elitist one itself insofar as it is naïve to believe
that those who have not gone to College will be able to follow it. Note, though, that the
same can be stated about the uses of language of all philosophers mentioned here. This
includes the use of language of analytic philosophers who are only willing to discuss
among themselves and dare to speak in the name of an ordinary language as if their
technical terms were appealing to an “ordinary man”, to put in Kripke’s terms. 464 I
emphasize, once again, that even when it comes to an apparently ordinary word, such as
464
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity, pp. 41.
251
“person”, analytic philosophers have not agreed on what counts as an ordinary use, as
indicated in 4.3. The same seems to the case about any core philosophical term.
The use of language adopted here is also alternative regarding those of the
continental tradition, especially, those of the French tradition of philosophers influenced
by Nietzsche, such as Deleuze himself. The reason is that I have not used the stated upfront
rhetorical devices, but actually criticized their over-libertarian character in 3.2 I have also
explicitly defined all technical terms used here in hopefully making it less likely for the
obscurity objection to be raised against me. Hence, “my monstrous Deleuze” speaks in
terms of (MCC 1) to (MCC 13); not (D-1) through (D-13). Indeed, the latter statements, I
grant analytic philosophers, make it very easy for one to make the obscurity objection.
Furthermore, an impersonation of an other regarding both the analytic and the
continental tradition has also been pursued throughout this dissertation. This other is
someone whose aim is to articulate a philosophy that resists being qualified either as
analytic (in resisting the supposedly apolitical, but actually right-wing approach of Quine,
Kripke and Fine), or as continental (in resisting any contemporary modernistic way of
pursing the left-wing approach to disputes). More directly, this is to state that this other is
“too continental to be analytic”; it is also “too analytic to be continental” and in the end
aims to be neither analytic nor continental. A metaphor that illustrates the trans-non-binary
character played here is that of someone whose face is a deformed superposition of
Carnap’s face and Nietzsche’s, a monstrous Deleuze who is likewise an ultimate other of
the lamb-in-itself; “Friedrich Carnap”, “Rudolf Nietzsche”, “Gilles A. G. Moreira”,
252
“Felipe G. A. Deleuze” or even “F.G.A.M.” (to put in the terms of several of my poems)
are some of the names that this conceptual character could have been given. 465
This dissertation also praised and pointed toward a utopian new context, that is, one
in which it would no longer be “shocking” or “embarrassing” to mention Nietzsche and
Deleuze in analytic circles or analytic philosophers, such as Carnap, in continental
contexts. This is a context in which the analytic-continental gap would no longer matter.
Moreover, the very others of the lamb-in-itself would be taken as members of a really
universal conflictual community as opposed to threats to a majority. In fact, this new
context would be one in which all persons would be in perfect accordance with the will to
synthesis, say, in managing to do what may be ultimately impossible: to perfectly satisfy
their individualistic and communitarian tendencies in ultimately ceasing to feel that there
is a contrast between the two. This new context, then, would be one in which communities
would allow oneself to express one’s singularity, and singularities would be expressed by
means of the community, not oppressed by them. Indeed, the very distinction between a
will to power and a will to order would no longer make sense. Accordingly, this dissertation
has aimed to be a libertarian Nietzschean one insofar as it has attempted to express a
singularity that resists association with the analytic and the continental tradition. This
dissertation has also aimed to be an egalitarian Carnapian one in attempting to bring about
a really universal community whose rules would seek to protect the interests of all as
opposed to those of majorities, such as the gradually increasing majority of those who take
the rules of political correctness for granted and get easily offended. What follows, then, is
465
Felipe G. A. Moreira, Por uma estética do constrangimento, Rio de Janeiro, ed. Oito e Meio, 2013.
253
(12); the claim that this very dissertation illustrates how one can pursue a left-wing political
practice of politicization in a metamodernist way as opposed to a modernist way. 466
466
To use Carnap’s expression, I have also “openly” adopted “the form of art, of poetry” in seeking to react
to modernist poetry by means of a metamodernist poetry of my own. What characterizes the metamodernist
poetry are features considerably similar to those I attribute to the left-wing metamodernist prudent approach
to micro-wars championed here. Consider, for instance, my own Felipe G. A. Moreira, Por uma estética do
constrangimento. I have also written a series of columns in the literary journal, Subversa, in aiming to spell
out the pertinence of metamodernist poetry. As of March 3rd of 2019, these columns were available at:
http://www.revistasubversa.com/category/metamodernismo/. See EML 80.
CHAPTER 7
CONCLUSION
7.1 Restatement of the Claims of the System of Disputes
What I have done over the last six chapters was to rely on imperfect justificatory
resources that back up the following twelve claims of the system of disputes:
(1) It seems that:
(1-i)
Among the others, some are legitimate rational peers insofar as disputes
are at stake.
(1-ii) No person has settled a dispute once and for all, that is, in a way that
others could not rationally unsettle.
(1-iii) (1-i) and (1-ii) are extremely important points insofar as those who fail
to acknowledge them react in a quite unpersuasive manner to the fact
that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.
(2) One is to adopt a conflictual craft, that is, a synthesis between the skeptic craft
and the dogmatic craft that serves to articulate the system of disputes.
(3) Friedrich Nietzsche and Rudolf Carnap champion contrasting reactions to the
fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in disputes.
While doing so, they both endorse, but interpret differently an overcoming
metametaphysics characterized by three metametaphysical normative claims:
(3-i)
An overcoming of metaphysics is to be performed.
(3-ii)
This overcoming is to be performed by adopting a method of
linguistic analysis that is suspicious of the metaphysical use of
language and interprets such use through a different use of language
that aims to avoid metaphysics.
(3-iii)
This overcoming is to contribute to the political task of resisting
“diseased” metaphysical practices and promoting “healthy” nonmetaphysical ones.
(4) The contrast between Nietzsche’s libertarian and Carnap’s egalitarian reaction
is to be considered, not only by the few scholars who are interested in both of
these philosophers’ works, but by a far larger group of philosophers that
includes: those who have addressed the continental-analytic gap; those who are
254
255
concerned with the development of the history of 20th and 21st century
philosophy; and/or those who are interested in the works of the likes of
Foucault, Derrida, Lewis and/or van Inwagen
(5) One is to do a synthesis of Nietzsche’s libertarian and Carnap’s egalitarian
reaction to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been engaged in
disputes.
(6) There is no undeniable metaphysical claim, but a properly dogmatic “subtle”
violence.
(7) Disputes are micro-political conflicts analogous to macro-political conflicts,
that is, they are micro-wars.
(8) There has been a right-wing allegedly apolitical approach to disputes that,
perhaps, avoids the properly dogmatic “subtle” violence, but still expresses the
pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence.
(9) The properly dogmatic and the pseudo non-dogmatic “subtle” violence are to
be avoided.
(10)
A left-wing political practice of politicization that deals with micro-wars by
avoiding the properly dogmatic and the pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle”
violence is to be pursued as an alternative to the right-wing allegedly
apolitical approach.
(11)
The left-wing political practice of politicization is to be prudently pursued
in a metamodernist way as opposed to a modernist way.
(12)
This very dissertation illustrates how one can do so.
Now I will use the rest of this conclusion to make a case for one more claim, to reply to
two opponents of mine and to indicate how I plan to continue my research from now on.
7.2 The Incommensurable Greatness of Disputes
The claim I have in mind is the thirteenth and last claim of the system of disputes:
(13)
Disputes have an incommensurable greatness.
256
I claim that disputes have a greatness, as indicated in 1.5, in the sense that, since
immemorial times, persons have deeply cared about disputes in being strongly emotionally
compelled to spend a considerable amount of their lives’ times in addressing disputes.
