Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Love
Love and Enhancement Technology
Brian D. Earp
This is the author’s copy of a book chapter published online ahead of print – accepted manuscript
version. The chapter may be cited as follows:
Earp, B. D. (2019). Love and enhancement technology. In C. Grau & A. Smuts (Eds.), Oxford
Handbook of Philosophy of Love. Online ahead of print at
http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199395729.001.0001/oxfordhb9780199395729-e-36
Abstract
Chemical and other interventions into the biological dimensions of love are currently possible
and will likely become more powerful in years to come. This chapter explores some of the
conceptual issues surrounding what it would mean to change love with biochemical agents,
and presents a handful of case studies of individuals and couples who might desire to use
such agents as a way of enhancing their love and relationships. The chapter then discusses a
number of ethical and other worries that would likely be raised by the development or use of
such biotechnologies and offers some tentative responses. Ultimately, it is argued that loveenhancing biotechnology is not just a conceptual possibility, but may already be practically
feasible, and is likely in some cases to be morally desirable.
Keywords:
love enhancement, ethics, biochemical agent, changing love, relationship
Consider a serious, romantic couple. The couple is facing difficulties in their long-term
relationship and is considering whether to break up. They value the relationship, and would
like it to continue, but their feelings of love and desire for each other have faded over the
years. They have tried counseling. It did not work. They went on a couple’s retreat. Their
feelings did not reignite. They opened up the relationship to other partners, but decided this
was not for them. In fact, they tried everything they could think of, and still no flame.
Nevertheless, they sincerely believe, and let us assume with good reason, that the
relationship is, all things considered, worth maintaining. They have a house together, and
children. They have shared goals and commitments. They get along with each other’s
families. There is nothing really wrong with the relationship. It is not violent or abusive.
There are no irreconcilable differences to contend with. It is just that the color has gone from
what was once a vibrant partnership.1
A couple in this situation faces a choice. They can resign themselves to a loveless future,
or they can sacrifice what they have built together over so many years and attempt to start
over with other partners. Or (among other options) they can simply get out of the relationship
business altogether. Such decisions are not easy, and it may often seem that there is no right
answer. But I want to explore whether there may be another way forward. In what follows I
ask whether it could it be prudent for a couple in this or a similar situation to use a loveenhancing biotechnology to keep their relationship intact while attempting to restore love and
happiness within it.
This possibility is starting to receive some attention in the philosophical literature.2 This
is a good thing. As my coauthors and I have argued, it is highly likely that some such
technology will be available in the not-too-distant future. And in fact, some medications can
already affect love, albeit in a haphazard and hard-to-predict way.3 The choice about whether
to use such technology or medicine, then, may soon be a live issue for many couples.
Assuming, of course, that it is not banned or otherwise rendered inaccessible, which is
exactly what some might argue should happen. Indeed, I assume that many people will find
the prospect of biochemical interventions into love and relationships at the very least
unsettling, if not outright frightening and absolutely to be avoided. One of my aims in this
chapter is to make sense of where such reactions might be coming from and to assess the
extent to which they are or can be justified.
One place they might be coming from is a pair of common intuitions about the nature of
love. True love, you might think, is both unchosen and unchanging. In other words, people
cannot just make themselves fall in love: it either happens or it does not. And as Shakespeare
said, love is not love which “alters when it alteration finds.”4 Putting these ideas together, the
thought is that if you are no longer in love with your partner, that is just the way things are
and you need to accept it; and perhaps it was never really love to begin with.
I think this view is mistaken, both descriptively and normatively. While it is true that you
cannot make yourself fall in love, as if by drinking an elixir, you can certainly take informed,
deliberate steps to make it more likely to come into existence and persist through time. Even
without biotechnology, you can do things like spend more time with your partner, increase
the frequency with which you have sex (assuming that is a positive experience for both of
you), focus on their best qualities, try to remove barriers to love that are rooted in past
traumas, and so on.
As for the claim that if you no longer love your partner it must never have been true love
in the first place, this strikes me the kind of thing people say as a post hoc rationalization: a
psychological trick to get over a horrible break-up, perhaps, but not necessarily an accurate
description of reality. Sometimes, that is, we do truly love someone, and then later, truly not.
Hence, true love can change and even go out of existence, or so I assert.
That is the descriptive issue. The normative issue is that if you adopt an
unchosen/unchanging view of love, this may foster a passive or even fatalistic approach to a
potentially valuable romantic relationship that directly contributes to its needless dissolution.
If you think of love as something you simply fall into when you meet the right person, for
example, as many people do think, then it becomes that much easier to fall back out of love
when the going gets tough. Or at least, it becomes that much easier to conceive of what is
happening in your relationship in such terms, thereby concluding that the loss of love is
unpreventable.
An alternative approach would be to take responsibility for your love, in part by putting
in the requisite time and effort to improve the relationship (assuming it is worth preserving).
In other words, there may be value in seeing love as something that is—at least to an
extent—up to us.5 Something that requires choice, skill, and determination, not passivity and
acquiescence. And while we cannot simply wave a magic wand (nor should we necessarily
want to), we can decide whether and how to intervene in the course of love, helping it to last
or, where appropriate, expire.
This is not a new idea, nor should it be controversial. Those who accept that couples
counseling—for instance—can be an appropriate, even praiseworthy, course of action for at
least some romantic partners should be comfortable with the idea that love “takes work.”6
The only real innovation here is to propose that interventions into the psychosocial
dimensions of love (couples counseling and the like) may one day fruitfully be
complemented by interventions into its biological dimensions: hence love-enhancing
biotechnology.7 In support of this proposal, for the rest of this chapter, I attempt to do the
following things:
1. Explain how some currently existing biotechnologies can be understood as already having
significant love-altering capacities, whether in enhancing love or hastening its end. This is to
highlight the urgency of this ethical conversation and to render analogous potential future
technologies more plausible.
2. Put these love-altering effects into a wider philosophical context by discussing a dualnature theory of love, according to which love is fundamentally both biological and
psychosocial in nature (and hence susceptible to being modified along either or both
dimensions).8
3. Give examples of situations where it would likely be morally justified and even prudent to
intervene in love’s biological dimension directly (ideally in conjunction with more
conventional forms of psychosocial intervention).
With respect to the third, I stop short of trying to defend any particular, much less allencompassing, ethical stance about when such biological intervention would be permissible,
prudent, or otherwise. My goal is not to answer such questions, but to raise them. I do,
however, stress their importance and float some ideas for how they might be productively
approached from a bird’s-eye view.
So what kind of biological interventions am I talking about, and how exactly would they
affect the love between romantic partners? I take this question up in the next section.
1. Real-Life Love Potions: A Primer and Proof of
Principle
It is a cliché to point out that love is associated more with the heart (or the soul) than the
brain, and to explain why such a view is naïve. Thus, a great many popular books and even
sober, scientific articles now openly discuss what are sometimes described as the biological
“underpinnings” of romantic love: that is, the brain chemistry, neural architecture, and
genetic foundations of lust, attraction, and longer-term attachment.9 Importantly for our
purposes, some scientists now think that the more we understand this biology, the more we
will be able to influence or even manipulate those variables directly, through biochemical or
other intervention.10 This, in turn, would give us increased control over the higher-level,
experiential aspects of love that are affected by those variables.
Love is not simply reducible to biology or neurochemistry, as I explain in a later section.
But interventions into the biological side of love have not received as much attention as
interventions into its psychosocial side, and it is time to start evening out the scales. This is
because interventions of the former kind are either here or on the horizon, as I have
suggested, and they have the potential to dramatically alter the experience, quality, or even
existence of love between individuals, on any number of plausible accounts of what love is.
To illustrate, I address just one higher-level feature of love that regularly appears at the center
of such accounts, and show how it can be manipulated—fairly directly—through brain-level
biochemical means.
Consider the view that true love, whatever else it is, is something that requires a genuine,
noninstrumental concern for the well-being of the person so beloved.11 If I really love you,
that is, I must be devoted to your ultimate flourishing for its own sake. Necessarily, then, I
must care deeply about your feelings: not only your transient emotional states, but also your
desires and preferences, your wishes and dreams, and your subjective experiences generally,
with all the various meanings they carry.
Well, then, imagine I took a drug that made it so I did not care about your feelings in
some or all of those senses, much less your overall well-being. Or perhaps I do care, but only
in some abstract, “cognitive” sense that does not correspond to the appropriate motivations or
behavior. For example, suppose I can see that you are very upset about something, but your
upset does not strike me as all that important (so long as I am taking this drug). I know it
should affect me. It is not that I think you are pretending. I believe you are genuinely hurt and
have good reason to be (let us say). But for all that, your anguish does not move me.
Does such an awful-sounding drug really exist? Yes, it does. It is called a selective
serotonin reuptake inhibitor, or SSRI—the most commonly used drug to treat depression.
Such SSRIs do not have this effect on everyone. But according to Adam Opbroek and
colleagues,12 a growing pile of case reports suggest that some patients taking SSRIs
experience diminished emotional responsiveness to things that should affect them—like their
partners’ feelings. To explore this issue, Opbroek asked patients reporting SSRI-induced
sexual dysfunction to complete a number of additional questionnaires assessing their
emotions. Compared to controls, the patients reported less ability to cry, experience irritation,
dream erotically, or express creativity. They were also less able to feel surprise, anger, or
sexual pleasure. Less able to worry over things or situations. And, crucially for our purposes,
less able to care about the feelings of others. In fact, fully 80 percent of the patients described
such clinically significant “blunting” of their emotions.
