To appear in International Journal of American Linguistics
THE DEFINITE ARTICLE IN YUCATEC MAYA: THE CASE OF LE… O’1
Violeta Vázquez-Rojas Maldonado, Josefina García Fajardo,
Rodrigo Gutiérrez Bravo, and Julia Pozas Loyo
EL COLEGIO DE MÉXICO
1. INTRODUCTION
The aim of this paper is to provide a semantic characterization of a particular determiner
in Yucatec Maya (ISO code: yua, henceforth Yucatec), a Mayan language spoken by
approximately 824,670 speakers (INEGI 2010) in the Yucatan Peninsula, Mexico, and
parts of Belize. In Yucatec, there is a paradigm of determiners formed by a prenominal
element le plus a clitic added at the end of the noun phrase, as pointed out by Andrade
(1955 [1940]), Hanks (1990), Briceño Chel (1996) and Lehmann (1998, 2012), inter alia.
1
First and foremost, we would like to thank Rosa María Couoh Pool, Alfredo Hau Caamal, José
Miguel Kanxoc Kumul, José Asunción Nahuat Canul, Irma Pomol Cahum, Gloria Nayeli Tun Tuz, and
Dalia Tuz Ek for their judgements, translations and comments on the Yucatec data reported here, which are
the core of research presented in this paper. We would also like to thank three anonymous reviewers, as
well as Lisa Matthewson and David Beck for their suggestions, which greatly helped to improve the
structure and content of this paper. Thanks also to Barbara Partee and Donka Farkas for their invaluable
observations and for having directed us to useful references. We would also like to thank the audiences at
the Conference on Indigenous Languages of Latin America (University of Texas at Austin, October 2013)
and at the XII Congreso Nacional de Lingüística (Universidad Autónoma de Querétaro, October 2013) for
their helpful feedback and suggestions. Lastly, many thanks also to Jorge Arroyo for his assistance with the
final typographical revision of this paper. All remaining errors are our own. This research was partially
funded by a grant from PRODEP (formerly PROMEP) for the project Estudio sintáctico y semántico de los
términos que generan la referencialidad nominal y sus inferencias: Un estudio translingüístico, COLMEXCA-47.
1
The resulting forms are shown in the following examples:2
(1)
a.
Le kajtalil way=a’
Le hamlet here=CL
‘This hamlet here’
b.
Le mejen
iik’=o’
le
air=CL
little
(Monforte et al. 2010:23-16)
‘Those tiny spirits’
c.
(Monforte et al. 2010:49-5)
Le janal=e’
le
food=CL
‘That food’
(Briceño Chel 1992:20)
The examples in (1) show the three determiners formed with prenominal le plus a clitic:
le…a’, le…e’ and le...o’, which have been regarded as demonstratives in the relevant
literature. However, a closer look at le…o’, based on data from controlled elicitation and
narrative texts, reveals that this determiner has also the referential functions expected of a
2
The abbreviations used in the examples are the following; 1: first person, 2: second person, 3: third
person, ABS: absolutive, AF: agent focus, CAUS: causative, CIT: reportative, CL: clitic, CLAS: classifier, CP:
completive, CPS: compulsive, DIM: diminutive, DUR: durative, EP: epenthesis, ERG: ergative, EX: existential,
FEM:
feminine, FOC: focus (adverb), HAB: habitual, INCH: inchoative, IND: indicative, IRR: irrealis, LOC:
locative, NEG: negation, PASS: passive, PL: plural, PREP: preposition, PRF: perfect, PRSV: presentative, RDP:
reduplication, SG: singular, TOP: topic, TRM: terminative, TRNS: transitive, V: vowel. The glosses ERG and
ABS
correspond to what is known in traditional Mayan linguistics as the A and B pronominal series. It
should be noted that ergativity in Yucatec is split on the basis of aspect, and hence not every instantiation of
a pronominal element labeled as ERG and ABS necessarily bears an ergative or absolutive grammatical
relation. All examples are presented according to the 1984 phonemic orthographic conventions of the
Academia de la Lengua Maya de Yucatán (CDAM 1984) and so they do not necessarily reflect their
phonetic form accurately. In this orthographical system, symbols have their expected values except for
ch=[tʃ], j=[h], x=[ʃ], and ’=[Ɂ]. We do not provide a morpheme gloss for each of the elements that
constitute the le + clitic complex. Since the purpose of our paper is precisely to find the specific semantic
value for these elements, we will simply gloss le as le and for the terminal clitics we use the gloss “CL”.
2
definite article. The case in favor of this claim has not been systematically argued in
previous analyses of the determiner system of Yucatec. Given the growing interest in
recent literature on the cross-linguistic expression of definiteness (Arkoh & Matthewson
2012; Schwarz 2013), it is of the utmost importance in the grammatical description of a
language to determine the formal resources available in that language to make definite
reference. The results of our investigation allow us to conclude that Yucatec has an
explicit mechanism to signal definite reference and that it consists of the determiner
le...o’ which, in its use as a marker of definiteness, can be characterized as a definite
article.
We assume that a determiner is a syntactic category that is typically comprised of
three sorts of elements: demonstratives, quantifiers, and articles. Determiners are
functional elements in the noun phrase that delimit the reference of the noun that
accompanies them. We adhere to the following general definition provided by
Panagidiotis (2014):
Determiners are a nominal syntactic category distinct both from adjectives
and nouns, despite the close affinity among them. They are commonly
understood to comprise the word classes of article, demonstrative, and
quantifier, as well as some possessives and some nominal agreement
markers.
English demonstratives and articles are examples of determiners. A determiner that is
specialized solely in marking the feature [+/- definite] is usually called a
definite/indefinite article (Gillon 2015:176). A definite article is thus a kind of determiner
that expresses solely definite reference –in other words, a determiner without any deictic
or person component added. In the framework adopted in this paper, noun phrases headed
by a definite article can be identified by their ability to find a referent within the Universe
of Discourse (the set of all entities whose existence is assumed by the interlocutors of a
linguistic exchange). Noun phrases with definite articles, crucially, are able to signal
generic reference, unlike noun phrases headed by other determiners (such as
demonstratives or possessives), but they must also be able to refer to particular
individuals and in general to entities in any subdomain of the Universe of Discourse (UD)
3
(unlike indefinite articles, which may make generic reference, but cannot have an
anaphoric interpretation). In what follows, we show that le...o’ has all of these properties,
and thus that it should be considered a definite article, aside from the fact that a
homophonous item can function as a demonstrative.
This article is organized as follows: in Section 2, we present a brief overview of
nominal expressions in Yucatec and a review of the previous analyses of le…o’, le…a’,
and le…e’. In Section 3, we provide a detailed definition of what we consider a definite
article alongside the empirical criteria needed to identify it. Section 4 presents a
description of the methodology used for elicitation and data collection. In Section 5, we
present the results of our controlled tests as well as some spontaneous data and we
provide the corresponding analyses organized in the four domains in which definite noun
phrases can find their referents, according to the framework put forth in Section 3. In
addition, in Section 5.5 we discuss some examples in which, as stated in previous
analyses, le…o’ functions as a demonstrative. The section concludes with a brief
discussion of the forms le...a’ (1a) and le...e’ (1c). This discussion is intended to show
that, although these two determiners share a number of contexts of use with le…o’, they
do not allow the noun phrase they introduce to find its referent in just any subdomain of
the Universe of Discourse, and therefore they are not definite articles. Finally, in Section
6 we summarize the main conclusions of our research.
2. OVERVIEW OF THE PHENOMENON
In Yucatec, certain noun phrases can be introduced by a determiner le and wrapped by a
clitic following the noun and its modifiers (if there are any). Examples of these
constructions appearing in full sentences are presented below.
(2) le
ko’olel=o’
t–u
ts’–aj–ø
u
ma’alob nook’.
le
woman=CL
CP–ERG:3
put–PRF–ABS:3SG
ERG:3
good
‘and the woman put on her good clothes.’
(3) Le x–ko’olel=a’,
le
yáan
FEM–woman=CL CPS
clothes
(Góngora Pacheco 1990:19-17/18)
u
lu’u–s–ik–ø
teen
ERG:3
leave–CAUS–PRF–ABS:3SG
1SG
4
in
meyaj!
ERG:1SG
work
‘This woman is going to take my job away from me!’
(Ceh Moo 2011:69-11/12)
(4) tumen
le
because le
máak=e’
ma’ ya’ab
person=CL
NEG
much
taak’in t–u
money
CP–ERG:3
‘because the man didn’t leave him much money.’
p’aat–aj–ø
ti’.
leave–PRF–ABS:3SG
PREP
(Ceh Moo 2011:45-4/5)
Most descriptions of these forms in Yucatec claim that the clitics are obligatory in the
presence of le. However, it is not uncommon that in texts and spontaneous speech the
clitics are omitted under certain circumstances. Andrade (1955 [1940]) suggests this is
due to phonotactic reasons (=o’ is omitted after [o], and =a’ is omitted after [a]), but also
to the fact that =o’ is sometimes omitted if the constituent introduced by le is especially
long and complex. Hanks (1990:57) further observes that the clitics are commonly
omitted when the lexical description, gestures, or available knowledge are enough to
identify the referent introduced by le. There is a further morphosyntactic restriction
(which we address in detail in §5.4 below): when two or more nominal expressions with
le co-occur in the post-verbal field, only one of them can show its clitic. However, in the
absence of these conditions the clitics are obligatory. While the bulk of our paper deals
with the form le…o’ and how we analyze it as a definite article, in what follows we will
occasionally need to compare it with the two other forms, le…a’ and le…e’. Alongside
this comparison we present some facts about le…a’ and le…e’ that have not been
considered (or have only been mentioned in passing) in the previous literature.
Since the constructions introduced by le characteristically correspond to noun
phrases, we now provide a brief description of nominal expressions in Yucatec. There are
a fair number of detailed descriptions of nominal expressions in this language, such as
Briceño Chel (1993, 1996) and Lehmann (1998), and brief comments on the properties of
Yucatec nominal expressions can be found in Andrade (1955 [1940]), Lucy (1992),
Verhoeven (2007:105–107) and numerous other works. The description we provide
5
below is merely introductory and makes reference only to those properties of Yucatec
nominal expressions that are related to the discussion of definite determiners that follows.
For more detailed descriptions, we refer the reader to the works cited above.
