Science And Secularization
Peter Harrison
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), 47-70. Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
In his 1973-4 Gifford Lectures on the topic of “The Secularization of the European
Mind”, Cambridge historian Owen Chadwick tells of a Harrow schoolboy who in the
1880s learned that “Darwin had disproved the bible” and adjusted his religious faith
accordingly.1 The anecdote represents a common, if unreflective, view about the
relationship between modern science and secularism which sees an incompatibility
between scientific theories and methods on the one hand, and traditional religion on
the other, such that the advance of the former will necessarily entail retreat of the
latter. The tale is repeated in Charles Taylor’s 1999 Gifford Lectures, also devoted to
the theme of secularization. 2 Again, Taylor presents the story as representative of a
standard view about the reasons for a putative decline in religious belief and practice.
Like Chadwick, Taylor does not think that this theory has much to commend it, yet as
his repetition of the story suggests, this is a narrative that has not gone away. The
idea that the forces of science and modernity have inexorably pushed the gods into an
involuntary redundancy remains a powerful one, and the notion of a fundamental
opposition between science and religion is often thought to be characteristic of
Western modernity.
In this paper I will evaluate the “science causes secularization” narrative, and offer an
account of its long history. After considering a number of versions of the thesis, and
the criticisms that have been levelled against it, I will provide an alternative account
of the relationship between science and secular modernity, one that accords to science
1
Owen Chadwick, The Secularization of the European Mind in the 19th Century (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1975), 164.
2
Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2007).
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
a more prominent role than it occupies in influential accounts such as those of
Chadwick, Taylor and others, but which I hope is less susceptible to the distortions
and oversimplification that beset the common story.
Clearly, in these discussions much hangs upon what counts as secularization. As a
starting point, I will follow José Casanova in taking secularization to encompass three
related processes: first, and most simply, a decline in religious belief and practice;
second, the increasing differentiation of secular spheres from religious institutions and
norms; and, third, the relegation of religion to the private sphere.3 However, much of
this paper is about narratives that seek to relate science and secularization, and these
narratives typically assume “secularization” to be mostly about the first of the senses
above. Conversely, when historical actors speak of a process of decline in religious
belief and practice I will take them to be articulating some version of a secularization
thesis.
1. The “Popular Narrative”: Secularization And The Stages Of History
In June 2012 the Irish biopsychologist Nigel Barber made international headlines with
his bold prediction that atheism would “defeat religion by 2038”. Barber contended
that with “better science ... there is less fear and uncertainty in people’s daily lives and
hence less of a market for religion.” He also explained that advanced technology and
medicine would give rise to material benefits “that do not require slavish conformity
to unscientific beliefs.”4 While few have offered so precise a timetable for the defeat
of religion at the hands of an advancing science, the general sentiment that science
has caused, is causing, and will cause, a decline in the power of religious faith is
relatively common in works of popular science, in the polemical writings of the “new
atheists” and, indeed, in the apologetic writings of some conservative Christians.
Nobel Laureate Steven Weinberg contends that “much of the weakening of religious
certitude in the Christian West can be laid at the door of science.”5 The Cambridge
theoretical physicist and popular science writer Stephen Hawking has declared that in
the death-struggle between science and religion, “Science will win because it works”.
This, we are informed, is because “there is a fundamental difference between religion,
which is based on authority, [and] science, which is based on observation and
reason.” 6 E. O. Wilson, the distinguished Harvard biologist and father of
sociobiology has contended that science offers us “an alternative mythology that until
now has always point for point in zones of conflict, defeated traditional religion.” For
3
José Casanova, Public Religions in the Modern World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994),
211.
4
Nigel Barber, Why Atheism will Replace Religion (Amazon Digital Services, 2012); cf. “Is Religion
on the Way Out?“, Huffington Post, accessed 2.Sept. 2013. Admittedly, Barber does not think that
science will be the sole cause of this development, and he has since resiled somewhat from his original
timetable.
5
Steven Weinberg, “A Deadly Certitude”, Times Literary Supplement, Jan 17, 2007.
6
“Stephen Hawking on Religion: Science will Win”. http://abcnews.go.com/WN/Technology/stephenhawking-religion-science-win/story?id=10830164&page=1. See also Paul Davies, God and the New
Physics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1984), 5.
2
Wilson, it is the evolutionary story that will provide the purpose and meaning once
offered by religion, and of all the sciences it is biology that can “explain the nature of
mind and reality and the meaning of life.” 7 Oxford neuroscientist and public
intellectual Colin Blakemore agrees that science is “the biggest challenge Christianity
has ever had to face”, concluding that “it will eventually make religion unnecessary.”8
The idea that science and religion are direct competitors is also an article of faith
amongst the so-called new atheists, whose most prominent representatives are
Richard Dawkins, Sam Harris, Christopher Hitchens and Daniel Dennett. Sam Harris
thus suggests that science and religion compete for the same explanatory territory, and
that there can be only one winner: “the conflict between religion and science is
inherent and (very nearly) zero-sum. The success of science often comes at the
expense of religious dogma; the maintenance of religious dogma always comes at the
expense of science.” Science, he concludes with characteristic forthrightness, “must
destroy religion”. Philosopher Daniel Dennett offers a slightly different take on this
narrative, offering a prediction about the future: “In about 25 years almost all
religions will have evolved into very different phenomena, so much so that in most
quarters religion will no longer command the awe that it does today.”9 In what is
shaping up to be a spectacular failure of prescience, Dennett went on to attribute this
future change to the “spread of information technology (not just the internet, but cell
phones and portable radios and television).”10 He thus echoes the views of Barber, for
whom science-based technologies are drivers of religious change.
I have referred to the contemporary conviction that science will bring about an
inevitable decline in religion as “the popular narrative” for a reason. While it has a
superficial plausibility and is relatively common in the blogsphere, television
documentaries, and popular science books, it is now encountered less frequently in the
contemporary scholarly literature of the humanities or social sciences. Moreover,
given the polemical contexts in which it now so often appears, it might seem better
simply to pass over this version of events in silence. Yet, if this view has now fallen
from favour amongst scholars, for all that, it still commands attention from some
sociologists.11 But more importantly for our purposes, these sentiments represent a
7
E. O. Wilson, On Human Nature (Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1978), 192, 201; The
Creation: An Appeal to Save Life on Earth (New York: Norton, 2006), 104-5.
8
Colin Blakemore, “God and the Scientists”, Christianity: A History, Channel 4 Documentary,
Episode 7.
9
Sam Harris, “Science must destroy Religion” The Huffington Post, January 2, 2006,
http://www.huffingtonpost.com/sam-harris/science-must-destroy-reli_b_13153.html, dowloaded 11
January, 2009. Cf. “Science is science because it represents our most committed effort to verify that
our statements about the world are true (or at least not false).” Harris, The End of Faith (New York:
Norton, 2005), 75-6.
10
The Edge, http://www.edge.org/response-detail/10090, accessed 12 March, 2013. The prediction
was made in 2007.
11
Liliane Voyé and Karen Dobbelaere argue that because “science offers a thoroughly secular
perspective on the world” its presence in our educational systems necessarily means “desacralising the
content of learning and the world view of students”. This accounts for “the long term decline of
religious practices”. L. Voyé and Karel Dobbelaere “Roman Catholicism: Universalism at Stake”, in
3
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
rehearsal of a long-standing view about the inverse relationship between science and
religion—one that appears at the same time as modern science itself and which is
worth exploring further. Further, while the “science causes secularization” thesis has
recently been subjected to searching criticism, it contains a kernel of truth.