These results are not entirely surprising. Part of the point of SSRIs, at least in their role
as a treatment for depression, is precisely to “blunt” emotions: specifically, a person’s
chronically maladaptive feelings of sadness. But for some patients, the ability to care about
other people’s feelings seems to be blunted as well. What if one of those other people is your
romantic partner? Remember that we are assuming that caring about your partner’s feelings is
one of the bare-bones necessary ingredients of true love. If your very capacity to do so is
sufficiently degraded by an SSRI, then it seems that the drug would be at least largely
responsible for altering—that is, diminishing or interfering with—your higher-level love for
your partner. Change in biology, change in love; proof of principle.
Take another example. Consider the loss of libido that often occurs as a side-effect of
SSRIs.13 How might that affect your relationship? For many couples, sexual interaction is a
very important part of how they relate to each other. Indeed, on some views, the experience
and expression of sexual desire is partly constitutive of romantic relationships—and romantic
love. In other words, wanting to be physically intimate with someone (more than fleetingly or
only under unusual circumstances), at least in the early stages of a relationship, is often seen
the very thing that carves a more or less distinct dividing line between the sort of love you
feel for your romantic partner and the sort of love may you feel for your platonic best
friend—no matter how strong and sincere your feelings of affection for the latter.14
If that sort of view is right, then a drug that removes your desire for sex (or sexual
activity more broadly construed) with your romantic partner is also a drug that changes
something essential about the nature of the love between you. At the extreme end, you might
think that sexual desire is required for romantic love to exist, in which case the drug would
be directly responsible for quelling such love, simply by lowering your libido below some
threshold (i.e., with no other changes being necessary).15 But there are also other ways the
drug could change, if not necessarily eliminate, your love for your partner, by more or less
direct pathways.
Consider the hormone oxytocin. This hormone is released in mothers during the birthing
process and through breastfeeding, and it is largely responsible for the formation and
maintenance of the mother–infant pair-bond—a paradigmatic instance of love and
attachment.16 This same hormone is released through intimate touch, sex, and orgasm; and it
is similarly responsible for the attachment that forms, insofar as it does, between adult
romantic partners. If, therefore, you stop having sex with your partner—due to the effects of
an SSRI, let us say—you will also stop releasing oxytocin together in one of its most potent
contexts, which in turn could negatively affect the attachment bond between you. Again,
insofar as a certain kind or degree of attachment features in one’s account of love (that is, as a
necessary ingredient), this change in biology would amount to a change in love.
So much for drugs that can interfere with love. What about love-enhancing
biotechnology, which is our topic for this chapter? Just run these alterations in reverse.
Oxytocin, for example, can now be administered artificially by way of a nasal spray.17
Testosterone—which can be boosted in various ways—has long been known to increase
libido.18 And MDMA, which was used in the 1980s as an adjunct to couples counseling, can
promote the ability to care about others’ feelings and take their perspective.19 In fact, even
SSRIs can bolster love when their effects are on target and the relationship difficulties stem
from whatever problem they are treating.20 Again, none of these effects in isolation is
necessarily sufficient for creating or augmenting love. But in combination with other
variables and given the right particulars, they may well bring about (or even constitute) the
missing ingredients, thus making love more likely or helping it to last.21
Needless to say, the precise connection between what is going on in someone’s brain as
the result of any particular biochemical intervention and their subjective experiences of
love—much less the nature or quality of love between them and their partner or partners—are
complex and currently only poorly understood. They likely differ from person to person and
couple to couple. Moreover, different doses, timings, contexts, and interactions between
neurochemical processes add further variability. But none of this detracts from the main point
of this section, which is simply that there is reason to believe that existing biotechnologies
are already capable of altering love, both positively and negatively, through a number of
different routes. Assuming that our understanding of the functional make-up of the brain—
and of the neurochemical means by which it can be influenced—continues to advance in this
area, we may soon face the prospect of even more powerful biotechnologies whose effects
can be better predicted or made more precise. To understand the implications of this potential
development for the modification of love, it will be useful to have a more fleshed-out theory
of what love is. I turn to that next.
2. A Dual-Nature Theory of Love
In this section I overview arguments suggesting that love has a dual nature, based primarily
on the recent articulation and defense of this idea by Carrie Jenkins.22 In a nutshell, the dualnature of theory of love holds that love is neither a purely biological or neurochemical
phenomenon, on the one hand, nor a purely psychosocial construction, on the other. Rather, it
is constituted by both dimensions. To convey what this means in more concrete terms, I shall
quickly summarize the “biological” dimension, since it builds on what we learned in the
previous section, and then circle back to the psychosocial side of love.
In rough outline, the science goes like this.23 Underlying romantic love is a set of
overlapping yet functionally distinct brain systems that evolved to suit the reproductive needs
of our ancestors. These go by various names, but a common typology distinguishes between
lust, attraction, and attachment. Lust or libido’s role—as assigned by natural selection—is to
inspire interest in a range of potential mating partners. The attraction system then narrows our
focus down to a smaller number of partners, often one in particular. And the attachment
system supports the formation of a long-term pair-bond, which is thought to have been
adaptive for child rearing in the ancestral environment.
Different brain chemicals regulate these quasi-independent systems, including
testosterone, oxytocin, dopamine, and many others, and their characteristic patterns of action
and reaction largely govern our interpersonal drives and emotions. According to some
theorists, these brain chemicals and the neural pathways along which they travel form the
universal building blocks of romantic love, which are then reflected in and shaped by various
cultural and historical factors across time and geography.
So, although there is considerable variation in both subjective experiences and
conceptions of love from person to person, between cultures, and over time, the thought is
that the same basic biological “machinery” is under the hood. And by tinkering with this
machinery through the application of biotechnologies, my coauthors and I have suggested, it
will soon be possible to strongly influence those aspects of love that manifest, as it were,
above the hood.24
Car analogies should be used sparingly, but let me run with this one a little further.
Obviously, the way a car operates, including how and where it moves through space, is
shaped not just by internal mechanical factors—corresponding to the biological or
neurochemical dimensions of love—but also by external factors such as the decisions of the
driver, the movement of pedestrians, the commands of traffic signals, and even completely
arbitrary conventions for coordinating behavior, like which side of the road one is supposed
to drive on. So, too, is the course and character of love constrained, and, on Jenkins’s
account, even partially constituted, by a complex tapestry of external forces flowing from
society in a given historical context and interacting with individual psychology and behavior.
Those forces, too, can be modified in various ways.
If this account is right, then it should be possible to change love, or make it more or less
likely to come about or endure, without any fancy technologies (as I hinted at earlier).
Changing behavior or circumstances, for example, like breaking off contact with a lover and
starting to see someone else, is an obvious way to try to fade love out and (perhaps) fade a
new love in. But wider social norms, expectations, and concepts about love can also change,
and this may affect what actually counts as love in a given society as we will see in a
moment. So sociocultural and behavioral factors must not be ignored.
As Lisa Diamond argues, “Calling attention to the biological substrates of love and
desire [does not] imply that biological factors are more important than cultural factors in
shaping these experiences. On the contrary, research across many disciplines has shown that
human experiences of sexual arousal and romantic love are always mediated by social,
cultural, and interpersonal contexts, and ignoring these contexts produces a distorted account
of human experience.”25
At the same time, however, “ignoring the biological underpinnings of human behavior
produces a similarly distorted account . . . human sexual and affectional experiences are
neither ‘mainly cultural’ nor ‘mainly biological’ but must always be understood as products
of powerful interactions between biological and social factors.” 26 In short, love has a dual
nature. It is both biological and psychosocial.
To see this dual nature in action, consider the example from Jenkins of a lesbian couple
in nineteenth-century England.27 Biologically, she tells us, they are in love: the brain systems
for lust, attraction, and romantic attachment are all firing away; the couple is experiencing the
rush of adrenaline, the high of serotonin and dopamine, the pull of oxytocin, and so on. But
given their historical context, the norms surrounding love and the available social scripts for
them to follow are highly restricted. They cannot get married. They cannot publicly express
their affection without putting themselves at risk. They cannot raise children together, and so
on. In short, the biological dimension of their love is disabled from manifesting in the social
sphere as it would for a heterosexual couple.
In fact, their feelings for one another—as passionate and sincere and deeply rooted as
they are—might not even be recognized as a true form of love by members of the wider
society. This lack of recognition, in turn, could shape how they conceive of their own
relationship, interpret their own emotions, behave even when they are alone, and so on, all of
which might affect what is happening biochemically between them. Feeling shame, for
instance, can interfere with sexual desire or inhibit its expression, which can decrease
testosterone levels and curb the release of oxytocin, which can erode attachment, which can
affect behavior, and round it goes. Simply put, historically contingent norms and expectations
drastically limit their ability to engage in, and have others recognize, the psychosocial aspects
of the biological machinery that is normally associated with romantic love.28
3. Intervening in Love’s Two Natures
Things have improved for lesbian couples in many countries since the late nineteenth
century. The social script for love—to repeat that metaphor—has in several respects
dramatically changed. Political debates, philosophical argument, appeals to people’s sense of
common decency and shared humanity; plays, books, movies, and television shows
presenting alternative visions of gay and lesbian relationships: all of this has combined to
make same-sex love a coherent concept with wide recognition. This, in turn, has
ramifications for the felt and enacted experiences of love between same-sex partners: less
shame and repression, perhaps; greater participation in dominant cultural practices like
marriage, and so on.