In their most basic form, nominal expressions in Yucatec can be made up of a bare noun
with no inflectional morphology. Bare nouns are allowed in argument position, with a
collective interpretation as in (5) or with a mass interpretation as in (6):
(5) …utia’al u
chan
man–ik–ø
máak
for
DIM
buy–IND–ABS:3SG
person thing
ERG:3
jaan–t–ø
bey=o’.
eat– TRNS–ABS:3SG
thus=CL
ba’al
u
ERG:3
‘…for people to buy a little thing to eat like that.’ (Monforte et al. 2010:101-9)
(6)
Maria–e’
t–u
man–aj–ø
sakam.
María–TOP
CP–ERG:3
buy–PRF–ABS:3SG tortilla.dough
‘María bought tortilla dough.’
Nominal inflection is fairly poor in Yucatec and possibly the most common
inflectional category is plurality. Plural marking is not restricted to animate nouns, as in
(7); it is also possible with inanimates, as shown in (8).
(7)
a. ko’olel–o’ob
woman–PL
‘women’
(Lehmann 1998:19)
b. ba’alche’–ob
animal–PL
‘animals’
(8)
(Monforte et al. 2010:16-3)
a. naj–o’ob
6
house–PL
‘houses’
(Monforte et al. 2010:24-8)
b. ba’al–o’ob
thing–PL
‘things’
(Monforte et al. 2010:14-16)
Plural marking is optional (as can be seen in (9a) below),3 although high animacy and
definiteness strongly favor that a semantically plural noun display plural morphology
(Lucy 1992; Lehmann 1998:19). Nominal expressions may include numerals and numeral
classifiers (Lucy 1992; Briceño Chel 1993). There are only four Mayan cardinals
currently in use in Yucatec: jun ‘one’, ka’a ‘two’, óox ‘three’, and kan ‘four’. Numerals
obligatorily appear with a numeral classifier or a mensurative expression, which are
formally (i.e. morphosyntactically) identical in Yucatec. This is illustrated in (9):
a. ka’a túul peek’
(9)
two
CLAS
dog
‘two dogs’
b. jun
one
(Briceño Chel 1996:98)
kúul che’
CLAS
wood
‘one tree’
c. jun
p’íit
(Góngora Pacheco 1990:30-14)
taak’in
one little.bit money
3
A reviewer notes that, given that plural marking is optional, it might not be an inflectional category
at all. In our view, inflectional categories are not necessarily characterized by being obligatory. The fact
that the plural suffix -(o)‘ob can attach to almost any member of the (count) nominal class, and that it does
not involve a categorial or distributional change in the base, speaks in favor of its inflectional nature. In any
case, the discussion is not germane to the main point of this paper, and if some later analysis shows that the
plural suffix in Yucatec is not an inflectional category, this would not affect our central claims in any way.
7
‘a little bit of money’
(Monforte et al. 2010:308-4)
For numbers five and above, Spanish numerals are used. In these cases, the classifier
appears as a possessed element, as can be seen in (10a), where the ergative pronoun
preceding a nominal functions as a possessive marker. The classifier is also accompanied
by a -Vl suffix (where V copies the vowel of the stem), as in (10a). Example (10b) shows
that classifiers are optional with Spanish numerals.
(10) a. trece
thirteen
u
p’éel–el
ERG:3 CLAS–RDP
waaj
tortilla
‘thirteen tortillas’
b. cinco
five
(Monforte et al. 2010:138-5)
k’áan
hammock
‘Five hammocks’
(Monforte et al. 2010:30-19)
Consider now the morphosyntactic properties of nominal expressions introduced by
le. As first shown in examples (1-4), le requires the presence of one of three clitics, =a’,
=o’, or =e’. These elements are phrasal clitics since they appear at the right edge of
nominal expressions irrespective of how much material appears between the head noun
and this edge. Consequently, noun phrases bracketed by le + clitic sequences can also
include embedded verb phrases or clauses. The latter case can be seen in the following
examples with relative clauses:
(11) [le x–ch’úupal [k–u
le
FEM–girl
HAB–ERG:3
wen–el=i’]]=o’…4
sleep-IND=LOC=CL
‘The girl that sleeps there.’
4
(Góngora Pacheco 1990:30-18)
As noted by two anonymous reviewers, example (11) is unusual because only one clitic is ever
allowed to appear in any given clitic position in Yucatec (Hanks 1990: 491), yet in this case two different
clitics appear on the right edge of this constituent: the clitic =o’ related to le, and a free-standing locative
clitic =i’ semantically related to the embedded verb wen-el ‘sleep’. At present we do not have any
8
(12) [ le
máak
le
[ ts’o’on–ø]]=o’.
person
shoot:PASS–ABS:3SG=CL
‘The person that was shot.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:65-4)
When a clause is embedded in the nominal expression, as in the examples above, the
right edge of the noun phrase is aligned with the right edge of the embedded clause, and it
is in this position that =a’, =o’, or =e’ are cliticized (Gutiérrez-Bravo 2012). In these
examples, the clitic at the right edge of the relative clauses is =o’, since the le…o’
sequence is the primary object of our study: however, similar text examples can readily
be found with the clitics =a’ and =e’.
Le can co-occur with other pre-nominal constituents. In Yucatec, as in other Mayan
languages, ergative pronouns also function as possessives, as in (10a). In (13) we show
that le can co-occur with the ergative proclitics:
(13) le u
le ERG:3
y–íicham=o’
EP–husband=CL
‘Her husband’
(Monforte et al. 2010:27-14)
Example (14) shows that le can also co-occur simultaneously with both ergative proclitics
functioning as possessive pronouns and with the numerals previously described.
(14) le in
ka’a
túul
w–íits’in–o’ob=a’
le
two
CLAS
EP–younger.sibling–PL=CL
ERG:1SG
‘These two younger siblings of mine’
(Briceño Chel 1996:101)
explanation for this fact, nor do we have any other examples displaying this behavior. However, since =i’ is
an anaphoric locative clitic that is not in a paradigmatic relation with the clitics that appear with le (see
Hanks 1990: 545, fn. 18), analyzing its specific morphosyntactic properties is not directly relevant to the
semantic analysis that we develop in what follows. As such, we leave this issue open for future research.
9
For ease of exposition in this paper we focus exclusively on constructions where le is
the only prenominal constituent. Lastly, observe that the clitics =a’, =o’, and =e’ are also
obligatorily found with other determiners/adverbial elements, most notably the
presentative je’, the locative te’, and the adverb bey ‘thus’ (which can be found with =a’
or =o’, but not with =e’).5 This is illustrated for je’ and te’ in the following examples
from Briceño Chel (1992).
(15) a. Je’
PRSV
janal=a’.
food=CL
‘Here’s the food.’
b. Je’
PRSV
janal=o’.
food=CL
‘There’s the food.’
(16) a. te’
LOC
kaaj=o’
town=CL
‘in that town’
b. te’ kaaj=e’
LOC town=CL
‘in that (distant) town’
These examples show that the terminal clitics are separable from the prenominal element
le, and that they very likely contribute deictic content not only to determiners, but also to
adverbs of location, adverbs of manner and presentatives. It makes sense, therefore, to
consider that determiners that co-occur with these clitics are always deictic (hence,
5
Observe, however, that the impossibility of combining bey with the clitic =e’ only holds in those
cases where there is no intervening material between bey and the terminal clitic (see Hanks 1990: 545, fn
17). For a complete description of the properties of =a’, =o’, and =e’ with these other determiners/adverbs,
see Hanks (1984, 1990, 2005).
10
demonstratives). However, as we will argue, this is not necessarily the case with the
determiner le…o’. Before we begin our analysis of le…o’ as a definite article in Yucatec,
there is an important descriptive and analytical issue to address. While it is unanimously
accepted that the clitics =a’ and =o’ are in a paradigmatic relation to one another, the
status of the clitic =e’ is considerably more controversial. The clitic =e’ observed in the
le…e’ construction in (1c) and (4) is homophonous with (at least) two other clitics widely
observed in Yucatec: the topic clitic in (17), and the clitic that functions as a clause linker
(“continuator” in the terminology of Verhoeven 2007) in (18):6
(17) Pero leti’=e’
but 3SG=TOP
k–u
p’áat–al te’
jool=o’.
HAB–ERG:3
stay–IND
door=CL
LOC
‘But her, she stayed at the door.’
(18) In
ERG:1SG
(Monforte et al. 2010:27-14)
k’áat–ø=e’
káa
k’áax–ak–ø
ja’.
wish–ABS:3SG=CL
SUBJ
fall–IRR–ABS:3SG
water
‘I wish that it would rain.’
(Verhoeven 2007:126)
In (17), =e’ attaches to a noun phrase that corresponds to the topic of the sentence. In
(18), it cliticizes to a verbal element, rather than to a nominal one.
Since these three clitics (the topic marker, the clause linker and the =e’ clitic used in
determiners) are widely used in Yucatec, it is worth considering whether they are not one
and the same clitic, instead of three different homophonous elements, as we claim.7 There
are indeed many cases where, for instance, distributionally it is not possible to distinguish
the =e’ clitic that accompanies le and the other two clitics. For instance, in (19) it is not
straightforward to claim that =e’ is the clitic that accompanies le, or if it is the same topic
clitic as the one observed in (17). Recall that, when two clitics compete for a host, only
6
The clause linker clitic optionally signals the right edge of the clause. Its precise behavior and
function are still poorly understood, but the existing evidence indicates that its distribution appears to be
conditioned by prosodic, and not syntactic or semantic requirements: see for instance Verhoeven &
Skopeteas (2015).
7
We thank two anonymous IJAL reviewers for bringing this issue to our attention.
11
one of them can actually occupy the slot, so in (19) it is not be possible to know if there is
only one clitic =e’ corresponding to a determiner, or if there is a clitic =e’ marking a
topic, or both:
(19) Le nojoch máasewáal máak=e’ chéen
le big
Indian
person=CL only
t–u
pak–t–aj–ø…
CP–ERG:3
look–TRNS–PRF–ABS:3SG
‘The large Indian man just stared at him…’
(Ceh Moo 2011:58-20/21)
In spite of this distributional overlap, syntactically it is actually possible to
distinguish between these three clitics. First, the clitic that functions as a clause linker is
only observed in segments of discourse or complex constructions where more than one
clause or sentence is involved. Second, sentence topics with the =e’ clitic always occupy
a clause-initial position, as expected of sentence topics in general. Now observe that in
examples (20) and (21) neither of these two conditions is met. In these examples, there is
no other clause following =e’ (in fact, (21) is a monoclausal construction), so =e’ cannot
be functioning as a clause linker:
(20) …leti’ túun=e’ t–u
3SG then=TOP
CP–ERG:3
beet–aj–ø
u
chéen leti’ jun–puul=i’
do–PRF–ABS:3SG
ERG:3
only 3SG one–CLAS=CL
máax ts’íib–ø
tuláakal ba’al t–u
who write.AF–ABS:3SG
every
thing
PREP–ERG:3
yo’olal le
kaaj=e’.
about
town=CL
le
‘And that made him the first and only one who wrote everything about the town.’