Indeed, nothing indicates that persons will cease to do so in the future. Hence, I tend to
agree with Immanuel Kant when he, in his 1783 Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics,
observes: “that the human mind would someday entirely give up metaphysical
investigations is just as little expected, as that we would someday gladly stop all breathing
so as never to take in impure air”. 467 As also stated in 1.5, the greatness I consider is of an
incommensurable kind. This incommensurability occurs because no common unit of
measurement to quantify over this greatness seems obtainable; it seems impossible to
measure persons’ overall “amount” of emotions and/or time spent in dealing with disputes.
All the philosophers mentioned in this dissertation attest to (13). More precisely, a
quite basic observation of these philosophers’ writings indicates that all of them have
deeply cared about disputes in being strongly emotionally compelled to spend a
considerable amount of the time of their lives in addressing disputes. So, (13) is the least
controversial claim of the system of disputes. Surprisingly, though, this claim has been
very rarely defended. What contemporary analytic philosophers have often done, instead,
has been to engage themselves on what may be called the inflationist-deflationist dispute.
This is the dispute on whether disputes are important, or, to put in my terms, have
a greatness, insofar as they are analogous to the disagreements of the empirical scientists
and/or mathematicians. Willard Van Orman Quine, David Lewis, Theodore Sider and
Timothy Williamson have pointed to this direction, whereas the likes of Eli Hirsch and
467
Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics: With Selection from the Critique of Pure
Reason, trans. Gary Hatfield, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2004: (4:367).
257
Amie Thomasson have indicated otherwise. 468 For the latter, what is the case is that
disputes (or at least some of them, such as the one on whether ordinary objects, like tables
and chairs, exist) are merely verbal quarrels. Such quarrels would have occurred due to
philosophers’ inability to apply the very rules of ordinary languages, such as English.
Disputes, then, could be “easily” solved, that is, all philosophers would have to do to solve
them would be to apply the rules of English correctly. Yet, over the last more than 2000
years of history of metaphysics, philosophers would have not realized this simple solution.
I emphasize that it is not my aim to address the views of Hirsch or Thomasson in
detail. 469 What I provide, to paraphrase Hirsch, is merely a “short rebuttal”: that the fact
that deflationists’ views have not been unanimously accepted not even by the quite narrow
community of philosophers they care to mention in their writings —that is, basically, the
community of those who share the particular identities these philosophers have in common
with Quine, Saul Kripke and Kit Fine and that were discussed in 5.2 —is, arguably,
sufficient reason for the claim that the very way they apply the expression “ordinary
language” or “English” is not at all “ordinary” and, consequently, is ultimately another
overly imperfect justificatory resource unable to establish an “easy” solution. 470
As indicated in 1.1 and 5.2, I suspend judgement on whether disputes are analogous
to the disagreements of empirical scientists and/or mathematicians. Thus, I also suspend
judgement on the inflationist-deflationist dispute. Yet, it is worth to mention that those
468
Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1960; David Lewis,
Philosophical Papers: Volume I, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1983; On the Plurality of Worlds, MA,
Blackwell, 1986; Timothy Williamson, The Philosophy of Philosophy, MA, Blackwell, 2007; Theodore
Sider, Writing the Book of the World, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011; Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance
and Realism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011; and Amie L. Thomasson, Ontology Made Easy,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2015.
469
I addressed Hirsch’s view in detail in Felipe G. A. Moreira, “An Apology of Carnap”, Manuscrito
(Unicamp), Vol 37, Número 2, 2014: pp.261-289.
470
Eli Hirsch, Quantifier Variance, pp. 42.
258
engaged in this dispute seem to sometimes rely on a quite problematic presupposition that,
as indicated in 2.1, Carnap and other logical positivists constantly suggested. I call it the
overly scientific-driven presupposition according to which the very criterion to access the
greatness or the lack of greatness of disputes is whether they are analogous to the
disagreements of empirical scientists, mathematicians and/or logicians. I reject this
presupposition. I do so under the basis that this is another sign of Carnap’s overly
egalitarian stance already criticized in 3.2. As also indicated in 2.1, Carnap presupposes
that consensus is more valuable than dissensus. So, given that scientists, mathematicians
and logicians would have reached more consensus than metaphysicians, Carnap suggests
that the former’s disagreements would be more valuable than the disputes of the latter. On
my part, I claim that Carnap’s view here seems, once again, quite “naïve”. To rely once
more on a conflictual-use of intuitive-talk, his view strikes me as being “counter-intuitive”.
Consider the macro-political conflicts addressed above, that is, the Charlottesvilleconflict and the immigration-conflict. What basic observation shows is that the macroright-wingers and macro-left-wingers involved in these conflicts have reached no
consensus. Indeed, consider several other macro-political conflicts, such as: whether there
is to be a state of Israel; whether the USA is to continue to intervene in the Middle-East;
whether the UK is to leave the European Union; whether Brazil’s former president, Luis
Inácio Lula da Silva, is to be released from jail; etc. Basic observation attests that no
consensus has been reached on such matters. This factor, though, has not been taken as a
reason for claiming that macro-political conflicts are unimportant. What seems quite
evident is that the opposite is the case; that these conflicts also have an incommensurable
greatness of their own, regardless of persons’ inabilities to reach an agreement on them.
259
My view is that the same is the case with micro-political conflicts, that is, disputes;
these micro-wars have an incommensurable greatness due to the very fact that, since
immemorial times, persons have been engaged in them, regardless of their inabilities to
convince their others or to simply cease to care about their opponents’ views, as Friedrich
Nietzsche sometimes proposes (see 2.1). In fact, I am inclined to think that, as indicated in
4.3, the power to engage oneself in such disputes may even be a broad condition for
personhood. This is to state that all persons have been more or less irresistibly drawn
toward disputes and that, consequently, perhaps, it is not too exaggerated to even claim
that to reject their greatness is almost to reject the greatness of person’s lives themselves.
Let me underline, then, that I am quite aware that this very dissertation will be
unable to convince all of my opponents. Accordingly, to put it metaphorically and to
paraphrase Albert Camus, all that I take myself to be able to do is “to imagine myself as a
happy Sisyphus”. 471 This is someone who, in relying on all sorts of imperfect justificatory
resources, pursues a singular health of one’s own. What I mean is that this person is a
conflictual crafter who, while proposing a criterion to deal with disputes (e.g., accordance
with the left-wing political practice of politicization), pushes a rock up a hill and endorses
several claims, such as (1) to (13), regardless of others who will likely push this rock down
the hill once again. Now, before I let these others start to do so, I would like to make some
final remarks in addressing two of these others, while further underlying that my likely
inability to convince them does not problematize (13), that, indeed, the fact that I, myself,
seek to act in agreement with the will to synthesis in feeling irresistibly inclined to seek
consensus as well as to provoke dissensus with opponents is further evidence of (13).
471
“One must imagine Sisyphus happy”, Camus states in concluding in his essay. See Albert Camus, The
Myth of Sisyphus: And Other Essays, New York, First Vintage International Edition, 1991; pp. 123.
260
7.3 Last Replies to Two Others of Mine
The first other I have in mind is the hardcore skeptic mentioned in 1.3. This is
someone who, given that skeptics cannot explicitly defend claims, limits oneself to
insinuate that to have a barely justified or ultimately arbitrary stance is just as rationally
appealing as having a justified and non-arbitrary stance; someone who insinuates that to
attempt and fail to be an “isentão” is just as rationally appealing as to not do so. Hence, a
hardcore skeptic would insinuate that the right-wing approach to disputes is just as
appealing as the left-wing one defended here; that to express the properly dogmatic or the
pseudo-non-dogmatic “subtle” violence is just as pertinent as attempting to avoid doing so.
Now imagine that this hardcore skeptic is also a quite influential philosopher; one who has
published extensively in all sorts of respected journals, is the chair of a distinguished
department, the editor of a respected journal and/or works in an important academic press.