So the psychosocial side of love can evidently change in response to concerted
interventions. Moreover, it can do so in a way that many people—including this author—see
as morally good. What about the biological side of love?
Suddenly, things grind to a halt. There is an immediate sense of danger here, and rightly
so. When the social script is held constant, and the biological “actor” cannot seem to pull off
the role they have been assigned, societies have often tried to coercively modify the
individual performer so that nothing upsets the production of the play.
I am thinking here of sexual orientation conversion efforts (SOCEs), many of which
have been biologically based.29 I have written at length about SOCEs elsewhere.30 There are
also chastity belts, genital mutilations intended curb sexual desire,31 teaching children they
will go to hell if they masturbate, punishing people for falling in love with the supposedly
wrong person, and other such destructive interventions. History is full of examples of
oppressive societies trying to retrain recalcitrant actors, often in vain, in an attempt to force
them into ill-suited roles. There are also many examples still today.
So perhaps we should conclude that the biological actor is right, at least most of the time,
and if there is a mismatch of some sort, it is the social script that should be expected to
change. I have defended something like this view before, calling it the “Principle of Default
Natural Ethics.”32 All else being equal, I argued, we should adopt social scripts—institutions,
norms, and so on—that are maximally consistent with our biological natures: for example,
our sexual orientations. The reason for this is that it helps us to avoid certain harmful effects
of misguided prohibitions and repression, whether enforced through law or custom, on
individual and societal well-being. As Erich Fromm argued in Man for Himself: An Inquiry
into the Psychology of Ethics:
If man were infinitely malleable then . . . norms and institutions unfavorable to
human welfare would have a chance to mold man forever into their patterns
without the possibility that intrinsic forces in man’s nature would be mobilized
and tend to change these patterns. Man would be only the puppet of social
arrangements and not—as he has proved to be in history—an agent whose
intrinsic properties react strenuously against the powerful pressure of
unfavorable social and cultural patterns. In fact if man were nothing but the
reflex of culture patterns no social order could be criticized or judged from the
standpoint of man’s welfare since there would be no concept of “man.”33
Sexual repression is a case in point.34 It has been argued that Puritanical sexual attitudes in
the United States, coupled with abstinence-only sex education policies, have led to such
backfiring ills as higher teen pregnancy rates and increased transmission of sexually
transmitted infections among American religious youths.35 Some researchers have drawn a
straight line from sexual repression and denial of bodily pleasure to seemingly unrelated acts
of violence.36 And the unspeakable scandal of child sex abuse in the Catholic Church has
been linked, in part, to norms of celibacy in the priesthood.37 This does not absolve anyone of
responsibility for their actions. But it does force us to ask whether widespread standards of
sexual repression do more harm than good.
It is only when biology-consistent norms about human behavior lead to harm or violate
other moral standards, like justice, that laissez faire policies should be reconsidered. Then,
the costs and benefits of different forms of social regulation can be tallied up. Consider the
example of forced sex, which in humans is a form of rape (some forms of rape do not involve
physical force, which is why I am drawing this distinction). Some theorists have
characterized such behavior as being ultimately rooted in biology, in the sense that it appears
to exist in our primate relatives and may have been a way for low-status ancestral human
males to pass on their genes despite not being able to find a willing mate.38 Rape is, in some
sense, “natural” according to this view.
This view is controversial, not just politically but also scientifically: the evidence raised
in support of it has been sharply criticized.39 (Among other problems, it shifts attention away
from sociocultural norms and structures that tend to be permissive of male violence in human
societies,40 when these are central to understanding the more immediate causes of rape in the
contemporary world.) The point I am making is more conceptual. It is that even if rape could
be meaningfully explained in terms of biological factors (in addition to social, psychological,
and cultural ones), this could never ethically justify rape. Rape is wrong not because it is
natural or unnatural, biological or social, or motived by a desire for sex or power. It is wrong
because it is a gross violation of another’s sexual autonomy and bodily integrity, and often
causes grievous harm.41 Therefore, we should condemn sexual assault in all its forms, punish
it as severely as the law (and human decency) allows, and try to prevent it from happening
whenever we can.
In a similar vein, some scientists believe that pedophilia—that is, primary erotic interest
in pubescent or prepubescent children—is at least partially explained by biological factors:
stable, internal factors present at birth that are not something a person can choose. Much like
a sexual orientation, in fact.42 So, for example, the finding that males with pedophilia are
more likely to be left-handed and have low IQs “suggests that pedophilia may [be] causally
related to neurodevelopment. It is possible, in other words, that associations exist among
pedophilia, left-handedness, and poor cognitive functioning, because neurodevelopmental
problems during prenatal life dispose a male to develop all three.” 43
This perspective, too, is controversial. But let us just assume for the sake of argument
that such findings turn out to be widely replicated,44 and that pedophilia even comes to be
seen as a sexual orientation (albeit one based on age or physical development rather than sex
or gender). Would this suggest that we should rewrite the social script condemning sexual
contact with children—that is, acting on a pedophilic orientation—so that those with
pedophilia can more easily express this part of their biological nature? Far from it. Although
we should not necessarily stigmatize those who have, but do not act on, such desires
(assuming that the desires themselves are unchosen), we should certainly uphold the strongest
possible norms against sexual abuse of children. Moreover, if a person with pedophilia
volunteers to have their biology changed—through the ingestion of testosterone-blockers, for
instance—in an effort to curb their risky sexual desires, some would argue that they should
be commended.45
The naturalistic fallacy is one of the oldest and most famous mistakes in ethics. It
involves drawing conclusions about what should be the case, or what should be done, directly
from descriptive statements about how things are, such as what our natural or biological
dispositions happen to be.46 But something’s being natural or biological does not, by itself,
logically, morally, or in any other way entail that it is good or desirable. 47 Cancer is natural
but bad. Modern medicine is unnatural but good. Naturalness and moral status can come
apart.
Now consider a very different example: people with transgender identities. Roughly
speaking, a transgender person is someone whose gender identity (such as man, woman, or
genderqueer)48 does not align with the gender role that was assigned to them at birth, usually
based on their external reproductive characteristics (like whether they have a penis or
vulva).49 This experience of misalignment, which often has both biological and social
components, can be profoundly distressing, and something has to give.
Part of the problem is that the dominant social norms surrounding gender are so binary
and restrictive. According to these norms, if you are an adult, you are either a man (who must
look, dress, and behave in particular ways) or a woman (who must look, dress, and behave in
other ways), or face the consequences. In a perfect world, these norms would be softened and
expanded and in general made much more fluid. We should all try to make that happen. But
in the meantime, many people, transgender or otherwise, feel that they have to conform to
one binary role or another, sometimes just to get by. They may even face violence for failing
to do so.50
In order to simply survive in the world, or in some cases, to manifest their gender
identity in a way that is most authentic for them (irrespective of social stigma), changing
biological features through hormone treatments51 or surgeries is the best option for some
transgender individuals.52 And these individuals may justifiably pursue such means even as
they work with others to rewrite the constricting social scripts that are currently available for
enacting gender.53
What this last example shows is that, even if you think the social script is bad—in this
case, because its gender roles are too narrow and restrictive—it does not automatically follow
that the biological aspects of the person or phenomenon must at all costs remain untouched.
Certainly, no person should be forced to undergo a biological modification, at least in most
cases (the moral bioenhancement of violent psychopaths has been proposed as an exception),
54
but some individuals might reasonably decide to modify aspects of their own biology, and
be well within their rights to do so, even if the social script has certain flaws.
The same general idea, I suggest, applies to love and relationships. As we saw in the
previous section, love has both biological and psychosocial aspects, and it can be modified
along either or both dimension(s). There may be inherent biological obstacles to the success
of especially long-term romantic partnerships in modern societies, due to various tensions
that can arise between the building blocks for love (lust, attraction, and attachment) and the
way these variables manifest in a given sociohistorical context. In short, the underlying
machinery for love did not evolve to promote happy, meaningful relationships in the
contemporary world, but rather the survival of offspring in the world of our ancestors.55 To
see how this can create difficulties for romantic partnerships of different kinds in the world of
today, I turn to some examples.
4. Human Natures
Consider a monogamous couple. Let us assume that they are married. In other words, as a
part of their wedding vows, they agreed to be sexually exclusive with each other so long as
their marriage lasts. Indeed, most couples who get married do make such a promise: it is a
largely taken-for-granted feature of the prevailing social script for long-term relationships in
Western (and many other) societies. It is also a promise that is often broken, leading to great
suffering in many cases. There is an obvious tension here, and if we are concerned about
human welfare, something must be done to relieve it.
So what should change? The social script that favors monogamy? Or the drive to have
sex with more than one person, notwithstanding a long-term partnership? This is a false
dichotomy, of course, and that is part of my point, but it gives us a place to start.
We can take the social script issue first. Based on our discussion in the previous section,
the default position—which can be overridden as necessary—should be to adopt social
scripts, including relationship norms, that are in line with those aspects of human biology that
do not respond well to cultural suppression (in the sense spelled out by Erich Fromm).
According to this perspective, the answer to the question about whether the social script
should change depends, in part, on facts about human biology as they bear on sexual
exclusivity.
Unsurprisingly, there is disagreement among scientists about those facts. Certainly,
humans as a species are generally disposed, biologically speaking, to form a long-term pairbond with at least one primary partner, with whom they will often raise offspring together.
