Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
8 pages
1 file
We must now examine…whether just people also live better and are happier than unjust ones. I think it's clear already that this is so, but we must look into it further, since the argument concerns no ordinary topic, but the way we ought to live." -Plato, Republic, I, 352d
Aristotle and Plato are the fathers of Democracy. Their ideas have shaped and continue to shape our political ideologies, reasoning, and constructs. Much like todays gulf in the understanding of Democracy, they too seem to disagree on it. From having read these two magnificent classics, one cannot help but to ponder if Aristotle actually built upon Plato"s premises rather than seeming to disagree with him. As a student of these two ancient political philosophers I will try to engage in this dialogue. This paper will argue that Aristotle"s view on democracy builds on the singular ideal socio-economic premise Plato lays out but adds conflicting premises for the need of practicality enabling him to observe other socio-economic prisms creating a more in-depth take on democracy. Furthermore, to understand Aristotle we need to first observe Plato"s premise.
The Review of Politics, 2022
Eastern Christianity and Late Antique Philosophy, 2020
Becoming like God by reading Plato After Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, every school of philosophy took one of the central tasks of ethics to be the specification of the telos at which our actions aim and the nature of eudaimonia. Though Plato's works pre-date the Ethics, it is not too difficult to see the Aristotelian idea of a telos or goal of living implicit in the Republic. 1 After all, the point of this work is to show that the truly just man is happier than the unjust man-even an unjust man who enjoys a good reputation-by inquiring into the nature of justice. The case for the happiness of the just man is not prosecuted by explicitly identifying what happiness is and then showing that he enjoys more of it than the unjust man. Rather, Plato's Republic offers rich portraits of different possible psychic and civic constitutions. The argumentative force of the dialogue relies on the reader sharing a preconception of what a happy life should be like with the characters in the dialogue. The freedom from internal dissension that is characteristic of both the just person and the just city is never argued to be the font of a notion of happiness that is explicitly articulated. Rather, the lack of internal dissension is shown to be the source or basis of many features of an individual's life (or of our collective political lives) that the participants in the dialogue value. Moreover, lives (and cities) that diverge from the ideal of unity found in the just person are taken to be unhappier the greater N.B. All references to classical texts are from the Loeb Classical Library (LCL). Titles and authors are abbreviated according to the Oxford Classical Dictionary List, https://oxfordre.com/classics/page/abbreviation-list/ 1 Irwin 2007, 114-116. This observation about the continuity of Plato's ethical project with Aristotle and the dominance of Aristotle's framework for subsequent theorists is now part of received wisdom in magisterial overviews such as Irwin's book. the internal dissension and lack of harmony that is involved. This is presented as at least one of the major reasons why these lives or these are ineffective and unhappy. So even if the exact nature of psychic or communal flourishing is left undefined, there is little doubt that unity plays a central role in securing it. 2 In light of the starring role that psychic harmony plays in Plato's dialogue, it would not be unreasonable for a modern reader to respond to the question, "If the writer of the Republic had addressed himself to the topic in the style of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, what would he have identified as the telos?" with the answer "psychic harmony". The role of harmony among the different parts of the soul in showing why the life of the just person is happier than that of the unjust man lends a certain plausibility to the thought that eudaimonia is simply to be identified with psychic harmony even if that identification is not guaranteed by Plato's text. It might then come as something of a surprise to learn that ancient Platonists from the 2 nd century onwards used the Aristotelian framework and identified the goal of living with likeness to god rather than psychic harmony. 