(Ceh Moo 2011:49-12/14)
(21) T–u
CP–ERG:3
tukl–aj–ø
bey–o’
le
think–PRF–ABS:3SG thus=CL le
‘The young man thought about it thus.’
xi’ipal–e’.
young.man=CL
{txt}
Perhaps more importantly, the nominal expressions with le…e’ in these cases do not
occupy the clause-initial position, which eliminates the possibility of =e’ being the
12
sentence topic clitic. For our purposes, what is relevant is that there are both text and
elicited examples where it is clear that =e’ is neither a topic marker nor a clause linker.
Hence, data like this justify our stance that the clitic =e’ at the right edge of nominal
expressions introduced by le can be taken to be a different clitic altogether.
Having clarified this important descriptive issue about the clitic sequences that will
be the core of our analysis, we now have a general idea of the structure of noun phrases in
Yucatec. Next, we provide a survey of the analyses and descriptions of the paradigm of
determiners made up by le and a terminal clitic that can be found in the literature.
In the grammatical sketch by Bricker et al. (1998:382), le is described as a definite
article, but this work does not mention anything about the relation between le and the
clitics it appears with, and no description or analysis of nominal expressions introduced
by le is provided either. The descriptions by Blair (1964) and Andrade (1955 [1940]) of
le and its relation with the clitics are somewhat more detailed. Blair (1964:122–124)
explicitly characterizes le as a demonstrative, and he describes the clitics that accompany
it as deictic elements. Hence he claims that =o’ “refers to something not so immediate in
time or space. It often translates as that or there,” (Blair 1964:123), in contrast with =a’
which he describes as referring to something near in time or space. The clitic =e’ is
actually the one for which Blair provides the most elaborate description, mentioning that
it “may refer to something in mind, something already under discussion, or it may mark
or set a topic to be commented on. Thus it often may be translated as the or as for though
frequently it is not translated at all” (Blair 1964:123). Therefore, in Blair’s description the
sequence that is taken to be the closest one in meaning with a definite article is le… e’, in
contrast with the analysis that we develop in what follows. It should be pointed out,
however, that the descriptions of the clitics provided by Blair are not specific to the
meaning they convey when they are found in combination with le: the deictic contrasts
described by this author are taken to be the same irrespective of the element that these
clitics appear combined with. Accordingly, in this work there is no specific description of
nominal expressions introduced by le and then combined with =o’. Similarly, Briceño
Chel (1996:96) assigns to these elements a strictly demonstrative function and explicitly
claims that Yucatec does not have a definite article.
13
The analysis by Andrade (1955 [1940]) shares some characteristics with the analyses
of Blair (1964) and Briceño Chel (1996), but it is different in that Andrade does not
assign to le and the clitics it appears with a uniquely demonstrative function. With respect
to the clitics observed in these constructions, Andrade (1955 [1940]: §4.51) points out
that:
[t]he terminal component -a’ is used exclusively in ostensive references to
items nearer to the speaker than to the listener, or to a time contemporary
with that in which the reference is made; or in reference to what the
speaker proceeds to demonstrate, exemplify, or speak of. -o’ is used both
in ostensive and in retrospective references. In ostensive references, the
item is nearer to the listener than to the speaker, or roughly at about the
same distance from both. For retrospective references, either -o’ or -e’ are
used, depending mainly on topical distinction.
For Andrade, “ostensive reference” corresponds to the extralinguistic context, while
“retrospective” reference points to elements in the discourse. With respect specifically to
the combination of le with these clitics, Andrade labels them as “contextual definitives”,
and suggests that le…=a’ is used only for ostensive reference, whereas le…=o’ is used
for both ostensive and retrospective reference. Finally, regarding le…=e’ in particular,
Andrade points out that (1955 [1940]:§4.51):
[t]he form le […]-e’ is used in retrospective references and in vague references to
what may be present or occur in a non-immediate future time. In retrospective
references, le […]-e’ is not used when the identity of the item specified by [the
nominal expression] is the dominant topic. Aside from such instances, it is difficult
to disclose what governs the choice of le […]-e’ or le […]-o’ in retrospective
references.
Importantly, Andrade’s distinction between “ostensive” and “retrospective” reference
does not correspond to a distinction between definite and demonstrative determiners. A
definite article is a determiner that exclusively marks definiteness (to be characterized
14
more precisely below) while having no deictic content, unlike demonstratives. Given that
both demonstratives (which are deictic determiners) and definite articles can have
ostensive reference and retrospective reference, this distinction is orthogonal to the
categories of demonstrative/definite article. Furthermore, since Andrade’s work is not
explicit on this matter, there is no reason to assume that he considers le…o’ to be a
definite article on these grounds.
Much more elaborate analyses of le and the clitics that it appears with are developed
by Hanks (1984, 1990, 2005) and Bohnemeyer (2012). In contrast with the works cited
above, Hanks’ proposal is that le and its clitics are not primarily used for ostensive/deictic
reference. It is beyond the scope of this paper to provide a summary of Hanks’ analysis
that would minimally cover this author’s findings with respect to the use of le and its
clitics in specific spatial and social contexts. Let us just point out that Hanks describes
le…a’ and le…o’ as nominal deictics, composed of le, which he takes to be by itself a
definite article (Hanks 1990:18-19, 21), plus the terminal deictics =a’ and =o’. It is not
clear if the term “definite article” is used here to refer to a determiner without inherent
deictic content, since Hanks describes le as an “initial deictic” (where “initial deictic” is
the term used to group the initial component of deictic expressions that combine with
“terminal deictics” such as =a’ and =o’). Furthermore, it should be noted that the analysis
of these forms is only a subpart of a larger analysis of deictic expressions in Yucatec in
which the function of initial deictics (i.e., le for the case at hand) is to orient “the
interactants to the character of a referent and its role in the predication”, whereas the
terminal deictics provide the “indexical grounding of the reference in the given portion of
the interactive framework” (Hanks 1990:27). For our purposes, however, what is crucial
is that this author specifically claims that le by itself corresponds to a definite article
(Hanks 1984:155, Table 1, Hanks 1990:18-19, 21 and 163, Hanks 2005:198, Table 1). As
will be discussed in detail in what follows, our proposal is different from this claim.
Lastly, there is the analysis by Bohnemeyer (2012), which focuses on the spatial
properties conveyed by le + clitic sequences. Based on elicited and spontaneous data, he
argues, contra Hanks (2005), that the location of the addressee does not determine the
choice of the clitic. As such, the discussion of le…o’ in this work centers around the
spatial properties of its referents and how they are different from those of the le…a’
15
sequence. More to the point, in Bohnemeyer’s analysis only le…a’ is “semantically
specified for exophoric reference” (Bohnemeyer 2012:106), while le…o’ has a “more
general indexical meaning”, which includes exophoric uses but is “also used for
anaphoric reference and definiteness marking” (2012:116). Although there is no explicit
definition of “definiteness” in Bohnemeyer (2012), he seems to identify definite
descriptions with those whose referent has been previously mentioned or is “assumed by
the speaker to be uniquely identifiable to the addressee” (2012:106).
Summing up, although there are various and considerably different analyses of le and
the clitics it appears with, there is yet no systematic analysis showing that the le…o’
sequence has the properties of a definite article: it is precisely this proposal that we will
argue in favor of in this paper. In order to make our point clear, in the following section
we present the theoretical framework that we use in our analysis of le…o’ as a definite
article.
3. A CHARACTERIZATION OF THE DEFINITE ARTICLE
Our analysis of Yucatec determiners is largely based on García Fajardo’s (1985 [1984],
1989, 1990, 1994) approach, which considers that the meaning of a definite article
consists of instructing the hearer to locate a set of entities that fit the description provided
by the noun phrase within any of the components of the Universe of Discourse, a concept
that we explain in detail below. We use the term “definite description” to refer to noun
phrases that are explicitly headed by a definite article. The term “definite description”
helps us set apart phrases with definite articles from noun phrases headed by
demonstratives or possessives, which shall be named, respectively, “demonstrative
descriptions” and “possessive descriptions”. We set aside the problem of whether
determinerless noun phrases in some languages can be considered “definite descriptions”
simply because they make (some sort of) definite reference.
Historically, formal analyses of definite descriptions emphasized their uniqueness
inferences (Russell 1905), their reference to a previously mentioned entity
(Christophersen 1939, Heim 1983), and their inclusive character (Hawkins 1978). These
notions (uniqueness, familiarity and inclusiveness) are central to the use of definite
descriptions; nevertheless, the structure of the domain in which these properties arise still
16
needed to be defined. This leads to the definition of the “Universe of Discourse” (UD), as
stated originally by García Fajardo (1985 [1984]), a crucial concept that serves as the
basis for the framework adopted in this paper. The Universe of Discourse amounts to the
set of all possible referents at a given communicative exchange, and these referents are
organized into multiple sub-domains or “components”, which we will explain below. In
this framework, the definite article is given a syncategorematic or “instructional”
meaning. Its role is to direct the listener toward the set that has the properties described
by the NP and that belongs to UD. When singular definite descriptions (such as the cat in
English or el gato in Spanish) pick out one element (i.e., when they have a particular—
non-generic—interpretation), the information ‘one entity’ combines with the meaning
that we just assigned to the definite article: “set in the Universe of Discourse with the
properties described by NP” (García Fajardo 1985 [1984]). The combination of these two
pieces of information leads to the following inference: “the set in UD that fulfills the
description provided by NP has only one element”, and this inference is the uniqueness
presupposition that has been traditionally associated with the definite article. As such,
uniqueness is inferred as a presupposition that arises from the meaning provided by the
definite article when it combines with the conceptual information provided by the NP. If
there is more than one element in some component of UD (e.g., if there are three entities
in the speech situation that fulfill the property described by NP), then the singular noun
phrase with the definite article picks out one element; however, the inference “the set in
UD has only one element with the properties described by NP” makes the construction
inappropriate for such a situation. Nevertheless, the phrase with the definite article may
target another subdomain of UD that satisfies the presupposition.