But very few species in the wider animal kingdom, including our closest primate relatives,
are completely sexually monogamous. From an evolutionary perspective, such stringent
fidelity tends not to maximize reproductive success, and so is unlikely to survive as a
dominant mating strategy. Humans are no exception. Quite a lot of sex occurs in our species
outside of the primary pair-bond—I do not need to cite evidence for this, it is so
widespread—and this is true even in societies where such behavior is strongly condemned
and heavily policed.56
This fact has led some researchers to argue that claims of “natural monogamy” for our
species are no more than conservative propaganda: desperate attempts to justify (by
commission of the naturalistic fallacy) outdated and oppressive cultural norms. The sex
researchers Christopher Ryan and Cacilda Jethá are well known for advancing such a view.
“Like bonobos and chimps,” they write, “we are the randy descendants of hypersexual
ancestors.” Accordingly:
Conventional notions of monogamous, till-death-do-us-part marriage strain
under the dead weight of a false narrative that insists we’re something else.
[The] campaign to obscure the true nature of our species’ sexuality leaves half
our marriages collapsing under an unstoppable tide of swirling sexual
frustration, libido-killing boredom, impulsive betrayal, dysfunction, confusion,
and shame.57
If Ryan and Jethá are right, the prevailing social script that valorizes monogamy should
indeed be revised. But not everyone is on board with this broad-brush picture of human
nature (including other leading sex researchers).58 According to Carrie Jenkins, it is almost as
though the traditional moralists—the ones who claim that human beings are primarily
sexually monogamous by nature and that they should follow the corresponding social norm—
have asserted that “blue is the natural eye color for humans, and then Ryan and Jethá, noting
that a lot of humans have green eyes, [counter] that green is the natural eye color for
humans.” But this is to make the same essentializing mistake the other way around. For many
people, as Jenkins observes, “monogamy really doesn’t seem to be a terrible struggle. They
say it feels perfectly ‘natural’ and delightful and right.”59
Others feel exactly the opposite—hence the “unstoppable tide of swirling sexual
frustration.” Humans are not uniform. So although it can be maddeningly hard to distinguish
what is “natural” for our species from deep-seated cultural expectations, even if those
expectations could somehow be magically filtered out, we would still find a lot of individual
variance down at the level of “pure” biology.
To put this another way: just as some people may be “wired up” to be attracted to
partners of the same sex or gender (I realize this is a gross oversimplification; also please
forgive the electronics metaphor),60 other people may be “wired up” to feel attracted to, and
desire a physical and emotional relationship with, more than one person at a time. The exact
percentage of humans this description applies to is not clear, and I am not really sure it
matters from a moral perspective. If homosexuality is “natural” for some people—meaning
something like, most consistent with a person’s innermost, unchosen, most stable, hard-toignore preferences and desires—then polyamory is probably natural for some people, too,
just as heterosexuality and/or monogamy are natural for others.61
What this suggests is that the social script for love should allow for a range of different
relationship norms, so that people can figure out what is right for them, and be socially
supported in their decision. In other words, even if there is a single, underlying human nature
that applies to the vast majority of our species, this does not entail that there should be a
single set of social norms to which everyone must conform. In fact, recent research suggests
that consensually nonmonogamous relationships can be just as functional and conducive to
happiness as consensually monogamous relationships, notwithstanding greater stigma toward
the former.62
5. Resolving Tensions
Let me take stock of where are. Depending on one’s nature (in the sense I sketched in the
previous section), the prevailing relationship norms in one’s society, and one’s own
considered beliefs and values, various sources of tension can arise among these and related
factors. I have suggested that the ideal social script would allow for a range of relationship
norms (so long as these as these are not unjust, harmful, and so on) so that people can choose
the one that works best for them. In that way, they can minimize the tensions alluded to
previously without having to modify various aspects of their biology that may be difficult or
risky to change. But even when there is room for such choice, this does not make for an easy
decision. Nor does it rule out the potential usefulness of a biological intervention. I consider
these last two points in turn.
First, to see some of the difficulty involved in deciding what norm(s) to adopt, consider
again the example of monogamy. According to Bryan R. Weaver and Fiona Woollard,
adopting this norm in a given relationship can be good or valuable when it is motivated by a
reasonable belief that doing so will fulfill the emotional and sexual needs of both partners. 63
In other words: when sacrificing other sexual opportunities—for the sake of the
relationship—is likely to promote the overall welfare and happiness of both. But they also
argue that monogamy can be disvaluable when it is motivated by jealousy, insecurity, or a
desire for control.
By the same token, rejection of monogamy can be valuable when it demonstrates
maturity and a well-grounded belief that the partnership is strong enough flourish even as the
partners see other people. And rejection of monogamy can be disvaluable when the motive is
selfish, or based in an attempt to avoid working together as partners to address whatever
sexual or other needs may be going unfulfilled.
Let us suppose that you do reject monogamy. Suppose you have carefully reflected on
the sorts of considerations raised by Weaver and Woolard, and based upon a deep reflection
about your innermost “nature” (in my sense) you have decided to foreground a commitment
to nonpossessiveness, sexual freedom, openness, and generosity about love in your
constellation of values. Does this mean that you are now immune from the sorts of tensions
we discussed in the previous section? Or that there is no potential role for a biological
intervention? By no means. Chances are, in this day and age, that at least one source of
tension for you is the existence of negative judgments from (some) members of the
surrounding culture who, mistakenly in your view, see polyamory as inherently sinful,
selfish, or unsustainable.64
One way to address this tension would be to try to contest those negative judgments:
difficult to do on your own, but if enough polyamorists come out of the closet and take a
stand for their relationship values, they might make good progress on rewriting the social
script. The gay rights movement, again, provides a model. Other sources of tension could be
internal, however. Maybe you struggle to control your jealousy, despite firmly believing that
this emotion is not a reliable guide to moral judgments or good behavior.65
It may be instructive to dwell on this example. Jealousy has deep evolutionary roots.
Most scientists think that it was an adaptive solution to the problem of paternity uncertainty
in ancestral males and resource insecurity in ancestral females (the details are interesting, but
they go beyond the scope of this chapter).66 In other words, they think that the capacity to feel
intensely jealous, especially when faced with a perceived sexual rival, is an ingrained feature
of your—and indeed most people’s—biological “actor.”
Could a biological antijealousy modification help you meet your relationship goals?
Something to supplement the more conventional methods of stamping out (unproductive)
jealousy you might already be using? Consider the following real-life case study—of a
monogamous couple rather than a polyamorous one, but the principle remains the same:
A 54-year-old male manager of an antique shop presented himself [to a
psychiatrist] with a 4-week complaint of “depression” . . . He volunteered two
causes, a council election with one party’s policies being a threat to his business,
and recent marital dysfunction.67
The “marital dysfunction” part is the one I am interested in:
Marital difficulties followed his stated wish to make contact with a former
girlfriend, with whom there had been no contact for 30 years. His wife agreed
pleasantly, however, a week later, asked if she could make contact with her old
boyfriend. The patient progressively developed a set of anxiety symptoms
including panic attacks, and depersonalization experiences. He began to harass
his wife, initially about her motivation for re-establishing contact, and later
pursuing all details of her original relationship with the man, questioning and
haranguing her for hours. He accepted referral when his wife stated that his
behavior threatened their 20-year-long happy marriage and that, if it persisted,
she would leave him.68
The man’s psychiatrist dug deeper.
Personality review suggested a man with a distinct obsessional personality:
always on time for appointments, preoccupied with order and efficiency,
extremely well organized, a meticulous checker of minor and major issues,
perfectionistic, productivity-focused, scrupulous about morality and ethics, and
distinctly conscientious. Symptom review indicated long-standing mild anxiety.
A diagnosis of anxiety state with secondary depression was made initially, and
he was prescribed alprazolam [Xanax] for a brief interval to reduce his anxiety.
At the third consultation, the possibility of OCD [obsessive-compulsive
disorder] was considered.69
Indeed, intense jealousy is a lot like OCD: fixation on tiny details, compulsive thinking,
intrusive and unwanted thoughts, persisting in repetitive behavior despite clear signs it is not
helping anything, and may very well be making things worse. Perhaps the two phenomena
have more in common than we realize. The psychiatrist Paul E. Mullen has pointed out that
“checking,” an obsessive behavior associated with OCD, also occurs in people who
experience jealousy: “an almost universal behavior among the jealous [is] checking that the
lover is where they say they are and with whom they say, cross checking, re-checking (with
frequent) inquisitorial cross-questioning of the lover.”70
Following this line of thinking, the man’s psychiatrist changed the course of medication
to clomipramine, sold under the brand name Anafranil, a common treatment for OCD. After
six days of taking the drug, the antique shop manager “stated that he felt less anxious . . . and
that his jealousy (subjective feeling and associated behavioral actions) had eased
considerably.” A specialized program of “exposure therapy, response prevention and
cognitive restructuring,” was then started; four weeks later, the man “reported that the
original concerns were no longer relevant.”71 Marriage saved.
Part of what is interesting about this case is that jealousy is not usually seen as being a
mental disorder that is amenable to being treated with medicine. In fact, this man was not
diagnosed with jealousy, as such, but was rather treated, in the words of his psychiatrist, “as
if he had an obsessive-compulsive disorder.”72 Emphasis on “as if.” What this goes to show is
that it may not be necessary to pathologize, that is, conceptualize as a disease state, so-called
ordinary human experiences, in order to recognize that sometimes our romantic biology pulls
on our conscious thinking and behavior in ways that we do not want and did not ask for, and
that pose a threat to our and our partners’ well-being.