Imagine that this skeptic is confronted with a practical dispute. The dispute is to
accept into a graduate program, publish a paper or a book, invite to give a talk and/or hire
as a faculty member either one of two candidates. The first candidate is someone who, like
me, addresses and supports (1) through (13), while articulating the left-wing political
practice of politicization. The second candidate is someone who takes oneself to be
politically neutral, while more or less unconsciously championing the right-wing political
practice of depoliticization, say, in dealing with issues micro-right-wingers have focused
on, such as the analytic-synthetic distinction. Imagine that, in relying on the skeptic craft
and seeking to achieve tranquility, this skeptic suspends judgment on (1) through (13). The
hardcore skeptic also suspends judgement on any claims defended by the micro-rightwinger. Indeed, this skeptic feels that the reasons for benefiting either one of the two
261
candidates are equally rationally persuasive; that both philosophers have articulated
equally valuable works. Nevertheless, similar to the skeptics addressed in 1.3., this skeptic
still needs to act, that is, the skeptic needs to: decide which candidate is to be accepted into
the graduate program, published, invited to give a talk, and/or hired as a faculty member;
attempt to find funding to accept into the graduate program, publish, invite to give a talk
and/or hire both candidates; indefinably postpone any decision; simply refuse to decide;
decide to leave the decision to someone else, say, another faculty member; etc.
Accordingly, in having a barely justified or even arbitrary stance, imagine that the
hardcore skeptic fails to be a “isentão” by ultimately acting in a micro-politically engaged
way. More importantly, consider that this way benefits either the micro-left-winger or the
micro-right-winger, say, under the basis that the former or the latter ultimately has a more
“relevant” work that runs more in alliance with the philosophical purposes of the skeptic’s
department, journal and/or publishing company. Note that this hardcore skeptic insinuates
that there is nothing wrong about this attitude; that it seems that to aim and, however, to
ultimately fail to be a “isentão” is just as rationally persuasive as to not do so. On my part,
for the time being, my last reply to this hardcore skeptic is of a dual sort.
On the one hand, if the hardcore skeptic, practically speaking, ultimately benefits
the micro-left-wing candidate, I do not think that the dispute on the differences between
his skeptic’s position and my own are worth pursuing. What I mean is that this skeptic is
such a minor opponent of mine that I am willing to treat him as an ally for all practical
matters and, indeed, there is not much more that a conflictual crafter can wish for from an
opponent insofar as disputes are at stake. On the other hand, if the hardcore skeptic,
practically speaking, ultimately benefits the micro-right-wing candidate, my only reply is
262
to repeat all the points made over the last two chapters. This is to state that, for all practical
purposes, it is hard to see why this hardcore skeptic’s stance would be significantly distinct
from those of micro-right-wingers, whose views I have problematized in seeking to
pressure them to change their practices and who are likely to reply harshly to me.
What I mean is that I expect micro-right-wingers to proceed as they have always
done by: making it hard for me to continue to spend time in dealing with disputes from a
left-wing perspective in practically benefiting those who, like themselves, champion
allegedly apolitical, but actually micro-right-wing approaches to disputes; rejecting that
they are micro-right-wingers and insisting that they are micro-politically neutral; mocking
the terms (e.g., “metamodernism”) that I have adopted just like they have done with terms
adopted by German or French philosophers who, nonetheless, they often do not mention in
their writings; using the “subtle” violence of denying that they have used “subtle” violence
just like macro-right-wingers have denied that they have used violence; claiming that, in
identifying and criticizing this “subtle” violence of theirs, I am actually the one who is
being violent just like macro-right-wingers have argued that black-skinned people who
have criticized racist practices are actually racists or that women who have problematized
sexist practices are the ones who are actually sexists; suggesting that I have misapplied the
rules of ordinary language, regardless of the fact that analytic philosophers have never
agreed on what exactly are the rules of such language in the first place; speaking in the
name of simplistic notions of “science” and/or “scientific” standards while suggesting that
I have violated such standards; insisting (usually, while raising their voices in seeking to
intimidate) that their claims are undeniable metaphysical ones insofar as they, indeed, run
in accordance with a intuition of theirs; etc. What I mean is that I am aware of traditional
263
right-wing moves; they all strike me as overly imperfect justificatory resources that,
ultimately, are unable to establish persuasive claims. In other words, micro-right-wingers
may convince one another, but they do not convince me; hopefully, others, especially those
who are more inclined toward left-wing approaches to macro-conflicts, are also
unconvinced by micro-right-wingers and will join me in showing resistance to them.
The second other of mine I would like to address, then, is the one who may be called
the hardcore right-winger. This is a philosopher who agrees that one’s practices are microright-wing ones but insists that this is not a negative aspect. The reason, the hardcore rightwinger believes, is that, indeed, macro-right approaches to macro-conflicts, such as those
of the Southern and the Parisian right-winger, are better than those of macro-left-wingers.
Indeed, the macro-right-winger takes that Donald Trump has been a better president than
Barack Obama; that Jair Bolsonaro is also very likely to be a better president than Lula,
etc. Now note that most contemporary analytic philosophers working on metaphysics are
similar to Saul Kripke and Kit Fine. 472 This is so insofar as they have exclusively addressed
disputes, without mentioning their views on macro-political conflicts. Hence, I do not wish
to identify the hardcore right-winger’s view to that of any contemporary analytic
philosopher working on metaphysics. Perhaps, one could do so with Quine’s view, but,
given that he refrains from dealing with macro-political conflicts in detail, this move would
also be a problematic one. Yet, I think that the view of the hardcore right-winger is to be
addressed. Indeed, I am inclined to believe that it is more coherent to be an upfront hardcore
right-winger than to take oneself to be micro-politically neutral, while, nonetheless,
spending a significant amount of the time of one’s life in benefiting micro-right wingers.
472
Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity; and Kit Fine “Essence and Modality”, in Philosophical Perspectives
Vol. 8: 1994: pp.1-16.
264
Notice that the hardcore right-winger is, so to speak, the deepest of my deep
opponents. Hence, this person poses the hardest challenge to my view. This takes place
because, while embracing problematic starting points of one’s own, the hardcore rightwinger simply rejects mine, such as my reasons for endorsing (5); for taking that one is to
attempt to maximize one’s individualistic as well as communitarian tendencies in being in
accordance with the will to synthesis; for being strongly inclined to believe that to privilege
empathy over self-defense is “healthier” (if not “ethically” superior) than to do otherwise;
that there simply is something “sick” about conservatives who overprivileged self-defense
in detriment of empathy; etc. Accordingly, I do not think that I can actually convince the
hardcore right-winger. We simply embrace radically distinct problematic starting points
and, hence, cannot really “refute” one another. All we can do is to struggle with each other.
Analogously, I tend to think that the same is the case with Jesus and Julius Caesar;
the Southern left-winger and the Southern right-winger; the Parisian left-winger and the
Parisian right-winger; Obama and Trump; Lula and Bolsonaro; etc. What these people have
done has been to struggle with one another while seeking to convince their respective
opponents to drop their practices, regardless of their likely impossibility of doing so in a
way that would permanently settle the issue. While recognizing the hardcore right-winger
as a legitimate rational peer of mine, what I have done here in a micro-level is the same.
7.4 Hegel and Toward an Object-Level Metaphysics
Throughout this dissertation, I have used the conflictual craft to back up (1) through
(13). These claims are all metametaphysical ones. Moreover, this dissertation has focused
on the micro-politics of metaphysics. Accordingly, I have been neutral on object-level
claims, such as those that God, human and physicalist-driven philosophers have constantly
265
discussed: respectively, there is evil, there is a thing-in-itself or there is consciousness. In
following Carnap and (in my reading proposed in 2.4) Nietzsche, I have likewise been
neutral on whether any kind of realism, such as those of God-driven philosophers and
physicalist ones, trumps any kind of idealism of the likes proposed by human-driven
philosophers. Currently, though, I am not sure that neutralism is the most persuasive
position, especially vis-à-vis a view that promotes a synthesis of realism and idealism.