The UD is a theoretical construct that represents a domain assumed to be shared by
the interlocutors of a linguistic exchange, and it is constituted by all the entities to which
definite descriptions may be targeted. The UD is organized into the following four
components:
Discourse Interpretation Level: the subdomain of entities that have been
previously introduced in the discourse, and the relations among them.
17
Perceptual Representation of the Speech Situation: the subdomain of entities
which are physically present during the utterance act.
Representation of Previous Particular States: the subdomain of entities that
belong to the memories shared by the interlocutors.
Conceptual Information: the subdomain of entities that belong to the extension of
the conceptual information described by the noun phrase, considering only the
noun and its modifiers (i.e. the Noun Phrase, as opposed to the whole Determiner
Phrase).
Thus, in this approach uniqueness is generated as a presupposition which is logically
inferred from the meaning proposed for the definite article plus the information about the
number of referents and the descriptive content of the noun, without adding any further
stipulation to the theory or any explicit content of unique reference to the article’s
meaning. Moreover, the semantic content proposed for the definite article allows us to
explain why speakers are able to make generic reference (i.e. they can refer to the total
extension of the set named by the NP) using definite descriptions.
As we will see, the generic use of definite descriptions is crucial for distinguishing them
from other definite noun phrases, like demonstrative and possessive descriptions, since
the last two cannot receive generic interpretations. What characterizes definite
descriptions in our framework is the requisite of finding a referent within any of the four
subdomains of UD: since Conceptual Information is a subdomain of UD, it is possible to
obtain the generic reading directly, without any additional rearrangement of the formal
system. Definite noun phrases that are not definite descriptions pose other restrictions
(such as possession or distal deixis), which do not allow them to pick out all the extension
of the noun phrase in any subcomponent of UD. In other words, demonstrative and
possessive descriptions may find their referent in some of the subdomains of UD, but
only phrases with a definite article may have any of the four subdomains of UD as their
possible domain of reference.
To confirm that le...o’ in Yucatec is indeed a definite article, and not simply a
demonstrative, we must show that noun phrases headed by this determiner can refer to
sets within any of the components of UD: the Discourse Representation Level, the
18
Perceptual Interpretation of the Speech Situation, the Representation of Previous
Particular States and the Conceptual Information level. In other words, they must be able
to make anaphoric reference, to refer to entities in the physical context surrounding the
speech act, to refer to individuals that belong in the memories of the interlocutors, and to
make generic reference. In contrast, demonstratives are not capable of making the last
kind of reference, although they may overlap with definite articles in picking out entities
in the first three subdomains.
4. METHODOLOGY
The data presented here were collected with questionnaires involving both acceptability
judgment tasks and production tasks, although texts were used as a secondary source of
data. Oral texts were taken mostly from Monforte et al. (2010) and Stolz et al. (2012),
and some data were also collected from a novel (Ceh Moo 2011). The questionnaires
were based on the framework presented in §3. The questions were designed to test
whether speakers could locate the referent of noun phrases with each of the three
determiners (le...a’, le...e’ and le...o’) within each of the four domains of UD. Our
purpose is to investigate whether one of these determiners corresponds to a definite
article. According to the framework described in §3, if a determiner is a definite article,
then its corresponding noun phrase should be felicitously used in any of the four
following settings: (a) tracing an antecedent that has been previously mentioned
(Discourse Representation Level); (b) locating a referent in the speech situation
(Perceptual Interpretation of the Speech Situation); (c) recovering a referent from shared
memories between interlocutors (Representation of Previous Particular States) and, (d)
making generic reference (Conceptual Information). Additionally, we tested the use of
each determiner in different deictic situations and in scenarios that either satisfied or did
not satisfy uniqueness conditions. Importantly, this does not entail that other forms
cannot refer to entities in some or other components.
Two questionnaires were used. The first questionnaire included 94 entries, and the
second one included 26. Our consultants were native Yucatec speakers from eastern
Yucatan, who were also fluent speakers of Spanish as a second language. The two
questionnaires were elicited first with one consultant, and then they were replicated with
19
other consultants. All participants ranged in the age of 21-30. In the tags used to label the
data obtained with these questionnaires, the initials correspond to the initials of each
collaborator, the first number after the dash to the number of the questionnaire (1 or 2),
and the second number and/or letter to the specific item in the questionnaire.
Following standard practice in semantic fieldwork (Matthewson 2004), the questions
were designed to obtain grammaticality, truth-value, and felicity judgments. Each data
point consists of a pair <sentence, context>. We collected these judgments basically by
two strategies: in one of them, the elicitor presented a context to a speaker and then asked
if a particular sentence in Yucatec (which had been constructed by the elicitor and
previously checked for grammaticality) was acceptable and true in such a context. This is
known as an acceptability judgment task. The other strategy was based on production
tasks: a context was described, along with a communicative intention (e.g., “There is one
table right in front of us, how would you ask me to clean it?”), and the speaker was asked
to give a sentence in Yucatec that conveyed such communicative intention in the context
provided (i.e. a free translation task). As stated by Matthewson (2004:386), the outcome
of a production task should be considered a grammatical sequence in the object language
(assuming, as we do, that the consultant is being cooperative). We further assume that the
sentence provided must also be felicitous in the context presented and true (if it is a
declarative sentence), otherwise it would have not been volunteered as an adequate
expression for the context. This kind of task was particularly useful when eliciting
anaphoric links and in prompting generic statements. These sentences were later modified
(with the relevant variable being the choice of the determiner) and judged by the
consultant compared to the same context in which the original sentence had been
provided, resorting to the first strategy described above (i.e. acceptability judgment task).
The contexts for each question were stated verbally in Spanish to avoid priming in the
object language. Note that the aim of our inquiry is to determine whether le…o’, le…a’
and le...e’ can be used in different contexts. Therefore, describing the context verbally in
Yucatec would have forced us to use of the very determiner whose choice we wanted to
test. In contrast, stating the context in Spanish avoided using le…o’ (or le...a’, or le...e’)
before asking the relevant question.
20
When the contexts in the questionnaires were not stated only verbally, they included
the physical setting up of “scenes”, which provided the context needed to judge the
acceptability of a sentence or to refer to a particular object. When asked to provide a
description of a certain situation, or to judge if a certain sentence was acceptable in a
given context, the speaker was asked to do so as if he were talking to an addressee, which
was often the elicitor—that is, the elicitor avoided asking questions like “How would I
say” / “Could I say x”, and instead the speaker was asked “How would you describe x to
someone?”, “How would you ask me to do y?”, or “Would you say z?” The speaker was
instructed to refer to certain objects in different spatial configurations, or was asked to
judge the acceptability of some statements referring to the situation. When the elicitor
asked the speaker to translate a sentence from Spanish to Maya, a clear and complete
context of the intended situation of use was provided. We did not rely on translations
from Maya to Spanish, but we did consider speakers’ comments as potential clues for
hypothesis design.
As for textual examples, we looked for occurrences of le...o’ in which it was clear that
the noun phrase was either referring to an entity that had been previously mentioned
(Discourse Interpretation Level) or to an entity that had not been mentioned explicitly but
that was part of the shared memories of the interlocutors. Given the nature of the data, it
was hard, but not impossible, to find instances of le…o’ that referred to entities which
were present in the speech situation. Lastly, we also looked for uses of le...o’ that made
reference to a whole class of objects (generics). When searching in texts, we only focused
on le...o’, in order to confirm that the results that our questionnaires had yielded were
supported by naturally occurring data.
5. ANALYSIS AND RESULTS
Our results show that le...o’ can appear felicitously in any of the four conditions
described, and hence, it corresponds to a definite article. These findings were also
corroborated in texts. We present the relevant data below. In section 5.6, we show that the
two other determiners were not accepted in every context in which definite articles are
expected to be felicitous, according to the results of our elicitation tasks.
21
5.1 Discourse Interpretation level
This level refers to the subdomain of UD which consists of all the entities that have been
previously introduced in the current discourse, along with the relations among them. At
this level, discourse interpretation is constructed step by step, utterance by utterance, with
the help of grammatical and conceptual information. Some definite descriptions find their
reference in the interpretation of a previous noun phrase, as in (22):
(22)
I remember our grandfather’s study. There was a desk near the window, there
were also a couch and some books in that room. The desk was always covered in
piles of paper.
In (22), the noun “desk” is first used with an indefinite article at the beginning of the
second sentence. In the last sentence, the definite description “the desk” refers back to the
same entity referred to by “a desk”. The anaphoric relation in (22) is direct. However, the
antecedent of a definite description may also be presented by a different noun that holds a
conceptual relation with it, for example a hypernym. In (23) “the fruit” refers to the entity
introduced by “apples and grapes”, and the association is possible because “fruit” is a
hypernym of the other two nouns.
(23)
Last Saturday I went to the market and bought some apples and grapes. I also
bought some cheese, meat, and wine. When I arrived home, I realized that the
fruit was not in the bag.
One more way of establishing anaphoric relations is by associating the referent of a
noun with some of its parts.
(24)
I remember our grandfather’s studio. The desk was in front of the window.
In (24), “desk” and “window” are associated with the aforementioned “studio” in a
meronymic relation: by world knowledge, we associate studios with these kinds of
entities as their parts. It is the part-whole relation that licenses the anaphoric definite noun
22
phrase “the window” and “the desk”, since they refer to entities indirectly introduced by
the noun “studio” in the Discourse Representation Level of UD.
Consider now the following elicited data from Yucatec, where the first mention of a
piglet involves the cardinal jun, ‘one’, while the second mention of this same individual
is obtained by means of a noun phrase with le...o’:
(25) Síib–ø
teen jun túul chan
give:gift:PASS–ABS:3SG 1SG one
CLAS
small pig
ba’ale’ le
chan
k’éen=o’, t–in
but
small
pig=CL
le
k’éek’en yéetel jun
and
one
túul
t’eel,
CLAS
rooster
kon–aj–ø.
CP–ERG:1SG
sell–PRF–ABS:3SG
Intended reading: ‘I was given a little pig and a rooster, but the pig, I sold it’.
(AN-2-26b)
The elicitation showed that noun phrases with le...o’, like le chan k’éen=o’, ‘the little pig’
in (25), can establish direct anaphoric relations with an antecedent, which is evidence that
they can find a referent in what was introduced above as the Discourse Representation
Level of UD.