The motif of an enlightened science displacing a superstitious religion first appears in
post-reformation Protestant critiques of Catholicism. English philosopher and
statesman Francis Bacon attributed to divine providence the fact that the reformation
of religion was accompanied by a renewal of science in the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries:
And we see before our eyes, that in the age of ourselves and our fathers,
when it pleased God to call the church of Rome to account for their
degenerate manners and ceremonies, and sundry doctrines obnoxious and
framed to uphold the same abuses; at one and the same time it was
ordained by the Divine Providence, that there should attend withal a
renovation and a new spring of all other knowledges.12
The idea that modern science could dispel the darkness and superstition associated
with medieval (Catholic) religion was not uncommon in early modern Protestant
interpretations of history.13 However, this was a thesis that could be applied with less
discrimination. A number of philosophes of Enlightenment France would accordingly
broaden this reading of history and argue that all revealed religion had at one time
impeded the growth of knowledge, and that it in turn would fall victim to an
advancing science. In a clandestine manuscript composed around 1705 César
Chesneau Du Marsais maintained that Christianity “hampers progress of human
knowledge and the sciences”.14 By the end of the century such sentiments were
openly expressed. Nicolas de Condorcet announced in his Sketch for a Historical
Picture of the Progress of the Human Spirit (1795) that “the triumph of Christianity
was the signal for the complete decadence of philosophy and the sciences”. The
converse was also held to be true—that in a new era of unfettered scientific
achievement, religion would fall into decline and society would continue to advance.
Condorcet believed that history could be divided into ten successive epochs, the last
of which would see the disappearance of the religion that for so long had imprisoned
human reason “in hopeless bondage, in eternal infancy”.15
Religions sans Frontières, ed. R. Cipriani (Rome: Dipartimento per L’Informazione e Editoria, 1994),
83-113.
12
Francis Bacon, Advancement of Learning, I.vi.15, in The Works of Francis Bacon. 14 vols. Edited
by James Spedding, Robert Ellis, and Douglas Heath London: Longman, 1857–74, vol. 3, 300.
13
Thomas Sprat History of the Royal Society (London, 1666), 371; Cotton Mather, American Tears
upon the Ruines of the Greek Churches (Boston, 1701), 42-3. See also Thomas Culpeper Morall
Discourses and Essayes (London, 1655), 63; Samuel Hartlib Sheffield University Library, Hartlib
Papers XLVIII 17, reproduced in Charles Webster The Great Instauration (London: Duckworth, 1976),
Appendix 1, 524-28; Noah Biggs Mataetechnia Medicinae Praxeos. The Vanity of the Craft of Physick
(London, 1651), To the Parliament.
14
César Chesneau Du Marsais, Examen, BL MS Landsdowne 414, 98-9, qu. in Jonathan Israel,
Radical Enlightenment (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 693.
15
Nicolas de Condorcet, Condorcet: Political Writings, ed. Steven Lukes and Nadia Urbinati
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 51, 129.
4
Enlightenment philosophes self-consciously moulded this view of things into a broad
theory of historical progress. As Dan Edelstein has recently suggested, the
achievement of these writers lay not in their contribution to philosophy or natural
science, but in their fabrication of a particular view of history:
The key contribution made by these French scholars, writing between
1680 and 1720, was less epistemological than narratological. In other
words, they did not propose a new method of reasoning or advocate a
new philosophical understanding of the world. Rather they offered a
seductive account of the events and discoveries of the past century, in
conjunction with a more overarching history of human civilization....
More generally, they argued, changes in science had led to changes in
society.
This idea was to become inextricable from the idea of “the Enlightenment” itself. In
Edelstein’s words: “The narrative that lay at the heart of what we now know as the
Enlightenment was more than just a story: it was and remains a “master narrative” of
modernity, even a myth.”16
This particular narrative of secularization was to be incorporated into a number of
subsequent theories of historical progress, and indeed informs accounts of “the
Enlightenment” down to the present.17 Perhaps the best-known general theory of
human progress in the immediate aftermath of the Enlightenment is that of positivist
philosopher Auguste Comte (1798—1857). Comte, who popularised the new term
“sociology” (sociologie) and is often credited with establishing the discipline, sought
both to analyze society and to reconstruct it on rational foundations analogous to
those employed in the natural sciences.18 His goal was to devise a “physics of
society” [physique sociale]. For Comte, this amounted to an explicit attempt to
supplant European Christianity with a new scientific and secular ideology. He thus
combined the analytic and descriptive elements of the discipline with his own
normative goals, and did so quite self-consciously. The idea that science would
displace religion was thus both a foundational aspiration of the discipline of
sociology—at least insofar as it has its origins in Comte’s thought—and a prediction
of the future direction of society, based on Comte’s well-known three-stage theory of
history according to which societies progress from a theological stage, through a
metaphysical stage, to a scientific or “positive” stage.19
16
Dan Edelstein, The Enlightenment: A Genealogy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2010), 2-3,
116.
17
See, e.g., Jonathan Israel’s trilogy, Radical Enlightenment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002),
Enlightenment Contested (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2008), Democratic Enlightenment (2011);
and, more recently, Anthony Pagden, The Enlightenment and Why it Still Matters (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2013).
18
Comte is often credited with coining the word, but it seems to have been used some 50 years earlier
by Emmanuel Joseph Sieyès. See Jacques Guilhaumou, “Sieyès et le non-dit de la sociologie: du mot à
la chose”, Revue d'histoire des sciences humaines 15 (2006): 117-34.
19
Gertrude Lenzer (ed.), Auguste Comte and Positivism: The Essential Writings, (New York: Harper
and Row, 1975), 71-86.
5
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
This version of history—at once descriptive, normative, and predictive—became
commonplace in early twentieth-century works of sociology. As Christian Smith has
recently shown, it was common for sociology texts of 1880s-1920s to teach this
version of events: “All . . . phenomena are now satisfactorily explained on strictly
natural principles. Among people acquainted with science, all . . . supernatural beings
have been dispensed with, and the belief in them is declared to be wholly false and to
have always been false.” We find in another textbook the suggestion that religion is
the “anthropomorphic projection of savages”, and that this projection constitutes “the
basis of all religious ideas.”20 To a degree, classical secularization theory in the
discipline of sociology remains indebted to the ideological commitments of its
progenitors. According to Philip Rieff, not only did sociology begin as “a deathwork
against European Catholic social order”, but “that deathwork is enacted every day in
the halls of our institutions of higher illiteracy.”21 This is disguised somewhat by the
fact that over the course of the twentieth century sociologists sought to emulate
another aspiration of practitioners of the natural sciences—ideological neutrality.
This neutrality is often equated to a commitment to secularism but it is in tension with
an inherited secularization theory that was never intended to be ideologically neutral.
The progressivist views implicit in nineteenth- and twentieth-century sociology may
also be found in pioneering efforts in the anthropology of religion, which began in the
nineteenth century. E. B. Tylor (1832-1917), the father of British anthropology, held
that myth (which he considered to be a central feature of religion) is a form of
primitive science which seeks to account for the operations of nature. Scientific and
mythological explanations are necessarily incompatible and hence the mythological
elements of religion are destined to be superseded by science. For Tylor this would
not necessarily lead to the total demise of religion in the modern age, for religion
could retreat into the realm of the moral and metaphysical where it could survive as
an important source of moral values (once it relinquished its pretensions to offer
explanations of natural phenomena). As successive stages in cultural development,
they are incompatible.22 Science succeeds because it does a better job of explaining
natural phenomena than religion.
J. G. Frazer (1854-1941), author of the seminal anthropological text The Golden
Bough (1890), set out a similar trajectory in which religion surrenders its primitive
explanatory ambitions to the natural sciences. If for Tylor religion is a primitive
20
Christian Smith, “Secularizing American Higher Education: The Case of Early American
Sociology,” The Secular Revolution: Power, Interests, and Conflict in the Secularization of American
Public Life, ed. Christian Smith (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2003), 111, 119. See
also John Evans, “Sociology”, in Harrison and Roberts (eds), Science without God? Forthcoming.
21
Philip Rieff, My Life among the Deathworks: Illustrations of the Aesthetics of Authority
(Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 2006), 16. Cf. Rodney Stark, “Putting an End to
Ancestor Worship”, Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 43 (2004): 465–75.
22
Robert A. Segal, “Myth as Primitive Philosophy”, in Kevin Schilbrack (ed.), Thinking Through
Myths: Philosophical Perspectives (London: Routledge, 2002), 18-45.