Moreover, as we just saw, sometimes biological interventions—especially when
combined with appropriate psychosocial approaches—can help to eliminate that threat,
whether we want to call it medicine or not.
That last example was brought up in a discussion of polyamory, where jealousy of any
kind is often seen as conflicting with the partners’ highest values. But suppose you are in a
monogamous relationship, like the couple we started with. Maybe you and your partner
genuinely believe that monogamy is the right way to go, all things considered: it is the closest
fit between your natures, your social and cultural environment, and your mutual goals and
values. In this case, instead of trying to tamp down jealousy about your partner’s other
partner(s), perhaps it is your own wandering eye that is standing between you and the
happiest version of your committed relationship. Could science, one day, help the biological
“actor” in you do a better job of following the social script you actively endorse and agreed to
follow?
Imagine this scenario. You and your partner are deeply in love. You are truly committed
to each other, and you make each other happy in just about every way. But there is one thing
gnawing at you—one persistent problem that you just cannot seem to shake no matter what
you do. Your sex drive is much stronger than that of your partner. You desire sex most of the
time, at least once a day, while your partner is more of an every-other-week type, give or
take. This asymmetry causes friction, despite your best attempts to dance around it.
Your partner starts to feel guilty, even though you have promised it is not their fault. You
start to feel resentful and unfulfilled, even though you try to push those feelings away.
There is nothing wrong with either of you. You just have different sexual needs—
something that applies to many long-term relationships. Maybe you even started out with
similar levels of desire, and things shifted for one or both of you over time. There is nothing
necessarily pathological about that, either.
Now you have a life together. A house, kids, mutual friends. Neither of you wants to
give this up. Your partner is “perfect” for you in every other way. You know sex is not
everything. You know that good relationships require sacrifice, and you are willing to do
whatever it takes. But still you find yourself fantasizing about sex with others, and you fear
you will act against your values at some point if something does not change.
Now let us further imagine that you and your partner have great communication. You
have been honest. You each know how the other feels. You have gone to a relationship
counselor together and tried various exercises to sync up your sexual drives. It does not work.
You have even talked about opening up your relationship (that is, allowing for sex outside the
relationship, with certain rules and restrictions to keep things secure), but, like the couple
from the start of this chapter, you both conclude, after much consideration, that it would
cause more trouble than it is worth.
You seem to be facing a horrible choice. Either end a relationship that means the world
to you, ignore or suppress your sexual desires, or cheat on your partner in a moment of
weakness.73 What do you do?
Let us add one more detail to this story. Suppose you are taking some medication,
prescribed by your doctor, for anxiety and mild depression—buproprion, let us say
(commonly sold as Wellbutrin). Unlike many antidepressant medications, Buproprion is not
an SSRI, but is rather an NDRI (norepinephrine-dopamine reuptake inhibitor), and it has
fewer sexual side-effects, like loss of libido.74 According to one study, subjects treated with
SSRI-based medications, compared to buproprion, experienced “significantly decreased
libido, arousal, duration of orgasm, and intensity of orgasm” below levels experienced before
treatment.75
The next time you see your doctor, you decide to ask about switching from an NDRI to
an SSRI, knowing full well that this might lower your libido. Assuming that the latter is an
equally valid treatment for your anxiety and depression, suppose that your doctor agrees. You
switch medications and you find that your desire for sex becomes more subdued. Your
fantasies about sex with others become less frequent. The friction in your relationship begins
to subside. Once again we have a case where biochemical intervention could be seen as
effectively resolving a source of serious tension between biology, norms, and values.
6. Analysis and Concluding Thoughts
I designed that case to be intuitively sensible. You are supposed to think it would be
justifiable, perhaps even praiseworthy, to switch your medication in order to save your
relationship and adhere to your values. If you do think that, then I have cleared a low bar: it
can sometimes be appropriate to intervene in love’s biological side to help a couple achieve
their relationship goals.
You might not agree with that perspective, however. You might think that you should
not turn to medication, no matter what the cost to you or your family, to resolve such tensions
in your romantic relationship. Now, let me remind you that you were already taking
medication in this scenario, and that other strategies had been tried in good faith and were not
working. Even so, you might say, that is just something you will have to deal with: you
should only change your medication if it is to address a “medical” problem, and desiring
more sex than your partner is not a medical problem.
True enough—it is not. There is nothing medically wrong with you if you happen to
desire a lot of sex (just as there is nothing medically wrong with you if you happen to feel
jealous about your wife’s ex-boyfriend—within reason). In many cases, trying to find a
partner with a similar sex drive, or one who is open to nonmonogamy, will be the best way
for you to secure a happy relationship. Maybe even breaking up with your current partner—
getting a divorce, splitting up the kids, moving to another part of town and starting over—is
the price to pay for being true to “who you are.”
Or maybe you should stay in the relationship, and try to convince your partner to
reconsider your promise of monogamy; or else bury that part of “who you are” underground.
There is no one right way to proceed. The most justifiable course of action will depend
on the details, and different couples will find that different solutions are (all things
considered) best for them. It would be strange indeed if everyone had the same needs and
values. Accordingly, there will never be a one-size fits-all resolution to the various tensions
that can arise in romantic partnerships. But the best decision will be one that takes seriously
the available options and weighs them against each other without prejudging the conclusion.
As my coauthor on much of this work—Julian Savulescu—has argued, how well our
lives go is largely determined by four major factors: natural environment, social environment,
psychology, and biology.76 Each of these can typically be modified in a number of different
ways. Absent a clear overriding reason not to, we should at least consider the full range of
potential modifications, and then choose the modification, or combination of modifications,
that is likeliest to be best or most effective at improving our lives.
There may be very good reasons to prefer psychosocial interventions over biological
interventions in trying to improve various facets of our lives, including our relationships. For
instance, such interventions might be safer, more likely to be successful, or more fair or just
(based on limited resources, for example). But we should not just dismiss biological
interventions from the start.77 Indeed, in some cases it may be the biological interventions
that are safer, more likely to be successful, and demanded by justice. Since love is
fundamentally both biological and psychosocial, I have argued, we should at least consider
intervening along both dimensions if we want love and happiness to coincide in our
relationships.
Bibliography
Aas, Sean, and Candice Delmas. “The Ethics of Sexual Reorientation: What Should
Clinicians and Researchers Do?” Journal of Medical Ethics 42, no. 6 (2016): 340–347.
https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103562.
Aas, Sean, and Candice Delmas. “Sexual Reorientation in Ideal and Non-Ideal Theory.”
Journal of Political Philosophy 26, no. 4 (2018): 463-485.
Arrell, Robbie. “Should We Biochemically Enhance Sexual Fidelity?” Royal Institute of
Philosophy Supplements 83 (2018): 389–414.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246118000462.
Baccarini, Elvio, and Luca Malatesti. “The Moral Bioenhancement of Psychopaths.”
Journal of Medical Ethics 43, no. 10 (2017): 697–701. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics2016-103537.
Bamford, Rebecca. “Unrequited: Neurochemical Enhancement of Love.” Cambridge
Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3 (2015): 355–360.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000668.
Diamond, Lisa M. “What Does Sexual Orientation Orient? A Biobehavioral Model
Distinguishing Romantic Love and Sexual Desire.” Psychological Review 110, no. 1
(2003): 173–92. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.173.
Earp, Brian D. “Love and Other Drugs.” Philosophy Now 91 (2012): 14–17.
Earp, Brian D. “Can You Be Gay by Choice?” In Philosophers Take on the World, edited
by David Edmonds, 95–98. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Earp, Brian D. “Psychedelic Moral Enhancement.” Royal Institute of Philosophy
Supplement 83, no. 1 (2018): 415–439.
Earp, Brian D., Thomas Douglas, and Julian Savulescu. “Moral Neuroenhancement.” In
Routledge Handbook of Neuroethics, edited by Sid M. Johnson and Karen S.
Rommelfanger, 166–184. Abingdon: Routledge, 2017.
Earp, Brian D., Bennett Foddy, Olga A. Wudarczyk, and Julian Savulescu. “Love
Addiction: Reply to Jenkins and Levy. ” Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 24, no.
1 (2017): 101–103.
Earp, Brian D., and Michael Hauskeller. “Binocularity in Bioethics—and Beyond.”
American Journal of Bioethics 16, no. 2 (2016): W3–W6.
Earp, Brian D., Anders Sandberg, Guy Kahane, and Julian Savulescu. “When Is
Diminishment a Form of Enhancement? Rethinking the Enhancement Debate in
Biomedical Ethics.” Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience 8, no. 12 (2014): 1–8.
Earp, Brian D., Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu. “Natural Selection, Childrearing,
and the Ethics of Marriage (and Divorce): Building a Case for the Neuroenhancement of
Human Relationships.” Philosophy and Technology 25, no. 4 (2012): 561–587.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-012-0081-8.
Earp, Brian D., Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu. “Brave New Love: The Threat of
High-Tech ‘Conversion’ Therapy and the Bio-Oppression of Sexual Minorities.” AJOB
Neuroscience 5, no. 1 (2014): 4–12. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2013.863242.
Earp, Brian D., Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu. “The Medicalization of Love.”
Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3 (2015): 323–336.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000206.
Earp, Brian D., Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu. “The Medicalization of Love:
Response to Critics.” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25, no. 4 (2016): 759–
771.