The synthesis I have in mind is one that, to begin with, would bring to light the
problematic starting points (already briefly discussed in 3.3) of realist and idealist views,
instead of presupposing them. Furthermore, this synthesis would problematize realism by
means of idealism and vice-versa so that the shortcomings of these views would be
avoided. Finally, this synthesis would aim to maintain the positive aspects of realistic as
well as of idealistic views in, perhaps, backing up a human-yet-physicalist-driven approach
of the sort tentatively suggested by Nietzsche and, sometimes, Carnap, as indicated in 2.2
and 2.4. I tend to think that the works of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, especially his
Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, indicate how this synthesis can be done insofar as
Hegel points toward a deviant (neither exactly realistic nor exactly idealist) concept of
God. 473 This concept is that God is the identity between identity and non-identity. Note that
this concept deserves to be called a deviant one because it does not imply what, arguably,
in Hegel’s view was implied by practically all other concepts of God distinct from his: that
God is some sort of “alien” natural force or self-conscious agent that commands persons
to perform certain practices, regardless of whether they freely will do to so.
473
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion: Vol 1, 2 and 3, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2007.
266
In the future, then, I may address Hegel’s works much more carefully than I have
done here, say, in translating his apparently paradoxical statements, such as God is the
identity between identity and non-identity, into claims that are less likely to allow the
obscurity objection to arise. In doing so, I likewise may investigate whether my conflictual
craft also serves to expand the metametaphysical system of disputes into a much more
ambitious system. To put it metaphorically, this more ambitious system I have in mind
would be a much less humble home and, perhaps, even a “monumental” one built with
object-level metaphysical claims bricks. More precisely, here is what I consider doing.
I think about addressing a practical question distinct from the one focused on here,
that is, how is one to react to the fact that, since immemorial times, persons have been
engaged in disputes? The distinct practical question I have in mind runs as follows: how is
one to react to the fact that, likewise since immemorial times, some persons have embraced
the claim, “I must perform a practice because a God commands me to do so”? Henceforth,
I will refer to this claim as (G). (G) deserves to be called a barely responsible claim because
this claim suggests that the reason one must perform a practice does not lie in the fact that
one freely wills to do so, but, rather, in the fact that an “alien” natural force or selfconscious agent imposes itself upon the agent in commanding the agent to do so. Also note
that those who have embraced this barely responsible claim fall into at least three groups.
First, the groups of political leaders, such as George W. Bush, Brazil’s current
president, Jair Messias Bolsonaro, and Islamic terrorists of the likes of Osama bin Laden.
Second, the groups of all kinds of ordinary believers, such as Buddhists, Hinduists, Jews,
Christians, Muslims, etc. Third, (G) has also been endorsed by these religions’ scriptural
figures. By this, I understand a person whose existence beyond such texts is considerably
267
challengeable, given that in such texts, the person is described as having done extremely
remarkable deeds that ordinary people are unable to perform. For instance, the patriarchs
of the Jewish, Christian and Islamic religions, such as Abraham, are scriptural figures.
Physicalist-driven philosophers and human ones have constantly presupposed a
dismissivist response or explicitly championed an eliminativist one to the stated distinct
practical question, that is, how is one to react to the fact that, since immemorial times, some
persons have embraced (G)? The dismissivist response is that one is to ignore those who
endorse (G) and/or make any appeal to any concept of God, regardless of political leaders’
use of (G); the fact that ordinary believers are the majority of the population and that such
believers assume that scriptural figures existed. The eliminativist response may be
attributed to David Hume, William K. Clifford, Nietzsche and, more recently, Daniel
Dennett and Richard Dawkins. 474 This response is that one is to quite explicitly pressure
those who embrace (G) to stop doing so, say, by arguing that appeals to any concept of
God are rationally unjustified unscientific superstitions, and/or even signs of disease. 475
I have been satisfied with the dismissivist and the eliminativist response. I not sure,
though, whether I still am. Thus, I may investigate whether a third response trumps the
dismissivist and the eliminativist one. I call it the revisionist response: that one is to react
474
David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
2007; William K. Clifford, The ethics of belief and other essays, New York, Prometheus Books, 1999; Daniel
Dennett, Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon, New York, Penguin Books, 2006; and
Richard Dawkins, “Viruses of the Mind”, in Bo Dahlbom (ed.), Dennett and his Critics, Oxford, Blackwell
Publishers, 1993.
475
To attribute this response to Carnap is more problematic. In his Autobiography, he states the following:
“at the present stage of development of our culture, many people still need religious mythological symbols
and images. It seems to be wrong to try to deprive [believers] of the support they obtain from these ideas, let
alone to ridicule them”. On the other hand, Carnap also claims that “an entirely different matter is the question
of theology, here understood as a system of doctrines in distinction to a system of valuation and prescriptions
for life […] I came in my philosophical development first to the insight that the main statements of traditional
metaphysics are outside the realm of science and irrelevant for scientific knowledge, and later to the more
radical conviction that they are devoid of any cognitive content. Since that time I have been convinced that
the same holds for most of the statements of contemporary Christian theology”. See IAB 7-8.
268
to the fact that, since immemorial times, some persons have embraced (G), by articulating
a deviant concept of God. An inclination of mine is that, in problematizing the views of
God-driven philosophers, Hegel’s Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion point to this
direction in also promoting a deviant concept of responsible agent. Arguably, Hegel’s
concept is that a responsible agent is one that performs an action that is simultaneously (in
a libertarian way) willed by what is singular about oneself and (in an egalitarian way)
beneficial to a really universal community. This concept deserves to be called a deviant
one because it does not imply what traditional notions of responsible agent seem to have
implied: that a responsible agent is simply one who acts in accordance with one’s own free
will. I also tend to read that, for Hegel, to act as a responsible agent (in his sense) is to act
in accordance with what God (also in Hegel’s sense) commands one to do.
Note that interpreters of Hegel’s Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, such as
Jon Stewart and Peter C. Hodgson, have mainly focused on the exegetical task of proposing
a persuasive reading of Hegel. 476 However, such interpreters have not discussed whether
Hegel’s deviant concepts of God and responsible agent are persuasive ones for
contemporary philosophers, such as those who embrace the dismissivist or the eliminativist
response. This is to state that works that compare these two responses with Hegel’s
revisionist response are largely lacking. Hence, I may want to fill this gap in the future by
pursuing three objectives. First, to articulate an interpretation of Hegel that spells out his
alternative concepts of God and responsible agent in a way that may be lacking in Hegel’s
literature. Second, to address the advantages and the (arguably, dogmatic and colonial)
476
Peter C. Hodgson, Hegel’s Christian Theology: A Reading of the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religions,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2005; and Jon Stewart, Hegel’s Interpretations of the Religions of the
World: The Logic of the Gods, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2018.
269
shortcomings of Hegel’s revisionist response vis-à-vis the dismissivist and the eliminativist
response as well as my Deleuze’s left-wing approach to micro-wars. The third objective
would be to articulate new deviant concepts of God as well as of responsible agent; that is,
new concepts of my own that, perhaps, would be respectively closely connected with this
dissertation’s notions of “will to synthesis” and “artist of micro-wars”; new concepts that
would likewise keep the advantages but avoid the shortcomings of Hegel’s philosophy,
such as its defense of a strong notion of philosophical progress briefly discussed and
problematized throughout the fourth chapter as well as his, arguably, dogmatic and colonial
reading of Pyrrho’s reaction to his others: the aforementioned bare wise persons.
REFERENCES
Abel, Günter. “Consciousness, Language, and Nature: Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Mind and
Nature”, in Manuel Dries (ed.) and P. J. E. Kail (ed.), Nietzsche on Mind and Nature,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2015.
Ahern, Daniel R. Nietzsche as Cultural Physician, Pennsylvania, Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1995.
Alquié, Ferdinand. La Découverte métaphysique de l'homme chez Descartes, Paris, PUF,
1950.
––––––. Nature et vérité dans la philosophie de Spinoza, Les Cours de Sorbonne, Paris,
CDU, 1965.