3 In reaching this conclusion, they gave pride of place to a text that Socrates himself identifies as a digression from the main argument in the Theaetetus. Socrates: But it is impossible that evils should be done away with, Theodorus, for there must always be something opposed to the good; and they cannot have their place among the gods but must inevitably hover about mortal nature and this earth. Therefore we ought to try to escape from earth to the 2 Of course, there are also other reasons why the just person is better off. So famously Book IX argues that the pleasures of the just philosopher in whom reason rules are superior to those in whom other parts of the soul dominate. This seems to be a result of the nature of the objects after which these souls strive. The things that philosophers seek to "fill their souls with" nourish the best part of us with the things that are truly real. 3 Since the turn of the century some scholars have assessed this idea as a genuine reading of
1991
My objective here is to reconstruct the plan of Aristotle's exposition of political science ipolitike) in his Nicomachean Ethics and Politics, and to show that this plan reveals certain fundamental but unnoticed features of his philosophical intention. First I demonstrate, on the basis of numerous programmatic but unfulfilled forward references in the extant Politics, that Aristotle planned to complete this work in certain promised "discourses on the regimes" (Pol. 1260b8-20) by reconsidering his accounts of moral virtue, education and household management from the perspective of the different forms of regime and the divergent ends each promotes. Secondly, I explore the philosophical intention of this plan of politike, arguing that Aristotle's enquiry remains fundamentally incomplete without this reconsideration. His aim of providing the statesman with the knowledge of "legislative science" necessary to apply the teaching on the human good presented in the ethical writings, I suggest, requires this promised account of the way in which the moral virtues vary according to the ends promoted by the different forms of regime. Our enquiry will help to clarify the philosophical significance of Aristotle's conception of "ethics," as tradition has come to know it, as political science.' *This paper has a long history: I first conceived many of the views here presented when I studied Aristotle's political thought with David O'Connor in 1984, and I remain indebted to him for much valuable discussion over the years. This paper was first presented at Duke University in December 1988, as part of a lecture series on Aristotle, and a subsequent version was read to the seminar in Traditional and Modem Philosophy at The University of Sydney in September 1990. I am grateful to these audiences, as well as to Michael Frede, Phillip Mitsis and A. E. Raubitschek, for helpful suggestions. Particular thanks are due to my late colleague in Chapel Hill, Friedrich Solmsen, who helped to shape my thinking on this subject through much stimulating discussion. It is an honor to dedicate the final result to his memory. In recent years three valuable studies on this subject have ap(>eared: E. Trepanier, "La politique comme philosophic morale chez Aristote," Dialogue 2 (1963) 251-79; S.
Outline the main social and political concepts of Plato and their applications to our current society. Can morals and values save civilization? Are philosopher kings the solution to civilization's discontent? Has history proven the existence of philosopher-kings? Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle were considered the first to conceptualize ideologies for the western realm's societal structure, starting in Ancient Greece. They introduced political abstractions and conceptions, setting principles, doctrines, and order that pose as blueprints for the Ancient Greek's progress and reform. Ancient Greeks actualized and experimented with these concepts to give them their path to satisfaction and development. They tried various Government systems until they picked one that suited them, brought out social classes, and did anything to develop their civilization. But the progress did not end with them. Through the following generations, these concepts flourished around the world. And men of the contemporary times are rooted in these abstracts, ideologies, and notions that project social order and governance, which they could apply to their current system. These all started with man seeking an imperative that encompasses ethics, principles, and doctrines for people to be on the same page of measures, creating harmony and balance, power and development, and changing and progressing the institutions. Political and social