6
science which seeks to explain the world, for Frazer religion functions as a primitive
technology which aims to manipulate the world. In Frazer’s scheme of things religion
is thus destined to disappear without remainder, since science can assume both its
explanatory and operative functions. Frazer’s developmental ideas exercised a
considerable influence over anthropology for the next decades. Just after the turn of
the century, anthropologist Ernest Crawley, taking note of the current antipathy
between science and religion, characterised the general mood of the period in this
fashion: “The opinion is everywhere gaining ground that religion is a mere survival
from a primitive and mythopaeic age, and its extinction only a matter of time.”23 The
science of anthropology, in his view, was to deliver the killer blow:
Religion is apparently a growth which cannot survive examination, and
withers at the touch of criticism. When the study of it becomes
comparative and is guided by anthropology back to the sources, its case
seems to be finally dismissed; previous criticism apparently proved it to
be an illusion; anthropology shows the illusion in its origin and
growth.24
We hear distant echoes of this view in the prediction of the distinguished
anthropologist Anthony Wallace, who in the 1960’s declared that “belief in
supernatural powers is doomed to die out, all over the world, as a result of the
increasing adequacy and diffusion of scientific knowledge.”25 This announcement of
the impending and universal collapse of religion under the irresistible weight of
accumulated scientific truths is a rehearsal of one of the founding myths of the
discipline, and still gives voice to its original, although now much more implicit,
normative agenda. Science-causes-secularization was thus a fundamental assumption
of many sociological account of the process.26
The progressivist framework of the social scientists was given more detailed
substance by two influential histories of science—those of John Draper and A. D.
White—which sought to offer historical evidence for the incompatibility of science
and religion, and for the stultifying affects of religion on human progress. These
names are legendary amongst the present generation of historians of science, albeit for
the wrong reasons. John Draper was a chemist, pioneering photographer, and amateur
historian. He attended the famous 1860 Huxley-Wilberforce debate at the British
Association meeting in Oxford where he read a long paper entitled “On the
Intellectual Development of Europe, considered with reference to the views of Mr.
Darwin and others, that the progression of organisms is determined by law.” It is not
insignificant that this was an attempt to apply evolutionary principles to social
23
Alfred Ernest Crawley, The Tree of Life (London: Hutchison and Co., 1905), 8.
Ibid., 45.
25
Anthony F. C. Wallace, Religion: An Anthropological View (New York: Random House,
1966), 265. Cf. Daniel Lerner, The Passing of Traditional Society: Modernizing the Middle
East (New York: The Free Press, 1958).
26
Rodney Stark and Roger Finke, Acts of Faith: Explaining the Human Side of Religion (Berkeley,
University of California Press, 2000), 61; Peter Berger, The Sacred Canopy (New York: Anchor
Books, 1990), 107.
24
7
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
development. (Joseph Hooker subsequently reported the episode in a letter to Darwin,
relating that a “yankee donkey called Draper” had read a boring paper filled with
flatulent stuff that was a cocktail of [Herbert] Spencer and [Henry Thomas] Buckle.)27
In 1874, Draper produced The History of the Conflict between Religion and Science in
which he declared that: “Whoever has had an opportunity of becoming acquainted
with the mental condition of the intelligent classes in Europe and America, must have
perceived that there is a rapidly-increasing departure from the public religious faith...”
This retreat from religion was attributed to the successive victories of science. The
history of science, he concluded “is no mere record of isolated discoveries; it is a
narrative of the conflict of two contending powers”. The book then offers a catalogue
of historical instances that were intended to establish its central thesis.
Draper’s book was followed by a succession of lectures and publications on the same
theme by Andrew Dickson White. As first president of Cornell, White had been
frustrated in his attempts to establish a private university independent of religious
institutions and in which the natural sciences would have an important place. White’s
historical labours on this topic culminated in the publication of History of the Warfare
of Science with Theology in Christendom (1896). The idée fixe of the work was “the
conflict between two epochs in the evolution of human thought—the theological and
the scientific.” Like Draper, White also depicted history in terms of two fundamental
successive periods. The reification of “science” is a significant feature of both works,
since it was only over the course of the nineteenth century that “science” as we
presently understand it came into being, and was distinguished from natural
philosophy. Along with it came neologisms such as “scientist” and “scientific
method”.28 Despite this, science was imagined to be an activity with a long history
and was characterized at least partly in terms of an essential opposition to religion. At
the same time it was regarded as an epoch in human thought that was only now
coming to full fruition. This historical narrative informed the fledgling discipline of
the history of science, and its imprint can be found in the work of influential figures
such as George Sarton and Karl Popper.
There is one further element in the creation of an overall 19th-century narrative. It
would be remiss to say nothing about the significance of the publication of Darwin’s
Origin of Species in 1859. The theory itself fed neatly into Victorian conceptions of
human progress (although advocates of the modern evolutionary synthesis tend now
to eschew any notion that evolution is going anywhere). The book generated
theological controversy, but it should be remembered that it had both religious
supporters and scientific detractors.29 It is also important to recall that conservative
27
Hooker to Darwin, 2 July 1860. Darwin Correspondence Project,
http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/entry-2852, accessed 13 March, 2013.
28
Peter Harrison, The Territories of Science and Religion (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2014), ch. 6.
29
David N. Livingstone, Darwin’s Forgotten Defenders (Vancouver: Regent College, 1984); James
Moore, The Post-Darwinian Controversies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981).
8
Christian reactions against it, and in particular the insistence on a literal 6-day
creation some 6,000 years ago, is a largely twentieth-century phenomenon.30 That
said, the theory did have its uses for those seeking to secularise science itself.
Moreover, a secularized science might subsequently be promoted as an agent for the
more general secularization of society. This was the mission of the “scientific
naturalists” of late nineteenth century England—Thomas Henry Huxley, John Tyndal,
Francis Galton, and others.31
At the time of the publication of Darwin’s origin, leading scientists of the period such
as William Whewell, John Herschel, and Adam Sedgwick subscribed to the view that
scientific knowledge was to be understood within a more general framework of
natural theology. These “men of science” were typically Oxbridge-educated and
often in holy orders. Huxley’s mission was to secularise science and forge a distinct
vocational identity for its practitioners. To this end, in 1864 he formed the “X-club”,
which was both a supporters’ group for the Darwinian theory of evolution and a
society whose members were devoted to the promotion of a science untainted by
religion.32 Huxley’s goals were essentially social and political. He sought to reduce
the clerical influence over scientific posts in universities and the civil service, to
establish a genuinely professional and secular science, and to elevate the status of
science and its practitioners.33 While many of his weapons were those of the political
lobbyist, the Darwinian theory of evolution served as a useful ideological ally. In his
1860 review of the Origin, Huxley memorably wrote: “Extinguished theologians lie
about the cradle of every science as the strangled snakes beside that of Hercules; and
history records that whenever science and orthodoxy have been fairly opposed, the
latter has been forced to retire from the lists, bleeding and crushed if no annihilated;
scotched, if not slain.”34 It is a measure of the success of his secularizing mission that
there is now a widespread belief in a Victorian “crisis of faith” attributable to the
inception of Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection. This is the perspective
encapsulated in the tale of the Harrow schoolboy.
Summing up these strands, there is a popular narrative that suggests science has been,
and will continue to be, a major contributor to secularization. An inchoate version of
this narrative is already present in the Protestant accounts of the new learning of the
seventeenth century, while a broader version was articulated by the first formulators
of the Enlightenment story. But it was the nineteenth century that saw the
consolidation of the narrative in a number of ways. First, fledgling social scientists
30
Ronald L. Numbers, The Creationists, expanded edn. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard, 2006).
See Bernard Lightman, “The History of Victorian Scientific Naturalism”, forthcoming.
32
J. Vernon Jenson, “The X-Club: Fraternity of Victorian Scientists, British Journal for the History of
Science 5 (1970), 63-72; Ruth Barton, “‘An Influential Set of Chaps’: The X-Club and Royal Society
Politics, 1864-85”, British Journal for the History of Science 23 (1990): 53-81.
33
Barton, “‘An Influential Set of Chaps’”; T. W. Heyck, The Transformation of Intellectual Life in
Victorian England (London: Croom Helm, 1982), 87.
34
T. H. Huxley, Review of Darwin’s Origin of Species, Westminster Review, 1860, in T. H. Huxley,
Darwiniana (New York: Appleton, 1897), 52.