Akehurst, Thomas L. The Cultural Politics of Analytic Philosophy: Britishness and the
Spectre of Europe, London, Continuum, 2010.
Alcoff, Linda. Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 2006.
Anselm, Saint. Proslogion with A reply on behalf of the fool, trans. M. J. Charlesworth,
with the original Latin text, Indiana, University of Notre Dame Press, 1979.
––––––. Proslogion, trans. Thomas Williams, Indiana, Hackett Publishing, 1995.
Ameriks, Karl. The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2000.
Apel, Karl-Otto. Selected Essays, New Jersey, Humanities Press, 1996.
Aquinas, Saint Thomas of. The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. Fathers
of the English Dominican Province, Indiana, Christian Classics, 1981.
Arendt, Hannah. The Origins of Totalitarianism, New York, Median Book, 1958.
Aristotle, Metaphysics, in Barnes, Jonathan (ed.). Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 2:
The Revised Oxford Translation, trans. W.D. Ross, New Jersey, Princeton University
Press, 1984.
––––––. Metaphysics: Books 1-9, trans. Hugh Tredennick with the original Greek text, MA,
Harvard University Press, 1933.
Assmann, Jan. The Invention of Religion: Faith and Covenant in the Book of Exodus, New
Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2018.
Augustine, Saint. Enchiridion on Faith, Hope, and Love, trans., Albert C. Outler, London,
Aeterna Press, 2014.
270
271
Ayer, A. J. Language, Truth and Logic, London, Dover Publication, 1936.
Blanchot, Maurice. The Space of Literature, Nebraska, University of Nebraska Press, 1989.
Bataille, George. On Nietzsche, New York, Suny Press, 2015.
Baudiou, Alain. Deleuze: The Clamor of Being, trans. Louise Burchill, Minneapolis,
University of Minnesota Press, 1999.
Barnes, Jonathan. “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist”, in Michael Frede and Myles F. Burnyeat
(eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company,
1997.
Block, Ned. “Troubles with Functionalism”, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, volume IX, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1978.
Beauchamp, Tom. “Hume on the Nonhuman Animal”, Journal of Medicine and
Philosophy 24, 1999.
Beaulieu, Alain (ed.); Kazarian, Edward (ed.); and Sushytska, Julia (ed). Deleuze and
Metaphysics, Lanham, Lexington Books, 2014.
Beauvoir, Simone de. The Second Sex, London, Lowe and Brydone, 1953.
Benjamin, Walter. Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings, vol 1: 1913-1926, Cambridge,
Harvard University Press, 1996.
Benovsky, Jiri. Meta-metaphysics: On Metaphysical Equivalence, Primitiveness, and
Theory Choice, Switzerland, Springer International, 2016.
Bergen, Véronique. L’Ontologie de Gilles Deleuze, Paris, Editions L'Harmattan, 2001.
Bernstein, Richard. Violence: Thinking Without Banisters, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2013.
Boonzaier, Emile; Malherbe, Candy; Smith Andy; Berens, Penny. The Cape Herders: A
History of the Khoikhoi of Southern Africa, Ohio, Ohio University Press, 1997.
Bourdieu, Pierre. Escritos de educação, Rio de Janeiro, Vozes, 1998.
Brandon, Robert. Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive
Commitment, MA, Harvard University Press, 1994.
Brogaard, Berit, and Marlow, Kristian. The Superhuman Mind: Free the Genius in Your
Brain, New York, Penguin, 2015.
––––––. “Intuitions as Intellectual Seemings”, in Analytic Philosophy Volume 55, Issue 4
(December 2014): pp. 382–39.
272
Buber, Martin. I and Thou, New York, Touchstone, 1970.
Bueno, Otávio. “Davidson and Skepticism: How not to Respond to the Skeptic”, Principia
9, 2005.
––––––. “Is the Pyrrhonist an Internalist”, in Diego Machuca (ed.), New Essays on Ancient
Pyrrhonism, Leiden, Brill, 2011.
––––––. “Disagreeing with the Pyrrhonist”, in Diego Machuca (ed.), Disagreement and
Skepticism, New York, Routledge, 2013.
––––––. “Carnap, Logicism, and Ontological Commitment”, in Costreie, Sorin (ed.). Early
Analytic Philosophy: New Perspectives on the Tradition, Dordrecht, Springer, 2016.
Bueno, Otávio; and Junqueira Smith, Plínio. “Skepticism in Latin America”, in Edward N.
Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2016;
Bueno, Otávio; and Shalkowski, Scott. “Modalism and Theoretical Virtues: Toward an
Epistemology of Modality”, Philosophical Studies 172, 2015: pp. 671-689.
Burnyeat, Myles F. “Can the Sceptic Live his Scepticism?” in Explorations in Ancient and
Modern Philosophy Vol. 1, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012.
Cappelen, Herman. Philosophy Without Intuitions, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012.
Camp, Elisabeth. “The Generality Constraint and Categorical Restrictions”, Philosophical
Quarterly Vol. 54, No. 215, April 2004: pp. 209-231.
Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus: And Other Essays, New York, First Vintage
International Edition, 1991.
Carnap, Rudolf. “Schema für den 9. Rundbrief”, Unpublished Manuscript (1918),
University of Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: RC 081-22-05.
––––––. “Lectures in Europe (Items 43-54)”, Unpublished Manuscript (1922-1933),
University of Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: RC 110-07-49.
––––––. “Ms.‘Vom Chaos zur Wirklichke’ (mit Notizen zum Konstitution-System”),
Unpublished Manuscript (1921-1926), University of Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific
Philosophy, code: RC 081-05-01.
––––––. “Lectures in Europe (Items 18-29)”, Unpublished Manuscript (1929-37),
University of Pittsburgh, Archive for Scientific Philosophy, code: (RC110-07-21).
––––––. “Überwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache”, Erkenntnis
Vol 2, 1931: pp. 219-241.
––––––. “Theoretische Fragen und praktische Entscheidungen”, Natur und Geist, Dresden
2. Jahrgang Nummer 9, September 1934: pp. 257-260.
––––––. “On the Character of Philosophic Problems”, trans., William M. Malisoff,
Philosophy of Science Vol 1, No. 1, Jan., 1934.
273
––––––. “Les Concepts psychologiques et les concepts physiques sont-ils foncierement
differents?”, trans. Robert Bouvier, Revue de synthese (Paris), t. 10, no. 1, April 1935: pp.
46. My translation.
––––––. Logical Syntax of Language, London, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co Ltd,
1937.
––––––. “Logic” in Factors Determining Human Behavior, Cambridge, Harvard
University Press, 1937.
––––––. “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie Vol
4, 1950: pp. 20-40.
––––––. “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology”, in Meaning and Necessity: A Study of
Semantics and Modal Logic, Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1956.
––––––. Intellectual Autobiography, in Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of
Rudolf Carnap, Illinois, Open Court, 1963.
––––––. “The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language”, A. J.
Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism, trans. A. Pap, New York, The Free Press, 1959.
––––––. The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, trans.,
Rolf A. George, Illinois, Open Court, 2003.
Carnap, Rudolf, Hahn, Hans and Neurath, Otto. “Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der
Wiener Kreis [The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle]”, in Otto
Neurath, Marie Neurath (ed.) and Robert S. Cohen (ed.), Empiricism and Sociology,
Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1973: pp. 306.
Carus, A. W. Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 2007.
Chalmers, David. The Conscious Mind: In search of a Fundamental Theory, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 1996.
––––––. (ed.). Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2002.
––––––. “Ontological Anti-Realism”, in David Chalmers (ed.), David Manley (ed.) and
Ryan Wasserman (ed.), Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009.
––––––. The Character of Consciousness, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2010.
Chang, Ruth. “Incommensurability (and Incomparability)”, in Hugh LaFollette (ed.),
International Encyclopedia of Ethics, New Jersey, Wiley-Blackwell, 2013: pp. 2591-2604.