Data extracted from narrative texts corroborate this finding. Example (26a)
introduces a new entity (‘a man’) at the beginning of a story. Reference to this same
individual is then recovered several sentences later in the text by le maak=o’ ‘the man’,
in (26b).8
(26) a. Yaan–chaj–ø
EX–INCH:CP–ABS:3SG
jun túul
máak=e’
yaan–ø
one
person=CL
EX–ABS:3SG ERG:3
CLAS
‘There was once a man who owned a cornfield…’
b. K–u
y–a’al–ik–ø
HAB–ERG:3 EP–say–IND–ABS:3SG
8
le
maak=o’
le
person=CL
u
kool
cornfield
(Stolz et al. 2012:38)
The orthography in the examples taken from Stolz et al. (2012) has been modified according to the
conventions we use in this paper. All the glosses and free translations are our own.
23
‘The man said:’
(Stolz et al. 2012:39)
A similar situation is presented in (27), where the antecedent noun phrase in (27a) is jun
p’éel kaan ‘a snake’, and the anaphoric noun phrase is le káan=o’ in (27b).
(27) a. K–u
HAB–ERG:3
k’uch–ul=e’
k–u
y–il–ik–ø=e’
jun
arrive–IND=CL
HAB–ERG:3
EP–see–IND–ABS:3SG=CL
one
p’éel kaan
CLAS
snake
‘When he arrived he saw it was a snake.’
b. Pero le máak=o’
but
le person=CL
le
kaan=o’.
le
snake=CL
káa t–u
then
CP–ERG:3
ch’a’–aj–ø
óotsilil
ti’
take–PRF–ABS:3SG
pity
PREP
‘But then the man felt pity for the snake.’
(Stolz et al. 2012:40)
From these examples we conclude that noun phrases with le...o’ are capable of referring
directly to an entity that was introduced explicitly in a previous passage of discourse.
Discourse-anaphoric reference with le...o’ is not limited to particular entities
introduced by noun phrases; it is also possible with abstract entities, like time intervals,
which are accessed indirectly by the description of events, as in (28):
(28) Le tiempo k–in
le
time
HAB–ERG:1SG
k
líik’–il
meyaj
ERG:1PL
rise–IND
work
w–a’al–ik–ø
teech=o’
temprano
EP–say–IND–ABS:3SG
2SG=CL
early
‘At the time I’m telling about we would rise to go work early.’
24
(Monforte et al. 2010:26-24, 25)
In (28), the antecedent of le tiempo kin wa’alik teecho’, ‘the time I’m telling you about’,
is not the referent of a previous single noun phrase, but a whole time span that comprises
the events that have been narrated in the preceding stretch of discourse (not included here
for reasons of space).
Lastly, in (29), we witness a particular type of anaphora in which the referent of the
noun phrase with le…o’ is not exactly the previously introduced plural entity. The
following examples are taken from a narrative where the speaker has been talking about
an old couple.
(29) a. In
teen=e’
w–íicham
ERG:1SG EP–husband 1SG=TOP
ch’a’–aj–ø
si’
grab–PRF–ABS:3SG firewood
k–u
bin=e’, k–u
HAB–ERG:3
go=CL
HAB–ERG:3
ti’
le
nukuch máak–o’ob=o’.
PREP
DM
great
bin
go
person–PLUR=CL
‘My husband, he used to go, he would go fetch firewood for the old folks.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:27-9, 10)
b. Le nojoch máak=o’
le
big
leti’=e’
person=CL 3SG=TOP
k–u
sáastal
HAB–ERG:3 to.dawn
día
ti’
yaan–ø
te’ jool
le
corral=o’.
day
PREP
EX–ABS:3SG LOC entrance le
corral=CL
k–u
máan
HAB–ERG:3
pass
‘The old lady, from dusk until the (whole) day had passed, she, she was there at
the corral’s gate.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:27-11, 12)
25
The noun phrase with le…o’ in (29b) does not refer to the totality of people mentioned (le
nukuch máako’obo’, ‘the old people’ in (29a)), but instead only recovers a part of it: le
nukuch máako’ ‘the old lady’.9
5.2. Perceptual Representation of the Speech Situation
This component of UD corresponds to the subdomain of entities which are physically
present during the speech act (i.e. entities we perceive in the scene in which the speech
occurs). For instance, we may express (30), when sitting at the table for dinner; or (31), at
the beach, looking at a boy who plays with sand at a distance of twelve feet; or (32),
while watching a ship on the horizon:
(30) Pass the salt, please.
(31) The boy is building a beautiful sand castle.
(32) The ship has a little flag; do you see it?
In these examples, definite descriptions are felicitously used regardless of the distance
between the interlocutors and the referent. All that matters is that there is no other entity
fitting the same description, and all that is required is that the referent is present and
visible to the interlocutors in the scene where the enunciation occurs.
As shown in the following examples, le…o’ can be used to refer to an entity in the
setting of the utterance, at any distance from—but perceivable by—the speaker.10
(33)
Context: A gourd is placed on the table. The speaker is asked how he/she would
request the elicitor to pass him/her the gourd.
Ts’a–ø
9
teen
le luuch=o’.
The feminine prefix x- is absent from this second nominal expression (since it is optional in
Yucatec), but from the sentences that follow in the original text it is clear that reference is being made in
this case to the wife, and not the husband.
10
If there are two possible referents at different distances from the speaker, le…o’ is used to refer to
the farther entity: we discuss these cases in §5.5.
26
give–ABS:3SG
1SG
le gourd=CL
‘Give me the gourd.’
(34)
(NT-1-3ai)
Context: A table is near both the speaker and the interviewer. The speaker is
asked how the interviewer should ask him to touch the table:
Mach–ø
le
mayakche’=o’.
touch–ABS:3SG
le
table=CL
‘Touch the table.’
(35)
(DT-1-pr3-b)
Context: Same as in (34). The speaker is asked how the interviewer should ask
him to clean the table:
Cho’–ø
le
clean–ABS:3SG le
mayakche’=o’.
table =CL
‘Clean the table.’
(RC-1-pr3-c)
In (36), a stone had been placed near both the speaker and the interviewer. The
speaker is asked to judge the acceptability of the sentence in this context. As in the other
examples, no previous mention of this stone had taken place before.
(36)
Context: A stone is placed near both the speaker and the interviewer.
Ts’a–ø
teen le tunich=o’.
give–ABS:3SG 1SG le stone=CL
‘Give me the stone.’
(DT-2-1b)
In example (37), the speakers were asked to judge the acceptability of (b) as a
response to (a):
27
(37)
a. Máax
who
lox–ech?
punch–ABS:2SG
‘Who hit you?’
b.
(Leti’) le
3SG
xi’paal=o’
le male.kid=CL
‘(He), the boy’
(RC-1-88b)
Examples (36) and (37) were obtained via acceptability tasks. In the contexts in
which the corresponding judgments were elicited, it was also possible to refer to the stone
in (36) with an indefinite article, which is what one consultant volunteered instead of just
replying that (36) was acceptable; crucially, he did not overtly reject it, so this piece of
data does not falsify our claim that the use of le…o’ is acceptable in this context. The
remaining four speakers consulted agreed that the use of le…o’ was acceptable. Of these
four, one provided a sentence with le…o’ in which he additionally included the adjective
‘small’, therefore producing a new sentence with le…o’ instead of just judging the one
that was presented to him. With respect to (37), all speakers consulted accepted the form
with le... o’ as a possible answer to the question ‘who hit you?’ but the results varied as to
whether they needed the presence of the pronoun leti’ before the noun phrase in order to
give a complete answer. Three speakers accepted it as it was elicited (without leti’),
whereas the other two mentioned that the presence of leti’ was required in this context.
The relevant point here is that; (i) the form with le…o’ was accepted in these contexts,
irrespective of the fact that other possible expressions were also volunteered, and; (ii)
even though the speakers consulted did not provide exactly the same answer for these
particular elicitation tasks, none of the different answers they provided contradicted the
judgements of the other speakers, and so they do not constitute evidence against our
observation that le...o’ can be used felicitously in this context, as expected of a definite
article. Lastly, example (38) is taken from an interview (which we regard as a kind of
conversation):
(38) Le k’áax=o’ t–a
w–il–ik=o’
28
le nuuk–tak–o’ob
le jungle=CL
EP–see–IND=CL
DUR–ERG:2
le big–PL–PL
ka’anal–tak–o’ob ya’ab
u
tall–PL–PL
ERG:3 EP–help–ABS:1PL=CL
much
y–áant–o’on=o’.
‘The jungle that you see, the one which is huge and tall that helps us a lot.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:16-19, 20)
This example confirms, in a naturally occurring setting, what is observed in (33-37). In
spontaneous data it is difficult to control or even determine whether a certain referred
entity is present or not in the speech situation, but in (38) the context itself makes it clear
that the jungle (‘the jungle that you see’) is present, in full view of the interlocutors
(additionally, one of the authors of this paper was present during the interview). It should
be mentioned, though, that le k’áax=o’, ‘the jungle’ is used in several previous passages
during the interview (all of them with generic reference), and it also has previous
occurrences with the proximal demonstrative le…a’, ‘this jungle’, with a particular
reference. However, (38) makes it explicit (by means of the modifying relative clause
“that you see”) that the referent is directly accessible and present at the moment of
speech. It is thus plausible to consider that this noun phrase does not have an anaphoric
interpretation even though it might be accidentally co-referential with a demonstrative
noun phrase that has been previously used.
5.3 Representation of Previous Particular States
We now address the third subdomain of the Universe of Discourse, Representation of
Previous Particular States, which refers to the set of entities that belong in the memories
shared by the speaker and addressee. Note that these entities are particular individuals
and not general concepts. Consider the following two examples:
(39) Last week, Fred told Ivan that he was reading a book by Sacks. Today they met at
the library and Ivan asked Fred:
“Did you finish the book?”
29
(40) Fred knows that Ivan has been working for some time on a paper. When they meet
on campus, Fred asks Ivan:
“How is the paper going?”
The referents for the book in (39) and of the paper in (40) are not traced
anaphorically, because there have not been any previous mentions of these entities in the
current discourse. However, they can be, easily identifiable within the memories that the
speaker assumes that he and his interlocutor have in common.
Let us turn now to the use of le...o’ in such situations in Yucatec. In order to set the
context to one in which the entities referred to were present in the shared memories of the
interlocutors, the elicitor asked the speaker to translate a sentence from Spanish to Maya
describing the exact context shown in (41) and (42). We were thus able to confirm that
le…o’ can be used to introduce entities that belong to previous particular states:
(41) Context: Pedro has sent his son to fix the fence of their house. Later, they meet in
the town square. His son tells Pedro that he has already fixed the fence.