31
9
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
spoke of an inevitable progression in human societies from a religious stage to a
scientific stage. Second, some historians sought to give substance to this story by
identifying historical points of tension in what they imagined was a protracted
transition from one stage to another. Science and religion, which represent what
ought to be successive stages in human development, are caught in a perennial
battle—a battle in which science will eventually be the inevitable victor. The history
of science is thus understood as the history of human progress, and as a struggle
against the regressive forces of religion. Third, individuals such T. H. Huxley
attempted with considerable success to utilize science, and evolutionary theory in
particular, to promote a particular social or secularist agenda. These pre-twentieth
century endeavours provide virtually all of the storylines now recounted in popular
narratives of secularization.
2. The Narrative Challenged
Critics of the science and secularization thesis have pointed to three major
shortcomings: first, the extent of secularization predicted by the thesis is not
supported by the evidence, and thus there is no historical inevitability to the decline of
religion; second, to the extent that secularization has occurred—and much here turns
on what counts as secularization—the advance of science is not a significant causal
factor; third, the thesis assumes that religion is primarily a belief system, and
secularization takes place when religious beliefs are increasingly rendered implausible
by the march of science.
The most conspicuous weakness of the science and secularization thesis lies in its
iterated predictive failures. The timetable for the demise of religion at the hands of
science has been successively postponed. As a predictive, “scientific” thesis, the
hypothesis that science causes secularization seems to have been falsified.
Sociologist Rodney Stark, while perhaps not the most impartial of witnesses, thinks
this sufficient to consign the secularization doctrine to “the graveyard of failed
theories”.35 More generally, most social scientists now reject the idea of progressive
or directional social change, and for their part, few historians now subscribe to the
idea that history moves through fixed stages or epochs.36 History does not seem
predictable in that kind of way, and the idea of laws of human progress are no longer
regarded as tenable.37
35
Rodney Stark, “Secularization, R.I.P.,” Sociology of Religion 60 (1999): 249-73 (269).
In the 1980s Stark and Bainbridge proposed a cyclical, as opposed to a linear view of secularization:
“Our model is a cycle of secularization, revival, and religious innovation.... Science accelerates the
process of secularization, thus speeding the decline of established religious traditions. But this does not
lead to the end of religion in general.” “New Religions, Science, and Secularization”, Religion and the
Social Order, 3A (1993): 277-292. Cf. R. Stark and W.S. Bainbridge, The Future of Religion.
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985).
37
Occasional anomalies like Francis Fukuyama’s The End of History and the Last Man (New York:
Free Press, 1992), notwithstanding.
36
10
The empirical data seem also to throw up challenges to the idea of an inevitable and
universal trend towards loss of religion. Sociologist Peter Berger has declared that
“The world today is massively religious, is anything but the secularised world that had
been predicted (whether joyfully or despondently) by so many analysts of
modernity.”38 This represents a remarkable volte-face by Berger, who in the 1960’s
announced that by the twenty-first century “religious believers are likely to be found
only in small sects, huddled together to resist a worldwide secular culture.”39 This
was a view he shared with most sociologists at the time, based on data that seemed to
indicate a precipitous decline in participation in formal religious observance in
Northern Europe.40 David Martin, another leading theorist of secularization, agrees
that the predictions of the geographical shrinkage of religions were misplaced. Part of
the point that both Berger and Martin wish to make is that the apparent patterns of
religious belief and practice in northern European may not be typical, and they note
the vast expansion of Pentecostal Protestant Christianity in Africa and South America.
Martin has estimated that there are at a minimum 250 million Pentecostals in the
world today, 50 million of whom are in Latin America. Peter Berger himself has
remarked that Max Weber is alive and well and living in Guatemala—regarding that
country as a new test case for the Weber’s Protestantism and capitalism thesis. In the
1990s, Andrew Greely offered a similar assessment of the religious situation in
Russia, reporting that “St. Vladimir has routed Karl Marx”. Perhaps best attested of
all is the case for the vitality of Islam, although this may not be welcome news to
all.41
If the scope and degree of secularization are deemed to have been exaggerated, so too
the role of science. In terms of the relevant historical details, historians of science
38
Peter Berger, “The Desecularization of the World: A Global Overview”, The Desecularization of the
World: Resurgent Religion and World Politics, ed. Peter L. Berger, (Washington, DC: Ethics and Public
Policy Center, 1999), 1-18 (9). For studies supporting this thesis see, e.g., Andrew Greeley, Religion in
Europe at the End of the Second Millennium (New Brunswick: Transaction, 2003); Scott M. Thomas,
The Global Resurgence of Religion and the Transformation of International Relations: The Struggle for
the Soul of the Twenty-First Century (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005); Jane Garnett et al. (eds.),
Redefining Christian Britain: Post-1945 Perspectives (London: SCM, 2007); Thomas Banchoff (ed.),
Religious Pluralism, Globalization, and World Politics (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008).
For a recent summary of the desecularization arguments see Vyacheslav Karpov, “Desecularization: A
Conceptual Framework”, Journal of Church and State 52 (2010): 232-70.
39
The New York Times, April 25, 1968.
40
Callum Brown, The Decline of Christendom in Western Europe, 1750-2000 (Cambridge; Cambridge
University Press, 2003), 29; cf. Brown, The Death of Christian Britain: Understanding Secularization
1800-2000 (London: Routledge, 2001); Hugh McLeod, The Religious Crisis of the 1960s (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2007).
41
David Martin, Pentecostalism: The World Their Parish (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002); Berger,
Desecularization of the World, 16; Andrew Greely, “A Religious Revival in Russia?”, Journal for the
Scientific Study of Religion, 33 (1994): 253-72 (272); cf. John Garrard and Carol Garrard, Russian
Orthodoxy Resurgent: Faith and Power in the New Russia (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2008); Elena Lisovskaya and Vyacheslav Karpov, “Orthodoxy, Islam, and Desecularization of Russia's
State Schools”, Politics and Religion 3 (2010): 276–302. On Islam see Gilles Kepel, The Revenge of
God: The Resurgence of Islam, Christianity, and Judaism in the Modern World (University Park:
Pennsylvania State University Press, 1994); Phillip W. Sutton and Stephen Vertigans, Resurgent Islam:
A Sociological Approach (Malden: Polity, 2005).
11
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
have spent the past thirty years dismantling what is commonly referred to as “the
conflict myth”. “Draper-and-White” is now code for a discredited model, and the
most common position amongst historians of science is that there is no single,
overarching narrative about historical relations between science and religion. This is
partly because “science” and “religion” are themselves historical constructions that
emerge relatively late in the history of the modern West. It is also widely recognized
that modern science did not emerge in opposition to religion and that, if anything,
while the relevant relations are complex (what counts as “science” and as “religion” is
again a relevant consideration), religion contributed positively to the emergence and
persistence of “science”. As for the specific episodes such as the “Victorian crisis of
faith” supposedly precipitated by the advancement of science, this crisis seems to
have been largely illusory. 42 Insofar as there was a group of self-identifying
secularists in the late nineteenth century, as Susan Budd’s pioneering studies in the
1960s and 70s demonstrate, moral issues played a far more prominent role in loss of
belief than more recondite scientific and theological issues. Budd concludes that
“loss of faith for Freethinkers was not an intellectual but a moral matter.”43 Dominic
Erdozain has made a related, if more general argument, about the moral sources of
religious skepticism in the modern West.44 Some sociologists have recently reached a
similar conclusion about the minimal role played by science in promoting religious
doubt. David Martin wrote in 2007 that: “There is no consistent relation between the
degree of scientific advance and a reduced profile of religious influence, belief and
practice.”45 Moreover, as John Brooke has suggested, where such relations can be
detected, it is more likely that the secularization of society leads to the secularization
of science, rather than the reverse.46
A third difficulty with this science and secularization story is that it tends to operate
with a particular, and problematic, conception of religion. Religion is understood as
entailing beliefs about the natural world that operate on the same explanatory level as
scientific theories. If this were so, it might explain an inevitable retreat of religion in
the face of well-grounded scientific claims about the physical world. However, if
religion were more concerned with morality, specific practices, or social relations, it
is difficult to see how science might play a direct role. British anthropologist Mary
Douglas has accordingly proposed that religion concerns social relations rather than
theories about nature, and that given this it is difficult to see how science would
42
See Timothy Larsen, Crisis of Doubt (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
Susan Budd, “The Loss of Faith: Reasons for Unbelief among Members of the Secular Movement in
England, 1850-1950”, Past and Present 36 (1967): 106-125 (125). Cf. Id. Varieties of Unbelief:
Atheists and Agnostics in English Society, 1850-1960 (London: Heinemann, 1977).
