Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
13 pages
1 file
This paper argues that time—not autonomy, freedom, or some other related concept—is the conceptual and phenomenological thread running through Minimalism, Conceptual Art, Earth Art, and most of twentieth century Modernism. At the heart of this argument is a view of time as a process rather than a static or eternal concept. When one considers time as a flow of process within which other processes occur, Modernist purity falls away and reveals a tacit phenomenological coherence between many, if not all, Modernist art movements. The role of the viewer is considered equally alongside that of the artist and the two enter into a dialogical relationship with each other and the artwork itself. This relationship happens within time and tacitly deals with it as its phenomenological focus. Instead of formal purity or art as an a priori constant, we see here a view of art as foundationally tied into life is a complicated, messy, and fundamental way. By entertaining a common primary source of nearly all art made by human beings, we might be able to let go of artistic prejudices and feuds more easily and instead focus on what matters-simply making art in all of its varied and wondrous forms.
This contribution analyzes the uses of time linked to materials in contemporary art practices. In the first part of the argument I consider the significance of the contemporary turning away from the normative idea that time should be external or non-intrinsic to fine or visual artworks. The change in mentality concerning the value of time in these works of art has been especially transforming among artists and opened up new opportunities for their creative work. I am particularly interested in the possibilities of an aesthetic translation of the human experience of time into the so-called spatial artworks through the intervention of changeable, non-permanent or non-lasting materials. When time ceases to be seen as a destructive element whose intervention should be avoided, or as a simple subject that the picture tries to depict, it can then be regarded as any other artistic material or as working inside the artistic materials as an active element that can attain a high impact on the final solution of the artistic process. Consequently, artists, viewers, art conservation institutions and so on ought to acknowledge that the temporal nodes should always count as a significant aesthetic component and that the performative temporal dimension is intimately linked to the amplification of the material possibilities in the creative process. In connection with this, I discuss the blurring of the di erence between the real and the representational in art practices and how that affects the very presence of temporal dimensions. The paper concludes with the proposal of a new temporal level in works of art that modifies (our temporal understanding of) the identity of the work.
In this essay, I analyse how it is possible that aesthetic forms can survive through history and genres. In the debate about the historicity of the aesthetic experience, the two main approaches differ on a fundamental point. On one hand, the symbolic theory, based on the cultural tradition (see from Gadamer to Danto), points at the recognition of the proper conceptual contents of the aesthetic properties in order to explain the possibility of the experience of an artwork. On the other hand, there is the post-structuralist theory, for which in the perception both the senses and their means (see C. A. Jones) intervene. This theory asserts that the medium, previously any conceptual mediation, is responsible for the most significant effects in the aesthetic experience. I will argue why both theories are unsatisfying. The idea I want to defend, and which I will ground with a cognitive model based on biological and neurophysiological investigations, is that there are aesthetic mechanisms that can significantly affect our perception to make it focus upon some specific sensitive properties of the object. These properties are neither merely formal nor are sings for symbols, but are perceptively meaningful and, as such, can orientate the aesthetic experience to concrete symbols or meanings. In doing so, it will be possible to understand why some signs or properties (aesthetic forms) are used along art history in relation to some meanings or topics (like Gombrich suggested). (...)
Art History, 2002
Book reviews are always late. Rushing for the deadline, you are already behind time ± the book was conceived, written, designed, printed and published long before you reached it and whatever you write follows on, belatedly. Mieke Bal's Quoting Caravaggio first appeared in hardback in 1999 and so this review is particularly belated in one sense. Yet perhaps this is strangely fitting for a volume which counters any sense of self-assured linear chronology through a sustained engagement with time, quotation, duration and art. If, as Martin Davies argued, the end of the twentieth century was marked by a tragic, selfimposed lateness, a perpetual sense of coming after the event and being left in its wake, 1 Bal's volume provides a strategy for moving beyond belatedness towards a material encounter with history and cultural memory which thinks of temporality as the entanglement of subject and object. Reading this book, you are invited to participate in histories, to make present connections with the past, in and of the spatial and bodily movement of time. What is especially significant for art historians in this encounter is the fact that Quoting Caravaggio enables its readers to engage in its arguments by taking art, history and the histories of art seriously. Quoting Caravaggio focuses on the work of art, attending closely to what art does, rather than what it is. This subtle shift of emphasis has far-reaching ramifications both within the book and beyond its borders. For instance, Bal's volume is beautifully illustrated, yet it is not an illustrated history, if what is meant by that is a text-based thesis on space, time, subjects and objects, lavishly`decorated' by pictures, themselves reduced to texts and`read' in support of abstract arguments. Neither Bal's emphasis upon semiotics, nor her careful visual analysis, suggest that art might be subsumed by text; her argument is far more compelling, pointing towards a position beyond the binary logic which sets word and image apart, and calling for a fuller recognition of the knowledges which are produced by the materiality of art. This stronger position is mapped early in the work, when Bal argues that art works need to be understood as`theoretical objects':`I wish to suggest that such works can be construed as theoretical objects that``theorize'' cultural history. This theorizing makes them such instances of cultural philosophy that they deserve the name theoretical objects.' (p. 5) Quoting Caravaggio unfolds over eight chapters, each tackling a complex conceptual problem around histories, time and the meanings materialized by art. Throughout the volume, art works ± in the stronger sense of the term. Art is never the mute hand-maiden of theory, awaiting the voice of an empowered interpreter to bring it to life; in every configuration of ideas, images and texts, the material call to the sensory, corporeal roots of subjectivity and cognition are brought to bear upon the structure of the argument. Conceived as a theoretical object, art is demonstrated to have an extraordinary capacity to make ideas, and make them. Thinking through and with art renegotiates the parameters of meaning so that spatial embodiment in the world can be seen as a critical precondition of knowledge and the communication of ideas. As Bal writes in the fourth chapter of the volume, meaningful spatiality is intimately entwined with corporeality and location; the embodied subject of history and knowledge does not exist in an empty space, but in a meaningful world: REVIEWS