Sáam in
TRM
ERG:1SG
koot–ø
le
build.fence–ABS:3SG le
‘I have already fixed the fence.’
koot=o’.
fence=CL
(RC-1-53)
(42) Context: Pedro has told you that the last time he saw your sister, she was weaving a
hammock. Some other day, you meet with Pedro. How would he ask you in Maya:
“Has your sister finished the hammock?”
A
kiik=e’
ts’o’ok u
ERG:2
big.sister=TOP TRM
ERG:3
ts’o’ok–s–ik–ø
le k’áan=o’?
finish–CAUS–IND–ABS:3SG le hammock=CL
‘Has your big sister finished the hammock?’
30
(RC-1-56)
The context description ensures that the referents of le koot=o’ ‘le fence’ in (41) and le
k’áan=o’ ‘le hammock’ in (42) are traceable to the shared memories of speaker and
addressee.
Similarly, using le...o’ to introduce referents that belong to previous particular states
is common in narrative texts. In (43) the noun phrase containing ‘jungle’ refers to a
particular stretch of jungle near the speaker’s hometown:
(43) Ma’
NEG
bin kíin–s–ik–ø
go
le nukuch
die–CAUS–IND–ABS:3SG le large
k’áax=o’, nuk–tak–o’ob=i’!
jungle=CL big–PL–PL=CL
‘Don’t go kill the high jungle(s), the ones that are big!’ (Monforte et al. 2010:15-25)
Thus, in (43), the referent of le nukuch k’áax=o’ ‘le large jungle’ is a particular entity
whose existence is assumed by speaker and addressee. The same is true in the case of ‘the
cenote’ in (44), where the noun phrase with le…o’ refers to a particular cenote from
which the inhabitants of the town used to get water:
(44) le túun
le
ts’ono’ot=o’ ti’
bin
k–u
le then
le
cenote=CL
CIT
HAB–ERG:3 EP–enter–IND
PREP
y–ok–ol
u
ERG:3
ch’a–ø–’ob
ja’
u
y–uk’–ø–o’ob=i’.
grab–ABS:3SG–PL
water
ERG:3
EP–drink–ABS:3SG–PL=LOC
‘And so, the cenote, that’s where they used to go to get water to drink.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:24-13)
This cenote is not present at the moment of speech, nor has it been mentioned explicitly
in the discourse. Rather, its referent is found in the shared memories of the interlocutors.
Finally, in (45), ‘the festivity of Tahdziu’ refers specifically to the yearly festivity for the
patron saint of Tahdziu, a neighboring town.
(45) je’el=o’
PRSV–CL
táan
le
during le
fiesta
Ts’iu=o’
festivities
Tahdziu=CL 1PL=TOP
31
to’on=e’
bin–o’on
go–ABS:1PL
úuch–ik–ø
u
festejar–t–ik-ø
happen–FOC–ABS:3SG
ERG:3
celebrate–TRNS–IND–ABS:3SG
úuch–ik–ø
u
bautisar–t–a’a–l
in
happen–FOC– ABS:3SG ERG:3 baptize–TRNS–PASS–IND
chan
ERG:1SG DIM
hijo…
son
‘And so, during the Tahdziu festivities, it so happened that we went to celebrate, as it
happens, to have my little son baptized…’
(Monforte et al. 2010:26-1, 2)
In naturally occurring examples it is not possible to state explicitly that the referents of
these noun phrases belong to shared memories (unlike what happens with controlled
elicitation). However, that the referents of the noun phrases with le...o’ belong to
previous particular states is inferable from the context to which sentences (43)-(45)
belong, since these entities belong to the interlocutors’ town, since there are no previous
mentions of these entities in the text, and because the episodic nature of the predicates
rules out a generic interpretation (which we discuss in section §5.4).
Summing up, in this section we have shown how the determiner le…o’ is able to
introduce noun phrases which refer to specific entities that belong to the memories shared
by the interlocutors. It is important to say that, in contrast with the previous two subsets
of the Universe of Discourse–Discourse Interpretation Level and Perceptual
Representation of the Speech Situation– the noun phrase with le…o’ does not need to be
anaphoric, and the entity to which it refers does not need to be present in the speech
situation. Referring to particular entities in shared memories is therefore a different
domain in which noun phrases with le...o’ are perfectly acceptable and interpretable. We
thus confirm that le...o’ is able to locate referents in three out of the four subdomains of
UD that we identify in our framework for definite reference.
5.4. Conceptual Information
Conceptual Information refers to the subdomain of entities that belong to the semantic
extension of the noun (plus its restrictive modifiers if it happens to have any),
independently from its particular context of occurrence. The descriptive content of a noun
32
is a property that holds of a set of individuals, thereby delimiting a class (e.g. the property
“velociraptor” holds of a set of individuals which jointly constitute to the class of
velociraptors). It is this descriptive content of the noun and the set of entities thus
delimited that we refer to as “Conceptual Information”. When a definite article combines
with a noun, it is possible for the resulting noun phrase to refer to the whole extension
originally denoted by the noun (and its modifiers), therefore achieving generic reference.
The link between definite articles and generic reference has been long recognized in
the literature (Christophersen 1939; Hawkins 1978), and is illustrated in the following
examples from Spanish (46a) and in English (46b):
(46) a. El perro es el mejor amigo del hombre.
‘Dogs are man’s best friend.’
b. The red gazelle is now extinct.
Importantly, one of the key features that distinguish the definite article from other
definite determiners (such as demonstratives) is that only the former can be used to refer
to whole kinds (“toto-generic” reference), as in “The velociraptor was a carnivore”.
Demonstratives, too, can have generic uses, but when this happens, they only can achieve
a species, or “parti-generic” reading, as in “This velociraptor was widespread in
Mongolia, while this other one was more common in South Asia” (see García Fajardo
1985 [1984], Laca 1990, and Krifka et al. 1995). We thus consider the ability to refer to
any of the components of the Universe of Discourse, including the possibility of making
toto-generic reference, as the signature property that allows us to identify definite articles.
We identify a generic reference by the non-episodic nature of the predicate involved.
Characterizing predicates (“The hazel dormouse hibernates for six months”) and kindlevel predicates (“The popsicle was invented in California”) are good indicators that the
relevant reference is generic (Krifka et al. 1995), and this is the criterion we rely on to
identify generic references in Yucatec.
In Yucatec, le…o’ is commonly used to make generic reference, as demonstrated in
(47) where le juuj=o’ refers to the whole kind of iguanas, as opposed to a particular
entity.
33
(47)
Le juuj=o’
jun túul
ba’alche’.
le
one
animal
iguana=CL
CLAS
‘Iguanas are animals.’
(RC-1-62)
We know that le juuj=o’ ‘le iguana’ refers to iguanas in general because the
predicate intends to express a characteristic property of these animals, and not just of one
particular entity. In the same vein, in (48) being male is taken to be a characteristic
property of the kind ‘priest’.11
(48)
Le
padre=o’
mantats’
xiib.
le
priest=CL
constantly
male
‘The priest is always a male.’
(RC-1-63)
The general character of the statement in (48) is reinforced by the presence of the adverb
mantats’ ‘constantly’ (i.e. ‘always’), therefore supporting the observation that le padre
=o’ refers to priests in general, and not to a single priest.
The generic use of le…o’ was previously noted by Hanks (1990:22), according to
whom ‘[D]eictics ending with o’ usually identify unique objects but may be generic (le’
ok’ot o’ ‘dancing, that dance’)…’12 Generic le…o’ is also documented in narrative texts.
Consider, for instance, examples (49) and (50). In these examples, the noun phrases le
saandia=o’ ‘le watermelon’ and le iik=o’ ‘le chili’, respectively, have occurred in
11
Examples (47) and (48) were obtained as the first response to a production task, where a Spanish
sentence was provided to set up a context like “Suppose that you don’t know what iguanas are, and so I tell
you ‘Iguanas are animals’”, thus ensuring a generic interpretation. These first outcomes were then modified
into sentences with the other two determiners, le...a’ and le...e’, to elicit acceptability judgments. The
results of these tests are described in §5.6.
12
Hanks’ data do not provide a context to guarantee that this interpretation is indeed generic, and the
translations offered suggest reference to particular events or entities rather than genericity –mostly because
they are translated with the demonstrative “that” – but we were able to confirm through controlled
elicitation that his original insight was correct.
34
previous passages, but the habitual interpretation of the predicates in these sentences is
consistent with a generic interpretation of the relevant noun phrases with le...o’:
(49) Le sandia
túun
le watermelon then
le
saandia=o’?
le
watermelon=CL
xan=o’, bix
k
pak’–ik–ø
also=CL how
ERG:1PL
plant–IND–ABS:3SG
‘So watermelons then, how do we plant watermelons?’
(50) Lekan k–u
y–a’al–ik–ø
u
(Monforte et al. 2010:14-24)
y–óo–t–ik–ø
HAB–ERG:3 EP–say–IND–ABS:3SG ERG.3
EP–want–TRNS–IND–ABS:3SG
u
pak’–o’ob=e’,
to’on=e’
ts’–u
káaj–al
ERG.3
sow–PL=TOP
1:PL=TOP
TRM–ERG:3
begin–IND
when
cosechar–t–ik–ø
le
iik=o’.
harvest–TRNS–IND–ABS:3SG
le
chili=CL
‘As soon as they want to sow, we, we will already have started to harvest the chili
peppers.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:13-15, 16)
The generic interpretation of le saandia=o’ ‘le watermelon’ in (50) and le iik=o’ ‘le
chili’ in (51) stems from the presence of a habitual aspect marker together with an
indicative suffix, along with world knowledge (e.g. the fact that a particular watermelon
cannot be planted more than once, or that particular chili peppers are not harvested more
than once, which is what the habitual meaning of the sentence would entail if the
referents were particular individuals).
In example (51), le tóolok=o’ ‘le basilisk lizard’ is mentioned for the first time in the
text and has a generic interpretation, as is reflected in the habitual interpretation of the
predicate.
35
(51) K–u
HAB–ERG:3
ka’a taal
yaanal, je’ebix tak
le
juuj,
two come
different like
le
iguana like
even
je’ebix
le
tóolok=o’,
k–u
bi–s–ik–ø,
le
basilisk.lizard=CL
HAB–ERG:3
go–CAUS–IND–ABS:3SG
k–u
jaan–t–ik–ø.
HAB–ERG:3
eat–TRNS–IND–ABS:3SG
tak
even
‘Something else comes again, (even) like iguanas, even like basilisks, and they
take it and eat it.’
(Monforte et al. 2010:195-18, 19)
Note that in (51), the nominal expression le juuj ‘le iguana’ presumably also has a generic
reference. However, it does not appear with the clitic =o’ because of the morphosyntactic
restriction mentioned briefly in §2.1, which bans more than one clitic in the post-verbal
field.