44
Dominic Erdozain, The Soul of Doubt: The Religious Roots of Unbelief from Luther to Marx
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016). Also see he contribution to this special issue.
45
David Martin, “Does the advance of science mean secularisation?, “Science and Christian Belief 19
(2007): 3-14 (9).
46
John Brooke, “That Modern Science has Secularized Western Culture”, in Ronald L. Numbers (ed.),
Galileo goes to Jail and other myths about Science and Religion (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 2009), 224-232. Frank James “Science in a Secular Age”, London Library Magazine
16-18. “Science became secular because society became secular, not the other way around.” (18).
43
12
impact negatively on religion.47 Charles Taylor’s understanding of secularization is
also a relevant consideration here. He proposes a focus on the conditions of belief
rather than the content of belief, and suggests that the shift to secularity be understood
as a move from a society in which belief in God is unchallenged and unproblematic,
to one in which as one in which it is one option amongst others.48 Secularity thus
suggests a particular framework for the holding of beliefs, rather than a situation in
which supernatural beliefs have been replaced by scientific ones.
All that said, it seems undeniable that certain parts of the world have seen a decline in
religious belief and practice, in so far as these are susceptible to measurement. Even
if this does not amount to a wholesale and universal disappearance of the sacred,
would it not count as an instance of secularization? In this context Peter Berger has
identified two exceptions to his thesis of a world desecularization. In Western
Europe, he concedes, “the old secularization thesis would seem to hold.” The other
exception is not geographically determined and consists rather of those individuals,
wherever they are encountered, “with Western-type higher education, especially in the
humanities and social sciences.”49 On the basis of these exceptions, Berger, Martin,
and Grace Davie have proposed that the standard secularization thesis be reversed.
Religious cultures are not the last redoubts against the inevitable victory of the forces
of the forces of secularization. Rather it is Western Europe and a secular globalized
elite that represent the exception to the general rule.50
This reversed version of the thesis leaves things to be explained. Why is it that we
encounter secularization in these places and peoples and, given that the relevant
places are scientifically and technologically advanced and the relevant people highly
educated, might not science and scientific literacy play a role?
3. Science and Secularization Revisited
In this section I want to suggest that science is involved in secularization—in these
three senses of the term: decline in religious belief and practice, increasing
differentiation of social institutions, and privatization of religion. In what follows I
will offer a brief sketch of this involvement, proposing that to the extent that
secularization has taken place in the West, this initially arose out of congenial
interactions between religion and science, rather than a growing separation and
opposition. That is to say, secularization does not arise out of a simple opposition
47
Mary Douglas, “The Effects of Modernization on Religious Change”, Proceedings of the American
Academy of Arts and Sciences 111 (1982): 1-19, cited in John Hedley Brooke, “Science and
Secularization” in The Cambridge Companion to Science and Religion, ed. Peter Harrison,
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 103-123.
48
Taylor, A Secular Age, 1-14.
49
Berger, “Desecularization of the World”, 9-11.
50
Peter Berger, A Far Glory: The Quest for Faith in an Age of Credulity (New York: Doubleday,
1992), David Martin, “The Secularization Issue: Prospect and Retrospect”, British Journal of Sociology
42 (1991): 465-74; Grace Davie, Europe: The Exceptional Case: Parameters of Faith in the Modern
World (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 2002).
13
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
between scientific and religious beliefs, but is rather the indirect result of the
conditions of belief that attend the successes of modern science. There are three
elements to this story. The first is to do with the rethinking of natural and
supernatural causality. In the early modern period three of Aristotle’s four causes
were expelled from the natural world, leaving only a single plane of efficient causes
on which both divine and natural causation were thought to operate. Second, was the
“secularization” of theology, in the sense that theological speculation became a
legitimate pursuit for non-theologians and specifically for natural philosophers.
Theology was conducted in the world, and by worldly persons. Again, this was
related to a rejection of Aristotelianism, in this instance involving a breakdown of the
boundaries between the speculative sciences of natural philosophy and theology.
Protestant conceptions of vocation also played an important role. Third, and
following on from this, was a new alliance between natural philosophy and theology
which promoted a new understanding of religion as essentially to do with beliefs for
which it was appropriate to seek scientific support. The new science was thus
accompanied by a new conception of religion which developed in tandem with a
conception of the secular.
Over the past twenty years a number of accounts of the emergence of secular
modernity attribute to late medieval conceptions of “univocity of being” a key role.51
The story goes that while in the thirteenth century Thomas Aquinas had insisted that
divine predicates (God is good, God is wise, etc.) are to be understood analogically,
his scholastic successor John Duns Scotus maintained that they must be understood
univocally. For Aquinas, when we predicate goodness of God, we mean “goodness”
in a way that is analogous to human conceptions of goodness. For Duns Scotus,
however, in order for such claims to be meaningful, the predicate “goodness” must
have the same sense in both cases. That is, it must be deployed univocally rather than
analogously. Similarly, if we were to say that God causes something to take place, we
must be using “cause” in the same sense that applies when we speak of natural
causation. The consequence of this development is that God came to be thought of as
the highest of beings, and that his causal activity was seen as operating on the same
level as creaturely or natural causation. When God’s causal activity subsequently
came to be seen unnecessary for the explanation of natural phenomena, there were
increasingly few places for him to be active in the world. This gave rise to a
naturalistic reading of nature which found no place for the divine.52
51
See, e.g., Brad Gregory, The Unintended Reformation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
2012), 25-73; Michael Gillespie, The Theological Origins of Modernity (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2008); John Milbank, Theology and Social Theory: Beyond Secular Reason 2nd edn.,
(Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2006), 302-6; Louis Dupré, Passage to Modernity (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1993).
52
Another part of this story concerns divine voluntarism and the medieval power distinction (between
Dei potentia absoluta and Dei potentia ordinata). I have reservations about this story, too. See
Harrison, “Voluntarism and Early Modern Science”, History of Science 40 (2002): 63-89. “Was Newton
a Voluntarist?”, in James E. Force and Sarah Hutton (eds.), Newton and Newtonianism: New Studies,
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2004), pp39-64; “Voluntarism and the Origins of Modern Science: A Reply to John
Henry”, History of Science 47 (2009): 223-31.
14
This analysis is on the right track in so far as it identifies as a key moment of
transition a flattening of causation in the early modern period, so that divine and
natural causality are seen as operating on the same level. However, the proposed
genealogy is problematic. For a start, there has been some discussion about whether
Duns Scotus was in fact the originator of the doctrine of univocity.53 But whatever
the origins of the notion, early modern natural philosophy (i.e “science”) is the key
driver of the conception, for it incorporated it into a view of causation that
underpinned the modern understanding of the operations of the natural world. This,
in turn, seems to be less a development of Scotist philosophy or its philosophical
descendants than a way of integrating a new corpuscular matter theory into natural
philosophy. The scientific explanations characteristic of medieval Aristotelianism
accounted for change in the world in terms of the intrinsic powers and virtues of
natural things. God is involved in these events because he is the causal source of
everything in the natural world. When God acts in nature, he does not do so
immediately but acts through the powers of the creatures. Thus, for Aquinas, each
natural event is wholly the effect of God and of the natural agent.54 Miraculous
events, by way of contrast, are wholly the work of God.
While some fourteenth- and fifteenth-century thinkers had expressed reservations
about this Aristotelian view of natural change, it was the adoption of Epicurean matter
theory by early modern natural philosophers in the seventeenth century that
necessitated a complete rethinking of causation, particularly in relation to what virtues
and powers might continue to reside in matter.55 The major Protestant reformers had
successfully challenged the key elements of the Aristotelian approach to moral
philosophy, denying that the moral status of human beings was related to virtues that
directing them towards particular ends. Luther and Calvin both held this approach to
be inconsistent with what they considered to be the biblical view of justification:
Individuals did not become righteous because of their own inherent qualities, but
because God had willed to impute righteousness to them. Moral worth was to be
understood relationally, rather than ontologically. The adoption of a corpuscular
matter theory in natural philosophy led to a parallel view of nature’s operations, now
accounted for not in terms of inherent powers or virtues directing them to particular
53
Richard Cross, “Duns Scotus and Suárez at the Origins of Modernity”, in Wayne J. Hankey and
Douglas Hedley (eds.), Deconstructing Radical Orthodoxy: Postmodern Theology, Rhetoric and Truth
(Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005), 65-80; Michael J. Dodds, Unlocking Divine Action: Contemporary Science
and Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D. C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2012), 52.