Chomsky, Noam; and Foucault, Michel. The Chomsky-Foucault Debate: On Human
Nature, New York, The New Press, 2006.
Chudnoff, Elijah. Intuiton, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013.
Churchland, Patricia, Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy, Cambridge, The MIT
Press, 2002.
Churchland, Paul. The Engine of Reason, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1996.
274
Clark, Maudemarie. Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1990.
Clifford, William K. The ethics of belief and other essays, New York, Prometheus Books,
1999.
Cressole, Michel. Deleuze, Paris, Éditions Universitaires, 1973.
Critchley, Simon. Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2001.
Davis, Angela. The Angela Y. Davis Reader, Cambridge, Blackwell Publishers, 1998.
Dawkins, Richard. “Viruses of the Mind”, in Bo Dahlbom (ed.), Dennett and his Critics,
Oxford, Blackwell Publishers, 1993.
Deleuze, Gilles. Nietzsche and Philosophy, New York, Columbia University Press, 1983.
––––––. Kant’s Critical Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam,
London, Athlone Press, 1984.
––––––. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin, NY, Zone Books,
1990.
––––––. Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, trans.
Constantin V. Boundas, New York, Columbia University Press, 1991.
––––––. The fold: Leibniz and the baroque, trans. Tom Conley, Minneapolis, University
of Minnesota Press, 1992.
––––––. “Letter to a Harsh Critic” in Negotiations, 1972-1990, trans. Martin Joughin, New
York, Columbia University, 1995.
––––––. Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, NY, Zone Books,
1998.
––––––. Foucault, trans. Sean Hand, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1998.
––––––. Gilles Deleuze, “Réponses à une Séries de Questions (Novembre 1981)”, in
Villani, Arnaud. La guêpe et l’orchidée: essai sur Gilles Deleuze, Paris, Éditions Belin,
1999.
––––––. Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, trans. Daniel W. Smith, Minneapolis,
University of Minnesota Press, 2005.
––––––. Gilles Deleuze: from A to Z (DVD), trans. Charles Stivale, Cambridge, The MIT
Press, 2011.
Deleuze, Gilles; and Guattari, Félix. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans.
Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and Helen R. Lane, London, The Athlone Press Ltd, 1984.
––––––. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi,
Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1987.
––––––. What is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell, NY,
Columbia University Press, 1994.
275
Deleuze, Gilles; and Grandjouan, Denise Paul “Fanny”. “Nietzsche and Saint Paul,
Lawrence and John of Patmos”, in Essays Critical and Clinical, trans., Daniel W. Smith
and Michael A. Greco, London, Verso, 1998.
Dennett, Daniel. “Conditions of Personhood,” in Rorty, Amélie O. (ed.). The Identities of
Persons, CA: University of California Press, 1976.
––––––. “Quining Qualia” in A. J. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds.), Consciousness in Modern
Science, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1988.
––––––. Consciousness Explained, New York, Little, Brown and Company Press, 1991.
––––––. Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon, New York, Penguin
Books, 2006.
Derrida, Jacques. Writing and Difference, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1978.
––––––. Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles/Eperons: Les Styles de Nietzsche, Chicago, Chicago
University Press, 1979.
––––––. Of spirit: Heidegger and the question, Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1989.
Empiricus, Sextus. Outlines of Skepticism, Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes (eds.),
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Evnine, Simon J. Epistemic Dimensions of Personhood, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
2008.
Fanon, Franz. The Wretched of the Earth, New York, Grove Press, 2004.
Farias, Victor. Heidegger and Nazism, Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 1989.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. The Science of Knowledge, trans., Peter Heath and John Lachs,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Fine, Gail. “Scepticism, Existence, and Belief: A Discussion of R.J. Hankinson, The
Sceptics”, in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Vol 14, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 1996.
Fine, Kit. “Essence and Modality”, in Philosophical Perspectives Vol. 8: 1994: pp.1-16.
––––––. “Guide to Ground”, in Correia, Fabrice (ed.); and Schnieder, Benjamin (ed.).
Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2012.
––––––. “What is Metaphysics?”, in Tahko, Tuomas E. (ed.). Contemporary Aristotelian
Metaphysics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012: pp. 8-25.
Fogelin, Robert J. Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Jutification, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 1994.
Forster, Michael N. Hegel and Skepticism, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1989.
––––––. “Hegelian vs. Kantian Interpretations of Pyrrhonism: Revolution or Reaction?”,
Kritisches Jahrbuch der Philosophie Vol. 10, 2005.
276
––––––. Kant and Skepticism, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2008.
Foucault, Michel. History of Madness, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006.
Frede, Michael. “The Sceptic’s Beliefs”, in Michael Frede and Myles F. Burnyeat (eds.),
The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company, 1997.
Friedman, Michael. Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1999.
––––––. A Parting of the Ways, Illinois, Open Court, 2000.
Gabriel, Gottfried. “Carnap’s ‘Elimination of metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of
Language’: A Retrospective Consideration of the Relationship between Continental and
Analytic Philosophy” in Parrini, Paolo (ed.); Salmon, Wesley C. (ed.); Salmon, Merrilee
H. (ed.). Logical Empiricism: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, Pennsylvania,
University of Pittsburgh Press, 2003.
Gabriel, Markus. Why the World Does Not Exist, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2015.
––––––. I am not a Brain, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2017.
Gueroult, Martial. Descartes’ Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of Reason
Volume 1: The Soul and God; Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984.
––––––. Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of Reason Volume 2: The Soul and
the Body. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985.
Guthrie, W. K. C. The Sophists, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1971: pp. 27.
Gutting, Gary. What Philosophers Know: Case Studies in Recent Analytic Philosophy,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2009.
––––––. Thinking the Impossible: French Philosophy Since 1960, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2011.
Habermas, Jürgen. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures,
Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1990.
Haack, Susan. “Some Preliminaries to Ontology”, Journal of Philosophical Logic Vol. 5,
Issue 4, 1976: pp. 457-474.
Hales, Steven D. “Nietzsche on Logic”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol.
56, No. 4, 1996.
Haslanger, Sally. Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2012.
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. “On the Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy,
Exposition of its Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the
277
Ancient One”, trans. H.S. Harris., in Giovanni, George di (ed.). Between Kant and Hegel:
Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, Cambridge, Hackett Publishing
Company, 2000.
––––––. Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion: Vol 1, 2 and 3, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 2007.
––––––. Lectures on the History of Philosophy Volume II: Greek Philosophy, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2006.
––––––. Lectures on the History of Philosophy 1825-6: Volume I: Introduction and
Oriental Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009.
––––––. Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume III: Medieval and Modern
Philosophy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009.
Heidegger, Martin. “Was ist Metaphysik?”, in Gesamtausgabe: I. Abteilung:
Veröffentlichte Schriften 1914-1970 Band 9 Wegmarken, Frankfurt, Vittorio Klostermann,
1976.
––––––. Nietzsche: Volumes One and Two, New York, Harper Collins, 1991.
––––––. Nietzsche: Volumes Three and Four, New York, Harper Collins, 1991.
––––––. “What is Metaphysics?”, trans. David Farrel Krell, in David Farrel Krell (ed.),
Basic Writings, New York, Harper Collins Publishers, 1993.
Hirsch, Eli. Quantifier Variance and Realism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011.
Hodgson, Peter C. Hegel’s Christian Theology: A Reading of the Lectures on the
Philosophy of Religions, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2005.
Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2007.
Hylton, Peter. Quine, New York, Routledge, 2007,
Imaguire, Guido. “In Defense of Quine’s Ostrich Nominalism”, in Grazer Philosophische
Studien 89, 2014.
––––––. Priority Nominalism: Grounding Ostrich Nominalism as a Solution to the
Problem of Universals, Switzerland, Springer, 2016.
Jackson, Frank. “Epiphenomenal Qualia”, in Chalmers, David (ed.). Philosophy of Mind:
Classical and Contemporary Readings, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2002.