As noted in Hanks (1990:488-494), clitics in the post-verbal field can only appear in
the rightmost boundary of any given clause. This is what prevents the clitic =o’ from
appearing immediately after le juuj in (49), where this noun phrase is not at the right edge
of the clause. Furthermore, in this specific context the clitic =o’ associated with le juuj
cannot appear at the rightmost boundary of the clause either. This is because, as Hanks
points out, only one clitic can appear at any given clitic boundary, and here the clitic
position at the rightmost edge of the clause is already taken by the clitic =o’ of le
tóolok=o’. In spite of this, there is good reason to think that the clitic related with le juuj
is =o’ (thus allowing for a generic interpretation) and not, for instance, =a’. The reason is
that when two clitics compete for the same clitic position, the outcome of the competition
is determined by a hierarchy in which =a’ takes precedence over =o’ or any other clitic
(Hanks 1990:491). Hence, if the clitic associated with le juuj were =a’, it would take
precedence over any other clitic competing for this position, which would result in the
sequence le tóolok=a’, contrary to what is observed in this example.
5.5 Demonstrative uses of le…o’
36
So far, we have argued that le…o’ has all the referential functions expected of a definite
article. This, however, does not mean that we do not recognize that in some contexts it
behaves in the way expected of a demonstrative, as observed in several previous analyses
(§2). Before introducing the relevant examples, it is necessary to tackle the question of
what the semantic distinction between demonstratives and definite articles is.
We consider noun phrases with definite articles to refer inclusively —that is, their
denotation includes the whole set of entities denoted by the noun and its modifiers.
Demonstratives are also considered definite determiners in the sense that they also make
inclusive reference (Hawkins 1991, Wolter 2006). The difference between them lies in
the fact that, while definite descriptions must locate their reference set within UD,
demonstratives may “update” their restriction using a pointing gesture or some other
deictic device, that is, they delimit their reference set with a deictic value (‘proximity’,
non-proximity’, etc.). It is by way of their inherent deictic component that demonstratives
delimit the domain within which the set referred to is to be found. For instance, given a
sentence like “This pan is hot”, the hearer must locate the set of pans within the domain
that is closer to the speaker and then assume that this set (which by the specifications of
number, must contain only one element) has the property of being hot. A speaker may
say, aided by a pointing gesture: “This pan is hot but this pan is not hot” without asserting
a contradiction, because the inclusive reference of the first utterance of “this pan” is
restricted to the domain signaled by a first pointing gesture, while the second utterance of
the same noun phrase is restricted to a different domain, delimited also deictically by a
subsequent pointing gesture. In contrast, definite articles lack this deictic capacity.
Building upon a simplified version of an idea put forth in Wolter (2006), we assume that
the deictic component in demonstratives does not serve the purpose of locating a
particular individual in the physical context of use, but rather delimits a particular
domain, within which the set described by the noun phrase must be located.
Having established that the difference between demonstratives and definite articles
lies in the deictic component of the former, we introduce the data in (52) as instances of a
demonstrative use of le…o’. Note that, in accordance with Bohnemeyer (2012:106), in
both cases le…o’ points to non-immediate objects, though not necessarily distant ones.
37
(52) Context: Speakers were asked to hold a large gourd in their hands and not to let go
of it. A small gourd was placed at the other end of the table where the elicitation
took place (out of the speakers’ reach). Then they were instructed to describe each
of the gourds. Example (a) is an example of the speakers’ description of the gourd
they held in their hands, and (b) of the other gourd.
a.
Le luuch=a’, nojoch, túuts’, léelemkil.
le
gourd=CL big
long
shiny
‘This gourd is big, long and shiny.
b.
(AH-1-85)
Le luuch=o’, chichan, náach, wóolis, sak.
le
gourd=CL small
distant round white
‘That gourd is small, far away, round and white.’
(AH-1-86)
We consider the use of le...o’ in (52b) as an instance of a demonstrative function because
the entity referred to by the corresponding noun phrase fulfills the description provided
by the noun enriched with a deictic component of non-proximity. Note that it cannot
simply locate the referent that fulfills the description “gourd”, because there are two of
them in this context. Evidently, in (52a) the form le…a’ is also a demonstrative which, as
noted in most (if not all) of the relevant literature, has the value of proximity to the
speaker. Examples like (52) thus support the idea put forward in §2 that le…a’ and le…o’
(in its demonstrative use) pertain to a single paradigm of demonstrative determiners, in
which le…a’ is a proximity demonstrative, and le…o’ conveys a more neutral value in
distal terms, similar to what Bohnemeyer (2012:12) refers to as a “more general indexical
meaning”.
Another illustrative case of the demonstrative use of le...o’ is provided in (53).
Speakers accept this use in which two noun phrases with le...o’ and identical descriptive
content can co-occur in the same sentence, each one referring to a different entity. In this
particular scenario, the entities referred to were equidistant from the speaker. It is
important to observe that in (53) the use of two noun phrases introduced by le…o’ is
38
felicitous only when each of them is accompanied by a pointing gesture which deictically
restricts a different domain.
(53) Le luuch=o’, nojoch, le luuch=o’, chichan.
le
gourd=CL big
le gourd=CL small
‘That gourd is big, that (other) gourd is small.’
(DT-2-27b)
Thus, le…o’ has the referential properties that we expect from a definite article, but (52)
and (53) show that le…o’ also has demonstrative uses, in accordance with previous
descriptions. The situation in which the same form is used as a demonstrative and as a
definite article is by no means unusual (see Dryer 2013). In fact, given that
demonstratives are a common diachronic source of definite articles cross-linguistically, it
is not surprising that, at some stage of the grammaticalization process, both the
demonstrative function (i.e., a deictic determiner), and a definite article function are
expressed by identical forms.
Although the present work does not intend to make any historical claims, it is likely
that a similar situation may be occurring in Yucatec: the form le…o’, identified originally
as a demonstrative, coexists with an identical form le…o’ that is currently a definite
article. In the former case, the terminal clitic adds the deictic feature characteristic of
demonstratives, thereby delimiting the domain of reference to a physical or conceptual
space that is non-proximal to the speaker. The definite article le...o’, in contrast, lacks this
deictic feature, and this is what triggers the interpretation “set in the universe of
discourse” as opposed to “set of entities in a particular domain non-proximal to the
speaker”. Definite articles and demonstratives, in the view adopted here, differ in the
non-deictic nature of the former, as opposed to the deictic nature of the latter, but they
still share the property of making inclusive reference. Along with the loss of its deictic
character, further research might be able to determine if the definite article le...o’ has also
started to show additional signs of grammaticalization.
5.6 Other determiners are not definite articles
39
What characterizes definite descriptions in our framework is the fact that they can target a
referent within any of the four subdomains of UD. This condition is met by le...o’ but not,
as we argue in this section, by the other two determiners le...a’ and le...e’. In order to
show that these other determiners do not fulfill the whole range of reference location that
le...o’ does, we must rely on negative evidence. Specifically, we must present contexts in
which a certain sub-domain of UD is targeted and then show that speakers reject the use
of the other two determiners in such contexts. Since negative evidence is hard—if not
impossible—to find in naturally occurring texts (Matthewson 2004), for this section we
rely solely on elicited data. Note that we are not interested in describing all the acceptable
uses of le...e’ and le...a’, some of which might coincide with uses of definite articles in
particular subdomains of UD. Rather, we are aiming to show that, unlike the definite
article, these determiners are not capable of locating a referent within just any subdomain
of UD: that is, there is at least one domain within which they fail to refer. Following
standard notation, the ‘#’ sign preceding some of the following examples signals that,
although grammatical, the sequence is unacceptable in the context provided.
First, in (54) we attest that le...e’ is not capable of referring to an entity in the
subdomain of Perceptual Representation of the Speech Situation.
(54)
Context: Two gourds are placed, one in the hands of the elicitor, the other one at a
certain distance, but out of reach for both interlocutors. The elicitor asks if he can
refer to each of them by le luuch=o’, le luuch=a’ and le luuch=e’:
Referring to the gourd in the speaker’s hands:
a.
b.
c.
#Le
luuch=o’
le
gourd=CL
Le
luuch=a’
le
gourd=CL
#Le
luuch=e’
le
gourd=CL
40
Referring to the gourd out of the speaker’s reach, but within sight:
d.
e.
f.
Le
luuch=o’
le
gourd=CL
#Le
luuch=a’
le
gourd=CL
#Le
luuch=e’.
le
gourd=CL
(AN-2-25)
In (54c), we see that le luuch=e’ cannot make reference to the gourd that is held by the
speaker, and in (54f) we also observe that le...e’ cannot refer to a gourd that is placed at a
certain distance, but within his/her sight. When referring to the gourd in the hands of the
speaker, consultants reject the use of le…e’, as well as that of le…o’.13 The only accepted
alternative is le…a’. When referring to the second gourd, placed at a certain distance
from both speaker and elicitor, all consultants accepted referring to it with le…o’ (54d),
rejected the use of le…a’ (54e) and, once again, rejected the use of le…e’ (54f).
The impossibility of le…e’ being used in referring to either the gourd in the domain
of the speaker, and to the one out of his/her reach, may well be due to some additional
semantic requirement. Specifically, it may be the case that its referent must not be within
the visual field of the speaker and/or hearer—an observation made originally in Andrade
(1955 [1940]) when contrasting some constructions that use le...e’ vs. le...o’. However,
for the purposes of our argument, what matters is that le...e’ cannot target the whole range
of UD to locate a referent, thus eliminating it as a possible definite article. More
importantly, neither le...e’ or le...a’ can make generic reference, as shown in the
following examples.
13
The unacceptability of le...o’ in (54a) is due to the fact that there are two objects at different
distances from the speech act participants, and so, as a demonstrative, it is used for non-proximal entities,
while le...a’ takes precedence if the referent is in the domain of the speaker. If instead of being used as a
demonstrative, le...o’ were functioning as a definite article, it still would be infelicitous because the context
does not fulfill the presupposition that there is only one gourd in the relevant situation. Thanks to Lisa
Matthewson for pointing this out to us.
41
(55) Context: Imagine that someone who is not from here does not know what iguanas
are. Can I explain it to him as in (a), (b), or (c)?
a.
Le juuj=o’
jun túul
ba’alche’.
le
one
animal
iguana=CL
CLAS
‘Iguanas are animals (lit. The iguana is an animal).’
b.