54
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, 3.66, 3.70, 3.77. Francisco Suárez, On Efficient
Causation, tr. Alfred Freddoso (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), 18. 1 (14). Cf. Peter
Lombard, Sentences 2.18.5.
55
Nicholas of Autrecourt (1300—c. 1350) was sceptical about Aristotelian causation as was Gabriel
Biel (c. 1425-1495). Alfred Freddoso, “Medieval Aristotelianism and the Case against Secondary
Causation in Nature,” in Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism, ed. Thomas
V. Morris, (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988). For a possible connection to the occasionalism of
Islamic thinkers see Harry Wolfson, “Nicolaus of Autrecourt and Ghazali’s Argument Against
Causality”, Speculum, 44 (1969): 234–38.
15
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
ends, but again because of externally imposed divine volitions. Natural explanations,
henceforth, will be understood in terms of divinely promulgated laws of nature rather
than inherent powers. In a way, God’s operations in the realms of both grace and
nature are now understood in terms of relations rather than the imbuing of intrinsic
qualities.56
In the Principles of Philosophy (1644), Descartes explains that the laws of nature are
nothing other than God’s continuous willing of certain regular states of affairs: “God
imparted various motions to the parts of matter when he first created them, and he
now preserves all this matter in the same way, and by the same process by which he
originally created it”.57 These laws are immutable because the divine nature from
which they issue is immutable. For Descartes, God acts constantly and consistently to
uphold the laws of nature. These reside not in the essences of natural things, but in
God’s constant willing.58 The Cartesian philosopher Nicolas Malebranche took these
assumptions to their logical conclusion by asserting that there are no genuine efficient
causes in nature. Natural events are simply the occasion on which God acts. Efficient
causes are thus the last of Aristotle’s causes to be banished from the natural world.
Their role is taken over by the new idea of laws of nature.59
While the Newtonians were to take issue with elements of the Cartesian programme,
they nonetheless adopted the vocabulary of laws of nature, along with the idea of the
primacy of divine causation in these laws.60 Newton himself held that gravity was
not an essential property inherent in matter, and while was he reluctant to identify
gravity with divine activity his followers were less so. William Whiston, Newton’s
successor in the Lucasian Chair of Mathematics at Cambridge, announced that the
effect of nature were nothing other than divine power “acting according to fixt and
56
For a more detailed account of these transitions see Harrison, Territories of Science and Religion.
Descartes, Principles of Philosophy, § 61, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. 2 vols.
Translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1984–91), vol. 1, 240.
58
Descartes, The World, in Philosophical Writings, vol. 1, 93, 96; Principles of Philosophy, in
Philosophical Writings, vol. 1, 240. Whether Descartes believed in the existence of secondary causes
remains a contested issue.
59
Nicholas Malebranche, Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion, ed. Nicholas Jolley and David Scott
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), intro. by Nicholas Jolley, xxii. cf. xxvii. From an
extensive secondary literature on the early modern conception of laws of nature see John Henry,
“Metaphysics and the Origins of Modern Science: Descartes and the Importance of Laws of Nature”,
Early Science and Medicine, 9 (2004): 73-114; J. R. Milton, “Laws of Nature”, in The Cambridge
History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy, 2 vols., ed. Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers, (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998), vol. 1, 680-701; Peter Harrison, “Laws of Nature in SeventeenthCentury England: From Cambridge Platonism to Newtonianism”, in The Divine Order, the Human
Order, and the Order of Nature: Historical Perspectives, ed. Eric Watkins, (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2013), 127-48, and Peter Harrison, “Voluntarism and Early Modern Science”, History
of Science 40 (2002): 63-89.
60
In a letter to Richard Bentley, Newton wrote: “You sometimes speak of Gravity as essential and
inherent to Matter. Pray do not ascribe that Notion to me; for the Cause of Gravity is what I do not
pretend to know, and therefore would take more Time to consider it.” B Cohen (ed.), Isaac Newton's
Papers & Letters on Natural Philosophy, 2nd edition (Cambridge, Mass., and London, 1978), 279-312
(298).
57
16
certain laws”.61 Indeed, all “natural” change came to be understood simply as
unmediated divine activity. The philosopher-theologian Samuel Clarke—Newton’s
spokesman in the protracted controversy with German philosopher G. W. Leibniz—
was even more direct. The course of nature, he contended “is nothing else but the
will of God producing certain effects in a continued, regular, constant, and uniform
manner; which course or manner of acting, being in every moment perfectly arbitrary,
is as easy to be altered at any time as to be preserved.”62 The distinction between
natural and supernatural, so carefully articulated by Aquinas, was now dispensed
with, leaving all events equally natural or supernatural. 63 Clarke states this
unambiguously:
...absolutely speaking, in This strict and Philosophical Sense; either nothing is
miraculous, namely, if we have respect to the Power of God; or, if we regard
our own Power and Understanding, then almost every thing, as well what we
call natural, as what we call supernatural, is in this Sense really miraculous; and
'tis only usualness or Unusualness that makes the distinction.64
This unitary conception of causation does not seem to have been indebted to the
philosophy of Duns Scotus. Rather it resulted from specific theological and
metaphysical problems associated with the new corpuscular theory, and with pious
natural philosophers’ attempts to demonstrate the compatibility of corpuscular matter
theory with Christian theism.
The Newtonians would doubtless be discomforted by the comparison, but this
conception of nature is not so far removed from Spinoza’s monistic Deus sive natura
(God-or-nature). Because there was a single layer of efficient causation, laws
describing regularities in nature admitted of two descriptions, being both laws of God
and laws of nature. And these could easily become simply laws of nature without
remainder. This move is foreshadowed in Laplace’s celebrated remark that he had no
need of the God hypothesis to account for the regular motions of the cosmos. These
developments are consistent with a more general theory of secularization according to
which the Protestant reformers’ attempt to make the theological domain allencompassing ultimately gives rise to a naturalistic re-description of that theological
totality.
There is much more that could be said here. In addition to possible connections
between Protestant critiques of Aristotelian teleology in the moral sphere and
challenges to final causation in the sphere of nature, other features of Reformation
61
William Whiston, A New Theory of the Earth (London, 1696), 6, 211.
Samuel Clarke, The Works of Samuel Clarke, D.D. 2 vols., (London, 1738),
vol. 2, 697-8.
63
Aquinas is one of the first to make an explicit distinction between natural and supernatural.
“Supernatural” [supernaturalis] becomes a common expression only in the thirteenth century. See
Robert Bartlett, The Natural and the Supernatural in the Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008), esp. 9-12. Talal Asad get this wrong way round when he asserts that an early
modern distinction between natural and supernatural is the premise for the construction of a “secular
space.” Formations of the Secular (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 27.
64
Clarke, Works, vol. 2, 698.
62
17
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
thought and practice informed early modern natural philosophy. I have suggested
elsewhere that Protestant approaches to the book of scripture (along with their view of
the sacraments) promoted the demise of sacramental understanding of the world, and
making room for “scientific” readings of the book of nature.65 Brad Gregory has
similarly suggested that Protestantism challenged a prevailing sacramental view of
nature in a way that was conducive to alternative scientific interpretations. 66
Protestant conceptions of divine omnipotence and providence, albeit in indirect ways,
were also significant in these transitions.67
A second way of linking science and secularization is to do with the secularization of
theology, by which I mean simply a democratization of theological reflection, which
allowed natural philosophers to put forward theological speculations. This process
was a prerequisite for the desacralization of nature described above. Aristotle had
identified three speculative sciences— natural philosophy (or physics), mathematics,
and theology —and had distinguished them by their respective subject matters.
Natural philosophy dealt with what was material, temporal, and mutable; theology,
with what was immaterial, eternal and immutable; mathematics with what lay
between. One feature of the new seventeenth century approaches to natural
philosophy was the transgression of the boundaries between these disciplines.
Historians of science have attended most to the new combinations natural philosophy
and mathematics which culminated in Newton’s magnum opus, Philosophiae
naturalis principia mathematica (Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy).