Earp, Brian D., and Julian Savulescu. “Is There Such a Thing as a Love Drug? Reply to
McGee.” Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 23, no. 2 (2016): 93–96.
Earp, Brian D., and Julian Savulescu. “Love Drugs: Why Scientists Should Study the
Effects of Pharmaceuticals on Human Romantic Relationships.” Technology in Society
52, no. 2 (2018): 10–16. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.techsoc.2017.02.001.
Earp, Brian D., Anders Sandberg, Julian Savulescu, and Ross Andersen. “The Case for
Using Drugs to Enhance our Relationships (and Our Break Ups).” The Atlantic, January
31, 2013. https://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2013/01/the-case-for-usingdrugs-to-enhance-our-relationships-and-our-break-ups/272615/.
Earp, Brian D., and Andrew Vierra. “Sexual Orientation Minority Rights and High-Tech
Conversion Therapy.” In The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Public Policy,
edited by David Boonin, 535–550. Cham, Switzerland: Springer International Publishing,
2018. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93907-0_41.
Earp, Brian D., Olga A. Wudarczyk, Bennett Foddy, and Julian Savulescu. “Addicted to
Love: What Is Love Addiction and When Should It Be Treated? ” Philosophy,
Psychiatry, and Psychology 24, no. 1 (2017): 77–92.
Earp, Brian D., Olga A. Wudarczyk, Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu. “If I Could
Just Stop Loving You: Anti-Love Biotechnology and the Ethics of a Chemical Breakup.”
American Journal of Bioethics 13, no. 11 (November 1, 2013): 3–17.
https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2013.839752.
Fisher, Helen E. Anatomy of Love. New York: Norton, 2016.
Fisher, Helen E., Arthur Aron, and Lucy L. Brown. “Romantic Love: A Mammalian Brain
System for Mate Choice.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological
Sciences 361, no. 1476 (2006): 2173–2186. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2006.1938.
Fromm, Erich. Man for Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics. London:
Routledge, 1947.
Fromm, Erich. The Art of Loving. New York: Harper & Row, 1956.
Giubilini, Alberto. “Normality, Therapy, and Enhancement: What Should Bioconservatives
Say about the Medicalization of Love?” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24,
no. 3 (2015): 347–354. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000656.
Greer, George R., and Requa Tolbert. “A Method of Conducting Therapeutic Sessions with
MDMA.” Journal of Psychoactive Drugs 30, no. 4 (1998): 371–379.
https://doi.org/10.1080/02791072.1998.10399713.
Hauskeller, Michael. “Clipping the Angel’s Wings: Why the Medicalization of Love May
Still Be Worrying.” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3 (2015): 361–
365. https://doi.org/10.1017/S096318011400067X.
Jenkins, Carrie. What Love Is: And What It Could Be. New York: Basic Books, 2017.
Klesse, Christian. “Theorizing Multi-Partner Relationships and Sexualities: Recent Work on
Non-Monogamy and Polyamory.” Sexualities 21, no. 7 (2018): 1109–1124.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1363460717701691.
Maslen, Hannah, Brian D. Earp, Roi Cohen Kadosh, and Julian Savulescu. “Brain
Stimulation for Treatment and Enhancement in Children: An Ethical Analysis.” Frontiers
in Human Neuroscience 8, no. 953 (2014): 1–5.
McGee, Andrew. “Is There Such a Thing as a Love Drug?” Philosophy, Psychiatry, and
Psychology 23, no. 2 (2016): 79–92. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2016.0006.
Minerva, Francesca. “Unrequited Love Hurts: The Medicalization of Broken Hearts Is
Therapy, Not Enhancement.” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 4
(2015): 479–485. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180115000134.
Naar, Hichem. “Real‐World Love Drugs: Reply to Nyholm.” Journal of Applied Philosophy
33, no. 2 (May 1, 2016): 197–201. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12141.
Nyholm, Sven. “Love Troubles: Human Attachment and Biomedical Enhancements.”
Journal of Applied Philosophy 32, no. 2 (2015): 190–202.
https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12085.
Nyholm, Sven. “The Medicalization of Love and Narrow and Broad Conceptions of Human
Well-Being.” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3 (2015): 337–346.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000644.
Parens, Erik. “On Good and Bad Forms of Medicalization.” Bioethics 27, no. 1 (2013): 28–
35. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2011.01885.x.
Savulescu, Julian. “New Breeds of Humans: The Moral Obligation to Enhance.”
Reproductive BioMedicine Online 10 (2005): 36–39. https://doi.org/10.1016/S14726483(10)62202-X.
Savulescu, Julian. “Genetic Interventions and the Ethics of Enhancement of Human
Beings.” In Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, edited by David M. Kaplan. New
York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2009.
Savulescu, Julian, and Brian D. Earp. “Neuroreductionism about Sex and Love.” Think 13,
no. 38 (2014): 7–12.
Savulescu, Julian, and Anders Sandberg. “Neuroenhancement of Love and Marriage: The
Chemicals between Us.” Neuroethics 1, no. 1 (2008): 31–44.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-007-9002-4.
de Sousa, Ronald. “Love, Jealousy, and Compersion.” In The Oxford Handbook of
Philosophy of Love, edited by Christopher Grau and Aaron Smuts. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2017.
http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199395729.001.0001/oxf
ordhb-9780199395729-e-30.
Spreeuwenberg, Lotte. “Taking the Love Pill: A Reply to Naar and Nyholm.” Journal of
Applied Philosophy, in press, online ahead of print. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12305.
Striepens, Nadine, Keith M. Kendrick, Wolfgang Maier, and René Hurlemann. “Prosocial
Effects of Oxytocin and Clinical Evidence for Its Therapeutic Potential.” Frontiers in
Neuroendocrinology 32, no. 4 (2011): 426–450.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.yfrne.2011.07.001.
Tweedy, Ann E. “Polyamory as a Sexual Orientation.” University of Cincinnati Law Review
79, no. 4 (2010): 1461–1515.
Weaver, Bryan R., and Fiona Woollard. “Marriage and the Norm of Monogamy.” The
Monist 91, no. 3/4 (2008): 506–522.
Wudarczyk, Olga A., Brian D. Earp, Adam Guastella, and Julian Savulescu. “Could
Intranasal Oxytocin Be Used to Enhance Relationships? Research Imperatives, Clinical
Policy, and Ethical Considerations.” Current Opinion in Psychiatry 26, no. 5 (2013):
474–484. https://doi.org/10.1097/YCO.0b013e3283642e10.
Notes
1
Of the more than one million divorces that occur annually in the United States, there is evidence that
the majority stem from relationships much like this. In other words, it is not just those marriages
characterized by constant fighting, abuse, or other clearly dysfunctional habits that keep the
divorce courts packed. Rather, a surprisingly high proportion consists of relatively low-conflict
marriages that are reasonably stable, functional, and perhaps even occasionally pleasant, but when
it comes right down to it, less than happy. See Pamela Haag, Marriage Confidential: Love in the
Post-Romantic Age (New York: HarperCollins, 2011). For a more formal discussion, see Tim B.
Heaton and Stan L. Albrecht, “Stable Unhappy Marriages,” Journal of Marriage and Family 53,
no. 3 (1991): 747–758, https://doi.org/10.2307/352748.
2
For recent discussions by others (that is, excluding myself and my usual coauthors; our papers are
listed in the bibliography), see Andrew McGee, “Is There Such a Thing as a Love Drug?”
Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 23, no. 2 (2016): 79–92,
https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2016.0006; Sven Nyholm, “Love Troubles: Human Attachment and
Biomedical Enhancements,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 32, no. 2 (2015): 190–202,
https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12085; Sven Nyholm, “The Medicalization of Love and Narrow and
Broad Conceptions of Human Well-Being,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3
(2015): 337–346, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000644; Hichem Naar, “Real‐World Love
Drugs: Reply to Nyholm,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 33, no. 2 (May 1, 2016): 197–201,
https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12141; Francesca Minerva, “Unrequited Love Hurts: The
Medicalization of Broken Hearts Is Therapy, Not Enhancement,” Cambridge Quarterly of
Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 4 (2015): 479–485, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180115000134;
Alberto Giubilini, “Normality, Therapy, and Enhancement: What Should Bioconservatives Say
about the Medicalization of Love?,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3 (2015):
347–354, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000656; Rebecca Bamford, “Unrequited:
Neurochemical Enhancement of Love,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3
(2015): 355–360, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000668; Robbie Arrell, “Should We
Biochemically Enhance Sexual Fidelity?,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 83 (2018):
389–414, https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246118000462; Michael Hauskeller, “Clipping the Angel’s
Wings: Why the Medicalization of Love May Still Be Worrying,” Cambridge Quarterly of
Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3 (2015): 361–365, https://doi.org/10.1017/S096318011400067X; Lotte
Spreeuwenberg, “Taking the Love Pill: A Reply to Naar and Nyholm,” Journal of Applied
Philosophy, in press, online ahead of print, https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12305.
3
See Brian D. Earp and Julian Savulescu, “Love Drugs: Why Scientists Should Study the Effects of
Pharmaceuticals on Human Romantic Relationships,” Technology in Society 52, no. 2 (2018): 10–
16, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.techsoc.2017.02.001. See also Brian D. Earp et al., “If I Could Just
Stop Loving You: Anti-Love Biotechnology and the Ethics of a Chemical Breakup,” American
Journal of Bioethics 13, no. 11 (2013): 3–17, https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2013.839752.