Jameson, Fredric. A Singular Modernity: Essay on the Ontology of the Present, New York,
Verso, 2002.
Junqueira Smith, Plínio. Uma Visão Cética do Mundo: Porchat e a Filosofia, São Paulo,
Editora Unesp, 2017.
Kallen, Horace M. “The Meanings of ‘Unity’ Among the Sciences, Once More”,
Philosophy and Phenomenal Research Vol 6, No 4, June., 1946: pp. 493-496.
278
Kant, Immanuel. Dreams of a Spirit-Seer: Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics, trans.
Emanuel F. Goerwitz, New York, The Macmillan Co, 1900.
––––––. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1998.
––––––. Correspondence, trans. Arnulf Zweig, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1999.
––––––. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics: With Selection from the Critique of Pure
Reason, trans. Gary Hatfield, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Kaufmann, Walter. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, New Jersey,
Princeton University Press, 1950.
Keller, John A. Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from the Philosophy of Peter van
Inwagen, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2017.
King, Martin Luther. A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches, New
York, Harper Collins Publishers, 1986.
Klein, Peter. “How to be an Infinitist about Doxastic Justification”, Philosophical Studies
134.1, 2007.
Klossowski, Pierre. Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle, London, Athlone Press, 1997.
Knobe, Joshua (ed.) and Nichols, Shaun (ed.). Experimental Philosophy: Volume I, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2008.
Kripke, Saul. Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1980.
Laertius, Diogenes. Lives of Eminent Philosophers, ed. James Miller, trans. Pamela
Mensch, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2018.
Lawlor, Leonard. From Violence to Speaking Out: Apocalypse and Expression in Foucault,
Derrida and Deleuze, Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press, 2016.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, Dordrecht, Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 1991.
Lewis, David. Philosophical Papers: Volume I, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1983.
––––––. On the Plurality of Worlds, MA, Blackwell, 1986.
––––––. “Are We Free to Break the Laws?” in Philosophical Papers: Vol. II, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 1986.
MacKinnon, Catherine. Are Women Human?, MA, Harvard University Press, 2006.
279
May, Todd. Between Genealogy and Epistemology: Psychology, Politics, and Knowledge
in the Thought of Michel Foucault, Pennsylvania¸ Pennsylvania State University, 1993.
––––––. Reconsidering Difference: Nancy, Derrida, Levinas, Deleuze, Pennsylvania, Penn
State Press, 1997.
––––––. Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Meillassoux, Quentin. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, London,
Continuum, 2008.
Moore, Adrian W. The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2012.
Moreira, Felipe G. A. Nietzsche como se sem metáfora: mente, corpo, doença e saúde na
obra nietzschiana, Unpublished Master Dissertation, Pontifícia Universidade Católica do
Rio de Janeiro, Rio de Janeiro, 2011.
––––––. Por uma estética do constrangimento, Rio de Janeiro, ed. Oito e Meio, 2013.
––––––. “An Apology of Carnap”, Manuscrito (Unicamp), Vol 37, Número 2, 2014:
pp.261-289.
––––––. “Overcoming Metametaphysics: Nietzsche and Carnap”, Nietzsche-Studien,
Volume 47, Issue 1, Nov. 2018: pp. 240-271.
Mormann, Thomas. “Carnap’s Boundless Ocean of Unlimited Possibilities: Between
Enlightenment and Romanticism”, in Pierre Wagner (ed.), Carnap’s Ideal of Explication
and Naturalism, New York, Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.
Muniz, Fernando. A Potência da Aparência: um estudo sobre o prazer e a sensação nos
Diálogos de Platão, São Paulo, ed. Annablume, 2011.
Müller-Lauter, Wolfgang. Nietzsche: His Philosophy of Contradictions and the
Contradictions of His Philosophy, Illinois, University of Illinois Press, 1999.
Nagel, Thomas. “What is it like to be a Bat?”, Philosophical Review 4, 1974: pp. 435-50.
––––––. “The absurd”, in Mortal Questions, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1979.
––––––. “Dennett: Content and Consciousness” in Other Minds: Critical Essays 19691994, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995.
––––––. “Dennett: Consciousness Dissolved” in Other Minds: Critical Essays 1969-1994,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995.
Nehamas, Alexander. Nietzsche: Life as Literature, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1985.
Neurath, Otto. “Protokollsätze”, Erkenntinis Vol. 3 (1932).
––––––. Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische, Vienna, Hölder-PichlerTempsky, 1981.
280
––––––. “The Orchestration of the Sciences by the Encyclopedism of Logical Empiricism”,
Philosophy and Phenomenal Research Vol 6, No 4, June., 1946: pp. 502. See also Otto
Neurath, Philosophical Papers 1913-1946, Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing Company,
1983.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Nachlass in Colli, Giorgio (ed.) and Montinari, Mazzino (ed.),
Sämtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Bänden, Berlin, de Gruyer, 1967- 1977.
––––––. The Will to Power, trans. W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale, New York, Vintage,
1968.
––––––. Beyond Good and Evil, trans. J. Norman, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
2001.
––––––. The Gay Science, trans. J. Nauckhoff, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
2001.
––––––. The Anti-Christ, trans. J. Norman, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
––––––. Twilight of the Idols, trans. J. Norman, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
2005.
––––––. Ecce Homo, trans. J. Norman, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
––––––. On the Genealogy of Morality, trans. C. Diethe, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2006.
––––––. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, A. Del Caro, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
2006.
Nolan, Daniel. David Lewis, Kingston, McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2005.
––––––. “Hyperintensional metaphysics”, Philosophical Studies, October 2014, Volume
171, Issue 1: pp 149-160.
Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New Jersey, Basic Books, 1974.
––––––. Philosophical Explanations, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1981.
Olaso, Ezequiel de. “La crisis pirrónica de Hume”, Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofía
3(2), 1997: pp. 131-143.
––––––. “Otra vez sobre el escepticismo de Hume”, Manuscrito 1 (1), 1978: pp. 65-82.
––––––. “Los dos escepticismos del vicario saboyano”, Manuscrito, 2(3), 1980: pp. 7–23.
––––––. “Thomas Hobbes y la recta razón”, Manuscrito, 4(1), 1980: pp. 29–35.
––––––. “La investigación y la verdad”, Manuscrito, 6(2), 1983: pp. 45–62.
––––––. “Certeza y escepticismo”, in L. Villoro (ed.), El conocimiento (Enciclopedia
Iberoamericana de Filosofía, Vol. 20), Madrid, Trotta, 1999.
Overgaard, Søren, Gilbert, Paul, and Burwood Stephen, An Introduction to
Metametaphysics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013.
Patton, Paul. “Utopian Political Philosophy: Deleuze and Rawls”, Deleuze Studies, Vol. 1,
Issue 1, 2008.
Peterson, Michael. The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings, Indiana, Notre Dame
University Press, 2017.
281
Pew Research Center’s “The Global Religious Landscape”, published online on 2012 and
(as of March 3rd of 2019) available at: http://www.pewforum.org/2012/12/18/globalreligious-landscape-exec/.
Plantinga, Alvin. God, Freedom, and Evil, New York, Harper and Row, 1974.
Plato. The Republic of Plato (2nd edition), trans., Allan Bloom, New York, Basic Books,
1991.
Plunkett, David. “Conceptual History, Conceptual Ethics, and the Aims of Inquiry: A
Framework for Thinking About the Relevance of the History / Genealogy of Concepts to
Normative Inquiry”, Ergo: Vol 3, no. 2 (2016): pp. 27-64.
Poellner, Peter. Nietzsche and Metaphysics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995.
Popper, Karl. The Open Society and its Enemies: New One Volume Edition, New Jersey,
Princeton University Press, 1994.
Porchat, Oswaldo. Rumo ao Ceticismo, São Paulo, Editora Unesp, 2007.
Price, Huw. “Metaphysics After Carnap: The Ghost Who Walks?”, in David Chalmers
(ed.), David Manley (ed.) and Ryan Wasserman (ed.), Metametaphysics, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2009.