But with the appearance of the new hybrid discipline of “physico-mathematics” come
another new combination of natural philosophy/physics and theology—physicotheology. Following Kant’s classification of arguments for the existence of God, it
has become customary to think of physico-theology as an inelegant synonym for the
argument from design. But originally it was a new combined disciplinary field akin
to physico-mathematics.68 And its practice gave rise to a new situation in which
natural philosophers assumed authority in the sphere of theology.
Aristotle’s insistence on the relative independence of natural philosophy and theology
had been reflected in the institutional structures of the medieval universities. Those
universities that had a “higher” Faculty of Theology—and not all did—observed a
clear demarcation between the subject matter of natural philosophy and theology.
65
Peter Harrison, The Bible, Protestantism, and the Rise of Natural Science (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1998). See also Alexandra Walsham, “The Reformation and the ‘Disenchantment of
the World’ Re-assessed”, The Historical Journal 51 (2008): 497-528, esp. 505-7. Edward Muir, Ritual
in early modern Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), ch. 5; Brian A. Gerrish,
“Sign and reality: the Lord’s Supper in the Reformed Confessions”, in Gerrish, The old Protestantism
and the New (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982).
66
Gregory, Unintended Reformation, 40-3.
67
Keith Hutchison, “Supernaturalism and the Mechanical Philosophy”, History of Science 21 (1983):
297-333; Gregory, Unintended Reformation, 41.
68
See Harrison, “Physico-theology and the Mixed Sciences: The Role of Theology in Early Modern
Natural Philosophy”, in The Science of Nature in the Seventeenth Century, ed. Peter Anstey and John
Schuster, (Dordrecht: Springer, 2005), 165-183.
18
The former was taught in the Faculty of Arts, the latter in the Faculty of Theology. A
1272 statute of Faculty of Arts of the University of Paris thus stipulated that “no
bachelor or master of our faculty should presume to determine or even to dispute any
purely theological question”. 69 (The subsequent Condemnation of 1277, which
prohibited discussion of some 219 philosophical and theological theses in the Faculty
of Arts at the University of Paris, represents a policing of this boundary.) It is
characteristic of the seventeenth-century natural philosophy, however, that its
practitioners assumed a license to engage in theological discussions. Amos
Funkenstein has spoken in this context of the emergence of “secular theologians”.70
A conspicuous instance of this was Galileo’s ill-fated foray into biblical
hermeneutics. In the “Letter to the Grand Duchess Christina” (1615), Galileo set out
principles of biblical interpretation, drawing upon Augustine, in order to support his
version of the Copernican hypothesis. As is well known, Catholic authorities took a
dim view of this incursion, endorsing the Tridentine principle that biblical exegesis
was the business of the Church, and not individual philosophers. René Descartes,
mindful of Galileo’s fate, exercised considerable caution in theological matters, often
disclaiming that he would leave theology to the theologians. This notwithstanding,
his radical thesis concerning the creation of eternal truths and his new theological
conception of the laws of nature represent the articulation of quite distinctive
theological positions, linked to his natural philosophical project. Protestants had even
fewer reservations about making theological claims. Francis Bacon suggested that
natural philosophy was a redemptive exercise, aimed at partially restoring the earth to
its prelapsarian perfection.71 Johannes Kepler proposed that astronomy be regarded as
a theological activity: “I wished to be a theologian; for a long time I was troubled, but
now see how God is also praised through my work in astronomy.” Astronomers, he
believed, were “priests of the most high God, with respect to the book of nature.”72
Robert Boyle used the same metaphor, and suggested that natural philosophy ought to
be regarded as “reasonable worship of God.” 73 Isaac Newton insisted, in direct
opposition to the Aristotelian division of intellectual labour, that “to treat of God from
the phenomena is certainly a part of natural philosophy”.74 These were not simply
pious glosses but, as we have already seen, involve specific conceptions of divine
69
Edward Grant, ed., A Source Book in Mediaeval Science (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1974), 45.
70
Amos Funkenstein, Theology and the Scientific Imagination (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1986), 4-10.
71
Francis Bacon, Novum organum, Bk. 2, §52, Works of Francis Bacon, vol. 4, 247
72
Johannes Kepler, Gesammelte Werke (Munich, 1937-45) XIII, 40. For Kepler’s own account,
Johannes Kepler, Selbstzeugnisse, ed. Franz Hammer, tr. Esther Hammer (Stuttgart-Bad Constatt,
1971), 61-5. Werke VII (1953), 25. Cf. Kepler, Letter to Herwath von Hohenburg, March 26, 1598,
Werke XIII (1945), 193.
73
Boyle, Some Considerations, in Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, 6 vols. Edited by Thomas
Birch, (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1966) vol. 2, 32, 29, 63, 62; Cf. vol. 3, 627, vol. 4, 401. “Reasonable
worship” is biblical phrase (Romans 1.12). Also see H. Fisch, “The Scientist as Priest: A Note on
Robert Boyle’s Natural Theology”, Isis 44 (1953): 252-65.
74
Isaac Newton, “General Scholium”, in Isaac Newton: The Principia, tr. I. Bernard Cohen and Anne
Whitman, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999), 943.
19
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
activity that provided crucial presuppositions to the science they underpinned.
Neither did natural philosophers restrict themselves to the more general field of
natural theology. A number of writers speculated about the physical causes of the
beginning and end of the world. Among Robert Boyle’s voluminous theological
writings was the intriguing Physico-theological considerations about the possibility of
the Resurrection (1675). Boyle also suggested that natural philosophers should
adjudicate on whether certain events were miraculous. Newton wrote much more on
theology than science, and covered topics ranging over biblical interpretation,
chronology and eschatology, and the nature of the Trinity.
One factor in the rise of “secular theology” was the new Protestant notion of vocation
with its associated critique of hierarchical medieval “estates”. The clergy had
represented one of three estates, the other two being the aristocracy and the laity. The
sacrament of Holy Orders was thought to confer on the priesthood a distinct
ontological status.75 The Protestant reformers had challenged the idea of the unique
status of the clergy, with Luther, for example, maintaining that all Christians “are of
the spiritual estate, and there is no difference among them except that of office.”76
This idea of “the priesthood of all believers” gave sanction to the theological
speculations of natural philosophers. The possibly of secular theology—that is,
theology practiced by the laity—was thus a consequence of secularization inasmuch
as it called for the extension of the sanctity of the priestly vocation into worldly
pursuits, including natural philosophy. Relating this to the most basic understanding
of “secularization” we might say that this resulted from the conversion of
ecclesiastical intellectual property to secular use. The implications of this were far
reaching, because with the growth in the social status of natural philosophy and
natural philosophers, theological pronouncements bearing the imprimatur of science
came eventually to be accorded considerable weight. Thus, as we have seen, the
success of Newtonianism promoted an either-or understanding of causality, paving
the way for a thoroughgoing naturalism.
The practice of physico-theology brings us to the third way in which science is
implicated in secularization. Physico-theology was not simply the apologetic defense
of religion by natural philosophy: it was at least as much about the apologetic defense
of a new experimental natural philosophy by a more socially secure theology.77 The
75
Council of Trent, Session 23, ch. 4. On estates, see Rosemary O’Day, “The Clergy of the Church
of England”, in The Professions in Early Modern England, ed. Wilfred Prest (London: Routledge,
1987), 25-63.
76
Martin Luther, To the Christian Nobility of the German Nation (1520), in Three Treatises
(Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970), 12. Cf. John Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion.
Translated by Henry Beveridge. 2 vols. (London: James Clarke, 1962), vol. 1, 502; vol. 2, 1473.
77
Thus Stephen Gaukroger: “… a good part of the distinctive success at the level of legitimation and
consolidation of the scientific enterprise in the early-modern West, derives not from any separation of religion
and natural philosophy, but rather from the fact that natural philosophy could be accommodated to projects in
natural theology.” Emergence of a Scientific Culture (Oxford; Oxford University Press, 2009), 23. Cf. Michael
J. Buckley, At the Origins of Modern Atheism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1987), 347.
20
baptism of Epicureanism is a case in point. One reason that natural philosophers
stressed the essential inertness of matter was in order to provide a role for God in a
worldview traditionally associated with atheism. The success of Epicurean matter
theory thus crucially depended upon its capacity to be Christianised. In a sense this
proved to be less problematic than it might at first seem, since unlike the competing
Peripatetic, Platonic, and Stoic systems, there was no indigenous theology to displace.