4
William Shakespeare, Sonnet 116. For a thoughtful discussion of the philosophical implications of
such a notion, see Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, “The Historicity of Psychological Attitudes: Love Is
Not Love Which Alters Not When It Alteration Finds,” Midwest Studies In Philosophy 10, no. 1
(n.d.): 399–412, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00548.x.
5
For a classic defense of this view, see Erich Fromm, The Art of Loving (New York: Harper & Row,
1956).
6
Erik Parens, “On Good and Bad Forms of Medicalization,” Bioethics 27, no. 1 (2013): 28–35,
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467–8519.2011.01885.x.
7
In fact, the innovation is only partial. As I have written about elsewhere, the use of biochemical
substances to enhance the effects of couples counseling is also, at least in some circles, old news:
MDMA was used in the 1980s as an aid to individual and interpersonal psychotherapy before it
was banned following a conservative shift in the culture: see Brian D. Earp, “Psychedelic Moral
Enhancement,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 83, no. 1 (2018): 415–439; Brian D.
Earp, “Drogen Nehmen—um Wohl Unserer Kinder?” GEO Magazine 10, no. 1 (2015): 62–63. My
so-called innovation, then, might better be described as a revival, although I do hope that the
philosophical and ethical insights I am trying to raise are original enough to inspire further
conversation.
8
Carrie Jenkins, What Love Is: And What It Could Be (New York: Basic Books, 2017).
9
For example, Helen E. Fisher, Arthur Aron, and Lucy L. Brown, “Romantic Love: A Mammalian
Brain System for Mate Choice,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological
Sciences 361, no. 1476 (2006): 2173–2186, https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2006.1938.
10
Larry J. Young, “Being Human: Love: Neuroscience Reveals All,” Nature 457 (2009): 148,
https://doi.org/10.1038/457148a.
11
Bennett Helm, “Love,” ed. Edward N. Zalta, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall (2017): 1–
52. For further discussion, see Earp, Brian D., Bennett Foddy, Olga A. Wudarczyk, and Julian
Savulescu. “Love Addiction: Reply to Jenkins and Levy. ” Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology
24, no. 1 (2017): 101–103.
12
Adam Opbroek et al., “Emotional Blunting Associated with SSRI-Induced Sexual Dysfunction. Do
SSRIs Inhibit Emotional Responses?,” International Journal of Neuropsychopharmacology 5, no.
2 (June 1, 2002): 147–151, https://doi.org/10.1017/S1461145702002870.
13
Richard Balon, “SSRI-Associated Sexual Dysfunction,” American Journal of Psychiatry 163, no. 9
(2006): 1504–1509, https://doi.org/10.1176/ajp.2006.163.9.1504.
14
Neil Delaney, “Romantic Loving Commitment: Articulating a Modern Ideal,” American
Philosophical Quarterly 33, no. 4 (1996): 339–355.
15
Anecdotally, there are also reports of such drugs “saving” marriages because one partner’s libido
was lowered to a point where they did not feel compelled to stray. I discuss this issue later in the
chapter. The upshot is that, depending on the aspects of love one finds most important—passion
versus commitment, for example—one and the same physiological effect could potentially count as
either love diminishing or love enhancing. For discussion, see Helen E. Fisher and J. Anderson
Thomson Jr., “Lust, Romance, Attachment: Do the Side Effects of Serotonin-Enhancing
Antidepressants Jeopardize Romantic Love, Marriage, and Fertility?,” in Evolutionary Cognitive
Neuroscience, ed. Steven Platek et al. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2007), 245–283.
16
Olga A. Wudarczyk et al., “Could Intranasal Oxytocin Be Used to Enhance Relationships?
Research Imperatives, Clinical Policy, and Ethical Considerations,” Current Opinion in Psychiatry
26, no. 5 (2013): 474–484, https://doi.org/10.1097/YCO.0b013e3283642e10; Beverley Fehr and
James A. Russell, “The Concept of Love Viewed from a Prototype Perspective,” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 60, no. 3 (1991): 425–438, https://doi.org/10.1037/00223514.60.3.425.
17
Nadine Striepens et al., “Prosocial Effects of Oxytocin and Clinical Evidence for Its Therapeutic
Potential,” Frontiers in Neuroendocrinology 32, no. 4 (2011): 426–450,
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.yfrne.2011.07.001.
18
Reid M. Rubsamen and Robert Cole, “Increasing Libido in Humans via Acute Testosterone
Administration,” United States US6632419B2, filed March 19, 2001, and issued October 14, 2003,
https://patents.google.com/patent/US6632419B2/en.
19
George R. Greer and Requa Tolbert, “A Method of Conducting Therapeutic Sessions with
MDMA,” Journal of Psychoactive Drugs 30, no. 4 (1998): 371–379,
https://doi.org/10.1080/02791072.1998.10399713.
20
For informal discussion and case studies, see Louisa Kamps, “The Couple Who Medicates
Together,” ELLE, April 18, 2012, https://www.elle.com/life-love/sexrelationships/advice/a14208/the-couple-who-medicates-together-654677/.
21
Naar, “Real World Love Drugs.”
22
Jenkins, What Love Is.
23
This paragraph and the next are adapted from Brian D. Earp, Anders Sandberg, and Julian
Savulescu, “The Medicalization of Love,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24, no. 3
(2015): 323–336, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180114000206. See that paper for primary sources.
For an extended discussion, see Helen E. Fisher, Anatomy of Love (New York: Norton, 2016).
24
Consider a set of animal experiments to get the basic idea. In one study, scientists induced a
monogamous pair-bond in a species of vole by injecting a dose of oxytocin into their brains. They
later did the opposite with an oxytocin blocker. In other words, voles that would have bonded if not
for the injection failed to do so and became interested in novel sexual partners. Humans would not
submit themselves to such experiments, so there is no direct evidence for such an effect in people.
But as a less invasive option, as I mentioned, they can sniff synthetic oxytocin into their brains
through their noses, which initial research suggests can increase attachment-related cognitions in
some individuals. See Wudarczyk et al., “Could Intranasal Oxytocin Be Used to Enhance
Relationships?”
25
<IBT>Lisa M. Diamond, “What Does Sexual Orientation Orient? A Biobehavioral Model
Distinguishing Romantic Love and Sexual Desire.,” Psychological Review 110, no. 1 (2003): 173–
192, https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.173. At page 174, internal references
omitted.</IBT>
26
Ibid.
27
Jenkins, What Love Is.
28
Ibid.
29
Brian D. Earp, Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu, “Brave New Love: The Threat of HighTech ‘Conversion’ Therapy and the Bio-Oppression of Sexual Minorities,” AJOB Neuroscience 5,
no. 1 (2014): 4–12, https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2013.863242; Sean Aas and Candice
Delmas, “The Ethics of Sexual Reorientation: What Should Clinicians and Researchers Do?,”
Journal of Medical Ethics 42, no. 6 (2016): 340–347, https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-
103562; Sean Aas and Candice Delmas, “Sexual Reorientation in Ideal and Non-Ideal Theory,”
Journal of Political Philosophy, 26, no. 4 (2018): 463-485.
30
Brian D. Earp and Andrew Vierra, “Sexual Orientation Minority Rights and High-Tech Conversion
Therapy,” in The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Public Policy, ed. David Boonin (Cham,
Switzerland: Springer International, 2018), 535–550, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-939070_41; Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu, “Brave New Love.”
31
For in-depth discussions, see Brian D. Earp, “Between Moral Relativism and Moral Hypocrisy:
Reframing the Debate on ‘FGM,’” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 26, no. 2 (2016): 105–144,
https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2016.0009; Brian D. Earp, “Female Genital Mutilation and Male
Circumcision: Toward an Autonomy-Based Ethical Framework,” Medicolegal and Bioethics 5, no.
1 (2015): 89–104, https://doi.org/10.2147/MB.S63709; Brian D. Earp and Rebecca Steinfeld,
“Gender and Genital Cutting: A New Paradigm,” in Gifted Women, Fragile Men, ed. T. G. Barbat,
Euromind Monographs 2 (Brussels: ALDE Group-EU Parliament., 2017),
http://euromind.global/brian-d-earp-and-rebecca-steinfeld/?lang=en; Brian D. Earp and Rebecca
Steinfeld, “Genital Autonomy and Sexual Well-Being,” Current Sexual Health Reports 10 (2018):
7–17, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11930-018-0141-x.
32
Brian D. Earp, Anders Sandberg, and Julian Savulescu, “Natural Selection, Childrearing, and the
Ethics of Marriage (and Divorce): Building a Case for the Neuroenhancement of Human
Relationships,” Philosophy and Technology 25, no. 4 (2012): 561–587,
https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-012-0081-8. Some material in this section is adapted from this
essay.
33
Erich Fromm, Man for Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics (London: Routledge,
1947), p. 31.
34
Christopher Ryan, “Sexual Repression,” Psychology Today, April 20, 2010,
https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/sex-dawn/201004/sexual-repression.
35
Kathrin F. Stanger-Hall and David W. Hall, “Abstinence-Only Education and Teen Pregnancy
Rates: Why We Need Comprehensive Sex Education in the U.S.,” PLOS ONE 6, no. 10 (2011):
e24658, https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0024658.
36
James W. Prescott, “Body Pleasure and the Origins of Violence,” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists
31, no. 9 (1975): 10–20, https://doi.org/10.1080/00963402.1975.11458292.
37
Christopher Ryan and Cacilda Jethá, Sex at Dawn (New York: HarperCollins, 2010); Thomas G.