Priest, Graham. Doubt Truth to be a Liar, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006.
Protevi, John. Political Physics: Deleuze, Derrida and the Body Politic, New York, The
Athlone Press, 2001.
Psillos, Stathis. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth, New York, Routledge,
1999.
Putnam, Hillary. “Philosophers and Human Understanding”, in Realism and Reason:
Philosophical Papers Vol 3, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981.
––––––. “Misling” (review of Quine’s Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical
Dictionary). London Review of Books (April 21, 1988).
––––––. Jewish Philosophy as a Guide to Life, Indiana, Indiana University Press, 2008.
Quine, Willard Van Orman. “On what there is”, The Review of Metaphysics Vol. 2. No. 5,
Sep., 1948.
––––––. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, Philosophical Review Vol 60, No 1, Jan 1951: pp.
20-43.
––––––. “Speaking of Objects”. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical
Association, Vol. 31 (1957-1958): pp. 5-22.
––––––. Word and Object, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1960.
––––––. The Time of My Life: An Autobiography, Cambridge, The MIT Press, 1985.
282
––––––. Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary, MA Harvard University
Press, 1987.
––––––. Pursuit of Truth, Cambridge, Harvard University, 1992.
––––––. Quine in Dialogue, MA, Harvard University Press, 2008.
Quine, Willard Van Orman, and Ullian, J.S. The Web of Belief, New York, McGraw-Hill
Education, 1978.
Ratner-Rosenhagen, Jennifer. American Nietzsche: A History of an Icon and His Ideas,
Chicago, Chicago University Press, 2012.
Reck, Erich H. “Carnap and Modern Logic,” in Michael Friedman (ed.) and Richard Creath
(ed.) Cambridge Companion to Carnap, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Reichenbach, Hans. The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, California, University of California
Press, 1951.
Reisch, George A. How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: to the Icy Slopes
of Logic, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Reynolds, Jack (ed.); Chase, James (ed.); Mares, Ed (ed.); and Williams, James (ed.).
Postanalytic and Metacontinental: Crossing Philosophical Divides, London, Continuum
International Publishing Group, 2010.
Richardson, Alan W. Carnap’s Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence
of Logical Empiricism, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1998.
––––––. “Carnapian Pragmatism”, in Michael Friedman (ed.) and Richard Creath (ed.),
Cambridge Companion to Carnap, Cambridge, Cambridge University press, 2007.
Richardson, John. Nietzsche’s System, Oxford, Oxford University Press 1996.
––––––. Nietzsche’s New Darwinism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2004.
Ricketts, Thomas. “Carnap’s principle of tolerance, empiricism, and conventionalism”, in
Bob Hale (ed.) and Peter Clark (ed.), Reading Putnam, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
1994.
Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. “Modal Realism and Metaphysical Nihilism”, Mind, 113
(452), 2004: pp. 683-704.
Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, New Jersey, Princeton University
Press, 1979.
––––––. Contingency, Irony and Solidarity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1989.
Rosen, Gideon. “Modal Fictionalism”, Mind, Vol. 99, No. 395, Jul., 1990: pp. 327-354.
283
Rosenzweig, Franz. The Star of Redemption, Indiana, Notre Dame Press, 1985.
Rovane, Carol. The Bounds of Agency: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics, New Jersey,
Princeton University Press, 1998.
Rowlands, Mark. Can Animals be Persons?, forthcoming.
Rubin, Gayle. Deviations: A Gayle Rubin Reader, North Caroline, Duke University Press,
2011.
Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, New York, Simon & Schuster, 1945.
Sachs, Carl B. “What is to be Overcome? Nietzsche, Carnap, and Modernism as the
Overcoming of Metaphysics”, History of Philosophy Quarterly Vol 28, Issue 3, 2011.
Santayana, George. The Life of Reason, New York, Prometheus Books, 1998.
Schaffer, Jonathan. “Ground Rules: Lessons from Wilson”, in Aizawa, Kenneth (ed.); and
Gillet, Carl (ed.), Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground, London, Palgrave,
2016.
Schmitt, Carl. The Concept of the Political, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1996.
Searle, John. “The Word Turned Upside Down”, The New York Review of Books, October
27th, 1983.
Serano, Julia. Outspoken: A Decade of Transgender Activism and Trans Feminism,
Oakland, Switch Hitter Press, 2016.
Sider, Theodore. Writing the Book of the World, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011.
Slote, Michael. From Enlightenment to Receptivity: Rethinking our Values, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2013.
––––––. “Philosophy’s Dirty Secret: What Virtue Epistemology Needs to Learn about
Human Irrationality”, forthcoming.
––––––. “Philosophical Sin”, forthcoming.
Soames, Scott. Analytic Philosophy in America: And Other Historical and Contemporary
Essays, New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2014.
––––––. The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Volume 1: The Founding Giants, New
Jersey, Princeton University Press, 2014.
––––––. The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Volume 2: A New Vision, New Jersey,
Princeton University Press, 2017.
Sokal, Alan; and Bricmont, Jean. Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals’ Abuse
of Science, NY, Picador, 1998.
284
Souza, Jessé de. A tolice da inteligência brasileira: ou como o país se deixa manipular
pela elite, São Paulo, Leya, 2015.
Stanley, Jason. How Fascism Works: The Politics of Us and Them, New York, Random
House, 2018.
Stewart, Jon. Hegel’s Interpretations of the Religions of the World: The Logic of the
Gods, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2018.
Stone, Abraham D. “Heidegger and Carnap on the Overcoming of Metaphysics”, in
Stephen Mulhall, Martin Heidegger, London, Ashgate Publishing, 2006.
Thomasson, Amie L. Ontology Made Easy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2015.
Uebel, Thomas. “Reconstruction as Elucidation? Carnap in the Early Protocol Sentence
Debate”, Synthese Vol 93, No. 1 / 2, Carnap: A Centenary Reappraisal, Nov., 1992.
––––––. “Political Philosophy of Science in Logical Empiricism: the Left Vienna Circle”,
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36, 2005.
––––––. “On the Production, History, and Aspects of the Reception of the Vienna Circle's
Manifesto”, Perspectives on Science Volume 16, Number 1, Spring 2008: pp. 70-102.
––––––. “Carnap, Philosophy and ‘Politics in its Broadest Sense’”, in Creath, Richard.
Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism, Dordrecht, Springer, 2012.
Van Inwagen Peter, “Freedom to Break the Laws”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXVIII,
2004: pp. 334-350.
––––––. The Problem of Evil, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2006.
West, Cornel. The Cornel West Reader, New York, Basic Civitas Book, 1999.
White, Thomas. In Defense of Dolphins: The New Moral Frontier, MA, Blackwell, 2007.
Wilkes, Kathleen. Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments, Oxford,
Clarendon Press, 1988.
Williams, Bernard. Ethics and the Limits of Inquiry, London, Routledge, 2006.
Williamson, Timothy. The Philosophy of Philosophy, MA, Blackwell, 2007.
Wilson, Jessica M. “Grounding-Based Formulations of Physicalism”, Topoi 37, 2018: pp.
495.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Tractatus-Logico-Philosophicus, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul
Ltd, 1974.
285
Wotling, Patrick. Nietzsche et le problème de la civilisation, Paris, Presses Universitaires
de France, 1995.
X, Malcolm. Malcolm X Speaks: Selected Speeches and Statements, New York, Merit
Publishers and Betty Shabazz, 1965.
Zavarzadeh, Mas’ud. “The Apocalyptic Fact and the Eclipse of Fiction in Recent American
Prose Narratives”, in Journal of American Studies: Vol. 9, No. 1, April, 1975: p.69-83.
Zizek, Slavoj. Organs Without Bodies: Deleuze and Consequences, New York, Routledge,
2004.
––––––. Violence: Six Sideways Reflections, New York, Pecador, 2008.