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
ACADEMIC SOCIAL RESOURCES (ASR JOURNAL), 2024
This article aims to reveal the strong interaction between ethics and politics by examining Aristotle's understanding of ethics and politics through the concept of eudaimonia. According to Aristotle, eudaimonia is the ultimate goal of human beings. The most effective means of achieving this goal is through the field of politics. In this respect, Aristotle argues that a social order should be ensured and a virtuous life should be encouraged for the happiness of the individual. Aristotle’s practical philosophy, taking into account the fact that the individual is a social being, exhibits an approach that evaluates morality and politics in an integrity. The fact that David Ross's particular examination of Aristotle's ethics with its social dimensions and his politics with its moral dimensions points to the importance of this idea. In our study, the critical roles of Aristotle’s concepts of phronesis (practical wisdom) and mesos (middle way) in the relationship between ethics and politics are elaborated. In particular, works such as Ethics of Nicomacheus, Ethics of Eudemos and Magna Moralia reveal how these concepts are handled. In this context, especially through these works, Aristotle, on the one hand, reveals the importance of practical wisdom and moderation, which are essential for a virtuous life, and on the other hand, he argues that individuals should contribute to the happiness of others not only for their own happiness, but also by fulfilling the duties of being a zoon politicon being. This view is previously encountered in Plato’s State by emphasising the relationship between the ideal social order, politics and virtue, and in this framework, the idea that moral virtues form the basis of political structures is put forward. Taking this context into consideration, the article analyses how Aristotle’s understanding of eudaimonia shapes both individual and social happiness within the relationship between morality and politics Bu makale, Aristoteles’in etik ve siyaset anlayışını eudaimonia kavramı üzerinden ele alarak, ahlak ve siyaset arasındaki güçlü etkileşimi ortaya koymayı amaçlamaktadır. Aristoteles’e göre eudaimonia, insanın nihai amacıdır. Bu amaca ulaşmanın en etkili aracı da siyaset alanından geçer. Bu minvalde de özellikle Aristoteles tarafından bireyin mutluluğu için toplumsal bir düzenin sağlanması ve erdemli bir yaşamın teşvik edilmesi gerektiği savunulur. Aristoteles'in pratik felsefesi, bireyin toplumsal varlık olmasını da dikkate alarak ahlak ve siyaseti bir bütünlük içinde değerlendiren bir yaklaşım sergiler. David Ross'un bilhassa Aristoteles’in etiğini toplumsal, politikasını da ahlaki boyutlarıyla ele alması, bu düşüncenin önemine işaret etmektedir. Çalışmamızda Aristoteles’in phronesis (pratik bilgelik) ve mesos (orta yol) kavramlarının, ahlak-siyaset ilişkisi içerisindeki kritik rolleri detaylandırılmıştır. Özellikle Nikomakhos’a Etik, Eudemos’a Etik ve Magna Moralia gibi eserler bu kavramların nasıl ele alındığını ortaya koyar. Bu bağlamda bilhassa söz konusu eserler aracılığıyla Aristoteles, bir yandan erdemli bir yaşam için elzem olan pratik bilgelik ve ölçülülüğün önemini ortaya koyarken, diğer yandan bireylerin sadece kendi mutlulukları için değil, aynı zamanda zoon politicon bir varlık olmanın vazifelerini yerine getirerek diğerlerinin de mutluluğuna katkıda bulunmaları gerektiğini savunur. Bu görüş daha önce Platon’un Devlet’inde ideal toplum düzeni ile siyaset ve erdem arasındaki ilişkinin vurgulanmasıyla karşımıza çıkar ve bu çerçevede ahlaki erdemlerin siyasal yapıların temelini oluşturduğu düşüncesinin öne sürüldüğü görülür. Bu bağlamın da göz önüne alındığı makalede, Aristoteles'in eudaimonia anlayışının hem bireysel hem de toplumsal mutluluğu nasıl şekillendirdiği meselesi ahlak ve siyaset ilişkisi dahilinde analiz edilmiştir.