It is important to understand that the adoption of Epicurean matter theory did not
come about through its displacement of some religious conception of nature, but
because it came to be regarded as potentially more compatible with theological
orthodoxy than its competitors.78
More importantly though, the physico-theological union of natural philosophy and
Christianity had a significant impact on how Christianity itself came to be
conceptualised. Increasingly, it was understood to be based on propositions that stood
in need of rational (or natural philosophical) support—because this was the form that
best suited the physico-theological model. The early modern rapprochement between
“science” and “religion” thus brought about an adjustment in the prevailing
understanding of what counted as “religion”.
This is not the context in which to set out in detail how our modern conception of
religion emerged in the early modern period. There is a significant literature devoted
to this.79 Suffice it to say that before the seventeenth century, religious identity in the
West was not understood in terms of commitment to a “religion”, constituted by a
discrete set of beliefs and practices. “Religio”, in fact, was one of the moral virtues
and the little used term “religions” (religiones) referred to different monastic orders.
Following the Reformation however, “religion” was increasingly understood in terms
of beliefs and practices, and the plural religions came into being as mutually exclusive
instantiations of a generic “religion”. The reformers’ insistence on the primacy of
explicit belief was also a key factor in this development, as was the process of
formally defining religious differences that arose out of the settlements of Augsburg
(1555) and Westphalia (1648). The co-incidence of the voyages of discovery and the
78
Descartes, admittedly, needed to work rather hard to render corpuscular matter theory compatible
with transubstantiation. But this same difficulty rendered it more attractive to Protestants. On this
general point it might also be said that even making allowances for its genre, Stephen Greenblatt’s
recent attempt to place a revived Epicureanism at the heart of modernity [The Swerve: How the World
became Modern (New York: Norton, 2012)] gets even the basics wrong. It overlooks the existence of
Carolingian MSS of De rerum natura, rehearses the humanists’ myths about their own place in history,
and almost completely ignores the role of natural philosophers in the revival and baptism of
Epicureanism.
79
See, e.g., Wilfred Cantwell Smith, The Meaning and End of Religion [1962] (London: SPCK, 1978);
Peter Harrison, “Religion” and the Religions in the English Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990); Michel Despland, La religion en occident: évolution des idées et du vécu.
(Montréal: Fides, 1979); Philip C. Almond, The British Discovery of Buddhism (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1988); Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions, (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2005); Guy Stroumsa, A New Science; The Discovery of Religion in the
Age of Reason (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2010); Brent Nongbri, Before Religion:
The History of a Modern Concept (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2013).
21
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
emergence of religious pluralism in Europe gave rise to the invention of world
religions. The result was the modern problem of competing religious truth claims,
and the need to adjudicate between the rival claims of the religions was acutely felt.
The standard solution was to speak of “evidences”, “proofs” and “impartial
comparisons.”80 It was at this point that the new natural philosophy could offer its
services. Physico-theology established the general truth of monotheistic religion,
while natural philosophical treatment of miracles and prophecies helped distinguish
among competing monotheistic creeds. This involvement of natural philosophy thus
helped reinforce the new idea of “religion”, while at the same time establishing its
own status as a socially useful activity. To this extent, science might thus be said to
be implicated in secularization, since as Talal Asad and others have rightly argued,
the formation of the category “religion” is the precondition or, perhaps more
accurately, the necessary concomitant, of an idea of the secular.81
Conclusion
Accounts of the role of science in the processes of secularization have tended to one
of two extremes. On a common view, science is the main driver of secularization,
since it has continually thrown up challenges to key religious beliefs and offers us an
alternative, rational way of looking at the world. This view has typically been
underpinned with a commitment to the idea that history progresses through stages,
leading to an inevitable displacement of religious conceptions by scientific ones. At
the other extreme are relatively sophisticated understandings of secularization that
propose that science plays little or no role in the process, and which give more weight
to factors such as historical criticism, the emergence of historical consciousness, to
late medieval nominalism and conceptions of univocity, or to less direct causes such
as social differentiation, the existence of a plurality of beliefs, or material prosperity
and personal security. I have offered a broad sketch of a position that seeks to
reinstate science as a significant factor in the emergence of secular modernity. At an
intellectual level, science, or natural philosophy as it then was, was the predominant
vector for a conception of causation that made it difficult to speak about divine action
in nature or history. This, in turn, was related to the changing status of natural
philosophy and its practitioners, such that the latter were able to make authoritative
pronouncements on theological matters. This authority has been retained right up to
the present, as the first section of this paper amply demonstrates, even if the
commitment now tends towards a thoroughgoing naturalism and negation of theology.
Finally, the intimate relationship between natural philosophy and theology that
characterized the seventeenth century was one factor that promoted a modern,
propositional understanding of religion, and this was itself a necessary condition for
the coming into being of “the secular”.
80
81
See Harrison, “Religion” and the religions, 19-28.
Talal Asad, Genealogies of Religion (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1993).
22
There are two deep ironies in all of this. First is that the popular narrative, with its
teleological development toward the purely secular condition, bears a significant
resemblance to forms of sacred history. There is a direct development from Protestant
providential history of the kind represented by Francis Bacon to the perspective of the
philosophes who turned Protestant history into a story about enlightenment liberation
from religious superstition. This suggests a lineage of what Ian Hunter has referred to
as secularization “combat concepts” that begins well before the nineteenth century.
The stadial histories of the Enlightenment have an even longer pedigree, mapping
more or less directly onto medieval millenarian divisions of time. Comte’s “three
stages” are the secular version of the trinitarian structuring of history developed by
thirteenth century Franciscan mystic Joachim of Fiore. Joachim’s third “age of the
Spirit” would see the reign of universal love and peace in which ecclesiastical rule
would become redundant. In Comte’s case, it is the redemptive transformative power
that Bacon attributed to science that would usher in the kingdom of reason.
Furthermore, as Norman Cohn demonstrated in his much lauded study of chiliastic
expectation in the middle ages, millenarian hope is highest in times of social stress,
actual or imagined.82 It is possible to identify such specific triggers for Comtean,
Hegelian and Marxist eschatologies.83 The most recent outbreaks of the science-willcause-secularization style eschatology, articulated by the new atheists, were
precipitated by the events of September 11 and what was thought to be the global
menace of Islamic fundamentalism.84
The second irony, to which John Brooke and Michael Buckley have previously drawn
attention, concerns that fact that it was religiously committed natural philosophers
who did most to establish the conditions for a secular understanding of the operations
of nature.85 This was accomplished not primarily through the influence of Scotist
thinking per se, but by the theologically inspired embodiment in early modern natural
philosophy of univocal understanding of causation, along with a non-symbolic
ordering of the natural world. This led to a wholly unintended desacralization of the
natural order. It is interesting in this context that it was sociologist Robert K. Merton,
author of a thesis that linked puritanism with the efflorescence of scientific activity in
seventeenth-century England, who developed and drew attention to the notion of
“unintended consequences” in sociological theory.86 Of more direct relevance to our
present subject, this analysis lends credence to elements of the argument set out in
82
Norman Cohn, The Pursuit of the Millennium (London: Paladin, 1970), 281-6.
See Andrew Wernick, Auguste Comte and the Religion of Humanity (Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2004), ch. 5.
84
Richard Dawkins, A Devil’s Chaplain (New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2004), 157-8; Sam
Harris, The End of Faith (New York: Norton, 2005), 333; Christopher Hitchens, God is not Great (New
York: Twelve, 2009), 31.
85
Brooke, “Science and Secularization” and Buckley, Origins of Modern Atheism, 322-63. Also see
Dominic Erdozain’s more recent The Soul of Doubt: The Religious Roots of Unbelief from Luther to
Marx (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).
86
R. K. Merton, “The Unanticipated Consequences of Purposive Social Action”, American
Sociological Review 1 (1936), 894-904.
83
23
Intellectual History Review, 27/1 (2017), Special Issue: Narratives of Secularization
Gregory’s Unintended Reformation, which similarly directs our attention to the
paradoxical consequences of the religious reformations of the early modern period.
24