#Le juuj=a’
le iguana=CL
c.
#Le juuj=e’
le iguana=CL
jun túul
ba’alche’.
one
animal
CLAS
jun túul
ba’alche’.
one
animal
CLAS
(AN-2-11)
The unacceptability of le...a’ and le...e’ in making generic reference is expected if they
are demonstratives, which, by definition, are not capable of referring to a whole class
(García Fajardo 1991). As discussed in §2, the possible demonstrative nature of these two
determiners has been scrutinized elsewhere (Andrade 1955 [1940]; Blair 1964;
Bohnemeyer 2012, inter alia). Our purpose here is simply to show with this negative
evidence that neither le...a’ or le...e’ are definite articles, but rather some other kind of
determiner whose thorough semantic characterization is tangential to the central claim
made in this paper.
6.
CONCLUSIONS
Based on a definition of the definite article as the kind of determiner that allows a noun
phrase to find its referent within any subdomain of the Universe of Discourse, our results
show that noun phrases with le…o’ are acceptable in contexts where its referent is found
in any of the components of UD: (a) the Discourse Interpretation Level, (b) the
Perceptual Representation of the Speech Situation, (c) the Representation of Previous
Particular States and (d) Conceptual Information. In other words, these noun phrases can
recover referents from previous discourse, they can refer to objects in the speech
42
situation, they can refer to objects that belong in the memories shared by interlocutors, or
they can make generic reference. Thus, according to our criteria, le…o’ corresponds to a
definite article. In contrast, noun phrases introduced by le… a’ and le…e’ fail to make
generic reference. Additionally, le…e’ is not suitable for referring to entities present at
the moment of speech. Therefore, these two determiners do not correspond to definite
articles, since they fail to meet the corresponding criteria.
The present study confirms previous analyses that have hinted at the possibility that
le...o’ is a marker of definiteness, based on acceptability judgments and production tasks,
as well as through naturally occurring data. At this point, we make no claim about the
exact semantic contribution of le…a’ and le…e’. We can assert, however, that although
they are possibly definite determiners, and specifically some particular kind of
demonstrative, it is clear that neither of them is a definite article, in contrast with le…o’.
We also confirmed the claims made in previous studies that identify the
demonstrative uses of le…o’. In these cases, le…o’ may refer to entities that are not
unique in fulfilling the description provided by the noun, but rather stand in contrast with
some other entity with the same characteristics. In short, le…o’ is a definite article, but in
some contexts (where there are two entities in contrast), the reference of a noun phrase
with le…o’ does not raise a uniqueness presupposition and may be accompanied by a
deictic gesture, hence fitting the characterization of a demonstrative. This raises the
question of whether we are dealing with two homophonous determiners (a definite article
and a demonstrative) or if le…=o’ belongs to a third category that can fulfill all functions
at the same time. For the time being, we adhere to the former explanation, but we deem
that the answer to this question must rely not only on more empirical evidence but also on
a more extensive theoretical discussion about what exactly distinguishes demonstratives
and definite articles: if they are mutually exclusive categories, or if they can be conflated
in a super-category that comprises all of their functions. The answer to this specific
problem, however, is beyond the scope of this paper and so must be left for future
research.
REFERENCES
43
ANDRADE, MANUEL J. 1955 [1940]. A Grammar of Modern Yucatec. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Microfilm Collection of Manuscripts.
<http://www.christianlehmann.eu/ling/sprachen/maya/andrade/index.html.>
ARKOH, RUBY, AND MATTHEWSON, LISA. 2012. A familiar definite article in Akan.
Lingua 123:1–30
BOHNEMEYER, JÜRGEN. 2012. Yucatec Demonstratives in Interaction. Practical Theories
and Empirical Practice, ed. Andrea C. Schalley, pp. 99–128.
Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
BLAIR, ROBERT. 1964. Yucatec Maya Noun and Verb Morpho-Syntax. Ph.D. dissertation,
Indiana University.
BRICEÑO CHEL, FIDENCIO. 1992. Curso de Maya Yucateco. Ms. Escuela Nacional de
Antropología e Historia (México City).
_____. 1993. La cuantificación en maya: El uso de clasificadores numerales y de
mensurativos. Honors thesis, Facultad de Ciencias Antropológicas, Universidad
Autónoma de Yucatán.
_____. 1996. La frase nominal en maya yucateco. Estudios de Lingüística Aplicada 14:
95–104.
BRICKER, VICTORIA; ELEUTERIO PO’OT YAH; AND OFELIA DZUL DE PO’OT. 1998. A
Dictionary of the Maya Language as spoken in Hocabá, Yucatán. Salt Lake City:
The University of Utah Press.
COMISIÓN DE DIFUSIÓN DEL ALFABETO MAYA (CDAM). 1984. Alfabeto maya acordado
en la reunión de agosto de 1984. Mérida: INEA/Academia de la Lengua Maya de
Yucatán.
CEH MOO, MARISOL. 2011. T’ambilak men tunk’ulilo’ob (El llamado de los tunk'ules).
México City: Conaculta.
CHRISTOPHERSEN, PAUL. 1939. The articles: a study of their theory and use in English.
Copenhagen: Munksgaard.
DRYER, MATTHEW S. 2013. Definite Articles. The World Atlas of Language Structures
Online, eds. Matthew S. Dryer and Martin Haspelmath. Leipzig: Max Planck
Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology. <http://wals.info/chapter/37>.
GARCÍA FAJARDO, JOSEFINA. 1985 [1984]. El sentido de los sintagmas nominales y los
44
tipos de predicación. Mexico City: Instituto Nacional de Antropología e Historia.
_____. 1989. El sentido en la función referencial de frases sustantivas del español. Nueva
Revista de Filología Hispánica 37:19–26.
_____. 1990. El sentido de conjunto y un tipo de presuposición. Homenaje a Jorge A.
Suárez: Lingüística indoamericana e hispánica, eds. Beatriz Garza Cuarón and
Paulette Levy, pp. 223–27. Mexico City: El Colegio de México.
_____. 1991. El significado de los determinantes españoles. Nueva Revista de Filología
Hispánica 39:737–52.
_____. 1994. Hacia el universo del discurso desde la semántica formal: El artículo
definido. Segundo Encuentro de Lingüistas y Filólogos de España y México, eds.
A. Alegría, B. Garza and J. A. Pascual, pp. 221–29. Salamanca: Universidad de
Salamanca.
GILLON, CARRIE. 2015. Investigating D in Languages With and Without Articles.
Methodologies in Semantic Fieldwork, eds. Ryan Bochnak and Lisa Matthewson,
pp. 175–204. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
GÓNGORA PACHECO, MARÍA LUISA. 1990. U Tzikbalilo’ob Oxkutzcaab Yeetel Mani.
Mérida: Dirección General de Culturas Populares.
GUTIÉRREZ-BRAVO, RODRIGO. 2012. Relative clauses in Yucatec Maya: Light heads vs.
null domain. Relative Clauses in Languages of the Americas: A Typological
Overview, eds. Bernard Comrie and Zarina Estrada, pp. 253–68.
Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
HANKS, WILLIAM. 1984. The evidential core of deixis in Yucatec Maya. Papers from the
Twentieth Regional Meeting, pp. 154–72. Chicago: Chicago Linguistics Society.
_____. 1990. Referential Practice: Language and Lived Space among the Maya. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press.
_____. 2005. Explorations in the deictic field. Current Anthropology 46:191–220.
HAWKINS, JOHN A. 1978. Definiteness and indefiniteness. London: Croom Helm.
_____. 1991. On (in)definite articles: Implicatures and (un)grammaticality prediction.
Journal of Linguistics 27:405–42.
45
HEIM, IRENE. 1983. File Change Semantics and the Familiarity Theory of Definiteness.
Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language, eds. Rainer Bauerle, Christoph
Schwarze, and Arnim v. Stechow, pp. 164–89. Berlin: de Gruyter.
INSTITUTO NACIONAL DE ESTADÍSTICA, GEOGRAFÍA E INFORMÁTICA (INEGI). 2010.
Censo de Población y Vivienda 2010. Mexico City: INEGI.
<http://www.beta.inegi.org.mx/proyectos/ccpv/2010/ >
KRIFKA, MANFRED; FRANCIS J. PELLETIER; GREG CARLSON; ALICE TER MEULEN;
GENNARO CHIERCHIA; AND GODEHARD LINK. 1995. Genericity: An introduction.
The Generic Book, eds. Gregory N. Carlson and Francis J. Pelletier, pp. 1–124.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
LACA, BRENDA. 1990. Generic objects: Some more pieces of the puzzle. Lingua 81:25–
46.
LEHMANN, CHRISTIAN. 1998. Possession in Yucatec Maya. Munich: Lincom Europa.
_____. 2012. Gramática Maya. Erfurt: Erfurt University.
<http://www.christianlehmann.eu/ling/sprachen/maya/index.php>, retrieved
08/10/2012.
LUCY, JOHN. 1992. Grammatical Categories and Cognition: A Case Study of the
Linguistic Relativity Hypothesis. Cambridge: Cambrige University Press.
MATTHEWSON, LISA. 2004. On the Methodology of Semantic Fieldwork. International
Journal of American Linguistics 70:369–415.
MONFORTE, JORGE; LÁZARO DZUL; AND RODRIGO GUTIÉRREZ-BRAVO. 2010. Narraciones
Mayas. Mexico City: Instituto Nacional de Lenguas Indígenas.
PANAGIDIOTIS, E. PHOEVOS. 2014. Determiners. Oxford Bibliografies in Linguistics.
<http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780199772810/obo9780199772810-0187.xml?rskey=iOyZ0V&result=46 >.
RUSSELL, BERTRAND. 1905. On Denoting. Mind 14:479–93.
SCHWARZ, FLORIAN. 2013. Two Kinds of Definites Cross-linguistically. Language and
Linguistics Compass 7:534–59.
STOLZ, CHRISTEL; THOMAS STOLZ; AND ELISABETH VERHOEVEN. 2012. Maya yucateco de
X-hazil Sur, Quintana Roo. Mexico City: El Colegio de México.
46
VERHOEVEN, ELISABETH. 2007. Experiential constructions in Yucatec Maya. Amsterdam/
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
VERHOEVEN, ELISABETH, AND STAVROS SKOPETEAS. 2015. Licensing focus constructions
in Yucatec Maya. International Journal of American Linguistics 81:1–40.
WOLTER, LYNSEY KAY. 2006. That’s that: The Semantics and Pragmatics of
Demonstrative Noun Phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Santa
Cruz.
47