V ir t u e ETHICS NOW CONSTITUTES one of three major approaches to the study of ethics by Anglophone philosophers.1 Its proponents almost all recognize the source of their approach in Aristotle, but relatively few of them confront the problem that source poses for contemporary ethicists. According to Aristotle, ethike belongs and is subordinate to politike. Because it [politike] makes use of the remaining sciences and, further, because it legislates what one ought to do and what to abstain from, its end would encompass those of the others, with the result that this would be the human good. For even if this is the same thing for an individual and a city, to secure and preserve the good of the city appears to be something greater and more complete: the good of the individual by himself is certainly desirable enough, but that of a nation and of cities is nobler and more divine.2 In the liberal democracies within which most, if not all Anglophone ethicists write, political authorities are not supposed to dictate or legislate the good of individuals; they are supposed merely to establish the conditions necessary for individuals to choose their own life paths. If, as Aristotle argues, the good life for a human being is a virtuous life, and if, as he argues at the conclusion of his Nicomachean Ethics,3 human beings cannot acquire the habits needed to make them virtuous if they do not receive a correct upbringing, and this upbringing needs to be supported and preserved by correct legislation, it is not clear
Interpretation, 2006
Philosophical Books, 2003
Scholarly research into ancient philosophy has not always been particularly good at pointing out its relevance to contemporary philosophical debate. It is one of the goals that Andreas Bächli and Andreas Graeser have set themselves to meet-in the rather unexpected medium of a concise encyclopaedia of 48 basic concepts of ancient philosophy. These are discussed in a format that combines the virtue of encyclopaedia articles, to provide concise, crossreferenced information, with the more discursive, and in this case sometimes even elegant, style of the philosophical essay. Art (τ 7 χνη /ars), beauty (τ 3 καλ 2 ν / pulchrum), cosmos (κ 2 σµος / mundus), form (µορφ 8 / forma), the good (τ 3 0 γαθ 2 ν / bonum), imitation (µ 1 µησις / imitatio), matter (6 λη / materia), nature (ϕ 9 σις / natura), quality (ποι 2 της / qualitas), the soul (ψυχ 8 / anima), time (χρ 2 νος / tempus), truth (0 λ 8 θεια / veritas), virtue (0 ρετ 8 / virtus) are among the concepts covered. The English translations suggested here can be just as misleading as the common German renderings of the terms Bächli and Graeser are dealing with; the authors point out throughout where and to what extent modern 'equivalents' of ancient terms are precisely not equivalent. This indicates already that the connections that Bächli and Graeser draw between ancient and modern philosophy do not result in a rash assimilation of both. Subject/ subiectum / 5 ποκε 1 µενον is an obvious opportunity to point out the deep gulf between both epochs. Nevertheless Bächli and Graeser insist that the philosophical literature between the sixth century and the sixth century has something to say where present philosophical disputes are concerned, and this is partly reflected even in the choice of topics; the article on meaning (σηµα 1 νειν / significatio) is a characteristic example. Another move that fits in well with this perspective of the book is a choice of texts that is against the current, aiming at a shift in the canon. While the classics, Plato and Aristotle, of course have to figure prominently, Bächli and Graeser at the same time see the tradition of Scepticism as central rather than marginal to ancient philosophy. Generally, texts that contain much of philosophical interest, but have tended to be overlooked, such as Cicero's Lucullus or Boethius's Contra Eutychen et Nestorium , are given due attention. In dealing with these texts, whether familiar or neglected, Bächli and Graeser are philosophers and also classicists rather than the other way round. Beyond the history of words, concepts and ideas, they engage in argument. The articles
Post-Truth and the Mediation of Reality New Conjunctures, 2019
Roman Replies and CLSA Advisory Opinions, 2022
Armenological Issues Bulletin 3 (6) 2015, 229-241, 2015
Association for the Advancement of Psychosynthesis, 2021
International Journal of Unani and Integrative Medicine, 2024
European Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies
Compr Health Biomed Stud., 2024
Journal of Research in Personality, 2020
Pakistan Journal of Biological Sciences, 2021
Uma festa no Rio colonial, Nossa História, n. 5, 2004
Journal of Imaging, 2024
Ana Cabana, Daniel Lanero and Víctor M. Santidrián (eds.), VII Encuentro de Investigadores del franquismo, Santiago de Compostela, Fundación 10 de Marzo, 2011, pp. 571-581, 2011
Waste Management, 2014
African Journal of Biological Sciences, 2020
Ciência & saúde coletiva, 2011
STID Mohammad Natsir, 2024
Sensors and Actuators B: Chemical, 2015
Academia Medicine, 2024
GSC Biological and Pharmaceutical Sciences