Plante, “Catholic Priests Who Sexually Abuse Minors: Why Do We Hear so Much yet Know so
Little?,” Pastoral Psychology 44, no. 5 (1996): 305–310, https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02262821;
Jason Berry, Lead Us Not into Temptation: Catholic Priests and the Sexual Abuse of Children
(New York: Doubleday, 1992).
38
Richard Wrangham and Dale Peterson, Demonic Males: Apes and the Origins of Human Violence
(London: Bloomsbury, 1997); Randy Thornhill and Craig T. Palmer, A Natural History of Rape:
Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2000).
39
Jerry A. Coyne and Andrew Berry, “Rape as an Adaptation,” Nature 404 (2000): 121–122,
https://doi.org/10.1038/35004636; Jonathan Marks, review of Review of Demonic Males: Apes and
the Origins of Human Violence, by Richard Wrangham and Dale Peterson, Human Biology 71, no.
1 (1999): 143–146.
40
For a general discussion, see Kate Manne, Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2017).
41
David Archard, “The Wrong of Rape,” Philosophical Quarterly 57, no. 228 (2007): 374–393,
https://www.jstor.org/stable/4543243; Brian D. Earp, “‘Legitimate Rape,’ Moral Coherence, and
Degrees of Sexual Harm,” Think 14, no. 41 (2015): 9–20,
https://doi.org/10.1017/S1477175615000172.
42
Michael C. Seto, “Is Pedophilia a Sexual Orientation?,” Archives of Sexual Behavior 41, no. 1
(2012): 231–236, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10508-011-9882-6.
43
Ray Blanchard, James M. Cantor, and Lori K. Robichaud, “Biological Factors in the Development
of Sexual Deviance and Aggression in Males,” in The Juvenile Sex Offender, ed. Howard E.
Barbaree and William L. Marshall (New York: Guilford Press, 2008), 77–104, p. 80.
44
There are now growing concerns about the replicability of many published findings in the human
sciences. For an overview, see Brian D. Earp and David Trafimow, “Replication, Falsification, and
the Crisis of Confidence in Social Psychology,” Frontiers in Psychology 6, no. 621 (2015): 1–11,
https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00621.
45
For discussion, see Ole Martin Moen, “The Ethics of Pedophilia,” Etikk i Praksis—Nordic Journal
of Applied Ethics 9, no. 1 (2015): 111–124, http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v9i1.1718.
46
Brian D. Earp, “Science Cannot Determine Human Values,” Think 15, no. 43 (2016): 17–23,
https://doi.org/10.1017/S1477175616000026.
47
William K. Frankena, “The Naturalistic Fallacy,” Mind 48, no. 192 (1939): 464–477.
48
See Robin A. Dembroff, “Beyond Binary: Genderqueer as a Critical Gender Kind,” unpublished
manuscript. Abstract of the forthcoming paper available at https://robindembroff.weebly.com/inprogress.html. See also Robin A. Dembroff, “Why Be Non-Binary?,” Aeon, October 30, 2018,
https://aeon.co/essays/nonbinary-identity-is-a-radical-stance-against-gender-segregation.
49
For an excellent overview, see Talia Mae Bettcher, “Feminist Perspectives on Trans Issues,” in The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2014 (Metaphysics Research
Lab, Stanford University, 2014), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/feminismtrans/.
50
Rebecca L. Stotzer, “Violence against Transgender People: A Review of United States Data,”
Aggression and Violent Behavior 14, no. 3 (2009): 170–179,
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.avb.2009.01.006; Talia Mae Bettcher, “Evil Deceivers and MakeBelievers: On Transphobic Violence and the Politics of Illusion,” Hypatia 22, no. 3 (2007): 43–65,
https://www.jstor.org/stable/4640081.
51
Sari L. Reisner, Asa Radix, and Madeline B. Deutsch, “Integrated and Gender-Affirming
Transgender Clinical Care and Research,” Journal of Acquired Immune Deficiency Syndromes
(1999) 72, no. Suppl 3 (2016): S235–S242, https://doi.org/10.1097/QAI.0000000000001088.
52
R. Vitelli et al., “Trans Identities and Medical Practice in Italy: Self-Positioning towards Gender
Affirmation Surgery,” Sexologies 26, no. 4 (2017): e43–e51,
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.sexol.2017.08.001.
53
Larry R. Martinez and Michelle R. Hebl, “Additional Agents of Change in Promoting Lesbian,
Gay, Bisexual, and Transgendered Inclusiveness in Organizations,” Industrial and Organizational
Psychology 3, no. 1 (2010): 82–85, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1754-9434.2009.01203.x.
54
Elvio Baccarini and Luca Malatesti, “The Moral Bioenhancement of Psychopaths,” Journal of
Medical Ethics 43, no. 10 (2017): 697–701, https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103537.
55
Julian Savulescu and Anders Sandberg, “Neuroenhancement of Love and Marriage: The Chemicals
between Us,” Neuroethics 1, no. 1 (2008): 31–44, https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-007-9002-4;
Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu, “Natural Selection, Childrearing, and the Ethics of Marriage (and
Divorce).”
56
David P. Barash and Judith E. Lipton, The Myth of Monogamy (New York: Macmillan, 2002).
According to the evolutionary psychologist and expert on human mating practices, Geoffrey
Miller, “Everybody who studies human mating knows that we tend to do lots of ‘nonmonogamous’ behavior, including adolescent sexual experimentation, short-term casual mating
during young adulthood, occasional affairs even given pair bonds, mate-switching to new pair
bonds (‘serial monogamy’), and polygyny among high-status males. The only real disagreement
among sex researchers is whether most people most of the time are in long-term pair bonds that are
highly sexually exclusive, or whether most people most of the time are in (one or more) long-term
pair bonds that are relatively open to other relationships” (personal communication, November 2,
2018).
57
Ryan and Jethá, Sex at Dawn, p. 2.
58
According to Miller (see note 56), in fact, only a small minority of sex researchers go as far as Ryan
and Jethá in claiming that our ancestors were full-fledged bonobo-like polyamorists.
59
Jenkins, What Love Is, p. 93 of the advanced copy. For a scientific defense of the view that
monogamy is largely in line with human nature, see David P. Schmidt, “An Evolutionary
Perspective on Mate Choice and Relationship Initiation,” in Handbook of Relationship Initiation,
ed. Amy Wenzel, Susan Sprecher, and John Harvey (Abingdon and New York: Routledge
Handbooks Online, 2018), https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203809853.ch3.
60
For discussion, see Brian D. Earp, “Can You Be Gay by Choice?,” in Philosophers Take on the
World, ed. David Edmonds (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 95–98.
61
For a fascinating discussion, see Ann E. Tweedy, “Polyamory as a Sexual Orientation,” University
of Cincinnati Law Review 79, no. 4 (2010): 1461–1515.
62
Terri D. Conley et al., “Investigation of Consensually Nonmonogamous Relationships: Theories,
Methods, and New Directions,” Perspectives on Psychological Science 12, no. 2 (2017): 205–232,
https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691616667925.
63
Bryan R. Weaver and Fiona Woollard, “Marriage and the Norm of Monogamy,” The Monist 91, no.
3/4 (2008): 506–522.
64
Amy C. Moors et al., “Stigma toward Individuals Engaged in Consensual Nonmonogamy: Robust
and Worthy of Additional Research,” Analyses of Social Issues and Public Policy 13, no. 1 (2013):
52–69, https://doi.org/10.1111/asap.12020.
65
For an argument that lovers should attempt to convert negative feelings of jealousy into a positive
feelings of compersion (pleasure taken in the thought of one’s lover enjoying love or sex with
someone else), see Ronald de Sousa, “Love, Jealousy, and Compersion,” in The Oxford Handbook
of Philosophy of Love, ed. Christopher Grau and Aaron Smuts (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2017),
http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199395729.001.0001/oxfordhb9780199395729-e-30.
66
David M. Buss and Martie Haselton, “The Evolution of Jealousy,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9,
no. 11 (2005): 506–507, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2005.09.006.
67
<IBT>Gordon Parker and Elaine Barrett, “Morbid Jealousy as a Variant of Obsessive-Compulsive
Disorder,” Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 31, no. 1 (February 1, 1997): 133–
138, p. 134,https://doi.org/10.3109/00048679709073811.</IBT>
68
Ibid.
69
Ibid.
70
Paul E. Mullen, “A Phenomenology of Jealousy,” Australian and New Zealand Journal of
Psychiatry 24, no. 1 (1990): 17–28, https://doi.org/10.3109/00048679009062882.
71
Parker and Barrett, “Morbid Jealousy,” p. 134.
72
Parker and Barrett, “Morbid Jealousy,” p. 133.
73
I do not mean to suggest that this is an exhaustive list of the choices you and your partner face. But
they are, I think, among the most likely or main ones.
74
<IBT>Jack G. Modell et al., “Comparative Sexual Side Effects of Bupropion, Fluoxetine,
Paroxetine, and Sertraline,” Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics 61, no. 4 (1997): 476–487,
https://doi.org/10.1016/S0009-9236(97)90198-3.</IBT>
75
Ibid., p. 476.
76
Julian Savulescu, “Genetic Interventions and the Ethics of Enhancement of Human Beings,” in
Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, ed. David M. Kaplan (New York: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2009).
77
Julian Savulescu, “New Breeds of Humans: The Moral Obligation to Enhance,” Reproductive
BioMedicine Online 10 (2005): 36–39, https://doi.org/10.1016/S1472-6483(10)62202-X.