This essay examines certain assumptions underlying Anglo-American " analytic " aesthetics, and more specifically the areas of that discipline that concern themselves with the nature and significance of art. The issues considered here are seldom discussed by analytic philosophers of art themselves – a matter to be regretted, as I will argue – but they are, nevertheless, of a quite fundamental kind and tell us much about the nature of the discipline, the presuppositions on which it is based, and, as I shall argue in the concluding stages, certain factors that isolate it from the world of art as we now know it. The dilemma I address here also affects the other major school of thought in modern aesthetics – the " Continental " school – but in that context it assumes a somewhat different form which would require separate consideration. To keep discussion within manageable proportions, the focus here is placed principally on the analytic school, a limitation that is perhaps less serious than it might seem given that this approach to the philosophy of art is currently quite influential not only in Anglophone countries but elsewhere as well. The dilemma in question concerns the relationship between art (understood in the general sense of the term) and the passing of time, and to avoid possible confusion, it is important to begin by clarifying what is at stake. The issue here has nothing to do with the function of time within works of art – for example, the ways in which the passing of time might be represented in film or the novel, or the role of tempo in music. Those questions are doubtless valid and important and, as one might expect, philosophers of art discuss them periodically, some employing the term " temporal arts " to identify art forms such as music or poetry in which time seems to play a prominent role. The present discussion, however, concerns the external relationship between art and time, that is, the effects of the passing of time – of history in the broadest sense of the term – on those objects, whether created in our own times or in the distant past, that we today call " works of art ". Given that from the moment of their creation, and whether the creator wills it or no, works of art are, like all other objects, immersed in the world of change – changing values, changing beliefs, changing ways of life – how are they affected, if at all? The question is not, of course, about physical change. Objects such as sculptures and paintings are as vulnerable to damage as any others, and if
Open Cultural Studies, 2018
Inspired by Marx’ view of “untimely temporalities,” I connect my own conception of the need for anachronism in art history with some contemporary artworks focusing on the political importance of art in the present. The analyses of work by three contemporary artists who each bring their own aesthetic of slowness, interruption, and activism to their art leads to a conception of political art as activating rather than directly activist. In addition to Marx, especially his view of temporality, and to Henri Bergson as a major philosopher of time, the article also establishes connections with the ideas of contemporary cultural analyst Kaja Silverman. These three thinkers, each in their own way, undermine the binary oppositions on which so much of thought is based.
Art History, 2002
Art writing normally contrasts art with "everyday life." This book explores art as integral to the everyday life of modern society, providing materials to represent class and class conflict, to explore sex and sexuality, and to think about modern industry and economic relationships. Art, as we know it, is not common to all forms of society but is peculiar to our own; what art is changes with people's conceptions of the tasks of art, conceptions that are themselves a part of social history. The history of society does not shape art from the outside, but includes the attempts of artists to find new ways of making art and thinking about it.
White Holes and the Visualization of the Body, 2019
JOURNAL OF NORTHEASTERN UNIVERSITY, 2022
In debates of art, the term "contemporary" is commonly used to refer to more nebulous, universal concepts such as "the current situation" or "contemporaneity." Often, brief citations of significant works by philosophers such as Giorgio Agamben, Jacques Rancière, and Peter Osborne serve as indicators of the boundaries of theoretical discourse. Before analyzing what these three current theorists have recently said about contemporaneity in general, contemporary art in particular, and the connections between the two, this article explains how I want to approach these subjects. Authors who have made significant contributions to these dialogues, such as artist-theorist Jean-Phillipe Antoine, Néstor Garca Canclini, and Jean-Luc Nancy, are also discussed. The analysis progresses from Agamben's poetic reference to "contemporariness" as a Nietzschean experience of "untimeliness" in relation to one's times, through Nancy's emphasis on art's constant return to its roots, Rancière's attribution of disagreement to the current regime of art, Osborne's adamant assertion of the "post-conceptual" nature of contemporary art, to Canclini's preference for historical art. When presentist immanence attempts to be inclusive, it is essential to restate Antoine's instruction to artists and others to "weave together a particular variety of periods" and to reflect on history.
Revista Crítica de Ciências Sociais
American Ethnologist, 1982
Journal of power electronics
Hispanic Review 74, 4 (2006), 2006
IEEE/CAA Journal of Automatica Sinica, 2023
Inclusão e educação 2, 2019
Journal of international business research, 2020
Revista Eptic, 2011
Acuity: Journal of English Language Pedagogy, Literature and Culture
2008
Case Reports in Psychiatry, 2021
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2014
The Annual of the British School at Athens, 2000
South Asian Journal of Cancer
The Journal of Heart and Lung Transplantation, 2002
Journal of Pharmacy and Pharmacology, 2007
European Journal of Operational Research, 2022